Skip to main content

Full text of "Aristotle Organon And Other Works"

See other formats


Aristotle - Works 
[Translated under the editorship of W. D. Ross] 



Organon I - Categories 


2 


Organon II - On Interpretation 


47 


Organon III - Prior Analytics 


81 


Organon IV - Posterior Analytics 


221 


Organon V - Topics 


326 


Organon VI - On Sophistical Refutations 


533 


Physics 


602 


On the Heavens 


852 


On Generation and Corruption 


952 


Meteorology 


1033 


On the Soul 


1159 


Parva Naturalia 


1256 


History of Animals 


1389 


On the Parts of Animals 


1791 


On the Motion of Animals 


1966 


On the Gait of Animals 


1984 


On the Generation of Animals 


2 009 


Metaphysics 


2 205 


Nicomachean Ethics 


2 536 


Politics 


2 788 


Athenian Constitution 


3 050 


Rhetoric 


3 132 


Poetics 


3 308 



Aristotle - Categories 
[Translated by E. M. Edghill] 



Things are said to be named 'equivocally' when, though they 
have a common name, the definition corresponding with the 
name differs for each. Thus, a real man and a figure in a picture 
can both lay claim to the name 'animal'; yet these are 
equivocally so named, for, though they have a common name, 
the definition corresponding with the name differs for each. For 
should any one define in what sense each is an animal, his 
definition in the one case will be appropriate to that case only. 

On the other hand, things are said to be named 'univocally' 
which have both the name and the definition answering to the 
name in common. A man and an ox are both 'animal', and these 
are univocally so named, inasmuch as not only the name, but 
also the definition, is the same in both cases: for if a man 
should state in what sense each is an animal, the statement in 
the one case would be identical with that in the other. 

Things are said to be named 'derivatively', which derive their 
name from some other name, but differ from it in termination. 
Thus the grammarian derives his name from the word 
'grammar', and the courageous man from the word 'courage'. 



Forms of speech are either simple or composite. Examples of 
the latter are such expressions as 'the man runs', 'the man 
wins'; of the former 'man', 'ox', 'runs', 'wins'. 

Of things themselves some are predicable of a subject, and are 
never present in a subject. Thus 'man' is predicable of the 
individual man, and is never present in a subject. 

By being 'present in a subject' I do not mean present as parts 
are present in a whole, but being incapable of existence apart 
from the said subject. 

Some things, again, are present in a subject, but are never 
predicable of a subject. For instance, a certain point of 
grammatical knowledge is present in the mind, but is not 
predicable of any subject; or again, a certain whiteness may be 
present in the body (for colour requires a material basis), yet it 
is never predicable of anything. 

Other things, again, are both predicable of a subject and present 
in a subject. Thus while knowledge is present in the human 
mind, it is predicable of grammar. 

There is, lastly, a class of things which are neither present in a 
subject nor predicable of a subject, such as the individual man 
or the individual horse. But, to speak more generally, that which 
is individual and has the character of a unit is never predicable 
of a subject. Yet in some cases there is nothing to prevent such 
being present in a subject. Thus a certain point of grammatical 
knowledge is present in a subject. 



When one thing is predicated of another, all that which is 
predicable of the predicate will be predicable also of the subject. 
Thus, 'man' is predicated of the individual man; but 'animal' is 
predicated of 'man'; it will, therefore, be predicable of the 
individual man also: for the individual man is both 'man' and 
'animal'. 

If genera are different and co-ordinate, their differentiae are 
themselves different in kind. Take as an instance the genus 
'animal' and the genus 'knowledge'. 'With feet', 'two-footed', 
'winged', 'aquatic', are differentiae of 'animal'; the species of 
knowledge are not distinguished by the same differentiae. One 
species of knowledge does not differ from another in being 
'two-footed'. 

But where one genus is subordinate to another, there is nothing 
to prevent their having the same differentiae: for the greater 
class is predicated of the lesser, so that all the differentiae of 
the predicate will be differentiae also of the subject. 



Expressions which are in no way composite signify substance, 
quantity, quality, relation, place, time, position, state, action, or 
affection. To sketch my meaning roughly, examples of substance 
are 'man' or 'the horse', of quantity, such terms as 'two cubits 
long' or 'three cubits long', of quality, such attributes as 'white', 
'grammatical'. 'Double', 'half, 'greater', fall under the category 
of relation; 'in a the market place', 'in the Lyceum', under that of 
place; 'yesterday', 'last year', under that of time. 'Lying', 'sitting', 



are terms indicating position, 'shod', 'armed', state; 'to lance', 'to 
cauterize', action; 'to be lanced', 'to be cauterized', affection. 

No one of these terms, in and by itself, involves an affirmation; 
it is by the combination of such terms that positive or negative 
statements arise. For every assertion must, as is admitted, be 
either true or false, whereas expressions which are not in any 
way composite such as 'man', 'white', 'runs', 'wins', cannot be 
either true or false. 



Substance, in the truest and primary and most definite sense of 
the word, is that which is neither predicable of a subject nor 
present in a subject; for instance, the individual man or horse. 
But in a secondary sense those things are called substances 
within which, as species, the primary substances are included; 
also those which, as genera, include the species. For instance, 
the individual man is included in the species 'man', and the 
genus to which the species belongs is 'animal'; these, therefore 
- that is to say, the species 'man' and the genus 'animal, - are 
termed secondary substances. 

It is plain from what has been said that both the name and the 
definition of the predicate must be predicable of the subject. For 
instance, 'man' is predicted of the individual man. Now in this 
case the name of the species man' is applied to the individual, 
for we use the term 'man' in describing the individual; and the 
definition of 'man' will also be predicated of the individual man, 
for the individual man is both man and animal. Thus, both the 
name and the definition of the species are predicable of the 
individual. 



With regard, on the other hand, to those things which are 
present in a subject, it is generally the case that neither their 
name nor their definition is predicable of that in which they are 
present. Though, however, the definition is never predicable, 
there is nothing in certain cases to prevent the name being 
used. For instance, 'white' being present in a body is predicated 
of that in which it is present, for a body is called white: the 
definition, however, of the colour white' is never predicable of 
the body. 

Everything except primary substances is either predicable of a 
primary substance or present in a primary substance. This 
becomes evident by reference to particular instances which 
occur. 'Animal' is predicated of the species 'man', therefore of 
the individual man, for if there were no individual man of 
whom it could be predicated, it could not be predicated of the 
species 'man' at all. Again, colour is present in body, therefore in 
individual bodies, for if there were no individual body in which 
it was present, it could not be present in body at all. Thus 
everything except primary substances is either predicated of 
primary substances, or is present in them, and if these last did 
not exist, it would be impossible for anything else to exist. 

Of secondary substances, the species is more truly substance 
than the genus, being more nearly related to primary substance. 
For if any one should render an account of what a primary 
substance is, he would render a more instructive account, and 
one more proper to the subject, by stating the species than by 
stating the genus. Thus, he would give a more instructive 
account of an individual man by stating that he was man than 
by stating that he was animal, for the former description is 
peculiar to the individual in a greater degree, while the latter is 
too general. Again, the man who gives an account of the nature 
of an individual tree will give a more instructive account by 



mentioning the species 'tree' than by mentioning the genus 
'plant'. 

Moreover, primary substances are most properly called 
substances in virtue of the fact that they are the entities which 
underlie every, else, and that everything else is either predicated 
of them or present in them. Now the same relation which 
subsists between primary substance and everything else 
subsists also between the species and the genus: for the species 
is to the genus as subject is to predicate, since the genus is 
predicated of the species, whereas the species cannot be 
predicated of the genus. Thus we have a second ground for 
asserting that the species is more truly substance than the 
genus. 

Of species themselves, except in the case of such as are genera, 
no one is more truly substance than another. We should not 
give a more appropriate account of the individual man by 
stating the species to which he belonged, than we should of an 
individual horse by adopting the same method of definition. In 
the same way, of primary substances, no one is more truly 
substance than another; an individual man is not more truly 
substance than an individual ox. 

It is, then, with good reason that of all that remains, when we 
exclude primary substances, we concede to species and genera 
alone the name 'secondary substance', for these alone of all the 
predicates convey a knowledge of primary substance. For it is by 
stating the species or the genus that we appropriately define 
any individual man; and we shall make our definition more 
exact by stating the former than by stating the latter. All other 
things that we state, such as that he is white, that he runs, and 
so on, are irrelevant to the definition. Thus it is just that these 
alone, apart from primary substances, should be called 
substances. 



Further, primary substances are most properly so called, 
because they underlie and are the subjects of everything else. 
Now the same relation that subsists between primary substance 
and everything else subsists also between the species and the 
genus to which the primary substance belongs, on the one 
hand, and every attribute which is not included within these, on 
the other. For these are the subjects of all such. If we call an 
individual man 'skilled in grammar', the predicate is applicable 
also to the species and to the genus to which he belongs. This 
law holds good in all cases. 

It is a common characteristic of all sub. stance that it is never 
present in a subject. For primary substance is neither present in 
a subject nor predicated of a subject; while, with regard to 
secondary substances, it is clear from the following arguments 
(apart from others) that they are not present in a subject. For 
'man' is predicated of the individual man, but is not present in 
any subject: for manhood is not present in the individual man. 
In the same way, 'animal' is also predicated of the individual 
man, but is not present in him. Again, when a thing is present 
in a subject, though the name may quite well be applied to that 
in which it is present, the definition cannot be applied. Yet of 
secondary substances, not only the name, but also the 
definition, applies to the subject: we should use both the 
definition of the species and that of the genus with reference to 
the individual man. Thus substance cannot be present in a 
subject. 

Yet this is not peculiar to substance, for it is also the case that 
differentiae cannot be present in subjects. The characteristics 
'terrestrial' and 'two-footed' are predicated of the species 'man', 
but not present in it. For they are not in man. Moreover, the 
definition of the differentia may be predicated of that of which 
the differentia itself is predicated. For instance, if the 
characteristic 'terrestrial' is predicated of the species 'man', the 



definition also of that characteristic may be used to form the 
predicate of the species 'man': for 'man' is terrestrial. 

The fact that the parts of substances appear to be present in the 
whole, as in a subject, should not make us apprehensive lest we 
should have to admit that such parts are not substances: for in 
explaining the phrase 'being present in a subject', we stated' 
that we meant 'otherwise than as parts in a whole'. 

It is the mark of substances and of differentiae that, in all 
propositions of which they form the predicate, they are 
predicated univocally. For all such propositions have for their 
subject either the individual or the species. It is true that, 
inasmuch as primary substance is not predicable of anything, it 
can never form the predicate of any proposition. But of 
secondary substances, the species is predicated of the 
individual, the genus both of the species and of the individual. 
Similarly the differentiae are predicated of the species and of 
the individuals. Moreover, the definition of the species and that 
of the genus are applicable to the primary substance, and that 
of the genus to the species. For all that is predicated of the 
predicate will be predicated also of the subject. Similarly, the 
definition of the differentiae will be applicable to the species 
and to the individuals. But it was stated above that the word 
'univocal' was applied to those things which had both name 
and definition in common. It is, therefore, established that in 
every proposition, of which either substance or a differentia 
forms the predicate, these are predicated univocally. 

All substance appears to signify that which is individual. In the 
case of primary substance this is indisputably true, for the thing 
is a unit. In the case of secondary substances, when we speak, 
for instance, of 'man' or 'animal', our form of speech gives the 
impression that we are here also indicating that which is 
individual, but the impression is not strictly true; for a 



secondary substance is not an individual, but a class with a 
certain qualification; for it is not one and single as a primary 
substance is; the words 'man', 'animal', are predicable of more 
than one subject. 

Yet species and genus do not merely indicate quality, like the 
term 'white'; 'white' indicates quality and nothing further, but 
species and genus determine the quality with reference to a 
substance: they signify substance qualitatively differentiated. 
The determinate qualification covers a larger field in the case of 
the genus that in that of the species: he who uses the word 
'animal' is herein using a word of wider extension than he who 
uses the word 'man'. 

Another mark of substance is that it has no contrary. What 
could be the contrary of any primary substance, such as the 
individual man or animal? It has none. Nor can the species or 
the genus have a contrary. Yet this characteristic is not peculiar 
to substance, but is true of many other things, such as quantity. 
There is nothing that forms the contrary of 'two cubits long' or 
of 'three cubits long', or of 'ten', or of any such term. A man may 
contend that 'much' is the contrary of 'little', or 'great' of 'small', 
but of definite quantitative terms no contrary exists. 

Substance, again, does not appear to admit of variation of 
degree. I do not mean by this that one substance cannot be 
more or less truly substance than another, for it has already 
been stated' that this is the case; but that no single substance 
admits of varying degrees within itself. For instance, one 
particular substance, 'man', cannot be more or less man either 
than himself at some other time or than some other man. One 
man cannot be more man than another, as that which is white 
may be more or less white than some other white object, or as 
that which is beautiful may be more or less beautiful than some 
other beautiful object. The same quality, moreover, is said to 



10 



subsist in a thing in varying degrees at different times. A body, 
being white, is said to be whiter at one time than it was before, 
or, being warm, is said to be warmer or less warm than at some 
other time. But substance is not said to be more or less that 
which it is: a man is not more truly a man at one time than he 
was before, nor is anything, if it is substance, more or less what 
it is. Substance, then, does not admit of variation of degree. 

The most distinctive mark of substance appears to be that, 
while remaining numerically one and the same, it is capable of 
admitting contrary qualities. From among things other than 
substance, we should find ourselves unable to bring forward any 
which possessed this mark. Thus, one and the same colour 
cannot be white and black. Nor can the same one action be 
good and bad: this law holds good with everything that is not 
substance. But one and the selfsame substance, while retaining 
its identity, is yet capable of admitting contrary qualities. The 
same individual person is at one time white, at another black, at 
one time warm, at another cold, at one time good, at another 
bad. This capacity is found nowhere else, though it might be 
maintained that a statement or opinion was an exception to the 
rule. The same statement, it is agreed, can be both true and 
false. For if the statement 'he is sitting' is true, yet, when the 
person in question has risen, the same statement will be false. 
The same applies to opinions. For if any one thinks truly that a 
person is sitting, yet, when that person has risen, this same 
opinion, if still held, will be false. Yet although this exception 
may be allowed, there is, nevertheless, a difference in the 
manner in which the thing takes place. It is by themselves 
changing that substances admit contrary qualities. It is thus 
that that which was hot becomes cold, for it has entered into a 
different state. Similarly that which was white becomes black, 
and that which was bad good, by a process of change; and in the 
same way in all other cases it is by changing that substances 
are capable of admitting contrary qualities. But statements and 



11 



opinions themselves remain unaltered in all respects: it is by 
the alteration in the facts of the case that the contrary quality 
comes to be theirs. The statement 'he is sitting' remains 
unaltered, but it is at one time true, at another false, according 
to circumstances. What has been said of statements applies 
also to opinions. Thus, in respect of the manner in which the 
thing takes place, it is the peculiar mark of substance that it 
should be capable of admitting contrary qualities; for it is by 
itself changing that it does so. 

If, then, a man should make this exception and contend that 
statements and opinions are capable of admitting contrary 
qualities, his contention is unsound. For statements and 
opinions are said to have this capacity, not because they 
themselves undergo modification, but because this modification 
occurs in the case of something else. The truth or falsity of a 
statement depends on facts, and not on any power on the part 
of the statement itself of admitting contrary qualities. In short, 
there is nothing which can alter the nature of statements and 
opinions. As, then, no change takes place in themselves, these 
cannot be said to be capable of admitting contrary qualities. 

But it is by reason of the modification which takes place within 
the substance itself that a substance is said to be capable of 
admitting contrary qualities; for a substance admits within 
itself either disease or health, whiteness or blackness. It is in 
this sense that it is said to be capable of admitting contrary 
qualities. 

To sum up, it is a distinctive mark of substance, that, while 
remaining numerically one and the same, it is capable of 
admitting contrary qualities, the modification taking place 
through a change in the substance itself. 

Let these remarks suffice on the subject of substance. 



12 



Quantity is either discrete or continuous. Moreover, some 
quantities are such that each part of the whole has a relative 
position to the other parts: others have within them no such 
relation of part to part. 

Instances of discrete quantities are number and speech; of 
continuous, lines, surfaces, solids, and, besides these, time and 
place. 

In the case of the parts of a number, there is no common 
boundary at which they join. For example: two fives make ten, 
but the two fives have no common boundary, but are separate; 
the parts three and seven also do not join at any boundary. Nor, 
to generalize, would it ever be possible in the case of number 
that there should be a common boundary among the parts; they 
are always separate. Number, therefore, is a discrete quantity. 

The same is true of speech. That speech is a quantity is evident: 
for it is measured in long and short syllables. I mean here that 
speech which is vocal. Moreover, it is a discrete quantity for its 
parts have no common boundary. There is no common 
boundary at which the syllables join, but each is separate and 
distinct from the rest. 

A line, on the other hand, is a continuous quantity, for it is 
possible to find a common boundary at which its parts join. In 
the case of the line, this common boundary is the point; in the 
case of the plane, it is the line: for the parts of the plane have 
also a common boundary. Similarly you can find a common 
boundary in the case of the parts of a solid, namely either a line 
or a plane. 



13 



Space and time also belong to this class of quantities. Time, 
past, present, and future, forms a continuous whole. Space, 
likewise, is a continuous quantity; for the parts of a solid occupy 
a certain space, and these have a common boundary; it follows 
that the parts of space also, which are occupied by the parts of 
the solid, have the same common boundary as the parts of the 
solid. Thus, not only time, but space also, is a continuous 
quantity, for its parts have a common boundary. 

Quantities consist either of parts which bear a relative position 
each to each, or of parts which do not. The parts of a line bear a 
relative position to each other, for each lies somewhere, and it 
would be possible to distinguish each, and to state the position 
of each on the plane and to explain to what sort of part among 
the rest each was contiguous. Similarly the parts of a plane 
have position, for it could similarly be stated what was the 
position of each and what sort of parts were contiguous. The 
same is true with regard to the solid and to space. But it would 
be impossible to show that the arts of a number had a relative 
position each to each, or a particular position, or to state what 
parts were contiguous. Nor could this be done in the case of 
time, for none of the parts of time has an abiding existence, and 
that which does not abide can hardly have position. It would be 
better to say that such parts had a relative order, in virtue of one 
being prior to another. Similarly with number: in counting, 'one' 
is prior to 'two', and 'two' to 'three', and thus the parts of 
number may be said to possess a relative order, though it would 
be impossible to discover any distinct position for each. This 
holds good also in the case of speech. None of its parts has an 
abiding existence: when once a syllable is pronounced, it is not 
possible to retain it, so that, naturally, as the parts do not abide, 
they cannot have position. Thus, some quantities consist of 
parts which have position, and some of those which have not. 



14 



Strictly speaking, only the things which I have mentioned 
belong to the category of quantity: everything else that is called 
quantitative is a quantity in a secondary sense. It is because we 
have in mind some one of these quantities, properly so called, 
that we apply quantitative terms to other things. We speak of 
what is white as large, because the surface over which the 
white extends is large; we speak of an action or a process as 
lengthy, because the time covered is long; these things cannot 
in their own right claim the quantitative epithet. For instance, 
should any one explain how long an action was, his statement 
would be made in terms of the time taken, to the effect that it 
lasted a year, or something of that sort. In the same way, he 
would explain the size of a white object in terms of surface, for 
he would state the area which it covered. Thus the things 
already mentioned, and these alone, are in their intrinsic nature 
quantities; nothing else can claim the name in its own right, 
but, if at all, only in a secondary sense. 

Quantities have no contraries. In the case of definite quantities 
this is obvious; thus, there is nothing that is the contrary of 'two 
cubits long' or of 'three cubits long', or of a surface, or of any 
such quantities. A man might, indeed, argue that 'much' was 
the contrary of 'little', and 'great' of 'small'. But these are not 
quantitative, but relative; things are not great or small 
absolutely, they are so called rather as the result of an act of 
comparison. For instance, a mountain is called small, a grain 
large, in virtue of the fact that the latter is greater than others of 
its kind, the former less. Thus there is a reference here to an 
external standard, for if the terms 'great' and 'small' were used 
absolutely, a mountain would never be called small or a grain 
large. Again, we say that there are many people in a village, and 
few in Athens, although those in the city are many times as 
numerous as those in the village: or we say that a house has 
many in it, and a theatre few, though those in the theatre far 
outnumber those in the house. The terms 'two cubits long, 



15 



"three cubits long,' and so on indicate quantity, the terms 'great' 
and 'small' indicate relation, for they have reference to an 
external standard. It is, therefore, plain that these are to be 
classed as relative. 

Again, whether we define them as quantitative or not, they 
have no contraries: for how can there be a contrary of an 
attribute which is not to be apprehended in or by itself, but only 
by reference to something external? Again, if 'great' and 'small' 
are contraries, it will come about that the same subject can 
admit contrary qualities at one and the same time, and that 
things will themselves be contrary to themselves. For it 
happens at times that the same thing is both small and great. 
For the same thing may be small in comparison with one thing, 
and great in comparison with another, so that the same thing 
comes to be both small and great at one and the same time, and 
is of such a nature as to admit contrary qualities at one and the 
same moment. Yet it was agreed, when substance was being 
discussed, that nothing admits contrary qualities at one and the 
same moment. For though substance is capable of admitting 
contrary qualities, yet no one is at the same time both sick and 
healthy, nothing is at the same time both white and black. Nor 
is there anything which is qualified in contrary ways at one and 
the same time. 

Moreover, if these were contraries, they would themselves be 
contrary to themselves. For if 'great' is the contrary of 'small', 
and the same thing is both great and small at the same time, 
then 'small' or 'great' is the contrary of itself. But this is 
impossible. The term 'great', therefore, is not the contrary of the 
term 'small', nor 'much' of 'little'. And even though a man 
should call these terms not relative but quantitative, they would 
not have contraries. 



16 



It is in the case of space that quantity most plausibly appears to 
admit of a contrary. For men define the term 'above' as the 
contrary of 'below', when it is the region at the centre they 
mean by 'below'; and this is so, because nothing is farther from 
the extremities of the universe than the region at the centre. 
Indeed, it seems that in defining contraries of every kind men 
have recourse to a spatial metaphor, for they say that those 
things are contraries which, within the same class, are 
separated by the greatest possible distance. 

Quantity does not, it appears, admit of variation of degree. One 
thing cannot be two cubits long in a greater degree than 
another. Similarly with regard to number: what is 'three' is not 
more truly three than what is 'five' is five; nor is one set of three 
more truly three than another set. Again, one period of time is 
not said to be more truly time than another. Nor is there any 
other kind of quantity, of all that have been mentioned, with 
regard to which variation of degree can be predicated. The 
category of quantity, therefore, does not admit of variation of 
degree. 

The most distinctive mark of quantity is that equality and 
inequality are predicated of it. Each of the aforesaid quantities 
is said to be equal or unequal. For instance, one solid is said to 
be equal or unequal to another; number, too, and time can have 
these terms applied to them, indeed can all those kinds of 
quantity that have been mentioned. 

That which is not a quantity can by no means, it would seem, 
be termed equal or unequal to anything else. One particular 
disposition or one particular quality, such as whiteness, is by no 
means compared with another in terms of equality and 
inequality but rather in terms of similarity. Thus it is the 
distinctive mark of quantity that it can be called equal and 
unequal. 



17 



Those things are called relative, which, being either said to be of 
something else or related to something else, are explained by 
reference to that other thing. For instance, the word 'superior' is 
explained by reference to something else, for it is superiority 
over something else that is meant. Similarly, the expression 
'double' has this external reference, for it is the double of 
something else that is meant. So it is with everything else of 
this kind. There are, moreover, other relatives, e.g. habit, 
disposition, perception, knowledge, and attitude. The 
significance of all these is explained by a reference to 
something else and in no other way. Thus, a habit is a habit of 
something, knowledge is knowledge of something, attitude is 
the attitude of something. So it is with all other relatives that 
have been mentioned. Those terms, then, are called relative, the 
nature of which is explained by reference to something else, the 
preposition 'of or some other preposition being used to indicate 
the relation. Thus, one mountain is called great in comparison 
with son with another; for the mountain claims this attribute by 
comparison with something. Again, that which is called similar 
must be similar to something else, and all other such attributes 
have this external reference. It is to be noted that lying and 
standing and sitting are particular attitudes, but attitude is itself 
a relative term. To lie, to stand, to be seated, are not themselves 
attitudes, but take their name from the aforesaid attitudes. 

It is possible for relatives to have contraries. Thus virtue has a 
contrary, vice, these both being relatives; knowledge, too, has a 
contrary, ignorance. But this is not the mark of all relatives; 
'double' and 'triple' have no contrary, nor indeed has any such 
term. 



18 



It also appears that relatives can admit of variation of degree. 
For 'like' and 'unlike', 'equal' and 'unequal', have the 
modifications 'more' and 'less' applied to them, and each of 
these is relative in character: for the terms 'like' and 'unequal' 
bear 'unequal' bear a reference to something external. Yet, 
again, it is not every relative term that admits of variation of 
degree. No term such as 'double' admits of this modification. All 
relatives have correlatives: by the term 'slave' we mean the 
slave of a master, by the term 'master', the master of a slave; by 
'double', the double of its hall; by 'half, the half of its double; by 
'greater', greater than that which is less; by 'less,' less than that 
which is greater. 

So it is with every other relative term; but the case we use to 
express the correlation differs in some instances. Thus, by 
knowledge we mean knowledge the knowable; by the knowable, 
that which is to be apprehended by knowledge; by perception, 
perception of the perceptible; by the perceptible, that which is 
apprehended by perception. 

Sometimes, however, reciprocity of correlation does not appear 
to exist. This comes about when a blunder is made, and that to 
which the relative is related is not accurately stated. If a man 
states that a wing is necessarily relative to a bird, the connexion 
between these two will not be reciprocal, for it will not be 
possible to say that a bird is a bird by reason of its wings. The 
reason is that the original statement was inaccurate, for the 
wing is not said to be relative to the bird qua bird, since many 
creatures besides birds have wings, but qua winged creature. If, 
then, the statement is made accurate, the connexion will be 
reciprocal, for we can speak of a wing, having reference 
necessarily to a winged creature, and of a winged creature as 
being such because of its wings. 



19 



Occasionally, perhaps, it is necessary to coin words, if no word 
exists by which a correlation can adequately be explained. If we 
define a rudder as necessarily having reference to a boat, our 
definition will not be appropriate, for the rudder does not have 
this reference to a boat qua boat, as there are boats which have 
no rudders. Thus we cannot use the terms reciprocally, for the 
word 'boat' cannot be said to find its explanation in the word 
'rudder'. As there is no existing word, our definition would 
perhaps be more accurate if we coined some word like 
'ruddered' as the correlative of 'rudder'. If we express ourselves 
thus accurately, at any rate the terms are reciprocally 
connected, for the 'ruddered' thing is 'ruddered' in virtue of its 
rudder. So it is in all other cases. A head will be more accurately 
defined as the correlative of that which is 'headed', than as that 
of an animal, for the animal does not have a head qua animal, 
since many animals have no head. 

Thus we may perhaps most easily comprehend that to which a 
thing is related, when a name does not exist, if, from that which 
has a name, we derive a new name, and apply it to that with 
which the first is reciprocally connected, as in the aforesaid 
instances, when we derived the word 'winged' from 'wing' and 
from 'rudder'. 

All relatives, then, if properly defined, have a correlative. I add 
this condition because, if that to which they are related is stated 
as haphazard and not accurately, the two are not found to be 
interdependent. Let me state what I mean more clearly. Even in 
the case of acknowledged correlatives, and where names exist 
for each, there will be no interdependence if one of the two is 
denoted, not by that name which expresses the correlative 
notion, but by one of irrelevant significance. The term 'slave,' if 
defined as related, not to a master, but to a man, or a biped, or 
anything of that sort, is not reciprocally connected with that in 
relation to which it is defined, for the statement is not exact. 



20 



Further, if one thing is said to be correlative with another, and 
the terminology used is correct, then, though all irrelevant 
attributes should be removed, and only that one attribute left in 
virtue of which it was correctly stated to be correlative with that 
other, the stated correlation will still exist. If the correlative of 
'the slave' is said to be 'the master', then, though all irrelevant 
attributes of the said 'master', such as 'biped', 'receptive of 
knowledge', 'human', should be removed, and the attribute 
'master' alone left, the stated correlation existing between him 
and the slave will remain the same, for it is of a master that a 
slave is said to be the slave. On the other hand, if, of two 
correlatives, one is not correctly termed, then, when all other 
attributes are removed and that alone is left in virtue of which it 
was stated to be correlative, the stated correlation will be found 
to have disappeared. 

For suppose the correlative of 'the slave' should be said to be 
'the man', or the correlative of 'the wing"the bird'; if the 
attribute 'master' be withdrawn from' the man', the correlation 
between 'the man' and 'the slave' will cease to exist, for if the 
man is not a master, the slave is not a slave. Similarly, if the 
attribute 'winged' be withdrawn from 'the bird', 'the wing' will 
no longer be relative; for if the so-called correlative is not 
winged, it follows that 'the wing' has no correlative. 

Thus it is essential that the correlated terms should be exactly 
designated; if there is a name existing, the statement will be 
easy; if not, it is doubtless our duty to construct names. When 
the terminology is thus correct, it is evident that all correlatives 
are interdependent. 

Correlatives are thought to come into existence simultaneously. 
This is for the most part true, as in the case of the double and 
the half. The existence of the half necessitates the existence of 
that of which it is a half. Similarly the existence of a master 



21 



necessitates the existence of a slave, and that of a slave implies 
that of a master; these are merely instances of a general rule. 
Moreover, they cancel one another; for if there is no double it 
follows that there is no half, and vice versa; this rule also 
applies to all such correlatives. Yet it does not appear to be true 
in all cases that correlatives come into existence 
simultaneously. The object of knowledge would appear to exist 
before knowledge itself, for it is usually the case that we acquire 
knowledge of objects already existing; it would be difficult, if 
not impossible, to find a branch of knowledge the beginning of 
the existence of which was contemporaneous with that of its 
object. 

Again, while the object of knowledge, if it ceases to exist, 
cancels at the same time the knowledge which was its 
correlative, the converse of this is not true. It is true that if the 
object of knowledge does not exist there can be no knowledge: 
for there will no longer be anything to know. Yet it is equally 
true that, if knowledge of a certain object does not exist, the 
object may nevertheless quite well exist. Thus, in the case of the 
squaring of the circle, if indeed that process is an object of 
knowledge, though it itself exists as an object of knowledge, yet 
the knowledge of it has not yet come into existence. Again, if all 
animals ceased to exist, there would be no knowledge, but there 
might yet be many objects of knowledge. 

This is likewise the case with regard to perception: for the 
object of perception is, it appears, prior to the act of perception. 
If the perceptible is annihilated, perception also will cease to 
exist; but the annihilation of perception does not cancel the 
existence of the perceptible. For perception implies a body 
perceived and a body in which perception takes place. Now if 
that which is perceptible is annihilated, it follows that the body 
is annihilated, for the body is a perceptible thing; and if the 
body does not exist, it follows that perception also ceases to 



22 



exist. Thus the annihilation of the perceptible involves that of 
perception. 

But the annihilation of perception does not involve that of the 
perceptible. For if the animal is annihilated, it follows that 
perception also is annihilated, but perceptibles such as body, 
heat, sweetness, bitterness, and so on, will remain. 

Again, perception is generated at the same time as the 
perceiving subject, for it comes into existence at the same time 
as the animal. But the perceptible surely exists before 
perception; for fire and water and such elements, out of which 
the animal is itself composed, exist before the animal is an 
animal at all, and before perception. Thus it would seem that 
the perceptible exists before perception. 

It may be questioned whether it is true that no substance is 
relative, as seems to be the case, or whether exception is to be 
made in the case of certain secondary substances. With regard 
to primary substances, it is quite true that there is no such 
possibility, for neither wholes nor parts of primary substances 
are relative. The individual man or ox is not defined with 
reference to something external. Similarly with the parts: a 
particular hand or head is not defined as a particular hand or 
head of a particular person, but as the hand or head of a 
particular person. It is true also, for the most part at least, in the 
case of secondary substances; the species 'man' and the species 
'ox' are not defined with reference to anything outside 
themselves. Wood, again, is only relative in so far as it is some 
one's property, not in so far as it is wood. It is plain, then, that in 
the cases mentioned substance is not relative. But with regard 
to some secondary substances there is a difference of opinion; 
thus, such terms as 'head' and 'hand' are defined with reference 
to that of which the things indicated are a part, and so it comes 
about that these appear to have a relative character. Indeed, if 



23 



our definition of that which is relative was complete, it is very 
difficult, if not impossible, to prove that no substance is relative. 
If, however, our definition was not complete, if those things only 
are properly called relative in the case of which relation to an 
external object is a necessary condition of existence, perhaps 
some explanation of the dilemma may be found. 

The former definition does indeed apply to all relatives, but the 
fact that a thing is explained with reference to something else 
does not make it essentially relative. 

From this it is plain that, if a man definitely apprehends a 
relative thing, he will also definitely apprehend that to which it 
is relative. Indeed this is self-evident: for if a man knows that 
some particular thing is relative, assuming that we call that a 
relative in the case of which relation to something is a 
necessary condition of existence, he knows that also to which it 
is related. For if he does not know at all that to which it is 
related, he will not know whether or not it is relative. This is 
clear, moreover, in particular instances. If a man knows 
definitely that such and such a thing is 'double', he will also 
forthwith know definitely that of which it is the double. For if 
there is nothing definite of which he knows it to be the double, 
he does not know at all that it is double. Again, if he knows that 
a thing is more beautiful, it follows necessarily that he will 
forthwith definitely know that also than which it is more 
beautiful. He will not merely know indefinitely that it is more 
beautiful than something which is less beautiful, for this would 
be supposition, not knowledge. For if he does not know 
definitely that than which it is more beautiful, he can no longer 
claim to know definitely that it is more beautiful than 
something else which is less beautiful: for it might be that 
nothing was less beautiful. It is, therefore, evident that if a man 
apprehends some relative thing definitely, he necessarily knows 
that also definitely to which it is related. 



24 



Now the head, the hand, and such things are substances, and it 
is possible to know their essential character definitely, but it 
does not necessarily follow that we should know that to which 
they are related. It is not possible to know forthwith whose 
head or hand is meant. Thus these are not relatives, and, this 
being the case, it would be true to say that no substance is 
relative in character. It is perhaps a difficult matter, in such 
cases, to make a positive statement without more exhaustive 
examination, but to have raised questions with regard to details 
is not without advantage. 



8 

By 'quality' I mean that in virtue of which people are said to be 
such and such. 

Quality is a term that is used in many senses. One sort of 
quality let us call 'habit' or 'disposition'. Habit differs from 
disposition in being more lasting and more firmly established. 
The various kinds of knowledge and of virtue are habits, for 
knowledge, even when acquired only in a moderate degree, is, it 
is agreed, abiding in its character and difficult to displace, 
unless some great mental upheaval takes place, through disease 
or any such cause. The virtues, also, such as justice, self- 
restraint, and so on, are not easily dislodged or dismissed, so as 
to give place to vice. 

By a disposition, on the other hand, we mean a condition that is 
easily changed and quickly gives place to its opposite. Thus, 
heat, cold, disease, health, and so on are dispositions. For a man 
is disposed in one way or another with reference to these, but 
quickly changes, becoming cold instead of warm, ill instead of 
well. So it is with all other dispositions also, unless through 



25 



lapse of time a disposition has itself become inveterate and 
almost impossible to dislodge: in which case we should perhaps 
go so far as to call it a habit. 

It is evident that men incline to call those conditions habits 
which are of a more or less permanent type and difficult to 
displace; for those who are not retentive of knowledge, but 
volatile, are not said to have such and such a 'habit' as regards 
knowledge, yet they are disposed, we may say, either better or 
worse, towards knowledge. Thus habit differs from disposition 
in this, that while the latter in ephemeral, the former is 
permanent and difficult to alter. 

Habits are at the same time dispositions, but dispositions are 
not necessarily habits. For those who have some specific habit 
may be said also, in virtue of that habit, to be thus or thus 
disposed; but those who are disposed in some specific way have 
not in all cases the corresponding habit. 

Another sort of quality is that in virtue of which, for example, 
we call men good boxers or runners, or healthy or sickly: in fact 
it includes all those terms which refer to inborn capacity or 
incapacity. Such things are not predicated of a person in virtue 
of his disposition, but in virtue of his inborn capacity or 
incapacity to do something with ease or to avoid defeat of any 
kind. Persons are called good boxers or good runners, not in 
virtue of such and such a disposition, but in virtue of an inborn 
capacity to accomplish something with ease. Men are called 
healthy in virtue of the inborn capacity of easy resistance to 
those unhealthy influences that may ordinarily arise; unhealthy, 
in virtue of the lack of this capacity. Similarly with regard to 
softness and hardness. Hardness is predicated of a thing 
because it has that capacity of resistance which enables it to 
withstand disintegration; softness, again, is predicated of a 
thing by reason of the lack of that capacity. 



26 



A third class within this category is that of affective qualities 
and affections. Sweetness, bitterness, sourness, are examples of 
this sort of quality, together with all that is akin to these; heat, 
moreover, and cold, whiteness, and blackness are affective 
qualities. It is evident that these are qualities, for those things 
that possess them are themselves said to be such and such by 
reason of their presence. Honey is called sweet because it 
contains sweetness; the body is called white because it contains 
whiteness; and so in all other cases. 

The term 'affective quality' is not used as indicating that those 
things which admit these qualities are affected in any way. 
Honey is not called sweet because it is affected in a specific way, 
nor is this what is meant in any other instance. Similarly heat 
and cold are called affective qualities, not because those things 
which admit them are affected. What is meant is that these said 
qualities are capable of producing an 'affection' in the way of 
perception. For sweetness has the power of affecting the sense 
of taste; heat, that of touch; and so it is with the rest of these 
qualities. 

Whiteness and blackness, however, and the other colours, are 
not said to be affective qualities in this sense, but - because 
they themselves are the results of an affection. It is plain that 
many changes of colour take place because of affections. When 
a man is ashamed, he blushes; when he is afraid, he becomes 
pale, and so on. So true is this, that when a man is by nature 
liable to such affections, arising from some concomitance of 
elements in his constitution, it is a probable inference that he 
has the corresponding complexion of skin. For the same 
disposition of bodily elements, which in the former instance 
was momentarily present in the case of an access of shame, 
might be a result of a man's natural temperament, so as to 
produce the corresponding colouring also as a natural 
characteristic. All conditions, therefore, of this kind, if caused by 



27 



certain permanent and lasting affections, are called affective 
qualities. For pallor and duskiness of complexion are called 
qualities, inasmuch as we are said to be such and such in virtue 
of them, not only if they originate in natural constitution, but 
also if they come about through long disease or sunburn, and 
are difficult to remove, or indeed remain throughout life. For in 
the same way we are said to be such and such because of these. 

Those conditions, however, which arise from causes which may 
easily be rendered ineffective or speedily removed, are called, 
not qualities, but affections: for we are not said to be such 
virtue of them. The man who blushes through shame is not said 
to be a constitutional blusher, nor is the man who becomes pale 
through fear said to be constitutionally pale. He is said rather to 
have been affected. 

Thus such conditions are called affections, not qualities. 

In like manner there are affective qualities and affections of the 
soul. That temper with which a man is born and which has its 
origin in certain deep-seated affections is called a quality. I 
mean such conditions as insanity, irascibility, and so on: for 
people are said to be mad or irascible in virtue of these. 
Similarly those abnormal psychic states which are not inborn, 
but arise from the concomitance of certain other elements, and 
are difficult to remove, or altogether permanent, are called 
qualities, for in virtue of them men are said to be such and 
such. 

Those, however, which arise from causes easily rendered 
ineffective are called affections, not qualities. Suppose that a 
man is irritable when vexed: he is not even spoken of as a bad- 
tempered man, when in such circumstances he loses his 
temper somewhat, but rather is said to be affected. Such 
conditions are therefore termed, not qualities, but affections. 



28 



The fourth sort of quality is figure and the shape that belongs to 
a thing; and besides this, straightness and curvedness and any 
other qualities of this type; each of these defines a thing as 
being such and such. Because it is triangular or quadrangular a 
thing is said to have a specific character, or again because it is 
straight or curved; in fact a thing's shape in every case gives rise 
to a qualification of it. 

Rarity and density, roughness and smoothness, seem to be 
terms indicating quality: yet these, it would appear, really 
belong to a class different from that of quality. For it is rather a 
certain relative position of the parts composing the thing thus 
qualified which, it appears, is indicated by each of these terms. 
A thing is dense, owing to the fact that its parts are closely 
combined with one another; rare, because there are interstices 
between the parts; smooth, because its parts lie, so to speak, 
evenly; rough, because some parts project beyond others. 

There may be other sorts of quality, but those that are most 
properly so called have, we may safely say, been enumerated. 

These, then, are qualities, and the things that take their name 
from them as derivatives, or are in some other way dependent 
on them, are said to be qualified in some specific way. In most, 
indeed in almost all cases, the name of that which is qualified is 
derived from that of the quality. Thus the terms 'whiteness', 
'grammar', 'justice', give us the adjectives 'white', 'grammatical', 
'just', and so on. 

There are some cases, however, in which, as the quality under 
consideration has no name, it is impossible that those 
possessed of it should have a name that is derivative. For 
instance, the name given to the runner or boxer, who is so 
called in virtue of an inborn capacity, is not derived from that of 
any quality; for lob those capacities have no name assigned to 
them. In this, the inborn capacity is distinct from the science, 



29 



with reference to which men are called, e.g. boxers or wrestlers. 
Such a science is classed as a disposition; it has a name, and is 
called 'boxing' or 'wrestling' as the case may be, and the name 
given to those disposed in this way is derived from that of the 
science. Sometimes, even though a name exists for the quality, 
that which takes its character from the quality has a name that 
is not a derivative. For instance, the upright man takes his 
character from the possession of the quality of integrity, but the 
name given him is not derived from the word 'integrity'. Yet this 
does not occur often. 

We may therefore state that those things are said to be 
possessed of some specific quality which have a name derived 
from that of the aforesaid quality, or which are in some other 
way dependent on it. 

One quality may be the contrary of another; thus justice is the 
contrary of injustice, whiteness of blackness, and so on. The 
things, also, which are said to be such and such in virtue of 
these qualities, may be contrary the one to the other; for that 
which is unjust is contrary to that which is just, that which is 
white to that which is black. This, however, is not always the 
case. Red, yellow, and such colours, though qualities, have no 
contraries. 

If one of two contraries is a quality, the other will also be a 
quality. This will be evident from particular instances, if we 
apply the names used to denote the other categories; for 
instance, granted that justice is the contrary of injustice and 
justice is a quality, injustice will also be a quality: neither 
quantity, nor relation, nor place, nor indeed any other category 
but that of quality, will be applicable properly to injustice. So it 
is with all other contraries falling under the category of quality. 

Qualities admit of variation of degree. Whiteness is predicated 
of one thing in a greater or less degree than of another. This is 



30 



also the case with reference to justice. Moreover, one and the 
same thing may exhibit a quality in a greater degree than it did 
before: if a thing is white, it may become whiter. 

Though this is generally the case, there are exceptions. For if we 
should say that justice admitted of variation of degree, 
difficulties might ensue, and this is true with regard to all those 
qualities which are dispositions. There are some, indeed, who 
dispute the possibility of variation here. They maintain that 
justice and health cannot very well admit of variation of degree 
themselves, but that people vary in the degree in which they 
possess these qualities, and that this is the case with 
grammatical learning and all those qualities which are classed 
as dispositions. However that may be, it is an incontrovertible 
fact that the things which in virtue of these qualities are said to 
be what they are vary in the degree in which they possess them; 
for one man is said to be better versed in grammar, or more 
healthy or just, than another, and so on. 

The qualities expressed by the terms 'triangular' and 
'quadrangular' do not appear to admit of variation of degree, 
nor indeed do any that have to do with figure. For those things 
to which the definition of the triangle or circle is applicable are 
all equally triangular or circular. Those, on the other hand, to 
which the same definition is not applicable, cannot be said to 
differ from one another in degree; the square is no more a circle 
than the rectangle, for to neither is the definition of the circle 
appropriate. In short, if the definition of the term proposed is 
not applicable to both objects, they cannot be compared. Thus it 
is not all qualities which admit of variation of degree. 

Whereas none of the characteristics I have mentioned are 
peculiar to quality, the fact that likeness and unlikeness can be 
predicated with reference to quality only, gives to that category 
its distinctive feature. One thing is like another only with 



31 



reference to that in virtue of which it is such and such; thus this 
forms the peculiar mark of quality. 

We must not be disturbed because it may be argued that, 
though proposing to discuss the category of quality, we have 
included in it many relative terms. We did say that habits and 
dispositions were relative. In practically all such cases the genus 
is relative, the individual not. Thus knowledge, as a genus, is 
explained by reference to something else, for we mean a 
knowledge of something. But particular branches of knowledge 
are not thus explained. The knowledge of grammar is not 
relative to anything external, nor is the knowledge of music, but 
these, if relative at all, are relative only in virtue of their genera; 
thus grammar is said be the knowledge of something, not the 
grammar of something; similarly music is the knowledge of 
something, not the music of something. 

Thus individual branches of knowledge are not relative. And it 
is because we possess these individual branches of knowledge 
that we are said to be such and such. It is these that we actually 
possess: we are called experts because we possess knowledge in 
some particular branch. Those particular branches, therefore, of 
knowledge, in virtue of which we are sometimes said to be such 
and such, are themselves qualities, and are not relative. Further, 
if anything should happen to fall within both the category of 
quality and that of relation, there would be nothing 
extraordinary in classing it under both these heads. 



Action and affection both admit of contraries and also of 
variation of degree. Heating is the contrary of cooling, being 
heated of being cooled, being glad of being vexed. Thus they 



32 



admit of contraries. They also admit of variation of degree: for it 
is possible to heat in a greater or less degree; also to be heated 
in a greater or less degree. Thus action and affection also admit 
of variation of degree. So much, then, is stated with regard to 
these categories. 

We spoke, moreover, of the category of position when we were 
dealing with that of relation, and stated that such terms derived 
their names from those of the corresponding attitudes. 

As for the rest, time, place, state, since they are easily 
intelligible, I say no more about them than was said at the 
beginning, that in the category of state are included such states 
as 'shod', 'armed', in that of place 'in the Lyceum' and so on, as 
was explained before. 



10 

The proposed categories have, then, been adequately dealt with. 

We must next explain the various senses in which the term 
'opposite' is used. Things are said to be opposed in four senses: 
(i) as correlatives to one another, (ii) as contraries to one 
another, (iii) as privatives to positives, (iv) as affirmatives to 
negatives. 

Let me sketch my meaning in outline. An instance of the use of 
the word 'opposite' with reference to correlatives is afforded by 
the expressions 'double' and 'half; with reference to contraries 
by 'bad' and 'good'. Opposites in the sense of 'privatives' and 
'positives' are' blindness' and 'sight'; in the sense of 
affirmatives and negatives, the propositions 'he sits', 'he does 
not sit'. 



33 



(i) Pairs of opposites which fall under the category of relation 
are explained by a reference of the one to the other, the 
reference being indicated by the preposition 'of or by some 
other preposition. Thus, double is a relative term, for that which 
is double is explained as the double of something. Knowledge, 
again, is the opposite of the thing known, in the same sense; 
and the thing known also is explained by its relation to its 
opposite, knowledge. For the thing known is explained as that 
which is known by something, that is, by knowledge. Such 
things, then, as are opposite the one to the other in the sense of 
being correlatives are explained by a reference of the one to the 
other. 

(ii) Pairs of opposites which are contraries are not in any way 
interdependent, but are contrary the one to the other. The good 
is not spoken of as the good of the had, but as the contrary of 
the bad, nor is white spoken of as the white of the black, but as 
the contrary of the black. These two types of opposition are 
therefore distinct. Those contraries which are such that the 
subjects in which they are naturally present, or of which they 
are predicated, must necessarily contain either the one or the 
other of them, have no intermediate, but those in the case of 
which no such necessity obtains, always have an intermediate. 
Thus disease and health are naturally present in the body of an 
animal, and it is necessary that either the one or the other 
should be present in the body of an animal. Odd and even, 
again, are predicated of number, and it is necessary that the one 
or the other should be present in numbers. Now there is no 
intermediate between the terms of either of these two pairs. On 
the other hand, in those contraries with regard to which no 
such necessity obtains, we find an intermediate. Blackness and 
whiteness are naturally present in the body, but it is not 
necessary that either the one or the other should be present in 
the body, inasmuch as it is not true to say that everybody must 
be white or black. Badness and goodness, again, are predicated 



34 



of man, and of many other things, but it is not necessary that 
either the one quality or the other should be present in that of 
which they are predicated: it is not true to say that everything 
that may be good or bad must be either good or bad. These pairs 
of contraries have intermediates: the intermediates between 
white and black are grey, sallow, and all the other colours that 
come between; the intermediate between good and bad is that 
which is neither the one nor the other. 

Some intermediate qualities have names, such as grey and 
sallow and all the other colours that come between white and 
black; in other cases, however, it is not easy to name the 
intermediate, but we must define it as that which is not either 
extreme, as in the case of that which is neither good nor bad, 
neither just nor unjust. 

(iii) 'privatives' and 'Positives' have reference to the same 
subject. Thus, sight and blindness have reference to the eye. It is 
a universal rule that each of a pair of opposites of this type has 
reference to that to which the particular 'positive' is natural. We 
say that that is capable of some particular faculty or possession 
has suffered privation when the faculty or possession in 
question is in no way present in that in which, and at the time 
at which, it should naturally be present. We do not call that 
toothless which has not teeth, or that blind which has not sight, 
but rather that which has not teeth or sight at the time when by 
nature it should. For there are some creatures which from birth 
are without sight, or without teeth, but these are not called 
toothless or blind. 

To be without some faculty or to possess it is not the same as 
the corresponding 'privative' or 'positive'. 'Sight' is a 'positive', 
'blindness' a 'privative', but 'to possess sight' is not equivalent 
to 'sight', 'to be blind' is not equivalent to 'blindness'. Blindness 
is a 'privative', to be blind is to be in a state of privation, but is 



35 



not a 'privative'. Moreover, if 'blindness' were equivalent to 
'being blind', both would be predicated of the same subject; but 
though a man is said to be blind, he is by no means said to be 
blindness. 

To be in a state of 'possession' is, it appears, the opposite of 
being in a state of 'privation', just as 'positives' and 'privatives' 
themselves are opposite. There is the same type of antithesis in 
both cases; for just as blindness is opposed to sight, so is being 
blind opposed to having sight. 

That which is affirmed or denied is not itself affirmation or 
denial. By 'affirmation' we mean an affirmative proposition, by 
'denial' a negative. Now, those facts which form the matter of 
the affirmation or denial are not propositions; yet these two are 
said to be opposed in the same sense as the affirmation and 
denial, for in this case also the type of antithesis is the same. 
For as the affirmation is opposed to the denial, as in the two 
propositions 'he sits', 'he does not sit', so also the fact which 
constitutes the matter of the proposition in one case is opposed 
to that in the other, his sitting, that is to say, to his not sitting. 

It is evident that 'positives' and 'privatives' are not opposed 
each to each in the same sense as relatives. The one is not 
explained by reference to the other; sight is not sight of 
blindness, nor is any other preposition used to indicate the 
relation. Similarly blindness is not said to be blindness of sight, 
but rather, privation of sight. Relatives, moreover, reciprocate; if 
blindness, therefore, were a relative, there would be a 
reciprocity of relation between it and that with which it was 
correlative. But this is not the case. Sight is not called the sight 
of blindness. 

That those terms which fall under the heads of 'positives' and 
'privatives' are not opposed each to each as contraries, either, is 
plain from the following facts: Of a pair of contraries such that 



36 



they have no intermediate, one or the other must needs be 
present in the subject in which they naturally subsist, or of 
which they are predicated; for it is those, as we proved,' in the 
case of which this necessity obtains, that have no intermediate. 
Moreover, we cited health and disease, odd and even, as 
instances. But those contraries which have an intermediate are 
not subject to any such necessity. It is not necessary that every 
substance, receptive of such qualities, should be either black or 
white, cold or hot, for something intermediate between these 
contraries may very well be present in the subject. We proved, 
moreover, that those contraries have an intermediate in the 
case of which the said necessity does not obtain. Yet when one 
of the two contraries is a constitutive property of the subject, as 
it is a constitutive property of fire to be hot, of snow to be white, 
it is necessary determinately that one of the two contraries, not 
one or the other, should be present in the subject; for fire 
cannot be cold, or snow black. Thus, it is not the case here that 
one of the two must needs be present in every subject receptive 
of these qualities, but only in that subject of which the one 
forms a constitutive property. Moreover, in such cases it is one 
member of the pair determinately, and not either the one or the 
other, which must be present. 

In the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', on the other hand, 
neither of the aforesaid statements holds good. For it is not 
necessary that a subject receptive of the qualities should always 
have either the one or the other; that which has not yet 
advanced to the state when sight is natural is not said either to 
be blind or to see. Thus 'positives' and 'privatives' do not belong 
to that class of contraries which consists of those which have 
no intermediate. On the other hand, they do not belong either to 
that class which consists of contraries which have an 
intermediate. For under certain conditions it is necessary that 
either the one or the other should form part of the constitution 
of every appropriate subject. For when a thing has reached the 



37 



stage when it is by nature capable of sight, it will be said either 
to see or to be blind, and that in an indeterminate sense, 
signifying that the capacity may be either present or absent; for 
it is not necessary either that it should see or that it should be 
blind, but that it should be either in the one state or in the 
other. Yet in the case of those contraries which have an 
intermediate we found that it was never necessary that either 
the one or the other should be present in every appropriate 
subject, but only that in certain subjects one of the pair should 
be present, and that in a determinate sense. It is, therefore, 
plain that 'positives' and 'privatives' are not opposed each to 
each in either of the senses in which contraries are opposed. 

Again, in the case of contraries, it is possible that there should 
be changes from either into the other, while the subject retains 
its identity, unless indeed one of the contraries is a constitutive 
property of that subject, as heat is of fire. For it is possible that 
that that which is healthy should become diseased, that which 
is white, black, that which is cold, hot, that which is good, bad, 
that which is bad, good. The bad man, if he is being brought into 
a better way of life and thought, may make some advance, 
however slight, and if he should once improve, even ever so 
little, it is plain that he might change completely, or at any rate 
make very great progress; for a man becomes more and more 
easily moved to virtue, however small the improvement was at 
first. It is, therefore, natural to suppose that he will make yet 
greater progress than he has made in the past; and as this 
process goes on, it will change him completely and establish 
him in the contrary state, provided he is not hindered by lack of 
time. In the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', however, change 
in both directions is impossible. There may be a change from 
possession to privation, but not from privation to possession. 
The man who has become blind does not regain his sight; the 
man who has become bald does not regain his hair; the man 
who has lost his teeth does not grow his grow a new set. 



38 



(iv) Statements opposed as affirmation and negation belong 
manifestly to a class which is distinct, for in this case, and in 
this case only, it is necessary for the one opposite to be true and 
the other false. 

Neither in the case of contraries, nor in the case of correlatives, 
nor in the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', is it necessary for 
one to be true and the other false. Health and disease are 
contraries: neither of them is true or false. 'Double' and 'half 
are opposed to each other as correlatives: neither of them is 
true or false. The case is the same, of course, with regard to 
'positives' and 'privatives' such as 'sight' and 'blindness'. In 
short, where there is no sort of combination of words, truth and 
falsity have no place, and all the opposites we have mentioned 
so far consist of simple words. 

At the same time, when the words which enter into opposed 
statements are contraries, these, more than any other set of 
opposites, would seem to claim this characteristic. 'Socrates is 
ill' is the contrary of 'Socrates is well', but not even of such 
composite expressions is it true to say that one of the pair must 
always be true and the other false. For if Socrates exists, one 
will be true and the other false, but if he does not exist, both 
will be false; for neither 'Socrates is ill' nor 'Socrates is well' is 
true, if Socrates does not exist at all. 

In the case of 'positives' and 'privatives', if the subject does not 
exist at all, neither proposition is true, but even if the subject 
exists, it is not always the fact that one is true and the other 
false. For 'Socrates has sight' is the opposite of 'Socrates is blind' 
in the sense of the word 'opposite' which applies to possession 
and privation. Now if Socrates exists, it is not necessary that 
one should be true and the other false, for when he is not yet 
able to acquire the power of vision, both are false, as also if 
Socrates is altogether non-existent. 



39 



But in the case of affirmation and negation, whether the subject 
exists or not, one is always false and the other true. For 
manifestly, if Socrates exists, one of the two propositions 
'Socrates is ill', 'Socrates is not ill', is true, and the other false. 
This is likewise the case if he does not exist; for if he does not 
exist, to say that he is ill is false, to say that he is not ill is true. 
Thus it is in the case of those opposites only, which are opposite 
in the sense in which the term is used with reference to 
affirmation and negation, that the rule holds good, that one of 
the pair must be true and the other false. 



11 

That the contrary of a good is an evil is shown by induction: the 
contrary of health is disease, of courage, cowardice, and so on. 
But the contrary of an evil is sometimes a good, sometimes an 
evil. For defect, which is an evil, has excess for its contrary, this 
also being an evil, and the mean, which is a good, is equally the 
contrary of the one and of the other. It is only in a few cases, 
however, that we see instances of this: in most, the contrary of 
an evil is a good. 

In the case of contraries, it is not always necessary that if one 
exists the other should also exist: for if all become healthy there 
will be health and no disease, and again, if everything turns 
white, there will be white, but no black. Again, since the fact 
that Socrates is ill is the contrary of the fact that Socrates is 
well, and two contrary conditions cannot both obtain in one and 
the same individual at the same time, both these contraries 
could not exist at once: for if that Socrates was well was a fact, 
then that Socrates was ill could not possibly be one. 



40 



It is plain that contrary attributes must needs be present in 
subjects which belong to the same species or genus. Disease 
and health require as their subject the body of an animal; white 
and black require a body, without further qualification; justice 
and injustice require as their subject the human soul. 

Moreover, it is necessary that pairs of contraries should in all 
cases either belong to the same genus or belong to contrary 
genera or be themselves genera. White and black belong to the 
same genus, colour; justice and injustice, to contrary genera, 
virtue and vice; while good and evil do not belong to genera, but 
are themselves actual genera, with terms under them. 



12 

There are four senses in which one thing can be said to be 
'prior' to another. Primarily and most properly the term has 
reference to time: in this sense the word is used to indicate that 
one thing is older or more ancient than another, for the 
expressions 'older' and 'more ancient' imply greater length of 
time. 

Secondly, one thing is said to be 'prior' to another when the 
sequence of their being cannot be reversed. In this sense 'one' is 
'prior' to 'two'. For if 'two' exists, it follows directly that 'one' 
must exist, but if 'one' exists, it does not follow necessarily that 
'two' exists: thus the sequence subsisting cannot be reversed. It 
is agreed, then, that when the sequence of two things cannot be 
reversed, then that one on which the other depends is called 
'prior' to that other. 

In the third place, the term 'prior' is used with reference to any 
order, as in the case of science and of oratory. For in sciences 



41 



which use demonstration there is that which is prior and that 
which is posterior in order; in geometry, the elements are prior 
to the propositions; in reading and writing, the letters of the 
alphabet are prior to the syllables. Similarly, in the case of 
speeches, the exordium is prior in order to the narrative. 

Besides these senses of the word, there is a fourth. That which 
is better and more honourable is said to have a natural priority. 
In common parlance men speak of those whom they honour 
and love as 'coming first' with them. This sense of the word is 
perhaps the most far-fetched. 

Such, then, are the different senses in which the term 'prior' is 
used. 

Yet it would seem that besides those mentioned there is yet 
another. For in those things, the being of each of which implies 
that of the other, that which is in any way the cause may 
reasonably be said to be by nature 'prior' to the effect. It is plain 
that there are instances of this. The fact of the being of a man 
carries with it the truth of the proposition that he is, and the 
implication is reciprocal: for if a man is, the proposition 
wherein we allege that he is true, and conversely, if the 
proposition wherein we allege that he is true, then he is. The 
true proposition, however, is in no way the cause of the being of 
the man, but the fact of the man's being does seem somehow to 
be the cause of the truth of the proposition, for the truth or 
falsity of the proposition depends on the fact of the man's being 
or not being. 

Thus the word 'prior' may be used in five senses. 



42 



13 

The term 'simultaneous' is primarily and most appropriately 
applied to those things the genesis of the one of which is 
simultaneous with that of the other; for in such cases neither is 
prior or posterior to the other. Such things are said to be 
simultaneous in point of time. Those things, again, are 
'simultaneous' in point of nature, the being of each of which 
involves that of the other, while at the same time neither is the 
cause of the other's being. This is the case with regard to the 
double and the half, for these are reciprocally dependent, since, 
if there is a double, there is also a half, and if there is a half, 
there is also a double, while at the same time neither is the 
cause of the being of the other. 

Again, those species which are distinguished one from another 
and opposed one to another within the same genus are said to 
be 'simultaneous' in nature. I mean those species which are 
distinguished each from each by one and the same method of 
division. Thus the 'winged' species is simultaneous with the 
'terrestrial' and the 'water' species. These are distinguished 
within the same genus, and are opposed each to each, for the 
genus 'animal' has the 'winged', the 'terrestrial', and the 'water' 
species, and no one of these is prior or posterior to another; on 
the contrary, all such things appear to be 'simultaneous' in 
nature. Each of these also, the terrestrial, the winged, and the 
water species, can be divided again into subspecies. Those 
species, then, also will be 'simultaneous' point of nature, which, 
belonging to the same genus, are distinguished each from each 
by one and the same method of differentiation. 

But genera are prior to species, for the sequence of their being 
cannot be reversed. If there is the species 'water-animal', there 
will be the genus 'animal', but granted the being of the genus 



43 



'animal', it does not follow necessarily that there will be the 
species 'water-animal'. 

Those things, therefore, are said to be 'simultaneous' in nature, 
the being of each of which involves that of the other, while at 
the same time neither is in any way the cause of the other's 
being; those species, also, which are distinguished each from 
each and opposed within the same genus. Those things, 
moreover, are 'simultaneous' in the unqualified sense of the 
word which come into being at the same time. 



14 

There are six sorts of movement: generation, destruction, 
increase, diminution, alteration, and change of place. 

It is evident in all but one case that all these sorts of movement 
are distinct each from each. Generation is distinct from 
destruction, increase and change of place from diminution, and 
so on. But in the case of alteration it may be argued that the 
process necessarily implies one or other of the other five sorts 
of motion. This is not true, for we may say that all affections, or 
nearly all, produce in us an alteration which is distinct from all 
other sorts of motion, for that which is affected need not suffer 
either increase or diminution or any of the other sorts of 
motion. Thus alteration is a distinct sort of motion; for, if it were 
not, the thing altered would not only be altered, but would 
forthwith necessarily suffer increase or diminution or some one 
of the other sorts of motion in addition; which as a matter of 
fact is not the case. Similarly that which was undergoing the 
process of increase or was subject to some other sort of motion 
would, if alteration were not a distinct form of motion, 
necessarily be subject to alteration also. But there are some 



44 



things which undergo increase but yet not alteration. The 
square, for instance, if a gnomon is applied to it, undergoes 
increase but not alteration, and so it is with all other figures of 
this sort. Alteration and increase, therefore, are distinct. 

Speaking generally, rest is the contrary of motion. But the 
different forms of motion have their own contraries in other 
forms; thus destruction is the contrary of generation, 
diminution of increase, rest in a place, of change of place. As for 
this last, change in the reverse direction would seem to be most 
truly its contrary; thus motion upwards is the contrary of 
motion downwards and vice versa. 

In the case of that sort of motion which yet remains, of those 
that have been enumerated, it is not easy to state what is its 
contrary. It appears to have no contrary, unless one should 
define the contrary here also either as 'rest in its quality' or as 
'change in the direction of the contrary quality', just as we 
defined the contrary of change of place either as rest in a place 
or as change in the reverse direction. For a thing is altered when 
change of quality takes place; therefore either rest in its quality 
or change in the direction of the contrary may be called the 
contrary of this qualitative form of motion. In this way 
becoming white is the contrary of becoming black; there is 
alteration in the contrary direction, since a change of a 
qualitative nature takes place. 



15 

The term 'to have' is used in various senses. In the first place it 
is used with reference to habit or disposition or any other 
quality, for we are said to 'have' a piece of knowledge or a virtue. 
Then, again, it has reference to quantity, as, for instance, in the 



45 



case of a man's height; for he is said to 'have' a height of three 
or four cubits. It is used, moreover, with regard to apparel, a 
man being said to 'have' a coat or tunic; or in respect of 
something which we have on a part of ourselves, as a ring on 
the hand: or in respect of something which is a part of us, as 
hand or foot. The term refers also to content, as in the case of a 
vessel and wheat, or of a jar and wine; a jar is said to 'have' 
wine, and a corn-measure wheat. The expression in such cases 
has reference to content. Or it refers to that which has been 
acquired; we are said to 'have' a house or a field. A man is also 
said to 'have' a wife, and a wife a husband, and this appears to 
be the most remote meaning of the term, for by the use of it we 
mean simply that the husband lives with the wife. 

Other senses of the word might perhaps be found, but the most 
ordinary ones have all been enumerated. 



46 



Aristotle - On Interpretation 
[Translated by E. M. Edghill] 



First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms 
'denial' and 'affirmation', then 'proposition' and 'sentence.' 

Spoken words are the symbols of mental experience and 
written words are the symbols of spoken words. Just as all men 
have not the same writing, so all men have not the same 
speech sounds, but the mental experiences, which these 
directly symbolize, are the same for all, as also are those things 
of which our experiences are the images. This matter has, 
however, been discussed in my treatise about the soul, for it 
belongs to an investigation distinct from that which lies before 
us. 

As there are in the mind thoughts which do not involve truth or 
falsity, and also those which must be either true or false, so it is 
in speech. For truth and falsity imply combination and 
separation. Nouns and verbs, provided nothing is added, are 
like thoughts without combination or separation; 'man' and 
'white', as isolated terms, are not yet either true or false. In 
proof of this, consider the word 'goat-stag.' It has significance, 
but there is no truth or falsity about it, unless 'is' or 'is not' is 
added, either in the present or in some other tense. 



47 



By a noun we mean a sound significant by convention, which 
has no reference to time, and of which no part is significant 
apart from the rest. In the noun 'Fairsteed,' the part 'steed' has 
no significance in and by itself, as in the phrase 'fair steed.' Yet 
there is a difference between simple and composite nouns; for 
in the former the part is in no way significant, in the latter it 
contributes to the meaning of the whole, although it has not an 
independent meaning. Thus in the word 'pirate-boat' the word 
'boat' has no meaning except as part of the whole word. 

The limitation 'by convention' was introduced because nothing 
is by nature a noun or name - it is only so when it becomes a 
symbol; inarticulate sounds, such as those which brutes 
produce, are significant, yet none of these constitutes a noun. 

The expression 'not-man' is not a noun. There is indeed no 
recognized term by which we may denote such an expression, 
for it is not a sentence or a denial. Let it then be called an 
indefinite noun. 

The expressions 'of Philo', 'to Philo', and so on, constitute not 
nouns, but cases of a noun. The definition of these cases of a 
noun is in other respects the same as that of the noun proper, 
but, when coupled with 'is', 'was', or will be', they do not, as 
they are, form a proposition either true or false, and this the 
noun proper always does, under these conditions. Take the 
words 'of Philo is' or 'of or 'of Philo is not'; these words do not, 
as they stand, form either a true or a false proposition. 



48 



A verb is that which, in addition to its proper meaning, carries 
with it the notion of time. No part of it has any independent 
meaning, and it is a sign of something said of something else. 

I will explain what I mean by saying that it carries with it the 
notion of time. 'Health' is a noun, but 'is healthy' is a verb; for 
besides its proper meaning it indicates the present existence of 
the state in question. 

Moreover, a verb is always a sign of something said of 
something else, i.e. of something either predicable of or present 
in some other thing. 

Such expressions as 'is not-healthy', 'is not, ill', I do not 
describe as verbs; for though they carry the additional note of 
time, and always form a predicate, there is no specified name 
for this variety; but let them be called indefinite verbs, since 
they apply equally well to that which exists and to that which 
does not. 

Similarly 'he was healthy', 'he will be healthy', are not verbs, 
but tenses of a verb; the difference lies in the fact that the verb 
indicates present time, while the tenses of the verb indicate 
those times which lie outside the present. 

Verbs in and by themselves are substantival and have 
significance, for he who uses such expressions arrests the 
hearer's mind, and fixes his attention; but they do not, as they 
stand, express any judgement, either positive or negative. For 
neither are 'to be' and 'not to be' the participle 'being' 
significant of any fact, unless something is added; for they do 
not themselves indicate anything, but imply a copulation, of 
which we cannot form a conception apart from the things 
coupled. 



49 



A sentence is a significant portion of speech, some parts of 
which have an independent meaning, that is to say, as an 
utterance, though not as the expression of any positive 
judgement. Let me explain. The word 'human' has meaning, 
but does not constitute a proposition, either positive or 
negative. It is only when other words are added that the whole 
will form an affirmation or denial. But if we separate one 
syllable of the word 'human' from the other, it has no meaning; 
similarly in the word 'mouse', the part 'ouse' has no meaning in 
itself, but is merely a sound. In composite words, indeed, the 
parts contribute to the meaning of the whole; yet, as has been 
pointed out, they have not an independent meaning. 

Every sentence has meaning, not as being the natural means by 
which a physical faculty is realized, but, as we have said, by 
convention. Yet every sentence is not a proposition; only such 
are propositions as have in them either truth or falsity. Thus a 
prayer is a sentence, but is neither true nor false. 

Let us therefore dismiss all other types of sentence but the 
proposition, for this last concerns our present inquiry, whereas 
the investigation of the others belongs rather to the study of 
rhetoric or of poetry. 



50 



The first class of simple propositions is the simple affirmation, 
the next, the simple denial; all others are only one by 
conjunction. 

Every proposition must contain a verb or the tense of a verb. 
The phrase which defines the species 'man', if no verb in 
present, past, or future time be added, is not a proposition. It 
may be asked how the expression 'a footed animal with two 
feet' can be called single; for it is not the circumstance that the 
words follow in unbroken succession that effects the unity. This 
inquiry, however, finds its place in an investigation foreign to 
that before us. 

We call those propositions single which indicate a single fact, or 
the conjunction of the parts of which results in unity: those 
propositions, on the other hand, are separate and many in 
number, which indicate many facts, or whose parts have no 
conjunction. 

Let us, moreover, consent to call a noun or a verb an expression 
only, and not a proposition, since it is not possible for a man to 
speak in this way when he is expressing something, in such a 
way as to make a statement, whether his utterance is an 
answer to a question or an act of his own initiation. 

To return: of propositions one kind is simple, i.e. that which 
asserts or denies something of something, the other composite, 
i.e. that which is compounded of simple propositions. A simple 
proposition is a statement, with meaning, as to the presence of 
something in a subject or its absence, in the present, past, or 
future, according to the divisions of time. 



51 



An affirmation is a positive assertion of something about 
something, a denial a negative assertion. 

Now it is possible both to affirm and to deny the presence of 
something which is present or of something which is not, and 
since these same affirmations and denials are possible with 
reference to those times which lie outside the present, it would 
be possible to contradict any affirmation or denial. Thus it is 
plain that every affirmation has an opposite denial, and 
similarly every denial an opposite affirmation. 

We will call such a pair of propositions a pair of contradictories. 
Those positive and negative propositions are said to be 
contradictory which have the same subject and predicate. The 
identity of subject and of predicate must not be 'equivocal'. 
Indeed there are definitive qualifications besides this, which we 
make to meet the casuistries of sophists. 



Some things are universal, others individual. By the term 
'universal' I mean that which is of such a nature as to be 
predicated of many subjects, by 'individual' that which is not 
thus predicated. Thus 'man' is a universal, 'Callias' an 
individual. 

Our propositions necessarily sometimes concern a universal 
subject, sometimes an individual. 

If, then, a man states a positive and a negative proposition of 
universal character with regard to a universal, these two 
propositions are 'contrary'. By the expression 'a proposition of 



52 



universal character with regard to a universal', such 
propositions as 'every man is white', 'no man is white' are 
meant. When, on the other hand, the positive and negative 
propositions, though they have regard to a universal, are yet 
not of universal character, they will not be contrary, albeit the 
meaning intended is sometimes contrary. As instances of 
propositions made with regard to a universal, but not of 
universal character, we may take the 'propositions 'man is 
white', 'man is not white'. 'Man' is a universal, but the 
proposition is not made as of universal character; for the word 
'every' does not make the subject a universal, but rather gives 
the proposition a universal character. If, however, both 
predicate and subject are distributed, the proposition thus 
constituted is contrary to truth; no affirmation will, under such 
circumstances, be true. The proposition 'every man is every 
animal' is an example of this type. 

An affirmation is opposed to a denial in the sense which I 
denote by the term 'contradictory', when, while the subject 
remains the same, the affirmation is of universal character and 
the denial is not. The affirmation 'every man is white' is the 
contradictory of the denial 'not every man is white', or again, 
the proposition 'no man is white' is the contradictory of the 
proposition 'some men are white'. But propositions are opposed 
as contraries when both the affirmation and the denial are 
universal, as in the sentences 'every man is white', 'no man is 
white', 'every man is just', 'no man is just'. 

We see that in a pair of this sort both propositions cannot be 
true, but the contradictories of a pair of contraries can 
sometimes both be true with reference to the same subject; for 
instance 'not every man is white' and some men are white' are 
both true. Of such corresponding positive and negative 
propositions as refer to universals and have a universal 
character, one must be true and the other false. This is the case 



53 



also when the reference is to individuals, as in the propositions 
'Socrates is white', 'Socrates is not white'. 

When, on the other hand, the reference is to universals, but the 
propositions are not universal, it is not always the case that one 
is true and the other false, for it is possible to state truly that 
man is white and that man is not white and that man is 
beautiful and that man is not beautiful; for if a man is deformed 
he is the reverse of beautiful, also if he is progressing towards 
beauty he is not yet beautiful. 

This statement might seem at first sight to carry with it a 
contradiction, owing to the fact that the proposition 'man is not 
white' appears to be equivalent to the proposition 'no man is 
white'. This, however, is not the case, nor are they necessarily 
at the same time true or false. 

It is evident also that the denial corresponding to a single 
affirmation is itself single; for the denial must deny just that 
which the affirmation affirms concerning the same subject, and 
must correspond with the affirmation both in the universal or 
particular character of the subject and in the distributed or 
undistributed sense in which it is understood. 

For instance, the affirmation 'Socrates is white' has its proper 
denial in the proposition 'Socrates is not white'. If anything else 
be negatively predicated of the subject or if anything else be the 
subject though the predicate remain the same, the denial will 
not be the denial proper to that affirmation, but on that is 
distinct. 

The denial proper to the affirmation 'every man is white' is 'not 
every man is white'; that proper to the affirmation 'some men 
are white' is 'no man is white', while that proper to the 
affirmation 'man is white' is 'man is not white'. 



54 



We have shown further that a single denial is contradictorily 
opposite to a single affirmation and we have explained which 
these are; we have also stated that contrary are distinct from 
contradictory propositions and which the contrary are; also that 
with regard to a pair of opposite propositions it is not always 
the case that one is true and the other false. We have pointed 
out, moreover, what the reason of this is and under what 
circumstances the truth of the one involves the falsity of the 
other. 



8 

An affirmation or denial is single, if it indicates some one fact 
about some one subject; it matters not whether the subject is 
universal and whether the statement has a universal character, 
or whether this is not so. Such single propositions are: 'every 
man is white', 'not every man is white';'man is white', 'man is 
not white'; 'no man is white', 'some men are white'; provided 
the word 'white' has one meaning. If, on the other hand, one 
word has two meanings which do not combine to form one, the 
affirmation is not single. For instance, if a man should establish 
the symbol 'garment' as significant both of a horse and of a 
man, the proposition 'garment is white' would not be a single 
affirmation, nor its opposite a single denial. For it is equivalent 
to the proposition 'horse and man are white', which, again, is 
equivalent to the two propositions 'horse is white', 'man is 
white'. If, then, these two propositions have more than a single 
significance, and do not form a single proposition, it is plain 
that the first proposition either has more than one significance 
or else has none; for a particular man is not a horse. 



55 



This, then, is another instance of those propositions of which 
both the positive and the negative forms may be true or false 
simultaneously. 



In the case of that which is or which has taken place, 
propositions, whether positive or negative, must be true or 
false. Again, in the case of a pair of contradictories, either when 
the subject is universal and the propositions are of a universal 
character, or when it is individual, as has been said,' one of the 
two must be true and the other false; whereas when the subject 
is universal, but the propositions are not of a universal 
character, there is no such necessity. We have discussed this 
type also in a previous chapter. 

When the subject, however, is individual, and that which is 
predicated of it relates to the future, the case is altered. For if all 
propositions whether positive or negative are either true or 
false, then any given predicate must either belong to the subject 
or not, so that if one man affirms that an event of a given 
character will take place and another denies it, it is plain that 
the statement of the one will correspond with reality and that 
of the other will not. For the predicate cannot both belong and 
not belong to the subject at one and the same time with regard 
to the future. 

Thus, if it is true to say that a thing is white, it must necessarily 
be white; if the reverse proposition is true, it will of necessity 
not be white. Again, if it is white, the proposition stating that it 
is white was true; if it is not white, the proposition to the 
opposite effect was true. And if it is not white, the man who 
states that it is making a false statement; and if the man who 



56 



states that it is white is making a false statement, it follows that 
it is not white. It may therefore be argued that it is necessary 
that affirmations or denials must be either true or false. 

Now if this be so, nothing is or takes place fortuitously, either in 
the present or in the future, and there are no real alternatives; 
everything takes place of necessity and is fixed. For either he 
that affirms that it will take place or he that denies this is in 
correspondence with fact, whereas if things did not take place 
of necessity, an event might just as easily not happen as 
happen; for the meaning of the word 'fortuitous' with regard to 
present or future events is that reality is so constituted that it 
may issue in either of two opposite directions. Again, if a thing 
is white now, it was true before to say that it would be white, so 
that of anything that has taken place it was always true to say 
'it is' or 'it will be'. But if it was always true to say that a thing is 
or will be, it is not possible that it should not be or not be about 
to be, and when a thing cannot not come to be, it is impossible 
that it should not come to be, and when it is impossible that it 
should not come to be, it must come to be. All, then, that is 
about to be must of necessity take place. It results from this 
that nothing is uncertain or fortuitous, for if it were fortuitous it 
would not be necessary. 

Again, to say that neither the affirmation nor the denial is true, 
maintaining, let us say, that an event neither will take place nor 
will not take place, is to take up a position impossible to defend. 
In the first place, though facts should prove the one proposition 
false, the opposite would still be untrue. Secondly, if it was true 
to say that a thing was both white and large, both these 
qualities must necessarily belong to it; and if they will belong to 
it the next day, they must necessarily belong to it the next day. 
But if an event is neither to take place nor not to take place the 
next day, the element of chance will be eliminated. For 



57 



example, it would be necessary that a sea-fight should neither 
take place nor fail to take place on the next day. 

These awkward results and others of the same kind follow, if it 
is an irrefragable law that of every pair of contradictory 
propositions, whether they have regard to universals and are 
stated as universally applicable, or whether they have regard to 
individuals, one must be true and the other false, and that there 
are no real alternatives, but that all that is or takes place is the 
outcome of necessity. There would be no need to deliberate or 
to take trouble, on the supposition that if we should adopt a 
certain course, a certain result would follow, while, if we did 
not, the result would not follow. For a man may predict an 
event ten thousand years beforehand, and another may predict 
the reverse; that which was truly predicted at the moment in 
the past will of necessity take place in the fullness of time. 

Further, it makes no difference whether people have or have 
not actually made the contradictory statements. For it is 
manifest that the circumstances are not influenced by the fact 
of an affirmation or denial on the part of anyone. For events 
will not take place or fail to take place because it was stated 
that they would or would not take place, nor is this any more 
the case if the prediction dates back ten thousand years or any 
other space of time. Wherefore, if through all time the nature of 
things was so constituted that a prediction about an event was 
true, then through all time it was necessary that that should 
find fulfillment; and with regard to all events, circumstances 
have always been such that their occurrence is a matter of 
necessity. For that of which someone has said truly that it will 
be, cannot fail to take place; and of that which takes place, it 
was always true to say that it would be. 

Yet this view leads to an impossible conclusion; for we see that 
both deliberation and action are causative with regard to the 



58 



future, and that, to speak more generally, in those things which 
are not continuously actual there is potentiality in either 
direction. Such things may either be or not be; events also 
therefore may either take place or not take place. There are 
many obvious instances of this. It is possible that this coat may 
be cut in half, and yet it may not be cut in half, but wear out 
first. In the same way, it is possible that it should not be cut in 
half; unless this were so, it would not be possible that it should 
wear out first. So it is therefore with all other events which 
possess this kind of potentiality. It is therefore plain that it is 
not of necessity that everything is or takes place; but in some 
instances there are real alternatives, in which case the 
affirmation is no more true and no more false than the denial; 
while some exhibit a predisposition and general tendency in 
one direction or the other, and yet can issue in the opposite 
direction by exception. 

Now that which is must needs be when it is, and that which is 
not must needs not be when it is not. Yet it cannot be said 
without qualification that all existence and non-existence is the 
outcome of necessity. For there is a difference between saying 
that that which is, when it is, must needs be, and simply saying 
that all that is must needs be, and similarly in the case of that 
which is not. In the case, also, of two contradictory propositions 
this holds good. Everything must either be or not be, whether in 
the present or in the future, but it is not always possible to 
distinguish and state determinately which of these alternatives 
must necessarily come about. 

Let me illustrate. A sea-fight must either take place to-morrow 
or not, but it is not necessary that it should take place to- 
morrow, neither is it necessary that it should not take place, yet 
it is necessary that it either should or should not take place to- 
morrow. Since propositions correspond with facts, it is evident 
that when in future events there is a real alternative, and a 



59 



potentiality in contrary directions, the corresponding 
affirmation and denial have the same character. 

This is the case with regard to that which is not always existent 
or not always nonexistent. One of the two propositions in such 
instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say 
determinately that this or that is false, but must leave the 
alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true 
than the other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually 
false. It is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of an 
affirmation and a denial one should be true and the other false. 
For in the case of that which exists potentially, but not actually, 
the rule which applies to that which exists actually does not 
hold good. The case is rather as we have indicated. 



10 

An affirmation is the statement of a fact with regard to a 
subject, and this subject is either a noun or that which has no 
name; the subject and predicate in an affirmation must each 
denote a single thing. I have already explained' what is meant 
by a noun and by that which has no name; for I stated that the 
expression 'not-man' was not a noun, in the proper sense of the 
word, but an indefinite noun, denoting as it does in a certain 
sense a single thing. Similarly the expression 'does not enjoy 
health' is not a verb proper, but an indefinite verb. Every 
affirmation, then, and every denial, will consist of a noun and a 
verb, either definite or indefinite. 

There can be no affirmation or denial without a verb; for the 
expressions 'is', 'will be', 'was', 'is coming to be', and the like 
are verbs according to our definition, since besides their specific 
meaning they convey the notion of time. Thus the primary 



60 



affirmation and denial are 'as follows: 'man is', 'man is not'. 
Next to these, there are the propositions: 'not-man is', 'not-man 
is not'. Again we have the propositions: 'every man is, 'every 
man is not', 'all that is not-man is', 'all that is not-man is not'. 
The same classification holds good with regard to such periods 
of time as lie outside the present. 

When the verb 'is' is used as a third element in the sentence, 
there can be positive and negative propositions of two sorts. 
Thus in the sentence 'man is just' the verb 'is' is used as a third 
element, call it verb or noun, which you will. Four propositions, 
therefore, instead of two can be formed with these materials. 
Two of the four, as regards their affirmation and denial, 
correspond in their logical sequence with the propositions 
which deal with a condition of privation; the other two do not 
correspond with these. 

I mean that the verb 'is' is added either to the term 'just' or to 
the term 'not-just', and two negative propositions are formed in 
the same way. Thus we have the four propositions. Reference to 
the subjoined table will make matters clear: 



A. Affirmation 



B. Denial 



Man is just 



Man is not just 



D. Denial 



C. Affirmation 



Man is not not-just Man is not-just 



Here 'is' and 'is not' are added either to 'just' or to 'not-just' 



61 



This then is the proper scheme for these propositions, as has 
been said in the Analytics. The same rule holds good, if the 
subject is distributed. Thus we have the table: 



A'. Affirmation 



Every man is just 



B\ Denial 

Not every man 
is just 



D\ Denial 

Not every man is 
not-just 



C. Affirmation 

Every man is 
not-just 



Yet here it is not possible, in the same way as in the former 
case, that the propositions joined in the table by a diagonal line 
should both be true; though under certain circumstances this is 
the case. 

We have thus set out two pairs of opposite propositions; there 
are moreover two other pairs, if a term be conjoined with 'not- 
man', the latter forming a kind of subject. Thus: 



A". Not-man is just 



B". Not-man is not 
just 



D". Not-man is not 
not-just 



C". Not-man is not- 
just 



62 



This is an exhaustive enumeration of all the pairs of opposite 
propositions that can possibly be framed. This last group should 
remain distinct from those which preceded it, since it employs 
as its subject the expression 'not-man'. 

When the verb 'is' does not fit the structure of the sentence (for 
instance, when the verbs 'walks', 'enjoys health' are used), that 
scheme applies, which applied when the word 'is' was added. 

Thus we have the propositions: 'every man enjoys health', 
'every man does-not-enjoy-health', 'all that is not-man enjoys 
health', 'all that is not-man does-not-enjoy-health'. We must 
not in these propositions use the expression 'not every man'. 
The negative must be attached to the word 'man', for the word 
'every' does not give to the subject a universal significance, but 
implies that, as a subject, it is distributed. This is plain from the 
following pairs: 'man enjoys health', 'man does not enjoy 
health'; 'not-man enjoys health', 'not man does not enjoy 
health'. These propositions differ from the former in being 
indefinite and not universal in character. Thus the adjectives 
'every' and no additional significance except that the subject, 
whether in a positive or in a negative sentence, is distributed. 
The rest of the sentence, therefore, will in each case be the 
same. 

Since the contrary of the proposition 'every animal is just' is 'no 
animal is just', it is plain that these two propositions will never 
both be true at the same time or with reference to the same 
subject. Sometimes, however, the contradictories of these 
contraries will both be true, as in the instance before us: the 
propositions 'not every animal is just' and 'some animals are 
just' are both true. 



63 



Further, the proposition 'no man is just' follows from the 
proposition 'every man is not just' and the proposition 'not 
every man is not just', which is the opposite of 'every man is 
not-just', follows from the proposition 'some men are just'; for 
if this be true, there must be some just men. 

It is evident, also, that when the subject is individual, if a 
question is asked and the negative answer is the true one, a 
certain positive proposition is also true. Thus, if the question 
were asked Socrates wise?' and the negative answer were the 
true one, the positive inference 'Then Socrates is unwise' is 
correct. But no such inference is correct in the case of 
universals, but rather a negative proposition. For instance, if to 
the question 'Is every man wise?' the answer is 'no', the 
inference 'Then every man is unwise' is false. But under these 
circumstances the inference 'Not every man is wise' is correct. 
This last is the contradictory, the former the contrary. Negative 
expressions, which consist of an indefinite noun or predicate, 
such as 'not-man' or 'not-just', may seem to be denials 
containing neither noun nor verb in the proper sense of the 
words. But they are not. For a denial must always be either true 
or false, and he that uses the expression 'not man', if nothing 
more be added, is not nearer but rather further from making a 
true or a false statement than he who uses the expression 
'man'. 

The propositions 'everything that is not man is just', and the 
contradictory of this, are not equivalent to any of the other 
propositions; on the other hand, the proposition 'everything 
that is not man is not just' is equivalent to the proposition 
'nothing that is not man is just'. 

The conversion of the position of subject and predicate in a 
sentence involves no difference in its meaning. Thus we say 
'man is white' and 'white is man'. If these were not equivalent, 



64 



there would be more than one contradictory to the same 
proposition, whereas it has been demonstrated' that each 
proposition has one proper contradictory and one only. For of 
the proposition 'man is white' the appropriate contradictory is 
'man is not white', and of the proposition 'white is man', if its 
meaning be different, the contradictory will either be 'white is 
not not-man' or 'white is not man'. Now the former of these is 
the contradictory of the proposition 'white is not-man', and the 
latter of these is the contradictory of the proposition 'man is 
white'; thus there will be two contradictories to one 
proposition. 

It is evident, therefore, that the inversion of the relative 
position of subject and predicate does not affect the sense of 
affirmations and denials. 



11 

There is no unity about an affirmation or denial which, either 
positively or negatively, predicates one thing of many subjects, 
or many things of the same subject, unless that which is 
indicated by the many is really some one thing, do not apply 
this word 'one' to those things which, though they have a single 
recognized name, yet do not combine to form a unity. Thus, 
man may be an animal, and biped, and domesticated, but these 
three predicates combine to form a unity. On the other hand, 
the predicates 'white', 'man', and 'walking' do not thus 
combine. Neither, therefore, if these three form the subject of 
an affirmation, nor if they form its predicate, is there any unity 
about that affirmation. In both cases the unity is linguistic, but 
not real. 



65 



If therefore the dialectical question is a request for an answer, 
i.e. either for the admission of a premiss or for the admission of 
one of two contradictories - and the premiss is itself always one 
of two contradictories - the answer to such a question as 
contains the above predicates cannot be a single proposition. 
For as I have explained in the Topics, question is not a single 
one, even if the answer asked for is true. 

At the same time it is plain that a question of the form 'what is 
it?' is not a dialectical question, for a dialectical questioner 
must by the form of his question give his opponent the chance 
of announcing one of two alternatives, whichever he wishes. He 
must therefore put the question into a more definite form, and 
inquire, e.g.. whether man has such and such a characteristic or 
not. 

Some combinations of predicates are such that the separate 
predicates unite to form a single predicate. Let us consider 
under what conditions this is and is not possible. We may 
either state in two separate propositions that man is an animal 
and that man is a biped, or we may combine the two, and state 
that man is an animal with two feet. Similarly we may use 
'man' and 'white' as separate predicates, or unite them into 
one. Yet if a man is a shoemaker and is also good, we cannot 
construct a composite proposition and say that he is a good 
shoemaker. For if, whenever two separate predicates truly 
belong to a subject, it follows that the predicate resulting from 
their combination also truly belongs to the subject, many 
absurd results ensue. For instance, a man is man and white. 
Therefore, if predicates may always be combined, he is a white 
man. Again, if the predicate 'white' belongs to him, then the 
combination of that predicate with the former composite 
predicate will be permissible. Thus it will be right to say that he 
is a white man so on indefinitely. Or, again, we may combine 
the predicates 'musical', 'white', and 'walking', and these may 



66 



be combined many times. Similarly we may say that Socrates is 
Socrates and a man, and that therefore he is the man Socrates, 
or that Socrates is a man and a biped, and that therefore he is a 
two-footed man. Thus it is manifest that if man states 
unconditionally that predicates can always be combined, many 
absurd consequences ensue. 

We will now explain what ought to be laid down. 

Those predicates, and terms forming the subject of predication, 
which are accidental either to the same subject or to one 
another, do not combine to form a unity. Take the proposition 
'man is white of complexion and musical'. Whiteness and being 
musical do not coalesce to form a unity, for they belong only 
accidentally to the same subject. Nor yet, if it were true to say 
that that which is white is musical, would the terms 'musical' 
and 'white' form a unity, for it is only incidentally that that 
which is musical is white; the combination of the two will, 
therefore, not form a unity. 

Thus, again, whereas, if a man is both good and a shoemaker, 
we cannot combine the two propositions and say simply that he 
is a good shoemaker, we are, at the same time, able to combine 
the predicates 'animal' and 'biped' and say that a man is an 
animal with two feet, for these predicates are not accidental. 

Those predicates, again, cannot form a unity, of which the one 
is implicit in the other: thus we cannot combine the predicate 
'white' again and again with that which already contains the 
notion 'white', nor is it right to call a man an animal-man or a 
two-footed man; for the notions 'animal' and 'biped' are 
implicit in the word 'man'. On the other hand, it is possible to 
predicate a term simply of any one instance, and to say that 
some one particular man is a man or that some one white man 
is a white man. 



67 



Yet this is not always possible: indeed, when in the adjunct 
there is some opposite which involves a contradiction, the 
predication of the simple term is impossible. Thus it is not right 
to call a dead man a man. When, however, this is not the case, 
it is not impossible. 

Yet the facts of the case might rather be stated thus: when 
some such opposite elements are present, resolution is never 
possible, but when they are not present, resolution is 
nevertheless not always possible. Take the proposition 'Homer 
is so-and-so', say 'a poet'; does it follow that Homer is, or does 
it not? The verb 'is' is here used of Homer only incidentally, the 
proposition being that Homer is a poet, not that he is, in the 
independent sense of the word. 

Thus, in the case of those predications which have within them 
no contradiction when the nouns are expanded into definitions, 
and wherein the predicates belong to the subject in their own 
proper sense and not in any indirect way, the individual may be 
the subject of the simple propositions as well as of the 
composite. But in the case of that which is not, it is not true to 
say that because it is the object of opinion, it is; for the opinion 
held about it is that it is not, not that it is. 



12 

As these distinctions have been made, we must consider the 
mutual relation of those affirmations and denials which assert 
or deny possibility or contingency, impossibility or necessity: 
for the subject is not without difficulty. 

We admit that of composite expressions those are contradictory 
each to each which have the verb 'to be' its positive and 



68 



negative form respectively. Thus the contradictory of the 
proposition 'man is' is 'man is not', not 'not-man is', and the 
contradictory of 'man is white' is 'man is not white', not 'man is 
not-white'. For otherwise, since either the positive or the 
negative proposition is true of any subject, it will turn out true 
to say that a piece of wood is a man that is not white. 

Now if this is the case, in those propositions which do not 
contain the verb 'to be' the verb which takes its place will 
exercise the same function. Thus the contradictory of 'man 
walks' is 'man does not walk', not 'not-man walks'; for to say 
'man walks' merely equivalent to saying 'man is walking'. 

If then this rule is universal, the contradictory of 'it may be' is 
may not be', not 'it cannot be'. 

Now it appears that the same thing both may and may not be; 
for instance, everything that may be cut or may walk may also 
escape cutting and refrain from walking; and the reason is that 
those things that have potentiality in this sense are not always 
actual. In such cases, both the positive and the negative 
propositions will be true; for that which is capable of walking or 
of being seen has also a potentiality in the opposite direction. 

But since it is impossible that contradictory propositions should 
both be true of the same subject, it follows that' it may not be' 
is not the contradictory of 'it may be'. For it is a logical 
consequence of what we have said, either that the same 
predicate can be both applicable and inapplicable to one and 
the same subject at the same time, or that it is not by the 
addition of the verbs 'be' and 'not be', respectively, that positive 
and negative propositions are formed. If the former of these 
alternatives must be rejected, we must choose the latter. 

The contradictory, then, of 'it may be' is 'it cannot be'. The 
same rule applies to the proposition 'it is contingent that it 



69 



should be'; the contradictory of this is 'it is not contingent that 
it should be'. The similar propositions, such as 'it is necessary' 
and 'it is impossible', may be dealt with in the same manner. 
For it comes about that just as in the former instances the verbs 
'is' and 'is not' were added to the subject-matter of the 
sentence 'white' and 'man', so here 'that it should be' and 'that 
it should not be' are the subject-matter and 'is possible', 'is 
contingent', are added. These indicate that a certain thing is or 
is not possible, just as in the former instances 'is' and 'is not' 
indicated that certain things were or were not the case. 

The contradictory, then, of 'it may not be' is not 'it cannot be', 
but 'it cannot not be', and the contradictory of 'it may be' is not 
'it may not be', but cannot be'. Thus the propositions 'it may be' 
and 'it may not be' appear each to imply the other: for, since 
these two propositions are not contradictory, the same thing 
both may and may not be. But the propositions 'it may be' and 
'it cannot be' can never be true of the same subject at the same 
time, for they are contradictory. Nor can the propositions 'it 
may not be' and 'it cannot not be' be at once true of the same 
subject. 

The propositions which have to do with necessity are governed 
by the same principle. The contradictory of 'it is necessary that 
it should be', is not 'it is necessary that it should not be,' but 'it 
is not necessary that it should be', and the contradictory of 'it is 
necessary that it should not be' is 'it is not necessary that it 
should not be'. 

Again, the contradictory of 'it is impossible that it should be' is 
not 'it is impossible that it should not be' but 'it is not 
impossible that it should be', and the contradictory of 'it is 
impossible that it should not be' is 'it is not impossible that it 
should not be'. 



70 



To generalize, we must, as has been stated, define the clauses 
'that it should be' and 'that it should not be' as the subject- 
matter of the propositions, and in making these terms into 
affirmations and denials we must combine them with 'that it 
should be' and 'that it should not be' respectively. 

We must consider the following pairs as contradictory 
propositions: 

It may be. It cannot be. 

It is contingent.lt is not contingent. 

It is impossible.lt is not impossible. 

It is necessary.lt is not necessary. 

It is true. It is not true. 



13 

Logical sequences follow in due course when we have arranged 
the propositions thus. From the proposition 'it may be' it 
follows that it is contingent, and the relation is reciprocal. It 
follows also that it is not impossible and not necessary. 

From the proposition 'it may not be' or 'it is contingent that it 
should not be' it follows that it is not necessary that it should 
not be and that it is not impossible that it should not be. From 
the proposition 'it cannot be' or 'it is not contingent' it follows 
that it is necessary that it should not be and that it is 
impossible that it should be. From the proposition 'it cannot not 
be' or 'it is not contingent that it should not be' it follows that it 



71 



is necessary that it should be and that it is impossible that it 
should not be. 

Let us consider these statements by the help of a table: 



A. B. 

It may be. It cannot be. 

It is contingent. It is not contingent. 

It is not impossible that it It is impossible that it should 

should be. be. 

It is not necessary that it It is necessary that it should 

should be. not be. 



C. D. 

It may not be. It cannot not be. 

It is contingent that it should It is not contingent that it 

not be. should not be. 

It is not impossible that it It is impossible that it should 

should not be. not be. 

It is not necessary that it It is necessary that it should 

should not be. be. 



Now the propositions 'it is impossible that it should be' and 'it 
is not impossible that it should be' are consequent upon the 
propositions 'it may be', 'it is contingent', and 'it cannot be', 'it 
is not contingent', the contradictories upon the contradictories. 



72 



But there is inversion. The negative of the proposition 'it is 
impossible' is consequent upon the proposition 'it may be' and 
the corresponding positive in the first case upon the negative in 
the second. For 'it is impossible' is a positive proposition and 'it 
is not impossible' is negative. 

We must investigate the relation subsisting between these 
propositions and those which predicate necessity. That there is 
a distinction is clear. In this case, contrary propositions follow 
respectively from contradictory propositions, and the 
contradictory propositions belong to separate sequences. For 
the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should be' is not the 
negative of 'it is necessary that it should not be', for both these 
propositions may be true of the same subject; for when it is 
necessary that a thing should not be, it is not necessary that it 
should be. The reason why the propositions predicating 
necessity do not follow in the same kind of sequence as the 
rest, lies in the fact that the proposition 'it is impossible' is 
equivalent, when used with a contrary subject, to the 
proposition 'it is necessary'. For when it is impossible that a 
thing should be, it is necessary, not that it should be, but that it 
should not be, and when it is impossible that a thing should not 
be, it is necessary that it should be. Thus, if the propositions 
predicating impossibility or non-impossibility follow without 
change of subject from those predicating possibility or non- 
possibility, those predicating necessity must follow with the 
contrary subject; for the propositions 'it is impossible' and 'it is 
necessary' are not equivalent, but, as has been said, inversely 
connected. 

Yet perhaps it is impossible that the contradictory propositions 
predicating necessity should be thus arranged. For when it is 
necessary that a thing should be, it is possible that it should be. 
(For if not, the opposite follows, since one or the other must 
follow; so, if it is not possible, it is impossible, and it is thus 



73 



impossible that a thing should be, which must necessarily be; 
which is absurd.) 

Yet from the proposition 'it may be' it follows that it is not 
impossible, and from that it follows that it is not necessary; it 
comes about therefore that the thing which must necessarily be 
need not be; which is absurd. But again, the proposition 'it is 
necessary that it should be' does not follow from the 
proposition 'it may be', nor does the proposition 'it is necessary 
that it should not be'. For the proposition 'it may be' implies a 
twofold possibility, while, if either of the two former 
propositions is true, the twofold possibility vanishes. For if a 
thing may be, it may also not be, but if it is necessary that it 
should be or that it should not be, one of the two alternatives 
will be excluded. It remains, therefore, that the proposition 'it is 
not necessary that it should not be' follows from the 
proposition 'it may be'. For this is true also of that which must 
necessarily be. 

Moreover the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not 
be' is the contradictory of that which follows from the 
proposition 'it cannot be'; for 'it cannot be' is followed by 'it is 
impossible that it should be' and by 'it is necessary that it 
should not be', and the contradictory of this is the proposition 
'it is not necessary that it should not be'. Thus in this case also 
contradictory propositions follow contradictory in the way 
indicated, and no logical impossibilities occur when they are 
thus arranged. 

It may be questioned whether the proposition 'it may be' 
follows from the proposition 'it is necessary that it should be'. If 
not, the contradictory must follow, namely that it cannot be, or, 
if a man should maintain that this is not the contradictory, then 
the proposition 'it may not be'. 



74 



Now both of these are false of that which necessarily is. At the 
same time, it is thought that if a thing may be cut it may also 
not be cut, if a thing may be it may also not be, and thus it 
would follow that a thing which must necessarily be may 
possibly not be; which is false. It is evident, then, that it is not 
always the case that that which may be or may walk possesses 
also a potentiality in the other direction. There are exceptions. 
In the first place we must except those things which possess a 
potentiality not in accordance with a rational principle, as fire 
possesses the potentiality of giving out heat, that is, an 
irrational capacity. Those potentialities which involve a rational 
principle are potentialities of more than one result, that is, of 
contrary results; those that are irrational are not always thus 
constituted. As I have said, fire cannot both heat and not heat, 
neither has anything that is always actual any twofold 
potentiality. Yet some even of those potentialities which are 
irrational admit of opposite results. However, thus much has 
been said to emphasize the truth that it is not every potentiality 
which admits of opposite results, even where the word is used 
always in the same sense. 

But in some cases the word is used equivocally. For the term 
'possible' is ambiguous, being used in the one case with 
reference to facts, to that which is actualized, as when a man is 
said to find walking possible because he is actually walking, 
and generally when a capacity is predicated because it is 
actually realized; in the other case, with reference to a state in 
which realization is conditionally practicable, as when a man is 
said to find walking possible because under certain conditions 
he would walk. This last sort of potentiality belongs only to that 
which can be in motion, the former can exist also in the case of 
that which has not this power. Both of that which is walking 
and is actual, and of that which has the capacity though not 
necessarily realized, it is true to say that it is not impossible 
that it should walk (or, in the other case, that it should be), but 



75 



while we cannot predicate this latter kind of potentiality of that 
which is necessary in the unqualified sense of the word, we can 
predicate the former. 

Our conclusion, then, is this: that since the universal is 
consequent upon the particular, that which is necessary is also 
possible, though not in every sense in which the word may be 
used. 

We may perhaps state that necessity and its absence are the 
initial principles of existence and non-existence, and that all 
else must be regarded as posterior to these. 

It is plain from what has been said that that which is of 
necessity is actual. Thus, if that which is eternal is prior, 
actuality also is prior to potentiality. Some things are actualities 
without potentiality, namely, the primary substances; a second 
class consists of those things which are actual but also 
potential, whose actuality is in nature prior to their potentiality, 
though posterior in time; a third class comprises those things 
which are never actualized, but are pure potentialities. 



14 

The question arises whether an affirmation finds its contrary in 
a denial or in another affirmation; whether the proposition 
'every man is just' finds its contrary in the proposition 'no man 
is just', or in the proposition 'every man is unjust'. Take the 
propositions 'Callias is just', 'Callias is not just', 'Callias is 
unjust'; we have to discover which of these form contraries. 

Now if the spoken word corresponds with the judgement of the 
mind, and if, in thought, that judgement is the contrary of 



76 



another, which pronounces a contrary fact, in the way, for 
instance, in which the judgement 'every man is just' 
pronounces a contrary to that pronounced by the judgement 
'every man is unjust', the same must needs hold good with 
regard to spoken affirmations. 

But if, in thought, it is not the judgement which pronounces a 
contrary fact that is the contrary of another, then one 
affirmation will not find its contrary in another, but rather in 
the corresponding denial. We must therefore consider which 
true judgement is the contrary of the false, that which forms 
the denial of the false judgement or that which affirms the 
contrary fact. 

Let me illustrate. There is a true judgement concerning that 
which is good, that it is good; another, a false judgement, that it 
is not good; and a third, which is distinct, that it is bad. Which 
of these two is contrary to the true? And if they are one and the 
same, which mode of expression forms the contrary? 

It is an error to suppose that judgements are to be defined as 
contrary in virtue of the fact that they have contrary subjects; 
for the judgement concerning a good thing, that it is good, and 
that concerning a bad thing, that it is bad, may be one and the 
same, and whether they are so or not, they both represent the 
truth. Yet the subjects here are contrary. But judgements are 
not contrary because they have contrary subjects, but because 
they are to the contrary effect. 

Now if we take the judgement that that which is good is good, 
and another that it is not good, and if there are at the same 
time other attributes, which do not and cannot belong to the 
good, we must nevertheless refuse to treat as the contraries of 
the true judgement those which opine that some other attribute 
subsists which does not subsist, as also those that opine that 



77 



some other attribute does not subsist which does subsist, for 
both these classes of judgement are of unlimited content. 

Those judgements must rather be termed contrary to the true 
judgements, in which error is present. Now these judgements 
are those which are concerned with the starting points of 
generation, and generation is the passing from one extreme to 
its opposite; therefore error is a like transition. 

Now that which is good is both good and not bad. The first 
quality is part of its essence, the second accidental; for it is by 
accident that it is not bad. But if that true judgement is most 
really true, which concerns the subject's intrinsic nature, then 
that false judgement likewise is most really false, which 
concerns its intrinsic nature. Now the judgement that that is 
good is not good is a false judgement concerning its intrinsic 
nature, the judgement that it is bad is one concerning that 
which is accidental. Thus the judgement which denies the true 
judgement is more really false than that which positively 
asserts the presence of the contrary quality. But it is the man 
who forms that judgement which is contrary to the true who is 
most thoroughly deceived, for contraries are among the things 
which differ most widely within the same class. If then of the 
two judgements one is contrary to the true judgement, but that 
which is contradictory is the more truly contrary, then the 
latter, it seems, is the real contrary. The judgement that that 
which is good is bad is composite. For presumably the man who 
forms that judgement must at the same time understand that 
that which is good is not good. 

Further, the contradictory is either always the contrary or 
never; therefore, if it must necessarily be so in all other cases, 
our conclusion in the case just dealt with would seem to be 
correct. Now where terms have no contrary, that judgement is 
false, which forms the negative of the true; for instance, he who 



78 



thinks a man is not a man forms a false judgement. If then in 
these cases the negative is the contrary, then the principle is 
universal in its application. 

Again, the judgement that that which is not good is not good is 
parallel with the judgement that that which is good is good. 
Besides these there is the judgement that that which is good is 
not good, parallel with the judgement that that that is not good 
is good. Let us consider, therefore, what would form the 
contrary of the true judgement that that which is not good is 
not good. The judgement that it is bad would, of course, fail to 
meet the case, since two true judgements are never contrary 
and this judgement might be true at the same time as that with 
which it is connected. For since some things which are not good 
are bad, both judgements may be true. Nor is the judgement 
that it is not bad the contrary, for this too might be true, since 
both qualities might be predicated of the same subject. It 
remains, therefore, that of the judgement concerning that 
which is not good, that it is not good, the contrary judgement is 
that it is good; for this is false. In the same way, moreover, the 
judgement concerning that which is good, that it is not good, is 
the contrary of the judgement that it is good. 

It is evident that it will make no difference if we universalize 
the positive judgement, for the universal negative judgement 
will form the contrary. For instance, the contrary of the 
judgement that everything that is good is good is that nothing 
that is good is good. For the judgement that that which is good 
is good, if the subject be understood in a universal sense, is 
equivalent to the judgement that whatever is good is good, and 
this is identical with the judgement that everything that is good 
is good. We may deal similarly with judgements concerning 
that which is not good. 



79 



If therefore this is the rule with judgements, and if spoken 
affirmations and denials are judgements expressed in words, it 
is plain that the universal denial is the contrary of the 
affirmation about the same subject. Thus the propositions 
'everything good is good', 'every man is good', have for their 
contraries the propositions 'nothing good is good', 'no man is 
good'. The contradictory propositions, on the other hand, are 
'not everything good is good', 'not every man is good'. 

It is evident, also, that neither true judgements nor true 
propositions can be contrary the one to the other. For whereas, 
when two propositions are true, a man may state both at the 
same time without inconsistency, contrary propositions are 
those which state contrary conditions, and contrary conditions 
cannot subsist at one and the same time in the same subject. 



80 



Aristotle - Prior Analytics 
[Translated by A. J. Jenkinson] 



Book I 



We must first state the subject of our inquiry and the faculty to 
which it belongs: its subject is demonstration and the faculty 
that carries it out demonstrative science. We must next define a 
premiss, a term, and a syllogism, and the nature of a perfect 
and of an imperfect syllogism; and after that, the inclusion or 
noninclusion of one term in another as in a whole, and what we 
mean by predicating one term of all, or none, of another. 

A premiss then is a sentence affirming or denying one thing of 
another. This is either universal or particular or indefinite. By 
universal I mean the statement that something belongs to all or 
none of something else; by particular that it belongs to some or 
not to some or not to all; by indefinite that it does or does not 
belong, without any mark to show whether it is universal or 
particular, e.g. 'contraries are subjects of the same science', or 
'pleasure is not good'. The demonstrative premiss differs from 
the dialectical, because the demonstrative premiss is the 
assertion of one of two contradictory statements (the 
demonstrator does not ask for his premiss, but lays it down), 
whereas the dialectical premiss depends on the adversary's 
choice between two contradictories. But this will make no 
difference to the production of a syllogism in either case; for 
both the demonstrator and the dialectician argue syllogistically 
after stating that something does or does not belong to 



81 



something else. Therefore a syllogistic premiss without 
qualification will be an affirmation or denial of something 
concerning something else in the way we have described; it will 
be demonstrative, if it is true and obtained through the first 
principles of its science; while a dialectical premiss is the giving 
of a choice between two contradictories, when a man is 
proceeding by question, but when he is syllogizing it is the 
assertion of that which is apparent and generally admitted, as 
has been said in the Topics. The nature then of a premiss and 
the difference between syllogistic, demonstrative, and 
dialectical premisses, may be taken as sufficiently defined by us 
in relation to our present need, but will be stated accurately in 
the sequel. 

I call that a term into which the premiss is resolved, i.e. both the 
predicate and that of which it is predicated, 'being' being added 
and 'not being' removed, or vice versa. 

A syllogism is discourse in which, certain things being stated, 
something other than what is stated follows of necessity from 
their being so. I mean by the last phrase that they produce the 
consequence, and by this, that no further term is required from 
without in order to make the consequence necessary. 

I call that a perfect syllogism which needs nothing other than 
what has been stated to make plain what necessarily follows; a 
syllogism is imperfect, if it needs either one or more 
propositions, which are indeed the necessary consequences of 
the terms set down, but have not been expressly stated as 
premisses. 

That one term should be included in another as in a whole is 
the same as for the other to be predicated of all of the first. And 
we say that one term is predicated of all of another, whenever 
no instance of the subject can be found of which the other term 



82 



cannot be asserted: 'to be predicated of none' must be 
understood in the same way. 



Every premiss states that something either is or must be or may 
be the attribute of something else; of premisses of these three 
kinds some are affirmative, others negative, in respect of each 
of the three modes of attribution; again some affirmative and 
negative premisses are universal, others particular, others 
indefinite. It is necessary then that in universal attribution the 
terms of the negative premiss should be convertible, e.g. if no 
pleasure is good, then no good will be pleasure; the terms of the 
affirmative must be convertible, not however, universally, but in 
part, e.g. if every pleasure, is good, some good must be pleasure; 
the particular affirmative must convert in part (for if some 
pleasure is good, then some good will be pleasure); but the 
particular negative need not convert, for if some animal is not 
man, it does not follow that some man is not animal. 

First then take a universal negative with the terms A and B. If no 
B is A, neither can any A be B. For if some A (say C) were B, it 
would not be true that no B is A; for C is a B. But if every B is A 
then some A is B. For if no A were B, then no B could be A. But 
we assumed that every B is A. Similarly too, if the premiss is 
particular. For if some B is A, then some of the As must be B. For 
if none were, then no B would be A. But if some B is not A, there 
is no necessity that some of the As should not be B; e.g. let B 
stand for animal and A for man. Not every animal is a man; but 
every man is an animal. 



83 



The same manner of conversion will hold good also in respect 
of necessary premisses. The universal negative converts 
universally; each of the affirmatives converts into a particular. If 
it is necessary that no B is A, it is necessary also that no A is B. 
For if it is possible that some A is B, it would be possible also 
that some B is A. If all or some B is A of necessity, it is necessary 
also that some A is B: for if there were no necessity, neither 
would some of the Bs be A necessarily. But the particular 
negative does not convert, for the same reason which we have 
already stated. 

In respect of possible premisses, since possibility is used in 
several senses (for we say that what is necessary and what is 
not necessary and what is potential is possible), affirmative 
statements will all convert in a manner similar to those 
described. For if it is possible that all or some B is A, it will be 
possible that some A is B. For if that were not possible, then no 
B could possibly be A. This has been already proved. But in 
negative statements the case is different. Whatever is said to be 
possible, either because B necessarily is A, or because B is not 
necessarily A, admits of conversion like other negative 
statements, e.g. if one should say, it is possible that man is not 
horse, or that no garment is white. For in the former case the 
one term necessarily does not belong to the other; in the latter 
there is no necessity that it should: and the premiss converts 
like other negative statements. For if it is possible for no man to 
be a horse, it is also admissible for no horse to be a man; and if 
it is admissible for no garment to be white, it is also admissible 
for nothing white to be a garment. For if any white thing must 
be a garment, then some garment will necessarily be white. This 
has been already proved. The particular negative also must be 



84 



treated like those dealt with above. But if anything is said to be 
possible because it is the general rule and natural (and it is in 
this way we define the possible), the negative premisses can no 
longer be converted like the simple negatives; the universal 
negative premiss does not convert, and the particular does. This 
will be plain when we speak about the possible. At present we 
may take this much as clear in addition to what has been said: 
the statement that it is possible that no B is A or some B is not A 
is affirmative in form: for the expression 'is possible' ranks 
along with 'is', and 'is' makes an affirmation always and in 
every case, whatever the terms to which it is added, in 
predication, e.g. 'it is not-good' or 'it is not-white' or in a word 'it 
is not-this'. But this also will be proved in the sequel. In 
conversion these premisses will behave like the other 
affirmative propositions. 



After these distinctions we now state by what means, when, 
and how every syllogism is produced; subsequently we must 
speak of demonstration. Syllogism should be discussed before 
demonstration because syllogism is the general: the 
demonstration is a sort of syllogism, but not every syllogism is a 
demonstration. 

Whenever three terms are so related to one another that the 
last is contained in the middle as in a whole, and the middle is 
either contained in, or excluded from, the first as in or from a 
whole, the extremes must be related by a perfect syllogism. I 
call that term middle which is itself contained in another and 
contains another in itself: in position also this comes in the 
middle. By extremes I mean both that term which is itself 



85 



contained in another and that in which another is contained. If 
A is predicated of all B, and B of all C, A must be predicated of 
all C: we have already explained what we mean by 'predicated 
of all'. Similarly also, if A is predicated of no B, and B of all C, it 
is necessary that no C will be A. 

But if the first term belongs to all the middle, but the middle to 
none of the last term, there will be no syllogism in respect of 
the extremes; for nothing necessary follows from the terms 
being so related; for it is possible that the first should belong 
either to all or to none of the last, so that neither a particular 
nor a universal conclusion is necessary. But if there is no 
necessary consequence, there cannot be a syllogism by means 
of these premisses. As an example of a universal affirmative 
relation between the extremes we may take the terms animal, 
man, horse; of a universal negative relation, the terms animal, 
man, stone. Nor again can syllogism be formed when neither 
the first term belongs to any of the middle, nor the middle to 
any of the last. As an example of a positive relation between the 
extremes take the terms science, line, medicine: of a negative 
relation science, line, unit. 

If then the terms are universally related, it is clear in this figure 
when a syllogism will be possible and when not, and that if a 
syllogism is possible the terms must be related as described, 
and if they are so related there will be a syllogism. 

But if one term is related universally, the other in part only, to 
its subject, there must be a perfect syllogism whenever 
universality is posited with reference to the major term either 
affirmatively or negatively, and particularity with reference to 
the minor term affirmatively: but whenever the universality is 
posited in relation to the minor term, or the terms are related in 
any other way, a syllogism is impossible. I call that term the 
major in which the middle is contained and that term the 



86 



minor which comes under the middle. Let all B be A and some C 
be B. Then if 'predicated of all' means what was said above, it is 
necessary that some C is A. And if no B is A but some C is B, it is 
necessary that some C is not A. The meaning of 'predicated of 
none' has also been defined. So there will be a perfect syllogism. 
This holds good also if the premiss BC should be indefinite, 
provided that it is affirmative: for we shall have the same 
syllogism whether the premiss is indefinite or particular. 

But if the universality is posited with respect to the minor term 
either affirmatively or negatively, a syllogism will not be 
possible, whether the major premiss is positive or negative, 
indefinite or particular: e.g. if some B is or is not A, and all C is 
B. As an example of a positive relation between the extremes 
take the terms good, state, wisdom: of a negative relation, good, 
state, ignorance. Again if no C is B, but some B is or is not A or 
not every B is A, there cannot be a syllogism. Take the terms 
white, horse, swan: white, horse, raven. The same terms may be 
taken also if the premiss BA is indefinite. 

Nor when the major premiss is universal, whether affirmative 
or negative, and the minor premiss is negative and particular, 
can there be a syllogism, whether the minor premiss be 
indefinite or particular: e.g. if all B is A and some C is not B, or if 
not all C is B. For the major term may be predicable both of all 
and of none of the minor, to some of which the middle term 
cannot be attributed. Suppose the terms are animal, man, 
white: next take some of the white things of which man is not 
predicated - swan and snow: animal is predicated of all of the 
one, but of none of the other. Consequently there cannot be a 
syllogism. Again let no B be A, but let some C not be B. Take the 
terms inanimate, man, white: then take some white things of 
which man is not predicated - swan and snow: the term 
inanimate is predicated of all of the one, of none of the other. 



87 



Further since it is indefinite to say some C is not B, and it is true 
that some C is not B, whether no C is B, or not all C is B, and 
since if terms are assumed such that no C is B, no syllogism 
follows (this has already been stated) it is clear that this 
arrangement of terms will not afford a syllogism: otherwise one 
would have been possible with a universal negative minor 
premiss. A similar proof may also be given if the universal 
premiss is negative. 

Nor can there in any way be a syllogism if both the relations of 
subject and predicate are particular, either positively or 
negatively, or the one negative and the other affirmative, or one 
indefinite and the other definite, or both indefinite. Terms 
common to all the above are animal, white, horse: animal, 
white, stone. 

It is clear then from what has been said that if there is a 
syllogism in this figure with a particular conclusion, the terms 
must be related as we have stated: if they are related otherwise, 
no syllogism is possible anyhow. It is evident also that all the 
syllogisms in this figure are perfect (for they are all completed 
by means of the premisses originally taken) and that all 
conclusions are proved by this figure, viz. universal and 
particular, affirmative and negative. Such a figure I call the first. 



Whenever the same thing belongs to all of one subject, and to 
none of another, or to all of each subject or to none of either, I 
call such a figure the second; by middle term in it I mean that 
which is predicated of both subjects, by extremes the terms of 
which this is said, by major extreme that which lies near the 
middle, by minor that which is further away from the middle. 



88 



The middle term stands outside the extremes, and is first in 
position. A syllogism cannot be perfect anyhow in this figure, 
but it may be valid whether the terms are related universally or 
not. 

If then the terms are related universally a syllogism will be 
possible, whenever the middle belongs to all of one subject and 
to none of another (it does not matter which has the negative 
relation), but in no other way. Let M be predicated of no N, but of 
all 0. Since, then, the negative relation is convertible, N will 
belong to no M: but M was assumed to belong to all 0: 
consequently N will belong to no 0. This has already been 
proved. Again if M belongs to all N, but to no 0, then N will 
belong to no 0. For if M belongs to no 0, belongs to no M: but 
M (as was said) belongs to all N: then will belong to no N: for 
the first figure has again been formed. But since the negative 
relation is convertible, N will belong to no 0. Thus it will be the 
same syllogism that proves both conclusions. 

It is possible to prove these results also by reductio ad 
impossibile. 

It is clear then that a syllogism is formed when the terms are so 
related, but not a perfect syllogism; for necessity is not perfectly 
established merely from the original premisses; others also are 
needed. 

But if M is predicated of every N and 0, there cannot be a 
syllogism. Terms to illustrate a positive relation between the 
extremes are substance, animal, man; a negative relation, 
substance, animal, number - substance being the middle term. 

Nor is a syllogism possible when M is predicated neither of any 
N nor of any 0. Terms to illustrate a positive relation are line, 
animal, man: a negative relation, line, animal, stone. 



89 



It is clear then that if a syllogism is formed when the terms are 
universally related, the terms must be related as we stated at 
the outset: for if they are otherwise related no necessary 
consequence follows. 

If the middle term is related universally to one of the extremes, 
a particular negative syllogism must result whenever the 
middle term is related universally to the major whether 
positively or negatively, and particularly to the minor and in a 
manner opposite to that of the universal statement: by 'an 
opposite manner' I mean, if the universal statement is negative, 
the particular is affirmative: if the universal is affirmative, the 
particular is negative. For if M belongs to no N, but to some 0, it 
is necessary that N does not belong to some 0. For since the 
negative statement is convertible, N will belong to no M: but M 
was admitted to belong to some 0: therefore N will not belong 
to some 0: for the result is reached by means of the first figure. 
Again if M belongs to all N, but not to some 0, it is necessary 
that N does not belong to some 0: for if N belongs to all 0, and 
M is predicated also of all N, M must belong to all 0: but we 
assumed that M does not belong to some 0. And if M belongs to 
all N but not to all 0, we shall conclude that N does not belong 
to all 0: the proof is the same as the above. But if M is 
predicated of all 0, but not of all N, there will be no syllogism. 
Take the terms animal, substance, raven; animal, white, raven. 
Nor will there be a conclusion when M is predicated of no 0, but 
of some N. Terms to illustrate a positive relation between the 
extremes are animal, substance, unit: a negative relation, 
animal, substance, science. 

If then the universal statement is opposed to the particular, we 
have stated when a syllogism will be possible and when not: 
but if the premisses are similar in form, I mean both negative or 
both affirmative, a syllogism will not be possible anyhow. First 
let them be negative, and let the major premiss be universal, e.g. 



90 



let M belong to no N, and not to some 0. It is possible then for N 
to belong either to all or to no 0. Terms to illustrate the 
negative relation are black, snow, animal. But it is not possible 
to find terms of which the extremes are related positively and 
universally, if M belongs to some 0, and does not belong to 
some 0. For if N belonged to all 0, but M to no N, then M would 
belong to no 0: but we assumed that it belongs to some 0. In 
this way then it is not admissible to take terms: our point must 
be proved from the indefinite nature of the particular 
statement. For since it is true that M does not belong to some 0, 
even if it belongs to no 0, and since if it belongs to no a 
syllogism is (as we have seen) not possible, clearly it will not be 
possible now either. 

Again let the premisses be affirmative, and let the major 
premiss as before be universal, e.g. let M belong to all N and to 
some 0. It is possible then for N to belong to all or to no 0. 
Terms to illustrate the negative relation are white, swan, stone. 
But it is not possible to take terms to illustrate the universal 
affirmative relation, for the reason already stated: the point 
must be proved from the indefinite nature of the particular 
statement. But if the minor premiss is universal, and M belongs 
to no 0, and not to some N, it is possible for N to belong either 
to all or to no 0. Terms for the positive relation are white, 
animal, raven: for the negative relation, white, stone, raven. If 
the premisses are affirmative, terms for the negative relation 
are white, animal, snow; for the positive relation, white, animal, 
swan. Evidently then, whenever the premisses are similar in 
form, and one is universal, the other particular, a syllogism can, 
not be formed anyhow. Nor is one possible if the middle term 
belongs to some of each of the extremes, or does not belong to 
some of either, or belongs to some of the one, not to some of the 
other, or belongs to neither universally, or is related to them 
indefinitely. Common terms for all the above are white, animal, 
man: white, animal, inanimate. It is clear then from what has 



91 



been said that if the terms are related to one another in the way 
stated, a syllogism results of necessity; and if there is a 
syllogism, the terms must be so related. But it is evident also 
that all the syllogisms in this figure are imperfect: for all are 
made perfect by certain supplementary statements, which 
either are contained in the terms of necessity or are assumed as 
hypotheses, i.e. when we prove per impossibile. And it is evident 
that an affirmative conclusion is not attained by means of this 
figure, but all are negative, whether universal or particular. 



But if one term belongs to all, and another to none, of a third, or 
if both belong to all, or to none, of it, I call such a figure the 
third; by middle term in it I mean that of which both the 
predicates are predicated, by extremes I mean the predicates, by 
the major extreme that which is further from the middle, by the 
minor that which is nearer to it. The middle term stands outside 
the extremes, and is last in position. A syllogism cannot be 
perfect in this figure either, but it may be valid whether the 
terms are related universally or not to the middle term. 

If they are universal, whenever both P and R belong to S, it 
follows that P will necessarily belong to some R. For, since the 
affirmative statement is convertible, S will belong to some R: 
consequently since P belongs to all S, and S to some R, P must 
belong to some R: for a syllogism in the first figure is produced. 
It is possible to demonstrate this also per impossibile and by 
exposition. For if both P and R belong to all S, should one of the 
Ss, e.g. N, be taken, both P and R will belong to this, and thus P 
will belong to some R. 



92 



If R belongs to all S, and P to no S, there will be a syllogism to 
prove that P will necessarily not belong to some R. This may be 
demonstrated in the same way as before by converting the 
premiss RS. It might be proved also per impossibile, as in the 
former cases. But if R belongs to no S, P to all S, there will be no 
syllogism. Terms for the positive relation are animal, horse, 
man: for the negative relation animal, inanimate, man. 

Nor can there be a syllogism when both terms are asserted of 
no S. Terms for the positive relation are animal, horse, 
inanimate; for the negative relation man, horse, inanimate - 
inanimate being the middle term. 

It is clear then in this figure also when a syllogism will be 
possible and when not, if the terms are related universally. For 
whenever both the terms are affirmative, there will be a 
syllogism to prove that one extreme belongs to some of the 
other; but when they are negative, no syllogism will be possible. 
But when one is negative, the other affirmative, if the major is 
negative, the minor affirmative, there will be a syllogism to 
prove that the one extreme does not belong to some of the 
other: but if the relation is reversed, no syllogism will be 
possible. If one term is related universally to the middle, the 
other in part only, when both are affirmative there must be a 
syllogism, no matter which of the premisses is universal. For if 
R belongs to all S, P to some S, P must belong to some R. For 
since the affirmative statement is convertible S will belong to 
some P: consequently since R belongs to all S, and S to some P, R 
must also belong to some P: therefore P must belong to some R. 

Again if R belongs to some S, and P to all S, P must belong to 
some R. This may be demonstrated in the same way as the 
preceding. And it is possible to demonstrate it also per 
impossibile and by exposition, as in the former cases. But if one 
term is affirmative, the other negative, and if the affirmative is 



93 



universal, a syllogism will be possible whenever the minor term 
is affirmative. For if R belongs to all S, but P does not belong to 
some S, it is necessary that P does not belong to some R. For if P 
belongs to all R, and R belongs to all S, then P will belong to all 
S: but we assumed that it did not. Proof is possible also without 
reduction ad impossibile, if one of the Ss be taken to which P 
does not belong. 

But whenever the major is affirmative, no syllogism will be 
possible, e.g. if P belongs to all S and R does not belong to some 
S. Terms for the universal affirmative relation are animate, man, 
animal. For the universal negative relation it is not possible to 
get terms, if R belongs to some S, and does not belong to some 
S. For if P belongs to all S, and R to some S, then P will belong to 
some R: but we assumed that it belongs to no R. We must put 
the matter as before.' Since the expression 'it does not belong to 
some' is indefinite, it may be used truly of that also which 
belongs to none. But if R belongs to no S, no syllogism is 
possible, as has been shown. Clearly then no syllogism will be 
possible here. 

But if the negative term is universal, whenever the major is 
negative and the minor affirmative there will be a syllogism. For 
if P belongs to no S, and R belongs to some S, P will not belong 
to some R: for we shall have the first figure again, if the premiss 
RS is converted. 

But when the minor is negative, there will be no syllogism. 
Terms for the positive relation are animal, man, wild: for the 
negative relation, animal, science, wild - the middle in both 
being the term wild. 

Nor is a syllogism possible when both are stated in the negative, 
but one is universal, the other particular. When the minor is 
related universally to the middle, take the terms animal, 
science, wild; animal, man, wild. When the major is related 



94 



universally to the middle, take as terms for a negative relation 
raven, snow, white. For a positive relation terms cannot be 
found, if R belongs to some S, and does not belong to some S. 
For if P belongs to all R, and R to some S, then P belongs to some 
S: but we assumed that it belongs to no S. Our point, then, must 
be proved from the indefinite nature of the particular 
statement. 

Nor is a syllogism possible anyhow, if each of the extremes 
belongs to some of the middle or does not belong, or one 
belongs and the other does not to some of the middle, or one 
belongs to some of the middle, the other not to all, or if the 
premisses are indefinite. Common terms for all are animal, 
man, white: animal, inanimate, white. 

It is clear then in this figure also when a syllogism will be 
possible, and when not; and that if the terms are as stated, a 
syllogism results of necessity, and if there is a syllogism, the 
terms must be so related. It is clear also that all the syllogisms 
in this figure are imperfect (for all are made perfect by certain 
supplementary assumptions), and that it will not be possible to 
reach a universal conclusion by means of this figure, whether 
negative or affirmative. 



It is evident also that in all the figures, whenever a proper 
syllogism does not result, if both the terms are affirmative or 
negative nothing necessary follows at all, but if one is 
affirmative, the other negative, and if the negative is stated 
universally, a syllogism always results relating the minor to the 
major term, e.g. if A belongs to all or some B, and B belongs to 
no C: for if the premisses are converted it is necessary that C 



95 



does not belong to some A. Similarly also in the other figures: a 
syllogism always results by means of conversion. It is evident 
also that the substitution of an indefinite for a particular 
affirmative will effect the same syllogism in all the figures. 

It is clear too that all the imperfect syllogisms are made perfect 
by means of the first figure. For all are brought to a conclusion 
either ostensively or per impossibile. In both ways the first 
figure is formed: if they are made perfect ostensively, because 
(as we saw) all are brought to a conclusion by means of 
conversion, and conversion produces the first figure: if they are 
proved per impossibile, because on the assumption of the false 
statement the syllogism comes about by means of the first 
figure, e.g. in the last figure, if A and B belong to all C, it follows 
that A belongs to some B: for if A belonged to no B, and B 
belongs to all C, A would belong to no C: but (as we stated) it 
belongs to all C. Similarly also with the rest. 

It is possible also to reduce all syllogisms to the universal 
syllogisms in the first figure. Those in the second figure are 
clearly made perfect by these, though not all in the same way; 
the universal syllogisms are made perfect by converting the 
negative premiss, each of the particular syllogisms by reductio 
ad impossibile. In the first figure particular syllogisms are 
indeed made perfect by themselves, but it is possible also to 
prove them by means of the second figure, reducing them ad 
impossibile, e.g. if A belongs to all B, and B to some C, it follows 
that A belongs to some C. For if it belonged to no C, and belongs 
to all B, then B will belong to no C: this we know by means of 
the second figure. Similarly also demonstration will be possible 
in the case of the negative. For if A belongs to no B, and B 
belongs to some C, A will not belong to some C: for if it belonged 
to all C, and belongs to no B, then B will belong to no C: and this 
(as we saw) is the middle figure. Consequently, since all 
syllogisms in the middle figure can be reduced to universal 



96 



syllogisms in the first figure, and since particular syllogisms in 
the first figure can be reduced to syllogisms in the middle 
figure, it is clear that particular syllogisms can be reduced to 
universal syllogisms in the first figure. Syllogisms in the third 
figure, if the terms are universal, are directly made perfect by 
means of those syllogisms; but, when one of the premisses is 
particular, by means of the particular syllogisms in the first 
figure: and these (we have seen) may be reduced to the 
universal syllogisms in the first figure: consequently also the 
particular syllogisms in the third figure may be so reduced. It is 
clear then that all syllogisms may be reduced to the universal 
syllogisms in the first figure. 

We have stated then how syllogisms which prove that 
something belongs or does not belong to something else are 
constituted, both how syllogisms of the same figure are 
constituted in themselves, and how syllogisms of different 
figures are related to one another. 



8 

Since there is a difference according as something belongs, 
necessarily belongs, or may belong to something else (for many 
things belong indeed, but not necessarily, others neither 
necessarily nor indeed at all, but it is possible for them to 
belong), it is clear that there will be different syllogisms to prove 
each of these relations, and syllogisms with differently related 
terms, one syllogism concluding from what is necessary, 
another from what is, a third from what is possible. 

There is hardly any difference between syllogisms from 
necessary premisses and syllogisms from premisses which 
merely assert. When the terms are put in the same way, then, 



97 



whether something belongs or necessarily belongs (or does not 
belong) to something else, a syllogism will or will not result 
alike in both cases, the only difference being the addition of the 
expression 'necessarily' to the terms. For the negative statement 
is convertible alike in both cases, and we should give the same 
account of the expressions 'to be contained in something as in a 
whole' and 'to be predicated of all of something'. With the 
exceptions to be made below, the conclusion will be proved to 
be necessary by means of conversion, in the same manner as in 
the case of simple predication. But in the middle figure when 
the universal statement is affirmative, and the particular 
negative, and again in the third figure when the universal is 
affirmative and the particular negative, the demonstration will 
not take the same form, but it is necessary by the 'exposition' of 
a part of the subject of the particular negative proposition, to 
which the predicate does not belong, to make the syllogism in 
reference to this: with terms so chosen the conclusion will 
necessarily follow. But if the relation is necessary in respect of 
the part taken, it must hold of some of that term in which this 
part is included: for the part taken is just some of that. And 
each of the resulting syllogisms is in the appropriate figure. 



It happens sometimes also that when one premiss is necessary 
the conclusion is necessary, not however when either premiss is 
necessary, but only when the major is, e.g. if A is taken as 
necessarily belonging or not belonging to B, but B is taken as 
simply belonging to C: for if the premisses are taken in this way, 
A will necessarily belong or not belong to C. For since 
necessarily belongs, or does not belong, to every B, and since C 
is one of the Bs, it is clear that for C also the positive or the 



98 



negative relation to A will hold necessarily. But if the major 
premiss is not necessary, but the minor is necessary, the 
conclusion will not be necessary. For if it were, it would result 
both through the first figure and through the third that A 
belongs necessarily to some B. But this is false; for B may be 
such that it is possible that A should belong to none of it. 
Further, an example also makes it clear that the conclusion not 
be necessary, e.g. if A were movement, B animal, C man: man is 
an animal necessarily, but an animal does not move necessarily, 
nor does man. Similarly also if the major premiss is negative; 
for the proof is the same. 

In particular syllogisms, if the universal premiss is necessary, 
then the conclusion will be necessary; but if the particular, the 
conclusion will not be necessary, whether the universal premiss 
is negative or affirmative. First let the universal be necessary, 
and let A belong to all B necessarily, but let B simply belong to 
some C: it is necessary then that A belongs to some C 
necessarily: for C falls under B, and A was assumed to belong 
necessarily to all B. Similarly also if the syllogism should be 
negative: for the proof will be the same. But if the particular 
premiss is necessary, the conclusion will not be necessary: for 
from the denial of such a conclusion nothing impossible results, 
just as it does not in the universal syllogisms. The same is true 
of negative syllogisms. Try the terms movement, animal, white. 



10 

In the second figure, if the negative premiss is necessary, then 
the conclusion will be necessary, but if the affirmative, not 
necessary. First let the negative be necessary; let A be possible 
of no B, and simply belong to C. Since then the negative 



99 



statement is convertible, B is possible of no A. But A belongs to 
all C; consequently B is possible of no C. For C falls under A. The 
same result would be obtained if the minor premiss were 
negative: for if A is possible be of no C, C is possible of no A: but 
A belongs to all B, consequently C is possible of none of the Bs: 
for again we have obtained the first figure. Neither then is B 
possible of C: for conversion is possible without modifying the 
relation. 

But if the affirmative premiss is necessary, the conclusion will 
not be necessary. Let A belong to all B necessarily, but to no C 
simply. If then the negative premiss is converted, the first figure 
results. But it has been proved in the case of the first figure that 
if the negative major premiss is not necessary the conclusion 
will not be necessary either. Therefore the same result will 
obtain here. Further, if the conclusion is necessary, it follows 
that C necessarily does not belong to some A. For if B 
necessarily belongs to no C, C will necessarily belong to no B. 
But B at any rate must belong to some A, if it is true (as was 
assumed) that A necessarily belongs to all B. Consequently it is 
necessary that C does not belong to some A. But nothing 
prevents such an A being taken that it is possible for C to belong 
to all of it. Further one might show by an exposition of terms 
that the conclusion is not necessary without qualification, 
though it is a necessary conclusion from the premisses. For 
example let A be animal, B man, C white, and let the premisses 
be assumed to correspond to what we had before: it is possible 
that animal should belong to nothing white. Man then will not 
belong to anything white, but not necessarily: for it is possible 
for man to be born white, not however so long as animal 
belongs to nothing white. Consequently under these conditions 
the conclusion will be necessary, but it is not necessary without 
qualification. 



100 



Similar results will obtain also in particular syllogisms. For 
whenever the negative premiss is both universal and necessary, 
then the conclusion will be necessary: but whenever the 
affirmative premiss is universal, the negative particular, the 
conclusion will not be necessary. First then let the negative 
premiss be both universal and necessary: let it be possible for 
no B that A should belong to it, and let A simply belong to some 
C. Since the negative statement is convertible, it will be possible 
for no A that B should belong to it: but A belongs to some C; 
consequently B necessarily does not belong to some of the Cs. 
Again let the affirmative premiss be both universal and 
necessary, and let the major premiss be affirmative. If then A 
necessarily belongs to all B, but does not belong to some C, it is 
clear that B will not belong to some C, but not necessarily. For 
the same terms can be used to demonstrate the point, which 
were used in the universal syllogisms. Nor again, if the negative 
statement is necessary but particular, will the conclusion be 
necessary. The point can be demonstrated by means of the 
same terms. 



11 

In the last figure when the terms are related universally to the 
middle, and both premisses are affirmative, if one of the two is 
necessary, then the conclusion will be necessary. But if one is 
negative, the other affirmative, whenever the negative is 
necessary the conclusion also will be necessary, but whenever 
the affirmative is necessary the conclusion will not be 
necessary. First let both the premisses be affirmative, and let A 
and B belong to all C, and let AC be necessary. Since then B 
belongs to all C, C also will belong to some B, because the 
universal is convertible into the particular: consequently if A 



101 



belongs necessarily to all C, and C belongs to some B, it is 
necessary that A should belong to some B also. For B is under C. 
The first figure then is formed. A similar proof will be given also 
if BC is necessary. For C is convertible with some A: 
consequently if B belongs necessarily to all C, it will belong 
necessarily also to some A. 

Again let AC be negative, BC affirmative, and let the negative 
premiss be necessary. Since then C is convertible with some B, 
but A necessarily belongs to no C, A will necessarily not belong 
to some B either: for B is under C. But if the affirmative is 
necessary, the conclusion will not be necessary. For suppose BC 
is affirmative and necessary, while AC is negative and not 
necessary. Since then the affirmative is convertible, C also will 
belong to some B necessarily: consequently if A belongs to none 
of the Cs, while C belongs to some of the Bs, A will not belong to 
some of the Bs - but not of necessity; for it has been proved, in 
the case of the first figure, that if the negative premiss is not 
necessary, neither will the conclusion be necessary. Further, the 
point may be made clear by considering the terms. Let the term 
A be 'good', let that which B signifies be 'animal', let the term C 
be 'horse'. It is possible then that the term good should belong 
to no horse, and it is necessary that the term animal should 
belong to every horse: but it is not necessary that some animal 
should not be good, since it is possible for every animal to be 
good. Or if that is not possible, take as the term 'awake' or 
'asleep': for every animal can accept these. 

If, then, the premisses are universal, we have stated when the 
conclusion will be necessary. But if one premiss is universal, the 
other particular, and if both are affirmative, whenever the 
universal is necessary the conclusion also must be necessary. 
The demonstration is the same as before; for the particular 
affirmative also is convertible. If then it is necessary that B 
should belong to all C, and A falls under C, it is necessary that B 



102 



should belong to some A. But if B must belong to some A, then A 
must belong to some B: for conversion is possible. Similarly also 
if AC should be necessary and universal: for B falls under C. But 
if the particular premiss is necessary, the conclusion will not be 
necessary. Let the premiss BC be both particular and necessary, 
and let A belong to all C, not however necessarily. If the 
proposition BC is converted the first figure is formed, and the 
universal premiss is not necessary, but the particular is 
necessary. But when the premisses were thus, the conclusion 
(as we proved was not necessary: consequently it is not here 
either. Further, the point is clear if we look at the terms. Let A be 
waking, B biped, and C animal. It is necessary that B should 
belong to some C, but it is possible for A to belong to C, and that 
A should belong to B is not necessary. For there is no necessity 
that some biped should be asleep or awake. Similarly and by 
means of the same terms proof can be made, should the 
proposition AC be both particular and necessary. 

But if one premiss is affirmative, the other negative, whenever 
the universal is both negative and necessary the conclusion also 
will be necessary. For if it is not possible that A should belong to 
any C, but B belongs to some C, it is necessary that A should not 
belong to some B. But whenever the affirmative proposition is 
necessary, whether universal or particular, or the negative is 
particular, the conclusion will not be necessary. The proof of 
this by reduction will be the same as before; but if terms are 
wanted, when the universal affirmative is necessary, take the 
terms 'waking' - 'animal' - 'man', 'man' being middle, and when 
the affirmative is particular and necessary, take the terms 
'waking' - 'animal' - 'white': for it is necessary that animal 
should belong to some white thing, but it is possible that 
waking should belong to none, and it is not necessary that 
waking should not belong to some animal. But when the 
negative proposition being particular is necessary, take the 
terms 'biped', 'moving', 'animal', 'animal' being middle. 



103 



12 

It is clear then that a simple conclusion is not reached unless 
both premisses are simple assertions, but a necessary- 
conclusion is possible although one only of the premisses is 
necessary. But in both cases, whether the syllogisms are 
affirmative or negative, it is necessary that one premiss should 
be similar to the conclusion. I mean by 'similar', if the 
conclusion is a simple assertion, the premiss must be simple; if 
the conclusion is necessary, the premiss must be necessary. 
Consequently this also is clear, that the conclusion will be 
neither necessary nor simple unless a necessary or simple 
premiss is assumed. 



13 

Perhaps enough has been said about the proof of necessity, how 
it comes about and how it differs from the proof of a simple 
statement. We proceed to discuss that which is possible, when 
and how and by what means it can be proved. I use the terms 
'to be possible' and 'the possible' of that which is not necessary 
but, being assumed, results in nothing impossible. We say 
indeed ambiguously of the necessary that it is possible. But that 
my definition of the possible is correct is clear from the phrases 
by which we deny or on the contrary affirm possibility. For the 
expressions 'it is not possible to belong', 'it is impossible to 
belong', and 'it is necessary not to belong' are either identical or 
follow from one another; consequently their opposites also, 'it is 
possible to belong', 'it is not impossible to belong', and 'it is not 



104 



necessary not to belong', will either be identical or follow from 
one another. For of everything the affirmation or the denial 
holds good. That which is possible then will be not necessary 
and that which is not necessary will be possible. It results that 
all premisses in the mode of possibility are convertible into one 
another. I mean not that the affirmative are convertible into the 
negative, but that those which are affirmative in form admit of 
conversion by opposition, e.g. 'it is possible to belong' may be 
converted into 'it is possible not to belong', and 'it is possible for 
A to belong to all B' into 'it is possible for A to belong to no B' or 
'not to all B', and 'it is possible for A to belong to some B' into 'it 
is possible for A not to belong to some B'. And similarly the 
other propositions in this mode can be converted. For since that 
which is possible is not necessary, and that which is not 
necessary may possibly not belong, it is clear that if it is 
possible that A should belong to B, it is possible also that it 
should not belong to B: and if it is possible that it should belong 
to all, it is also possible that it should not belong to all. The 
same holds good in the case of particular affirmations: for the 
proof is identical. And such premisses are affirmative and not 
negative; for 'to be possible' is in the same rank as 'to be', as 
was said above. 

Having made these distinctions we next point out that the 
expression 'to be possible' is used in two ways. In one it means 
to happen generally and fall short of necessity, e.g. man's 
turning grey or growing or decaying, or generally what naturally 
belongs to a thing (for this has not its necessity unbroken, since 
man's existence is not continuous for ever, although if a man 
does exist, it comes about either necessarily or generally). In 
another sense the expression means the indefinite, which can 
be both thus and not thus, e.g. an animal's walking or an 
earthquake's taking place while it is walking, or generally what 
happens by chance: for none of these inclines by nature in the 
one way more than in the opposite. 



105 



That which is possible in each of its two senses is convertible 
into its opposite, not however in the same way: but what is 
natural is convertible because it does not necessarily belong (for 
in this sense it is possible that a man should not grow grey) and 
what is indefinite is convertible because it inclines this way no 
more than that. Science and demonstrative syllogism are not 
concerned with things which are indefinite, because the middle 
term is uncertain; but they are concerned with things that are 
natural, and as a rule arguments and inquiries are made about 
things which are possible in this sense. Syllogisms indeed can 
be made about the former, but it is unusual at any rate to 
inquire about them. 

These matters will be treated more definitely in the sequel; our 
business at present is to state the moods and nature of the 
syllogism made from possible premisses. The expression 'it is 
possible for this to belong to that' may be understood in two 
senses: 'that' may mean either that to which 'that' belongs or 
that to which it may belong; for the expression 'A is possible of 
the subject of B' means that it is possible either of that of which 
B is stated or of that of which B may possibly be stated. It makes 
no difference whether we say, A is possible of the subject of B, or 
all B admits of A. It is clear then that the expression 'A may 
possibly belong to all B' might be used in two senses. First then 
we must state the nature and characteristics of the syllogism 
which arises if B is possible of the subject of C, and A is possible 
of the subject of B. For thus both premisses are assumed in the 
mode of possibility; but whenever A is possible of that of which 
B is true, one premiss is a simple assertion, the other a 
problematic. Consequently we must start from premisses which 
are similar in form, as in the other cases. 



106 



14 

Whenever A may possibly belong to all B, and B to all C, there 
will be a perfect syllogism to prove that A may possibly belong 
to all C. This is clear from the definition: for it was in this way 
that we explained 'to be possible for one term to belong to all of 
another'. Similarly if it is possible for A to belong no B, and for B 
to belong to all C, then it is possible for A to belong to no C. For 
the statement that it is possible for A not to belong to that of 
which B may be true means (as we saw) that none of those 
things which can possibly fall under the term B is left out of 
account. But whenever A may belong to all B, and B may belong 
to no C, then indeed no syllogism results from the premisses 
assumed, but if the premiss BC is converted after the manner of 
problematic propositions, the same syllogism results as before. 
For since it is possible that B should belong to no C, it is possible 
also that it should belong to all C. This has been stated above. 
Consequently if B is possible for all C, and A is possible for all B, 
the same syllogism again results. Similarly if in both the 
premisses the negative is joined with 'it is possible': e.g. if A 
may belong to none of the Bs, and B to none of the Cs. No 
syllogism results from the assumed premisses, but if they are 
converted we shall have the same syllogism as before. It is clear 
then that if the minor premiss is negative, or if both premisses 
are negative, either no syllogism results, or if one it is not 
perfect. For the necessity results from the conversion. 

But if one of the premisses is universal, the other particular, 
when the major premiss is universal there will be a perfect 
syllogism. For if A is possible for all B, and B for some C, then A 
is possible for some C. This is clear from the definition of being 
possible. Again if A may belong to no B, and B may belong to 
some of the Cs, it is necessary that A may possibly not belong to 
some of the Cs. The proof is the same as above. But if the 
particular premiss is negative, and the universal is affirmative, 



107 



the major still being universal and the minor particular, e.g. A is 
possible for all B, B may possibly not belong to some C, then a 
clear syllogism does not result from the assumed premisses, but 
if the particular premiss is converted and it is laid down that B 
possibly may belong to some C, we shall have the same 
conclusion as before, as in the cases given at the beginning. 

But if the major premiss is the minor universal, whether both 
are affirmative, or negative, or different in quality, or if both are 
indefinite or particular, in no way will a syllogism be possible. 
For nothing prevents B from reaching beyond A, so that as 
predicates cover unequal areas. Let C be that by which B 
extends beyond A. To C it is not possible that A should belong - 
either to all or to none or to some or not to some, since 
premisses in the mode of possibility are convertible and it is 
possible for B to belong to more things than A can. Further, this 
is obvious if we take terms; for if the premisses are as assumed, 
the major term is both possible for none of the minor and must 
belong to all of it. Take as terms common to all the cases under 
consideration 'animal' - 'white' - 'man', where the major 
belongs necessarily to the minor; 'animal' - 'white' - 'garment', 
where it is not possible that the major should belong to the 
minor. It is clear then that if the terms are related in this 
manner, no syllogism results. For every syllogism proves that 
something belongs either simply or necessarily or possibly. It is 
clear that there is no proof of the first or of the second. For the 
affirmative is destroyed by the negative, and the negative by the 
affirmative. There remains the proof of possibility. But this is 
impossible. For it has been proved that if the terms are related 
in this manner it is both necessary that the major should 
belong to all the minor and not possible that it should belong to 
any. Consequently there cannot be a syllogism to prove the 
possibility; for the necessary (as we stated) is not possible. 



108 



It is clear that if the terms are universal in possible premisses a 
syllogism always results in the first figure, whether they are 
affirmative or negative, only a perfect syllogism results in the 
first case, an imperfect in the second. But possibility must be 
understood according to the definition laid down, not as 
covering necessity. This is sometimes forgotten. 



15 

If one premiss is a simple proposition, the other a problematic, 
whenever the major premiss indicates possibility all the 
syllogisms will be perfect and establish possibility in the sense 
defined; but whenever the minor premiss indicates possibility 
all the syllogisms will be imperfect, and those which are 
negative will establish not possibility according to the 
definition, but that the major does not necessarily belong to 
any, or to all, of the minor. For if this is so, we say it is possible 
that it should belong to none or not to all. Let A be possible for 
all B, and let B belong to all C. Since C falls under B, and A is 
possible for all B, clearly it is possible for all C also. So a perfect 
syllogism results. Likewise if the premiss AB is negative, and the 
premiss BC is affirmative, the former stating possible, the latter 
simple attribution, a perfect syllogism results proving that A 
possibly belongs to no C. 

It is clear that perfect syllogisms result if the minor premiss 
states simple belonging: but that syllogisms will result if the 
modality of the premisses is reversed, must be proved per 
impossibile. At the same time it will be evident that they are 
imperfect: for the proof proceeds not from the premisses 
assumed. First we must state that if B's being follows 
necessarily from As being, B's possibility will follow necessarily 



109 



from A's possibility. Suppose, the terms being so related, that A 
is possible, and B is impossible. If then that which is possible, 
when it is possible for it to be, might happen, and if that which 
is impossible, when it is impossible, could not happen, and if at 
the same time A is possible and B impossible, it would be 
possible for A to happen without B, and if to happen, then to be. 
For that which has happened, when it has happened, is. But we 
must take the impossible and the possible not only in the 
sphere of becoming, but also in the spheres of truth and 
predicability, and the various other spheres in which we speak 
of the possible: for it will be alike in all. Further we must 
understand the statement that B's being depends on A's being, 
not as meaning that if some single thing A is, B will be: for 
nothing follows of necessity from the being of some one thing, 
but from two at least, i.e. when the premisses are related in the 
manner stated to be that of the syllogism. For if C is predicated 
of D, and D of F, then G is necessarily predicated of F. And if each 
is possible, the conclusion also is possible. If then, for example, 
one should indicate the premisses by A, and the conclusion by 
B, it would not only result that if A is necessary B is necessary, 
but also that if A is possible, B is possible. 

Since this is proved it is evident that if a false and not 
impossible assumption is made, the consequence of the 
assumption will also be false and not impossible: e.g. if A is 
false, but not impossible, and if B is the consequence of A, B also 
will be false but not impossible. For since it has been proved 
that if B's being is the consequence of A's being, then B's 
possibility will follow from A's possibility (and A is assumed to 
be possible), consequently B will be possible: for if it were 
impossible, the same thing would at the same time be possible 
and impossible. 

Since we have defined these points, let A belong to all B, and B 
be possible for all C: it is necessary then that should be a 



no 



possible attribute for all C. Suppose that it is not possible, but 
assume that B belongs to all C: this is false but not impossible. If 
then A is not possible for C but B belongs to all C, then A is not 
possible for all B: for a syllogism is formed in the third degree. 
But it was assumed that A is a possible attribute for all B. It is 
necessary then that A is possible for all C. For though the 
assumption we made is false and not impossible, the 
conclusion is impossible. It is possible also in the first figure to 
bring about the impossibility, by assuming that B belongs to C. 
For if B belongs to all C, and A is possible for all B, then A would 
be possible for all C. But the assumption was made that A is not 
possible for all C. 

We must understand 'that which belongs to all' with no 
limitation in respect of time, e.g. to the present or to a particular 
period, but simply without qualification. For it is by the help of 
such premisses that we make syllogisms, since if the premiss is 
understood with reference to the present moment, there cannot 
be a syllogism. For nothing perhaps prevents 'man' belonging at 
a particular time to everything that is moving, i.e. if nothing else 
were moving: but 'moving' is possible for every horse; yet 'man' 
is possible for no horse. Further let the major term be 'animal', 
the middle 'moving', the the minor 'man'. The premisses then 
will be as before, but the conclusion necessary, not possible. For 
man is necessarily animal. It is clear then that the universal 
must be understood simply, without limitation in respect of 
time. 

Again let the premiss AB be universal and negative, and assume 
that A belongs to no B, but B possibly belongs to all C. These 
propositions being laid down, it is necessary that A possibly 
belongs to no C. Suppose that it cannot belong, and that B 
belongs to C, as above. It is necessary then that A belongs to 
some B: for we have a syllogism in the third figure: but this is 
impossible. Thus it will be possible for A to belong to no C; for if 



111 



at is supposed false, the consequence is an impossible one. This 
syllogism then does not establish that which is possible 
according to the definition, but that which does not necessarily 
belong to any part of the subject (for this is the contradictory of 
the assumption which was made: for it was supposed that A 
necessarily belongs to some C, but the syllogism per impossibile 
establishes the contradictory which is opposed to this). Further, 
it is clear also from an example that the conclusion will not 
establish possibility. Let A be 'raven', B 'intelligent', and C 'man'. 
A then belongs to no B: for no intelligent thing is a raven. But B 
is possible for all C: for every man may possibly be intelligent. 
But A necessarily belongs to no C: so the conclusion does not 
establish possibility. But neither is it always necessary. Let A be 
'moving', B 'science', C 'man'. A then will belong to no B; but B is 
possible for all C. And the conclusion will not be necessary. For 
it is not necessary that no man should move; rather it is not 
necessary that any man should move. Clearly then the 
conclusion establishes that one term does not necessarily 
belong to any instance of another term. But we must take our 
terms better. 

If the minor premiss is negative and indicates possibility, from 
the actual premisses taken there can be no syllogism, but if the 
problematic premiss is converted, a syllogism will be possible, 
as before. Let A belong to all B, and let B possibly belong to no C. 
If the terms are arranged thus, nothing necessarily follows: but 
if the proposition BC is converted and it is assumed that B is 
possible for all C, a syllogism results as before: for the terms are 
in the same relative positions. Likewise if both the relations are 
negative, if the major premiss states that A does not belong to B, 
and the minor premiss indicates that B may possibly belong to 
no C. Through the premisses actually taken nothing necessary 
results in any way; but if the problematic premiss is converted, 
we shall have a syllogism. Suppose that A belongs to no B, and B 
may possibly belong to no C. Through these comes nothing 



112 



necessary. But if B is assumed to be possible for all C (and this is 
true) and if the premiss AB remains as before, we shall again 
have the same syllogism. But if it be assumed that B does not 
belong to any C, instead of possibly not belonging, there cannot 
be a syllogism anyhow, whether the premiss AB is negative or 
affirmative. As common instances of a necessary and positive 
relation we may take the terms white - animal - snow: of a 
necessary and negative relation, white - animal - pitch. Clearly 
then if the terms are universal, and one of the premisses is 
assertoric, the other problematic, whenever the minor premiss 
is problematic a syllogism always results, only sometimes it 
results from the premisses that are taken, sometimes it requires 
the conversion of one premiss. We have stated when each of 
these happens and the reason why. But if one of the relations is 
universal, the other particular, then whenever the major 
premiss is universal and problematic, whether affirmative or 
negative, and the particular is affirmative and assertoric, there 
will be a perfect syllogism, just as when the terms are universal. 
The demonstration is the same as before. But whenever the 
major premiss is universal, but assertoric, not problematic, and 
the minor is particular and problematic, whether both 
premisses are negative or affirmative, or one is negative, the 
other affirmative, in all cases there will be an imperfect 
syllogism. Only some of them will be proved per impossibile, 
others by the conversion of the problematic premiss, as has 
been shown above. And a syllogism will be possible by means of 
conversion when the major premiss is universal and assertoric, 
whether positive or negative, and the minor particular, negative, 
and problematic, e.g. if A belongs to all B or to no B, and B may 
possibly not belong to some C. For if the premiss BC is 
converted in respect of possibility, a syllogism results. But 
whenever the particular premiss is assertoric and negative, 
there cannot be a syllogism. As instances of the positive relation 
we may take the terms white - animal - snow; of the negative, 



113 



white - animal - pitch. For the demonstration must be made 
through the indefinite nature of the particular premiss. But if 
the minor premiss is universal, and the major particular, 
whether either premiss is negative or affirmative, problematic 
or assertoric, nohow is a syllogism possible. Nor is a syllogism 
possible when the premisses are particular or indefinite, 
whether problematic or assertoric, or the one problematic, the 
other assertoric. The demonstration is the same as above. As 
instances of the necessary and positive relation we may take 
the terms animal - white - man; of the necessary and negative 
relation, animal - white - garment. It is evident then that if the 
major premiss is universal, a syllogism always results, but if the 
minor is universal nothing at all can ever be proved. 



16 

Whenever one premiss is necessary, the other problematic, 
there will be a syllogism when the terms are related as before; 
and a perfect syllogism when the minor premiss is necessary. If 
the premisses are affirmative the conclusion will be 
problematic, not assertoric, whether the premisses are universal 
or not: but if one is affirmative, the other negative, when the 
affirmative is necessary the conclusion will be problematic, not 
negative assertoric; but when the negative is necessary the 
conclusion will be problematic negative, and assertoric negative, 
whether the premisses are universal or not. Possibility in the 
conclusion must be understood in the same manner as before. 
There cannot be an inference to the necessary negative 
proposition: for 'not necessarily to belong' is different from 
'necessarily not to belong'. 



114 



If the premisses are affirmative, clearly the conclusion which 
follows is not necessary. Suppose A necessarily belongs to all B, 
and let B be possible for all C. We shall have an imperfect 
syllogism to prove that A may belong to all C. That it is 
imperfect is clear from the proof: for it will be proved in the 
same manner as above. Again, let A be possible for all B, and let 
B necessarily belong to all C. We shall then have a syllogism to 
prove that A may belong to all C, not that A does belong to all C: 
and it is perfect, not imperfect: for it is completed directly 
through the original premisses. 

But if the premisses are not similar in quality, suppose first that 
the negative premiss is necessary, and let necessarily A not be 
possible for any B, but let B be possible for all C. It is necessary 
then that A belongs to no C. For suppose A to belong to all C or 
to some C. Now we assumed that A is not possible for any B. 
Since then the negative proposition is convertible, B is not 
possible for any A. But A is supposed to belong to all C or to 
some C. Consequently B will not be possible for any C or for all 
C. But it was originally laid down that B is possible for all C. And 
it is clear that the possibility of belonging can be inferred, since 
the fact of not belonging is inferred. Again, let the affirmative 
premiss be necessary, and let A possibly not belong to any B, 
and let B necessarily belong to all C. The syllogism will be 
perfect, but it will establish a problematic negative, not an 
assertoric negative. For the major premiss was problematic, and 
further it is not possible to prove the assertoric conclusion per 
impossibile. For if it were supposed that A belongs to some C, 
and it is laid down that A possibly does not belong to any B, no 
impossible relation between B and C follows from these 
premisses. But if the minor premiss is negative, when it is 
problematic a syllogism is possible by conversion, as above; but 
when it is necessary no syllogism can be formed. Nor again 
when both premisses are negative, and the minor is necessary. 
The same terms as before serve both for the positive relation - 



115 



white-animal-snow, and for the negative relation - white- 
animal-pitch. 

The same relation will obtain in particular syllogisms. 
Whenever the negative proposition is necessary, the conclusion 
will be negative assertoric: e.g. if it is not possible that A should 
belong to any B, but B may belong to some of the Cs, it is 
necessary that A should not belong to some of the Cs. For if A 
belongs to all C, but cannot belong to any B, neither can B 
belong to any A. So if A belongs to all C, to none of the Cs can B 
belong. But it was laid down that B may belong to some C. But 
when the particular affirmative in the negative syllogism, e.g. 
BC the minor premiss, or the universal proposition in the 
affirmative syllogism, e.g. AB the major premiss, is necessary, 
there will not be an assertoric conclusion. The demonstration is 
the same as before. But if the minor premiss is universal, and 
problematic, whether affirmative or negative, and the major 
premiss is particular and necessary, there cannot be a syllogism. 
Premisses of this kind are possible both where the relation is 
positive and necessary, e.g. animal-white-man, and where it is 
necessary and negative, e.g. animal-white-garment. But when 
the universal is necessary, the particular problematic, if the 
universal is negative we may take the terms animal-white- 
raven to illustrate the positive relation, or animal-white-pitch to 
illustrate the negative; and if the universal is affirmative we 
may take the terms animal-white-swan to illustrate the positive 
relation, and animal-white-snow to illustrate the negative and 
necessary relation. Nor again is a syllogism possible when the 
premisses are indefinite, or both particular. Terms applicable in 
either case to illustrate the positive relation are animal-white- 
man: to illustrate the negative, animal-white-inanimate. For the 
relation of animal to some white, and of white to some 
inanimate, is both necessary and positive and necessary and 
negative. Similarly if the relation is problematic: so the terms 
may be used for all cases. 



116 



Clearly then from what has been said a syllogism results or not 
from similar relations of the terms whether we are dealing with 
simple existence or necessity, with this exception, that if the 
negative premiss is assertoric the conclusion is problematic, but 
if the negative premiss is necessary the conclusion is both 
problematic and negative assertoric. [It is clear also that all the 
syllogisms are imperfect and are perfected by means of the 
figures above mentioned.] 



17 

In the second figure whenever both premisses are problematic, 
no syllogism is possible, whether the premisses are affirmative 
or negative, universal or particular. But when one premiss is 
assertoric, the other problematic, if the affirmative is assertoric 
no syllogism is possible, but if the universal negative is 
assertoric a conclusion can always be drawn. Similarly when 
one premiss is necessary, the other problematic. Here also we 
must understand the term 'possible' in the conclusion, in the 
same sense as before. 

First we must point out that the negative problematic 
proposition is not convertible, e.g. if A may belong to no B, it 
does not follow that B may belong to no A. For suppose it to 
follow and assume that B may belong to no A. Since then 
problematic affirmations are convertible with negations, 
whether they are contraries or contradictories, and since B may 
belong to no A, it is clear that B may belong to all A. But this is 
false: for if all this can be that, it does not follow that all that 
can be this: consequently the negative proposition is not 
convertible. Further, these propositions are not incompatible, 'A 
may belong to no B', 'B necessarily does not belong to some of 



117 



the As'; e.g. it is possible that no man should be white (for it is 
also possible that every man should be white), but it is not true 
to say that it is possible that no white thing should be a man: 
for many white things are necessarily not men, and the 
necessary (as we saw) other than the possible. 

Moreover it is not possible to prove the convertibility of these 
propositions by a reductio ad absurdum, i.e. by claiming assent 
to the following argument: 'since it is false that B may belong to 
no A, it is true that it cannot belong to no A, for the one 
statement is the contradictory of the other. But if this is so, it is 
true that B necessarily belongs to some of the As: consequently 
A necessarily belongs to some of the Bs. But this is impossible.' 
The argument cannot be admitted, for it does not follow that 
some A is necessarily B, if it is not possible that no A should be 
B. For the latter expression is used in two senses, one if A some 
is necessarily B, another if some A is necessarily not B. For it is 
not true to say that that which necessarily does not belong to 
some of the As may possibly not belong to any A, just as it is not 
true to say that what necessarily belongs to some A may 
possibly belong to all A. If any one then should claim that 
because it is not possible for C to belong to all D, it necessarily 
does not belong to some D, he would make a false assumption: 
for it does belong to all D, but because in some cases it belongs 
necessarily, therefore we say that it is not possible for it to 
belong to all. Hence both the propositions 'A necessarily belongs 
to some B' and A necessarily does not belong to some B' are 
opposed to the proposition A belongs to all B'. Similarly also 
they are opposed to the proposition A may belong to no B'. It is 
clear then that in relation to what is possible and not possible, 
in the sense originally defined, we must assume, not that A 
necessarily belongs to some B, but that A necessarily does not 
belong to some B. But if this is assumed, no absurdity results: 
consequently no syllogism. It is clear from what has been said 
that the negative proposition is not convertible. 



118 



This being proved, suppose it possible that A may belong to no B 
and to all C. By means of conversion no syllogism will result: for 
the major premiss, as has been said, is not convertible. Nor can 
a proof be obtained by a reductio ad absurdum: for if it is 
assumed that B can belong to all C, no false consequence 
results: for A may belong both to all C and to no C. In general, if 
there is a syllogism, it is clear that its conclusion will be 
problematic because neither of the premisses is assertoric; and 
this must be either affirmative or negative. But neither is 
possible. Suppose the conclusion is affirmative: it will be proved 
by an example that the predicate cannot belong to the subject. 
Suppose the conclusion is negative: it will be proved that it is 
not problematic but necessary. Let A be white, B man, C horse. It 
is possible then for A to belong to all of the one and to none of 
the other. But it is not possible for B to belong nor not to belong 
to C. That it is not possible for it to belong, is clear. For no horse 
is a man. Neither is it possible for it not to belong. For it is 
necessary that no horse should be a man, but the necessary we 
found to be different from the possible. No syllogism then 
results. A similar proof can be given if the major premiss is 
negative, the minor affirmative, or if both are affirmative or 
negative. The demonstration can be made by means of the same 
terms. And whenever one premiss is universal, the other 
particular, or both are particular or indefinite, or in whatever 
other way the premisses can be altered, the proof will always 
proceed through the same terms. Clearly then, if both the 
premisses are problematic, no syllogism results. 



18 

But if one premiss is assertoric, the other problematic, if the 
affirmative is assertoric and the negative problematic no 



119 



syllogism will be possible, whether the premisses are universal 
or particular. The proof is the same as above, and by means of 
the same terms. But when the affirmative premiss is 
problematic, and the negative assertoric, we shall have a 
syllogism. Suppose A belongs to no B, but can belong to all C. If 
the negative proposition is converted, B will belong to no A. But 
ex hypothesi can belong to all C: so a syllogism is made, proving 
by means of the first figure that B may belong to no C. Similarly 
also if the minor premiss is negative. But if both premisses are 
negative, one being assertoric, the other problematic, nothing 
follows necessarily from these premisses as they stand, but if 
the problematic premiss is converted into its complementary 
affirmative a syllogism is formed to prove that B may belong to 
no C, as before: for we shall again have the first figure. But if 
both premisses are affirmative, no syllogism will be possible. 
This arrangement of terms is possible both when the relation is 
positive, e.g. health, animal, man, and when it is negative, e.g. 
health, horse, man. 

The same will hold good if the syllogisms are particular. 
Whenever the affirmative proposition is assertoric, whether 
universal or particular, no syllogism is possible (this is proved 
similarly and by the same examples as above), but when the 
negative proposition is assertoric, a conclusion can be drawn by 
means of conversion, as before. Again if both the relations are 
negative, and the assertoric proposition is universal, although 
no conclusion follows from the actual premisses, a syllogism 
can be obtained by converting the problematic premiss into its 
complementary affirmative as before. But if the negative 
proposition is assertoric, but particular, no syllogism is possible, 
whether the other premiss is affirmative or negative. Nor can a 
conclusion be drawn when both premisses are indefinite, 
whether affirmative or negative, or particular. The proof is the 
same and by the same terms. 



120 



19 

If one of the premisses is necessary, the other problematic, then 
if the negative is necessary a syllogistic conclusion can be 
drawn, not merely a negative problematic but also a negative 
assertoric conclusion; but if the affirmative premiss is 
necessary, no conclusion is possible. Suppose that A necessarily 
belongs to no B, but may belong to all C. If the negative premiss 
is converted B will belong to no A: but A ex hypothesi is capable 
of belonging to all C: so once more a conclusion is drawn by the 
first figure that B may belong to no C. But at the same time it is 
clear that B will not belong to any C. For assume that it does: 
then if A cannot belong to any B, and B belongs to some of the 
Cs, A cannot belong to some of the Cs: but ex hypothesi it may 
belong to all. A similar proof can be given if the minor premiss 
is negative. Again let the affirmative proposition be necessary, 
and the other problematic; i.e. suppose that A may belong to no 
B, but necessarily belongs to all C. When the terms are arranged 
in this way, no syllogism is possible. For (1) it sometimes turns 
out that B necessarily does not belong to C. Let A be white, B 
man, C swan. White then necessarily belongs to swan, but may 
belong to no man; and man necessarily belongs to no swan; 
Clearly then we cannot draw a problematic conclusion; for that 
which is necessary is admittedly distinct from that which is 
possible. (2) Nor again can we draw a necessary conclusion: for 
that presupposes that both premisses are necessary, or at any 
rate the negative premiss. (3) Further it is possible also, when 
the terms are so arranged, that B should belong to C: for 
nothing prevents C falling under B, A being possible for all B, 
and necessarily belonging to C; e.g. if C stands for 'awake', B for 
'animal', A for 'motion'. For motion necessarily belongs to what 



121 



is awake, and is possible for every animal: and everything that is 
awake is animal. Clearly then the conclusion cannot be the 
negative assertion, if the relation must be positive when the 
terms are related as above. Nor can the opposite affirmations be 
established: consequently no syllogism is possible. A similar 
proof is possible if the major premiss is affirmative. 

But if the premisses are similar in quality, when they are 
negative a syllogism can always be formed by converting the 
problematic premiss into its complementary affirmative as 
before. Suppose A necessarily does not belong to B, and possibly 
may not belong to C: if the premisses are converted B belongs to 
no A, and A may possibly belong to all C: thus we have the first 
figure. Similarly if the minor premiss is negative. But if the 
premisses are affirmative there cannot be a syllogism. Clearly 
the conclusion cannot be a negative assertoric or a negative 
necessary proposition because no negative premiss has been 
laid down either in the assertoric or in the necessary mode. Nor 
can the conclusion be a problematic negative proposition. For if 
the terms are so related, there are cases in which B necessarily 
will not belong to C; e.g. suppose that A is white, B swan, C man. 
Nor can the opposite affirmations be established, since we have 
shown a case in which B necessarily does not belong to C. A 
syllogism then is not possible at all. 

Similar relations will obtain in particular syllogisms. For 
whenever the negative proposition is universal and necessary, a 
syllogism will always be possible to prove both a problematic 
and a negative assertoric proposition (the proof proceeds by 
conversion); but when the affirmative proposition is universal 
and necessary, no syllogistic conclusion can be drawn. This can 
be proved in the same way as for universal propositions, and by 
the same terms. Nor is a syllogistic conclusion possible when 
both premisses are affirmative: this also may be proved as 
above. But when both premisses are negative, and the premiss 



122 



that definitely disconnects two terms is universal and 
necessary, though nothing follows necessarily from the 
premisses as they are stated, a conclusion can be drawn as 
above if the problematic premiss is converted into its 
complementary affirmative. But if both are indefinite or 
particular, no syllogism can be formed. The same proof will 
serve, and the same terms. 

It is clear then from what has been said that if the universal and 
negative premiss is necessary, a syllogism is always possible, 
proving not merely a negative problematic, but also a negative 
assertoric proposition; but if the affirmative premiss is 
necessary no conclusion can be drawn. It is clear too that a 
syllogism is possible or not under the same conditions whether 
the mode of the premisses is assertoric or necessary. And it is 
clear that all the syllogisms are imperfect, and are completed by 
means of the figures mentioned. 



20 

In the last figure a syllogism is possible whether both or only 
one of the premisses is problematic. When the premisses are 
problematic the conclusion will be problematic; and also when 
one premiss is problematic, the other assertoric. But when the 
other premiss is necessary, if it is affirmative the conclusion will 
be neither necessary or assertoric; but if it is negative the 
syllogism will result in a negative assertoric proposition, as 
above. In these also we must understand the expression 
'possible' in the conclusion in the same way as before. 

First let the premisses be problematic and suppose that both A 
and B may possibly belong to every C. Since then the affirmative 
proposition is convertible into a particular, and B may possibly 



123 



belong to every C, it follows that C may possibly belong to some 
B. So, if A is possible for every C, and C is possible for some of 
the Bs, then A is possible for some of the Bs. For we have got the 
first figure. And A if may possibly belong to no C, but B may 
possibly belong to all C, it follows that A may possibly not 
belong to some B: for we shall have the first figure again by 
conversion. But if both premisses should be negative no 
necessary consequence will follow from them as they are 
stated, but if the premisses are converted into their 
corresponding affirmatives there will be a syllogism as before. 
For if A and B may possibly not belong to C, if 'may possibly 
belong' is substituted we shall again have the first figure by 
means of conversion. But if one of the premisses is universal, 
the other particular, a syllogism will be possible, or not, under 
the arrangement of the terms as in the case of assertoric 
propositions. Suppose that A may possibly belong to all C, and B 
to some C. We shall have the first figure again if the particular 
premiss is converted. For if A is possible for all C, and C for 
some of the Bs, then A is possible for some of the Bs. Similarly if 
the proposition BC is universal. Likewise also if the proposition 
AC is negative, and the proposition BC affirmative: for we shall 
again have the first figure by conversion. But if both premisses 
should be negative - the one universal and the other particular 
- although no syllogistic conclusion will follow from the 
premisses as they are put, it will follow if they are converted, as 
above. But when both premisses are indefinite or particular, no 
syllogism can be formed: for A must belong sometimes to all B 
and sometimes to no B. To illustrate the affirmative relation 
take the terms animal-man-white; to illustrate the negative, 
take the terms horse-man-white - white being the middle term. 



124 



21 

If one premiss is pure, the other problematic, the conclusion 
will be problematic, not pure; and a syllogism will be possible 
under the same arrangement of the terms as before. First let the 
premisses be affirmative: suppose that A belongs to all C, and B 
may possibly belong to all C. If the proposition BC is converted, 
we shall have the first figure, and the conclusion that A may 
possibly belong to some of the Bs. For when one of the 
premisses in the first figure is problematic, the conclusion also 
(as we saw) is problematic. Similarly if the proposition BC is 
pure, AC problematic; or if AC is negative, BC affirmative, no 
matter which of the two is pure; in both cases the conclusion 
will be problematic: for the first figure is obtained once more, 
and it has been proved that if one premiss is problematic in that 
figure the conclusion also will be problematic. But if the minor 
premiss BC is negative, or if both premisses are negative, no 
syllogistic conclusion can be drawn from the premisses as they 
stand, but if they are converted a syllogism is obtained as 
before. 

If one of the premisses is universal, the other particular, then 
when both are affirmative, or when the universal is negative, 
the particular affirmative, we shall have the same sort of 
syllogisms: for all are completed by means of the first figure. So 
it is clear that we shall have not a pure but a problematic 
syllogistic conclusion. But if the affirmative premiss is 
universal, the negative particular, the proof will proceed by a 
reductio ad impossibile. Suppose that B belongs to all C, and A 
may possibly not belong to some C: it follows that may possibly 
not belong to some B. For if A necessarily belongs to all B, and B 
(as has been assumed) belongs to all C, A will necessarily belong 
to all C: for this has been proved before. But it was assumed at 
the outset that A may possibly not belong to some C. 



125 



Whenever both premisses are indefinite or particular, no 
syllogism will be possible. The demonstration is the same as 
was given in the case of universal premisses, and proceeds by 
means of the same terms. 



22 

If one of the premisses is necessary, the other problematic, 
when the premisses are affirmative a problematic affirmative 
conclusion can always be drawn; when one proposition is 
affirmative, the other negative, if the affirmative is necessary a 
problematic negative can be inferred; but if the negative 
proposition is necessary both a problematic and a pure negative 
conclusion are possible. But a necessary negative conclusion 
will not be possible, any more than in the other figures. Suppose 
first that the premisses are affirmative, i.e. that A necessarily 
belongs to all C, and B may possibly belong to all C. Since then A 
must belong to all C, and C may belong to some B, it follows that 
A may (not does) belong to some B: for so it resulted in the first 
figure. A similar proof may be given if the proposition BC is 
necessary, and AC is problematic. Again suppose one 
proposition is affirmative, the other negative, the affirmative 
being necessary: i.e. suppose A may possibly belong to no C, but 
B necessarily belongs to all C. We shall have the first figure once 
more: and - since the negative premiss is problematic - it is 
clear that the conclusion will be problematic: for when the 
premisses stand thus in the first figure, the conclusion (as we 
found) is problematic. But if the negative premiss is necessary, 
the conclusion will be not only that A may possibly not belong 
to some B but also that it does not belong to some B. For 
suppose that A necessarily does not belong to C, but B may 
belong to all C. If the affirmative proposition BC is converted, we 



126 



shall have the first figure, and the negative premiss is necessary. 
But when the premisses stood thus, it resulted that A might 
possibly not belong to some C, and that it did not belong to 
some C; consequently here it follows that A does not belong to 
some B. But when the minor premiss is negative, if it is 
problematic we shall have a syllogism by altering the premiss 
into its complementary affirmative, as before; but if it is 
necessary no syllogism can be formed. For A sometimes 
necessarily belongs to all B, and sometimes cannot possibly 
belong to any B. To illustrate the former take the terms sleep- 
sleeping horse-man; to illustrate the latter take the terms sleep- 
waking horse-man. 

Similar results will obtain if one of the terms is related 
universally to the middle, the other in part. If both premisses 
are affirmative, the conclusion will be problematic, not pure; 
and also when one premiss is negative, the other affirmative, 
the latter being necessary. But when the negative premiss is 
necessary, the conclusion also will be a pure negative 
proposition; for the same kind of proof can be given whether 
the terms are universal or not. For the syllogisms must be made 
perfect by means of the first figure, so that a result which 
follows in the first figure follows also in the third. But when the 
minor premiss is negative and universal, if it is problematic a 
syllogism can be formed by means of conversion; but if it is 
necessary a syllogism is not possible. The proof will follow the 
same course as where the premisses are universal; and the 
same terms may be used. 

It is clear then in this figure also when and how a syllogism can 
be formed, and when the conclusion is problematic, and when 
it is pure. It is evident also that all syllogisms in this figure are 
imperfect, and that they are made perfect by means of the first 
figure. 



127 



23 

It is clear from what has been said that the syllogisms in these 
figures are made perfect by means of universal syllogisms in 
the first figure and are reduced to them. That every syllogism 
without qualification can be so treated, will be clear presently, 
when it has been proved that every syllogism is formed through 
one or other of these figures. 

It is necessary that every demonstration and every syllogism 
should prove either that something belongs or that it does not, 
and this either universally or in part, and further either 
ostensively or hypothetically. One sort of hypothetical proof is 
the reductio ad impossibile. Let us speak first of ostensive 
syllogisms: for after these have been pointed out the truth of 
our contention will be clear with regard to those which are 
proved per impossibile, and in general hypothetically. 

If then one wants to prove syllogistically A of B, either as an 
attribute of it or as not an attribute of it, one must assert 
something of something else. If now A should be asserted of B, 
the proposition originally in question will have been assumed. 
But if A should be asserted of C, but C should not be asserted of 
anything, nor anything of it, nor anything else of A, no syllogism 
will be possible. For nothing necessarily follows from the 
assertion of some one thing concerning some other single thing. 
Thus we must take another premiss as well. If then A be 
asserted of something else, or something else of A, or 
something different of C, nothing prevents a syllogism being 
formed, but it will not be in relation to B through the premisses 
taken. Nor when C belongs to something else, and that to 
something else and so on, no connexion however being made 



128 



with B, will a syllogism be possible concerning A in its relation 
to B. For in general we stated that no syllogism can establish the 
attribution of one thing to another, unless some middle term is 
taken, which is somehow related to each by way of predication. 
For the syllogism in general is made out of premisses, and a 
syllogism referring to this out of premisses with the same 
reference, and a syllogism relating this to that proceeds through 
premisses which relate this to that. But it is impossible to take a 
premiss in reference to B, if we neither affirm nor deny 
anything of it; or again to take a premiss relating A to B, if we 
take nothing common, but affirm or deny peculiar attributes of 
each. So we must take something midway between the two, 
which will connect the predications, if we are to have a 
syllogism relating this to that. If then we must take something 
common in relation to both, and this is possible in three ways 
(either by predicating A of C, and C of B, or C of both, or both of 
C), and these are the figures of which we have spoken, it is clear 
that every syllogism must be made in one or other of these 
figures. The argument is the same if several middle terms 
should be necessary to establish the relation to B; for the figure 
will be the same whether there is one middle term or many. 

It is clear then that the ostensive syllogisms are effected by 
means of the aforesaid figures; these considerations will show 
that reductiones ad also are effected in the same way. For all 
who effect an argument per impossibile infer syllogistically 
what is false, and prove the original conclusion hypothetically 
when something impossible results from the assumption of its 
contradictory; e.g. that the diagonal of the square is 
incommensurate with the side, because odd numbers are equal 
to evens if it is supposed to be commensurate. One infers 
syllogistically that odd numbers come out equal to evens, and 
one proves hypothetically the incommensurability of the 
diagonal, since a falsehood results through contradicting this. 
For this we found to be reasoning per impossibile, viz. proving 



129 



something impossible by means of an hypothesis conceded at 
the beginning. Consequently, since the falsehood is established 
in reductions ad impossibile by an ostensive syllogism, and the 
original conclusion is proved hypothetically, and we have 
already stated that ostensive syllogisms are effected by means 
of these figures, it is evident that syllogisms per impossibile 
also will be made through these figures. Likewise all the other 
hypothetical syllogisms: for in every case the syllogism leads up 
to the proposition that is substituted for the original thesis; but 
the original thesis is reached by means of a concession or some 
other hypothesis. But if this is true, every demonstration and 
every syllogism must be formed by means of the three figures 
mentioned above. But when this has been shown it is clear that 
every syllogism is perfected by means of the first figure and is 
reducible to the universal syllogisms in this figure. 



24 

Further in every syllogism one of the premisses must be 
affirmative, and universality must be present: unless one of the 
premisses is universal either a syllogism will not be possible, or 
it will not refer to the subject proposed, or the original position 
will be begged. Suppose we have to prove that pleasure in music 
is good. If one should claim as a premiss that pleasure is good 
without adding 'all', no syllogism will be possible; if one should 
claim that some pleasure is good, then if it is different from 
pleasure in music, it is not relevant to the subject proposed; if it 
is this very pleasure, one is assuming that which was proposed 
at the outset to be proved. This is more obvious in geometrical 
proofs, e.g. that the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle 
are equal. Suppose the lines A and B have been drawn to the 
centre. If then one should assume that the angle AC is equal to 



130 



the angle BD, without claiming generally that angles of 
semicircles are equal; and again if one should assume that the 
angle C is equal to the angle D, without the additional 
assumption that every angle of a segment is equal to every 
other angle of the same segment; and further if one should 
assume that when equal angles are taken from the whole 
angles, which are themselves equal, the remainders E and F are 
equal, he will beg the thing to be proved, unless he also states 
that when equals are taken from equals the remainders are 
equal. 

It is clear then that in every syllogism there must be a universal 
premiss, and that a universal statement is proved only when all 
the premisses are universal, while a particular statement is 
proved both from two universal premisses and from one only: 
consequently if the conclusion is universal, the premisses also 
must be universal, but if the premisses are universal it is 
possible that the conclusion may not be universal. And it is 
clear also that in every syllogism either both or one of the 
premisses must be like the conclusion. I mean not only in being 
affirmative or negative, but also in being necessary, pure, 
problematic. We must consider also the other forms of 
predication. 

It is clear also when a syllogism in general can be made and 
when it cannot; and when a valid, when a perfect syllogism can 
be formed; and that if a syllogism is formed the terms must be 
arranged in one of the ways that have been mentioned. 



25 

It is clear too that every demonstration will proceed through 
three terms and no more, unless the same conclusion is 



131 



established by different pairs of propositions; e.g. the 
conclusion E may be established through the propositions A and 
B, and through the propositions C and D, or through the 
propositions A and B, or A and C, or B and C. For nothing 
prevents there being several middles for the same terms. But in 
that case there is not one but several syllogisms. Or again when 
each of the propositions A and B is obtained by syllogistic 
inference, e.g. by means of D and E, and again B by means of F 
and G. Or one may be obtained by syllogistic, the other by 
inductive inference. But thus also the syllogisms are many; for 
the conclusions are many, e.g. A and B and C. But if this can be 
called one syllogism, not many, the same conclusion may be 
reached by more than three terms in this way, but it cannot be 
reached as C is established by means of A and B. Suppose that 
the proposition E is inferred from the premisses A, B, C, and D. It 
is necessary then that of these one should be related to another 
as whole to part: for it has already been proved that if a 
syllogism is formed some of its terms must be related in this 
way. Suppose then that A stands in this relation to B. Some 
conclusion then follows from them. It must either be E or one or 
other of C and D, or something other than these. 

(1) If it is E the syllogism will have A and B for its sole premisses. 
But if C and D are so related that one is whole, the other part, 
some conclusion will follow from them also; and it must be 
either E, or one or other of the propositions A and B, or 
something other than these. And if it is (i) E, or (ii) A or B, either 
(i) the syllogisms will be more than one, or (ii) the same thing 
happens to be inferred by means of several terms only in the 
sense which we saw to be possible. But if (iii) the conclusion is 
other than E or A or B, the syllogisms will be many, and 
unconnected with one another. But if C is not so related to D as 
to make a syllogism, the propositions will have been assumed 
to no purpose, unless for the sake of induction or of obscuring 
the argument or something of the sort. 



132 



(2) But if from the propositions A and B there follows not E but 
some other conclusion, and if from C and D either A or B follows 
or something else, then there are several syllogisms, and they 
do not establish the conclusion proposed: for we assumed that 
the syllogism proved E. And if no conclusion follows from C and 
D, it turns out that these propositions have been assumed to no 
purpose, and the syllogism does not prove the original 
proposition. 

So it is clear that every demonstration and every syllogism will 
proceed through three terms only. 

This being evident, it is clear that a syllogistic conclusion 
follows from two premisses and not from more than two. For 
the three terms make two premisses, unless a new premiss is 
assumed, as was said at the beginning, to perfect the 
syllogisms. It is clear therefore that in whatever syllogistic 
argument the premisses through which the main conclusion 
follows (for some of the preceding conclusions must be 
premisses) are not even in number, this argument either has 
not been drawn syllogistically or it has assumed more than was 
necessary to establish its thesis. 

If then syllogisms are taken with respect to their main 
premisses, every syllogism will consist of an even number of 
premisses and an odd number of terms (for the terms exceed 
the premisses by one), and the conclusions will be half the 
number of the premisses. But whenever a conclusion is reached 
by means of prosyllogisms or by means of several continuous 
middle terms, e.g. the proposition AB by means of the middle 
terms C and D, the number of the terms will similarly exceed 
that of the premisses by one (for the extra term must either be 
added outside or inserted: but in either case it follows that the 
relations of predication are one fewer than the terms related), 
and the premisses will be equal in number to the relations of 



133 



predication. The premisses however will not always be even, the 
terms odd; but they will alternate - when the premisses are 
even, the terms must be odd; when the terms are even, the 
premisses must be odd: for along with one term one premiss is 
added, if a term is added from any quarter. Consequently since 
the premisses were (as we saw) even, and the terms odd, we 
must make them alternately even and odd at each addition. But 
the conclusions will not follow the same arrangement either in 
respect to the terms or to the premisses. For if one term is 
added, conclusions will be added less by one than the pre- 
existing terms: for the conclusion is drawn not in relation to the 
single term last added, but in relation to all the rest, e.g. if to 
ABC the term D is added, two conclusions are thereby added, 
one in relation to A, the other in relation to B. Similarly with any 
further additions. And similarly too if the term is inserted in the 
middle: for in relation to one term only, a syllogism will not be 
constructed. Consequently the conclusions will be much more 
numerous than the terms or the premisses. 



26 

Since we understand the subjects with which syllogisms are 
concerned, what sort of conclusion is established in each figure, 
and in how many moods this is done, it is evident to us both 
what sort of problem is difficult and what sort is easy to prove. 
For that which is concluded in many figures and through many 
moods is easier; that which is concluded in few figures and 
through few moods is more difficult to attempt. The universal 
affirmative is proved by means of the first figure only and by 
this in only one mood; the universal negative is proved both 
through the first figure and through the second, through the 
first in one mood, through the second in two. The particular 



134 



affirmative is proved through the first and through the last 
figure, in one mood through the first, in three moods through 
the last. The particular negative is proved in all the figures, but 
once in the first, in two moods in the second, in three moods in 
the third. It is clear then that the universal affirmative is most 
difficult to establish, most easy to overthrow. In general, 
universals are easier game for the destroyer than particulars: 
for whether the predicate belongs to none or not to some, they 
are destroyed: and the particular negative is proved in all the 
figures, the universal negative in two. Similarly with universal 
negatives: the original statement is destroyed, whether the 
predicate belongs to all or to some: and this we found possible 
in two figures. But particular statements can be refuted in one 
way only - by proving that the predicate belongs either to all or 
to none. But particular statements are easier to establish: for 
proof is possible in more figures and through more moods. And 
in general we must not forget that it is possible to refute 
statements by means of one another, I mean, universal 
statements by means of particular, and particular statements by 
means of universal: but it is not possible to establish universal 
statements by means of particular, though it is possible to 
establish particular statements by means of universal. At the 
same time it is evident that it is easier to refute than to 
establish. 

The manner in which every syllogism is produced, the number 
of the terms and premisses through which it proceeds, the 
relation of the premisses to one another, the character of the 
problem proved in each figure, and the number of the figures 
appropriate to each problem, all these matters are clear from 
what has been said. 



135 



27 

We must now state how we may ourselves always have a supply 
of syllogisms in reference to the problem proposed and by what 
road we may reach the principles relative to the problem: for 
perhaps we ought not only to investigate the construction of 
syllogisms, but also to have the power of making them. 

Of all the things which exist some are such that they cannot be 
predicated of anything else truly and universally, e.g. Cleon and 
Callias, i.e. the individual and sensible, but other things may be 
predicated of them (for each of these is both man and animal); 
and some things are themselves predicated of others, but 
nothing prior is predicated of them; and some are predicated of 
others, and yet others of them, e.g. man of Callias and animal of 
man. It is clear then that some things are naturally not stated of 
anything: for as a rule each sensible thing is such that it cannot 
be predicated of anything, save incidentally: for we sometimes 
say that that white object is Socrates, or that that which 
approaches is Callias. We shall explain in another place that 
there is an upward limit also to the process of predicating: for 
the present we must assume this. Of these ultimate predicates 
it is not possible to demonstrate another predicate, save as a 
matter of opinion, but these may be predicated of other things. 
Neither can individuals be predicated of other things, though 
other things can be predicated of them. Whatever lies between 
these limits can be spoken of in both ways: they may be stated 
of others, and others stated of them. And as a rule arguments 
and inquiries are concerned with these things. We must select 
the premisses suitable to each problem in this manner: first we 
must lay down the subject and the definitions and the 
properties of the thing; next we must lay down those attributes 
which follow the thing, and again those which the thing follows, 
and those which cannot belong to it. But those to which it 
cannot belong need not be selected, because the negative 



136 



statement implied above is convertible. Of the attributes which 
follow we must distinguish those which fall within the 
definition, those which are predicated as properties, and those 
which are predicated as accidents, and of the latter those which 
apparently and those which really belong. The larger the supply 
a man has of these, the more quickly will he reach a conclusion; 
and in proportion as he apprehends those which are truer, the 
more cogently will he demonstrate. But he must select not 
those which follow some particular but those which follow the 
thing as a whole, e.g. not what follows a particular man but 
what follows every man: for the syllogism proceeds through 
universal premisses. If the statement is indefinite, it is 
uncertain whether the premiss is universal, but if the statement 
is definite, the matter is clear. Similarly one must select those 
attributes which the subject follows as wholes, for the reason 
given. But that which follows one must not suppose to follow as 
a whole, e.g. that every animal follows man or every science 
music, but only that it follows, without qualification, and indeed 
we state it in a proposition: for the other statement is useless 
and impossible, e.g. that every man is every animal or justice is 
all good. But that which something follows receives the mark 
'every'. Whenever the subject, for which we must obtain the 
attributes that follow, is contained by something else, what 
follows or does not follow the highest term universally must not 
be selected in dealing with the subordinate term (for these 
attributes have been taken in dealing with the superior term; for 
what follows animal also follows man, and what does not 
belong to animal does not belong to man); but we must choose 
those attributes which are peculiar to each subject. For some 
things are peculiar to the species as distinct from the genus; for 
species being distinct there must be attributes peculiar to each. 
Nor must we take as things which the superior term follows, 
those things which the inferior term follows, e.g. take as 
subjects of the predicate 'animal' what are really subjects of the 



137 



predicate 'man'. It is necessary indeed, if animal follows man, 
that it should follow all these also. But these belong more 
properly to the choice of what concerns man. One must 
apprehend also normal consequents and normal antecedents - 
for propositions which obtain normally are established 
syllogistically from premisses which obtain normally, some if 
not all of them having this character of normality. For the 
conclusion of each syllogism resembles its principles. We must 
not however choose attributes which are consequent upon all 
the terms: for no syllogism can be made out of such premisses. 
The reason why this is so will be clear in the sequel. 



28 

If men wish to establish something about some whole, they 
must look to the subjects of that which is being established (the 
subjects of which it happens to be asserted), and the attributes 
which follow that of which it is to be predicated. For if any of 
these subjects is the same as any of these attributes, the 
attribute originally in question must belong to the subject 
originally in question. But if the purpose is to establish not a 
universal but a particular proposition, they must look for the 
terms of which the terms in question are predicable: for if any 
of these are identical, the attribute in question must belong to 
some of the subject in question. Whenever the one term has to 
belong to none of the other, one must look to the consequents 
of the subject, and to those attributes which cannot possibly be 
present in the predicate in question: or conversely to the 
attributes which cannot possibly be present in the subject, and 
to the consequents of the predicate. If any members of these 
groups are identical, one of the terms in question cannot 
possibly belong to any of the other. For sometimes a syllogism 



138 



in the first figure results, sometimes a syllogism in the second. 
But if the object is to establish a particular negative proposition, 
we must find antecedents of the subject in question and 
attributes which cannot possibly belong to the predicate in 
question. If any members of these two groups are identical, it 
follows that one of the terms in question does not belong to 
some of the other. Perhaps each of these statements will 
become clearer in the following way. Suppose the consequents 
of A are designated by B, the antecedents of A by C, attributes 
which cannot possibly belong to A by D. Suppose again that the 
attributes of E are designated by F, the antecedents of E by G, 
and attributes which cannot belong to E by H. If then one of the 
Cs should be identical with one of the Fs, A must belong to all E: 
for F belongs to all E, and A to all C, consequently A belongs to 
all E. If C and G are identical, A must belong to some of the Es: 
for A follows C, and E follows all G. If F and D are identical, A 
will belong to none of the Es by a prosyllogism: for since the 
negative proposition is convertible, and F is identical with D, A 
will belong to none of the Fs, but F belongs to all E. Again, if B 
and H are identical, A will belong to none of the Es: for B will 
belong to all A, but to no E: for it was assumed to be identical 
with H, and H belonged to none of the Es. If D and G are 
identical, A will not belong to some of the Es: for it will not 
belong to G, because it does not belong to D: but G falls under E: 
consequently A will not belong to some of the Es. If B is 
identical with G, there will be a converted syllogism: for E will 
belong to all A since B belongs to A and E to B (for B was found 
to be identical with G): but that A should belong to all E is not 
necessary, but it must belong to some E because it is possible to 
convert the universal statement into a particular. 

It is clear then that in every proposition which requires proof 
we must look to the aforesaid relations of the subject and 
predicate in question: for all syllogisms proceed through these. 
But if we are seeking consequents and antecedents we must 



139 



look for those which are primary and most universal, e.g. in 
reference to E we must look to KF rather than to F alone, and in 
reference to A we must look to KC rather than to C alone. For if 
A belongs to KF, it belongs both to F and to E: but if it does not 
follow KF, it may yet follow F. Similarly we must consider the 
antecedents of A itself: for if a term follows the primary 
antecedents, it will follow those also which are subordinate, but 
if it does not follow the former, it may yet follow the latter. 

It is clear too that the inquiry proceeds through the three terms 
and the two premisses, and that all the syllogisms proceed 
through the aforesaid figures. For it is proved that A belongs to 
all E, whenever an identical term is found among the Cs and Fs. 
This will be the middle term; A and E will be the extremes. So 
the first figure is formed. And A will belong to some E, whenever 
C and G are apprehended to be the same. This is the last figure: 
for G becomes the middle term. And A will belong to no E, when 
D and F are identical. Thus we have both the first figure and the 
middle figure; the first, because A belongs to no F, since the 
negative statement is convertible, and F belongs to all E: the 
middle figure because D belongs to no A, and to all E. And A will 
not belong to some E, whenever D and G are identical. This is 
the last figure: for A will belong to no G, and E will belong to all 
G. Clearly then all syllogisms proceed through the aforesaid 
figures, and we must not select consequents of all the terms, 
because no syllogism is produced from them. For (as we saw) it 
is not possible at all to establish a proposition from 
consequents, and it is not possible to refute by means of a 
consequent of both the terms in question: for the middle term 
must belong to the one, and not belong to the other. 

It is clear too that other methods of inquiry by selection of 
middle terms are useless to produce a syllogism, e.g. if the 
consequents of the terms in question are identical, or if the 
antecedents of A are identical with those attributes which 



140 



cannot possibly belong to E, or if those attributes are identical 
which cannot belong to either term: for no syllogism is 
produced by means of these. For if the consequents are 
identical, e.g. B and F, we have the middle figure with both 
premisses affirmative: if the antecedents of A are identical with 
attributes which cannot belong to E, e.g. C with H, we have the 
first figure with its minor premiss negative. If attributes which 
cannot belong to either term are identical, e.g. C and H, both 
premisses are negative, either in the first or in the middle 
figure. But no syllogism is possible in this way. 

It is evident too that we must find out which terms in this 
inquiry are identical, not which are different or contrary, first 
because the object of our investigation is the middle term, and 
the middle term must be not diverse but identical. Secondly, 
wherever it happens that a syllogism results from taking 
contraries or terms which cannot belong to the same thing, all 
arguments can be reduced to the aforesaid moods, e.g. if B and F 
are contraries or cannot belong to the same thing. For if these 
are taken, a syllogism will be formed to prove that A belongs to 
none of the Es, not however from the premisses taken but in the 
aforesaid mood. For B will belong to all A and to no E. 
Consequently B must be identical with one of the Hs. Again, if B 
and G cannot belong to the same thing, it follows that A will not 
belong to some of the Es: for then too we shall have the middle 
figure: for B will belong to all A and to no G. Consequently B 
must be identical with some of the Hs. For the fact that B and G 
cannot belong to the same thing differs in no way from the fact 
that B is identical with some of the Hs: for that includes 
everything which cannot belong to E. 

It is clear then that from the inquiries taken by themselves no 
syllogism results; but if B and F are contraries B must be 
identical with one of the Hs, and the syllogism results through 
these terms. It turns out then that those who inquire in this 



141 



manner are looking gratuitously for some other way than the 
necessary way because they have failed to observe the identity 
of the Bs with the Hs. 



29 

Syllogisms which lead to impossible conclusions are similar to 
ostensive syllogisms; they also are formed by means of the 
consequents and antecedents of the terms in question. In both 
cases the same inquiry is involved. For what is proved 
ostensively may also be concluded syllogistically per 
impossibile by means of the same terms; and what is proved 
per impossibile may also be proved ostensively, e.g. that A 
belongs to none of the Es. For suppose A to belong to some E: 
then since B belongs to all A and A to some of the Es, B will 
belong to some of the Es: but it was assumed that it belongs to 
none. Again we may prove that A belongs to some E: for if A 
belonged to none of the Es, and E belongs to all G, A will belong 
to none of the Gs: but it was assumed to belong to all. Similarly 
with the other propositions requiring proof. The proof per 
impossibile will always and in all cases be from the 
consequents and antecedents of the terms in question. 
Whatever the problem the same inquiry is necessary whether 
one wishes to use an ostensive syllogism or a reduction to 
impossibility. For both the demonstrations start from the same 
terms, e.g. suppose it has been proved that A belongs to no E, 
because it turns out that otherwise B belongs to some of the Es 
and this is impossible - if now it is assumed that B belongs to 
no E and to all A, it is clear that A will belong to no E. Again if it 
has been proved by an ostensive syllogism that A belongs to no 
E, assume that A belongs to some E and it will be proved per 
impossibile to belong to no E. Similarly with the rest. In all cases 



142 



it is necessary to find some common term other than the 
subjects of inquiry, to which the syllogism establishing the false 
conclusion may relate, so that if this premiss is converted, and 
the other remains as it is, the syllogism will be ostensive by 
means of the same terms. For the ostensive syllogism differs 
from the reductio ad impossibile in this: in the ostensive 
syllogism both remisses are laid down in accordance with the 
truth, in the reductio ad impossibile one of the premisses is 
assumed falsely 

These points will be made clearer by the sequel, when we 
discuss the reduction to impossibility: at present this much 
must be clear, that we must look to terms of the kinds 
mentioned whether we wish to use an ostensive syllogism or a 
reduction to impossibility In the other hypothetical syllogisms, 
I mean those which proceed by substitution, or by positing a 
certain quality, the inquiry will be directed to the terms of the 
problem to be proved - not the terms of the original problem, 
but the new terms introduced; and the method of the inquiry 
will be the same as before. But we must consider and determine 
in how many ways hypothetical syllogisms are possible. 

Each of the problems then can be proved in the manner 
described; but it is possible to establish some of them 
syllogistically in another way, e.g. universal problems by the 
inquiry which leads up to a particular conclusion, with the 
addition of an hypothesis. For if the Cs and the Gs should be 
identical, but E should be assumed to belong to the Gs only, 
then A would belong to every E: and again if the Ds and the Gs 
should be identical, but E should be predicated of the Gs only, it 
follows that A will belong to none of the Es. Clearly then we 
must consider the matter in this way also. The method is the 
same whether the relation is necessary or possible. For the 
inquiry will be the same, and the syllogism will proceed through 
terms arranged in the same order whether a possible or a pure 



143 



proposition is proved. We must find in the case of possible 
relations, as well as terms that belong, terms which can belong 
though they actually do not: for we have proved that the 
syllogism which establishes a possible relation proceeds 
through these terms as well. Similarly also with the other 
modes of predication. 

It is clear then from what has been said not only that all 
syllogisms can be formed in this way, but also that they cannot 
be formed in any other. For every syllogism has been proved to 
be formed through one of the aforementioned figures, and 
these cannot be composed through other terms than the 
consequents and antecedents of the terms in question: for from 
these we obtain the premisses and find the middle term. 
Consequently a syllogism cannot be formed by means of other 
terms. 



30 

The method is the same in all cases, in philosophy, in any art or 
study. We must look for the attributes and the subjects of both 
our terms, and we must supply ourselves with as many of these 
as possible, and consider them by means of the three terms, 
refuting statements in one way, confirming them in another, in 
the pursuit of truth starting from premisses in which the 
arrangement of the terms is in accordance with truth, while if 
we look for dialectical syllogisms we must start from probable 
premisses. The principles of syllogisms have been stated in 
general terms, both how they are characterized and how we 
must hunt for them, so as not to look to everything that is said 
about the terms of the problem or to the same points whether 
we are confirming or refuting, or again whether we are 



144 



confirming of all or of some, and whether we are refuting of all 
or some, we must look to fewer points and they must be 
definite. We have also stated how we must select with reference 
to everything that is, e.g. about good or knowledge. But in each 
science the principles which are peculiar are the most 
numerous. Consequently it is the business of experience to give 
the principles which belong to each subject. I mean for example 
that astronomical experience supplies the principles of 
astronomical science: for once the phenomena were adequately 
apprehended, the demonstrations of astronomy were 
discovered. Similarly with any other art or science. 
Consequently, if the attributes of the thing are apprehended, 
our business will then be to exhibit readily the demonstrations. 
For if none of the true attributes of things had been omitted in 
the historical survey, we should be able to discover the proof 
and demonstrate everything which admitted of proof, and to 
make that clear, whose nature does not admit of proof. 

In general then we have explained fairly well how we must 
select premisses: we have discussed the matter accurately in 
the treatise concerning dialectic. 



31 

It is easy to see that division into classes is a small part of the 
method we have described: for division is, so to speak, a weak 
syllogism; for what it ought to prove, it begs, and it always 
establishes something more general than the attribute in 
question. First, this very point had escaped all those who used 
the method of division; and they attempted to persuade men 
that it was possible to make a demonstration of substance and 
essence. Consequently they did not understand what it is 



145 



possible to prove syllogistically by division, nor did they 
understand that it was possible to prove syllogistically in the 
manner we have described. In demonstrations, when there is a 
need to prove a positive statement, the middle term through 
which the syllogism is formed must always be inferior to and 
not comprehend the first of the extremes. But division has a 
contrary intention: for it takes the universal as middle. Let 
animal be the term signified by A, mortal by B, and immortal by 
C, and let man, whose definition is to be got, be signified by D. 
The man who divides assumes that every animal is either 
mortal or immortal: i.e. whatever is A is all either B or C. Again, 
always dividing, he lays it down that man is an animal, so he 
assumes A of D as belonging to it. Now the true conclusion is 
that every D is either B or C, consequently man must be either 
mortal or immortal, but it is not necessary that man should be a 
mortal animal - this is begged: and this is what ought to have 
been proved syllogistically. And again, taking A as mortal 
animal, B as footed, C as footless, and D as man, he assumes in 
the same way that A inheres either in B or in C (for every mortal 
animal is either footed or footless), and he assumes A of D (for 
he assumed man, as we saw, to be a mortal animal); 
consequently it is necessary that man should be either a footed 
or a footless animal; but it is not necessary that man should be 
footed: this he assumes: and it is just this again which he ought 
to have demonstrated. Always dividing then in this way it turns 
out that these logicians assume as middle the universal term, 
and as extremes that which ought to have been the subject of 
demonstration and the differentiae. In conclusion, they do not 
make it clear, and show it to be necessary, that this is man or 
whatever the subject of inquiry may be: for they pursue the 
other method altogether, never even suspecting the presence of 
the rich supply of evidence which might be used. It is clear that 
it is neither possible to refute a statement by this method of 
division, nor to draw a conclusion about an accident or property 



146 



of a thing, nor about its genus, nor in cases in which it is 
unknown whether it is thus or thus, e.g. whether the diagonal is 
incommensurate. For if he assumes that every length is either 
commensurate or incommensurate, and the diagonal is a 
length, he has proved that the diagonal is either 
incommensurate or commensurate. But if he should assume 
that it is incommensurate, he will have assumed what he ought 
to have proved. He cannot then prove it: for this is his method, 
but proof is not possible by this method. Let A stand for 
'incommensurate or commensurate', B for 'length', C for 
'diagonal'. It is clear then that this method of investigation is 
not suitable for every inquiry, nor is it useful in those cases in 
which it is thought to be most suitable. 

From what has been said it is clear from what elements 
demonstrations are formed and in what manner, and to what 
points we must look in each problem. 



32 

Our next business is to state how we can reduce syllogisms to 
the aforementioned figures: for this part of the inquiry still 
remains. If we should investigate the production of the 
syllogisms and had the power of discovering them, and further 
if we could resolve the syllogisms produced into the 
aforementioned figures, our original problem would be brought 
to a conclusion. It will happen at the same time that what has 
been already said will be confirmed and its truth made clearer 
by what we are about to say. For everything that is true must in 
every respect agree with itself First then we must attempt to 
select the two premisses of the syllogism (for it is easier to 
divide into large parts than into small, and the composite parts 



147 



are larger than the elements out of which they are made); next 
we must inquire which are universal and which particular, and 
if both premisses have not been stated, we must ourselves 
assume the one which is missing. For sometimes men put 
forward the universal premiss, but do not posit the premiss 
which is contained in it, either in writing or in discussion: or 
men put forward the premisses of the principal syllogism, but 
omit those through which they are inferred, and invite the 
concession of others to no purpose. We must inquire then 
whether anything unnecessary has been assumed, or anything 
necessary has been omitted, and we must posit the one and 
take away the other, until we have reached the two premisses: 
for unless we have these, we cannot reduce arguments put 
forward in the way described. In some arguments it is easy to 
see what is wanting, but some escape us, and appear to be 
syllogisms, because something necessary results from what has 
been laid down, e.g. if the assumptions were made that 
substance is not annihilated by the annihilation of what is not 
substance, and that if the elements out of which a thing is 
made are annihilated, then that which is made out of them is 
destroyed: these propositions being laid down, it is necessary 
that any part of substance is substance; this has not however 
been drawn by syllogism from the propositions assumed, but 
premisses are wanting. Again if it is necessary that animal 
should exist, if man does, and that substance should exist, if 
animal does, it is necessary that substance should exist if man 
does: but as yet the conclusion has not been drawn 
syllogistically: for the premisses are not in the shape we 
required. We are deceived in such cases because something 
necessary results from what is assumed, since the syllogism 
also is necessary. But that which is necessary is wider than the 
syllogism: for every syllogism is necessary, but not everything 
which is necessary is a syllogism. Consequently, though 
something results when certain propositions are assumed, we 



148 



must not try to reduce it directly, but must first state the two 
premisses, then divide them into their terms. We must take that 
term as middle which is stated in both the remisses: for it is 
necessary that the middle should be found in both premisses in 
all the figures. 

If then the middle term is a predicate and a subject of 
predication, or if it is a predicate, and something else is denied 
of it, we shall have the first figure: if it both is a predicate and is 
denied of something, the middle figure: if other things are 
predicated of it, or one is denied, the other predicated, the last 
figure. For it was thus that we found the middle term placed in 
each figure. It is placed similarly too if the premisses are not 
universal: for the middle term is determined in the same way. 
Clearly then, if the same term is not stated more than once in 
the course of an argument, a syllogism cannot be made: for a 
middle term has not been taken. Since we know what sort of 
thesis is established in each figure, and in which the universal, 
in what sort the particular is described, clearly we must not 
look for all the figures, but for that which is appropriate to the 
thesis in hand. If the thesis is established in more figures than 
one, we shall recognize the figure by the position of the middle 
term. 



33 

Men are frequently deceived about syllogisms because the 
inference is necessary, as has been said above; sometimes they 
are deceived by the similarity in the positing of the terms; and 
this ought not to escape our notice. E.g. if A is stated of B, and B 
of C: it would seem that a syllogism is possible since the terms 
stand thus: but nothing necessary results, nor does a syllogism. 



149 



Let A represent the term 'being eternal', B 'Aristomenes as an 
object of thought', C Aristomenes'. It is true then that A belongs 
to B. For Aristomenes as an object of thought is eternal. But B 
also belongs to C: for Aristomenes is Aristomenes as an object 
of thought. But A does not belong to C: for Aristomenes is 
perishable. For no syllogism was made although the terms 
stood thus: that required that the premiss AB should be stated 
universally. But this is false, that every Aristomenes who is an 
object of thought is eternal, since Aristomenes is perishable. 
Again let C stand for 'Miccalus', B for 'musical Miccalus', A for 
'perishing to-morrow'. It is true to predicate B of C: for Miccalus 
is musical Miccalus. Also A can be predicated of B: for musical 
Miccalus might perish to-morrow. But to state A of C is false at 
any rate. This argument then is identical with the former; for it 
is not true universally that musical Miccalus perishes to- 
morrow: but unless this is assumed, no syllogism (as we have 
shown) is possible. 

This deception then arises through ignoring a small distinction. 
For if we accept the conclusion as though it made no difference 
whether we said 'This belong to that' or 'This belongs to all of 
that'. 



34 

Men will frequently fall into fallacies through not setting out 
the terms of the premiss well, e.g. suppose A to be health, B 
disease, C man. It is true to say that A cannot belong to any B 
(for health belongs to no disease) and again that B belongs to 
every C (for every man is capable of disease). It would seem to 
follow that health cannot belong to any man. The reason for 
this is that the terms are not set out well in the statement, since 



150 



if the things which are in the conditions are substituted, no 
syllogism can be made, e.g. if 'healthy' is substituted for 'health' 
and 'diseased' for 'disease'. For it is not true to say that being 
healthy cannot belong to one who is diseased. But unless this is 
assumed no conclusion results, save in respect of possibility: 
but such a conclusion is not impossible: for it is possible that 
health should belong to no man. Again the fallacy may occur in 
a similar way in the middle figure: 'it is not possible that health 
should belong to any disease, but it is possible that health 
should belong to every man, consequently it is not possible that 
disease should belong to any man'. In the third figure the fallacy 
results in reference to possibility. For health and diseae and 
knowledge and ignorance, and in general contraries, may 
possibly belong to the same thing, but cannot belong to one 
another. This is not in agreement with what was said before: for 
we stated that when several things could belong to the same 
thing, they could belong to one another. 

It is evident then that in all these cases the fallacy arises from 
the setting out of the terms: for if the things that are in the 
conditions are substituted, no fallacy arises. It is clear then that 
in such premisses what possesses the condition ought always 
to be substituted for the condition and taken as the term. 



35 

We must not always seek to set out the terms a single word: for 
we shall often have complexes of words to which a single name 
is not given. Hence it is difficult to reduce syllogisms with such 
terms. Sometimes too fallacies will result from such a search, 
e.g. the belief that syllogism can establish that which has no 
mean. Let A stand for two right angles, B for triangle, C for 



151 



isosceles triangle. A then belongs to C because of B: but A 
belongs to B without the mediation of another term: for the 
triangle in virtue of its own nature contains two right angles, 
consequently there will be no middle term for the proposition 
AB, although it is demonstrable. For it is clear that the middle 
must not always be assumed to be an individual thing, but 
sometimes a complex of words, as happens in the case 
mentioned. 



36 

That the first term belongs to the middle, and the middle to the 
extreme, must not be understood in the sense that they can 
always be predicated of one another or that the first term will 
be predicated of the middle in the same way as the middle is 
predicated of the last term. The same holds if the premisses are 
negative. But we must suppose the verb 'to belong' to have as 
many meanings as the senses in which the verb 'to be' is used, 
and in which the assertion that a thing 'is' may be said to be 
true. Take for example the statement that there is a single 
science of contraries. Let A stand for 'there being a single 
science', and B for things which are contrary to one another. 
Then A belongs to B, not in the sense that contraries are the fact 
of there being a single science of them, but in the sense that it 
is true to say of the contraries that there is a single science of 
them. 

It happens sometimes that the first term is stated of the middle, 
but the middle is not stated of the third term, e.g. if wisdom is 
knowledge, and wisdom is of the good, the conclusion is that 
there is knowledge of the good. The good then is not knowledge, 
though wisdom is knowledge. Sometimes the middle term is 



152 



stated of the third, but the first is not stated of the middle, e.g. if 
there is a science of everything that has a quality, or is a 
contrary, and the good both is a contrary and has a quality, the 
conclusion is that there is a science of the good, but the good is 
not science, nor is that which has a quality or is a contrary, 
though the good is both of these. Sometimes neither the first 
term is stated of the middle, nor the middle of the third, while 
the first is sometimes stated of the third, and sometimes not: 
e.g. if there is a genus of that of which there is a science, and if 
there is a science of the good, we conclude that there is a genus 
of the good. But nothing is predicated of anything. And if that of 
which there is a science is a genus, and if there is a science of 
the good, we conclude that the good is a genus. The first term 
then is predicated of the extreme, but in the premisses one 
thing is not stated of another. 

The same holds good where the relation is negative. For 'that 
does not belong to this' does not always mean that 'this is not 
that', but sometimes that 'this is not of that' or 'for that', e.g. 
'there is not a motion of a motion or a becoming of a becoming, 
but there is a becoming of pleasure: so pleasure is not a 
becoming.' Or again it may be said that there is a sign of 
laughter, but there is not a sign of a sign, consequently laughter 
is not a sign. This holds in the other cases too, in which the 
thesis is refuted because the genus is asserted in a particular 
way, in relation to the terms of the thesis. Again take the 
inference 'opportunity is not the right time: for opportunity 
belongs to God, but the right time does not, since nothing is 
useful to God'. We must take as terms opportunity-right time- 
God: but the premiss must be understood according to the case 
of the noun. For we state this universally without qualification, 
that the terms ought always to be stated in the nominative, e.g. 
man, good, contraries, not in oblique cases, e.g. of man, of a 
good, of contraries, but the premisses ought to be understood 
with reference to the cases of each term -either the dative, e.g. 



153 



'equal to this', or the genitive, e.g. 'double of this', or the 
accusative, e.g. 'that which strikes or sees this', or the 
nominative, e.g. 'man is an animal', or in whatever other way 
the word falls in the premiss. 



37 

The expressions 'this belongs to that' and 'this holds true of 
that' must be understood in as many ways as there are different 
categories, and these categories must be taken either with or 
without qualification, and further as simple or compound: the 
same holds good of the corresponding negative expressions. We 
must consider these points and define them better. 



38 

A term which is repeated in the premisses ought to be joined to 
the first extreme, not to the middle. I mean for example that if a 
syllogism should be made proving that there is knowledge of 
justice, that it is good, the expression 'that it is good' (or 'qua 
good') should be joined to the first term. Let A stand for 
'knowledge that it is good', B for good, G for justice. It is true to 
predicate A of B. For of the good there is knowledge that it is 
good. Also it is true to predicate B of C. For justice is identical 
with a good. In this way an analysis of the argument can be 
made. But if the expression 'that it is good' were added to B, the 
conclusion will not follow: for A will be true of B, but B will not 
be true of C. For to predicate of justice the term 'good that it is 
good' is false and not intelligible. Similarly if it should be proved 



154 



that the healthy is an object of knowledge qua good, of goat- 
stag an object of knowledge qua not existing, or man perishable 
qua an object of sense: in every case in which an addition is 
made to the predicate, the addition must be joined to the 
extreme. 

The position of the terms is not the same when something is 
established without qualification and when it is qualified by 
some attribute or condition, e.g. when the good is proved to be 
an object of knowledge and when it is proved to be an object of 
knowledge that it is good. If it has been proved to be an object of 
knowledge without qualification, we must put as middle term 
'that which is', but if we add the qualification 'that it is good', 
the middle term must be 'that which is something'. Let A stand 
for 'knowledge that it is something', B stand for 'something', 
and C stand for 'good'. It is true to predicate A of B: for ex 
hypothesi there is a science of that which is something, that it 
is something. B too is true of C: for that which C represents is 
something. Consequently A is true of C: there will then be 
knowledge of the good, that it is good: for ex hypothesi the term 
'something' indicates the thing's special nature. But if 'being' 
were taken as middle and 'being' simply were joined to the 
extreme, not 'being something', we should not have had a 
syllogism proving that there is knowledge of the good, that it is 
good, but that it is; e.g. let A stand for knowledge that it is, B for 
being, C for good. Clearly then in syllogisms which are thus 
limited we must take the terms in the way stated. 



39 

We ought also to exchange terms which have the same value, 
word for word, and phrase for phrase, and word and phrase, and 



155 



always take a word in preference to a phrase: for thus the 
setting out of the terms will be easier. For example if it makes 
no difference whether we say that the supposable is not the 
genus of the opinable or that the opinable is not identical with a 
particular kind of supposable (for what is meant is the same in 
both statements), it is better to take as the terms the 
supposable and the opinable in preference to the phrase 
suggested. 



40 

Since the expressions 'pleasure is good' and 'pleasure is the 
good' are not identical, we must not set out the terms in the 
same way; but if the syllogism is to prove that pleasure is the 
good, the term must be 'the good', but if the object is to prove 
that pleasure is good, the term will be 'good'. Similarly in all 
other cases. 



41 

It is not the same, either in fact or in speech, that A belongs to 
all of that to which B belongs, and that A belongs to all of that to 
all of which B belongs: for nothing prevents B from belonging to 
C, though not to all C: e.g. let B stand for beautiful, and C for 
white. If beauty belongs to something white, it is true to say 
that beauty belongs to that which is white; but not perhaps to 
everything that is white. If then A belongs to B, but not to 
everything of which B is predicated, then whether B belongs to 
all C or merely belongs to C, it is not necessary that A should 



156 



belong, I do not say to all C, but even to C at all. But if A belongs 
to everything of which B is truly stated, it will follow that A can 
be said of all of that of all of which B is said. If however A is said 
of that of all of which B may be said, nothing prevents B 
belonging to C, and yet A not belonging to all C or to any C at all. 
If then we take three terms it is clear that the expression A is 
said of all of which B is said' means this, A is said of all the 
things of which B is said'. And if B is said of all of a third term, 
so also is A: but if B is not said of all of the third term, there is 
no necessity that A should be said of all of it. 

We must not suppose that something absurd results through 
setting out the terms: for we do not use the existence of this 
particular thing, but imitate the geometrician who says that 
'this line a foot long' or 'this straight line' or 'this line without 
breadth' exists although it does not, but does not use the 
diagrams in the sense that he reasons from them. For in 
general, if two things are not related as whole to part and part 
to whole, the prover does not prove from them, and so no 
syllogism a is formed. We (I mean the learner) use the process 
of setting out terms like perception by sense, not as though it 
were impossible to demonstrate without these illustrative 
terms, as it is to demonstrate without the premisses of the 
syllogism. 



42 

We should not forget that in the same syllogism not all 
conclusions are reached through one figure, but one through 
one figure, another through another. Clearly then we must 
analyse arguments in accordance with this. Since not every 
problem is proved in every figure, but certain problems in each 



157 



figure, it is clear from the conclusion in what figure the 
premisses should be sought. 



43 

In reference to those arguments aiming at a definition which 
have been directed to prove some part of the definition, we 
must take as a term the point to which the argument has been 
directed, not the whole definition: for so we shall be less likely 
to be disturbed by the length of the term: e.g. if a man proves 
that water is a drinkable liquid, we must take as terms 
drinkable and water. 



44 

Further we must not try to reduce hypothetical syllogisms; for 
with the given premisses it is not possible to reduce them. For 
they have not been proved by syllogism, but assented to by 
agreement. For instance if a man should suppose that unless 
there is one faculty of contraries, there cannot be one science, 
and should then argue that not every faculty is of contraries, e.g. 
of what is healthy and what is sickly: for the same thing will 
then be at the same time healthy and sickly. He has shown that 
there is not one faculty of all contraries, but he has not proved 
that there is not a science. And yet one must agree. But the 
agreement does not come from a syllogism, but from an 
hypothesis. This argument cannot be reduced: but the proof 
that there is not a single faculty can. The latter argument 
perhaps was a syllogism: but the former was an hypothesis. 



158 



The same holds good of arguments which are brought to a 
conclusion per impossibile. These cannot be analysed either; 
but the reduction to what is impossible can be analysed since it 
is proved by syllogism, though the rest of the argument cannot, 
because the conclusion is reached from an hypothesis. But 
these differ from the previous arguments: for in the former a 
preliminary agreement must be reached if one is to accept the 
conclusion; e.g. an agreement that if there is proved to be one 
faculty of contraries, then contraries fall under the same 
science; whereas in the latter, even if no preliminary agreement 
has been made, men still accept the reasoning, because the 
falsity is patent, e.g. the falsity of what follows from the 
assumption that the diagonal is commensurate, viz. that then 
odd numbers are equal to evens. 

Many other arguments are brought to a conclusion by the help 
of an hypothesis; these we ought to consider and mark out 
clearly. We shall describe in the sequel their differences, and the 
various ways in which hypothetical arguments are formed: but 
at present this much must be clear, that it is not possible to 
resolve such arguments into the figures. And we have explained 
the reason. 



45 

Whatever problems are proved in more than one figure, if they 
have been established in one figure by syllogism, can be 
reduced to another figure, e.g. a negative syllogism in the first 
figure can be reduced to the second, and a syllogism in the 
middle figure to the first, not all however but some only. The 
point will be clear in the sequel. If A belongs to no B, and B to all 
C, then A belongs to no C. Thus the first figure; but if the 



159 



negative statement is converted, we shall have the middle 
figure. For B belongs to no A, and to all C. Similarly if the 
syllogism is not universal but particular, e.g. if A belongs to no B, 
and B to some C. Convert the negative statement and you will 
have the middle figure. 

The universal syllogisms in the second figure can be reduced to 
the first, but only one of the two particular syllogisms. Let A 
belong to no B and to all C. Convert the negative statement, and 
you will have the first figure. For B will belong to no A and A to 
all C. But if the affirmative statement concerns B, and the 
negative C, C must be made first term. For C belongs to no A, 
and A to all B: therefore C belongs to no B. B then belongs to no 
C: for the negative statement is convertible. 

But if the syllogism is particular, whenever the negative 
statement concerns the major extreme, reduction to the first 
figure will be possible, e.g. if A belongs to no B and to some C: 
convert the negative statement and you will have the first 
figure. For B will belong to no A and A to some C. But when the 
affirmative statement concerns the major extreme, no 
resolution will be possible, e.g. if A belongs to all B, but not to all 
C: for the statement AB does not admit of conversion, nor would 
there be a syllogism if it did. 

Again syllogisms in the third figure cannot all be resolved into 
the first, though all syllogisms in the first figure can be resolved 
into the third. Let A belong to all B and B to some C. Since the 
particular affirmative is convertible, C will belong to some B: but 
A belonged to all B: so that the third figure is formed. Similarly 
if the syllogism is negative: for the particular affirmative is 
convertible: therefore A will belong to no B, and to some C. 

Of the syllogisms in the last figure one only cannot be resolved 
into the first, viz. when the negative statement is not universal: 
all the rest can be resolved. Let A and B be affirmed of all C: 



160 



then C can be converted partially with either A or B: C then 
belongs to some B. Consequently we shall get the first figure, if 
A belongs to all C, and C to some of the Bs. If A belongs to all C 
and B to some C, the argument is the same: for B is convertible 
in reference to C. But if B belongs to all C and A to some C, the 
first term must be B: for B belongs to all C, and C to some A, 
therefore B belongs to some A. But since the particular 
statement is convertible, A will belong to some B. If the 
syllogism is negative, when the terms are universal we must 
take them in a similar way. Let B belong to all C, and A to no C: 
then C will belong to some B, and A to no C; and so C will be 
middle term. Similarly if the negative statement is universal, 
the affirmative particular: for A will belong to no C, and C to 
some of the Bs. But if the negative statement is particular, no 
resolution will be possible, e.g. if B belongs to all C, and A not 
belong to some C: convert the statement BC and both premisses 
will be particular. 

It is clear that in order to resolve the figures into one another 
the premiss which concerns the minor extreme must be 
converted in both the figures: for when this premiss is altered, 
the transition to the other figure is made. 

One of the syllogisms in the middle figure can, the other 
cannot, be resolved into the third figure. Whenever the 
universal statement is negative, resolution is possible. For if A 
belongs to no B and to some C, both B and C alike are 
convertible in relation to A, so that B belongs to no A and C to 
some A. A therefore is middle term. But when A belongs to all B, 
and not to some C, resolution will not be possible: for neither of 
the premisses is universal after conversion. 

Syllogisms in the third figure can be resolved into the middle 
figure, whenever the negative statement is universal, e.g. if A 
belongs to no C, and B to some or all C. For C then will belong to 



161 



no A and to some B. But if the negative statement is particular, 
no resolution will be possible: for the particular negative does 
not admit of conversion. 

It is clear then that the same syllogisms cannot be resolved in 
these figures which could not be resolved into the first figure, 
and that when syllogisms are reduced to the first figure these 
alone are confirmed by reduction to what is impossible. 

It is clear from what we have said how we ought to reduce 
syllogisms, and that the figures may be resolved into one 
another. 



46 

In establishing or refuting, it makes some difference whether 
we suppose the expressions 'not to be this' and 'to be not-this' 
are identical or different in meaning, e.g. 'not to be white' and 
'to be not-white'. For they do not mean the same thing, nor is 
'to be not-white' the negation of 'to be white', but 'not to be 
white'. The reason for this is as follows. The relation of 'he can 
walk' to 'he can not-walk' is similar to the relation of 'it is 
white' to 'it is not-white'; so is that of 'he knows what is good' 
to 'he knows what is not-good'. For there is no difference 
between the expressions 'he knows what is good' and 'he is 
knowing what is good', or 'he can walk' and 'he is able to walk': 
therefore there is no difference between their contraries 'he 
cannot walk'-'he is not able to walk'. If then 'he is not able to 
walk' means the same as 'he is able not to walk', capacity to 
walk and incapacity to walk will belong at the same time to the 
same person (for the same man can both walk and not-walk, 
and is possessed of knowledge of what is good and of what is 
not-good), but an affirmation and a denial which are opposed to 



162 



one another do not belong at the same time to the same thing. 
As then 'not to know what is good' is not the same as 'to know 
what is not good', so 'to be not-good' is not the same as 'not to 
be good'. For when two pairs correspond, if the one pair are 
different from one another, the other pair also must be 
different. Nor is 'to be not-equal' the same as 'not to be equal': 
for there is something underlying the one, viz. that which is 
not-equal, and this is the unequal, but there is nothing 
underlying the other. Wherefore not everything is either equal 
or unequal, but everything is equal or is not equal. Further the 
expressions 'it is a not-white log' and 'it is not a white log' do 
not imply one another's truth. For if 'it is a not-white log', it 
must be a log: but that which is not a white log need not be a 
log at all. Therefore it is clear that 'it is not-good' is not the 
denial of 'it is good'. If then every single statement may truly be 
said to be either an affirmation or a negation, if it is not a 
negation clearly it must in a sense be an affirmation. But every 
affirmation has a corresponding negation. The negation then of 
'it is not-good' is 'it is not not-good'. The relation of these 
statements to one another is as follows. Let A stand for 'to be 
good', B for 'not to be good', let C stand for 'to be not-good' and 
be placed under B, and let D stand for not to be not-good' and 
be placed under A. Then either A or B will belong to everything, 
but they will never belong to the same thing; and either C or D 
will belong to everything, but they will never belong to the same 
thing. And B must belong to everything to which C belongs. For 
if it is true to say 'it is a not-white', it is true also to say 'it is not 
white': for it is impossible that a thing should simultaneously 
be white and be not-white, or be a not-white log and be a white 
log; consequently if the affirmation does not belong, the denial 
must belong. But C does not always belong to B: for what is not 
a log at all, cannot be a not-white log either. On the other hand 
D belongs to everything to which A belongs. For either C or D 
belongs to everything to which A belongs. But since a thing 



163 



cannot be simultaneously not-white and white, D must belong 
to everything to which A belongs. For of that which is white it is 
true to say that it is not not-white. But A is not true of all D. For 
of that which is not a log at all it is not true to say A, viz. that it 
is a white log. Consequently D is true, but A is not true, i.e. that 
it is a white log. It is clear also that A and C cannot together 
belong to the same thing, and that B and D may possibly belong 
to the same thing. 

Privative terms are similarly related positive ter terms respect of 
this arrangement. Let A stand for 'equal', B for 'not equal', C for 
'unequal', D for 'not unequal'. 

In many things also, to some of which something belongs which 
does not belong to others, the negation may be true in a similar 
way, viz. that all are not white or that each is not white, while 
that each is not-white or all are not-white is false. Similarly also 
'every animal is not-white' is not the negation of 'every animal 
is white' (for both are false): the proper negation is 'every 
animal is not white'. Since it is clear that 'it is not-white' and 'it 
is not white' mean different things, and one is an affirmation, 
the other a denial, it is evident that the method of proving each 
cannot be the same, e.g. that whatever is an animal is not white 
or may not be white, and that it is true to call it not-white; for 
this means that it is not-white. But we may prove that it is true 
to call it white or not-white in the same way for both are proved 
constructively by means of the first figure. For the expression 'it 
is true' stands on a similar footing to 'it is'. For the negation of 
'it is true to call it white' is not 'it is true to call it not-white' but 
'it is not true to call it white'. If then it is to be true to say that 
whatever is a man is musical or is not-musical, we must 
assume that whatever is an animal either is musical or is not- 
musical; and the proof has been made. That whatever is a man 
is not musical is proved destructively in the three ways 
mentioned. 



164 



In general whenever A and B are such that they cannot belong 
at the same time to the same thing, and one of the two 
necessarily belongs to everything, and again C and D are related 
in the same way, and A follows C but the relation cannot be 
reversed, then D must follow B and the relation cannot be 
reversed. And A and D may belong to the same thing, but B and 
C cannot. First it is clear from the following consideration that D 
follows B. For since either C or D necessarily belongs to 
everything; and since C cannot belong to that to which B 
belongs, because it carries A along with it and A and B cannot 
belong to the same thing; it is clear that D must follow B. Again 
since C does not reciprocate with but A, but C or D belongs to 
everything, it is possible that A and D should belong to the same 
thing. But B and C cannot belong to the same thing, because A 
follows C; and so something impossible results. It is clear then 
that B does not reciprocate with D either, since it is possible that 
D and A should belong at the same time to the same thing. 

It results sometimes even in such an arrangement of terms that 
one is deceived through not apprehending the opposites rightly, 
one of which must belong to everything, e.g. we may reason 
that 'if A and B cannot belong at the same time to the same 
thing, but it is necessary that one of them should belong to 
whatever the other does not belong to: and again C and D are 
related in the same way, and follows everything which C 
follows: it will result that B belongs necessarily to everything to 
which D belongs': but this is false. Assume that F stands for the 
negation of A and B, and again that H stands for the negation of 
C and D. It is necessary then that either A or F should belong to 
everything: for either the affirmation or the denial must belong. 
And again either C or H must belong to everything: for they are 
related as affirmation and denial. And ex hypothesi A belongs to 
everything ever thing to which C belongs. Therefore H belongs 
to everything to which F belongs. Again since either F or B 
belongs to everything, and similarly either H or D, and since H 



165 



follows F, B must follow D: for we know this. If then A follows C, 
B must follow D'. But this is false: for as we proved the sequence 
is reversed in terms so constituted. The fallacy arises because 
perhaps it is not necessary that A or F should belong to 
everything, or that F or B should belong to everything: for F is 
not the denial of A. For not good is the negation of good: and 
not-good is not identical with 'neither good nor not-good'. 
Similarly also with C and D. For two negations have been 
assumed in respect to one term. 



Book II 



We have already explained the number of the figures, the 
character and number of the premisses, when and how a 
syllogism is formed; further what we must look for when a 
refuting and establishing propositions, and how we should 
investigate a given problem in any branch of inquiry, also by 
what means we shall obtain principles appropriate to each 
subject. Since some syllogisms are universal, others particular, 
all the universal syllogisms give more than one result, and of 
particular syllogisms the affirmative yield more than one, the 
negative yield only the stated conclusion. For all propositions 
are convertible save only the particular negative: and the 
conclusion states one definite thing about another definite 
thing. Consequently all syllogisms save the particular negative 



166 



yield more than one conclusion, e.g. if A has been proved to to 
all or to some B, then B must belong to some A: and if A has 
been proved to belong to no B, then B belongs to no A. This is a 
different conclusion from the former. But if A does not belong to 
some B, it is not necessary that B should not belong to some A: 
for it may possibly belong to all A. 

This then is the reason common to all syllogisms whether 
universal or particular. But it is possible to give another reason 
concerning those which are universal. For all the things that are 
subordinate to the middle term or to the conclusion may be 
proved by the same syllogism, if the former are placed in the 
middle, the latter in the conclusion; e.g. if the conclusion AB is 
proved through C, whatever is subordinate to B or C must accept 
the predicate A: for if D is included in B as in a whole, and B is 
included in A, then D will be included in A. Again if E is included 
in C as in a whole, and C is included in A, then E will be 
included in A. Similarly if the syllogism is negative. In the 
second figure it will be possible to infer only that which is 
subordinate to the conclusion, e.g. if A belongs to no B and to all 
C; we conclude that B belongs to no C. If then D is subordinate 
to C, clearly B does not belong to it. But that B does not belong 
to what is subordinate to A is not clear by means of the 
syllogism. And yet B does not belong to E, if E is subordinate to 
A. But while it has been proved through the syllogism that B 
belongs to no C, it has been assumed without proof that B does 
not belong to A, consequently it does not result through the 
syllogism that B does not belong to E. 

But in particular syllogisms there will be no necessity of 
inferring what is subordinate to the conclusion (for a syllogism 
does not result when this premiss is particular), but whatever is 
subordinate to the middle term may be inferred, not however 
through the syllogism, e.g. if A belongs to all B and B to some C. 
Nothing can be inferred about that which is subordinate to C; 



167 



something can be inferred about that which is subordinate to B, 
but not through the preceding syllogism. Similarly in the other 
figures. That which is subordinate to the conclusion cannot be 
proved; the other subordinate can be proved, only not through 
the syllogism, just as in the universal syllogisms what is 
subordinate to the middle term is proved (as we saw) from a 
premiss which is not demonstrated: consequently either a 
conclusion is not possible in the case of universal syllogisms or 
else it is possible also in the case of particular syllogisms. 



It is possible for the premisses of the syllogism to be true, or to 
be false, or to be the one true, the other false. The conclusion is 
either true or false necessarily. From true premisses it is not 
possible to draw a false conclusion, but a true conclusion may 
be drawn from false premisses, true however only in respect to 
the fact, not to the reason. The reason cannot be established 
from false premisses: why this is so will be explained in the 
sequel. 

First then that it is not possible to draw a false conclusion from 
true premisses, is made clear by this consideration. If it is 
necessary that B should be when A is, it is necessary that A 
should not be when B is not. If then A is true, B must be true: 
otherwise it will turn out that the same thing both is and is not 
at the same time. But this is impossible. Let it not, because A is 
laid down as a single term, be supposed that it is possible, when 
a single fact is given, that something should necessarily result. 
For that is not possible. For what results necessarily is the 
conclusion, and the means by which this comes about are at the 
least three terms, and two relations of subject and predicate or 



168 



premisses. If then it is true that A belongs to all that to which B 
belongs, and that B belongs to all that to which C belongs, it is 
necessary that A should belong to all that to which C belongs, 
and this cannot be false: for then the same thing will belong 
and not belong at the same time. So A is posited as one thing, 
being two premisses taken together. The same holds good of 
negative syllogisms: it is not possible to prove a false conclusion 
from true premisses. 

But from what is false a true conclusion may be drawn, whether 
both the premisses are false or only one, provided that this is 
not either of the premisses indifferently, if it is taken as wholly 
false: but if the premiss is not taken as wholly false, it does not 
matter which of the two is false. (1) Let A belong to the whole of 
C, but to none of the Bs, neither let B belong to C. This is 
possible, e.g. animal belongs to no stone, nor stone to any man. 
If then A is taken to belong to all B and B to all C, A will belong 
to all C; consequently though both the premisses are false the 
conclusion is true: for every man is an animal. Similarly with 
the negative. For it is possible that neither A nor B should 
belong to any C, although A belongs to all B, e.g. if the same 
terms are taken and man is put as middle: for neither animal 
nor man belongs to any stone, but animal belongs to every man. 
Consequently if one term is taken to belong to none of that to 
which it does belong, and the other term is taken to belong to 
all of that to which it does not belong, though both the 
premisses are false the conclusion will be true. (2) A similar 
proof may be given if each premiss is partially false. 

(3) But if one only of the premisses is false, when the first 
premiss is wholly false, e.g. AB, the conclusion will not be true, 
but if the premiss BC is wholly false, a true conclusion will be 
possible. I mean by 'wholly false' the contrary of the truth, e.g. if 
what belongs to none is assumed to belong to all, or if what 
belongs to all is assumed to belong to none. Let A belong to no 



169 



B, and B to all C. If then the premiss BC which I take is true, and 
the premiss AB is wholly false, viz. that A belongs to all B, it is 
impossible that the conclusion should be true: for A belonged to 
none of the Cs, since A belonged to nothing to which B 
belonged, and B belonged to all C. Similarly there cannot be a 
true conclusion if A belongs to all B, and B to all C, but while the 
true premiss BC is assumed, the wholly false premiss AB is also 
assumed, viz. that A belongs to nothing to which B belongs: 
here the conclusion must be false. For A will belong to all C, 
since A belongs to everything to which B belongs, and B to all C. 
It is clear then that when the first premiss is wholly false, 
whether affirmative or negative, and the other premiss is true, 
the conclusion cannot be true. 

(4) But if the premiss is not wholly false, a true conclusion is 
possible. For if A belongs to all C and to some B, and if B belongs 
to all C, e.g. animal to every swan and to some white thing, and 
white to every swan, then if we take as premisses that A 
belongs to all B, and B to all C, A will belong to all C truly: for 
every swan is an animal. Similarly if the statement AB is 
negative. For it is possible that A should belong to some B and to 
no C, and that B should belong to all C, e.g. animal to some 
white thing, but to no snow, and white to all snow. If then one 
should assume that A belongs to no B, and B to all C, then will 
belong to no C. 

(5) But if the premiss AB, which is assumed, is wholly true, and 
the premiss BC is wholly false, a true syllogism will be possible: 
for nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to all C, though B 
belongs to no C, e.g. these being species of the same genus 
which are not subordinate one to the other: for animal belongs 
both to horse and to man, but horse to no man. If then it is 
assumed that A belongs to all B and B to all C, the conclusion 
will be true, although the premiss BC is wholly false. Similarly if 
the premiss AB is negative. For it is possible that A should 



170 



belong neither to any B nor to any C, and that B should not 
belong to any C, e.g. a genus to species of another genus: for 
animal belongs neither to music nor to the art of healing, nor 
does music belong to the art of healing. If then it is assumed 
that A belongs to no B, and B to all C, the conclusion will be true. 

(6) And if the premiss BC is not wholly false but in part only, 
even so the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents A 
belonging to the whole of B and of C, while B belongs to some C, 
e.g. a genus to its species and difference: for animal belongs to 
every man and to every footed thing, and man to some footed 
things though not to all. If then it is assumed that A belongs to 
all B, and B to all C, A will belong to all C: and this ex hypothesi 
is true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative. For it is possible 
that A should neither belong to any B nor to any C, though B 
belongs to some C, e.g. a genus to the species of another genus 
and its difference: for animal neither belongs to any wisdom 
nor to any instance of 'speculative', but wisdom belongs to 
some instance of 'speculative'. If then it should be assumed that 
A belongs to no B, and B to all C, will belong to no C: and this ex 
hypothesi is true. 

In particular syllogisms it is possible when the first premiss is 
wholly false, and the other true, that the conclusion should be 
true; also when the first premiss is false in part, and the other 
true; and when the first is true, and the particular is false; and 
when both are false. (7) For nothing prevents A belonging to no 

B, but to some C, and B to some C, e.g. animal belongs to no 
snow, but to some white thing, and snow to some white thing. If 
then snow is taken as middle, and animal as first term, and it is 
assumed that A belongs to the whole of B, and B to some C, then 
the premiss BC is wholly false, the premiss BC true, and the 
conclusion true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative: for it is 
possible that A should belong to the whole of B, but not to some 

C, although B belongs to some C, e.g. animal belongs to every 



171 



man, but does not follow some white, but man belongs to some 
white; consequently if man be taken as middle term and it is 
assumed that A belongs to no B but B belongs to some C, the 
conclusion will be true although the premiss AB is wholly false. 
(If the premiss AB is false in part, the conclusion may be true. 
For nothing prevents A belonging both to B and to some C, and 
B belonging to some C, e.g. animal to something beautiful and 
to something great, and beautiful belonging to something great. 
If then A is assumed to belong to all B, and B to some C, the a 
premiss AB will be partially false, the premiss BC will be true, 
and the conclusion true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative. 
For the same terms will serve, and in the same positions, to 
prove the point. 

(9) Again if the premiss AB is true, and the premiss BC is false, 
the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents A belonging to 
the whole of B and to some C, while B belongs to no C, e.g. 
animal to every swan and to some black things, though swan 
belongs to no black thing. Consequently if it should be assumed 
that A belongs to all B, and B to some C, the conclusion will be 
true, although the statement BC is false. Similarly if the premiss 
AB is negative. For it is possible that A should belong to no B, 
and not to some C, while B belongs to no C, e.g. a genus to the 
species of another genus and to the accident of its own species: 
for animal belongs to no number and not to some white things, 
and number belongs to nothing white. If then number is taken 
as middle, and it is assumed that A belongs to no B, and B to 
some C, then A will not belong to some C, which ex hypothesi is 
true. And the premiss AB is true, the premiss BC false. 

(10) Also if the premiss AB is partially false, and the premiss BC 
is false too, the conclusion may be true. For nothing prevents A 
belonging to some B and to some C, though B belongs to no C, 
e.g. if B is the contrary of C, and both are accidents of the same 
genus: for animal belongs to some white things and to some 



172 



black things, but white belongs to no black thing. If then it is 
assumed that A belongs to all B, and B to some C, the conclusion 
will be true. Similarly if the premiss AB is negative: for the same 
terms arranged in the same way will serve for the proof. 

(11) Also though both premisses are false the conclusion may be 
true. For it is possible that A may belong to no B and to some C, 
while B belongs to no C, e.g. a genus in relation to the species of 
another genus, and to the accident of its own species: for 
animal belongs to no number, but to some white things, and 
number to nothing white. If then it is assumed that A belongs to 
all B and B to some C, the conclusion will be true, though both 
premisses are false. Similarly also if the premiss AB is negative. 
For nothing prevents A belonging to the whole of B, and not to 
some C, while B belongs to no C, e.g. animal belongs to every 
swan, and not to some black things, and swan belongs to 
nothing black. Consequently if it is assumed that A belongs to 
no B, and B to some C, then A does not belong to some C. The 
conclusion then is true, but the premisses arc false. 



In the middle figure it is possible in every way to reach a true 
conclusion through false premisses, whether the syllogisms are 
universal or particular, viz. when both premisses are wholly 
false; when each is partially false; when one is true, the other 
wholly false (it does not matter which of the two premisses is 
false); if both premisses are partially false; if one is quite true, 
the other partially false; if one is wholly false, the other partially 
true. For (1) if A belongs to no B and to all C, e.g. animal to no 
stone and to every horse, then if the premisses are stated 
contrariwise and it is assumed that A belongs to all B and to no 



173 



C, though the premisses are wholly false they will yield a true 
conclusion. Similarly if A belongs to all B and to no C: for we 
shall have the same syllogism. 

(2) Again if one premiss is wholly false, the other wholly true: 
for nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to all C, though B 
belongs to no C, e.g. a genus to its co-ordinate species. For 
animal belongs to every horse and man, and no man is a horse. 
If then it is assumed that animal belongs to all of the one, and 
none of the other, the one premiss will be wholly false, the 
other wholly true, and the conclusion will be true whichever 
term the negative statement concerns. 

(3) Also if one premiss is partially false, the other wholly true. 
For it is possible that A should belong to some B and to all C, 
though B belongs to no C, e.g. animal to some white things and 
to every raven, though white belongs to no raven. If then it is 
assumed that A belongs to no B, but to the whole of C, the 
premiss AB is partially false, the premiss AC wholly true, and 
the conclusion true. Similarly if the negative statement is 
transposed: the proof can be made by means of the same terms. 
Also if the affirmative premiss is partially false, the negative 
wholly true, a true conclusion is possible. For nothing prevents 
A belonging to some B, but not to C as a whole, while B belongs 
to no C, e.g. animal belongs to some white things, but to no 
pitch, and white belongs to no pitch. Consequently if it is 
assumed that A belongs to the whole of B, but to no C, the 
premiss AB is partially false, the premiss AC is wholly true, and 
the conclusion is true. 

(4) And if both the premisses are partially false, the conclusion 
may be true. For it is possible that A should belong to some B 
and to some C, and B to no C, e.g. animal to some white things 
and to some black things, though white belongs to nothing 
black. If then it is assumed that A belongs to all B and to no C, 



174 



both premisses are partially false, but the conclusion is true. 
Similarly, if the negative premiss is transposed, the proof can be 
made by means of the same terms. 

It is clear also that our thesis holds in particular syllogisms. For 
(5) nothing prevents A belonging to all B and to some C, though 
B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal to every man and to 
some white things, though man will not belong to some white 
things. If then it is stated that A belongs to no B and to some C, 
the universal premiss is wholly false, the particular premiss is 
true, and the conclusion is true. Similarly if the premiss AB is 
affirmative: for it is possible that A should belong to no B, and 
not to some C, though B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal 
belongs to nothing lifeless, and does not belong to some white 
things, and lifeless will not belong to some white things. If then 
it is stated that A belongs to all B and not to some C, the 
premiss AB which is universal is wholly false, the premiss AC is 
true, and the conclusion is true. Also a true conclusion is 
possible when the universal premiss is true, and the particular 
is false. For nothing prevents A following neither B nor C at all, 
while B does not belong to some C, e.g. animal belongs to no 
number nor to anything lifeless, and number does not follow 
some lifeless things. If then it is stated that A belongs to no B 
and to some C, the conclusion will be true, and the universal 
premiss true, but the particular false. Similarly if the premiss 
which is stated universally is affirmative. For it is possible that 
should A belong both to B and to G as wholes, though B does not 
follow some C, e.g. a genus in relation to its species and 
difference: for animal follows every man and footed things as a 
whole, but man does not follow every footed thing. 
Consequently if it is assumed that A belongs to the whole of B, 
but does not belong to some C, the universal premiss is true, the 
particular false, and the conclusion true. 



175 



(6) It is clear too that though both premisses are false they may 
yield a true conclusion, since it is possible that A should belong 
both to B and to C as wholes, though B does not follow some C. 
For if it is assumed that A belongs to no B and to some C, the 
premisses are both false, but the conclusion is true. Similarly if 
the universal premiss is affirmative and the particular negative. 
For it is possible that A should follow no B and all C, though B 
does not belong to some C, e.g. animal follows no science but 
every man, though science does not follow every man. If then A 
is assumed to belong to the whole of B, and not to follow some 
C, the premisses are false but the conclusion is true. 



In the last figure a true conclusion may come through what is 
false, alike when both premisses are wholly false, when each is 
partly false, when one premiss is wholly true, the other false, 
when one premiss is partly false, the other wholly true, and vice 
versa, and in every other way in which it is possible to alter the 
premisses. For (1) nothing prevents neither A nor B from 
belonging to any C, while A belongs to some B, e.g. neither man 
nor footed follows anything lifeless, though man belongs to 
some footed things. If then it is assumed that A and B belong to 
all C, the premisses will be wholly false, but the conclusion true. 
Similarly if one premiss is negative, the other affirmative. For it 
is possible that B should belong to no C, but A to all C, and that 
should not belong to some B, e.g. black belongs to no swan, 
animal to every swan, and animal not to everything black. 
Consequently if it is assumed that B belongs to all C, and A to 
no C, A will not belong to some B: and the conclusion is true, 
though the premisses are false. 



176 



(2) Also if each premiss is partly false, the conclusion may be 
true. For nothing prevents both A and B from belonging to some 
C while A belongs to some B, e.g. white and beautiful belong to 
some animals, and white to some beautiful things. If then it is 
stated that A and B belong to all C, the premisses are partially 
false, but the conclusion is true. Similarly if the premiss AC is 
stated as negative. For nothing prevents A from not belonging, 
and B from belonging, to some C, while A does not belong to all 
B, e.g. white does not belong to some animals, beautiful belongs 
to some animals, and white does not belong to everything 
beautiful. Consequently if it is assumed that A belongs to no C, 
and B to all C, both premisses are partly false, but the 
conclusion is true. 

(3) Similarly if one of the premisses assumed is wholly false, the 
other wholly true. For it is possible that both A and B should 
follow all C, though A does not belong to some B, e.g. animal 
and white follow every swan, though animal does not belong to 
everything white. Taking these then as terms, if one assumes 
that B belongs to the whole of C, but A does not belong to C at 
all, the premiss BC will be wholly true, the premiss AC wholly 
false, and the conclusion true. Similarly if the statement BC is 
false, the statement AC true, the conclusion may be true. The 
same terms will serve for the proof. Also if both the premisses 
assumed are affirmative, the conclusion may be true. For 
nothing prevents B from following all C, and A from not 
belonging to C at all, though A belongs to some B, e.g. animal 
belongs to every swan, black to no swan, and black to some 
animals. Consequently if it is assumed that A and B belong to 
every C, the premiss BC is wholly true, the premiss AC is wholly 
false, and the conclusion is true. Similarly if the premiss AC 
which is assumed is true: the proof can be made through the 
same terms. 



177 



(4) Again if one premiss is wholly true, the other partly false, the 
conclusion may be true. For it is possible that B should belong to 
all C, and A to some C, while A belongs to some B, e.g. biped 
belongs to every man, beautiful not to every man, and beautiful 
to some bipeds. If then it is assumed that both A and B belong 
to the whole of C, the premiss BC is wholly true, the premiss AC 
partly false, the conclusion true. Similarly if of the premisses 
assumed AC is true and BC partly false, a true conclusion is 
possible: this can be proved, if the same terms as before are 
transposed. Also the conclusion may be true if one premiss is 
negative, the other affirmative. For since it is possible that B 
should belong to the whole of C, and A to some C, and, when 
they are so, that A should not belong to all B, therefore it is 
assumed that B belongs to the whole of C, and A to no C, the 
negative premiss is partly false, the other premiss wholly true, 
and the conclusion is true. Again since it has been proved that if 
A belongs to no C and B to some C, it is possible that A should 
not belong to some C, it is clear that if the premiss AC is wholly 
true, and the premiss BC partly false, it is possible that the 
conclusion should be true. For if it is assumed that A belongs to 
no C, and B to all C, the premiss AC is wholly true, and the 
premiss BC is partly false. 

(5) It is clear also in the case of particular syllogisms that a true 
conclusion may come through what is false, in every possible 
way. For the same terms must be taken as have been taken 
when the premisses are universal, positive terms in positive 
syllogisms, negative terms in negative. For it makes no 
difference to the setting out of the terms, whether one assumes 
that what belongs to none belongs to all or that what belongs to 
some belongs to all. The same applies to negative statements. 

It is clear then that if the conclusion is false, the premisses of 
the argument must be false, either all or some of them; but 
when the conclusion is true, it is not necessary that the 



178 



premisses should be true, either one or all, yet it is possible, 
though no part of the syllogism is true, that the conclusion may 
none the less be true; but it is not necessitated. The reason is 
that when two things are so related to one another, that if the 
one is, the other necessarily is, then if the latter is not, the 
former will not be either, but if the latter is, it is not necessary 
that the former should be. But it is impossible that the same 
thing should be necessitated by the being and by the not-being 
of the same thing. I mean, for example, that it is impossible that 
B should necessarily be great since A is white and that B should 
necessarily be great since A is not white. For whenever since 
this, A, is white it is necessary that that, B, should be great, and 
since B is great that C should not be white, then it is necessary 
if is white that C should not be white. And whenever it is 
necessary, since one of two things is, that the other should be, it 
is necessary, if the latter is not, that the former (viz. A) should 
not be. If then B is not great A cannot be white. But if, when A is 
not white, it is necessary that B should be great, it necessarily 
results that if B is not great, B itself is great. (But this is 
impossible.) For if B is not great, A will necessarily not be white. 
If then when this is not white B must be great, it results that if B 
is not great, it is great, just as if it were proved through three 
terms. 



Circular and reciprocal proof means proof by means of the 
conclusion, i.e. by converting one of the premisses simply and 
inferring the premiss which was assumed in the original 
syllogism: e.g. suppose it has been necessary to prove that A 
belongs to all C, and it has been proved through B; suppose that 
A should now be proved to belong to B by assuming that A 



179 



belongs to C, and C to B - so A belongs to B: but in the first 
syllogism the converse was assumed, viz. that B belongs to C. Or 
suppose it is necessary to prove that B belongs to C, and A is 
assumed to belong to C, which was the conclusion of the first 
syllogism, and B to belong to A but the converse was assumed 
in the earlier syllogism, viz. that A belongs to B. In no other way 
is reciprocal proof possible. If another term is taken as middle, 
the proof is not circular: for neither of the propositions assumed 
is the same as before: if one of the accepted terms is taken as 
middle, only one of the premisses of the first syllogism can be 
assumed in the second: for if both of them are taken the same 
conclusion as before will result: but it must be different. If the 
terms are not convertible, one of the premisses from which the 
syllogism results must be undemonstrated: for it is not possible 
to demonstrate through these terms that the third belongs to 
the middle or the middle to the first. If the terms are 
convertible, it is possible to demonstrate everything reciprocally, 
e.g. if A and B and C are convertible with one another. Suppose 
the proposition AC has been demonstrated through B as middle 
term, and again the proposition AB through the conclusion and 
the premiss BC converted, and similarly the proposition BC 
through the conclusion and the premiss AB converted. But it is 
necessary to prove both the premiss CB, and the premiss BA: for 
we have used these alone without demonstrating them. If then 
it is assumed that B belongs to all C, and C to all A, we shall 
have a syllogism relating B to A. Again if it is assumed that C 
belongs to all A, and A to all B, C must belong to all B. In both 
these syllogisms the premiss CA has been assumed without 
being demonstrated: the other premisses had ex hypothesi been 
proved. Consequently if we succeed in demonstrating this 
premiss, all the premisses will have been proved reciprocally. If 
then it is assumed that C belongs to all B, and B to all A, both 
the premisses assumed have been proved, and C must belong to 
A. It is clear then that only if the terms are convertible is 



180 



circular and reciprocal demonstration possible (if the terms are 
not convertible, the matter stands as we said above). But it turns 
out in these also that we use for the demonstration the very 
thing that is being proved: for C is proved of B, and B of by 
assuming that C is said of and C is proved of A through these 
premisses, so that we use the conclusion for the demonstration. 

In negative syllogisms reciprocal proof is as follows. Let B 
belong to all C, and A to none of the Bs: we conclude that A 
belongs to none of the Cs. If again it is necessary to prove that A 
belongs to none of the Bs (which was previously assumed) A 
must belong to no C, and C to all B: thus the previous premiss is 
reversed. If it is necessary to prove that B belongs to C, the 
proposition AB must no longer be converted as before: for the 
premiss 'B belongs to no A' is identical with the premiss 'A 
belongs to no B'. But we must assume that B belongs to all of 
that to none of which longs. Let A belong to none of the Cs 
(which was the previous conclusion) and assume that B belongs 
to all of that to none of which A belongs. It is necessary then 
that B should belong to all C. Consequently each of the three 
propositions has been made a conclusion, and this is circular 
demonstration, to assume the conclusion and the converse of 
one of the premisses, and deduce the remaining premiss. 

In particular syllogisms it is not possible to demonstrate the 
universal premiss through the other propositions, but the 
particular premiss can be demonstrated. Clearly it is impossible 
to demonstrate the universal premiss: for what is universal is 
proved through propositions which are universal, but the 
conclusion is not universal, and the proof must start from the 
conclusion and the other premiss. Further a syllogism cannot 
be made at all if the other premiss is converted: for the result is 
that both premisses are particular. But the particular premiss 
may be proved. Suppose that A has been proved of some C 
through B. If then it is assumed that B belongs to all A and the 



181 



conclusion is retained, B will belong to some C: for we obtain 
the first figure and A is middle. But if the syllogism is negative, 
it is not possible to prove the universal premiss, for the reason 
given above. But it is possible to prove the particular premiss, if 
the proposition AB is converted as in the universal syllogism, i.e 
'B belongs to some of that to some of which A does not belong': 
otherwise no syllogism results because the particular premiss is 
negative. 



In the second figure it is not possible to prove an affirmative 
proposition in this way, but a negative proposition may be 
proved. An affirmative proposition is not proved because both 
premisses of the new syllogism are not affirmative (for the 
conclusion is negative) but an affirmative proposition is (as we 
saw) proved from premisses which are both affirmative. The 
negative is proved as follows. Let A belong to all B, and to no C: 
we conclude that B belongs to no C. If then it is assumed that B 
belongs to all A, it is necessary that A should belong to no C: for 
we get the second figure, with B as middle. But if the premiss AB 
was negative, and the other affirmative, we shall have the first 
figure. For C belongs to all A and B to no C, consequently B 
belongs to no A: neither then does A belong to B. Through the 
conclusion, therefore, and one premiss, we get no syllogism, but 
if another premiss is assumed in addition, a syllogism will be 
possible. But if the syllogism not universal, the universal 
premiss cannot be proved, for the same reason as we gave 
above, but the particular premiss can be proved whenever the 
universal statement is affirmative. Let A belong to all B, and not 
to all C: the conclusion is BC. If then it is assumed that B 
belongs to all A, but not to all C, A will not belong to some C, B 



182 



being middle. But if the universal premiss is negative, the 
premiss AC will not be demonstrated by the conversion of AB: 
for it turns out that either both or one of the premisses is 
negative; consequently a syllogism will not be possible. But the 
proof will proceed as in the universal syllogisms, if it is 
assumed that A belongs to some of that to some of which B 
does not belong. 



In the third figure, when both premisses are taken universally, it 
is not possible to prove them reciprocally: for that which is 
universal is proved through statements which are universal, but 
the conclusion in this figure is always particular, so that it is 
clear that it is not possible at all to prove through this figure the 
universal premiss. But if one premiss is universal, the other 
particular, proof of the latter will sometimes be possible, 
sometimes not. When both the premisses assumed are 
affirmative, and the universal concerns the minor extreme, 
proof will be possible, but when it concerns the other extreme, 
impossible. Let A belong to all C and B to some C: the conclusion 
is the statement AB. If then it is assumed that C belongs to all A, 
it has been proved that C belongs to some B, but that B belongs 
to some C has not been proved. And yet it is necessary, if C 
belongs to some B, that B should belong to some C. But it is not 
the same that this should belong to that, and that to this: but 
we must assume besides that if this belongs to some of that, 
that belongs to some of this. But if this is assumed the 
syllogism no longer results from the conclusion and the other 
premiss. But if B belongs to all C, and A to some C, it will be 
possible to prove the proposition AC, when it is assumed that C 
belongs to all B, and A to some B. For if C belongs to all B and A 



183 



to some B, it is necessary that A should belong to some C, B 
being middle. And whenever one premiss is affirmative the 
other negative, and the affirmative is universal, the other 
premiss can be proved. Let B belong to all C, and A not to some 
C: the conclusion is that A does not belong to some B. If then it 
is assumed further that C belongs to all B, it is necessary that A 
should not belong to some C, B being middle. But when the 
negative premiss is universal, the other premiss is not except as 
before, viz. if it is assumed that that belongs to some of that, to 
some of which this does not belong, e.g. if A belongs to no C, 
and B to some C: the conclusion is that A does not belong to 
some B. If then it is assumed that C belongs to some of that to 
some of which does not belong, it is necessary that C should 
belong to some of the Bs. In no other way is it possible by 
converting the universal premiss to prove the other: for in no 
other way can a syllogism be formed. 

It is clear then that in the first figure reciprocal proof is made 
both through the third and through the first figure - if the 
conclusion is affirmative through the first; if the conclusion is 
negative through the last. For it is assumed that that belongs to 
all of that to none of which this belongs. In the middle figure, 
when the syllogism is universal, proof is possible through the 
second figure and through the first, but when particular 
through the second and the last. In the third figure all proofs 
are made through itself. It is clear also that in the third figure 
and in the middle figure those syllogisms which are not made 
through those figures themselves either are not of the nature of 
circular proof or are imperfect. 



184 



8 

To convert a syllogism means to alter the conclusion and make 
another syllogism to prove that either the extreme cannot 
belong to the middle or the middle to the last term. For it is 
necessary, if the conclusion has been changed into its opposite 
and one of the premisses stands, that the other premiss should 
be destroyed. For if it should stand, the conclusion also must 
stand. It makes a difference whether the conclusion is 
converted into its contradictory or into its contrary. For the 
same syllogism does not result whichever form the conversion 
takes. This will be made clear by the sequel. By contradictory 
opposition I mean the opposition of 'to all' to 'not to all', and of 
'to some' to 'to none'; by contrary opposition I mean the 
opposition of 'to all' to 'to none', and of 'to some' to 'not to 
some'. Suppose that A been proved of C, through B as middle 
term. If then it should be assumed that A belongs to no C, but to 
all B, B will belong to no C. And if A belongs to no C, and B to all 
C, A will belong, not to no B at all, but not to all B. For (as we 
saw) the universal is not proved through the last figure. In a 
word it is not possible to refute universally by conversion the 
premiss which concerns the major extreme: for the refutation 
always proceeds through the third since it is necessary to take 
both premisses in reference to the minor extreme. Similarly if 
the syllogism is negative. Suppose it has been proved that A 
belongs to no C through B. Then if it is assumed that A belongs 
to all C, and to no B, B will belong to none of the Cs. And if A and 
B belong to all C, A will belong to some B: but in the original 
premiss it belonged to no B. 

If the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, the 
syllogisms will be contradictory and not universal. For one 
premiss is particular, so that the conclusion also will be 
particular. Let the syllogism be affirmative, and let it be 
converted as stated. Then if A belongs not to all C, but to all B, B 



185 



will belong not to all C. And if A belongs not to all C, but B 
belongs to all C, A will belong not to all B. Similarly if the 
syllogism is negative. For if A belongs to some C, and to no B, B 
will belong, not to no C at all, but - not to some C. And if A 
belongs to some C, and B to all C, as was originally assumed, A 
will belong to some B. 

In particular syllogisms when the conclusion is converted into 
its contradictory, both premisses may be refuted, but when it is 
converted into its contrary, neither. For the result is no longer, 
as in the universal syllogisms, refutation in which the 
conclusion reached by 0, conversion lacks universality, but no 
refutation at all. Suppose that A has been proved of some C. If 
then it is assumed that A belongs to no C, and B to some C, A 
will not belong to some B: and if A belongs to no C, but to all B, B 
will belong to no C.Thus both premisses are refuted. But neither 
can be refuted if the conclusion is converted into its contrary. 
For if A does not belong to some C, but to all B, then B will not 
belong to some C. But the original premiss is not yet refuted: for 
it is possible that B should belong to some C, and should not 
belong to some C. The universal premiss AB cannot be affected 
by a syllogism at all: for if A does not belong to some of the Cs, 
but B belongs to some of the Cs, neither of the premisses is 
universal. Similarly if the syllogism is negative: for if it should 
be assumed that A belongs to all C, both premisses are refuted: 
but if the assumption is that A belongs to some C, neither 
premiss is refuted. The proof is the same as before. 



In the second figure it is not possible to refute the premiss 
which concerns the major extreme by establishing something 



186 



contrary to it, whichever form the conversion of the conclusion 
may take. For the conclusion of the refutation will always be in 
the third figure, and in this figure (as we saw) there is no 
universal syllogism. The other premiss can be refuted in a 
manner similar to the conversion: I mean, if the conclusion of 
the first syllogism is converted into its contrary, the conclusion 
of the refutation will be the contrary of the minor premiss of 
the first, if into its contradictory, the contradictory. Let A belong 
to all B and to no C: conclusion BC. If then it is assumed that B 
belongs to all C, and the proposition AB stands, A will belong to 
all C, since the first figure is produced. If B belongs to all C, and 
A to no C, then A belongs not to all B: the figure is the last. But if 
the conclusion BC is converted into its contradictory, the 
premiss AB will be refuted as before, the premiss, AC by its 
contradictory. For if B belongs to some C, and A to no C, then A 
will not belong to some B. Again if B belongs to some C, and A to 
all B, A will belong to some C, so that the syllogism results in 
the contradictory of the minor premiss. A similar proof can be 
given if the premisses are transposed in respect of their quality. 

If the syllogism is particular, when the conclusion is converted 
into its contrary neither premiss can be refuted, as also 
happened in the first figure,' if the conclusion is converted into 
its contradictory, both premisses can be refuted. Suppose that A 
belongs to no B, and to some C: the conclusion is BC. If then it is 
assumed that B belongs to some C, and the statement AB 
stands, the conclusion will be that A does not belong to some C. 
But the original statement has not been refuted: for it is 
possible that A should belong to some C and also not to some C. 
Again if B belongs to some C and A to some C, no syllogism will 
be possible: for neither of the premisses taken is universal. 
Consequently the proposition AB is not refuted. But if the 
conclusion is converted into its contradictory, both premisses 
can be refuted. For if B belongs to all C, and A to no B, A will 
belong to no C: but it was assumed to belong to some C. Again if 



187 



B belongs to all C and A to some C, A will belong to some B. The 
same proof can be given if the universal statement is 
affirmative. 



10 

In the third figure when the conclusion is converted into its 
contrary, neither of the premisses can be refuted in any of the 
syllogisms, but when the conclusion is converted into its 
contradictory, both premisses may be refuted and in all the 
moods. Suppose it has been proved that A belongs to some B, C 
being taken as middle, and the premisses being universal. If 
then it is assumed that A does not belong to some B, but B 
belongs to all C, no syllogism is formed about A and C. Nor if A 
does not belong to some B, but belongs to all C, will a syllogism 
be possible about B and C. A similar proof can be given if the 
premisses are not universal. For either both premisses arrived at 
by the conversion must be particular, or the universal premiss 
must refer to the minor extreme. But we found that no 
syllogism is possible thus either in the first or in the middle 
figure. But if the conclusion is converted into its contradictory, 
both the premisses can be refuted. For if A belongs to no B, and 
B to all C, then A belongs to no C: again if A belongs to no B, and 
to all C, B belongs to no C. And similarly if one of the premisses 
is not universal. For if A belongs to no B, and B to some C, A will 
not belong to some C: if A belongs to no B, and to C, B will 
belong to no C. 

Similarly if the original syllogism is negative. Suppose it has 
been proved that A does not belong to some B, BC being 
affirmative, AC being negative: for it was thus that, as we saw, a 
syllogism could be made. Whenever then the contrary of the 



188 



conclusion is assumed a syllogism will not be possible. For if A 
belongs to some B, and B to all C, no syllogism is possible (as we 
saw) about A and C. Nor, if A belongs to some B, and to no C, 
was a syllogism possible concerning B and C. Therefore the 
premisses are not refuted. But when the contradictory of the 
conclusion is assumed, they are refuted. For if A belongs to all B, 
and B to C, A belongs to all C: but A was supposed originally to 
belong to no C. Again if A belongs to all B, and to no C, then B 
belongs to no C: but it was supposed to belong to all C. A similar 
proof is possible if the premisses are not universal. For AC 
becomes universal and negative, the other premiss particular 
and affirmative. If then A belongs to all B, and B to some C, it 
results that A belongs to some C: but it was supposed to belong 
to no C. Again if A belongs to all B, and to no C, then B belongs 
to no C: but it was assumed to belong to some C. If A belongs to 
some B and B to some C, no syllogism results: nor yet if A 
belongs to some B, and to no C. Thus in one way the premisses 
are refuted, in the other way they are not. 

From what has been said it is clear how a syllogism results in 
each figure when the conclusion is converted; when a result 
contrary to the premiss, and when a result contradictory to the 
premiss, is obtained. It is clear that in the first figure the 
syllogisms are formed through the middle and the last figures, 
and the premiss which concerns the minor extreme is alway 
refuted through the middle figure, the premiss which concerns 
the major through the last figure. In the second figure 
syllogisms proceed through the first and the last figures, and 
the premiss which concerns the minor extreme is always 
refuted through the first figure, the premiss which concerns the 
major extreme through the last. In the third figure the 
refutation proceeds through the first and the middle figures; the 
premiss which concerns the major is always refuted through 
the first figure, the premiss which concerns the minor through 
the middle figure. 



189 



11 

It is clear then what conversion is, how it is effected in each 
figure, and what syllogism results. The syllogism per 
impossibile is proved when the contradictory of the conclusion 
stated and another premiss is assumed; it can be made in all 
the figures. For it resembles conversion, differing only in this: 
conversion takes place after a syllogism has been formed and 
both the premisses have been taken, but a reduction to the 
impossible takes place not because the contradictory has been 
agreed to already, but because it is clear that it is true. The 
terms are alike in both, and the premisses of both are taken in 
the same way. For example if A belongs to all B, C being middle, 
then if it is supposed that A does not belong to all B or belongs 
to no B, but to all C (which was admitted to be true), it follows 
that C belongs to no B or not to all B. But this is impossible: 
consequently the supposition is false: its contradictory then is 
true. Similarly in the other figures: for whatever moods admit of 
conversion admit also of the reduction per impossibile. 

All the problems can be proved per impossibile in all the figures, 
excepting the universal affirmative, which is proved in the 
middle and third figures, but not in the first. Suppose that A 
belongs not to all B, or to no B, and take besides another 
premiss concerning either of the terms, viz. that C belongs to all 
A, or that B belongs to all D; thus we get the first figure. If then 
it is supposed that A does not belong to all B, no syllogism 
results whichever term the assumed premiss concerns; but if it 
is supposed that A belongs to no B, when the premiss BD is 
assumed as well we shall prove syllogistically what is false, but 
not the problem proposed. For if A belongs to no B, and B 
belongs to all D, A belongs to no D. Let this be impossible: it is 



190 



false then A belongs to no B. But the universal affirmative is not 
necessarily true if the universal negative is false. But if the 
premiss CA is assumed as well, no syllogism results, nor does it 
do so when it is supposed that A does not belong to all B. 
Consequently it is clear that the universal affirmative cannot be 
proved in the first figure per impossibile. 

But the particular affirmative and the universal and particular 
negatives can all be proved. Suppose that A belongs to no B, and 
let it have been assumed that B belongs to all or to some C. 
Then it is necessary that A should belong to no C or not to all C. 
But this is impossible (for let it be true and clear that A belongs 
to all C): consequently if this is false, it is necessary that A 
should belong to some B. But if the other premiss assumed 
relates to A, no syllogism will be possible. Nor can a conclusion 
be drawn when the contrary of the conclusion is supposed, e.g. 
that A does not belong to some B. Clearly then we must suppose 
the contradictory. 

Again suppose that A belongs to some B, and let it have been 
assumed that C belongs to all A. It is necessary then that C 
should belong to some B. But let this be impossible, so that the 
supposition is false: in that case it is true that A belongs to no B. 
We may proceed in the same way if the proposition CA has been 
taken as negative. But if the premiss assumed concerns B, no 
syllogism will be possible. If the contrary is supposed, we shall 
have a syllogism and an impossible conclusion, but the problem 
in hand is not proved. Suppose that A belongs to all B, and let it 
have been assumed that C belongs to all A. It is necessary then 
that C should belong to all B. But this is impossible, so that it is 
false that A belongs to all B. But we have not yet shown it to be 
necessary that A belongs to no B, if it does not belong to all B. 
Similarly if the other premiss taken concerns B; we shall have a 
syllogism and a conclusion which is impossible, but the 



191 



hypothesis is not refuted. Therefore it is the contradictory that 
we must suppose. 

To prove that A does not belong to all B, we must suppose that it 
belongs to all B: for if A belongs to all B, and C to all A, then C 
belongs to all B; so that if this is impossible, the hypothesis is 
false. Similarly if the other premiss assumed concerns B. The 
same results if the original proposition CA was negative: for 
thus also we get a syllogism. But if the negative proposition 
concerns B, nothing is proved. If the hypothesis is that A 
belongs not to all but to some B, it is not proved that A belongs 
not to all B, but that it belongs to no B. For if A belongs to some 
B, and C to all A, then C will belong to some B. If then this is 
impossible, it is false that A belongs to some B; consequently it 
is true that A belongs to no B. But if this is proved, the truth is 
refuted as well; for the original conclusion was that A belongs to 
some B, and does not belong to some B. Further the impossible 
does not result from the hypothesis: for then the hypothesis 
would be false, since it is impossible to draw a false conclusion 
from true premisses: but in fact it is true: for A belongs to some 
B. Consequently we must not suppose that A belongs to some B, 
but that it belongs to all B. Similarly if we should be proving that 
A does not belong to some B: for if 'not to belong to some' and 
'to belong not to all' have the same meaning, the demonstration 
of both will be identical. 

It is clear then that not the contrary but the contradictory ought 
to be supposed in all the syllogisms. For thus we shall have 
necessity of inference, and the claim we make is one that will 
be generally accepted. For if of everything one or other of two 
contradictory statements holds good, then if it is proved that 
the negation does not hold, the affirmation must be true. Again 
if it is not admitted that the affirmation is true, the claim that 
the negation is true will be generally accepted. But in neither 
way does it suit to maintain the contrary: for it is not necessary 



192 



that if the universal negative is false, the universal affirmative 
should be true, nor is it generally accepted that if the one is 
false the other is true. 



12 

It is clear then that in the first figure all problems except the 
universal affirmative are proved per impossibile. But in the 
middle and the last figures this also is proved. Suppose that A 
does not belong to all B, and let it have been assumed that A 
belongs to all C. If then A belongs not to all B, but to all C, C will 
not belong to all B. But this is impossible (for suppose it to be 
clear that C belongs to all B): consequently the hypothesis is 
false. It is true then that A belongs to all B. But if the contrary is 
supposed, we shall have a syllogism and a result which is 
impossible: but the problem in hand is not proved. For if A 
belongs to no B, and to all C, C will belong to no B. This is 
impossible; so that it is false that A belongs to no B. But though 
this is false, it does not follow that it is true that A belongs to all 
B. 

When A belongs to some B, suppose that A belongs to no B, and 
let A belong to all C. It is necessary then that C should belong to 
no B. Consequently, if this is impossible, A must belong to some 

B. But if it is supposed that A does not belong to some B, we 
shall have the same results as in the first figure. 

Again suppose that A belongs to some B, and let A belong to no 

C. It is necessary then that C should not belong to some B. But 
originally it belonged to all B, consequently the hypothesis is 
false: A then will belong to no B. 



193 



When A does not belong to an B, suppose it does belong to all B, 
and to no C. It is necessary then that C should belong to no B. 
But this is impossible: so that it is true that A does not belong to 
all B. It is clear then that all the syllogisms can be formed in the 
middle figure. 



13 

Similarly they can all be formed in the last figure. Suppose that 
A does not belong to some B, but C belongs to all B: then A does 
not belong to some C. If then this is impossible, it is false that A 
does not belong to some B; so that it is true that A belongs to all 
B. But if it is supposed that A belongs to no B, we shall have a 
syllogism and a conclusion which is impossible: but the 
problem in hand is not proved: for if the contrary is supposed, 
we shall have the same results as before. 

But to prove that A belongs to some B, this hypothesis must be 
made. If A belongs to no B, and C to some B, A will belong not to 
all C. If then this is false, it is true that A belongs to some B. 

When A belongs to no B, suppose A belongs to some B, and let it 
have been assumed that C belongs to all B. Then it is necessary 
that A should belong to some C. But ex hypothesi it belongs to 
no C, so that it is false that A belongs to some B. But if it is 
supposed that A belongs to all B, the problem is not proved. 

But this hypothesis must be made if we are prove that A belongs 
not to all B. For if A belongs to all B and C to some B, then A 
belongs to some C. But this we assumed not to be so, so it is 
false that A belongs to all B. But in that case it is true that A 
belongs not to all B. If however it is assumed that A belongs to 
some B, we shall have the same result as before. 



194 



It is clear then that in all the syllogisms which proceed per 
impossibile the contradictory must be assumed. And it is plain 
that in the middle figure an affirmative conclusion, and in the 
last figure a universal conclusion, are proved in a way. 



14 

Demonstration per impossibile differs from ostensive proof in 
that it posits what it wishes to refute by reduction to a 
statement admitted to be false; whereas ostensive proof starts 
from admitted positions. Both, indeed, take two premisses that 
are admitted, but the latter takes the premisses from which the 
syllogism starts, the former takes one of these, along with the 
contradictory of the original conclusion. Also in the ostensive 
proof it is not necessary that the conclusion should be known, 
nor that one should suppose beforehand that it is true or not: in 
the other it is necessary to suppose beforehand that it is not 
true. It makes no difference whether the conclusion is 
affirmative or negative; the method is the same in both cases. 
Everything which is concluded ostensively can be proved per 
impossibile, and that which is proved per impossibile can be 
proved ostensively, through the same terms. Whenever the 
syllogism is formed in the first figure, the truth will be found in 
the middle or the last figure, if negative in the middle, if 
affirmative in the last. Whenever the syllogism is formed in the 
middle figure, the truth will be found in the first, whatever the 
problem may be. Whenever the syllogism is formed in the last 
figure, the truth will be found in the first and middle figures, if 
affirmative in first, if negative in the middle. Suppose that A has 
been proved to belong to no B, or not to all B, through the first 
figure. Then the hypothesis must have been that A belongs to 
some B, and the original premisses that C belongs to all A and to 



195 



no B. For thus the syllogism was made and the impossible 
conclusion reached. But this is the middle figure, if C belongs to 
all A and to no B. And it is clear from these premisses that A 
belongs to no B. Similarly if has been proved not to belong to all 
B. For the hypothesis is that A belongs to all B; and the original 
premisses are that C belongs to all A but not to all B. Similarly 
too, if the premiss CA should be negative: for thus also we have 
the middle figure. Again suppose it has been proved that A 
belongs to some B. The hypothesis here is that is that A belongs 
to no B; and the original premisses that B belongs to all C, and A 
either to all or to some C: for in this way we shall get what is 
impossible. But if A and B belong to all C, we have the last 
figure. And it is clear from these premisses that A must belong 
to some B. Similarly if B or A should be assumed to belong to 
some C. 

Again suppose it has been proved in the middle figure that A 
belongs to all B. Then the hypothesis must have been that A 
belongs not to all B, and the original premisses that A belongs to 
all C, and C to all B: for thus we shall get what is impossible. But 
if A belongs to all C, and C to all B, we have the first figure. 
Similarly if it has been proved that A belongs to some B: for the 
hypothesis then must have been that A belongs to no B, and the 
original premisses that A belongs to all C, and C to some B. If 
the syllogism is negative, the hypothesis must have been that A 
belongs to some B, and the original premisses that A belongs to 
no C, and C to all B, so that the first figure results. If the 
syllogism is not universal, but proof has been given that A does 
not belong to some B, we may infer in the same way. The 
hypothesis is that A belongs to all B, the original premisses that 
A belongs to no C, and C belongs to some B: for thus we get the 
first figure. 

Again suppose it has been proved in the third figure that A 
belongs to all B. Then the hypothesis must have been that A 



196 



belongs not to all B, and the original premisses that C belongs to 
all B, and A belongs to all C; for thus we shall get what is 
impossible. And the original premisses form the first figure. 
Similarly if the demonstration establishes a particular 
proposition: the hypothesis then must have been that A belongs 
to no B, and the original premisses that C belongs to some B, 
and A to all C. If the syllogism is negative, the hypothesis must 
have been that A belongs to some B, and the original premisses 
that C belongs to no A and to all B, and this is the middle figure. 
Similarly if the demonstration is not universal. The hypothesis 
will then be that A belongs to all B, the premisses that C belongs 
to no A and to some B: and this is the middle figure. 

It is clear then that it is possible through the same terms to 
prove each of the problems ostensively as well. Similarly it will 
be possible if the syllogisms are ostensive to reduce them ad 
impossibile in the terms which have been taken, whenever the 
contradictory of the conclusion of the ostensive syllogism is 
taken as a premiss. For the syllogisms become identical with 
those which are obtained by means of conversion, so that we 
obtain immediately the figures through which each problem 
will be solved. It is clear then that every thesis can be proved in 
both ways, i.e. per impossibile and ostensively, and it is not 
possible to separate one method from the other. 



15 

In what figure it is possible to draw a conclusion from 
premisses which are opposed, and in what figure this is not 
possible, will be made clear in this way. Verbally four kinds of 
opposition are possible, viz. universal affirmative to universal 
negative, universal affirmative to particular negative, particular 



197 



affirmative to universal negative, and particular affirmative to 
particular negative: but really there are only three: for the 
particular affirmative is only verbally opposed to the particular 
negative. Of the genuine opposites I call those which are 
universal contraries, the universal affirmative and the universal 
negative, e.g. 'every science is good', 'no science is good'; the 
others I call contradictories. 

In the first figure no syllogism whether affirmative or negative 
can be made out of opposed premisses: no affirmative syllogism 
is possible because both premisses must be affirmative, but 
opposites are, the one affirmative, the other negative: no 
negative syllogism is possible because opposites affirm and 
deny the same predicate of the same subject, and the middle 
term in the first figure is not predicated of both extremes, but 
one thing is denied of it, and it is affirmed of something else: 
but such premisses are not opposed. 

In the middle figure a syllogism can be made both 
oLcontradictories and of contraries. Let A stand for good, let B 
and C stand for science. If then one assumes that every science 
is good, and no science is good, A belongs to all B and to no C, so 
that B belongs to no C: no science then is a science. Similarly if 
after taking 'every science is good' one took 'the science of 
medicine is not good'; for A belongs to all B but to no C, so that 
a particular science will not be a science. Again, a particular 
science will not be a science if A belongs to all C but to no B, and 
B is science, C medicine, and A supposition: for after taking 'no 
science is supposition', one has assumed that a particular 
science is supposition. This syllogism differs from the preceding 
because the relations between the terms are reversed: before, 
the affirmative statement concerned B, now it concerns C. 
Similarly if one premiss is not universal: for the middle term is 
always that which is stated negatively of one extreme, and 
affirmatively of the other. Consequently it is possible that 



198 



contradictories may lead to a conclusion, though not always or 
in every mood, but only if the terms subordinate to the middle 
are such that they are either identical or related as whole to 
part. Otherwise it is impossible: for the premisses cannot 
anyhow be either contraries or contradictories. 

In the third figure an affirmative syllogism can never be made 
out of opposite premisses, for the reason given in reference to 
the first figure; but a negative syllogism is possible whether the 
terms are universal or not. Let B and C stand for science, A for 
medicine. If then one should assume that all medicine is 
science and that no medicine is science, he has assumed that B 
belongs to all A and C to no A, so that a particular science will 
not be a science. Similarly if the premiss BA is not assumed 
universally. For if some medicine is science and again no 
medicine is science, it results that some science is not science, 
The premisses are contrary if the terms are taken universally; if 
one is particular, they are contradictory. 

We must recognize that it is possible to take opposites in the 
way we said, viz. 'all science is good' and 'no science is good' or 
'some science is not good'. This does not usually escape notice. 
But it is possible to establish one part of a contradiction through 
other premisses, or to assume it in the way suggested in the 
Topics. Since there are three oppositions to affirmative 
statements, it follows that opposite statements may be 
assumed as premisses in six ways; we may have either 
universal affirmative and negative, or universal affirmative and 
particular negative, or particular affirmative and universal 
negative, and the relations between the terms may be reversed; 
e.g. A may belong to all B and to no C, or to all C and to no B, or 
to all of the one, not to all of the other; here too the relation 
between the terms may be reversed. Similarly in the third 
figure. So it is clear in how many ways and in what figures a 



199 



syllogism can be made by means of premisses which are 
opposed. 

It is clear too that from false premisses it is possible to draw a 
true conclusion, as has been said before, but it is not possible if 
the premisses are opposed. For the syllogism is always contrary 
to the fact, e.g. if a thing is good, it is proved that it is not good, 
if an animal, that it is not an animal because the syllogism 
springs out of a contradiction and the terms presupposed are 
either identical or related as whole and part. It is evident also 
that in fallacious reasonings nothing prevents a contradiction to 
the hypothesis from resulting, e.g. if something is odd, it is not 
odd. For the syllogism owed its contrariety to its contradictory 
premisses; if we assume such premisses we shall get a result 
that contradicts our hypothesis. But we must recognize that 
contraries cannot be inferred from a single syllogism in such a 
way that we conclude that what is not good is good, or anything 
of that sort unless a self-contradictory premiss is at once 
assumed, e.g. 'every animal is white and not white', and we 
proceed 'man is an animal'. Either we must introduce the 
contradiction by an additional assumption, assuming, e.g., that 
every science is supposition, and then assuming 'Medicine is a 
science, but none of it is supposition' (which is the mode in 
which refutations are made), or we must argue from two 
syllogisms. In no other way than this, as was said before, is it 
possible that the premisses should be really contrary. 



16 

To beg and assume the original question is a species of failure 
to demonstrate the problem proposed; but this happens in 
many ways. A man may not reason syllogistically at all, or he 



200 



may argue from premisses which are less known or equally 
unknown, or he may establish the antecedent by means of its 
consequents; for demonstration proceeds from what is more 
certain and is prior. Now begging the question is none of these: 
but since we get to know some things naturally through 
themselves, and other things by means of something else (the 
first principles through themselves, what is subordinate to 
them through something else), whenever a man tries to prove 
what is not self-evident by means of itself, then he begs the 
original question. This may be done by assuming what is in 
question at once; it is also possible to make a transition to other 
things which would naturally be proved through the thesis 
proposed, and demonstrate it through them, e.g. if A should be 
proved through B, and B through C, though it was natural that C 
should be proved through A: for it turns out that those who 
reason thus are proving A by means of itself. This is what those 
persons do who suppose that they are constructing parallel 
straight lines: for they fail to see that they are assuming facts 
which it is impossible to demonstrate unless the parallels exist. 
So it turns out that those who reason thus merely say a 
particular thing is, if it is: in this way everything will be self- 
evident. But that is impossible. 

If then it is uncertain whether A belongs to C, and also whether 
A belongs to B, and if one should assume that A does belong to 
B, it is not yet clear whether he begs the original question, but it 
is evident that he is not demonstrating: for what is as uncertain 
as the question to be answered cannot be a principle of a 
demonstration. If however B is so related to C that they are 
identical, or if they are plainly convertible, or the one belongs to 
the other, the original question is begged. For one might equally 
well prove that A belongs to B through those terms if they are 
convertible. But if they are not convertible, it is the fact that they 
are not that prevents such a demonstration, not the method of 
demonstrating. But if one were to make the conversion, then he 



201 



would be doing what we have described and effecting a 
reciprocal proof with three propositions. 

Similarly if he should assume that B belongs to C, this being as 
uncertain as the question whether A belongs to C, the question 
is not yet begged, but no demonstration is made. If however A 
and B are identical either because they are convertible or 
because A follows B, then the question is begged for the same 
reason as before. For we have explained the meaning of begging 
the question, viz. proving that which is not self-evident by 
means of itself. 

If then begging the question is proving what is not self-evident 
by means of itself, in other words failing to prove when the 
failure is due to the thesis to be proved and the premiss through 
which it is proved being equally uncertain, either because 
predicates which are identical belong to the same subject, or 
because the same predicate belongs to subjects which are 
identical, the question may be begged in the middle and third 
figures in both ways, though, if the syllogism is affirmative, only 
in the third and first figures. If the syllogism is negative, the 
question is begged when identical predicates are denied of the 
same subject; and both premisses do not beg the question 
indifferently (in a similar way the question may be begged in 
the middle figure), because the terms in negative syllogisms are 
not convertible. In scientific demonstrations the question is 
begged when the terms are really related in the manner 
described, in dialectical arguments when they are according to 
common opinion so related. 



202 



17 

The objection that 'this is not the reason why the result is false', 
which we frequently make in argument, is made primarily in 
the case of a reductio ad impossibile, to rebut the proposition 
which was being proved by the reduction. For unless a man has 
contradicted this proposition he will not say, 'False cause', but 
urge that something false has been assumed in the earlier parts 
of the argument; nor will he use the formula in the case of an 
ostensive proof; for here what one denies is not assumed as a 
premiss. Further when anything is refuted ostensively by the 
terms ABC, it cannot be objected that the syllogism does not 
depend on the assumption laid down. For we use the expression 
'false cause', when the syllogism is concluded in spite of the 
refutation of this position; but that is not possible in ostensive 
proofs: since if an assumption is refuted, a syllogism can no 
longer be drawn in reference to it. It is clear then that the 
expression 'false cause' can only be used in the case of a 
reductio ad impossibile, and when the original hypothesis is so 
related to the impossible conclusion, that the conclusion results 
indifferently whether the hypothesis is made or not. The most 
obvious case of the irrelevance of an assumption to a 
conclusion which is false is when a syllogism drawn from 
middle terms to an impossible conclusion is independent of the 
hypothesis, as we have explained in the Topics. For to put that 
which is not the cause as the cause, is just this: e.g. if a man, 
wishing to prove that the diagonal of the square is 
incommensurate with the side, should try to prove Zeno's 
theorem that motion is impossible, and so establish a reductio 
ad impossibile: for Zeno's false theorem has no connexion at all 
with the original assumption. Another case is where the 
impossible conclusion is connected with the hypothesis, but 
does not result from it. This may happen whether one traces the 
connexion upwards or downwards, e.g. if it is laid down that A 
belongs to B, B to C, and C to D, and it should be false that B 



203 



belongs to D: for if we eliminated A and assumed all the same 
that B belongs to C and C to D, the false conclusion would not 
depend on the original hypothesis. Or again trace the connexion 
upwards; e.g. suppose that A belongs to B, E to A and F to E, it 
being false that F belongs to A. In this way too the impossible 
conclusion would result, though the original hypothesis were 
eliminated. But the impossible conclusion ought to be 
connected with the original terms: in this way it will depend on 
the hypothesis, e.g. when one traces the connexion downwards, 
the impossible conclusion must be connected with that term 
which is predicate in the hypothesis: for if it is impossible that 
A should belong to D, the false conclusion will no longer result 
after A has been eliminated. If one traces the connexion 
upwards, the impossible conclusion must be connected with 
that term which is subject in the hypothesis: for if it is 
impossible that F should belong to B, the impossible conclusion 
will disappear if B is eliminated. Similarly when the syllogisms 
are negative. 

It is clear then that when the impossibility is not related to the 
original terms, the false conclusion does not result on account 
of the assumption. Or perhaps even so it may sometimes be 
independent. For if it were laid down that A belongs not to B but 
to K, and that K belongs to C and C to D, the impossible 
conclusion would still stand. Similarly if one takes the terms in 
an ascending series. Consequently since the impossibility 
results whether the first assumption is suppressed or not, it 
would appear to be independent of that assumption. Or perhaps 
we ought not to understand the statement that the false 
conclusion results independently of the assumption, in the 
sense that if something else were supposed the impossibility 
would result; but rather we mean that when the first 
assumption is eliminated, the same impossibility results 
through the remaining premisses; since it is not perhaps absurd 
that the same false result should follow from several 



204 



hypotheses, e.g. that parallels meet, both on the assumption 
that the interior angle is greater than the exterior and on the 
assumption that a triangle contains more than two right angles. 



18 

A false argument depends on the first false statement in it. 
Every syllogism is made out of two or more premisses. If then 
the false conclusion is drawn from two premisses, one or both 
of them must be false: for (as we proved) a false syllogism 
cannot be drawn from two premisses. But if the premisses are 
more than two, e.g. if C is established through A and B, and 
these through D, E, F, and G, one of these higher propositions 
must be false, and on this the argument depends: for A and B 
are inferred by means of D, E, F, and G. Therefore the conclusion 
and the error results from one of them. 



19 

In order to avoid having a syllogism drawn against us we must 
take care, whenever an opponent asks us to admit the reason 
without the conclusions, not to grant him the same term twice 
over in his premisses, since we know that a syllogism cannot be 
drawn without a middle term, and that term which is stated 
more than once is the middle. How we ought to watch the 
middle in reference to each conclusion, is evident from our 
knowing what kind of thesis is proved in each figure. This will 
not escape us since we know how we are maintaining the 
argument. 



205 



That which we urge men to beware of in their admissions, they 
ought in attack to try to conceal. This will be possible first, if, 
instead of drawing the conclusions of preliminary syllogisms, 
they take the necessary premisses and leave the conclusions in 
the dark; secondly if instead of inviting assent to propositions 
which are closely connected they take as far as possible those 
that are not connected by middle terms. For example suppose 
that A is to be inferred to be true of F, B, C, D, and E being middle 
terms. One ought then to ask whether A belongs to B, and next 
whether D belongs to E, instead of asking whether B belongs to 
C; after that he may ask whether B belongs to C, and so on. If 
the syllogism is drawn through one middle term, he ought to 
begin with that: in this way he will most likely deceive his 
opponent. 



20 

Since we know when a syllogism can be formed and how its 
terms must be related, it is clear when refutation will be 
possible and when impossible. A refutation is possible whether 
everything is conceded, or the answers alternate (one, I mean, 
being affirmative, the other negative). For as has been shown a 
syllogism is possible whether the terms are related in 
affirmative propositions or one proposition is affirmative, the 
other negative: consequently, if what is laid down is contrary to 
the conclusion, a refutation must take place: for a refutation is a 
syllogism which establishes the contradictory. But if nothing is 
conceded, a refutation is impossible: for no syllogism is possible 
(as we saw) when all the terms are negative: therefore no 
refutation is possible. For if a refutation were possible, a 
syllogism must be possible; although if a syllogism is possible it 
does not follow that a refutation is possible. Similarly refutation 



206 



is not possible if nothing is conceded universally: since the 
fields of refutation and syllogism are defined in the same way. 



21 

It sometimes happens that just as we are deceived in the 
arrangement of the terms, so error may arise in our thought 
about them, e.g. if it is possible that the same predicate should 
belong to more than one subject immediately, but although 
knowing the one, a man may forget the other and think the 
opposite true. Suppose that A belongs to B and to C in virtue of 
their nature, and that B and C belong to all D in the same way. If 
then a man thinks that A belongs to all B, and B to D, but A to no 

C, and C to all D, he will both know and not know the same 
thing in respect of the same thing. Again if a man were to make 
a mistake about the members of a single series; e.g. suppose A 
belongs to B, B to C, and C to D, but some one thinks that A 
belongs to all B, but to no C: he will both know that A belongs to 

D, and think that it does not. Does he then maintain after this 
simply that what he knows, he does not think? For he knows in 
a way that A belongs to C through B, since the part is included 
in the whole; so that what he knows in a way, this he maintains 
he does not think at all: but that is impossible. 

In the former case, where the middle term does not belong to 
the same series, it is not possible to think both the premisses 
with reference to each of the two middle terms: e.g. that A 
belongs to all B, but to no C, and both B and C belong to all D. 
For it turns out that the first premiss of the one syllogism is 
either wholly or partially contrary to the first premiss of the 
other. For if he thinks that A belongs to everything to which B 
belongs, and he knows that B belongs to D, then he knows that 



207 



A belongs to D. Consequently if again he thinks that A belongs 
to nothing to which C belongs, he thinks that A does not belong 
to some of that to which B belongs; but if he thinks that A 
belongs to everything to which B belongs, and again thinks that 
A does not belong to some of that to which B belongs, these 
beliefs are wholly or partially contrary. In this way then it is not 
possible to think; but nothing prevents a man thinking one 
premiss of each syllogism of both premisses of one of the two 
syllogisms: e.g. A belongs to all B, and B to D, and again A 
belongs to no C. An error of this kind is similar to the error into 
which we fall concerning particulars: e.g. if A belongs to all B, 
and B to all C, A will belong to all C. If then a man knows that A 
belongs to everything to which B belongs, he knows that A 
belongs to C. But nothing prevents his being ignorant that C 
exists; e.g. let A stand for two right angles, B for triangle, C for a 
particular diagram of a triangle. A man might think that C did 
not exist, though he knew that every triangle contains two right 
angles; consequently he will know and not know the same 
thing at the same time. For the expression 'to know that every 
triangle has its angles equal to two right angles' is ambiguous, 
meaning to have the knowledge either of the universal or of the 
particulars. Thus then he knows that C contains two right 
angles with a knowledge of the universal, but not with a 
knowledge of the particulars; consequently his knowledge will 
not be contrary to his ignorance. The argument in the Meno that 
learning is recollection may be criticized in a similar way. For it 
never happens that a man starts with a foreknowledge of the 
particular, but along with the process of being led to see the 
general principle he receives a knowledge of the particulars, by 
an act (as it were) of recognition. For we know some things 
directly; e.g. that the angles are equal to two right angles, if we 
know that the figure is a triangle. Similarly in all other cases. 

By a knowledge of the universal then we see the particulars, but 
we do not know them by the kind of knowledge which is proper 



208 



to them; consequently it is possible that we may make mistakes 
about them, but not that we should have the knowledge and 
error that are contrary to one another: rather we have the 
knowledge of the universal but make a mistake in 
apprehending the particular. Similarly in the cases stated above. 
The error in respect of the middle term is not contrary to the 
knowledge obtained through the syllogism, nor is the thought 
in respect of one middle term contrary to that in respect of the 
other. Nothing prevents a man who knows both that A belongs 
to the whole of B, and that B again belongs to C, thinking that A 
does not belong to C, e.g. knowing that every mule is sterile and 
that this is a mule, and thinking that this animal is with foal: for 
he does not know that A belongs to C, unless he considers the 
two propositions together. So it is evident that if he knows the 
one and does not know the other, he will fall into error. And this 
is the relation of knowledge of the universal to knowledge of 
the particular. For we know no sensible thing, once it has 
passed beyond the range of our senses, even if we happen to 
have perceived it, except by means of the universal and the 
possession of the knowledge which is proper to the particular, 
but without the actual exercise of that knowledge. For to know 
is used in three senses: it may mean either to have knowledge 
of the universal or to have knowledge proper to the matter in 
hand or to exercise such knowledge: consequently three kinds 
of error also are possible. Nothing then prevents a man both 
knowing and being mistaken about the same thing, provided 
that his knowledge and his error are not contrary. And this 
happens also to the man whose knowledge is limited to each of 
the premisses and who has not previously considered the 
particular question. For when he thinks that the mule is with 
foal he has not the knowledge in the sense of its actual exercise, 
nor on the other hand has his thought caused an error contrary 
to his knowledge: for the error contrary to the knowledge of the 
universal would be a syllogism. 



209 



But he who thinks the essence of good is the essence of bad will 
think the same thing to be the essence of good and the essence 
of bad. Let A stand for the essence of good and B for the essence 
of bad, and again C for the essence of good. Since then he thinks 
B and C identical, he will think that G is B, and similarly that B is 
A, consequently that C is A. For just as we saw that if B is true of 
all of which C is true, and A is true of all of which B is true, A is 
true of C, similarly with the word 'think'. Similarly also with the 
word 'is'; for we saw that if C is the same as B, and B as A, C is 
the same as A. Similarly therefore with 'opine'. Perhaps then 
this is necessary if a man will grant the first point. But 
presumably that is false, that any one could suppose the 
essence of good to be the essence of bad, save incidentally. For it 
is possible to think this in many different ways. But we must 
consider this matter better. 



22 

Whenever the extremes are convertible it is necessary that the 
middle should be convertible with both. For if A belongs to C 
through B, then if A and C are convertible and C belongs 
everything to which A belongs, B is convertible with A, and B 
belongs to everything to which A belongs, through C as middle, 
and C is convertible with B through A as middle. Similarly if the 
conclusion is negative, e.g. if B belongs to C, but A does not 
belong to B, neither will A belong to C. If then B is convertible 
with A, C will be convertible with A. Suppose B does not belong 
to A; neither then will C: for ex hypothesi B belonged to all C. 
And if C is convertible with B, B is convertible also with A, for C 
is said of that of all of which B is said. And if C is convertible in 
relation to A and to B, B also is convertible in relation to A. For C 
belongs to that to which B belongs: but C does not belong to 



210 



that to which A belongs. And this alone starts from the 
conclusion; the preceding moods do not do so as in the 
affirmative syllogism. Again if A and B are convertible, and 
similarly C and D, and if A or C must belong to anything 
whatever, then B and D will be such that one or other belongs to 
anything whatever. For since B belongs to that to which A 
belongs, and D belongs to that to which C belongs, and since A 
or C belongs to everything, but not together, it is clear that B or 
D belongs to everything, but not together. For example if that 
which is uncreated is incorruptible and that which is 
incorruptible is uncreated, it is necessary that what is created 
should be corruptible and what is corruptible should have been 
created. For two syllogisms have been put together. Again if A or 
B belongs to everything and if C or D belongs to everything, but 
they cannot belong together, then when A and C are convertible 
B and D are convertible. For if B does not belong to something to 
which D belongs, it is clear that A belongs to it. But if A then C: 
for they are convertible. Therefore C and D belong together. But 
this is impossible. When A belongs to the whole of B and to C 
and is affirmed of nothing else, and B also belongs to all C, it is 
necessary that A and B should be convertible: for since A is said 
of B and C only, and B is affirmed both of itself and of C, it is 
clear that B will be said of everything of which A is said, except 
A itself. Again when A and B belong to the whole of C, and C is 
convertible with B, it is necessary that A should belong to all B: 
for since A belongs to all C, and C to B by conversion, A will 
belong to all B. 

When, of two opposites A and B, A is preferable to B, and 
similarly D is preferable to C, then if A and C together are 
preferable to B and D together, A must be preferable to D. For A 
is an object of desire to the same extent as B is an object of 
aversion, since they are opposites: and C is similarly related to 
D, since they also are opposites. If then A is an object of desire 
to the same extent as D, B is an object of aversion to the same 



211 



extent as C (since each is to the same extent as each - the one 
an object of aversion, the other an object of desire). Therefore 
both A and C together, and B and D together, will be equally 
objects of desire or aversion. But since A and C are preferable to 
B and D, A cannot be equally desirable with D; for then B along 
with D would be equally desirable with A along with C. But if D 
is preferable to A, then B must be less an object of aversion than 
C: for the less is opposed to the less. But the greater good and 
lesser evil are preferable to the lesser good and greater evil: the 
whole BD then is preferable to the whole AC. But ex hypothesi 
this is not so. A then is preferable to D, and C consequently is 
less an object of aversion than B. If then every lover in virtue of 
his love would prefer A, viz. that the beloved should be such as 
to grant a favour, and yet should not grant it (for which C 
stands), to the beloved's granting the favour (represented by D) 
without being such as to grant it (represented by B), it is clear 
that A (being of such a nature) is preferable to granting the 
favour. To receive affection then is preferable in love to sexual 
intercourse. Love then is more dependent on friendship than on 
intercourse. And if it is most dependent on receiving affection, 
then this is its end. Intercourse then either is not an end at all 
or is an end relative to the further end, the receiving of 
affection. And indeed the same is true of the other desires and 
arts. 



23 

It is clear then how the terms are related in conversion, and in 
respect of being in a higher degree objects of aversion or of 
desire. We must now state that not only dialectical and 
demonstrative syllogisms are formed by means of the aforesaid 
figures, but also rhetorical syllogisms and in general any form of 



212 



persuasion, however it may be presented. For every belief comes 
either through syllogism or from induction. 

Now induction, or rather the syllogism which springs out of 
induction, consists in establishing syllogistically a relation 
between one extreme and the middle by means of the other 
extreme, e.g. if B is the middle term between A and C, it consists 
in proving through C that A belongs to B. For this is the manner 
in which we make inductions. For example let A stand for long- 
lived, B for bileless, and C for the particular long-lived animals, 
e.g. man, horse, mule. A then belongs to the whole of C: for 
whatever is bileless is long-lived. But B also ('not possessing 
bile') belongs to all C. If then C is convertible with B, and the 
middle term is not wider in extension, it is necessary that A 
should belong to B. For it has already been proved that if two 
things belong to the same thing, and the extreme is convertible 
with one of them, then the other predicate will belong to the 
predicate that is converted. But we must apprehend C as made 
up of all the particulars. For induction proceeds through an 
enumeration of all the cases. 

Such is the syllogism which establishes the first and immediate 
premiss: for where there is a middle term the syllogism 
proceeds through the middle term; when there is no middle 
term, through induction. And in a way induction is opposed to 
syllogism: for the latter proves the major term to belong to the 
third term by means of the middle, the former proves the major 
to belong to the middle by means of the third. In the order of 
nature, syllogism through the middle term is prior and better 
known, but syllogism through induction is clearer to us. 



213 



24 

We have an 'example' when the major term is proved to belong 
to the middle by means of a term which resembles the third. It 
ought to be known both that the middle belongs to the third 
term, and that the first belongs to that which resembles the 
third. For example let A be evil, B making war against 
neighbours, C Athenians against Thebans, D Thebans against 
Phocians. If then we wish to prove that to fight with the 
Thebans is an evil, we must assume that to fight against 
neighbours is an evil. Evidence of this is obtained from similar 
cases, e.g. that the war against the Phocians was an evil to the 
Thebans. Since then to fight against neighbours is an evil, and 
to fight against the Thebans is to fight against neighbours, it is 
clear that to fight against the Thebans is an evil. Now it is clear 
that B belongs to C and to D (for both are cases of making war 
upon one's neighbours) and that A belongs to D (for the war 
against the Phocians did not turn out well for the Thebans): but 
that A belongs to B will be proved through D. Similarly if the 
belief in the relation of the middle term to the extreme should 
be produced by several similar cases. Clearly then to argue by 
example is neither like reasoning from part to whole, nor like 
reasoning from whole to part, but rather reasoning from part to 
part, when both particulars are subordinate to the same term, 
and one of them is known. It differs from induction, because 
induction starting from all the particular cases proves (as we 
saw) that the major term belongs to the middle, and does not 
apply the syllogistic conclusion to the minor term, whereas 
argument by example does make this application and does not 
draw its proof from all the particular cases. 



214 



25 

By reduction we mean an argument in which the first term 
clearly belongs to the middle, but the relation of the middle to 
the last term is uncertain though equally or more probable than 
the conclusion; or again an argument in which the terms 
intermediate between the last term and the middle are few. For 
in any of these cases it turns out that we approach more nearly 
to knowledge. For example let A stand for what can be taught, B 
for knowledge, C for justice. Now it is clear that knowledge can 
be taught: but it is uncertain whether virtue is knowledge. If 
now the statement BC is equally or more probable than AC, we 
have a reduction: for we are nearer to knowledge, since we have 
taken a new term, being so far without knowledge that A 
belongs to C. Or again suppose that the terms intermediate 
between B and C are few: for thus too we are nearer knowledge. 
For example let D stand for squaring, E for rectilinear figure, F 
for circle. If there were only one term intermediate between E 
and F (viz. that the circle is made equal to a rectilinear figure by 
the help of lunules), we should be near to knowledge. But when 
BC is not more probable than AC, and the intermediate terms 
are not few, I do not call this reduction: nor again when the 
statement BC is immediate: for such a statement is knowledge. 



26 

An objection is a premiss contrary to a premiss. It differs from a 
premiss, because it may be particular, but a premiss either 
cannot be particular at all or not in universal syllogisms. An 
objection is brought in two ways and through two figures; in 
two ways because every objection is either universal or 
particular, by two figures because objections are brought in 



215 



opposition to the premiss, and opposites can be proved only in 
the first and third figures. If a man maintains a universal 
affirmative, we reply with a universal or a particular negative; 
the former is proved from the first figure, the latter from the 
third. For example let stand for there being a single science, B 
for contraries. If a man premises that contraries are subjects of 
a single science, the objection may be either that opposites are 
never subjects of a single science, and contraries are opposites, 
so that we get the first figure, or that the knowable and the 
unknowable are not subjects of a single science: this proof is in 
the third figure: for it is true of C (the knowable and the 
unknowable) that they are contraries, and it is false that they 
are the subjects of a single science. 

Similarly if the premiss objected to is negative. For if a man 
maintains that contraries are not subjects of a single science, 
we reply either that all opposites or that certain contraries, e.g. 
what is healthy and what is sickly, are subjects of the same 
science: the former argument issues from the first, the latter 
from the third figure. 

In general if a man urges a universal objection he must frame 
his contradiction with reference to the universal of the terms 
taken by his opponent, e.g. if a man maintains that contraries 
are not subjects of the same science, his opponent must reply 
that there is a single science of all opposites. Thus we must 
have the first figure: for the term which embraces the original 
subject becomes the middle term. 

If the objection is particular, the objector must frame his 
contradiction with reference to a term relatively to which the 
subject of his opponent's premiss is universal, e.g. he will point 
out that the knowable and the unknowable are not subjects of 
the same science: 'contraries' is universal relatively to these. 
And we have the third figure: for the particular term assumed is 



216 



middle, e.g. the knowable and the unknowable. Premisses from 
which it is possible to draw the contrary conclusion are what we 
start from when we try to make objections. Consequently we 
bring objections in these figures only: for in them only are 
opposite syllogisms possible, since the second figure cannot 
produce an affirmative conclusion. 

Besides, an objection in the middle figure would require a fuller 
argument, e.g. if it should not be granted that A belongs to B, 
because C does not follow B. This can be made clear only by 
other premisses. But an objection ought not to turn off into 
other things, but have its new premiss quite clear immediately. 
For this reason also this is the only figure from which proof by 
signs cannot be obtained. 

We must consider later the other kinds of objection, namely the 
objection from contraries, from similars, and from common 
opinion, and inquire whether a particular objection cannot be 
elicited from the first figure or a negative objection from the 
second. 



27 

A probability and a sign are not identical, but a probability is a 
generally approved proposition: what men know to happen or 
not to happen, to be or not to be, for the most part thus and 
thus, is a probability, e.g. 'the envious hate', 'the beloved show 
affection'. A sign means a demonstrative proposition necessary 
or generally approved: for anything such that when it is another 
thing is, or when it has come into being the other has come into 
being before or after, is a sign of the other's being or having 
come into being. Now an enthymeme is a syllogism starting 
from probabilities or signs, and a sign may be taken in three 



217 



ways, corresponding to the position of the middle term in the 
figures. For it may be taken as in the first figure or the second or 
the third. For example the proof that a woman is with child 
because she has milk is in the first figure: for to have milk is the 
middle term. Let A represent to be with child, B to have milk, C 
woman. The proof that wise men are good, since Pittacus is 
good, comes through the last figure. Let A stand for good, B for 
wise men, C for Pittacus. It is true then to affirm both A and B of 
C: only men do not say the latter, because they know it, though 
they state the former. The proof that a woman is with child 
because she is pale is meant to come through the middle figure: 
for since paleness follows women with child and is a 
concomitant of this woman, people suppose it has been proved 
that she is with child. Let A stand for paleness, B for being with 
child, C for woman. Now if the one proposition is stated, we 
have only a sign, but if the other is stated as well, a syllogism, 
e.g. 'Pittacus is generous, since ambitious men are generous and 
Pittacus is ambitious.' Or again 'Wise men are good, since 
Pittacus is not only good but wise.' In this way then syllogisms 
are formed, only that which proceeds through the first figure is 
irrefutable if it is true (for it is universal), that which proceeds 
through the last figure is refutable even if the conclusion is true, 
since the syllogism is not universal nor correlative to the matter 
in question: for though Pittacus is good, it is not therefore 
necessary that all other wise men should be good. But the 
syllogism which proceeds through the middle figure is always 
refutable in any case: for a syllogism can never be formed when 
the terms are related in this way: for though a woman with 
child is pale, and this woman also is pale, it is not necessary 
that she should be with child. Truth then may be found in signs 
whatever their kind, but they have the differences we have 
stated. 

We must either divide signs in the way stated, and among them 
designate the middle term as the index (for people call that the 



218 



index which makes us know, and the middle term above all has 
this character), or else we must call the arguments derived from 
the extremes signs, that derived from the middle term the 
index: for that which is proved through the first figure is most 
generally accepted and most true. 

It is possible to infer character from features, if it is granted that 
the body and the soul are changed together by the natural 
affections: I say 'natural', for though perhaps by learning music 
a man has made some change in his soul, this is not one of 
those affections which are natural to us; rather I refer to 
passions and desires when I speak of natural emotions. If then 
this were granted and also that for each change there is a 
corresponding sign, and we could state the affection and sign 
proper to each kind of animal, we shall be able to infer 
character from features. For if there is an affection which 
belongs properly to an individual kind, e.g. courage to lions, it is 
necessary that there should be a sign of it: for ex hypothesi 
body and soul are affected together. Suppose this sign is the 
possession of large extremities: this may belong to other kinds 
also though not universally. For the sign is proper in the sense 
stated, because the affection is proper to the whole kind, 
though not proper to it alone, according to our usual manner of 
speaking. The same thing then will be found in another kind, 
and man may be brave, and some other kinds of animal as well. 
They will then have the sign: for ex hypothesi there is one sign 
corresponding to each affection. If then this is so, and we can 
collect signs of this sort in these animals which have only one 
affection proper to them - but each affection has its sign, since 
it is necessary that it should have a single sign - we shall then 
be able to infer character from features. But if the kind as a 
whole has two properties, e.g. if the lion is both brave and 
generous, how shall we know which of the signs which are its 
proper concomitants is the sign of a particular affection? 
Perhaps if both belong to some other kind though not to the 



219 



whole of it, and if, in those kinds in which each is found though 
not in the whole of their members, some members possess one 
of the affections and not the other: e.g. if a man is brave but not 
generous, but possesses, of the two signs, large extremities, it is 
clear that this is the sign of courage in the lion also. To judge 
character from features, then, is possible in the first figure if the 
middle term is convertible with the first extreme, but is wider 
than the third term and not convertible with it: e.g. let A stand 
for courage, B for large extremities, and C for lion. B then 
belongs to everything to which C belongs, but also to others. But 
A belongs to everything to which B belongs, and to nothing 
besides, but is convertible with B: otherwise, there would not be 
a single sign correlative with each affection. 



220 



Aristotle - Posterior Analytics 
[Translated by G. R. G. Mure] 



Book I 



All instruction given or received by way of argument proceeds 
from pre-existent knowledge. This becomes evident upon a 
survey of all the species of such instruction. The mathematical 
sciences and all other speculative disciplines are acquired in 
this way, and so are the two forms of dialectical reasoning, 
syllogistic and inductive; for each of these latter make use of 
old knowledge to impart new, the syllogism assuming an 
audience that accepts its premisses, induction exhibiting the 
universal as implicit in the clearly known particular. Again, the 
persuasion exerted by rhetorical arguments is in principle the 
same, since they use either example, a kind of induction, or 
enthymeme, a form of syllogism. 

The pre-existent knowledge required is of two kinds. In some 
cases admission of the fact must be assumed, in others 
comprehension of the meaning of the term used, and 
sometimes both assumptions are essential. Thus, we assume 
that every predicate can be either truly affirmed or truly denied 
of any subject, and that 'triangle' means so and so; as regards 
'unit' we have to make the double assumption of the meaning 
of the word and the existence of the thing. The reason is that 
these several objects are not equally obvious to us. Recognition 
of a truth may in some cases contain as factors both previous 
knowledge and also knowledge acquired simultaneously with 



221 



that recognition - knowledge, this latter, of the particulars 
actually falling under the universal and therein already virtually 
known. For example, the student knew beforehand that the 
angles of every triangle are equal to two right angles; but it was 
only at the actual moment at which he was being led on to 
recognize this as true in the instance before him that he came 
to know 'this figure inscribed in the semicircle' to be a triangle. 
For some things (viz. the singulars finally reached which are not 
predicable of anything else as subject) are only learnt in this 
way, i.e. there is here no recognition through a middle of a 
minor term as subject to a major. Before he was led on to 
recognition or before he actually drew a conclusion, we should 
perhaps say that in a manner he knew, in a manner not. 

If he did not in an unqualified sense of the term know the 
existence of this triangle, how could he know without 
qualification that its angles were equal to two right angles? No: 
clearly he knows not without qualification but only in the sense 
that he knows universally. If this distinction is not drawn, we 
are faced with the dilemma in the Meno: either a man will learn 
nothing or what he already knows; for we cannot accept the 
solution which some people offer. A man is asked, 'Do you, or do 
you not, know that every pair is even?' He says he does know it. 
The questioner then produces a particular pair, of the existence, 
and so a fortiori of the evenness, of which he was unaware. The 
solution which some people offer is to assert that they do not 
know that every pair is even, but only that everything which 
they know to be a pair is even: yet what they know to be even is 
that of which they have demonstrated evenness, i.e. what they 
made the subject of their premiss, viz. not merely every triangle 
or number which they know to be such, but any and every 
number or triangle without reservation. For no premiss is ever 
couched in the form 'every number which you know to be such', 
or 'every rectilinear figure which you know to be such': the 
predicate is always construed as applicable to any and every 



222 



instance of the thing. On the other hand, I imagine there is 
nothing to prevent a man in one sense knowing what he is 
learning, in another not knowing it. The strange thing would be, 
not if in some sense he knew what he was learning, but if he 
were to know it in that precise sense and manner in which he 
was learning it. 



We suppose ourselves to possess unqualified scientific 
knowledge of a thing, as opposed to knowing it in the accidental 
way in which the sophist knows, when we think that we know 
the cause on which the fact depends, as the cause of that fact 
and of no other, and, further, that the fact could not be other 
than it is. Now that scientific knowing is something of this sort 
is evident - witness both those who falsely claim it and those 
who actually possess it, since the former merely imagine 
themselves to be, while the latter are also actually, in the 
condition described. Consequently the proper object of 
unqualified scientific knowledge is something which cannot be 
other than it is. 

There may be another manner of knowing as well - that will be 
discussed later. What I now assert is that at all events we do 
know by demonstration. By demonstration I mean a syllogism 
productive of scientific knowledge, a syllogism, that is, the grasp 
of which is eo ipso such knowledge. Assuming then that my 
thesis as to the nature of scientific knowing is correct, the 
premisses of demonstrated knowledge must be true, primary, 
immediate, better known than and prior to the conclusion, 
which is further related to them as effect to cause. Unless these 
conditions are satisfied, the basic truths will not be 



223 



'appropriate' to the conclusion. Syllogism there may indeed be 
without these conditions, but such syllogism, not being 
productive of scientific knowledge, will not be demonstration. 
The premisses must be true: for that which is non-existent 
cannot be known - we cannot know, e.g. that the diagonal of a 
square is commensurate with its side. The premisses must be 
primary and indemonstrable; otherwise they will require 
demonstration in order to be known, since to have knowledge, if 
it be not accidental knowledge, of things which are 
demonstrable, means precisely to have a demonstration of 
them. The premisses must be the causes of the conclusion, 
better known than it, and prior to it; its causes, since we possess 
scientific knowledge of a thing only when we know its cause; 
prior, in order to be causes; antecedently known, this 
antecedent knowledge being not our mere understanding of the 
meaning, but knowledge of the fact as well. Now 'prior' and 
'better known' are ambiguous terms, for there is a difference 
between what is prior and better known in the order of being 
and what is prior and better known to man. I mean that objects 
nearer to sense are prior and better known to man; objects 
without qualification prior and better known are those further 
from sense. Now the most universal causes are furthest from 
sense and particular causes are nearest to sense, and they are 
thus exactly opposed to one another. In saying that the 
premisses of demonstrated knowledge must be primary, I mean 
that they must be the 'appropriate' basic truths, for I identify 
primary premiss and basic truth. A 'basic truth' in a 
demonstration is an immediate proposition. An immediate 
proposition is one which has no other proposition prior to it. A 
proposition is either part of an enunciation, i.e. it predicates a 
single attribute of a single subject. If a proposition is dialectical, 
it assumes either part indifferently; if it is demonstrative, it lays 
down one part to the definite exclusion of the other because 
that part is true. The term 'enunciation' denotes either part of a 



224 



contradiction indifferently. A contradiction is an opposition 
which of its own nature excludes a middle. The part of a 
contradiction which conjoins a predicate with a subject is an 
affirmation; the part disjoining them is a negation. I call an 
immediate basic truth of syllogism a 'thesis' when, though it is 
not susceptible of proof by the teacher, yet ignorance of it does 
not constitute a total bar to progress on the part of the pupil: 
one which the pupil must know if he is to learn anything 
whatever is an axiom. I call it an axiom because there are such 
truths and we give them the name of axioms par excellence. If a 
thesis assumes one part or the other of an enunciation, i.e. 
asserts either the existence or the non-existence of a subject, it 
is a hypothesis; if it does not so assert, it is a definition. 
Definition is a 'thesis' or a 'laying something down', since the 
arithmetician lays it down that to be a unit is to be 
quantitatively indivisible; but it is not a hypothesis, for to define 
what a unit is is not the same as to affirm its existence. 

Now since the required ground of our knowledge - i.e. of our 
conviction - of a fact is the possession of such a syllogism as we 
call demonstration, and the ground of the syllogism is the facts 
constituting its premisses, we must not only know the primary 
premisses - some if not all of them - beforehand, but know 
them better than the conclusion: for the cause of an attribute's 
inherence in a subject always itself inheres in the subject more 
firmly than that attribute; e.g. the cause of our loving anything 
is dearer to us than the object of our love. So since the primary 
premisses are the cause of our knowledge - i.e. of our conviction 
- it follows that we know them better - that is, are more 
convinced of them - than their consequences, precisely because 
of our knowledge of the latter is the effect of our knowledge of 
the premisses. Now a man cannot believe in anything more 
than in the things he knows, unless he has either actual 
knowledge of it or something better than actual knowledge. But 
we are faced with this paradox if a student whose belief rests 



225 



on demonstration has not prior knowledge; a man must believe 
in some, if not in all, of the basic truths more than in the 
conclusion. Moreover, if a man sets out to acquire the scientific 
knowledge that comes through demonstration, he must not 
only have a better knowledge of the basic truths and a firmer 
conviction of them than of the connexion which is being 
demonstrated: more than this, nothing must be more certain or 
better known to him than these basic truths in their character 
as contradicting the fundamental premisses which lead to the 
opposed and erroneous conclusion. For indeed the conviction of 
pure science must be unshakable. 



Some hold that, owing to the necessity of knowing the primary 
premisses, there is no scientific knowledge. Others think there 
is, but that all truths are demonstrable. Neither doctrine is 
either true or a necessary deduction from the premisses. The 
first school, assuming that there is no way of knowing other 
than by demonstration, maintain that an infinite regress is 
involved, on the ground that if behind the prior stands no 
primary, we could not know the posterior through the prior 
(wherein they are right, for one cannot traverse an infinite 
series): if on the other hand - they say - the series terminates 
and there are primary premisses, yet these are unknowable 
because incapable of demonstration, which according to them 
is the only form of knowledge. And since thus one cannot know 
the primary premisses, knowledge of the conclusions which 
follow from them is not pure scientific knowledge nor properly 
knowing at all, but rests on the mere supposition that the 
premisses are true. The other party agree with them as regards 
knowing, holding that it is only possible by demonstration, but 



226 



they see no difficulty in holding that all truths are 
demonstrated, on the ground that demonstration may be 
circular and reciprocal. 

Our own doctrine is that not all knowledge is demonstrative: on 
the contrary, knowledge of the immediate premisses is 
independent of demonstration. (The necessity of this is obvious; 
for since we must know the prior premisses from which the 
demonstration is drawn, and since the regress must end in 
immediate truths, those truths must be indemonstrable.) Such, 
then, is our doctrine, and in addition we maintain that besides 
scientific knowledge there is its originative source which 
enables us to recognize the definitions. 

Now demonstration must be based on premisses prior to and 
better known than the conclusion; and the same things cannot 
simultaneously be both prior and posterior to one another: so 
circular demonstration is clearly not possible in the unqualified 
sense of 'demonstration', but only possible if 'demonstration' be 
extended to include that other method of argument which rests 
on a distinction between truths prior to us and truths without 
qualification prior, i.e. the method by which induction produces 
knowledge. But if we accept this extension of its meaning, our 
definition of unqualified knowledge will prove faulty; for there 
seem to be two kinds of it. Perhaps, however, the second form of 
demonstration, that which proceeds from truths better known 
to us, is not demonstration in the unqualified sense of the term. 

The advocates of circular demonstration are not only faced with 
the difficulty we have just stated: in addition their theory 
reduces to the mere statement that if a thing exists, then it does 
exist - an easy way of proving anything. That this is so can be 
clearly shown by taking three terms, for to constitute the circle 
it makes no difference whether many terms or few or even only 
two are taken. Thus by direct proof, if A is, B must be; if B is, C 



227 



must be; therefore if A is, C must be. Since then - by the circular 
proof - if A is, B must be, and if B is, A must be, A may be 
substituted for C above. Then 'if B is, A must be'='if B is, C must 
be', which above gave the conclusion 'if A is, C must be': but C 
and A have been identified. Consequently the upholders of 
circular demonstration are in the position of saying that if A is, 
A must be - a simple way of proving anything. Moreover, even 
such circular demonstration is impossible except in the case of 
attributes that imply one another, viz. 'peculiar' properties. 

Now, it has been shown that the positing of one thing - be it one 
term or one premiss - never involves a necessary consequent: 
two premisses constitute the first and smallest foundation for 
drawing a conclusion at all and therefore a fortiori for the 
demonstrative syllogism of science. If, then, A is implied in B 
and C, and B and C are reciprocally implied in one another and 
in A, it is possible, as has been shown in my writings on the 
syllogism, to prove all the assumptions on which the original 
conclusion rested, by circular demonstration in the first figure. 
But it has also been shown that in the other figures either no 
conclusion is possible, or at least none which proves both the 
original premisses. Propositions the terms of which are not 
convertible cannot be circularly demonstrated at all, and since 
convertible terms occur rarely in actual demonstrations, it is 
clearly frivolous and impossible to say that demonstration is 
reciprocal and that therefore everything can be demonstrated. 



Since the object of pure scientific knowledge cannot be other 
than it is, the truth obtained by demonstrative knowledge will 
be necessary. And since demonstrative knowledge is only 



228 



present when we have a demonstration, it follows that 
demonstration is an inference from necessary premisses. So we 
must consider what are the premisses of demonstration - i.e. 
what is their character: and as a preliminary, let us define what 
we mean by an attribute 'true in every instance of its subject', 
an 'essential' attribute, and a 'commensurate and universal' 
attribute. I call 'true in every instance' what is truly predicable 
of all instances - not of one to the exclusion of others - and at 
all times, not at this or that time only; e.g. if animal is truly 
predicable of every instance of man, then if it be true to say 'this 
is a man', 'this is an animal' is also true, and if the one be true 
now the other is true now. A corresponding account holds if 
point is in every instance predicable as contained in line. There 
is evidence for this in the fact that the objection we raise 
against a proposition put to us as true in every instance is either 
an instance in which, or an occasion on which, it is not true. 
Essential attributes are (1) such as belong to their subject as 
elements in its essential nature (e.g. line thus belongs to 
triangle, point to line; for the very being or 'substance' of 
triangle and line is composed of these elements, which are 
contained in the formulae defining triangle and line): (2) such 
that, while they belong to certain subjects, the subjects to which 
they belong are contained in the attribute's own defining 
formula. Thus straight and curved belong to line, odd and even, 
prime and compound, square and oblong, to number; and also 
the formula defining any one of these attributes contains its 
subject - e.g. line or number as the case may be. 

Extending this classification to all other attributes, I distinguish 
those that answer the above description as belonging 
essentially to their respective subjects; whereas attributes 
related in neither of these two ways to their subjects I call 
accidents or 'coincidents'; e.g. musical or white is a 'coincident' 
of animal. 



229 



Further (a) that is essential which is not predicated of a subject 
other than itself: e.g. 'the walking [thing]' walks and is white in 
virtue of being something else besides; whereas substance, in 
the sense of whatever signifies a 'this somewhat', is not what it 
is in virtue of being something else besides. Things, then, not 
predicated of a subject I call essential; things predicated of a 
subject I call accidental or 'coincidental'. 

In another sense again (b) a thing consequentially connected 
with anything is essential; one not so connected is 
'coincidental'. An example of the latter is 'While he was walking 
it lightened': the lightning was not due to his walking; it was, 
we should say, a coincidence. If, on the other hand, there is a 
consequential connexion, the predication is essential; e.g. if a 
beast dies when its throat is being cut, then its death is also 
essentially connected with the cutting, because the cutting was 
the cause of death, not death a 'coincident' of the cutting. 

So far then as concerns the sphere of connexions scientifically 
known in the unqualified sense of that term, all attributes 
which (within that sphere) are essential either in the sense that 
their subjects are contained in them, or in the sense that they 
are contained in their subjects, are necessary as well as 
consequentially connected with their subjects. For it is 
impossible for them not to inhere in their subjects either simply 
or in the qualified sense that one or other of a pair of opposites 
must inhere in the subject; e.g. in line must be either 
straightness or curvature, in number either oddness or 
evenness. For within a single identical genus the contrary of a 
given attribute is either its privative or its contradictory; e.g. 
within number what is not odd is even, inasmuch as within this 
sphere even is a necessary consequent of not-odd. So, since any 
given predicate must be either affirmed or denied of any 
subject, essential attributes must inhere in their subjects of 
necessity. 



230 



Thus, then, we have established the distinction between the 
attribute which is 'true in every instance' and the 'essential' 
attribute. 

I term 'commensurately universal' an attribute which belongs to 
every instance of its subject, and to every instance essentially 
and as such; from which it clearly follows that all 
commensurate universals inhere necessarily in their subjects. 
The essential attribute, and the attribute that belongs to its 
subject as such, are identical. E.g. point and straight belong to 
line essentially, for they belong to line as such; and triangle as 
such has two right angles, for it is essentially equal to two right 
angles. 

An attribute belongs commensurately and universally to a 
subject when it can be shown to belong to any random instance 
of that subject and when the subject is the first thing to which 
it can be shown to belong. Thus, e.g. (1) the equality of its angles 
to two right angles is not a commensurately universal attribute 
of figure. For though it is possible to show that a figure has its 
angles equal to two right angles, this attribute cannot be 
demonstrated of any figure selected at haphazard, nor in 
demonstrating does one take a figure at random - a square is a 
figure but its angles are not equal to two right angles. On the 
other hand, any isosceles triangle has its angles equal to two 
right angles, yet isosceles triangle is not the primary subject of 
this attribute but triangle is prior. So whatever can be shown to 
have its angles equal to two right angles, or to possess any other 
attribute, in any random instance of itself and primarily - that is 
the first subject to which the predicate in question belongs 
commensurately and universally, and the demonstration, in the 
essential sense, of any predicate is the proof of it as belonging 
to this first subject commensurately and universally: while the 
proof of it as belonging to the other subjects to which it 
attaches is demonstration only in a secondary and unessential 



231 



sense. Nor again (2) is equality to two right angles a 
commensurately universal attribute of isosceles; it is of wider 
application. 



We must not fail to observe that we often fall into error because 
our conclusion is not in fact primary and commensurately 
universal in the sense in which we think we prove it so. We 
make this mistake (1) when the subject is an individual or 
individuals above which there is no universal to be found: (2) 
when the subjects belong to different species and there is a 
higher universal, but it has no name: (3) when the subject which 
the demonstrator takes as a whole is really only a part of a 
larger whole; for then the demonstration will be true of the 
individual instances within the part and will hold in every 
instance of it, yet the demonstration will not be true of this 
subject primarily and commensurately and universally. When a 
demonstration is true of a subject primarily and 
commensurately and universally, that is to be taken to mean 
that it is true of a given subject primarily and as such. Case (3) 
may be thus exemplified. If a proof were given that 
perpendiculars to the same line are parallel, it might be 
supposed that lines thus perpendicular were the proper subject 
of the demonstration because being parallel is true of every 
instance of them. But it is not so, for the parallelism depends 
not on these angles being equal to one another because each is 
a right angle, but simply on their being equal to one another. An 
example of (1) would be as follows: if isosceles were the only 
triangle, it would be thought to have its angles equal to two 
right angles qua isosceles. An instance of (2) would be the law 
that proportionals alternate. Alternation used to be 



232 



demonstrated separately of numbers, lines, solids, and 
durations, though it could have been proved of them all by a 
single demonstration. Because there was no single name to 
denote that in which numbers, lengths, durations, and solids 
are identical, and because they differed specifically from one 
another, this property was proved of each of them separately. 
To-day, however, the proof is commensurately universal, for 
they do not possess this attribute qua lines or qua numbers, but 
qua manifesting this generic character which they are 
postulated as possessing universally. Hence, even if one prove of 
each kind of triangle that its angles are equal to two right 
angles, whether by means of the same or different proofs; still, 
as long as one treats separately equilateral, scalene, and 
isosceles, one does not yet know, except sophistically, that 
triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, nor does one 
yet know that triangle has this property commensurately and 
universally, even if there is no other species of triangle but 
these. For one does not know that triangle as such has this 
property, nor even that 'all' triangles have it - unless 'all' means 
'each taken singly': if 'all' means 'as a whole class', then, though 
there be none in which one does not recognize this property, 
one does not know it of 'all triangles'. 

When, then, does our knowledge fail of commensurate 
universality, and when it is unqualified knowledge? If triangle 
be identical in essence with equilateral, i.e. with each or all 
equilaterals, then clearly we have unqualified knowledge: if on 
the other hand it be not, and the attribute belongs to equilateral 
qua triangle; then our knowledge fails of commensurate 
universality. 'But', it will be asked, 'does this attribute belong to 
the subject of which it has been demonstrated qua triangle or 
qua isosceles? What is the point at which the subject, to which 
it belongs is primary? (i.e. to what subject can it be 
demonstrated as belonging commensurately and universally?)' 
Clearly this point is the first term in which it is found to inhere 



233 



as the elimination of inferior differentiae proceeds. Thus the 
angles of a brazen isosceles triangle are equal to two right 
angles: but eliminate brazen and isosceles and the attribute 
remains. 'But' - you may say - 'eliminate figure or limit, and the 
attribute vanishes.' True, but figure and limit are not the first 
differentiae whose elimination destroys the attribute. 'Then 
what is the first?' If it is triangle, it will be in virtue of triangle 
that the attribute belongs to all the other subjects of which it is 
predicable, and triangle is the subject to which it can be 
demonstrated as belonging commensurately and universally. 



Demonstrative knowledge must rest on necessary basic truths; 
for the object of scientific knowledge cannot be other than it is. 
Now attributes attaching essentially to their subjects attach 
necessarily to them: for essential attributes are either elements 
in the essential nature of their subjects, or contain their 
subjects as elements in their own essential nature. (The pairs of 
opposites which the latter class includes are necessary because 
one member or the other necessarily inheres.) It follows from 
this that premisses of the demonstrative syllogism must be 
connexions essential in the sense explained: for all attributes 
must inhere essentially or else be accidental, and accidental 
attributes are not necessary to their subjects. 

We must either state the case thus, or else premise that the 
conclusion of demonstration is necessary and that a 
demonstrated conclusion cannot be other than it is, and then 
infer that the conclusion must be developed from necessary 
premisses. For though you may reason from true premisses 
without demonstrating, yet if your premisses are necessary you 



234 



will assuredly demonstrate - in such necessity you have at once 
a distinctive character of demonstration. That demonstration 
proceeds from necessary premisses is also indicated by the fact 
that the objection we raise against a professed demonstration is 
that a premiss of it is not a necessary truth - whether we think 
it altogether devoid of necessity, or at any rate so far as our 
opponent's previous argument goes. This shows how naive it is 
to suppose one's basic truths rightly chosen if one starts with a 
proposition which is (1) popularly accepted and (2) true, such as 
the sophists' assumption that to know is the same as to possess 
knowledge. For (1) popular acceptance or rejection is no 
criterion of a basic truth, which can only be the primary law of 
the genus constituting the subject matter of the demonstration; 
and (2) not all truth is 'appropriate'. 

A further proof that the conclusion must be the development of 
necessary premisses is as follows. Where demonstration is 
possible, one who can give no account which includes the cause 
has no scientific knowledge. If, then, we suppose a syllogism in 
which, though A necessarily inheres in G, yet B, the middle term 
of the demonstration, is not necessarily connected with A and 
C, then the man who argues thus has no reasoned knowledge of 
the conclusion, since this conclusion does not owe its necessity 
to the middle term; for though the conclusion is necessary, the 
mediating link is a contingent fact. Or again, if a man is without 
knowledge now, though he still retains the steps of the 
argument, though there is no change in himself or in the fact 
and no lapse of memory on his part; then neither had he 
knowledge previously. But the mediating link, not being 
necessary, may have perished in the interval; and if so, though 
there be no change in him nor in the fact, and though he will 
still retain the steps of the argument, yet he has not knowledge, 
and therefore had not knowledge before. Even if the link has not 
actually perished but is liable to perish, this situation is possible 
and might occur. But such a condition cannot be knowledge. 



235 



When the conclusion is necessary, the middle through which it 
was proved may yet quite easily be non-necessary. You can in 
fact infer the necessary even from a non-necessary premiss, 
just as you can infer the true from the not true. On the other 
hand, when the middle is necessary the conclusion must be 
necessary; just as true premisses always give a true conclusion. 
Thus, if A is necessarily predicated of B and B of C, then A is 
necessarily predicated of C. But when the conclusion is 
nonnecessary the middle cannot be necessary either. Thus: let A 
be predicated non-necessarily of G but necessarily of B, and let B 
be a necessary predicate of C; then A too will be a necessary 
predicate of C, which by hypothesis it is not. 

To sum up, then: demonstrative knowledge must be knowledge 
of a necessary nexus, and therefore must clearly be obtained 
through a necessary middle term; otherwise its possessor will 
know neither the cause nor the fact that his conclusion is a 
necessary connexion. Either he will mistake the non-necessary 
for the necessary and believe the necessity of the conclusion 
without knowing it, or else he will not even believe it - in which 
case he will be equally ignorant, whether he actually infers the 
mere fact through middle terms or the reasoned fact and from 
immediate premisses. 

Of accidents that are not essential according to our definition of 
essential there is no demonstrative knowledge; for since an 
accident, in the sense in which I here speak of it, may also not 
inhere, it is impossible to prove its inherence as a necessary 
conclusion. A difficulty, however, might be raised as to why in 
dialectic, if the conclusion is not a necessary connexion, such 
and such determinate premisses should be proposed in order to 
deal with such and such determinate problems. Would not the 
result be the same if one asked any questions whatever and 
then merely stated one's conclusion? The solution is that 
determinate questions have to be put, not because the replies to 



236 



them affirm facts which necessitate facts affirmed by the 
conclusion, but because these answers are propositions which if 
the answerer affirm, he must affirm the conclusion and affirm 
it with truth if they are true. 

Since it is just those attributes within every genus which are 
essential and possessed by their respective subjects as such 
that are necessary it is clear that both the conclusions and the 
premisses of demonstrations which produce scientific 
knowledge are essential. For accidents are not necessary: and, 
further, since accidents are not necessary one does not 
necessarily have reasoned knowledge of a conclusion drawn 
from them (this is so even if the accidental premisses are 
invariable but not essential, as in proofs through signs; for 
though the conclusion be actually essential, one will not know 
it as essential nor know its reason); but to have reasoned 
knowledge of a conclusion is to know it through its cause. We 
may conclude that the middle must be consequentially 
connected with the minor, and the major with the middle. 



It follows that we cannot in demonstrating pass from one genus 
to another. We cannot, for instance, prove geometrical truths by 
arithmetic. For there are three elements in demonstration: (1) 
what is proved, the conclusion - an attribute inhering 
essentially in a genus; (2) the axioms, i.e. axioms which are 
premisses of demonstration; (3) the subject - genus whose 
attributes, i.e. essential properties, are revealed by the 
demonstration. The axioms which are premisses of 
demonstration may be identical in two or more sciences: but in 
the case of two different genera such as arithmetic and 



237 



geometry you cannot apply arithmetical demonstration to the 
properties of magnitudes unless the magnitudes in question are 
numbers. How in certain cases transference is possible I will 
explain later. 

Arithmetical demonstration and the other sciences likewise 
possess, each of them, their own genera; so that if the 
demonstration is to pass from one sphere to another, the genus 
must be either absolutely or to some extent the same. If this is 
not so, transference is clearly impossible, because the extreme 
and the middle terms must be drawn from the same genus: 
otherwise, as predicated, they will not be essential and will thus 
be accidents. That is why it cannot be proved by geometry that 
opposites fall under one science, nor even that the product of 
two cubes is a cube. Nor can the theorem of any one science be 
demonstrated by means of another science, unless these 
theorems are related as subordinate to superior (e.g. as optical 
theorems to geometry or harmonic theorems to arithmetic). 
Geometry again cannot prove of lines any property which they 
do not possess qua lines, i.e. in virtue of the fundamental truths 
of their peculiar genus: it cannot show, for example, that the 
straight line is the most beautiful of lines or the contrary of the 
circle; for these qualities do not belong to lines in virtue of their 
peculiar genus, but through some property which it shares with 
other genera. 



8 

It is also clear that if the premisses from which the syllogism 
proceeds are commensurately universal, the conclusion of such 
i.e. in the unqualified sense - must also be eternal. Therefore no 
attribute can be demonstrated nor known by strictly scientific 



238 



knowledge to inhere in perishable things. The proof can only be 
accidental, because the attribute's connexion with its perishable 
subject is not commensurately universal but temporary and 
special. If such a demonstration is made, one premiss must be 
perishable and not commensurately universal (perishable 
because only if it is perishable will the conclusion be perishable; 
not commensurately universal, because the predicate will be 
predicable of some instances of the subject and not of others); 
so that the conclusion can only be that a fact is true at the 
moment - not commensurately and universally. The same is 
true of definitions, since a definition is either a primary premiss 
or a conclusion of a demonstration, or else only differs from a 
demonstration in the order of its terms. Demonstration and 
science of merely frequent occurrences - e.g. of eclipse as 
happening to the moon - are, as such, clearly eternal: whereas 
so far as they are not eternal they are not fully commensurate. 
Other subjects too have properties attaching to them in the 
same way as eclipse attaches to the moon. 



It is clear that if the conclusion is to show an attribute inhering 
as such, nothing can be demonstrated except from its 
'appropriate' basic truths. Consequently a proof even from true, 
indemonstrable, and immediate premisses does not constitute 
knowledge. Such proofs are like Bryson's method of squaring 
the circle; for they operate by taking as their middle a common 
character - a character, therefore, which the subject may share 
with another - and consequently they apply equally to subjects 
different in kind. They therefore afford knowledge of an 
attribute only as inhering accidentally, not as belonging to its 



239 



subject as such: otherwise they would not have been applicable 
to another genus. 

Our knowledge of any attribute's connexion with a subject is 
accidental unless we know that connexion through the middle 
term in virtue of which it inheres, and as an inference from 
basic premisses essential and 'appropriate' to the subject - 
unless we know, e.g. the property of possessing angles equal to 
two right angles as belonging to that subject in which it inheres 
essentially, and as inferred from basic premisses essential and 
'appropriate' to that subject: so that if that middle term also 
belongs essentially to the minor, the middle must belong to the 
same kind as the major and minor terms. The only exceptions 
to this rule are such cases as theorems in harmonics which are 
demonstrable by arithmetic. Such theorems are proved by the 
same middle terms as arithmetical properties, but with a 
qualification - the fact falls under a separate science (for the 
subject genus is separate), but the reasoned fact concerns the 
superior science, to which the attributes essentially belong. 
Thus, even these apparent exceptions show that no attribute is 
strictly demonstrable except from its 'appropriate' basic truths, 
which, however, in the case of these sciences have the requisite 
identity of character. 

It is no less evident that the peculiar basic truths of each 
inhering attribute are indemonstrable; for basic truths from 
which they might be deduced would be basic truths of all that 
is, and the science to which they belonged would possess 
universal sovereignty. This is so because he knows better whose 
knowledge is deduced from higher causes, for his knowledge is 
from prior premisses when it derives from causes themselves 
uncaused: hence, if he knows better than others or best of all, 
his knowledge would be science in a higher or the highest 
degree. But, as things are, demonstration is not transferable to 
another genus, with such exceptions as we have mentioned of 



240 



the application of geometrical demonstrations to theorems in 
mechanics or optics, or of arithmetical demonstrations to those 
of harmonics. 

It is hard to be sure whether one knows or not; for it is hard to 
be sure whether one's knowledge is based on the basic truths 
appropriate to each attribute - the differentia of true knowledge. 
We think we have scientific knowledge if we have reasoned 
from true and primary premisses. But that is not so: the 
conclusion must be homogeneous with the basic facts of the 
science. 



10 

I call the basic truths of every genus those elements in it the 
existence of which cannot be proved. As regards both these 
primary truths and the attributes dependent on them the 
meaning of the name is assumed. The fact of their existence as 
regards the primary truths must be assumed; but it has to be 
proved of the remainder, the attributes. Thus we assume the 
meaning alike of unity, straight, and triangular; but while as 
regards unity and magnitude we assume also the fact of their 
existence, in the case of the remainder proof is required. 

Of the basic truths used in the demonstrative sciences some are 
peculiar to each science, and some are common, but common 
only in the sense of analogous, being of use only in so far as 
they fall within the genus constituting the province of the 
science in question. 

Peculiar truths are, e.g. the definitions of line and straight; 
common truths are such as 'take equals from equals and equals 
remain'. Only so much of these common truths is required as 



241 



falls within the genus in question: for a truth of this kind will 
have the same force even if not used generally but applied by 
the geometer only to magnitudes, or by the arithmetician only 
to numbers. Also peculiar to a science are the subjects the 
existence as well as the meaning of which it assumes, and the 
essential attributes of which it investigates, e.g. in arithmetic 
units, in geometry points and lines. Both the existence and the 
meaning of the subjects are assumed by these sciences; but of 
their essential attributes only the meaning is assumed. For 
example arithmetic assumes the meaning of odd and even, 
square and cube, geometry that of incommensurable, or of 
deflection or verging of lines, whereas the existence of these 
attributes is demonstrated by means of the axioms and from 
previous conclusions as premisses. Astronomy too proceeds in 
the same way. For indeed every demonstrative science has three 
elements: (1) that which it posits, the subject genus whose 
essential attributes it examines; (2) the so-called axioms, which 
are primary premisses of its demonstration; (3) the attributes, 
the meaning of which it assumes. Yet some sciences may very 
well pass over some of these elements; e.g. we might not 
expressly posit the existence of the genus if its existence were 
obvious (for instance, the existence of hot and cold is more 
evident than that of number); or we might omit to assume 
expressly the meaning of the attributes if it were well 
understood. In the way the meaning of axioms, such as 'Take 
equals from equals and equals remain', is well known and so 
not expressly assumed. Nevertheless in the nature of the case 
the essential elements of demonstration are three: the subject, 
the attributes, and the basic premisses. 

That which expresses necessary self-grounded fact, and which 
we must necessarily believe, is distinct both from the 
hypotheses of a science and from illegitimate postulate - I say 
'must believe', because all syllogism, and therefore a fortiori 
demonstration, is addressed not to the spoken word, but to the 



242 



discourse within the soul, and though we can always raise 
objections to the spoken word, to the inward discourse we 
cannot always object. That which is capable of proof but 
assumed by the teacher without proof is, if the pupil believes 
and accepts it, hypothesis, though only in a limited sense 
hypothesis - that is, relatively to the pupil; if the pupil has no 
opinion or a contrary opinion on the matter, the same 
assumption is an illegitimate postulate. Therein lies the 
distinction between hypothesis and illegitimate postulate: the 
latter is the contrary of the pupil's opinion, demonstrable, but 
assumed and used without demonstration. 

The definition - viz. those which are not expressed as 
statements that anything is or is not - are not hypotheses: but it 
is in the premisses of a science that its hypotheses are 
contained. Definitions require only to be understood, and this is 
not hypothesis - unless it be contended that the pupil's hearing 
is also an hypothesis required by the teacher. Hypotheses, on 
the contrary, postulate facts on the being of which depends the 
being of the fact inferred. Nor are the geometer's hypotheses 
false, as some have held, urging that one must not employ 
falsehood and that the geometer is uttering falsehood in stating 
that the line which he draws is a foot long or straight, when it is 
actually neither. The truth is that the geometer does not draw 
any conclusion from the being of the particular line of which he 
speaks, but from what his diagrams symbolize. A further 
distinction is that all hypotheses and illegitimate postulates are 
either universal or particular, whereas a definition is neither. 



243 



11 

So demonstration does not necessarily imply the being of Forms 
nor a One beside a Many, but it does necessarily imply the 
possibility of truly predicating one of many; since without this 
possibility we cannot save the universal, and if the universal 
goes, the middle term goes witb. it, and so demonstration 
becomes impossible. We conclude, then, that there must be a 
single identical term unequivocally predicable of a number of 
individuals. 

The law that it is impossible to affirm and deny simultaneously 
the same predicate of the same subject is not expressly posited 
by any demonstration except when the conclusion also has to 
be expressed in that form; in which case the proof lays down as 
its major premiss that the major is truly affirmed of the middle 
but falsely denied. It makes no difference, however, if we add to 
the middle, or again to the minor term, the corresponding 
negative. For grant a minor term of which it is true to predicate 
man - even if it be also true to predicate not-man of it - still 
grant simply that man is animal and not not-animal, and the 
conclusion follows: for it will still be true to say that Callias - 
even if it be also true to say that not-Callias - is animal and not 
not-animal. The reason is that the major term is predicable not 
only of the middle, but of something other than the middle as 
well, being of wider application; so that the conclusion is not 
affected even if the middle is extended to cover the original 
middle term and also what is not the original middle term. 

The law that every predicate can be either truly affirmed or 
truly denied of every subject is posited by such demonstration 
as uses reductio ad impossibile, and then not always 
universally, but so far as it is requisite; within the limits, that is, 
of the genus - the genus, I mean (as I have already explained), to 
which the man of science applies his demonstrations. In virtue 



244 



of the common elements of demonstration - I mean the 
common axioms which are used as premisses of 
demonstration, not the subjects nor the attributes 
demonstrated as belonging to them - all the sciences have 
communion with one another, and in communion with them all 
is dialectic and any science which might attempt a universal 
proof of axioms such as the law of excluded middle, the law 
that the subtraction of equals from equals leaves equal 
remainders, or other axioms of the same kind. Dialectic has no 
definite sphere of this kind, not being confined to a single 
genus. Otherwise its method would not be interrogative; for the 
interrogative method is barred to the demonstrator, who cannot 
use the opposite facts to prove the same nexus. This was shown 
in my work on the syllogism. 



12 

If a syllogistic question is equivalent to a proposition 
embodying one of the two sides of a contradiction, and if each 
science has its peculiar propositions from which its peculiar 
conclusion is developed, then there is such a thing as a 
distinctively scientific question, and it is the interrogative form 
of the premisses from which the 'appropriate' conclusion of 
each science is developed. Hence it is clear that not every 
question will be relevant to geometry, nor to medicine, nor to 
any other science: only those questions will be geometrical 
which form premisses for the proof of the theorems of 
geometry or of any other science, such as optics, which uses the 
same basic truths as geometry. Of the other sciences the like is 
true. Of these questions the geometer is bound to give his 
account, using the basic truths of geometry in conjunction with 
his previous conclusions; of the basic truths the geometer, as 



245 



such, is not bound to give any account. The like is true of the 
other sciences. There is a limit, then, to the questions which we 
may put to each man of science; nor is each man of science 
bound to answer all inquiries on each several subject, but only 
such as fall within the defined field of his own science. If, then, 
in controversy with a geometer qua geometer the disputant 
confines himself to geometry and proves anything from 
geometrical premisses, he is clearly to be applauded; if he goes 
outside these he will be at fault, and obviously cannot even 
refute the geometer except accidentally. One should therefore 
not discuss geometry among those who are not geometers, for 
in such a company an unsound argument will pass unnoticed. 
This is correspondingly true in the other sciences. 

Since there are 'geometrical' questions, does it follow that there 
are also distinctively 'ungeometrical' questions? Further, in each 
special science - geometry for instance - what kind of error is it 
that may vitiate questions, and yet not exclude them from that 
science? Again, is the erroneous conclusion one constructed 
from premisses opposite to the true premisses, or is it formal 
fallacy though drawn from geometrical premisses? Or, perhaps, 
the erroneous conclusion is due to the drawing of premisses 
from another science; e.g. in a geometrical controversy a 
musical question is distinctively ungeometrical, whereas the 
notion that parallels meet is in one sense geometrical, being 
ungeometrical in a different fashion: the reason being that 
'ungeometrical', like 'unrhythmical', is equivocal, meaning in 
the one case not geometry at all, in the other bad geometry? It 
is this error, i.e. error based on premisses of this kind - 'of the 
science but false - that is the contrary of science. In 
mathematics the formal fallacy is not so common, because it is 
the middle term in which the ambiguity lies, since the major is 
predicated of the whole of the middle and the middle of the 
whole of the minor (the predicate of course never has the prefix 
'all'); and in mathematics one can, so to speak, see these middle 



246 



terms with an intellectual vision, while in dialectic the 
ambiguity may escape detection. E.g. 'Is every circle a figure?' A 
diagram shows that this is so, but the minor premiss 'Are epics 
circles?' is shown by the diagram to be false. 

If a proof has an inductive minor premiss, one should not bring 
an 'objection' against it. For since every premiss must be 
applicable to a number of cases (otherwise it will not be true in 
every instance, which, since the syllogism proceeds from 
universals, it must be), then assuredly the same is true of an 
'objection'; since premisses and 'objections' are so far the same 
that anything which can be validly advanced as an 'objection' 
must be such that it could take the form of a premiss, either 
demonstrative or dialectical. On the other hand, arguments 
formally illogical do sometimes occur through taking as 
middles mere attributes of the major and minor terms. An 
instance of this is Caeneus' proof that fire increases in 
geometrical proportion: 'Fire', he argues, 'increases rapidly, and 
so does geometrical proportion'. There is no syllogism so, but 
there is a syllogism if the most rapidly increasing proportion is 
geometrical and the most rapidly increasing proportion is 
attributable to fire in its motion. Sometimes, no doubt, it is 
impossible to reason from premisses predicating mere 
attributes: but sometimes it is possible, though the possibility is 
overlooked. If false premisses could never give true conclusions 
'resolution' would be easy, for premisses and conclusion would 
in that case inevitably reciprocate. I might then argue thus: let A 
be an existing fact; let the existence of A imply such and such 
facts actually known to me to exist, which we may call B. I can 
now, since they reciprocate, infer A from B. 

Reciprocation of premisses and conclusion is more frequent in 
mathematics, because mathematics takes definitions, but never 
an accident, for its premisses - a second characteristic 



247 



distinguishing mathematical reasoning from dialectical 
disputations. 

A science expands not by the interposition of fresh middle 
terms, but by the apposition of fresh extreme terms. E.g. A is 
predicated of B, B of C, C of D, and so indefinitely. Or the 
expansion may be lateral: e.g. one major A, may be proved of 
two minors, C and E. Thus let A represent number - a number or 
number taken indeterminately; B determinate odd number; C 
any particular odd number. We can then predicate A of C. Next 
let D represent determinate even number, and E even number. 
Then A is predicable of E. 



13 

Knowledge of the fact differs from knowledge of the reasoned 
fact. To begin with, they differ within the same science and in 
two ways: (1) when the premisses of the syllogism are not 
immediate (for then the proximate cause is not contained in 
them - a necessary condition of knowledge of the reasoned 
fact): (2) when the premisses are immediate, but instead of the 
cause the better known of the two reciprocals is taken as the 
middle; for of two reciprocally predicable terms the one which 
is not the cause may quite easily be the better known and so 
become the middle term of the demonstration. Thus (2) (a) you 
might prove as follows that the planets are near because they 
do not twinkle: let C be the planets, B not twinkling, A 
proximity. Then B is predicable of C; for the planets do not 
twinkle. But A is also predicable of B, since that which does not 
twinkle is near - we must take this truth as having been 
reached by induction or sense-perception. Therefore A is a 
necessary predicate of C; so that we have demonstrated that the 



248 



planets are near. This syllogism, then, proves not the reasoned 
fact but only the fact; since they are not near because they do 
not twinkle, but, because they are near, do not twinkle. The 
major and middle of the proof, however, may be reversed, and 
then the demonstration will be of the reasoned fact. Thus: let C 
be the planets, B proximity, A not twinkling. Then B is an 
attribute of C, and A - not twinkling - of B. Consequently A is 
predicable of C, and the syllogism proves the reasoned fact, 
since its middle term is the proximate cause. Another example 
is the inference that the moon is spherical from its manner of 
waxing. Thus: since that which so waxes is spherical, and since 
the moon so waxes, clearly the moon is spherical. Put in this 
form, the syllogism turns out to be proof of the fact, but if the 
middle and major be reversed it is proof of the reasoned fact; 
since the moon is not spherical because it waxes in a certain 
manner, but waxes in such a manner because it is spherical. 
(Let C be the moon, B spherical, and A waxing.) Again (b), in 
cases where the cause and the effect are not reciprocal and the 
effect is the better known, the fact is demonstrated but not the 
reasoned fact. This also occurs (1) when the middle falls outside 
the major and minor, for here too the strict cause is not given, 
and so the demonstration is of the fact, not of the reasoned fact. 
For example, the question 'Why does not a wall breathe?' might 
be answered, 'Because it is not an animal'; but that answer 
would not give the strict cause, because if not being an animal 
causes the absence of respiration, then being an animal should 
be the cause of respiration, according to the rule that if the 
negation of causes the non-inherence of y, the affirmation of x 
causes the inherence of y; e.g. if the disproportion of the hot 
and cold elements is the cause of ill health, their proportion is 
the cause of health; and conversely, if the assertion of x causes 
the inherence of y, the negation of x must cause y's non- 
inherence. But in the case given this consequence does not 
result; for not every animal breathes. A syllogism with this kind 



249 



of cause takes place in the second figure. Thus: let A be animal, 
B respiration, C wall. Then A is predicable of all B (for all that 
breathes is animal), but of no C; and consequently B is 
predicable of no C; that is, the wall does not breathe. Such 
causes are like far-fetched explanations, which precisely consist 
in making the cause too remote, as in Anacharsis' account of 
why the Scythians have no flute-players; namely because they 
have no vines. 

Thus, then, do the syllogism of the fact and the syllogism of the 
reasoned fact differ within one science and according to the 
position of the middle terms. But there is another way too in 
which the fact and the reasoned fact differ, and that is when 
they are investigated respectively by different sciences. This 
occurs in the case of problems related to one another as 
subordinate and superior, as when optical problems are 
subordinated to geometry, mechanical problems to stereometry, 
harmonic problems to arithmetic, the data of observation to 
astronomy. (Some of these sciences bear almost the same 
name; e.g. mathematical and nautical astronomy, mathematical 
and acoustical harmonics.) Here it is the business of the 
empirical observers to know the fact, of the mathematicians to 
know the reasoned fact; for the latter are in possession of the 
demonstrations giving the causes, and are often ignorant of the 
fact: just as we have often a clear insight into a universal, but 
through lack of observation are ignorant of some of its 
particular instances. These connexions have a perceptible 
existence though they are manifestations of forms. For the 
mathematical sciences concern forms: they do not demonstrate 
properties of a substratum, since, even though the geometrical 
subjects are predicable as properties of a perceptible 
substratum, it is not as thus predicable that the mathematician 
demonstrates properties of them. As optics is related to 
geometry, so another science is related to optics, namely the 
theory of the rainbow. Here knowledge of the fact is within the 



250 



province of the natural philosopher, knowledge of the reasoned 
fact within that of the optician, either qua optician or qua 
mathematical optician. Many sciences not standing in this 
mutual relation enter into it at points; e.g. medicine and 
geometry: it is the physician's business to know that circular 
wounds heal more slowly, the geometer's to know the reason 
why. 



14 

Of all the figures the most scientific is the first. Thus, it is the 
vehicle of the demonstrations of all the mathematical sciences, 
such as arithmetic, geometry, and optics, and practically all of 
all sciences that investigate causes: for the syllogism of the 
reasoned fact is either exclusively or generally speaking and in 
most cases in this figure - a second proof that this figure is the 
most scientific; for grasp of a reasoned conclusion is the 
primary condition of knowledge. Thirdly, the first is the only 
figure which enables us to pursue knowledge of the essence of a 
thing. In the second figure no affirmative conclusion is possible, 
and knowledge of a thing's essence must be affirmative; while 
in the third figure the conclusion can be affirmative, but cannot 
be universal, and essence must have a universal character: e.g. 
man is not two-footed animal in any qualified sense, but 
universally. Finally, the first figure has no need of the others, 
while it is by means of the first that the other two figures are 
developed, and have their intervals closepacked until 
immediate premisses are reached. 

Clearly, therefore, the first figure is the primary condition of 
knowledge. 



251 



15 

Just as an attribute A may (as we saw) be atomically connected 
with a subject B, so its disconnexion may be atomic. I call 
'atomic' connexions or disconnexions which involve no 
intermediate term; since in that case the connexion or 
disconnexion will not be mediated by something other than the 
terms themselves. It follows that if either A or B, or both A and 
B, have a genus, their disconnexion cannot be primary. Thus: let 
C be the genus of A. Then, if C is not the genus of B - for A may 
well have a genus which is not the genus of B - there will be a 
syllogism proving As disconnexion from B thus: 

all A is C, 

no B is C, 

therefore no B is A. 

Or if it is B which has a genus D, we have 

all B is D, 

no D is A, 

therefore no B is A, by syllogism; 

and the proof will be similar if both A and B have a genus. That 
the genus of A need not be the genus of B and vice versa, is 
shown by the existence of mutually exclusive coordinate series 
of predication. If no term in the series ACD... is predicable of any 
term in the series BEE.., and if G - a term in the former series - 
is the genus of A, clearly G will not be the genus of B; since, if it 
were, the series would not be mutually exclusive. So also if B 
has a genus, it will not be the genus of A. If, on the other hand, 
neither A nor B has a genus and A does not inhere in B, this 



252 



disconnexion must be atomic. If there be a middle term, one or 
other of them is bound to have a genus, for the syllogism will be 
either in the first or the second figure. If it is in the first, B will 
have a genus - for the premiss containing it must be 
affirmative: if in the second, either A or B indifferently, since 
syllogism is possible if either is contained in a negative premiss, 
but not if both premisses are negative. 

Hence it is clear that one thing may be atomically disconnected 
from another, and we have stated when and how this is 
possible. 



16 

Ignorance - defined not as the negation of knowledge but as a 
positive state of mind - is error produced by inference. 

(1) Let us first consider propositions asserting a predicate's 
immediate connexion with or disconnexion from a subject. 
Here, it is true, positive error may befall one in alternative ways; 
for it may arise where one directly believes a connexion or 
disconnexion as well as where one's belief is acquired by 
inference. The error, however, that consists in a direct belief is 
without complication; but the error resulting from inference - 
which here concerns us - takes many forms. Thus, let A be 
atomically disconnected from all B: then the conclusion inferred 
through a middle term C, that all B is A, will be a case of error 
produced by syllogism. Now, two cases are possible. Either (a) 
both premisses, or (b) one premiss only, may be false, (a) If 
neither A is an attribute of any C nor C of any B, whereas the 
contrary was posited in both cases, both premisses will be false. 
(C may quite well be so related to A and B that C is neither 
subordinate to A nor a universal attribute of B: for B, since A was 



253 



said to be primarily disconnected from B, cannot have a genus, 
and A need not necessarily be a universal attribute of all things. 
Consequently both premisses may be false.) On the other hand, 

(b) one of the premisses may be true, though not either 
indifferently but only the major A-C since, B having no genus, 
the premiss C-B will always be false, while A-C may be true. This 
is the case if, for example, A is related atomically to both C and 
B; because when the same term is related atomically to more 
terms than one, neither of those terms will belong to the other. 
It is, of course, equally the case if A-C is not atomic. 

Error of attribution, then, occurs through these causes and in 
this form only - for we found that no syllogism of universal 
attribution was possible in any figure but the first. On the other 
hand, an error of non-attribution may occur either in the first or 
in the second figure. Let us therefore first explain the various 
forms it takes in the first figure and the character of the 
premisses in each case. 

(c) It may occur when both premisses are false; e.g. supposing A 
atomically connected with both C and B, if it be then assumed 
that no C is and all B is C, both premisses are false. 

(d) It is also possible when one is false. This may be either 
premiss indifferently. A-C may be true, C-B false - A-C true 
because A is not an attribute of all things, C-B false because C, 
which never has the attribute A, cannot be an attribute of B; for 
if C-B were true, the premiss A-C would no longer be true, and 
besides if both premisses were true, the conclusion would be 
true. Or again, C-B may be true and A-C false; e.g. if both C and 
A contain B as genera, one of them must be subordinate to the 
other, so that if the premiss takes the form No C is A, it will be 
false. This makes it clear that whether either or both premisses 
are false, the conclusion will equally be false. 



254 



In the second figure the premisses cannot both be wholly false; 
for if all B is A, no middle term can be with truth universally 
affirmed of one extreme and universally denied of the other: 
but premisses in which the middle is affirmed of one extreme 
and denied of the other are the necessary condition if one is to 
get a valid inference at all. Therefore if, taken in this way, they 
are wholly false, their contraries conversely should be wholly 
true. But this is impossible. On the other hand, there is nothing 
to prevent both premisses being partially false; e.g. if actually 
some A is C and some B is C, then if it is premised that all A is C 
and no B is C, both premisses are false, yet partially, not wholly, 
false. The same is true if the major is made negative instead of 
the minor. Or one premiss may be wholly false, and it may be 
either of them. Thus, supposing that actually an attribute of all 
A must also be an attribute of all B, then if C is yet taken to be a 
universal attribute of all but universally non-attributable to B, C- 
A will be true but C-B false. Again, actually that which is an 
attribute of no B will not be an attribute of all A either; for if it 
be an attribute of all A, it will also be an attribute of all B, which 
is contrary to supposition; but if C be nevertheless assumed to 
be a universal attribute of A, but an attribute of no B, then the 
premiss C-B is true but the major is false. The case is similar if 
the major is made the negative premiss. For in fact what is an 
attribute of no A will not be an attribute of any B either; and if it 
be yet assumed that C is universally non-attributable to A, but a 
universal attribute of B, the premiss C-A is true but the minor 
wholly false. Again, in fact it is false to assume that that which 
is an attribute of all B is an attribute of no A, for if it be an 
attribute of all B, it must be an attribute of some A. If then C is 
nevertheless assumed to be an attribute of all B but of no A, G-B 
will be true but C-A false. 

It is thus clear that in the case of atomic propositions erroneous 
inference will be possible not only when both premisses are 
false but also when only one is false. 



255 



17 

In the case of attributes not atomically connected with or 
disconnected from their subjects, (a) (i) as long as the false 
conclusion is inferred through the 'appropriate' middle, only the 
major and not both premisses can be false. By 'appropriate 
middle' I mean the middle term through which the 
contradictory - i.e. the true-conclusion is inferrible. Thus, let A 
be attributable to B through a middle term C: then, since to 
produce a conclusion the premiss C-B must be taken 
affirmatively, it is clear that this premiss must always be true, 
for its quality is not changed. But the major A-C is false, for it is 
by a change in the quality of A-C that the conclusion becomes 
its contradictory - i.e. true. Similarly (ii) if the middle is taken 
from another series of predication; e.g. suppose D to be not only 
contained within A as a part within its whole but also 
predicable of all B. Then the premiss D-B must remain 
unchanged, but the quality of A-D must be changed; so that D-B 
is always true, A-D always false. Such error is practically 
identical with that which is inferred through the 'appropriate' 
middle. On the other hand, (b) if the conclusion is not inferred 
through the 'appropriate' middle - (i) when the middle is 
subordinate to A but is predicable of no B, both premisses must 
be false, because if there is to be a conclusion both must be 
posited as asserting the contrary of what is actually the fact, 
and so posited both become false: e.g. suppose that actually all 
D is A but no B is D; then if these premisses are changed in 
quality, a conclusion will follow and both of the new premisses 
will be false. When, however, (ii) the middle D is not subordinate 
to A, A-D will be true, D-B false - A-D true because A was not 
subordinate to D, D-B false because if it had been true, the 



256 



conclusion too would have been true; but it is ex hypothesi 
false. 

When the erroneous inference is in the second figure, both 
premisses cannot be entirely false; since if B is subordinate to A, 
there can be no middle predicable of all of one extreme and of 
none of the other, as was stated before. One premiss, however, 
may be false, and it may be either of them. Thus, if C is actually 
an attribute of both A and B, but is assumed to be an attribute of 
A only and not of B, C-A will be true, C-B false: or again if C be 
assumed to be attributable to B but to no A, C-B will be true, C-A 
false. 

We have stated when and through what kinds of premisses 
error will result in cases where the erroneous conclusion is 
negative. If the conclusion is affirmative, (a) (i) it may be 
inferred through the 'appropriate' middle term. In this case both 
premisses cannot be false since, as we said before, C-B must 
remain unchanged if there is to be a conclusion, and 
consequently A-C, the quality of which is changed, will always 
be false. This is equally true if (ii) the middle is taken from 
another series of predication, as was stated to be the case also 
with regard to negative error; for D-B must remain unchanged, 
while the quality of A-D must be converted, and the type of 
error is the same as before. 

(b) The middle may be inappropriate. Then (i) if D is subordinate 
to A, A-D will be true, but D-B false; since A may quite well be 
predicable of several terms no one of which can be 
subordinated to another. If, however, (ii) D is not subordinate to 
A, obviously A-D, since it is affirmed, will always be false, while 
D-B may be either true or false; for A may very well be an 
attribute of no D, whereas all B is D, e.g. no science is animal, all 
music is science. Equally well A may be an attribute of no D, and 
D of no B. It emerges, then, that if the middle term is not 



257 



subordinate to the major, not only both premisses but either 
singly may be false. 

Thus we have made it clear how many varieties of erroneous 
inference are liable to happen and through what kinds of 
premisses they occur, in the case both of immediate and of 
demonstrable truths. 



18 

It is also clear that the loss of any one of the senses entails the 
loss of a corresponding portion of knowledge, and that, since we 
learn either by induction or by demonstration, this knowledge 
cannot be acquired. Thus demonstration develops from 
universals, induction from particulars; but since it is possible to 
familiarize the pupil with even the so-called mathematical 
abstractions only through induction - i.e. only because each 
subject genus possesses, in virtue of a determinate 
mathematical character, certain properties which can be treated 
as separate even though they do not exist in isolation - it is 
consequently impossible to come to grasp universals except 
through induction. But induction is impossible for those who 
have not sense-perception. For it is sense-perception alone 
which is adequate for grasping the particulars: they cannot be 
objects of scientific knowledge, because neither can universals 
give us knowledge of them without induction, nor can we get it 
through induction without sense-perception. 



258 



19 

Every syllogism is effected by means of three terms. One kind of 
syllogism serves to prove that A inheres in C by showing that A 
inheres in B and B in C; the other is negative and one of its 
premisses asserts one term of another, while the other denies 
one term of another. It is clear, then, that these are the 
fundamentals and so-called hypotheses of syllogism. Assume 
them as they have been stated, and proof is bound to follow - 
proof that A inheres in C through B, and again that A inheres in 
B through some other middle term, and similarly that B inheres 
in C. If our reasoning aims at gaining credence and so is merely 
dialectical, it is obvious that we have only to see that our 
inference is based on premisses as credible as possible: so that 
if a middle term between A and B is credible though not real, 
one can reason through it and complete a dialectical syllogism. 
If, however, one is aiming at truth, one must be guided by the 
real connexions of subjects and attributes. Thus: since there are 
attributes which are predicated of a subject essentially or 
naturally and not coincidentally - not, that is, in the sense in 
which we say 'That white (thing) is a man', which is not the 
same mode of predication as when we say 'The man is white': 
the man is white not because he is something else but because 
he is man, but the white is man because 'being white' coincides 
with 'humanity' within one substratum - therefore there are 
terms such as are naturally subjects of predicates. Suppose, 
then, C such a term not itself attributable to anything else as to 
a subject, but the proximate subject of the attribute B - i.e. so 
that B-C is immediate; suppose further E related immediately to 
F, and F to B. The first question is, must this series terminate, or 
can it proceed to infinity? The second question is as follows: 
Suppose nothing is essentially predicated of A, but A is 
predicated primarily of H and of no intermediate prior term, and 
suppose H similarly related to G and G to B; then must this 
series also terminate, or can it too proceed to infinity? There is 



259 



this much difference between the questions: the first is, is it 
possible to start from that which is not itself attributable to 
anything else but is the subject of attributes, and ascend to 
infinity? The second is the problem whether one can start from 
that which is a predicate but not itself a subject of predicates, 
and descend to infinity? A third question is, if the extreme 
terms are fixed, can there be an infinity of middles? I mean this: 
suppose for example that A inheres in C and B is intermediate 
between them, but between B and A there are other middles, 
and between these again fresh middles; can these proceed to 
infinity or can they not? This is the equivalent of inquiring, do 
demonstrations proceed to infinity, i.e. is everything 
demonstrable? Or do ultimate subject and primary attribute 
limit one another? 

I hold that the same questions arise with regard to negative 
conclusions and premisses: viz. if A is attributable to no B, then 
either this predication will be primary, or there will be an 
intermediate term prior to B to which a is not attributable - G, 
let us say, which is attributable to all B - and there may still be 
another term H prior to G, which is attributable to all G. The 
same questions arise, I say, because in these cases too either the 
series of prior terms to which a is not attributable is infinite or it 
terminates. 

One cannot ask the same questions in the case of reciprocating 
terms, since when subject and predicate are convertible there is 
neither primary nor ultimate subject, seeing that all the 
reciprocals qua subjects stand in the same relation to one 
another, whether we say that the subject has an infinity of 
attributes or that both subjects and attributes - and we raised 
the question in both cases - are infinite in number. These 
questions then cannot be asked - unless, indeed, the terms can 
reciprocate by two different modes, by accidental predication in 
one relation and natural predication in the other. 



260 



20 

Now, it is clear that if the predications terminate in both the 
upward and the downward direction (by 'upward' I mean the 
ascent to the more universal, by 'downward' the descent to the 
more particular), the middle terms cannot be infinite in number. 
For suppose that A is predicated of F, and that the intermediates 
- call them B B' B"... - are infinite, then clearly you might 
descend from and find one term predicated of another ad 
infinitum, since you have an infinity of terms between you and 
F; and equally, if you ascend from F, there are infinite terms 
between you and A. It follows that if these processes are 
impossible there cannot be an infinity of intermediates between 
A and F. Nor is it of any effect to urge that some terms of the 
series AB...F are contiguous so as to exclude intermediates, 
while others cannot be taken into the argument at all: 
whichever terms of the series B...I take, the number of 
intermediates in the direction either of A or of F must be finite 
or infinite: where the infinite series starts, whether from the 
first term or from a later one, is of no moment, for the 
succeeding terms in any case are infinite in number. 



21 

Further, if in affirmative demonstration the series terminates in 
both directions, clearly it will terminate too in negative 
demonstration. Let us assume that we cannot proceed to 
infinity either by ascending from the ultimate term (by 'ultimate 
term' I mean a term such as was, not itself attributable to a 



261 



subject but itself the subject of attributes), or by descending 
towards an ultimate from the primary term (by 'primary term' I 
mean a term predicable of a subject but not itself a subject). If 
this assumption is justified, the series will also terminate in the 
case of negation. For a negative conclusion can be proved in all 
three figures. In the first figure it is proved thus: no B is A, all C 
is B. In packing the interval B-C we must reach immediate 
propositions - as is always the case with the minor premiss - 
since B-C is affirmative. As regards the other premiss it is plain 
that if the major term is denied of a term D prior to B, D will 
have to be predicable of all B, and if the major is denied of yet 
another term prior to D, this term must be predicable of all D. 
Consequently, since the ascending series is finite, the descent 
will also terminate and there will be a subject of which A is 
primarily non-predicable. In the second figure the syllogism is, 
all A is B, no C is B,..no C is A. If proof of this is required, plainly 
it may be shown either in the first figure as above, in the second 
as here, or in the third. The first figure has been discussed, and 
we will proceed to display the second, proof by which will be as 
follows: all B is D, no C is D..., since it is required that B should 
be a subject of which a predicate is affirmed. Next, since D is to 
be proved not to belong to C, then D has a further predicate 
which is denied of C. Therefore, since the succession of 
predicates affirmed of an ever higher universal terminates, the 
succession of predicates denied terminates too. 

The third figure shows it as follows: all B is A, some B is not C. 
Therefore some A is not C. This premiss, i.e. C-B, will be proved 
either in the same figure or in one of the two figures discussed 
above. In the first and second figures the series terminates. If 
we use the third figure, we shall take as premisses, all E is B, 
some E is not C, and this premiss again will be proved by a 
similar prosyllogism. But since it is assumed that the series of 
descending subjects also terminates, plainly the series of more 
universal non-predicables will terminate also. Even supposing 



262 



that the proof is not confined to one method, but employs them 
all and is now in the first figure, now in the second or third - 
even so the regress will terminate, for the methods are finite in 
number, and if finite things are combined in a finite number of 
ways, the result must be finite. 

Thus it is plain that the regress of middles terminates in the 
case of negative demonstration, if it does so also in the case of 
affirmative demonstration. That in fact the regress terminates 
in both these cases may be made clear by the following 
dialectical considerations. 



22 

In the case of predicates constituting the essential nature of a 
thing, it clearly terminates, seeing that if definition is possible, 
or in other words, if essential form is knowable, and an infinite 
series cannot be traversed, predicates constituting a thing's 
essential nature must be finite in number. But as regards 
predicates generally we have the following prefatory remarks to 
make. (1) We can affirm without falsehood 'the white (thing) is 
walking', and that big (thing) is a log'; or again, 'the log is big', 
and 'the man walks'. But the affirmation differs in the two 
cases. When I affirm 'the white is a log', I mean that something 
which happens to be white is a log - not that white is the 
substratum in which log inheres, for it was not qua white or qua 
a species of white that the white (thing) came to be a log, and 
the white (thing) is consequently not a log except incidentally. 
On the other hand, when I affirm 'the log is white', I do not 
mean that something else, which happens also to be a log, is 
white (as I should if I said 'the musician is white,' which would 
mean 'the man who happens also to be a musician is white'); on 



263 



the contrary, log is here the substratum - the substratum which 
actually came to be white, and did so qua wood or qua a species 
of wood and qua nothing else. 

If we must lay down a rule, let us entitle the latter kind of 
statement predication, and the former not predication at all, or 
not strict but accidental predication. 'White' and 'log' will thus 
serve as types respectively of predicate and subject. 

We shall assume, then, that the predicate is invariably 
predicated strictly and not accidentally of the subject, for on 
such predication demonstrations depend for their force. It 
follows from this that when a single attribute is predicated of a 
single subject, the predicate must affirm of the subject either 
some element constituting its essential nature, or that it is in 
some way qualified, quantified, essentially related, active, 
passive, placed, or dated. 

(2) Predicates which signify substance signify that the subject is 
identical with the predicate or with a species of the predicate. 
Predicates not signifying substance which are predicated of a 
subject not identical with themselves or with a species of 
themselves are accidental or coincidental; e.g. white is a 
coincident of man, seeing that man is not identical with white 
or a species of white, but rather with animal, since man is 
identical with a species of animal. These predicates which do 
not signify substance must be predicates of some other subject, 
and nothing can be white which is not also other than white. 
The Forms we can dispense with, for they are mere sound 
without sense; and even if there are such things, they are not 
relevant to our discussion, since demonstrations are concerned 
with predicates such as we have defined. 

(3) If A is a quality of B, B cannot be a quality of A - a quality of a 
quality. Therefore A and B cannot be predicated reciprocally of 
one another in strict predication: they can be affirmed without 



264 



falsehood of one another, but not genuinely predicated of each 
other. For one alternative is that they should be substantially 
predicated of one another, i.e. B would become the genus or 
differentia of A - the predicate now become subject. But it has 
been shown that in these substantial predications neither the 
ascending predicates nor the descending subjects form an 
infinite series; e.g. neither the series, man is biped, biped is 
animal, &c, nor the series predicating animal of man, man of 
Callias, Callias of a further, subject as an element of its essential 
nature, is infinite. For all such substance is definable, and an 
infinite series cannot be traversed in thought: consequently 
neither the ascent nor the descent is infinite, since a substance 
whose predicates were infinite would not be definable. Hence 
they will not be predicated each as the genus of the other; for 
this would equate a genus with one of its own species. Nor (the 
other alternative) can a quale be reciprocally predicated of a 
quale, nor any term belonging to an adjectival category of 
another such term, except by accidental predication; for all such 
predicates are coincidents and are predicated of substances. On 
the other hand - in proof of the impossibility of an infinite 
ascending series - every predication displays the subject as 
somehow qualified or quantified or as characterized under one 
of the other adjectival categories, or else is an element in its 
substantial nature: these latter are limited in number, and the 
number of the widest kinds under which predications fall is 
also limited, for every predication must exhibit its subject as 
somehow qualified, quantified, essentially related, acting or 
suffering, or in some place or at some time. 

I assume first that predication implies a single subject and a 
single attribute, and secondly that predicates which are not 
substantial are not predicated of one another. We assume this 
because such predicates are all coincidents, and though some 
are essential coincidents, others of a different type, yet we 
maintain that all of them alike are predicated of some 



265 



substratum and that a coincident is never a substratum - since 
we do not class as a coincident anything which does not owe its 
designation to its being something other than itself, but always 
hold that any coincident is predicated of some substratum 
other than itself, and that another group of coincidents may 
have a different substratum. Subject to these assumptions then, 
neither the ascending nor the descending series of predication 
in which a single attribute is predicated of a single subject is 
infinite. For the subjects of which coincidents are predicated are 
as many as the constitutive elements of each individual 
substance, and these we have seen are not infinite in number, 
while in the ascending series are contained those constitutive 
elements with their coincidents - both of which are finite. We 
conclude that there is a given subject (D) of which some 
attribute (C) is primarily predicable; that there must be an 
attribute (B) primarily predicable of the first attribute, and that 
the series must end with a term (A) not predicable of any term 
prior to the last subject of which it was predicated (B), and of 
which no term prior to it is predicable. 

The argument we have given is one of the so-called proofs; an 
alternative proof follows. Predicates so related to their subjects 
that there are other predicates prior to them predicable of those 
subjects are demonstrable; but of demonstrable propositions 
one cannot have something better than knowledge, nor can one 
know them without demonstration. Secondly, if a consequent is 
only known through an antecedent (viz. premisses prior to it) 
and we neither know this antecedent nor have something 
better than knowledge of it, then we shall not have scientific 
knowledge of the consequent. Therefore, if it is possible through 
demonstration to know anything without qualification and not 
merely as dependent on the acceptance of certain premisses - 
i.e. hypothetically - the series of intermediate predications must 
terminate. If it does not terminate, and beyond any predicate 
taken as higher than another there remains another still higher, 



266 



then every predicate is demonstrable. Consequently, since these 
demonstrable predicates are infinite in number and therefore 
cannot be traversed, we shall not know them by demonstration. 
If, therefore, we have not something better than knowledge of 
them, we cannot through demonstration have unqualified but 
only hypothetical science of anything. 

As dialectical proofs of our contention these may carry 
conviction, but an analytic process will show more briefly that 
neither the ascent nor the descent of predication can be infinite 
in the demonstrative sciences which are the object of our 
investigation. Demonstration proves the inherence of essential 
attributes in things. Now attributes may be essential for two 
reasons: either because they are elements in the essential 
nature of their subjects, or because their subjects are elements 
in their essential nature. An example of the latter is odd as an 
attribute of number - though it is number's attribute, yet 
number itself is an element in the definition of odd; of the 
former, multiplicity or the indivisible, which are elements in the 
definition of number. In neither kind of attribution can the 
terms be infinite. They are not infinite where each is related to 
the term below it as odd is to number, for this would mean the 
inherence in odd of another attribute of odd in whose nature 
odd was an essential element: but then number will be an 
ultimate subject of the whole infinite chain of attributes, and be 
an element in the definition of each of them. Hence, since an 
infinity of attributes such as contain their subject in their 
definition cannot inhere in a single thing, the ascending series 
is equally finite. Note, moreover, that all such attributes must so 
inhere in the ultimate subject - e.g. its attributes in number and 
number in them - as to be commensurate with the subject and 
not of wider extent. Attributes which are essential elements in 
the nature of their subjects are equally finite: otherwise 
definition would be impossible. Hence, if all the attributes 
predicated are essential and these cannot be infinite, the 



267 



ascending series will terminate, and consequently the 
descending series too. 

If this is so, it follows that the intermediates between any two 
terms are also always limited in number. An immediately 
obvious consequence of this is that demonstrations necessarily 
involve basic truths, and that the contention of some - referred 
to at the outset - that all truths are demonstrable is mistaken. 
For if there are basic truths, (a) not all truths are demonstrable, 
and (b) an infinite regress is impossible; since if either (a) or (b) 
were not a fact, it would mean that no interval was immediate 
and indivisible, but that all intervals were divisible. This is true 
because a conclusion is demonstrated by the interposition, not 
the apposition, of a fresh term. If such interposition could 
continue to infinity there might be an infinite number of terms 
between any two terms; but this is impossible if both the 
ascending and descending series of predication terminate; and 
of this fact, which before was shown dialectically, analytic proof 
has now been given. 



23 

It is an evident corollary of these conclusions that if the same 
attribute A inheres in two terms C and D predicable either not at 
all, or not of all instances, of one another, it does not always 
belong to them in virtue of a common middle term. Isosceles 
and scalene possess the attribute of having their angles equal to 
two right angles in virtue of a common middle; for they possess 
it in so far as they are both a certain kind of figure, and not in so 
far as they differ from one another. But this is not always the 
case: for, were it so, if we take B as the common middle in virtue 
of which A inheres in C and D, clearly B would inhere in C and D 



268 



through a second common middle, and this in turn would 
inhere in C and D through a third, so that between two terms an 
infinity of intermediates would fall - an impossibility. Thus it 
need not always be in virtue of a common middle term that a 
single attribute inheres in several subjects, since there must be 
immediate intervals. Yet if the attribute to be proved common to 
two subjects is to be one of their essential attributes, the middle 
terms involved must be within one subject genus and be 
derived from the same group of immediate premisses; for we 
have seen that processes of proof cannot pass from one genus 
to another. 

It is also clear that when A inheres in B, this can be 
demonstrated if there is a middle term. Further, the 'elements' 
of such a conclusion are the premisses containing the middle in 
question, and they are identical in number with the middle 
terms, seeing that the immediate propositions - or at least such 
immediate propositions as are universal - are the 'elements'. If, 
on the other hand, there is no middle term, demonstration 
ceases to be possible: we are on the way to the basic truths. 
Similarly if A does not inhere in B, this can be demonstrated if 
there is a middle term or a term prior to B in which A does not 
inhere: otherwise there is no demonstration and a basic truth is 
reached. There are, moreover, as many 'elements' of the 
demonstrated conclusion as there are middle terms, since it is 
propositions containing these middle terms that are the basic 
premisses on which the demonstration rests; and as there are 
some indemonstrable basic truths asserting that 'this is that' or 
that 'this inheres in that', so there are others denying that 'this 
is that' or that 'this inheres in that' - in fact some basic truths 
will affirm and some will deny being. 

When we are to prove a conclusion, we must take a primary 
essential predicate - suppose it C - of the subject B, and then 
suppose A similarly predicable of C. If we proceed in this 



269 



manner, no proposition or attribute which falls beyond A is 
admitted in the proof: the interval is constantly condensed until 
subject and predicate become indivisible, i.e. one. We have our 
unit when the premiss becomes immediate, since the 
immediate premiss alone is a single premiss in the unqualified 
sense of 'single'. And as in other spheres the basic element is 
simple but not identical in all - in a system of weight it is the 
mina, in music the quarter-tone, and so on - so in syllogism the 
unit is an immediate premiss, and in the knowledge that 
demonstration gives it is an intuition. In syllogisms, then, which 
prove the inherence of an attribute, nothing falls outside the 
major term. In the case of negative syllogisms on the other 
hand, (1) in the first figure nothing falls outside the major term 
whose inherence is in question; e.g. to prove through a middle C 
that A does not inhere in B the premisses required are, all B is C, 
no C is A. Then if it has to be proved that no C is A, a middle 
must be found between and C; and this procedure will never 
vary. 

(2) If we have to show that E is not D by means of the premisses, 
all D is C; no E, or not all E, is C; then the middle will never fall 
beyond E, and E is the subject of which D is to be denied in the 
conclusion. 

(3) In the third figure the middle will never fall beyond the 
limits of the subject and the attribute denied of it. 



24 

Since demonstrations may be either commensurately universal 
or particular, and either affirmative or negative; the question 
arises, which form is the better? And the same question may be 
put in regard to so-called 'direct' demonstration and reductio ad 



270 



impossibile. Let us first examine the commensurately universal 
and the particular forms, and when we have cleared up this 
problem proceed to discuss 'direct' demonstration and reductio 
ad impossibile. 

The following considerations might lead some minds to prefer 
particular demonstration. 

(1) The superior demonstration is the demonstration which 
gives us greater knowledge (for this is the ideal of 
demonstration), and we have greater knowledge of a particular 
individual when we know it in itself than when we know it 
through something else; e.g. we know Coriscus the musician 
better when we know that Coriscus is musical than when we 
know only that man is musical, and a like argument holds in all 
other cases. But commensurately universal demonstration, 
instead of proving that the subject itself actually is x, proves 
only that something else is x - e.g. in attempting to prove that 
isosceles is x, it proves not that isosceles but only that triangle 
is x - whereas particular demonstration proves that the subject 
itself is x. The demonstration, then, that a subject, as such, 
possesses an attribute is superior. If this is so, and if the 
particular rather than the commensurately universal forms 
demonstrates, particular demonstration is superior. 

(2) The universal has not a separate being over against groups of 
singulars. Demonstration nevertheless creates the opinion that 
its function is conditioned by something like this - some 
separate entity belonging to the real world; that, for instance, of 
triangle or of figure or number, over against particular triangles, 
figures, and numbers. But demonstration which touches the 
real and will not mislead is superior to that which moves 
among unrealities and is delusory. Now commensurately 
universal demonstration is of the latter kind: if we engage in it 
we find ourselves reasoning after a fashion well illustrated by 



271 



the argument that the proportionate is what answers to the 
definition of some entity which is neither line, number, solid, 
nor plane, but a proportionate apart from all these. Since, then, 
such a proof is characteristically commensurate and universal, 
and less touches reality than does particular demonstration, 
and creates a false opinion, it will follow that commensurate 
and universal is inferior to particular demonstration. 

We may retort thus. (1) The first argument applies no more to 
commensurate and universal than to particular demonstration. 
If equality to two right angles is attributable to its subject not 
qua isosceles but qua triangle, he who knows that isosceles 
possesses that attribute knows the subject as qua itself 
possessing the attribute, to a less degree than he who knows 
that triangle has that attribute. To sum up the whole matter: if a 
subject is proved to possess qua triangle an attribute which it 
does not in fact possess qua triangle, that is not demonstration: 
but if it does possess it qua triangle the rule applies that the 
greater knowledge is his who knows the subject as possessing 
its attribute qua that in virtue of which it actually does possess 
it. Since, then, triangle is the wider term, and there is one 
identical definition of triangle - i.e. the term is not equivocal - 
and since equality to two right angles belongs to all triangles, it 
is isosceles qua triangle and not triangle qua isosceles which 
has its angles so related. It follows that he who knows a 
connexion universally has greater knowledge of it as it in fact is 
than he who knows the particular; and the inference is that 
commensurate and universal is superior to particular 
demonstration. 

(2) If there is a single identical definition i.e. if the 
commensurate universal is unequivocal - then the universal 
will possess being not less but more than some of the 
particulars, inasmuch as it is universals which comprise the 
imperishable, particulars that tend to perish. 



272 



(3) Because the universal has a single meaning, we are not 
therefore compelled to suppose that in these examples it has 
being as a substance apart from its particulars - any more than 
we need make a similar supposition in the other cases of 
unequivocal universal predication, viz. where the predicate 
signifies not substance but quality, essential relatedness, or 
action. If such a supposition is entertained, the blame rests not 
with the demonstration but with the hearer. 

(4) Demonstration is syllogism that proves the cause, i.e. the 
reasoned fact, and it is rather the commensurate universal than 
the particular which is causative (as may be shown thus: that 
which possesses an attribute through its own essential nature is 
itself the cause of the inherence, and the commensurate 
universal is primary; hence the commensurate universal is the 
cause). Consequently commensurately universal demonstration 
is superior as more especially proving the cause, that is the 
reasoned fact. 

(5) Our search for the reason ceases, and we think that we know, 
when the coming to be or existence of the fact before us is not 
due to the coming to be or existence of some other fact, for the 
last step of a search thus conducted is eo ipso the end and limit 
of the problem. Thus: 'Why did he come?' 'To get the money - 
wherewith to pay a debt - that he might thereby do what was 
right.' When in this regress we can no longer find an efficient or 
final cause, we regard the last step of it as the end of the coming 
- or being or coming to be - and we regard ourselves as then 
only having full knowledge of the reason why he came. 

If, then, all causes and reasons are alike in this respect, and if 
this is the means to full knowledge in the case of final causes 
such as we have exemplified, it follows that in the case of the 
other causes also full knowledge is attained when an attribute 
no longer inheres because of something else. Thus, when we 



273 



learn that exterior angles are equal to four right angles because 
they are the exterior angles of an isosceles, there still remains 
the question 'Why has isosceles this attribute?' and its answer 
'Because it is a triangle, and a triangle has it because a triangle 
is a rectilinear figure.' If rectilinear figure possesses the property 
for no further reason, at this point we have full knowledge - but 
at this point our knowledge has become commensurately 
universal, and so we conclude that commensurately universal 
demonstration is superior. 

(6) The more demonstration becomes particular the more it 
sinks into an indeterminate manifold, while universal 
demonstration tends to the simple and determinate. But objects 
so far as they are an indeterminate manifold are unintelligible, 
so far as they are determinate, intelligible: they are therefore 
intelligible rather in so far as they are universal than in so far as 
they are particular. From this it follows that universals are more 
demonstrable: but since relative and correlative increase 
concomitantly, of the more demonstrable there will be fuller 
demonstration. Hence the commensurate and universal form, 
being more truly demonstration, is the superior. 

(7) Demonstration which teaches two things is preferable to 
demonstration which teaches only one. He who possesses 
commensurately universal demonstration knows the particular 
as well, but he who possesses particular demonstration does 
not know the universal. So that this is an additional reason for 
preferring commensurately universal demonstration. And there 
is yet this further argument: 

(8) Proof becomes more and more proof of the commensurate 
universal as its middle term approaches nearer to the basic 
truth, and nothing is so near as the immediate premiss which is 
itself the basic truth. If, then, proof from the basic truth is more 
accurate than proof not so derived, demonstration which 



274 



depends more closely on it is more accurate than 
demonstration which is less closely dependent. But 
commensurately universal demonstration is characterized by 
this closer dependence, and is therefore superior. Thus, if A had 
to be proved to inhere in D, and the middles were B and C, B 
being the higher term would render the demonstration which it 
mediated the more universal. 

Some of these arguments, however, are dialectical. The clearest 
indication of the precedence of commensurately universal 
demonstration is as follows: if of two propositions, a prior and a 
posterior, we have a grasp of the prior, we have a kind of 
knowledge - a potential grasp - of the posterior as well. For 
example, if one knows that the angles of all triangles are equal 
to two right angles, one knows in a sense - potentially - that the 
isosceles' angles also are equal to two right angles, even if one 
does not know that the isosceles is a triangle; but to grasp this 
posterior proposition is by no means to know the 
commensurate universal either potentially or actually. 
Moreover, commensurately universal demonstration is through 
and through intelligible; particular demonstration issues in 
sense-perception. 



25 

The preceding arguments constitute our defence of the 
superiority of commensurately universal to particular 
demonstration. That affirmative demonstration excels negative 
may be shown as follows. 

(1) We may assume the superiority ceteris paribus of the 
demonstration which derives from fewer postulates or 
hypotheses - in short from fewer premisses; for, given that all 



275 



these are equally well known, where they are fewer knowledge 
will be more speedily acquired, and that is a desideratum. The 
argument implied in our contention that demonstration from 
fewer assumptions is superior may be set out in universal form 
as follows. Assuming that in both cases alike the middle terms 
are known, and that middles which are prior are better known 
than such as are posterior, we may suppose two demonstrations 
of the inherence of A in E, the one proving it through the 
middles B, C and D, the other through F and G. Then A-D is 
known to the same degree as A-E (in the second proof), but A-D 
is better known than and prior to A-E (in the first proof); since 
A-E is proved through A-D, and the ground is more certain than 
the conclusion. 

Hence demonstration by fewer premisses is ceteris paribus 
superior. Now both affirmative and negative demonstration 
operate through three terms and two premisses, but whereas 
the former assumes only that something is, the latter assumes 
both that something is and that something else is not, and thus 
operating through more kinds of premiss is inferior. 

(2) It has been proved that no conclusion follows if both 
premisses are negative, but that one must be negative, the other 
affirmative. So we are compelled to lay down the following 
additional rule: as the demonstration expands, the affirmative 
premisses must increase in number, but there cannot be more 
than one negative premiss in each complete proof. Thus, 
suppose no B is A, and all C is B. Then if both the premisses are 
to be again expanded, a middle must be interposed. Let us 
interpose D between A and B, and E between B and C. Then 
clearly E is affirmatively related to B and C, while D is 
affirmatively related to B but negatively to A; for all B is D, but 
there must be no D which is A. Thus there proves to be a single 
negative premiss, A-D. In the further prosyllogisms too it is the 
same, because in the terms of an affirmative syllogism the 



276 



middle is always related affirmatively to both extremes; in a 
negative syllogism it must be negatively related only to one of 
them, and so this negation comes to be a single negative 
premiss, the other premisses being affirmative. If, then, that 
through which a truth is proved is a better known and more 
certain truth, and if the negative proposition is proved through 
the affirmative and not vice versa, affirmative demonstration, 
being prior and better known and more certain, will be superior. 

(3) The basic truth of demonstrative syllogism is the universal 
immediate premiss, and the universal premiss asserts in 
affirmative demonstration and in negative denies: and the 
affirmative proposition is prior to and better known than the 
negative (since affirmation explains denial and is prior to 
denial, just as being is prior to not-being). It follows that the 
basic premiss of affirmative demonstration is superior to that of 
negative demonstration, and the demonstration which uses 
superior basic premisses is superior. 

(4) Affirmative demonstration is more of the nature of a basic 
form of proof, because it is a sine qua non of negative 
demonstration. 



26 

Since affirmative demonstration is superior to negative, it is 
clearly superior also to reductio ad impossibile. We must first 
make certain what is the difference between negative 
demonstration and reductio ad impossibile. Let us suppose that 
no B is A, and that all C is B: the conclusion necessarily follows 
that no C is A. If these premisses are assumed, therefore, the 
negative demonstration that no C is A is direct. Reductio ad 
impossibile, on the other hand, proceeds as follows. Supposing 



277 



we are to prove that does not inhere in B, we have to assume 
that it does inhere, and further that B inheres in C, with the 
resulting inference that A inheres in C. This we have to suppose 
a known and admitted impossibility; and we then infer that A 
cannot inhere in B. Thus if the inherence of B in C is not 
questioned, As inherence in B is impossible. 

The order of the terms is the same in both proofs: they differ 
according to which of the negative propositions is the better 
known, the one denying A of B or the one denying A of C. When 
the falsity of the conclusion is the better known, we use 
reductio ad impossible; when the major premiss of the 
syllogism is the more obvious, we use direct demonstration. All 
the same the proposition denying A of B is, in the order of being, 
prior to that denying A of C; for premisses are prior to the 
conclusion which follows from them, and 'no C is A is the 
conclusion, 'no B is A one of its premisses. For the destructive 
result of reductio ad impossibile is not a proper conclusion, nor 
are its antecedents proper premisses. On the contrary: the 
constituents of syllogism are premisses related to one another 
as whole to part or part to whole, whereas the premisses A-C 
and A-B are not thus related to one another. Now the superior 
demonstration is that which proceeds from better known and 
prior premisses, and while both these forms depend for 
credence on the not-being of something, yet the source of the 
one is prior to that of the other. Therefore negative 
demonstration will have an unqualified superiority to reductio 
ad impossibile, and affirmative demonstration, being superior to 
negative, will consequently be superior also to reductio ad 
impossibile. 



278 



27 

The science which is knowledge at once of the fact and of the 
reasoned fact, not of the fact by itself without the reasoned fact, 
is the more exact and the prior science. 

A science such as arithmetic, which is not a science of 
properties qua inhering in a substratum, is more exact than and 
prior to a science like harmonics, which is a science of 
properties inhering in a substratum; and similarly a science like 
arithmetic, which is constituted of fewer basic elements, is 
more exact than and prior to geometry, which requires 
additional elements. What I mean by 'additional elements' is 
this: a unit is substance without position, while a point is 
substance with position; the latter contains an additional 
element. 



28 

A single science is one whose domain is a single genus, viz. all 
the subjects constituted out of the primary entities of the genus 
- i.e. the parts of this total subject - and their essential 
properties. 

One science differs from another when their basic truths have 
neither a common source nor are derived those of the one 
science from those the other. This is verified when we reach the 
indemonstrable premisses of a science, for they must be within 
one genus with its conclusions: and this again is verified if the 
conclusions proved by means of them fall within one genus - 
i.e. are homogeneous. 



279 



29 

One can have several demonstrations of the same connexion 
not only by taking from the same series of predication middles 
which are other than the immediately cohering term e.g. by 
taking C, D, and F severally to prove A-B - but also by taking a 
middle from another series. Thus let A be change, D alteration 
of a property, B feeling pleasure, and G relaxation. We can then 
without falsehood predicate D of B and A of D, for he who is 
pleased suffers alteration of a property, and that which alters a 
property changes. Again, we can predicate A of G without 
falsehood, and G of B; for to feel pleasure is to relax, and to relax 
is to change. So the conclusion can be drawn through middles 
which are different, i.e. not in the same series - yet not so that 
neither of these middles is predicable of the other, for they must 
both be attributable to some one subject. 

A further point worth investigating is how many ways of 
proving the same conclusion can be obtained by varying the 
figure. 



30 

There is no knowledge by demonstration of chance 
conjunctions; for chance conjunctions exist neither by necessity 
nor as general connexions but comprise what comes to be as 
something distinct from these. Now demonstration is 
concerned only with one or other of these two; for all reasoning 
proceeds from necessary or general premisses, the conclusion 
being necessary if the premisses are necessary and general if 



280 



the premisses are general. Consequently, if chance conjunctions 
are neither general nor necessary, they are not demonstrable. 



31 

Scientific knowledge is not possible through the act of 
perception. Even if perception as a faculty is of 'the such' and 
not merely of a 'this somewhat', yet one must at any rate 
actually perceive a 'this somewhat', and at a definite present 
place and time: but that which is commensurately universal 
and true in all cases one cannot perceive, since it is not 'this' 
and it is not 'now'; if it were, it would not be commensurately 
universal - the term we apply to what is always and 
everywhere. Seeing, therefore, that demonstrations are 
commensurately universal and universals imperceptible, we 
clearly cannot obtain scientific knowledge by the act of 
perception: nay, it is obvious that even if it were possible to 
perceive that a triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, 
we should still be looking for a demonstration - we should not 
(as some say) possess knowledge of it; for perception must be of 
a particular, whereas scientific knowledge involves the 
recognition of the commensurate universal. So if we were on 
the moon, and saw the earth shutting out the sun's light, we 
should not know the cause of the eclipse: we should perceive 
the present fact of the eclipse, but not the reasoned fact at all, 
since the act of perception is not of the commensurate 
universal. I do not, of course, deny that by watching the 
frequent recurrence of this event we might, after tracking the 
commensurate universal, possess a demonstration, for the 
commensurate universal is elicited from the several groups of 
singulars. 



281 



The commensurate universal is precious because it makes clear 
the cause; so that in the case of facts like these which have a 
cause other than themselves universal knowledge is more 
precious than sense-perceptions and than intuition. (As regards 
primary truths there is of course a different account to be 
given.) Hence it is clear that knowledge of things demonstrable 
cannot be acquired by perception, unless the term perception is 
applied to the possession of scientific knowledge through 
demonstration. Nevertheless certain points do arise with regard 
to connexions to be proved which are referred for their 
explanation to a failure in sense-perception: there are cases 
when an act of vision would terminate our inquiry, not because 
in seeing we should be knowing, but because we should have 
elicited the universal from seeing; if, for example, we saw the 
pores in the glass and the light passing through, the reason of 
the kindling would be clear to us because we should at the 
same time see it in each instance and intuit that it must be so 
in all instances. 



32 

All syllogisms cannot have the same basic truths. This may be 
shown first of all by the following dialectical considerations. (1) 
Some syllogisms are true and some false: for though a true 
inference is possible from false premisses, yet this occurs once 
only - I mean if A for instance, is truly predicable of C, but B, the 
middle, is false, both A-B and B-C being false; nevertheless, if 
middles are taken to prove these premisses, they will be false 
because every conclusion which is a falsehood has false 
premisses, while true conclusions have true premisses, and 
false and true differ in kind. Then again, (2) falsehoods are not 
all derived from a single identical set of principles: there are 



282 



falsehoods which are the contraries of one another and cannot 
coexist, e.g. 'justice is injustice', and 'justice is cowardice'; 'man 
is horse', and 'man is ox'; 'the equal is greater', and 'the equal is 
less.' From established principles we may argue the case as 
follows, confining ourselves therefore to true conclusions. Not 
even all these are inferred from the same basic truths; many of 
them in fact have basic truths which differ generically and are 
not transferable; units, for instance, which are without position, 
cannot take the place of points, which have position. The 
transferred terms could only fit in as middle terms or as major 
or minor terms, or else have some of the other terms between 
them, others outside them. 

Nor can any of the common axioms - such, I mean, as the law 
of excluded middle - serve as premisses for the proof of all 
conclusions. For the kinds of being are different, and some 
attributes attach to quanta and some to qualia only; and proof 
is achieved by means of the common axioms taken in 
conjunction with these several kinds and their attributes. 

Again, it is not true that the basic truths are much fewer than 
the conclusions, for the basic truths are the premisses, and the 
premisses are formed by the apposition of a fresh extreme term 
or the interposition of a fresh middle. Moreover, the number of 
conclusions is indefinite, though the number of middle terms is 
finite; and lastly some of the basic truths are necessary, others 
variable. 

Looking at it in this way we see that, since the number of 
conclusions is indefinite, the basic truths cannot be identical or 
limited in number. If, on the other hand, identity is used in 
another sense, and it is said, e.g. 'these and no other are the 
fundamental truths of geometry, these the fundamentals of 
calculation, these again of medicine'; would the statement 
mean anything except that the sciences have basic truths? To 



283 



call them identical because they are self-identical is absurd, 
since everything can be identified with everything in that sense 
of identity. Nor again can the contention that all conclusions 
have the same basic truths mean that from the mass of all 
possible premisses any conclusion may be drawn. That would 
be exceedingly naive, for it is not the case in the clearly evident 
mathematical sciences, nor is it possible in analysis, since it is 
the immediate premisses which are the basic truths, and a 
fresh conclusion is only formed by the addition of a new 
immediate premiss: but if it be admitted that it is these primary 
immediate premisses which are basic truths, each subject- 
genus will provide one basic truth. If, however, it is not argued 
that from the mass of all possible premisses any conclusion 
may be proved, nor yet admitted that basic truths differ so as to 
be generically different for each science, it remains to consider 
the possibility that, while the basic truths of all knowledge are 
within one genus, special premisses are required to prove 
special conclusions. But that this cannot be the case has been 
shown by our proof that the basic truths of things generically 
different themselves differ generically. For fundamental truths 
are of two kinds, those which are premisses of demonstration 
and the subject-genus; and though the former are common, the 
latter - number, for instance, and magnitude - are peculiar. 



33 

Scientific knowledge and its object differ from opinion and the 
object of opinion in that scientific knowledge is 
commensurately universal and proceeds by necessary 
connexions, and that which is necessary cannot be otherwise. 
So though there are things which are true and real and yet can 
be otherwise, scientific knowledge clearly does not concern 



284 



them: if it did, things which can be otherwise would be 
incapable of being otherwise. Nor are they any concern of 
rational intuition - by rational intuition I mean an originative 
source of scientific knowledge - nor of indemonstrable 
knowledge, which is the grasping of the immediate premiss. 
Since then rational intuition, science, and opinion, and what is 
revealed by these terms, are the only things that can be 'true', it 
follows that it is opinion that is concerned with that which may 
be true or false, and can be otherwise: opinion in fact is the 
grasp of a premiss which is immediate but not necessary. This 
view also fits the observed facts, for opinion is unstable, and so 
is the kind of being we have described as its object. Besides, 
when a man thinks a truth incapable of being otherwise he 
always thinks that he knows it, never that he opines it. He 
thinks that he opines when he thinks that a connexion, though 
actually so, may quite easily be otherwise; for he believes that 
such is the proper object of opinion, while the necessary is the 
object of knowledge. 

In what sense, then, can the same thing be the object of both 
opinion and knowledge? And if any one chooses to maintain 
that all that he knows he can also opine, why should not 
opinion be knowledge? For he that knows and he that opines 
will follow the same train of thought through the same middle 
terms until the immediate premisses are reached; because it is 
possible to opine not only the fact but also the reasoned fact, 
and the reason is the middle term; so that, since the former 
knows, he that opines also has knowledge. 

The truth perhaps is that if a man grasp truths that cannot be 
other than they are, in the way in which he grasps the 
definitions through which demonstrations take place, he will 
have not opinion but knowledge: if on the other hand he 
apprehends these attributes as inhering in their subjects, but 
not in virtue of the subjects' substance and essential nature 



285 



possesses opinion and not genuine knowledge; and his opinion, 
if obtained through immediate premisses, will be both of the 
fact and of the reasoned fact; if not so obtained, of the fact 
alone. The object of opinion and knowledge is not quite 
identical; it is only in a sense identical, just as the object of true 
and false opinion is in a sense identical. The sense in which 
some maintain that true and false opinion can have the same 
object leads them to embrace many strange doctrines, 
particularly the doctrine that what a man opines falsely he does 
not opine at all. There are really many senses of 'identical', and 
in one sense the object of true and false opinion can be the 
same, in another it cannot. Thus, to have a true opinion that the 
diagonal is commensurate with the side would be absurd: but 
because the diagonal with which they are both concerned is the 
same, the two opinions have objects so far the same: on the 
other hand, as regards their essential definable nature these 
objects differ. The identity of the objects of knowledge and 
opinion is similar. Knowledge is the apprehension of, e.g. the 
attribute 'animal' as incapable of being otherwise, opinion the 
apprehension of 'animal' as capable of being otherwise - e.g. the 
apprehension that animal is an element in the essential nature 
of man is knowledge; the apprehension of animal as predicable 
of man but not as an element in man's essential nature is 
opinion: man is the subject in both judgements, but the mode 
of inherence differs. 

This also shows that one cannot opine and know the same 
thing simultaneously; for then one would apprehend the same 
thing as both capable and incapable of being otherwise - an 
impossibility. Knowledge and opinion of the same thing can co- 
exist in two different people in the sense we have explained, 
but not simultaneously in the same person. That would involve 
a man's simultaneously apprehending, e.g. (1) that man is 
essentially animal - i.e. cannot be other than animal - and (2) 



286 



that man is not essentially animal, that is, we may assume, may 
be other than animal. 

Further consideration of modes of thinking and their 
distribution under the heads of discursive thought, intuition, 
science, art, practical wisdom, and metaphysical thinking, 
belongs rather partly to natural science, partly to moral 
philosophy. 



34 

Quick wit is a faculty of hitting upon the middle term 
instantaneously. It would be exemplified by a man who saw 
that the moon has her bright side always turned towards the 
sun, and quickly grasped the cause of this, namely that she 
borrows her light from him; or observed somebody in 
conversation with a man of wealth and divined that he was 
borrowing money, or that the friendship of these people sprang 
from a common enmity. In all these instances he has seen the 
major and minor terms and then grasped the causes, the 
middle terms. 

Let A represent 'bright side turned sunward', B 'lighted from the 
sun', C the moon. Then B, 'lighted from the sun' is predicable of 
C, the moon, and A, 'having her bright side towards the source 
of her light', is predicable of B. So A is predicable of C through B. 



287 



Book II 



The kinds of question we ask are as many as the kinds of things 
which we know. They are in fact four: - (1) whether the 
connexion of an attribute with a thing is a fact, (2) what is the 
reason of the connexion, (3) whether a thing exists, (4) What is 
the nature of the thing. Thus, when our question concerns a 
complex of thing and attribute and we ask whether the thing is 
thus or otherwise qualified - whether, e.g. the sun suffers 
eclipse or not - then we are asking as to the fact of a connexion. 
That our inquiry ceases with the discovery that the sun does 
suffer eclipse is an indication of this; and if we know from the 
start that the sun suffers eclipse, we do not inquire whether it 
does so or not. On the other hand, when we know the fact we 
ask the reason; as, for example, when we know that the sun is 
being eclipsed and that an earthquake is in progress, it is the 
reason of eclipse or earthquake into which we inquire. 

Where a complex is concerned, then, those are the two 
questions we ask; but for some objects of inquiry we have a 
different kind of question to ask, such as whether there is or is 
not a centaur or a God. (By 'is or is not' I mean 'is or is not, 
without further qualification'; as opposed to 'is or is not [e.g.] 
white'.) On the other hand, when we have ascertained the 
thing's existence, we inquire as to its nature, asking, for 
instance, 'what, then, is God?' or 'what is man?'. 



288 



These, then, are the four kinds of question we ask, and it is in 
the answers to these questions that our knowledge consists. 

Now when we ask whether a connexion is a fact, or whether a 
thing without qualification is, we are really asking whether the 
connexion or the thing has a 'middle'; and when we have 
ascertained either that the connexion is a fact or that the thing 
is - i.e. ascertained either the partial or the unqualified being of 
the thing-and are proceeding to ask the reason of the connexion 
or the nature of the thing, then we are asking what the 'middle' 
is. 

(By distinguishing the fact of the connexion and the existence 
of the thing as respectively the partial and the unqualified being 
of the thing, I mean that if we ask 'does the moon suffer 
eclipse?', or 'does the moon wax?', the question concerns a part 
of the thing's being; for what we are asking in such questions is 
whether a thing is this or that, i.e. has or has not this or that 
attribute: whereas, if we ask whether the moon or night exists, 
the question concerns the unqualified being of a thing.) 

We conclude that in all our inquiries we are asking either 
whether there is a 'middle' or what the 'middle' is: for the 
'middle' here is precisely the cause, and it is the cause that we 
seek in all our inquiries. Thus, 'Does the moon suffer eclipse?' 
means 'Is there or is there not a cause producing eclipse of the 
moon?', and when we have learnt that there is, our next 
question is, 'What, then, is this cause? for the cause through 
which a thing is - not is this or that, i.e. has this or that 
attribute, but without qualification is - and the cause through 
which it is - not is without qualification, but is this or that as 
having some essential attribute or some accident - are both 
alike the middle'. By that which is without qualification I mean 
the subject, e.g. moon or earth or sun or triangle; by that which 



289 



a subject is (in the partial sense) I mean a property, e.g. eclipse, 
equality or inequality, interposition or non-interposition. For in 
all these examples it is clear that the nature of the thing and 
the reason of the fact are identical: the question 'What is 
eclipse?' and its answer 'The privation of the moon's light by the 
interposition of the earth' are identical with the question 'What 
is the reason of eclipse?' or 'Why does the moon suffer eclipse?' 
and the reply 'Because of the failure of light through the earth's 
shutting it out'. Again, for 'What is a concord? A commensurate 
numerical ratio of a high and a low note', we may substitute 
'What ratio makes a high and a low note concordant? Their 
relation according to a commensurate numerical ratio.' 'Are the 
high and the low note concordant?' is equivalent to 'Is their 
ratio commensurate?'; and when we find that it is 
commensurate, we ask 'What, then, is their ratio?'. 

Cases in which the 'middle' is sensible show that the object of 
our inquiry is always the 'middle': we inquire, because we have 
not perceived it, whether there is or is not a 'middle' causing, 
e.g. an eclipse. On the other hand, if we were on the moon we 
should not be inquiring either as to the fact or the reason, but 
both fact and reason would be obvious simultaneously. For the 
act of perception would have enabled us to know the universal 
too; since, the present fact of an eclipse being evident, 
perception would then at the same time give us the present fact 
of the earth's screening the sun's light, and from this would 
arise the universal. 

Thus, as we maintain, to know a thing's nature is to know the 
reason why it is; and this is equally true of things in so far as 
they are said without qualification to he as opposed to being 
possessed of some attribute, and in so far as they are said to be 
possessed of some attribute such as equal to right angles, or 
greater or less. 



290 



It is clear, then, that all questions are a search for a 'middle'. Let 
us now state how essential nature is revealed and in what way 
it can be reduced to demonstration; what definition is, and 
what things are definable. And let us first discuss certain 
difficulties which these questions raise, beginning what we 
have to say with a point most intimately connected with our 
immediately preceding remarks, namely the doubt that might 
be felt as to whether or not it is possible to know the same thing 
in the same relation, both by definition and by demonstration. It 
might, I mean, be urged that definition is held to concern 
essential nature and is in every case universal and affirmative; 
whereas, on the other hand, some conclusions are negative and 
some are not universal; e.g. all in the second figure are negative, 
none in the third are universal. And again, not even all 
affirmative conclusions in the first figure are definable, e.g. 
'every triangle has its angles equal to two right angles'. An 
argument proving this difference between demonstration and 
definition is that to have scientific knowledge of the 
demonstrable is identical with possessing a demonstration of it: 
hence if demonstration of such conclusions as these is possible, 
there clearly cannot also be definition of them. If there could, 
one might know such a conclusion also in virtue of its 
definition without possessing the demonstration of it; for there 
is nothing to stop our having the one without the other. 

Induction too will sufficiently convince us of this difference; for 
never yet by defining anything - essential attribute or accident - 
did we get knowledge of it. Again, if to define is to acquire 
knowledge of a substance, at any rate such attributes are not 
substances. 



291 



It is evident, then, that not everything demonstrable can be 
defined. What then? Can everything definable be demonstrated, 
or not? There is one of our previous arguments which covers 
this too. Of a single thing qua single there is a single scientific 
knowledge. Hence, since to know the demonstrable 
scientifically is to possess the demonstration of it, an 
impossible consequence will follow: - possession of its 
definition without its demonstration will give knowledge of the 
demonstrable. 

Moreover, the basic premisses of demonstrations are 
definitions, and it has already been shown that these will be 
found indemonstrable; either the basic premisses will be 
demonstrable and will depend on prior premisses, and the 
regress will be endless; or the primary truths will be 
indemonstrable definitions. 

But if the definable and the demonstrable are not wholly the 
same, may they yet be partially the same? Or is that impossible, 
because there can be no demonstration of the definable? There 
can be none, because definition is of the essential nature or 
being of something, and all demonstrations evidently posit and 
assume the essential nature - mathematical demonstrations, 
for example, the nature of unity and the odd, and all the other 
sciences likewise. Moreover, every demonstration proves a 
predicate of a subject as attaching or as not attaching to it, but 
in definition one thing is not predicated of another; we do not, 
e.g. predicate animal of biped nor biped of animal, nor yet figure 
of plane - plane not being figure nor figure plane. Again, to 
prove essential nature is not the same as to prove the fact of a 
connexion. Now definition reveals essential nature, 
demonstration reveals that a given attribute attaches or does 
not attach to a given subject; but different things require 
different demonstrations - unless the one demonstration is 
related to the other as part to whole. I add this because if all 



292 



triangles have been proved to possess angles equal to two right 
angles, then this attribute has been proved to attach to 
isosceles; for isosceles is a part of which all triangles constitute 
the whole. But in the case before us the fact and the essential 
nature are not so related to one another, since the one is not a 
part of the other. 

So it emerges that not all the definable is demonstrable nor all 
the demonstrable definable; and we may draw the general 
conclusion that there is no identical object of which it is 
possible to possess both a definition and a demonstration. It 
follows obviously that definition and demonstration are neither 
identical nor contained either within the other: if they were, 
their objects would be related either as identical or as whole 
and part. 



So much, then, for the first stage of our problem. The next step 
is to raise the question whether syllogism - i.e. demonstration - 
of the definable nature is possible or, as our recent argument 
assumed, impossible. 

We might argue it impossible on the following grounds: - (a) 
syllogism proves an attribute of a subject through the middle 
term; on the other hand (b) its definable nature is both 'peculiar' 
to a subject and predicated of it as belonging to its essence. But 
in that case (1) the subject, its definition, and the middle term 
connecting them must be reciprocally predicable of one 
another; for if A is to C, obviously A is 'peculiar' to B and B to C - 
in fact all three terms are 'peculiar' to one another: and further 
(2) if A inheres in the essence of all B and B is predicated 



293 



universally of all C as belonging to C's essence, A also must be 
predicated of C as belonging to its essence. 

If one does not take this relation as thus duplicated - if, that is, 
A is predicated as being of the essence of B, but B is not of the 
essence of the subjects of which it is predicated - A will not 
necessarily be predicated of C as belonging to its essence. So 
both premisses will predicate essence, and consequently B also 
will be predicated of C as its essence. Since, therefore, both 
premisses do predicate essence - i.e. definable form - C's 
definable form will appear in the middle term before the 
conclusion is drawn. 

We may generalize by supposing that it is possible to prove the 
essential nature of man. Let C be man, A man's essential nature 
- two-footed animal, or aught else it may be. Then, if we are to 
syllogize, A must be predicated of all B. But this premiss will be 
mediated by a fresh definition, which consequently will also be 
the essential nature of man. Therefore the argument assumes 
what it has to prove, since B too is the essential nature of man. 
It is, however, the case in which there are only the two 
premisses - i.e. in which the premisses are primary and 
immediate - which we ought to investigate, because it best 
illustrates the point under discussion. 

Thus they who prove the essential nature of soul or man or 
anything else through reciprocating terms beg the question. It 
would be begging the question, for example, to contend that the 
soul is that which causes its own life, and that what causes its 
own life is a self-moving number; for one would have to 
postulate that the soul is a self-moving number in the sense of 
being identical with it. For if A is predicable as a mere 
consequent of B and B of C, A will not on that account be the 
definable form of C: A will merely be what it was true to say of 
C. Even if A is predicated of all B inasmuch as B is identical with 



294 



a species of A, still it will not follow: being an animal is 
predicated of being a man - since it is true that in all instances 
to be human is to be animal, just as it is also true that every 
man is an animal - but not as identical with being man. 

We conclude, then, that unless one takes both the premisses as 
predicating essence, one cannot infer that A is the definable 
form and essence of C: but if one does so take them, in 
assuming B one will have assumed, before drawing the 
conclusion, what the definable form of C is; so that there has 
been no inference, for one has begged the question. 



Nor, as was said in my formal logic, is the method of division a 
process of inference at all, since at no point does the 
characterization of the subject follow necessarily from the 
premising of certain other facts: division demonstrates as little 
as does induction. For in a genuine demonstration the 
conclusion must not be put as a question nor depend on a 
concession, but must follow necessarily from its premisses, 
even if the respondent deny it. The definer asks 'Is man animal 
or inanimate?' and then assumes - he has not inferred - that 
man is animal. Next, when presented with an exhaustive 
division of animal into terrestrial and aquatic, he assumes that 
man is terrestrial. Moreover, that man is the complete formula, 
terrestrial-animal, does not follow necessarily from the 
premisses: this too is an assumption, and equally an 
assumption whether the division comprises many differentiae 
or few. (Indeed as this method of division is used by those who 
proceed by it, even truths that can be inferred actually fail to 
appear as such.) For why should not the whole of this formula 



295 



be true of man, and yet not exhibit his essential nature or 
definable form? Again, what guarantee is there against an 
unessential addition, or against the omission of the final or of 
an intermediate determinant of the substantial being? 

The champion of division might here urge that though these 
lapses do occur, yet we can solve that difficulty if all the 
attributes we assume are constituents of the definable form, 
and if, postulating the genus, we produce by division the 
requisite uninterrupted sequence of terms, and omit nothing; 
and that indeed we cannot fail to fulfil these conditions if what 
is to be divided falls whole into the division at each stage, and 
none of it is omitted; and that this - the dividendum - must 
without further question be (ultimately) incapable of fresh 
specific division. Nevertheless, we reply, division does not 
involve inference; if it gives knowledge, it gives it in another 
way. Nor is there any absurdity in this: induction, perhaps, is 
not demonstration any more than is division, et it does make 
evident some truth. Yet to state a definition reached by division 
is not to state a conclusion: as, when conclusions are drawn 
without their appropriate middles, the alleged necessity by 
which the inference follows from the premisses is open to a 
question as to the reason for it, so definitions reached by 
division invite the same question. 

Thus to the question 'What is the essential nature of man?' the 
divider replies 'Animal, mortal, footed, biped, wingless'; and 
when at each step he is asked 'Why?', he will say, and, as he 
thinks, proves by division, that all animal is mortal or immortal: 
but such a formula taken in its entirety is not definition; so that 
even if division does demonstrate its formula, definition at any 
rate does not turn out to be a conclusion of inference. 



296 



Can we nevertheless actually demonstrate what a thing 
essentially and substantially is, but hypothetically, i.e. by 
premising (1) that its definable form is constituted by the 
'peculiar' attributes of its essential nature; (2) that such and 
such are the only attributes of its essential nature, and that the 
complete synthesis of them is peculiar to the thing; and thus - 
since in this synthesis consists the being of the thing - 
obtaining our conclusion? Or is the truth that, since proof must 
be through the middle term, the definable form is once more 
assumed in this minor premiss too? 

Further, just as in syllogizing we do not premise what syllogistic 
inference is (since the premisses from which we conclude must 
be related as whole and part), so the definable form must not 
fall within the syllogism but remain outside the premisses 
posited. It is only against a doubt as to its having been a 
syllogistic inference at all that we have to defend our argument 
as conforming to the definition of syllogism. It is only when 
some one doubts whether the conclusion proved is the 
definable form that we have to defend it as conforming to the 
definition of definable form which we assumed. Hence 
syllogistic inference must be possible even without the express 
statement of what syllogism is or what definable form is. 

The following type of hypothetical proof also begs the question. 
If evil is definable as the divisible, and the definition of a thing's 
contrary - if it has one the contrary of the thing's definition; 
then, if good is the contrary of evil and the indivisible of the 
divisible, we conclude that to be good is essentially to be 
indivisible. The question is begged because definable form is 
assumed as a premiss, and as a premiss which is to prove 
definable form. 'But not the same definable form', you may 
object. That I admit, for in demonstrations also we premise that 



297 



'this' is predicable of 'that'; but in this premiss the term we 
assert of the minor is neither the major itself nor a term 
identical in definition, or convertible, with the major. 

Again, both proof by division and the syllogism just described 
are open to the question why man should be animal-biped- 
terrestrial and not merely animal and terrestrial, since what 
they premise does not ensure that the predicates shall 
constitute a genuine unity and not merely belong to a single 
subject as do musical and grammatical when predicated of the 
same man. 



How then by definition shall we prove substance or essential 
nature? We cannot show it as a fresh fact necessarily following 
from the assumption of premisses admitted to be facts - the 
method of demonstration: we may not proceed as by induction 
to establish a universal on the evidence of groups of particulars 
which offer no exception, because induction proves not what 
the essential nature of a thing is but that it has or has not some 
attribute. Therefore, since presumably one cannot prove 
essential nature by an appeal to sense perception or by pointing 
with the finger, what other method remains? 

To put it another way: how shall we by definition prove 
essential nature? He who knows what human - or any other - 
nature is, must know also that man exists; for no one knows the 
nature of what does not exist - one can know the meaning of 
the phrase or name 'goat-stag' but not what the essential 
nature of a goat-stag is. But further, if definition can prove what 
is the essential nature of a thing, can it also prove that it exists? 
And how will it prove them both by the same process, since 



298 



definition exhibits one single thing and demonstration another 
single thing, and what human nature is and the fact that man 
exists are not the same thing? Then too we hold that it is by 
demonstration that the being of everything must be proved - 
unless indeed to be were its essence; and, since being is not a 
genus, it is not the essence of anything. Hence the being of 
anything as fact is matter for demonstration; and this is the 
actual procedure of the sciences, for the geometer assumes the 
meaning of the word triangle, but that it is possessed of some 
attribute he proves. What is it, then, that we shall prove in 
defining essential nature? Triangle? In that case a man will 
know by definition what a thing's nature is without knowing 
whether it exists. But that is impossible. 

Moreover it is clear, if we consider the methods of defining 
actually in use, that definition does not prove that the thing 
defined exists: since even if there does actually exist something 
which is equidistant from a centre, yet why should the thing 
named in the definition exist? Why, in other words, should this 
be the formula defining circle? One might equally well call it the 
definition of mountain copper. For definitions do not carry a 
further guarantee that the thing defined can exist or that it is 
what they claim to define: one can always ask why. 

Since, therefore, to define is to prove either a thing's essential 
nature or the meaning of its name, we may conclude that 
definition, if it in no sense proves essential nature, is a set of 
words signifying precisely what a name signifies. But that were 
a strange consequence; for (1) both what is not substance and 
what does not exist at all would be definable, since even non- 
existents can be signified by a name: (2) all sets of words or 
sentences would be definitions, since any kind of sentence 
could be given a name; so that we should all be talking in 
definitions, and even the Iliad would be a definition: (3) no 
demonstration can prove that any particular name means any 



299 



particular thing: neither, therefore, do definitions, in addition to 
revealing the meaning of a name, also reveal that the name has 
this meaning. It appears then from these considerations that 
neither definition and syllogism nor their objects are identical, 
and further that definition neither demonstrates nor proves 
anything, and that knowledge of essential nature is not to be 
obtained either by definition or by demonstration. 



8 

We must now start afresh and consider which of these 
conclusions are sound and which are not, and what is the 
nature of definition, and whether essential nature is in any 
sense demonstrable and definable or in none. 

Now to know its essential nature is, as we said, the same as to 
know the cause of a thing's existence, and the proof of this 
depends on the fact that a thing must have a cause. Moreover, 
this cause is either identical with the essential nature of the 
thing or distinct from it; and if its cause is distinct from it, the 
essential nature of the thing is either demonstrable or 
indemonstrable. Consequently, if the cause is distinct from the 
thing's essential nature and demonstration is possible, the 
cause must be the middle term, and, the conclusion proved 
being universal and affirmative, the proof is in the first figure. 
So the method just examined of proving it through another 
essential nature would be one way of proving essential nature, 
because a conclusion containing essential nature must be 
inferred through a middle which is an essential nature just as a 
'peculiar' property must be inferred through a middle which is a 
'peculiar' property; so that of the two definable natures of a 
single thing this method will prove one and not the other. 



300 



Now it was said before that this method could not amount to 
demonstration of essential nature - it is actually a dialectical 
proof of it - so let us begin again and explain by what method it 
can be demonstrated. When we are aware of a fact we seek its 
reason, and though sometimes the fact and the reason dawn on 
us simultaneously, yet we cannot apprehend the reason a 
moment sooner than the fact; and clearly in just the same way 
we cannot apprehend a thing's definable form without 
apprehending that it exists, since while we are ignorant 
whether it exists we cannot know its essential nature. Moreover 
we are aware whether a thing exists or not sometimes through 
apprehending an element in its character, and sometimes 
accidentally, as, for example, when we are aware of thunder as a 
noise in the clouds, of eclipse as a privation of light, or of man 
as some species of animal, or of the soul as a self-moving thing. 
As often as we have accidental knowledge that the thing exists, 
we must be in a wholly negative state as regards awareness of 
its essential nature; for we have not got genuine knowledge 
even of its existence, and to search for a thing's essential nature 
when we are unaware that it exists is to search for nothing. On 
the other hand, whenever we apprehend an element in the 
thing's character there is less difficulty. Thus it follows that the 
degree of our knowledge of a thing's essential nature is 
determined by the sense in which we are aware that it exists. 
Let us then take the following as our first instance of being 
aware of an element in the essential nature. Let A be eclipse, C 
the moon, B the earth's acting as a screen. Now to ask whether 
the moon is eclipsed or not is to ask whether or not B has 
occurred. But that is precisely the same as asking whether A has 
a defining condition; and if this condition actually exists, we 
assert that A also actually exists. Or again we may ask which 
side of a contradiction the defining condition necessitates: does 
it make the angles of a triangle equal or not equal to two right 
angles? When we have found the answer, if the premisses are 



301 



immediate, we know fact and reason together; if they are not 
immediate, we know the fact without the reason, as in the 
following example: let C be the moon, A eclipse, B the fact that 
the moon fails to produce shadows though she is full and 
though no visible body intervenes between us and her. Then if 
B, failure to produce shadows in spite of the absence of an 
intervening body, is attributable A to C, and eclipse, is 
attributable to B, it is clear that the moon is eclipsed, but the 
reason why is not yet clear, and we know that eclipse exists, but 
we do not know what its essential nature is. But when it is clear 
that A is attributable to C and we proceed to ask the reason of 
this fact, we are inquiring what is the nature of B: is it the 
earth's acting as a screen, or the moon's rotation or her 
extinction? But B is the definition of the other term, viz. in these 
examples, of the major term A; for eclipse is constituted by the 
earth acting as a screen. Thus, (1) 'What is thunder?' 'The 
quenching of fire in cloud', and (2) 'Why does it thunder?' 
'Because fire is quenched in the cloud', are equivalent. Let C be 
cloud, A thunder, B the quenching of fire. Then B is attributable 
to C, cloud, since fire is quenched in it; and A, noise, is 
attributable to B; and B is assuredly the definition of the major 
term A. If there be a further mediating cause of B, it will be one 
of the remaining partial definitions of A. 

We have stated then how essential nature is discovered and 
becomes known, and we see that, while there is no syllogism - 
i.e. no demonstrative syllogism - of essential nature, yet it is 
through syllogism, viz. demonstrative syllogism, that essential 
nature is exhibited. So we conclude that neither can the 
essential nature of anything which has a cause distinct from 
itself be known without demonstration, nor can it be 
demonstrated; and this is what we contended in our 
preliminary discussions. 



302 



Now while some things have a cause distinct from themselves, 
others have not. Hence it is evident that there are essential 
natures which are immediate, that is are basic premisses; and 
of these not only that they are but also what they are must be 
assumed or revealed in some other way. This too is the actual 
procedure of the arithmetician, who assumes both the nature 
and the existence of unit. On the other hand, it is possible (in 
the manner explained) to exhibit through demonstration the 
essential nature of things which have a 'middle', i.e. a cause of 
their substantial being other than that being itself; but we do 
not thereby demonstrate it. 



10 

Since definition is said to be the statement of a thing's nature, 
obviously one kind of definition will be a statement of the 
meaning of the name, or of an equivalent nominal formula. A 
definition in this sense tells you, e.g. the meaning of the phrase 
'triangular character'. When we are aware that triangle exists, 
we inquire the reason why it exists. But it is difficult thus to 
learn the definition of things the existence of which we do not 
genuinely know - the cause of this difficulty being, as we said 
before, that we only know accidentally whether or not the thing 
exists. Moreover, a statement may be a unity in either of two 
ways, by conjunction, like the Iliad, or because it exhibits a 
single predicate as inhering not accidentally in a single subject. 

That then is one way of defining definition. Another kind of 
definition is a formula exhibiting the cause of a thing's 



303 



existence. Thus the former signifies without proving, but the 
latter will clearly be a quasi-demonstration of essential nature, 
differing from demonstration in the arrangement of its terms. 
For there is a difference between stating why it thunders, and 
stating what is the essential nature of thunder; since the first 
statement will be 'Because fire is quenched in the clouds', while 
the statement of what the nature of thunder is will be 'The 
noise of fire being quenched in the clouds'. Thus the same 
statement takes a different form: in one form it is continuous 
demonstration, in the other definition. Again, thunder can be 
defined as noise in the clouds, which is the conclusion of the 
demonstration embodying essential nature. On the other hand 
the definition of immediates is an indemonstrable positing of 
essential nature. 

We conclude then that definition is (a) an indemonstrable 
statement of essential nature, or (b) a syllogism of essential 
nature differing from demonstration in grammatical form, or (c) 
the conclusion of a demonstration giving essential nature. 

Our discussion has therefore made plain (1) in what sense and 
of what things the essential nature is demonstrable, and in 
what sense and of what things it is not; (2) what are the various 
meanings of the term definition, and in what sense and of what 
things it proves the essential nature, and in what sense and of 
what things it does not; (3) what is the relation of definition to 
demonstration, and how far the same thing is both definable 
and demonstrable and how far it is not. 



11 

We think we have scientific knowledge when we know the 
cause, and there are four causes: (1) the definable form, (2) an 



304 



antecedent which necessitates a consequent, (3) the efficient 
cause, (4) the final cause. Hence each of these can be the middle 
term of a proof, for (a) though the inference from antecedent to 
necessary consequent does not hold if only one premiss is 
assumed - two is the minimum - still when there are two it 
holds on condition that they have a single common middle 
term. So it is from the assumption of this single middle term 
that the conclusion follows necessarily. The following example 
will also show this. Why is the angle in a semicircle a right 
angle? - or from what assumption does it follow that it is a right 
angle? Thus, let A be right angle, B the half of two right angles, C 
the angle in a semicircle. Then B is the cause in virtue of which 

A, right angle, is attributable to C, the angle in a semicircle, 
since B=A and the other, viz. C,=B, for C is half of two right 
angles. Therefore it is the assumption of B, the half of two right 
angles, from which it follows that A is attributable to C, i.e. that 
the angle in a semicircle is a right angle. Moreover, B is identical 
with (b) the defining form of A, since it is what As definition 
signifies. Moreover, the formal cause has already been shown to 
be the middle, (c) 'Why did the Athenians become involved in 
the Persian war?' means 'What cause originated the waging of 
war against the Athenians?' and the answer is, 'Because they 
raided Sardis with the Eretrians', since this originated the war. 
Let A be war, B unprovoked raiding, C the Athenians. Then B, 
unprovoked raiding, is true of C, the Athenians, and A is true of 

B, since men make war on the unjust aggressor. So A, having 
war waged upon them, is true of B, the initial aggressors, and B 
is true of C, the Athenians, who were the aggressors. Hence here 
too the cause - in this case the efficient cause - is the middle 
term, (d) This is no less true where the cause is the final cause. 
E.g. why does one take a walk after supper? For the sake of one's 
health. Why does a house exist? For the preservation of one's 
goods. The end in view is in the one case health, in the other 
preservation. To ask the reason why one must walk after supper 



305 



is precisely to ask to what end one must do it. Let C be walking 
after supper, B the non-regurgitation of food, A health. Then let 
walking after supper possess the property of preventing food 
from rising to the orifice of the stomach, and let this condition 
be healthy; since it seems that B, the non-regurgitation of food, 
is attributable to C, taking a walk, and that A, health, is 
attributable to B. What, then, is the cause through which A, the 
final cause, inheres in C? It is B, the non-regurgitation of food; 
but B is a kind of definition of A, for A will be explained by it. 
Why is B the cause of A's belonging to C? Because to be in a 
condition such as B is to be in health. The definitions must be 
transposed, and then the detail will become clearer. 
Incidentally, here the order of coming to be is the reverse of 
what it is in proof through the efficient cause: in the efficient 
order the middle term must come to be first, whereas in the 
teleological order the minor, C, must first take place, and the 
end in view comes last in time. 

The same thing may exist for an end and be necessitated as 
well. For example, light shines through a lantern (1) because 
that which consists of relatively small particles necessarily 
passes through pores larger than those particles - assuming 
that light does issue by penetration - and (2) for an end, namely 
to save us from stumbling. If then, a thing can exist through two 
causes, can it come to be through two causes - as for instance if 
thunder be a hiss and a roar necessarily produced by the 
quenching of fire, and also designed, as the Pythagoreans say, 
for a threat to terrify those that lie in Tartarus? Indeed, there are 
very many such cases, mostly among the processes and 
products of the natural world; for nature, in different senses of 
the term 'nature', produces now for an end, now by necessity. 

Necessity too is of two kinds. It may work in accordance with a 
thing's natural tendency, or by constraint and in opposition to it; 



306 



as, for instance, by necessity a stone is borne both upwards and 
downwards, but not by the same necessity. 

Of the products of man's intelligence some are never due to 
chance or necessity but always to an end, as for example a 
house or a statue; others, such as health or safety, may result 
from chance as well. 

It is mostly in cases where the issue is indeterminate (though 
only where the production does not originate in chance, and the 
end is consequently good), that a result is due to an end, and 
this is true alike in nature or in art. By chance, on the other 
hand, nothing comes to be for an end. 



12 

The effect may be still coming to be, or its occurrence may be 
past or future, yet the cause will be the same as when it is 
actually existent - for it is the middle which is the cause - 
except that if the effect actually exists the cause is actually 
existent, if it is coming to be so is the cause, if its occurrence is 
past the cause is past, if future the cause is future. For example, 
the moon was eclipsed because the earth intervened, is 
becoming eclipsed because the earth is in process of 
intervening, will be eclipsed because the earth will intervene, is 
eclipsed because the earth intervenes. 

To take a second example: assuming that the definition of ice is 
solidified water, let C be water, A solidified, B the middle, which 
is the cause, namely total failure of heat. Then B is attributed to 
C, and A, solidification, to B: ice when B is occurring, has formed 
when B has occurred, and will form when B shall occur. 



307 



This sort of cause, then, and its effect come to be 
simultaneously when they are in process of becoming, and exist 
simultaneously when they actually exist; and the same holds 
good when they are past and when they are future. But what of 
cases where they are not simultaneous? Can causes and effects 
different from one another form, as they seem to us to form, a 
continuous succession, a past effect resulting from a past cause 
different from itself, a future effect from a future cause different 
from it, and an effect which is coming-to-be from a cause 
different from and prior to it? Now on this theory it is from the 
posterior event that we reason (and this though these later 
events actually have their source of origin in previous events - a 
fact which shows that also when the effect is coming-to-be we 
still reason from the posterior event), and from the event we 
cannot reason (we cannot argue that because an event A has 
occurred, therefore an event B has occurred subsequently to A 
but still in the past - and the same holds good if the occurrence 
is future) - cannot reason because, be the time interval definite 
or indefinite, it will never be possible to infer that because it is 
true to say that A occurred, therefore it is true to say that B, the 
subsequent event, occurred; for in the interval between the 
events, though A has already occurred, the latter statement will 
be false. And the same argument applies also to future events; 
i.e. one cannot infer from an event which occurred in the past 
that a future event will occur. The reason of this is that the 
middle must be homogeneous, past when the extremes are 
past, future when they are future, coming to be when they are 
coming-to-be, actually existent when they are actually existent; 
and there cannot be a middle term homogeneous with 
extremes respectively past and future. And it is a further 
difficulty in this theory that the time interval can be neither 
indefinite nor definite, since during it the inference will be false. 
We have also to inquire what it is that holds events together so 
that the coming-to-be now occurring in actual things follows 



308 



upon a past event. It is evident, we may suggest, that a past 
event and a present process cannot be 'contiguous', for not even 
two past events can be 'contiguous'. For past events are limits 
and atomic; so just as points are not 'contiguous' neither are 
past events, since both are indivisible. For the same reason a 
past event and a present process cannot be 'contiguous', for the 
process is divisible, the event indivisible. Thus the relation of 
present process to past event is analogous to that of line to 
point, since a process contains an infinity of past events. These 
questions, however, must receive a more explicit treatment in 
our general theory of change. 

The following must suffice as an account of the manner in 
which the middle would be identical with the cause on the 
supposition that coming-to-be is a series of consecutive events: 
for in the terms of such a series too the middle and major terms 
must form an immediate premiss; e.g. we argue that, since C 
has occurred, therefore A occurred: and C's occurrence was 
posterior, A's prior; but C is the source of the inference because 
it is nearer to the present moment, and the starting-point of 
time is the present. We next argue that, since D has occurred, 
therefore C occurred. Then we conclude that, since D has 
occurred, therefore A must have occurred; and the cause is C, 
for since D has occurred C must have occurred, and since C has 
occurred A must previously have occurred. 

If we get our middle term in this way, will the series terminate 
in an immediate premiss, or since, as we said, no two events are 
'contiguous', will a fresh middle term always intervene because 
there is an infinity of middles? No: though no two events are 
'contiguous', yet we must start from a premiss consisting of a 
middle and the present event as major. The like is true of future 
events too, since if it is true to say that D will exist, it must be a 
prior truth to say that A will exist, and the cause of this 
conclusion is C; for if D will exist, C will exist prior to D, and if C 



309 



will exist, A will exist prior to it. And here too the same infinite 
divisibility might be urged, since future events are not 
'contiguous'. But here too an immediate basic premiss must be 
assumed. And in the world of fact this is so: if a house has been 
built, then blocks must have been quarried and shaped. The 
reason is that a house having been built necessitates a 
foundation having been laid, and if a foundation has been laid 
blocks must have been shaped beforehand. Again, if a house 
will be built, blocks will similarly be shaped beforehand; and 
proof is through the middle in the same way, for the foundation 
will exist before the house. 

Now we observe in Nature a certain kind of circular process of 
coming-to-be; and this is possible only if the middle and 
extreme terms are reciprocal, since conversion is conditioned by 
reciprocity in the terms of the proof. This - the convertibility of 
conclusions and premisses - has been proved in our early 
chapters, and the circular process is an instance of this. In 
actual fact it is exemplified thus: when the earth had been 
moistened an exhalation was bound to rise, and when an 
exhalation had risen cloud was bound to form, and from the 
formation of cloud rain necessarily resulted and by the fall of 
rain the earth was necessarily moistened: but this was the 
starting-point, so that a circle is completed; for posit any one of 
the terms and another follows from it, and from that another, 
and from that again the first. 

Some occurrences are universal (for they are, or come-to-be 
what they are, always and in ever case); others again are not 
always what they are but only as a general rule: for instance, 
not every man can grow a beard, but it is the general rule. In the 
case of such connexions the middle term too must be a general 
rule. For if A is predicated universally of B and B of C, A too must 
be predicated always and in every instance of C, since to hold in 
every instance and always is of the nature of the universal. But 



310 



we have assumed a connexion which is a general rule; 
consequently the middle term B must also be a general rule. So 
connexions which embody a general rule - i.e. which exist or 
come to be as a general rule - will also derive from immediate 
basic premisses. 



13 

We have already explained how essential nature is set out in 
the terms of a demonstration, and the sense in which it is or is 
not demonstrable or definable; so let us now discuss the 
method to be adopted in tracing the elements predicated as 
constituting the definable form. 

Now of the attributes which inhere always in each several thing 
there are some which are wider in extent than it but not wider 
than its genus (by attributes of wider extent mean all such as 
are universal attributes of each several subject, but in their 
application are not confined to that subject), while an attribute 
may inhere in every triad, yet also in a subject not a triad - as 
being inheres in triad but also in subjects not numbers at all - 
odd on the other hand is an attribute inhering in every triad and 
of wider application (inhering as it does also in pentad), but 
which does not extend beyond the genus of triad; for pentad is a 
number, but nothing outside number is odd. It is such attributes 
which we have to select, up to the exact point at which they are 
severally of wider extent than the subject but collectively 
coextensive with it; for this synthesis must be the substance of 
the thing. For example every triad possesses the attributes 
number, odd, and prime in both senses, i.e. not only as 
possessing no divisors, but also as not being a sum of numbers. 
This, then, is precisely what triad is, viz. a number, odd, and 



311 



prime in the former and also the latter sense of the term: for 
these attributes taken severally apply, the first two to all odd 
numbers, the last to the dyad also as well as to the triad, but, 
taken collectively, to no other subject. Now since we have 
shown above' that attributes predicated as belonging to the 
essential nature are necessary and that universals are 
necessary, and since the attributes which we select as inhering 
in triad, or in any other subject whose attributes we select in 
this way, are predicated as belonging to its essential nature, 
triad will thus possess these attributes necessarily. Further, that 
the synthesis of them constitutes the substance of triad is 
shown by the following argument. If it is not identical with the 
being of triad, it must be related to triad as a genus named or 
nameless. It will then be of wider extent than triad - assuming 
that wider potential extent is the character of a genus. If on the 
other hand this synthesis is applicable to no subject other than 
the individual triads, it will be identical with the being of triad, 
because we make the further assumption that the substance of 
each subject is the predication of elements in its essential 
nature down to the last differentia characterizing the 
individuals. It follows that any other synthesis thus exhibited 
will likewise be identical with the being of the subject. 

The author of a hand-book on a subject that is a generic whole 
should divide the genus into its first infimae species - number 
e.g. into triad and dyad - and then endeavour to seize their 
definitions by the method we have described - the definition, 
for example, of straight line or circle or right angle. After that, 
having established what the category is to which the subaltern 
genus belongs - quantity or quality, for instance - he should 
examine the properties 'peculiar' to the species, working 
through the proximate common differentiae. He should proceed 
thus because the attributes of the genera compounded of the 
infimae species will be clearly given by the definitions of the 
species; since the basic element of them all is the definition, i.e. 



312 



the simple infirma species, and the attributes inhere essentially 
in the simple infimae species, in the genera only in virtue of 
these. 

Divisions according to differentiae are a useful accessory to this 
method. What force they have as proofs we did, indeed, explain 
above, but that merely towards collecting the essential nature 
they may be of use we will proceed to show. They might, indeed, 
seem to be of no use at all, but rather to assume everything at 
the start and to be no better than an initial assumption made 
without division. But, in fact, the order in which the attributes 
are predicated does make a difference - it matters whether we 
say animal-tame-biped, or biped-animal-tame. For if every 
definable thing consists of two elements and 'animal-tame' 
forms a unity, and again out of this and the further differentia 
man (or whatever else is the unity under construction) is 
constituted, then the elements we assume have necessarily 
been reached by division. Again, division is the only possible 
method of avoiding the omission of any element of the 
essential nature. Thus, if the primary genus is assumed and we 
then take one of the lower divisions, the dividendum will not 
fall whole into this division: e.g. it is not all animal which is 
either whole-winged or split-winged but all winged animal, for 
it is winged animal to which this differentiation belongs. The 
primary differentiation of animal is that within which all 
animal falls. The like is true of every other genus, whether 
outside animal or a subaltern genus of animal; e.g. the primary 
differentiation of bird is that within which falls every bird, of 
fish that within which falls every fish. So, if we proceed in this 
way, we can be sure that nothing has been omitted: by any 
other method one is bound to omit something without knowing 
it. 

To define and divide one need not know the whole of existence. 
Yet some hold it impossible to know the differentiae 



313 



distinguishing each thing from every single other thing without 
knowing every single other thing; and one cannot, they say, 
know each thing without knowing its differentiae, since 
everything is identical with that from which it does not differ, 
and other than that from which it differs. Now first of all this is 
a fallacy: not every differentia precludes identity, since many 
differentiae inhere in things specifically identical, though not in 
the substance of these nor essentially Secondly, when one has 
taken one's differing pair of opposites and assumed that the 
two sides exhaust the genus, and that the subject one seeks to 
define is present in one or other of them, and one has further 
verified its presence in one of them; then it does not matter 
whether or not one knows all the other subjects of which the 
differentiae are also predicated. For it is obvious that when by 
this process one reaches subjects incapable of further 
differentiation one will possess the formula defining the 
substance. Moreover, to postulate that the division exhausts the 
genus is not illegitimate if the opposites exclude a middle; since 
if it is the differentia of that genus, anything contained in the 
genus must lie on one of the two sides. 

In establishing a definition by division one should keep three 
objects in view: (1) the admission only of elements in the 
definable form, (2) the arrangement of these in the right order, 
(3) the omission of no such elements. The first is feasible 
because one can establish genus and differentia through the 
topic of the genus, just as one can conclude the inherence of an 
accident through the topic of the accident. The right order will 
be achieved if the right term is assumed as primary, and this 
will be ensured if the term selected is predicable of all the 
others but not all they of it; since there must be one such term. 
Having assumed this we at once proceed in the same way with 
the lower terms; for our second term will be the first of the 
remainder, our third the first of those which follow the second 
in a 'contiguous' series, since when the higher term is excluded, 



314 



that term of the remainder which is 'contiguous' to it will be 
primary, and so on. Our procedure makes it clear that no 
elements in the definable form have been omitted: we have 
taken the differentia that comes first in the order of division, 
pointing out that animal, e.g. is divisible exhaustively into A and 
B, and that the subject accepts one of the two as its predicate. 
Next we have taken the differentia of the whole thus reached, 
and shown that the whole we finally reach is not further 
divisible - i.e. that as soon as we have taken the last differentia 
to form the concrete totality, this totality admits of no division 
into species. For it is clear that there is no superfluous addition, 
since all these terms we have selected are elements in the 
definable form; and nothing lacking, since any omission would 
have to be a genus or a differentia. Now the primary term is a 
genus, and this term taken in conjunction with its differentiae 
is a genus: moreover the differentiae are all included, because 
there is now no further differentia; if there were, the final 
concrete would admit of division into species, which, we said, is 
not the case. 

To resume our account of the right method of investigation: We 
must start by observing a set of similar - i.e. specifically 
identical - individuals, and consider what element they have in 
common. We must then apply the same process to another set 
of individuals which belong to one species and are generically 
but not specifically identical with the former set. When we have 
established what the common element is in all members of this 
second species, and likewise in members of further species, we 
should again consider whether the results established possess 
any identity, and persevere until we reach a single formula, 
since this will be the definition of the thing. But if we reach not 
one formula but two or more, evidently the definiendum cannot 
be one thing but must be more than one. I may illustrate my 
meaning as follows. If we were inquiring what the essential 
nature of pride is, we should examine instances of proud men 



315 



we know of to see what, as such, they have in common; e.g. if 
Alcibiades was proud, or Achilles and Ajax were proud, we 
should find on inquiring what they all had in common, that it 
was intolerance of insult; it was this which drove Alcibiades to 
war, Achilles wrath, and Ajax to suicide. We should next 
examine other cases, Lysander, for example, or Socrates, and 
then if these have in common indifference alike to good and ill 
fortune, I take these two results and inquire what common 
element have equanimity amid the vicissitudes of life and 
impatience of dishonour. If they have none, there will be two 
genera of pride. Besides, every definition is always universal and 
commensurate: the physician does not prescribe what is 
healthy for a single eye, but for all eyes or for a determinate 
species of eye. It is also easier by this method to define the 
single species than the universal, and that is why our procedure 
should be from the several species to the universal genera - this 
for the further reason too that equivocation is less readily 
detected in genera than in infimae species. Indeed, perspicuity 
is essential in definitions, just as inferential movement is the 
minimum required in demonstrations; and we shall attain 
perspicuity if we can collect separately the definition of each 
species through the group of singulars which we have 
established e.g. the definition of similarity not unqualified but 
restricted to colours and to figures; the definition of acuteness, 
but only of sound - and so proceed to the common universal 
with a careful avoidance of equivocation. We may add that if 
dialectical disputation must not employ metaphors, clearly 
metaphors and metaphorical expressions are precluded in 
definition: otherwise dialectic would involve metaphors. 



316 



14 

In order to formulate the connexions we wish to prove we have 
to select our analyses and divisions. The method of selection 
consists in laying down the common genus of all our subjects of 
investigation - if e.g. they are animals, we lay down what the 
properties are which inhere in every animal. These established, 
we next lay down the properties essentially connected with the 
first of the remaining classes - e.g. if this first subgenus is bird, 
the essential properties of every bird - and so on, always 
characterizing the proximate subgenus. This will clearly at once 
enable us to say in virtue of what character the subgenera - 
man, e.g. or horse - possess their properties. Let A be animal, B 
the properties of every animal, C D E various species of animal. 
Then it is clear in virtue of what character B inheres in D - 
namely A - and that it inheres in C and E for the same reason: 
and throughout the remaining subgenera always the same rule 
applies. 

We are now taking our examples from the traditional class- 
names, but we must not confine ourselves to considering these. 
We must collect any other common character which we 
observe, and then consider with what species it is connected 
and what.properties belong to it. For example, as the common 
properties of horned animals we collect the possession of a 
third stomach and only one row of teeth. Then since it is clear 
in virtue of what character they possess these attributes - 
namely their horned character - the next question is, to what 
species does the possession of horns attach? 

Yet a further method of selection is by analogy: for we cannot 
find a single identical name to give to a squid's pounce, a fish's 
spine, and an animal's bone, although these too possess 
common properties as if there were a single osseous nature. 



317 



15 

Some connexions that require proof are identical in that they 
possess an identical 'middle' e.g. a whole group might be proved 
through 'reciprocal replacement' - and of these one class are 
identical in genus, namely all those whose difference consists 
in their concerning different subjects or in their mode of 
manifestation. This latter class may be exemplified by the 
questions as to the causes respectively of echo, of reflection, 
and of the rainbow: the connexions to be proved which these 
questions embody are identical generically, because all three are 
forms of repercussion; but specifically they are different. 

Other connexions that require proof only differ in that the 
'middle' of the one is subordinate to the 'middle' of the other. 
For example: Why does the Nile rise towards the end of the 
month? Because towards its close the month is more stormy. 
Why is the month more stormy towards its close? Because the 
moon is waning. Here the one cause is subordinate to the other. 



16 

The question might be raised with regard to cause and effect 
whether when the effect is present the cause also is present; 
whether, for instance, if a plant sheds its leaves or the moon is 
eclipsed, there is present also the cause of the eclipse or of the 
fall of the leaves - the possession of broad leaves, let us say, in 
the latter case, in the former the earth's interposition. For, one 
might argue, if this cause is not present, these phenomena will 
have some other cause: if it is present, its effect will be at once 
implied by it - the eclipse by the earth's interposition, the fall of 



318 



the leaves by the possession of broad leaves; but if so, they will 
be logically coincident and each capable of proof through the 
other. Let me illustrate: Let A be deciduous character, B the 
possession of broad leaves, C vine. Now if A inheres in B (for 
every broad-leaved plant is deciduous), and B in C (every vine 
possessing broad leaves); then A inheres in C (every vine is 
deciduous), and the middle term B is the cause. But we can also 
demonstrate that the vine has broad leaves because it is 
deciduous. Thus, let D be broad-leaved, E deciduous, F vine. 
Then E inheres in F (since every vine is deciduous), and D in E 
(for every deciduous plant has broad leaves): therefore every 
vine has broad leaves, and the cause is its deciduous character. 
If, however, they cannot each be the cause of the other (for 
cause is prior to effect, and the earth's interposition is the cause 
of the moon's eclipse and not the eclipse of the interposition) - 
if, then, demonstration through the cause is of the reasoned 
fact and demonstration not through the cause is of the bare 
fact, one who knows it through the eclipse knows the fact of the 
earth's interposition but not the reasoned fact. Moreover, that 
the eclipse is not the cause of the interposition, but the 
interposition of the eclipse, is obvious because the interposition 
is an element in the definition of eclipse, which shows that the 
eclipse is known through the interposition and not vice versa. 

On the other hand, can a single effect have more than one 
cause? One might argue as follows: if the same attribute is 
predicable of more than one thing as its primary subject, let B 
be a primary subject in which A inheres, and C another primary 
subject of A, and D and E primary subjects of B and C 
respectively. A will then inhere in D and E, and B will be the 
cause of As inherence in D, C of As inherence in E.The presence 
of the cause thus necessitates that of the effect, but the 
presence of the effect necessitates the presence not of all that 
may cause it but only of a cause which yet need not be the 
whole cause. We may, however, suggest that if the connexion to 



319 



be proved is always universal and commensurate, not only will 
the cause be a whole but also the effect will be universal and 
commensurate. For instance, deciduous character will belong 
exclusively to a subject which is a whole, and, if this whole has 
species, universally and commensurately to those species - i.e. 
either to all species of plant or to a single species. So in these 
universal and commensurate connexions the 'middle' and its 
effect must reciprocate, i.e. be convertible. Supposing, for 
example, that the reason why trees are deciduous is the 
coagulation of sap, then if a tree is deciduous, coagulation must 
be present, and if coagulation is present - not in any subject but 
in a tree - then that tree must be deciduous. 



17 

Can the cause of an identical effect be not identical in every 
instance of the effect but different? Or is that impossible? 
Perhaps it is impossible if the effect is demonstrated as 
essential and not as inhering in virtue of a symptom or an 
accident - because the middle is then the definition of the 
major term - though possible if the demonstration is not 
essential. Now it is possible to consider the effect and its subject 
as an accidental conjunction, though such conjunctions would 
not be regarded as connexions demanding scientific proof. But 
if they are accepted as such, the middle will correspond to the 
extremes, and be equivocal if they are equivocal, generically one 
if they are generically one. Take the question why proportionals 
alternate. The cause when they are lines, and when they are 
numbers, is both different and identical; different in so far as 
lines are lines and not numbers, identical as involving a given 
determinate increment. In all proportionals this is so. Again, the 
cause of likeness between colour and colour is other than that 



320 



between figure and figure; for likeness here is equivocal, 
meaning perhaps in the latter case equality of the ratios of the 
sides and equality of the angles, in the case of colours identity 
of the act of perceiving them, or something else of the sort. 
Again, connexions requiring proof which are identical by 
analogy middles also analogous. 

The truth is that cause, effect, and subject are reciprocally 
predicable in the following way. If the species are taken 
severally, the effect is wider than the subject (e.g. the possession 
of external angles equal to four right angles is an attribute 
wider than triangle or are), but it is coextensive with the species 
taken collectively (in this instance with all figures whose 
external angles are equal to four right angles). And the middle 
likewise reciprocates, for the middle is a definition of the major; 
which is incidentally the reason why all the sciences are built 
up through definition. 

We may illustrate as follows. Deciduous is a universal attribute 
of vine, and is at the same time of wider extent than vine; and 
of fig, and is of wider extent than fig: but it is not wider than but 
coextensive with the totality of the species. Then if you take the 
middle which is proximate, it is a definition of deciduous. I say 
that, because you will first reach a middle next the subject, and 
a premiss asserting it of the whole subject, and after that a 
middle - the coagulation of sap or something of the sort - 
proving the connexion of the first middle with the major: but it 
is the coagulation of sap at the junction of leaf-stalk and stem 
which defines deciduous. 

If an explanation in formal terms of the inter-relation of cause 
and effect is demanded, we shall offer the following. Let A be an 
attribute of all B, and B of every species of D, but so that both A 
and B are wider than their respective subjects. Then B will be a 
universal attribute of each species of D (since I call such an 



321 



attribute universal even if it is not commensurate, and I call an 
attribute primary universal if it is commensurate, not with each 
species severally but with their totality), and it extends beyond 
each of them taken separately. 

Thus, B is the cause of A's inherence in the species of D: 
consequently A must be of wider extent than B; otherwise why 
should B be the cause of A's inherence in D any more than A the 
cause of B's inherence in D? Now if A is an attribute of all the 
species of E, all the species of E will be united by possessing 
some common cause other than B: otherwise how shall we be 
able to say that A is predicable of all of which E is predicable, 
while E is not predicable of all of which A can be predicated? I 
mean how can there fail to be some special cause of A's 
inherence in E, as there was of A's inherence in all the species of 
D? Then are the species of E, too, united by possessing some 
common cause? This cause we must look for. Let us call it C. 

We conclude, then, that the same effect may have more than 
one cause, but not in subjects specifically identical. For 
instance, the cause of longevity in quadrupeds is lack of bile, in 
birds a dry constitution - or certainly something different. 



18 

If immediate premisses are not reached at once, and there is 
not merely one middle but several middles, i.e. several causes; is 
the cause of the property's inherence in the several species the 
middle which is proximate to the primary universal, or the 
middle which is proximate to the species? Clearly the cause is 
that nearest to each species severally in which it is manifested, 
for that is the cause of the subject's falling under the universal. 
To illustrate formally: C is the cause of B's inherence in D; hence 



322 



C is the cause of A's inherence in D, B of A's inherence in C, 
while the cause of A's inherence in B is B itself. 



19 

As regards syllogism and demonstration, the definition of, and 
the conditions required to produce each of them, are now clear, 
and with that also the definition of, and the conditions required 
to produce, demonstrative knowledge, since it is the same as 
demonstration. As to the basic premisses, how they become 
known and what is the developed state of knowledge of them is 
made clear by raising some preliminary problems. 

We have already said that scientific knowledge through 
demonstration is impossible unless a man knows the primary 
immediate premisses. But there are questions which might be 
raised in respect of the apprehension of these immediate 
premisses: one might not only ask whether it is of the same 
kind as the apprehension of the conclusions, but also whether 
there is or is not scientific knowledge of both; or scientific 
knowledge of the latter, and of the former a different kind of 
knowledge; and, further, whether the developed states of 
knowledge are not innate but come to be in us, or are innate but 
at first unnoticed. Now it is strange if we possess them from 
birth; for it means that we possess apprehensions more 
accurate than demonstration and fail to notice them. If on the 
other hand we acquire them and do not previously possess 
them, how could we apprehend and learn without a basis of 
pre-existent knowledge? For that is impossible, as we used to 
find in the case of demonstration. So it emerges that neither 
can we possess them from birth, nor can they come to be in us 
if we are without knowledge of them to the extent of having no 



323 



such developed state at all. Therefore we must possess a 
capacity of some sort, but not such as to rank higher in accuracy 
than these developed states. And this at least is an obvious 
characteristic of all animals, for they possess a congenital 
discriminative capacity which is called sense-perception. But 
though sense-perception is innate in all animals, in some the 
sense-impression comes to persist, in others it does not. So 
animals in which this persistence does not come to be have 
either no knowledge at all outside the act of perceiving, or no 
knowledge of objects of which no impression persists; animals 
in which it does come into being have perception and can 
continue to retain the sense-impression in the soul: and when 
such persistence is frequently repeated a further distinction at 
once arises between those which out of the persistence of such 
sense-impressions develop a power of systematizing them and 
those which do not. So out of sense-perception comes to be 
what we call memory, and out of frequently repeated memories 
of the same thing develops experience; for a number of 
memories constitute a single experience. From experience again 
- i.e. from the universal now stabilized in its entirety within the 
soul, the one beside the many which is a single identity within 
them all - originate the skill of the craftsman and the 
knowledge of the man of science, skill in the sphere of coming 
to be and science in the sphere of being. 

We conclude that these states of knowledge are neither innate 
in a determinate form, nor developed from other higher states 
of knowledge, but from sense-perception. It is like a rout in 
battle stopped by first one man making a stand and then 
another, until the original formation has been restored. The soul 
is so constituted as to be capable of this process. 

Let us now restate the account given already, though with 
insufficient clearness. When one of a number of logically 
indiscriminable particulars has made a stand, the earliest 



324 



universal is present in the soul: for though the act of sense- 
perception is of the particular, its content is universal - is man, 
for example, not the man Callias. A fresh stand is made among 
these rudimentary universals, and the process does not cease 
until the indivisible concepts, the true universals, are 
established: e.g. such and such a species of animal is a step 
towards the genus animal, which by the same process is a step 
towards a further generalization. 

Thus it is clear that we must get to know the primary premisses 
by induction; for the method by which even sense-perception 
implants the universal is inductive. Now of the thinking states 
by which we grasp truth, some are unfailingly true, others admit 
of error - opinion, for instance, and calculation, whereas 
scientific knowing and intuition are always true: further, no 
other kind of thought except intuition is more accurate than 
scientific knowledge, whereas primary premisses are more 
knowable than demonstrations, and all scientific knowledge is 
discursive. From these considerations it follows that there will 
be no scientific knowledge of the primary premisses, and since 
except intuition nothing can be truer than scientific knowledge, 
it will be intuition that apprehends the primary premisses - a 
result which also follows from the fact that demonstration 
cannot be the originative source of demonstration, nor, 
consequently, scientific knowledge of scientific knowledge. If, 
therefore, it is the only other kind of true thinking except 
scientific knowing, intuition will be the originative source of 
scientific knowledge. And the originative source of science 
grasps the original basic premiss, while science as a whole is 
similarly related as originative source to the whole body of fact. 



325 



Aristotle - Topics 
[Translated by W. A. Pickard-Cambridge] 



Book I 



Our treatise proposes to find a line of inquiry whereby we shall 
be able to reason from opinions that are generally accepted 
about every problem propounded to us, and also shall ourselves, 
when standing up to an argument, avoid saying anything that 
will obstruct us. First, then, we must say what reasoning is, and 
what its varieties are, in order to grasp dialectical reasoning: for 
this is the object of our search in the treatise before us. 

Now reasoning is an argument in which, certain things being 
laid down, something other than these necessarily comes about 
through them, (a) It is a 'demonstration', when the premisses 
from which the reasoning starts are true and primary, or are 
such that our knowledge of them has originally come through 
premisses which are primary and true: (b) reasoning, on the 
other hand, is 'dialectical', if it reasons from opinions that are 
generally accepted. Things are 'true' and 'primary' which are 
believed on the strength not of anything else but of themselves: 
for in regard to the first principles of science it is improper to 
ask any further for the why and wherefore of them; each of the 
first principles should command belief in and by itself. On the 
other hand, those opinions are 'generally accepted' which are 
accepted by every one or by the majority or by the philosophers 
- i.e. by all, or by the majority, or by the most notable and 



326 



illustrious of them. Again (c), reasoning is 'contentious' if it 
starts from opinions that seem to be generally accepted, but are 
not really such, or again if it merely seems to reason from 
opinions that are or seem to be generally accepted. For not 
every opinion that seems to be generally accepted actually is 
generally accepted. For in none of the opinions which we call 
generally accepted is the illusion entirely on the surface, as 
happens in the case of the principles of contentious arguments; 
for the nature of the fallacy in these is obvious immediately, 
and as a rule even to persons with little power of 
comprehension. So then, of the contentious reasonings 
mentioned, the former really deserves to be called 'reasoning' 
as well, but the other should be called 'contentious reasoning', 
but not 'reasoning', since it appears to reason, but does not 
really do so. Further (d), besides all the reasonings we have 
mentioned there are the mis-reasonings that start from the 
premisses peculiar to the special sciences, as happens (for 
example) in the case of geometry and her sister sciences. For 
this form of reasoning appears to differ from the reasonings 
mentioned above; the man who draws a false figure reasons 
from things that are neither true and primary, nor yet generally 
accepted. For he does not fall within the definition; he does not 
assume opinions that are received either by every one or by the 
majority or by philosophers - that is to say, by all, or by most, or 
by the most illustrious of them - but he conducts his reasoning 
upon assumptions which, though appropriate to the science in 
question, are not true; for he effects his mis-reasoning either by 
describing the semicircles wrongly or by drawing certain lines in 
a way in which they could not be drawn. 

The foregoing must stand for an outline survey of the species of 
reasoning. In general, in regard both to all that we have already 
discussed and to those which we shall discuss later, we may 
remark that that amount of distinction between them may 
serve, because it is not our purpose to give the exact definition 



327 



of any of them; we merely want to describe them in outline; we 
consider it quite enough from the point of view of the line of 
inquiry before us to be able to recognize each of them in some 
sort of way. 



Next in order after the foregoing, we must say for how many 
and for what purposes the treatise is useful. They are three - 
intellectual training, casual encounters, and the philosophical 
sciences. That it is useful as a training is obvious on the face of 
it. The possession of a plan of inquiry will enable us more easily 
to argue about the subject proposed. For purposes of casual 
encounters, it is useful because when we have counted up the 
opinions held by most people, we shall meet them on the 
ground not of other people's convictions but of their own, while 
we shift the ground of any argument that they appear to us to 
state unsoundly. For the study of the philosophical sciences it is 
useful, because the ability to raise searching difficulties on both 
sides of a subject will make us detect more easily the truth and 
error about the several points that arise. It has a further use in 
relation to the ultimate bases of the principles used in the 
several sciences. For it is impossible to discuss them at all from 
the principles proper to the particular science in hand, seeing 
that the principles are the prius of everything else: it is through 
the opinions generally held on the particular points that these 
have to be discussed, and this task belongs properly, or most 
appropriately, to dialectic: for dialectic is a process of criticism 
wherein lies the path to the principles of all inquiries. 



328 



We shall be in perfect possession of the way to proceed when 
we are in a position like that which we occupy in regard to 
rhetoric and medicine and faculties of that kind: this means the 
doing of that which we choose with the materials that are 
available. For it is not every method that the rhetorician will 
employ to persuade, or the doctor to heal; still, if he omits none 
of the available means, we shall say that his grasp of the science 
is adequate. 



First, then, we must see of what parts our inquiry consists. Now 
if we were to grasp (a) with reference to how many, and what 
kind of, things arguments take place, and with what materials 
they start, and (b) how we are to become well supplied with 
these, we should have sufficiently won our goal. Now the 
materials with which arguments start are equal in number, and 
are identical, with the subjects on which reasonings take place. 
For arguments start with 'propositions', while the subjects on 
which reasonings take place are 'problems'. Now every 
proposition and every problem indicates either a genus or a 
peculiarity or an accident - for the differentia too, applying as it 
does to a class (or genus), should be ranked together with the 
genus. Since, however, of what is peculiar to anything part 
signifies its essence, while part does not, let us divide the 
'peculiar' into both the aforesaid parts, and call that part which 
indicates the essence a 'definition', while of the remainder let 
us adopt the terminology which is generally current about these 
things, and speak of it as a 'property'. What we have said, then, 
makes it clear that according to our present division, the 



329 



elements turn out to be four, all told, namely either property or 
definition or genus or accident. Do not let any one suppose us 
to mean that each of these enunciated by itself constitutes a 
proposition or problem, but only that it is from these that both 
problems and propositions are formed. The difference between 
a problem and a proposition is a difference in the turn of the 
phrase. For if it be put in this way, «'An animal that walks on 
two feet» is the definition of man, is it not?' or '«Animal» is the 
genus of man, is it not?' the result is a proposition: but if thus, 
'Is «an animal that walks on two feet» a definition of man or 
no?' [or 'Is «animal» his genus or no?'] the result is a problem. 
Similarly too in other cases. Naturally, then, problems and 
propositions are equal in number: for out of every proposition 
you will make a problem if you change the turn of the phrase. 



We must now say what are 'definition', 'property', 'genus', and 
'accident'. A 'definition' is a phrase signifying a thing's essence. 
It is rendered in the form either of a phrase in lieu of a term, or 
of a phrase in lieu of another phrase; for it is sometimes 
possible to define the meaning of a phrase as well. People 
whose rendering consists of a term only, try it as they may, 
clearly do not render the definition of the thing in question, 
because a definition is always a phrase of a certain kind. One 
may, however, use the word 'definitory' also of such a remark as 
'The «becoming» is «beautiful»', and likewise also of the 
question, 'Are sensation and knowledge the same or different?', 
for argument about definitions is mostly concerned with 
questions of sameness and difference. In a word we may call 
'definitory' everything that falls under the same branch of 
inquiry as definitions; and that all the above-mentioned 



330 



examples are of this character is clear on the face of them. For if 
we are able to argue that two things are the same or are 
different, we shall be well supplied by the same turn of 
argument with lines of attack upon their definitions as well: for 
when we have shown that they are not the same we shall have 
demolished the definition. Observe, please, that the converse of 
this last statement does not hold: for to show that they are the 
same is not enough to establish a definition. To show, however, 
that they are not the same is enough of itself to overthrow it. 

A 'property' is a predicate which does not indicate the essence 
of a thing, but yet belongs to that thing alone, and is predicated 
convertibly of it. Thus it is a property of man to-be-capable of 
learning grammar: for if A be a man, then he is capable of 
learning grammar, and if he be capable of learning grammar, he 
is a man. For no one calls anything a 'property' which may 
possibly belong to something else, e.g. 'sleep' in the case of 
man, even though at a certain time it may happen to belong to 
him alone. That is to say, if any such thing were actually to be 
called a property, it will be called not a 'property' absolutely, but 
a 'temporary' or a 'relative' property: for 'being on the right 
hand side' is a temporary property, while 'two-footed' is in point 
of fact ascribed as a property in certain relations; e.g. it is a 
property of man relatively to a horse and a dog. That nothing 
which may belong to anything else than A is a convertible 
predicate of A is clear: for it does not necessarily follow that if 
something is asleep it is a man. 

A 'genus' is what is predicated in the category of essence of a 
number of things exhibiting differences in kind. We should treat 
as predicates in the category of essence all such things as it 
would be appropriate to mention in reply to the question, 'What 
is the object before you?'; as, for example, in the case of man, if 
asked that question, it is appropriate to say 'He is an animal'. 
The question, 'Is one thing in the same genus as another or in a 



331 



different one?' is also a 'generic' question; for a question of that 
kind as well falls under the same branch of inquiry as the 
genus: for having argued that 'animal' is the genus of man, and 
likewise also of ox, we shall have argued that they are in the 
same genus; whereas if we show that it is the genus of the one 
but not of the other, we shall have argued that these things are 
not in the same genus. 

An 'accident' is (i) something which, though it is none of the 
foregoing - i.e. neither a definition nor a property nor a genus 
yet belongs to the thing: (something which may possibly either 
belong or not belong to any one and the self-same thing, as 
(e.g.) the 'sitting posture' may belong or not belong to some self- 
same thing. Likewise also 'whiteness', for there is nothing to 
prevent the same thing being at one time white, and at another 
not white. Of the definitions of accident the second is the 
better: for if he adopts the first, any one is bound, if he is to 
understand it, to know already what 'definition' and 'genus' and 
'property' are, whereas the second is sufficient of itself to tell us 
the essential meaning of the term in question. To Accident are 
to be attached also all comparisons of things together, when 
expressed in language that is drawn in any kind of way from 
what happens (accidit) to be true of them; such as, for example, 
the question, 'Is the honourable or the expedient preferable?' 
and 'Is the life of virtue or the life of self-indulgence the 
pleasanter?', and any other problem which may happen to be 
phrased in terms like these. For in all such cases the question is 
'to which of the two does the predicate in question happen 
(accidit) to belong more closely?' It is clear on the face of it that 
there is nothing to prevent an accident from becoming a 
temporary or relative property. Thus the sitting posture is an 
accident, but will be a temporary property, whenever a man is 
the only person sitting, while if he be not the only one sitting, it 
is still a property relatively to those who are not sitting. So then, 
there is nothing to prevent an accident from becoming both a 



332 



relative and a temporary property; but a property absolutely it 
will never be. 



We must not fail to observe that all remarks made in criticism 
of a 'property' and 'genus' and 'accident' will be applicable to 
'definitions' as well. For when we have shown that the attribute 
in question fails to belong only to the term defined, as we do 
also in the case of a property, or that the genus rendered in the 
definition is not the true genus, or that any of the things 
mentioned in the phrase used does not belong, as would be 
remarked also in the case of an accident, we shall have 
demolished the definition; so that, to use the phrase previously 
employed,' all the points we have enumerated might in a 
certain sense be called 'definitory'. But we must not on this 
account expect to find a single line of inquiry which will apply 
universally to them all: for this is not an easy thing to find, and, 
even were one found, it would be very obscure indeed, and of 
little service for the treatise before us. Rather, a special plan of 
inquiry must be laid down for each of the classes we have 
distinguished, and then, starting from the rules that are 
appropriate in each case, it will probably be easier to make our 
way right through the task before us. So then, as was said 
before,' we must outline a division of our subject, and other 
questions we must relegate each to the particular branch to 
which it most naturally belongs, speaking of them as 'definitory' 
and 'generic' questions. The questions I mean have practically 
been already assigned to their several branches. 



333 



First of all we must define the number of senses borne by the 
term 'Sameness'. Sameness would be generally regarded as 
falling, roughly speaking, into three divisions. We generally 
apply the term numerically or specifically or generically - 
numerically in cases where there is more than one name but 
only one thing, e.g. 'doublet' and 'cloak'; specifically, where 
there is more than one thing, but they present no differences in 
respect of their species, as one man and another, or one horse 
and another: for things like this that fall under the same species 
are said to be 'specifically the same'. Similarly, too, those things 
are called generically the same which fall under the same 
genus, such as a horse and a man. It might appear that the 
sense in which water from the same spring is called 'the same 
water' is somehow different and unlike the senses mentioned 
above: but really such a case as this ought to be ranked in the 
same class with the things that in one way or another are called 
'the same' in view of unity of species. For all such things seem 
to be of one family and to resemble one another. For the reaon 
why all water is said to be specifically the same as all other 
water is because of a certain likeness it bears to it, and the only 
difference in the case of water drawn from the same spring is 
this, that the likeness is more emphatic: that is why we do not 
distinguish it from the things that in one way or another are 
called 'the same' in view of unity of species. It is generally 
supposed that the term 'the same' is most used in a sense 
agreed on by every one when applied to what is numerically 
one. But even so, it is apt to be rendered in more than one 
sense; its most literal and primary use is found whenever the 
sameness is rendered in reference to an alternative name or 
definition, as when a cloak is said to be the same as a doublet, 
or an animal that walks on two feet is said to be the same as a 
man: a second sense is when it is rendered in reference to a 
property, as when what can acquire knowledge is called the 



334 



same as a man, and what naturally travels upward the same as 
fire: while a third use is found when it is rendered in reference 
to some term drawn from Accident, as when the creature who is 
sitting, or who is musical, is called the same as Socrates. For all 
these uses mean to signify numerical unity. That what I have 
just said is true may be best seen where one form of appellation 
is substituted for another. For often when we give the order to 
call one of the people who are sitting down, indicating him by 
name, we change our description, whenever the person to 
whom we give the order happens not to understand us; he will, 
we think, understand better from some accidental feature; so 
we bid him call to us 'the man who is sitting' or 'who is 
conversing over there' - clearly supposing ourselves to be 
indicating the same object by its name and by its accident. 



8 

Of 'sameness' then, as has been said,' three senses are to be 
distinguished. Now one way to confirm that the elements 
mentioned above are those out of which and through which and 
to which arguments proceed, is by induction: for if any one were 
to survey propositions and problems one by one, it would be 
seen that each was formed either from the definition of 
something or from its property or from its genus or from its 
accident. Another way to confirm it is through reasoning. For 
every predicate of a subject must of necessity be either 
convertible with its subject or not: and if it is convertible, it 
would be its definition or property, for if it signifies the essence, 
it is the definition; if not, it is a property: for this was what a 
property is, viz. what is predicated convertibly, but does not 
signify the essence. If, on the other hand, it is not predicated 
convertibly of the thing, it either is or is not one of the terms 



335 



contained in the definition of the subject: and if it be one of 
those terms, then it will be the genus or the differentia, 
inasmuch as the definition consists of genus and differentiae; 
whereas, if it be not one of those terms, clearly it would be an 
accident, for accident was said' to be what belongs as an 
attribute to a subject without being either its definition or its 
genus or a property. 



Next, then, we must distinguish between the classes of 
predicates in which the four orders in question are found. These 
are ten in number: Essence, Quantity, Quality, Relation, Place, 
Time, Position, State, Activity, Passivity. For the accident and 
genus and property and definition of anything will always be in 
one of these categories: for all the propositions found through 
these signify either something's essence or its quality or 
quantity or some one of the other types of predicate. It is clear, 
too, on the face of it that the man who signifies something's 
essence signifies sometimes a substance, sometimes a quality, 
sometimes some one of the other types of predicate. For when 
man is set before him and he says that what is set there is 'a 
man' or 'an animal', he states its essence and signifies a 
substance; but when a white colour is set before him and he 
says that what is set there is 'white' or is 'a colour', he states its 
essence and signifies a quality. Likewise, also, if a magnitude of 
a cubit be set before him and he says that what is set there is a 
magnitude of a cubit, he will be describing its essence and 
signifying a quantity. Likewise, also, in the other cases: for each 
of these kinds of predicate, if either it be asserted of itself, or its 
genus be asserted of it, signifies an essence: if, on the other 
hand, one kind of predicate is asserted of another kind, it does 



336 



not signify an essence, but a quantity or a quality or one of the 
other kinds of predicate. Such, then, and so many, are the 
subjects on which arguments take place, and the materials with 
which they start. How we are to acquire them, and by what 
means we are to become well supplied with them, falls next to 
be told. 



10 

First, then, a definition must be given of a 'dialectical 
proposition' and a 'dialectical problem'. For it is not every 
proposition nor yet every problem that is to be set down as 
dialectical: for no one in his senses would make a proposition of 
what no one holds, nor yet make a problem of what is obvious 
to everybody or to most people: for the latter admits of no 
doubt, while to the former no one would assent. Now a 
dialectical proposition consists in asking something that is held 
by all men or by most men or by the philosophers, i.e. either by 
all, or by most, or by the most notable of these, provided it be 
not contrary to the general opinion; for a man would probably 
assent to the view of the philosophers, if it be not contrary to 
the opinions of most men. Dialectical propositions also include 
views which are like those generally accepted; also propositions 
which contradict the contraries of opinions that are taken to be 
generally accepted, and also all opinions that are in accordance 
with the recognized arts. Thus, supposing it to be a general 
opinion that the knowledge of contraries is the same, it might 
probably pass for a general opinion also that the perception of 
contraries is the same: also, supposing it to be a general opinion 
that there is but one single science of grammar, it might pass 
for a general opinion that there is but one science of flute- 
playing as well, whereas, if it be a general opinion that there is 



337 



more than one science of grammar, it might pass for a general 
opinion that there is more than one science of flute-playing as 
well: for all these seem to be alike and akin. Likewise, also, 
propositions contradicting the contraries of general opinions 
will pass as general opinions: for if it be a general opinion that 
one ought to do good to one's friends, it will also be a general 
opinion that one ought not to do them harm. Here, that one 
ought to do harm to one's friends is contrary to the general 
view, and that one ought not to do them harm is the 
contradictory of that contrary. Likewise also, if one ought to do 
good to one's friends, one ought not to do good to one's 
enemies: this too is the contradictory of the view contrary to the 
general view; the contrary being that one ought to do good to 
one's enemies. Likewise, also, in other cases. Also, on 
comparison, it will look like a general opinion that the contrary 
predicate belongs to the contrary subject: e.g. if one ought to do 
good to one's friends, one ought also to do evil to one's enemies, 
it might appear also as if doing good to one's friends were a 
contrary to doing evil to one's enemies: but whether this is or is 
not so in reality as well will be stated in the course of the 
discussion upon contraries. Clearly also, all opinions that are in 
accordance with the arts are dialectical propositions; for people 
are likely to assent to the views held by those who have made a 
study of these things, e.g. on a question of medicine they will 
agree with the doctor, and on a question of geometry with the 
geometrician; and likewise also in other cases. 



11 

A dialectical problem is a subject of inquiry that contributes 
either to choice and avoidance, or to truth and knowledge, and 
that either by itself, or as a help to the solution of some other 



338 



such problem. It must, moreover, be something on which either 
people hold no opinion either way, or the masses hold a 
contrary opinion to the philosophers, or the philosophers to the 
masses, or each of them among themselves. For some problems 
it is useful to know with a view to choice or avoidance, e.g. 
whether pleasure is to be chosen or not, while some it is useful 
to know merely with a view to knowledge, e.g. whether the 
universe is eternal or not: others, again, are not useful in and by 
themselves for either of these purposes, but yet help us in 
regard to some such problems; for there are many things which 
we do not wish to know in and by themselves, but for the sake 
of other things, in order that through them we may come to 
know something else. Problems also include questions in regard 
to which reasonings conflict (the difficulty then being whether 
so - and so is so or not, there being convincing arguments for 
both views); others also in regard to which we have no 
argument because they are so vast, and we find it difficult to 
give our reasons, e.g. the question whether the universe is 
eternal or no: for into questions of that kind too it is possible to 
inquire. 

Problems, then, and propositions are to be defined as aforesaid. 
A 'thesis' is a supposition of some eminent philosopher that 
conflicts with the general opinion; e.g. the view that 
contradiction is impossible, as Antisthenes said; or the view of 
Heraclitus that all things are in motion; or that Being is one, as 
Melissus says: for to take notice when any ordinary person 
expresses views contrary to men's usual opinions would be silly. 
Or it may be a view about which we have a reasoned theory 
contrary to men's usual opinions, e.g. the view maintained by 
the sophists that what is need not in every case either have 
come to be or be eternal: for a musician who is a grammarian 
'is' so without ever having 'come to be' so, or being so eternally. 
For even if a man does not accept this view, he might do so on 
the ground that it is reasonable. 



339 



Now a 'thesis' also is a problem, though a problem is not always 
a thesis, inasmuch as some problems are such that we have no 
opinion about them either way. That a thesis, however, also 
forms a problem, is clear: for it follows of necessity from what 
has been said that either the mass of men disagree with the 
philosophers about the thesis, or that the one or the other class 
disagree among themselves, seeing that the thesis is a 
supposition in conflict with general opinion. Practically all 
dialectical problems indeed are now called 'theses'. But it 
should make no difference whichever description is used; for 
our object in thus distinguishing them has not been to create a 
terminology, but to recognize what differences happen to be 
found between them. 

Not every problem, nor every thesis, should be examined, but 
only one which might puzzle one of those who need argument, 
not punishment or perception. For people who are puzzled to 
know whether one ought to honour the gods and love one's 
parents or not need punishment, while those who are puzzled 
to know whether snow is white or not need perception. The 
subjects should not border too closely upon the sphere of 
demonstration, nor yet be too far removed from it: for the 
former cases admit of no doubt, while the latter involve 
difficulties too great for the art of the trainer. 



12 

Having drawn these definitions, we must distinguish how many 
species there are of dialectical arguments. There is on the one 
hand Induction, on the other Reasoning. Now what reasoning is 
has been said before: induction is a passage from individuals to 
universals, e.g. the argument that supposing the skilled pilot is 



340 



the most effective, and likewise the skilled charioteer, then in 
general the skilled man is the best at his particular task. 
Induction is the more convincing and clear: it is more readily 
learnt by the use of the senses, and is applicable generally to 
the mass of men, though reasoning is more forcible and 
effective against contradictious people. 



13 

The classes, then, of things about which, and of things out of 
which, arguments are constructed, are to be distinguished in 
the way we have said before. The means whereby we are to 
become well supplied with reasonings are four: (1) the securing 
of propositions; (2) the power to distinguish in how many 
senses particular expression is used; (3) the discovery of the 
differences of things; (4) the investigation of likeness. The last 
three, as well, are in a certain sense propositions: for it is 
possible to make a proposition corresponding to each of them, 
e.g. (1) 'The desirable may mean either the honourable or the 
pleasant or the expedient'; and (2) Sensation differs from 
knowledge in that the latter may be recovered again after it has 
been lost, while the former cannot'; and (3) The relation of the 
healthy to health is like that of the vigorous to vigour'. The first 
proposition depends upon the use of one term in several senses, 
the second upon the differences of things, the third upon their 
likenesses. 



341 



14 

Propositions should be selected in a number of ways 
corresponding to the number of distinctions drawn in regard to 
the proposition: thus one may first take in hand the opinions 
held by all or by most men or by the philosophers, i.e. by all, or 
most, or the most notable of them; or opinions contrary to those 
that seem to be generally held; and, again, all opinions that are 
in accordance with the arts. We must make propositions also of 
the contradictories of opinions contrary to those that seem to 
be generally held, as was laid down before. It is useful also to 
make them by selecting not only those opinions that actually 
are accepted, but also those that are like these, e.g. 'The 
perception of contraries is the same' - the knowledge of them 
being so - and 'we see by admission of something into 
ourselves, not by an emission'; for so it is, too, in the case of the 
other senses; for in hearing we admit something into ourselves; 
we do not emit; and we taste in the same way. Likewise also in 
the other cases. Moreover, all statements that seem to be true in 
all or in most cases, should be taken as a principle or accepted 
position; for they are posited by those who do not also see what 
exception there may be. We should select also from the written 
handbooks of argument, and should draw up sketch-lists of 
them upon each several kind of subject, putting them down 
under separate headings, e.g. 'On Good', or 'On Life' - and that 
'On Good' should deal with every form of good, beginning with 
the category of essence. In the margin, too, one should indicate 
also the opinions of individual thinkers, e.g. 'Empedocles said 
that the elements of bodies were four': for any one might assent 
to the saying of some generally accepted authority. 

Of propositions and problems there are - to comprehend the 
matter in outline - three divisions: for some are ethical 
propositions, some are on natural philosophy, while some are 
logical. Propositions such as the following are ethical, e.g. 



342 



'Ought one rather to obey one's parents or the laws, if they 
disagree?'; such as this are logical, e.g. 'Is the knowledge of 
opposites the same or not?'; while such as this are on natural 
philosophy, e.g. 'Is the universe eternal or not?' Likewise also 
with problems. The nature of each of the aforesaid kinds of 
proposition is not easily rendered in a definition, but we have to 
try to recognize each of them by means of the familiarity 
attained through induction, examining them in the light of the 
illustrations given above. 

For purposes of philosophy we must treat of these things 
according to their truth, but for dialectic only with an eye to 
general opinion. All propositions should be taken in their most 
universal form; then, the one should be made into many. E.g. 
'The knowledge of opposites is the same'; next, 'The knowledge 
of contraries is the same', and that 'of relative terms'. In the 
same way these two should again be divided, as long as division 
is possible, e.g. the knowledge of 'good and evil', of 'white and 
black', or 'cold and hot'. Likewise also in other cases. 



15 

On the formation, then, of propositions, the above remarks are 
enough. As regards the number of senses a term bears, we must 
not only treat of those terms which bear different senses, but 
we must also try to render their definitions; e.g. we must not 
merely say that justice and courage are called 'good' in one 
sense, and that what conduces to vigour and what conduces to 
health are called so in another, but also that the former are so 
called because of a certain intrinsic quality they themselves 
have, the latter because they are productive of a certain result 



343 



and not because of any intrinsic quality in themselves. Similarly 
also in other cases. 

Whether a term bears a number of specific meanings or one 
only, may be considered by the following means. First, look and 
see if its contrary bears a number of meanings, whether the 
discrepancy between them be one of kind or one of names. For 
in some cases a difference is at once displayed even in the 
names; e.g. the contrary of 'sharp' in the case of a note is 'flat', 
while in the case of a solid edge it is 'dull'. Clearly, then, the 
contrary of 'sharp' bears several meanings, and if so, also does 
'sharp'; for corresponding to each of the former terms the 
meaning of its contrary will be different. For 'sharp' will not be 
the same when contrary to 'dull' and to 'flat', though 'sharp' is 
the contrary of each. Again Barhu ('flat', 'heavy') in the case of a 
note has 'sharp' as its contrary, but in the case of a solid mass 
'light', so that Barhu is used with a number of meanings, 
inasmuch as its contrary also is so used. Likewise, also, 'fine' as 
applied to a picture has 'ugly' as its contrary, but, as applied to a 
house, 'ramshackle'; so that 'fine' is an ambiguous term. 

In some cases there is no discrepancy of any sort in the names 
used, but a difference of kind between the meanings is at once 
obvious: e.g. in the case of 'clear' and 'obscure': for sound is 
called 'clear' and 'obscure', just as 'colour' is too. As regards the 
names, then, there is no discrepancy, but the difference in kind 
between the meanings is at once obvious: for colour is not 
called 'clear' in a like sense to sound. This is plain also through 
sensation: for of things that are the same in kind we have the 
same sensation, whereas we do not judge clearness by the same 
sensation in the case of sound and of colour, but in the latter 
case we judge by sight, in the former by hearing. Likewise also 
with 'sharp' and 'dull' in regard to flavours and solid edges: here 
in the latter case we judge by touch, but in the former by taste. 
For here again there is no discrepancy in the names used, in the 



344 



case either of the original terms or of their contraries: for the 
contrary also of sharp in either sense is 'dull'. 

Moreover, see if one sense of a term has a contrary, while 
another has absolutely none; e.g. the pleasure of drinking has a 
contrary in the pain of thirst, whereas the pleasure of seeing 
that the diagonal is incommensurate with the side has none, so 
that 'pleasure' is used in more than one sense. To 'love' also, 
used of the frame of mind, has to 'hate' as its contrary, while as 
used of the physical activity (kissing) it has none: clearly, 
therefore, to 'love' is an ambiguous term. Further, see in regard 
to their intermediates, if some meanings and their contraries 
have an intermediate, others have none, or if both have one but 
not the same one, e.g. 'clear' and 'obscure' in the case of colours 
have 'grey' as an intermediate, whereas in the case of sound 
they have none, or, if they have, it is 'harsh', as some people say 
that a harsh sound is intermediate. 'Clear', then, is an 
ambiguous term, and likewise also 'obscure'. See, moreover, if 
some of them have more than one intermediate, while others 
have but one, as is the case with 'clear' and 'obscure', for in the 
case of colours there are numbers of intermediates, whereas in 
regard to sound there is but one, viz. 'harsh'. 

Again, in the case of the contradictory opposite, look and see if 
it bears more than one meaning. For if this bears more than one 
meaning, then the opposite of it also will be used in more than 
one meaning; e.g. 'to fail to see' a phrase with more than one 
meaning, viz. (1) to fail to possess the power of sight, (2) to fail 
to put that power to active use. But if this has more than one 
meaning, it follows necessarily that 'to see' also has more than 
one meaning: for there will be an opposite to each sense of 'to 
fail to see'; e.g. the opposite of 'not to possess the power of 
sight' is to possess it, while of 'not to put the power of sight to 
active use', the opposite is to put it to active use. 



345 



Moreover, examine the case of terms that denote the privation 
or presence of a certain state: for if the one term bears more 
than one meaning, then so will the remaining term: e.g. if 'to 
have sense' be used with more than one meaning, as applied to 
the soul and to the body, then 'to be wanting in sense' too will 
be used with more than one meaning, as applied to the soul and 
to the body. That the opposition between the terms now in 
question depends upon the privation or presence of a certain 
state is clear, since animals naturally possess each kind of 
'sense', both as applied to the soul and as applied to the body. 

Moreover, examine the inflected forms. For if 'justly' has more 
than one meaning, then 'just', also, will be used with more than 
one meaning; for there will be a meaning of 'just' to each of the 
meanings of 'justly'; e.g. if the word 'justly' be used of judging 
according to one's own opinion, and also of judging as one 
ought, then 'just' also will be used in like manner. In the same 
way also, if 'healthy' has more than one meaning, then 
'healthily' also will be used with more than one meaning: e.g. if 
'healthy' describes both what produces health and what 
preserves health and what betokens health, then 'healthily' also 
will be used to mean 'in such a way as to produce' or 'preserve' 
or 'betoken' health. Likewise also in other cases, whenever the 
original term bears more than one meaning, the inflexion also 
that is formed from it will be used with more than one 
meaning, and vice versa. 

Look also at the classes of the predicates signified by the term, 
and see if they are the same in all cases. For if they are not the 
same, then clearly the term is ambiguous: e.g. 'good' in the case 
of food means 'productive of pleasure', and in the case of 
medicine 'productive of health', whereas as applied to the soul 
it means to be of a certain quality, e.g. temperate or courageous 
or just: and likewise also, as applied to 'man'. Sometimes it 
signifies what happens at a certain time, as (e.g.) the good that 



346 



happens at the right time: for what happens at the right time is 
called good. Often it signifies what is of certain quantity, e.g. as 
applied to the proper amount: for the proper amount too is 
called good. So then the term 'good' is ambiguous. In the same 
way also 'clear', as applied to a body, signifies a colour, but in 
regard to a note it denotes what is 'easy to hear'. 'Sharp', too, is 
in a closely similar case: for the same term does not bear the 
same meaning in all its applications: for a sharp note is a swift 
note, as the mathematical theorists of harmony tell us, whereas 
a sharp (acute) angle is one that is less than a right angle, while 
a sharp dagger is one containing a sharp angle (point). 

Look also at the genera of the objects denoted by the same 
term, and see if they are different without being subaltern, as 
(e.g.) 'donkey', which denotes both the animal and the engine. 
For the definition of them that corresponds to the name is 
different: for the one will be declared to be an animal of a 
certain kind, and the other to be an engine of a certain kind. If, 
however, the genera be subaltern, there is no necessity for the 
definitions to be different. Thus (e.g.) 'animal' is the genus of 
'raven', and so is 'bird'. Whenever therefore we say that the 
raven is a bird, we also say that it is a certain kind of animal, so 
that both the genera are predicated of it. Likewise also 
whenever we call the raven a 'flying biped animal', we declare it 
to be a bird: in this way, then, as well, both the genera are 
predicated of raven, and also their definition. But in the case of 
genera that are not subaltern this does not happen, for 
whenever we call a thing an 'engine', we do not call it an 
animal, nor vice versa. 

Look also and see not only if the genera of the term before you 
are different without being subaltern, but also in the case of its 
contrary: for if its contrary bears several senses, clearly the term 
before you does so as well. 



347 



It is useful also to look at the definition that arises from the use 
of the term in combination, e.g. of a 'clear (lit. white) body' of a 
'clear note'. For then if what is peculiar in each case be 
abstracted, the same expression ought to remain over. This does 
not happen in the case of ambiguous terms, e.g. in the cases 
just mentioned. For the former will be body possessing such 
and such a colour', while the latter will be 'a note easy to hear'. 
Abstract, then, 'a body 'and' a note', and the remainder in each 
case is not the same. It should, however, have been had the 
meaning of 'clear' in each case been synonymous. 

Often in the actual definitions as well ambiguity creeps in 
unawares, and for this reason the definitions also should be 
examined. If (e.g.) any one describes what betokens and what 
produces health as 'related commensurably to health', we must 
not desist but go on to examine in what sense he has used the 
term 'commensurably' in each case, e.g. if in the latter case it 
means that 'it is of the right amount to produce health', 
whereas in the for it means that 'it is such as to betoken what 
kind of state prevails'. 

Moreover, see if the terms cannot be compared as 'more or less' 
or as 'in like manner', as is the case (e.g.) with a 'clear' (lit. 
white) sound and a 'clear' garment, and a 'sharp' flavour and a 
'sharp' note. For neither are these things said to be clear or 
sharp 'in a like degree', nor yet is the one said to be clearer or 
sharper than the other. 'Clear', then, and 'sharp' are ambiguous. 
For synonyms are always comparable; for they will always be 
used either in like manner, or else in a greater degree in one 
case. 

Now since of genera that are different without being subaltern 
the differentiae also are different in kind, e.g. those of 'animal' 
and 'knowledge' (for the differentiae of these are different), look 
and see if the meanings comprised under the same term are 



348 



differentiae of genera that are different without being subaltern, 
as e.g. 'sharp' is of a 'note' and a 'solid'. For being 'sharp' 
differentiates note from note, and likewise also one solid from 
another. 'Sharp', then, is an ambiguous term: for it forms 
differentiae of genera that are different without being subaltern. 

Again, see if the actual meanings included under the same term 
themselves have different differentiae, e.g. 'colour' in bodies 
and 'colour' in tunes: for the differentiae of 'colour' in bodies are 
'sight-piercing' and 'sight compressing', whereas 'colour' in 
melodies has not the same differentiae. Colour, then, is an 
ambiguous term; for things that are the same have the same 
differentiae. 

Moreover, since the species is never the differentia of anything, 
look and see if one of the meanings included under the same 
term be a species and another a differentia, as (e.g.) clear' (lit. 
white) as applied to a body is a species of colour, whereas in the 
case of a note it is a differentia; for one note is differentiated 
from another by being 'clear'. 



16 

The presence, then, of a number of meanings in a term may be 
investigated by these and like means. The differences which 
things present to each other should be examined within the 
same genera, e.g. 'Wherein does justice differ from courage, and 
wisdom from temperance?' - for all these belong to the same 
genus; and also from one genus to another, provided they be not 
very much too far apart, e.g. 'Wherein does sensation differ 
from knowledge?: for in the case of genera that are very far 
apart, the differences are entirely obvious. 



349 



17 

Likeness should be studied, first, in the case of things belonging 
to different genera, the formulae being 'A:B = C:D' (e.g. as 
knowledge stands to the object of knowledge, so is sensation 
related to the object of sensation), and 'As A is in B, so is C in D' 
(e.g. as sight is in the eye, so is reason in the soul, and as is a 
calm in the sea, so is windlessness in the air). Practice is more 
especially needed in regard to terms that are far apart; for in the 
case of the rest, we shall be more easily able to see in one 
glance the points of likeness. We should also look at things 
which belong to the same genus, to see if any identical attribute 
belongs to them all, e.g. to a man and a horse and a dog; for in 
so far as they have any identical attribute, in so far they are 
alike. 



18 

It is useful to have examined the number of meanings of a term 
both for clearness' sake (for a man is more likely to know what 
it is he asserts, if it bas been made clear to him how many 
meanings it may have), and also with a view to ensuring that 
our reasonings shall be in accordance with the actual facts and 
not addressed merely to the term used. For as long as it is not 
clear in how many senses a term is used, it is possible that the 
answerer and the questioner are not directing their minds upon 
the same thing: whereas when once it has been made clear how 
many meanings there are, and also upon which of them the 
former directs his mind when he makes his assertion, the 



350 



questioner would then look ridiculous if he failed to address his 
argument to this. It helps us also both to avoid being misled and 
to mislead by false reasoning: for if we know the number of 
meanings of a term, we shall certainly never be misled by false 
reasoning, but shall know if the questioner fails to address his 
argument to the same point; and when we ourselves put the 
questions we shall be able to mislead him, if our answerer 
happens not to know the number of meanings of our terms. 
This, however, is not possible in all cases, but only when of the 
many senses some are true and others are false. This manner of 
argument, however, does not belong properly to dialectic; 
dialecticians should therefore by all means beware of this kind 
of verbal discussion, unless any one is absolutely unable to 
discuss the subject before him in any other way. 

The discovery of the differences of things helps us both in 
reasonings about sameness and difference, and also in 
recognizing what any particular thing is. That it helps us in 
reasoning about sameness and difference is clear: for when we 
have discovered a difference of any kind whatever between the 
objects before us, we shall already have shown that they are not 
the same: while it helps us in recognizing what a thing is, 
because we usually distinguish the expression that is proper to 
the essence of each particular thing by means of the 
differentiae that are proper to it. 

The examination of likeness is useful with a view both to 
inductive arguments and to hypothetical reasonings, and also 
with a view to the rendering of definitions. It is useful for 
inductive arguments, because it is by means of an induction of 
individuals in cases that are alike that we claim to bring the 
universal in evidence: for it is not easy to do this if we do not 
know the points of likeness. It is useful for hypothetical 
reasonings because it is a general opinion that among similars 
what is true of one is true also of the rest. If, then, with regard 



351 



to any of them we are well supplied with matter for a 
discussion, we shall secure a preliminary admission that 
however it is in these cases, so it is also in the case before us: 
then when we have shown the former we shall have shown, on 
the strength of the hypothesis, the matter before us as well: for 
we have first made the hypothesis that however it is in these 
cases, so it is also in the case before us, and have then proved 
the point as regards these cases. It is useful for the rendering of 
definitions because, if we are able to see in one glance what is 
the same in each individual case of it, we shall be at no loss into 
what genus we ought to put the object before us when we 
define it: for of the common predicates that which is most 
definitely in the category of essence is likely to be the genus. 
Likewise, also, in the case of objects widely divergent, the 
examination of likeness is useful for purposes of definition, e.g. 
the sameness of a calm at sea, and windlessness in the air (each 
being a form of rest), and of a point on a line and the unit in 
number - each being a starting point. If, then, we render as the 
genus what is common to all the cases, we shall get the credit 
of defining not inappropriately. Definition-mongers too nearly 
always render them in this way: they declare the unit to be the 
startingpoint of number, and the point the startingpoint of a 
line. It is clear, then, that they place them in that which is 
common to both as their genus. 

The means, then, whereby reasonings are effected, are these: 
the commonplace rules, for the observance of which the 
aforesaid means are useful, are as follows. 



352 



Book II 



Of problems some are universal, others particular. Universal 
problems are such as 'Every pleasure is good' and 'No pleasure 
is good'; particular problems are such as 'Some pleasure is good' 
and 'Some pleasure is not good'. The methods of establishing 
and overthrowing a view universally are common to both kinds 
of problems; for when we have shown that a predicate belongs 
in every case, we shall also have shown that it belongs in some 
cases. Likewise, also, if we show that it does not belong in any 
case, we shall also have shown that it does not belong in every 
case. First, then, we must speak of the methods of overthrowing 
a view universally, because such are common to both universal 
and particular problems, and because people more usually 
introduce theses asserting a predicate than denying it, while 
those who argue with them overthrow it. The conversion of an 
appropriate name which is drawn from the element 'accident' is 
an extremely precarious thing; for in the case of accidents and 
in no other it is possible for something to be true conditionally 
and not universally. Names drawn from the elements 
'definition' and 'property' and 'genus' are bound to be 
convertible; e.g. if 'to be an animal that walks on two feet is an 
attribute of S', then it will be true by conversion to say that 'S is 
an animal that walks on two feet'. Likewise, also, if drawn from 
the genus; for if 'to be an animal is an attribute of S', then 'S is 
an animal'. The same is true also in the case of a property; for if 
'to be capable of learning grammar is an attribute of S', then 'S 
will be capable of learning grammar'. For none of these 
attributes can possibly belong or not belong in part; they must 
either belong or not belong absolutely. In the case of accidents, 



353 



on the other hand, there is nothing to prevent an attribute (e.g. 
whiteness or justice) belonging in part, so that it is not enough 
to show that whiteness or justice is an attribute of a man in 
order to show that he is white or just; for it is open to dispute it 
and say that he is white or just in part only. Conversion, then, is 
not a necessary process in the case of accidents. 

We must also define the errors that occur in problems. They are 
of two kinds, caused either by false statement or by 
transgression of the established diction. For those who make 
false statements, and say that an attribute belongs to thing 
which does not belong to it, commit error; and those who call 
objects by the names of other objects (e.g. calling a planetree a 
'man') transgress the established terminology. 



Now one commonplace rule is to look and see if a man has 
ascribed as an accident what belongs in some other way. This 
mistake is most commonly made in regard to the genera of 
things, e.g. if one were to say that white happens (accidit) to be 
a colour - for being a colour does not happen by accident to 
white, but colour is its genus. The assertor may of course define 
it so in so many words, saying (e.g.) that 'Justice happens 
(accidit) to be a virtue'; but often even without such definition it 
is obvious that he has rendered the genus as an accident; e.g. 
suppose that one were to say that whiteness is coloured or that 
walking is in motion. For a predicate drawn from the genus is 
never ascribed to the species in an inflected form, but always 
the genera are predicated of their species literally; for the 
species take on both the name and the definition of their 
genera. A man therefore who says that white is 'coloured' has 



354 



not rendered 'coloured' as its genus, seeing that he has used an 
inflected form, nor yet as its property or as its definition: for the 
definition and property of a thing belong to it and to nothing 
else, whereas many things besides white are coloured, e.g. a log, 
a stone, a man, and a horse. Clearly then he renders it as an 
accident. 

Another rule is to examine all cases where a predicate has been 
either asserted or denied universally to belong to something. 
Look at them species by species, and not in their infinite 
multitude: for then the inquiry will proceed more directly and 
in fewer steps. You should look and begin with the most 
primary groups, and then proceed in order down to those that 
are not further divisible: e.g. if a man has said that the 
knowledge of opposites is the same, you should look and see 
whether it be so of relative opposites and of contraries and of 
terms signifying the privation or presence of certain states, and 
of contradictory terms. Then, if no clear result be reached so far 
in these cases, you should again divide these until you come to 
those that are not further divisible, and see (e.g.) whether it be 
so of just deeds and unjust, or of the double and the half, or of 
blindness and sight, or of being and not-being: for if in any case 
it be shown that the knowledge of them is not the same we 
shall have demolished the problem. Likewise, also, if the 
predicate belongs in no case. This rule is convertible for both 
destructive and constructive purposes: for if, when we have 
suggested a division, the predicate appears to hold in all or in a 
large number of cases, we may then claim that the other should 
actually assert it universally, or else bring a negative instance to 
show in what case it is not so: for if he does neither of these 
things, a refusal to assert it will make him look absurd. 

Another rule is to make definitions both of an accident and of 
its subject, either of both separately or else of one of them, and 
then look and see if anything untrue has been assumed as true 



355 



in the definitions. Thus (e.g.) to see if it is possible to wrong a 
god, ask what is 'to wrong? For if it be 'to injure deliberately', 
clearly it is not possible for a god to be wronged: for it is 
impossible that God should be injured. Again, to see if the good 
man is jealous, ask who is the 'jealous' man and what is 
'jealousy'. For if 'jealousy' is pain at the apparent success of 
some well-behaved person, clearly the good man is not jealous: 
for then he would be bad. Again, to see if the indignant man is 
jealous, ask who each of them is: for then it will be obvious 
whether the statement is true or false; e.g. if he is 'jealous' who 
grieves at the successes of the good, and he is 'indignant' who 
grieves at the successes of the evil, then clearly the indignant 
man would not be jealous. A man should substitute definitions 
also for the terms contained in his definitions, and not stop 
until he comes to a familiar term: for often if the definition be 
rendered whole, the point at issue is not cleared up, whereas if 
for one of the terms used in the definition a definition be stated, 
it becomes obvious. 

Moreover, a man should make the problem into a proposition 
for himself, and then bring a negative instance against it: for the 
negative instance will be a ground of attack upon the assertion. 
This rule is very nearly the same as the rule to look into cases 
where a predicate has been attributed or denied universally: but 
it differs in the turn of the argument. 

Moreover, you should define what kind of things should be 
called as most men call them, and what should not. For this is 
useful both for establishing and for overthrowing a view: e.g. 
you should say that we ought to use our terms to mean the 
same things as most people mean by them, but when we ask 
what kind of things are or are not of such and such a kind, we 
should not here go with the multitude: e.g. it is right to call 
'healthy' whatever tends to produce health, as do most men: 
but in saying whether the object before us tends to produce 



356 



health or not, we should adopt the language no longer of the 
multitude but of the doctor. 



Moreover, if a term be used in several senses, and it has been 
laid down that it is or that it is not an attribute of S, you should 
show your case of one of its several senses, if you cannot show 
it of both. This rule is to be observed in cases where the 
difference of meaning is undetected; for supposing this to be 
obvious, then the other man will object that the point which he 
himself questioned has not been discussed, but only the other 
point. This commonplace rule is convertible for purposes both 
of establishing and of overthrowing a view. For if we want to 
establish a statement, we shall show that in one sense the 
attribute belongs, if we cannot show it of both senses: whereas 
if we are overthrowing a statement, we shall show that in one 
sense the attribute does not belong, if we cannot show it of both 
senses. Of course, in overthrowing a statement there is no need 
to start the discussion by securing any admission, either when 
the statement asserts or when it denies the attribute 
universally: for if we show that in any case whatever the 
attribute does not belong, we shall have demolished the 
universal assertion of it, and likewise also if we show that it 
belongs in a single case, we shall demolish the universal denial 
of it. Whereas in establishing a statement we ought to secure a 
preliminary admission that if it belongs in any case whatever, it 
belongs universally, supposing this claim to be a plausible one. 
For it is not enough to discuss a single instance in order to show 
that an attribute belongs universally; e.g. to argue that if the 
soul of man be immortal, then every soul is immortal, so that a 
previous admission must be secured that if any soul whatever 



357 



be immortal, then every soul is immortal. This is not to be done 
in every case, but only whenever we are not easily able to quote 
any single argument applying to all cases in common, as (e.g.) 
the geometrician can argue that the triangle has its angles 
equal to two right angles. 

If, again, the variety of meanings of a term be obvious, 
distinguish how many meanings it has before proceeding either 
to demolish or to establish it: e.g. supposing 'the right' to mean 
'the expedient' or 'the honourable', you should try either to 
establish or to demolish both descriptions of the subject in 
question; e.g. by showing that it is honourable and expedient, or 
that it is neither honourable nor expedient. Supposing, however, 
that it is impossible to show both, you should show the one, 
adding an indication that it is true in the one sense and not in 
the other. The same rule applies also when the number of 
senses into which it is divided is more than two. 

Again, consider those expressions whose meanings are many, 
but differ not by way of ambiguity of a term, but in some other 
way: e.g. 'The science of many things is one': here 'many things' 
may mean the end and the means to that end, as (e.g.) medicine 
is the science both of producing health and of dieting; or they 
may be both of them ends, as the science of contraries is said to 
be the same (for of contraries the one is no more an end than 
the other); or again they may be an essential and an accidental 
attribute, as (e.g.) the essential fact that the triangle has its 
angles equal to two right angles, and the accidental fact that the 
equilateral figure has them so: for it is because of the accident 
of the equilateral triangle happening to be a triangle that we 
know that it has its angles equal to two right angles. If, then, it 
is not possible in any sense of the term that the science of 
many things should be the same, it clearly is altogether 
impossible that it should be so; or, if it is possible in some sense, 
then clearly it is possible. Distinguish as many meanings as are 



358 



required: e.g. if we want to establish a view, we should bring 
forward all such meanings as admit that view and should divide 
them only into those meanings which also are required for the 
establishment of our case: whereas if we want to overthrow a 
view, we should bring forward all that do not admit that view, 
and leave the rest aside. We must deal also in these cases as 
well with any uncertainty about the number of meanings 
involved. Further, that one thing is, or is not, 'of another should 
be established by means of the same commonplace rules; e.g. 
that a particular science is of a particular thing, treated either 
as an end or as a means to its end, or as accidentally connected 
with it; or again that it is not 'of it in any of the aforesaid ways. 
The same rule holds true also of desire and all other terms that 
have more than one object. For the 'desire of X' may mean the 
desire of it as an end (e.g. the desire of health) or as a means to 
an end (e.g. the desire of being doctored), or as a thing desired 
accidentally, as, in the case of wine, the sweet-toothed person 
desires it not because it is wine but because it is sweet. For 
essentially he desires the sweet, and only accidentally the wine: 
for if it be dry, he no longer desires it. His desire for it is 
therefore accidental. This rule is useful in dealing with relative 
terms: for cases of this kind are generally cases of relative 
terms. 



Moreover, it is well to alter a term into one more familiar, e.g. to 
substitute 'clear' for 'exact' in describing a conception, and 
'being fussy' for 'being busy': for when the expression is made 
more familiar, the thesis becomes easier to attack. This 
commonplace rule also is available for both purposes alike, both 
for establishing and for overthrowing a view. 



359 



In order to show that contrary attributes belong to the same 
thing, look at its genus; e.g. if we want to show that Tightness 
and wrongness are possible in regard to perception, and to 
perceive is to judge, while it is possible to judge rightly or 
wrongly, then in regard to perception as well Tightness and 
wrongness must be possible. In the present instance the proof 
proceeds from the genus and relates to the species: for 'to 
judge' is the genus of 'to perceive'; for the man who perceives 
judges in a certain way. But per contra it may proceed from the 
species to the genus: for all the attributes that belong to the 
species belong to the genus as well; e.g. if there is a bad and a 
good knowledge there is also a bad and a good disposition: for 
'disposition' is the genus of knowledge. Now the former 
commonplace argument is fallacious for purposes of 
establishing a view, while the second is true. For there is no 
necessity that all the attributes that belong to the genus should 
belong also to the species; for 'animal' is flying and quadruped, 
but not so 'man'. All the attributes, on the other hand, that 
belong to the species must of necessity belong also to the 
genus; for if 'man' is good, then animal also is good. On the 
other hand, for purposes of overthrowing a view, the former 
argument is true while the latter is fallacious; for all the 
attributes which do not belong to the genus do not belong to the 
species either; whereas all those that are wanting to the species 
are not of necessity wanting to the genus. 

Since those things of which the genus is predicated must also of 
necessity have one of its species predicated of them, and since 
those things that are possessed of the genus in question, or are 
described by terms derived from that genus, must also of 
necessity be possessed of one of its species or be described by 
terms derived from one of its species (e.g. if to anything the 
term 'scientific knowledge' be applied, then also there will be 
applied to it the term 'grammatical' or 'musical' knowledge, or 
knowledge of one of the other sciences; and if any one 



360 



possesses scientific knowledge or is described by a term derived 
from 'science', then he will also possess grammatical or musical 
knowledge or knowledge of one of the other sciences, or will be 
described by a term derived from one of them, e.g. as a 
'grammarian' or a 'musician') - therefore if any expression be 
asserted that is in any way derived from the genus (e.g. that the 
soul is in motion), look and see whether it be possible for the 
soul to be moved with any of the species of motion; whether 
(e.g.) it can grow or be destroyed or come to be, and so forth 
with all the other species of motion. For if it be not moved in 
any of these ways, clearly it does not move at all. This 
commonplace rule is common for both purposes, both for 
overthrowing and for establishing a view: for if the soul moves 
with one of the species of motion, clearly it does move; while if 
it does not move with any of the species of motion, clearly it 
does not move. 

If you are not well equipped with an argument against the 
assertion, look among the definitions, real or apparent, of the 
thing before you, and if one is not enough, draw upon several. 
For it will be easier to attack people when committed to a 
definition: for an attack is always more easily made on 
definitions. 

Moreover, look and see in regard to the thing in question, what 
it is whose reality conditions the reality of the thing in question, 
or what it is whose reality necessarily follows if the thing in 
question be real: if you wish to establish a view inquire what 
there is on whose reality the reality of the thing in question will 
follow (for if the former be shown to be real, then the thing in 
question will also have been shown to be real); while if you 
want to overthrow a view, ask what it is that is real if the thing 
in question be real, for if we show that what follows from the 
thing in question is unreal, we shall have demolished the thing 
in question. 



361 



Moreover, look at the time involved, to see if there be any 
discrepancy anywhere: e.g. suppose a man to have stated that 
what is being nourished of necessity grows: for animals are 
always of necessity being nourished, but they do not always 
grow. Likewise, also, if he has said that knowing is 
remembering: for the one is concerned with past time, whereas 
the other has to do also with the present and the future. For we 
are said to know things present and future (e.g. that there will 
be an eclipse), whereas it is impossible to remember anything 
save what is in the past. 



Moreover, there is the sophistic turn of argument, whereby we 
draw our opponent into the kind of statement against which we 
shall be well supplied with lines of argument. This process is 
sometimes a real necessity, sometimes an apparent necessity, 
sometimes neither an apparent nor a real necessity. It is really 
necessary whenever the answerer has denied any view that 
would be useful in attacking the thesis, and the questioner 
thereupon addresses his arguments to the support of this view, 
and when moreover the view in question happens to be one of a 
kind on which he has a good stock of lines of argument. 
Likewise, also, it is really necessary whenever he (the 
questioner) first, by an induction made by means of the view 
laid down, arrives at a certain statement and then tries to 
demolish that statement: for when once this has been 
demolished, the view originally laid down is demolished as well. 
It is an apparent necessity, when the point to which the 
discussion comes to be directed appears to be useful, and 
relevant to the thesis, without being really so; whether it be that 
the man who is standing up to the argument has refused to 



362 



concede something, or whether he (the questioner) has first 
reached it by a plausible induction based upon the thesis and 
then tries to demolish it. The remaining case is when the point 
to which the discussion comes to be directed is neither really 
nor apparently necessary, and it is the answerer's luck to be 
confuted on a mere side issue You should beware of the last of 
the aforesaid methods; for it appears to be wholly disconnected 
from, and foreign to, the art of dialectic. For this reason, 
moreover, the answerer should not lose his temper, but assent 
to those statements that are of no use in attacking the thesis, 
adding an indication whenever he assents although he does not 
agree with the view. For, as a rule, it increases the confusion of 
questioners if, after all propositions of this kind have been 
granted them, they can then draw no conclusion. 

Moreover, any one who has made any statement whatever has 
in a certain sense made several statements, inasmuch as each 
statement has a number of necessary consequences: e.g. the 
man who said 'X is a man' has also said that it is an animal and 
that it is animate and a biped and capable of acquiring reason 
and knowledge, so that by the demolition of any single one of 
these consequences, of whatever kind, the original statement is 
demolished as well. But you should beware here too of making a 
change to a more difficult subject: for sometimes the 
consequence, and sometimes the original thesis, is the easier to 
demolish. 



In regard to subjects which must have one and one only of two 
predicates, as (e.g.) a man must have either a disease or health, 
supposing we are well supplied as regards the one for arguing 



363 



its presence or absence, we shall be well equipped as regards 
the remaining one as well. This rule is convertible for both 
purposes: for when we have shown that the one attribute 
belongs, we shall have shown that the remaining one does not 
belong; while if we show that the one does not belong, we shall 
have shown that the remaining one does belong. Clearly then 
the rule is useful for both purposes. 

Moreover, you may devise a line of attack by reinterpreting a 
term in its literal meaning, with the implication that it is most 
fitting so to take it rather than in its established meaning: e.g. 
the expression 'strong at heart' will suggest not the courageous 
man, according to the use now established, but the man the 
state of whose heart is strong; just as also the expression 'of a 
good hope' may be taken to mean the man who hopes for good 
things. Likewise also 'well-starred' may be taken to mean the 
man whose star is good, as Xenocrates says 'well-starred is he 
who has a noble soul'.' For a man's star is his soul. 

Some things occur of necessity, others usually, others however it 
may chance; if therefore a necessary event has been asserted to 
occur usually, or if a usual event (or, failing such an event itself, 
its contrary) has been stated to occur of necessity, it always 
gives an opportunity for attack. For if a necessary event has 
been asserted to occur usually, clearly the speaker has denied 
an attribute to be universal which is universal, and so has made 
a mistake: and so he has if he has declared the usual attribute 
to be necessary: for then he declares it to belong universally 
when it does not so belong. Likewise also if he has declared the 
contrary of what is usual to be necessary. For the contrary of a 
usual attribute is always a comparatively rare attribute: e.g. if 
men are usually bad, they are comparatively seldom good, so 
that his mistake is even worse if he has declared them to be 
good of necessity. The same is true also if he has declared a 
mere matter of chance to happen of necessity or usually; for a 



364 



chance event happens neither of necessity nor usually. If the 
thing happens usually, then even supposing his statement does 
not distinguish whether he meant that it happens usually or 
that it happens necessarily, it is open to you to discuss it on the 
assumption that he meant that it happens necessarily: e.g. if he 
has stated without any distinction that disinherited persons are 
bad, you may assume in discussing it that he means that they 
are so necessarily. 

Moreover, look and see also if he has stated a thing to be an 
accident of itself, taking it to be a different thing because it has 
a different name, as Prodicus used to divide pleasures into joy 
and delight and good cheer: for all these are names of the same 
thing, to wit, Pleasure. If then any one says that joyfulness is an 
accidental attribute of cheerfulness, he would be declaring it to 
be an accidental attribute of itself. 



Inasmuch as contraries can be conjoined with each other in six 
ways, and four of these conjunctions constitute a contrariety, 
we must grasp the subject of contraries, in order that it may 
help us both in demolishing and in establishing a view. Well 
then, that the modes of conjunction are six is clear: for either (1) 
each of the contrary verbs will be conjoined to each of the 
contrary objects; and this gives two modes: e.g. to do good to 
friends and to do evil to enemies, or per contra to do evil to 
friends and to do good to enemies. Or else (2) both verbs may be 
attached to one object; and this too gives two modes, e.g. to do 
good to friends and to do evil to friends, or to do good to 
enemies and to do evil to enemies. Or (3) a single verb may be 
attached to both objects: and this also gives two modes; e.g. to 



365 



do good to friends and to do good to enemies, or to do evil to 
friends and evil to enemies. 

The first two then of the aforesaid conjunctions do not 
constitute any contrariety; for the doing of good to friends is not 
contrary to the doing of evil to enemies: for both courses are 
desirable and belong to the same disposition. Nor is the doing of 
evil to friends contrary to the doing of good to enemies: for both 
of these are objectionable and belong to the same disposition: 
and one objectionable thing is not generally thought to be the 
contrary of another, unless the one be an expression denoting 
an excess, and the other an expression denoting a defect: for an 
excess is generally thought to belong to the class of 
objectionable things, and likewise also a defect. But the other 
four all constitute a contrariety. For to do good to friends is 
contrary to the doing of evil to friends: for it proceeds from the 
contrary disposition, and the one is desirable, and the other 
objectionable. The case is the same also in regard to the other 
conjunctions: for in each combination the one course is 
desirable, and the other objectionable, and the one belongs to a 
reasonable disposition and the other to a bad. Clearly, then, 
from what has been said, the same course has more than one 
contrary. For the doing of good to friends has as its contrary 
both the doing of good to enemies and the doing of evil to 
friends. Likewise, if we examine them in the same way, we shall 
find that the contraries of each of the others also are two in 
number. Select therefore whichever of the two contraries is 
useful in attacking the thesis. 

Moreover, if the accident of a thing have a contrary, see whether 
it belongs to the subject to which the accident in question has 
been declared to belong: for if the latter belongs the former 
could not belong; for it is impossible that contrary predicates 
should belong at the same time to the same thing. 



366 



Or again, look and see if anything has been said about 
something, of such a kind that if it be true, contrary predicates 
must necessarily belong to the thing: e.g. if he has said that the 
'Ideas' exist in us. For then the result will be that they are both 
in motion and at rest, and moreover that they are objects both 
of sensation and of thought. For according to the views of those 
who posit the existence of Ideas, those Ideas are at rest and are 
objects of thought; while if they exist in us, it is impossible that 
they should be unmoved: for when we move, it follows 
necessarily that all that is in us moves with us as well. Clearly 
also they are objects of sensation, if they exist in us: for it is 
through the sensation of sight that we recognize the Form 
present in each individual. 

Again, if there be posited an accident which has a contrary, look 
and see if that which admits of the accident will admit of its 
contrary as well: for the same thing admits of contraries. Thus 
(e.g.) if he has asserted that hatred follows anger, hatred would 
in that case be in the 'spirited faculty': for that is where anger is. 
You should therefore look and see if its contrary, to wit, 
friendship, be also in the 'spirited faculty': for if not - if 
friendship is in the faculty of desire - then hatred could not 
follow anger. Likewise also if he has asserted that the faculty of 
desire is ignorant. For if it were capable of ignorance, it would be 
capable of knowledge as well: and this is not generally held - I 
mean that the faculty of desire is capable of knowledge. For 
purposes, then, of overthrowing a view, as has been said, this 
rule should be observed: but for purposes of establishing one, 
though the rule will not help you to assert that the accident 
actually belongs, it will help you to assert that it may possibly 
belong. For having shown that the thing in question will not 
admit of the contrary of the accident asserted, we shall have 
shown that the accident neither belongs nor can possibly 
belong; while on the other hand, if we show that the contrary 
belongs, or that the thing is capable of the contrary, we shall not 



367 



indeed as yet have shown that the accident asserted does 
belong as well; our proof will merely have gone to this point, 
that it is possible for it to belong. 



8 

Seeing that the modes of opposition are four in number, you 
should look for arguments among the contradictories of your 
terms, converting the order of their sequence, both when 
demolishing and when establishing a view, and you should 
secure them by means of induction - such arguments (e.g.) as 
that man be an animal, what is not an animal is not a man': 
and likewise also in other instances of contradictories. For in 
those cases the sequence is converse: for 'animal' follows upon 
'man but 'not-animal' does not follow upon 'not-man', but 
conversely 'not-man' upon 'not-animal'. In all cases, therefore, a 
postulate of this sort should be made, (e.g.) that 'If the 
honourable is pleasant, what is not pleasant is not honourable, 
while if the latter be untrue, so is the former'. Likewise, also, 'If 
what is not pleasant be not honourable, then what is 
honourable is pleasant'. Clearly, then, the conversion of the 
sequence formed by contradiction of the terms of the thesis is a 
method convertible for both purposes. 

Then look also at the case of the contraries of S and P in the 
thesis, and see if the contrary of the one follows upon the 
contrary of the other, either directly or conversely, both when 
you are demolishing and when you are establishing a view: 
secure arguments of this kind as well by means of induction, so 
far as may be required. Now the sequence is direct in a case 
such as that of courage and cowardice: for upon the one of 
them virtue follows, and vice upon the other; and upon the one 



368 



it follows that it is desirable, while upon the other it follows that 
it is objectionable. The sequence, therefore, in the latter case 
also is direct; for the desirable is the contrary of the 
objectionable. Likewise also in other cases. The sequence is, on 
the other hand, converse in such a case as this: Health follows 
upon vigour, but disease does not follow upon debility; rather 
debility follows upon disease. In this case, then, clearly the 
sequence is converse. Converse sequence is, however, rare in 
the case of contraries; usually the sequence is direct. If, 
therefore, the contrary of the one term does not follow upon the 
contrary of the other either directly or conversely, clearly 
neither does the one term follow upon the other in the 
statement made: whereas if the one followed the other in the 
case of the contraries, it must of necessity do so as well in the 
original statement. 

You should look also into cases of the privation or presence of a 
state in like manner to the case of contraries. Only, in the case 
of such privations the converse sequence does not occur: the 
sequence is always bound to be direct: e.g. as sensation follows 
sight, while absence of sensation follows blindness. For the 
opposition of sensation to absence of sensation is an opposition 
of the presence to the privation of a state: for the one of them is 
a state, and the other the privation of it. 

The case of relative terms should also be studied in like manner 
to that of a state and its privation: for the sequence of these as 
well is direct; e.g. if 3/1 is a multiple, then 1/3 is a fraction: for 
3/1 is relative to 1/3, and so is a multiple to a fraction. Again, if 
knowledge be a conceiving, then also the object of knowledge is 
an object of conception; and if sight be a sensation, then also 
the object of sight is an object of sensation. An objection may be 
made that there is no necessity for the sequence to take place, 
in the case of relative terms, in the way described: for the object 
of sensation is an object of knowledge, whereas sensation is not 



369 



knowledge. The objection is, however, not generally received as 
really true; for many people deny that there is knowledge of 
objects of sensation. Moreover, the principle stated is just as 
useful for the contrary purpose, e.g. to show that the object of 
sensation is not an object of knowledge, on the ground that 
neither is sensation knowledge. 



Again look at the case of the co-ordinates and inflected forms of 
the terms in the thesis, both in demolishing and in establishing 
it. By co-ordinates' are meant terms such as the following: 'Just 
deeds' and the 'just man' are coordinates of 'justice', and 
'courageous deeds' and the 'courageous man' are co-ordinates 
of courage. Likewise also things that tend to produce and to 
preserve anything are called co-ordinates of that which they 
tend to produce and to preserve, as e.g. 'healthy habits' are co- 
ordinates of 'health' and a 'vigorous constitutional' of a 
'vigorous constitution' and so forth also in other cases. 'Co- 
ordinate', then, usually describes cases such as these, whereas 
'inflected forms' are such as the following: 'justly', 
'courageously', 'healthily', and such as are formed in this way. It 
is usually held that words when used in their inflected forms as 
well are co-ordinates, as (e.g.) 'justly' in relation to justice, and 
'courageously' to courage; and then 'co-ordinate' describes all 
the members of the same kindred series, e.g. 'justice', 'just', of a 
man or an act, 'justly'. Clearly, then, when any one member, 
whatever its kind, of the same kindred series is shown to be 
good or praiseworthy, then all the rest as well come to be shown 
to be so: e.g. if 'justice' be something praiseworthy, then so will 
'just', of a man or thing, and 'justly' connote something 
praiseworthy. Then 'justly' will be rendered also 'praiseworthily', 



370 



derived will by the same inflexion from 'the praiseworthy' 
whereby 'justly' is derived from 'justice'. 

Look not only in the case of the subject mentioned, but also in 
the case of its contrary, for the contrary predicate: e.g. argue 
that good is not necessarily pleasant; for neither is evil painful: 
or that, if the latter be the case, so is the former. Also, if justice 
be knowledge, then injustice is ignorance: and if 'justly' means 
'knowingly' and 'skilfully', then 'unjustly' means 'ignorantly' 
and 'unskilfully': whereas if the latter be not true, neither is the 
former, as in the instance given just now: for 'unjustly' is more 
likely to seem equivalent to 'skilfully' than to 'unskilfully'. This 
commonplace rule has been stated before in dealing with the 
sequence of contraries; for all we are claiming now is that the 
contrary of P shall follow the contrary of S. 

Moreover, look at the modes of generation and destruction of a 
thing, and at the things which tend to produce or to destroy it, 
both in demolishing and in establishing a view. For those things 
whose modes of generation rank among good things, are 
themselves also good; and if they themselves be good, so also 
are their modes of generation. If, on the other hand, their 
modes of generation be evil, then they themselves also are evil. 
In regard to modes of destruction the converse is true: for if the 
modes of destruction rank as good things, then they themselves 
rank as evil things; whereas if the modes of destruction count 
as evil, they themselves count as good. The same argument 
applies also to things tending to produce and destroy: for things 
whose productive causes are good, themselves also rank as 
good; whereas if causes destructive of them are good, they 
themselves rank as evil. 



371 



10 

Again, look at things which are like the subject in question, and 
see if they are in like case; e.g. if one branch of knowledge has 
more than one object, so also will one opinion; and if to possess 
sight be to see, then also to possess hearing will be to hear. 
Likewise also in the case of other things, both those which are 
and those which are generally held to be like. The rule in 
question is useful for both purposes; for if it be as stated in the 
case of some one like thing, it is so with the other like things as 
well, whereas if it be not so in the case of some one of them, 
neither is it so in the case of the others. Look and see also 
whether the cases are alike as regards a single thing and a 
number of things: for sometimes there is a discrepancy. Thus, if 
to 'know' a thing be to 'think of it, then also to 'know many 
things' is to 'be thinking of many things'; whereas this is not 
true; for it is possible to know many things but not to be 
thinking of them. If, then, the latter proposition be not true, 
neither was the former that dealt with a single thing, viz. that to 
'know' a thing is to 'think of it. 

Moreover, argue from greater and less degrees. In regard to 
greater degrees there are four commonplace rules. One is: See 
whether a greater degree of the predicate follows a greater 
degree of the subject: e.g. if pleasure be good, see whether also a 
greater pleasure be a greater good: and if to do a wrong be evil, 
see whether also to do a greater wrong is a greater evil. Now 
this rule is of use for both purposes: for if an increase of the 
accident follows an increase of the subject, as we have said, 
clearly the accident belongs; while if it does not follow, the 
accident does not belong. You should establish this by 
induction. Another rule is: If one predicate be attributed to two 
subjects; then supposing it does not belong to the subject to 
which it is the more likely to belong, neither does it belong 
where it is less likely to belong; while if it does belong where it 



372 



is less likely to belong, then it belongs as well where it is more 
likely. Again: If two predicates be attributed to one subject, then 
if the one which is more generally thought to belong does not 
belong, neither does the one that is less generally thought to 
belong; or, if the one that is less generally thought to belong 
does belong, so also does the other. Moreover: If two predicates 
be attributed to two subjects, then if the one which is more 
usually thought to belong to the one subject does not belong, 
neither does the remaining predicate belong to the remaining 
subject; or, if the one which is less usually thought to belong to 
the one subject does belong, so too does the remaining 
predicate to the remaining subject. 

Moreover, you can argue from the fact that an attribute belongs, 
or is generally supposed to belong, in a like degree, in three 
ways, viz. those described in the last three rules given in regard 
to a greater degree.' For supposing that one predicate belongs, or 
is supposed to belong, to two subjects in a like degree, then if it 
does not belong to the one, neither does it belong to the other; 
while if it belongs to the one, it belongs to the remaining one as 
well. Or, supposing two predicates to belong in a like degree to 
the same subject, then, if the one does not belong, neither does 
the remaining one; while if the one does belong, the remaining 
one belongs as well. The case is the same also if two predicates 
belong in a like degree to two subjects; for if the one predicate 
does not belong to the one subject, neither does the remaining 
predicate belong to the remaining subject, while if the one 
predicate does belong to the one subject, the remaining 
predicate belongs to the remaining subject as well. 



373 



11 

You can argue, then, from greater or less or like degrees of truth 
in the aforesaid number of ways. Moreover, you should argue 
from the addition of one thing to another. If the addition of one 
thing to another makes that other good or white, whereas 
formerly it was not white or good, then the thing added will be 
white or good - it will possess the character it imparts to the 
whole as well. Moreover, if an addition of something to a given 
object intensifies the character which it had as given, then the 
thing added will itself as well be of that character. Likewise, 
also, in the case of other attributes. The rule is not applicable in 
all cases, but only in those in which the excess described as an 
'increased intensity' is found to take place. The above rule is, 
however, not convertible for overthrowing a view. For if the 
thing added does not make the other good, it is not thereby 
made clear whether in itself it may not be good: for the addition 
of good to evil does not necessarily make the whole good, any 
more than the addition of white to black makes the whole 
white. 

Again, any predicate of which we can speak of greater or less 
degrees belongs also absolutely: for greater or less degrees of 
good or of white will not be attributed to what is not good or 
white: for a bad thing will never be said to have a greater or less 
degree of goodness than another, but always of badness. This 
rule is not convertible, either, for the purpose of overthrowing a 
predication: for several predicates of which we cannot speak of 
a greater degree belong absolutely: for the term 'man' is not 
attributed in greater and less degrees, but a man is a man for all 
that. 

You should examine in the same way predicates attributed in a 
given respect, and at a given time and place: for if the predicate 
be possible in some respect, it is possible also absolutely. 



374 



Likewise, also, is what is predicated at a given time or place: for 
what is absolutely impossible is not possible either in any 
respect or at any place or time. An objection may be raised that 
in a given respect people may be good by nature, e.g. they may 
be generous or temperately inclined, while absolutely they are 
not good by nature, because no one is prudent by nature. 
Likewise, also, it is possible for a destructible thing to escape 
destruction at a given time, whereas it is not possible for it to 
escape absolutely. In the same way also it is a good thing at 
certain places to follow see and such a diet, e.g. in infected 
areas, though it is not a good thing absolutely. Moreover, in 
certain places it is possible to live singly and alone, but 
absolutely it is not possible to exist singly and alone. In the 
same way also it is in certain places honourable to sacrifice 
one's father, e.g. among the Triballi, whereas, absolutely, it is not 
honourable. Or possibly this may indicate a relativity not to 
places but to persons: for it is all the same wherever they may 
be: for everywhere it will be held honourable among the Triballi 
themselves, just because they are Triballi. Again, at certain 
times it is a good thing to take medicines, e.g. when one is ill, 
but it is not so absolutely. Or possibly this again may indicate a 
relativity not to a certain time, but to a certain state of health: 
for it is all the same whenever it occurs, if only one be in that 
state. A thing is 'absolutely' so which without any addition you 
are prepared to say is honourable or the contrary. Thus (e.g.) you 
will deny that to sacrifice one's father is honourable: it is 
honourable only to certain persons: it is not therefore 
honourable absolutely. On the other hand, to honour the gods 
you will declare to be honourable without adding anything, 
because that is honourable absolutely. So that whatever without 
any addition is generally accounted to be honourable or 
dishonourable or anything else of that kind, will be said to be so 
'absolutely'. 



375 



Book III 



The question which is the more desirable, or the better, of two 
or more things, should be examined upon the following lines: 
only first of all it must be clearly laid down that the inquiry we 
are making concerns not things that are widely divergent and 
that exhibit great differences from one another (for nobody 
raises any doubt whether happiness or wealth is more 
desirable), but things that are nearly related and about which 
we commonly discuss for which of the two we ought rather to 
vote, because we do not see any advantage on either side as 
compared with the other. Clearly, in such cases if we can show a 
single advantage, or more than one, our judgement will record 
our assent that whichever side happens to have the advantage 
is the more desirable. 

First, then, that which is more lasting or secure is more 
desirable than that which is less so: and so is that which is 
more likely to be chosen by the prudent or by the good man or 
by the right law, or by men who are good in any particular line, 
when they make their choice as such, or by the experts in 
regard to any particular class of things; i.e. either whatever most 
of them or what all of them would choose; e.g. in medicine or in 
carpentry those things are more desirable which most, or all, 
doctors would choose; or, in general, whatever most men or all 
men or all things would choose, e.g. the good: for everything 
aims at the good. You should direct the argument you intend to 



376 



employ to whatever purpose you require. Of what is 'better' or 
'more desirable' the absolute standard is the verdict of the 
better science, though relatively to a given individual the 
standard may be his own particular science. 

In the second place, that which is known as 'an x' is more 
desirable than that which does not come within the genus 'x' - 
e.g. justice than a just man; for the former falls within the 
genus 'good', whereas the other does not, and the former is 
called 'a good', whereas the latter is not: for nothing which does 
not happen to belong to the genus in question is called by the 
generic name; e.g. a 'white man' is not 'a colour'. Likewise also 
in other cases. 

Also, that which is desired for itself is more desirable than that 
which is desired for something else; e.g. health is more 
desirable than gymnastics: for the former is desired for itself, 
the latter for something else. Also, that which is desirable in 
itself is more desirable than what is desirable per accidens; e.g. 
justice in our friends than justice in our enemies: for the former 
is desirable in itself, the latter per accidens: for we desire that 
our enemies should be just per accidens, in order that they may 
do us no harm. This last principle is the same as the one that 
precedes it, with, however, a different turn of expression. For we 
desire justice in our friends for itself, even though it will make 
no difference to us, and even though they be in India; whereas 
in our enemies we desire it for something else, in order that 
they may do us no harm. 

Also, that which is in itself the cause of good is more desirable 
than what is so per accidens, e.g. virtue than luck (for the 
former in itself, and the latter per accidens, the cause of good 
things), and so in other cases of the same kind. Likewise also in 
the case of the contrary; for what is in itself the cause of evil is 
more objectionable than what is so per accidens, e.g. vice and 



377 



chance: for the one is bad in itself, whereas chance is so per 
accidens. 

Also, what is good absolutely is more desirable than what is 
good for a particular person, e.g. recovery of health than a 
surgical operation; for the former is good absolutely, the latter 
only for a particular person, viz. the man who needs an 
operation. So too what is good by nature is more desirable than 
the good that is not so by nature, e.g. justice than the just man; 
for the one is good by nature, whereas in the other case the 
goodness is acquired. Also the attribute is more desirable which 
belongs to the better and more honourable subject, e.g. to a god 
rather than to a man, and to the soul rather than to the body. So 
too the property of the better thing is better than the property 
of the worse; e.g. the property of God than the property of man: 
for whereas in respect of what is common in both of them they 
do not differ at all from each other, in respect of their properties 
the one surpasses the other. Also that is better which is 
inherent in things better or prior or more honourable: thus (e.g.) 
health is better than strength and beauty: for the former is 
inherent in the moist and the dry, and the hot and the cold, in 
fact in all the primary constituents of an animal, whereas the 
others are inherent in what is secondary, strength being a 
feature of the sinews and bones, while beauty is generally 
supposed to consist in a certain symmetry of the limbs. Also the 
end is generally supposed to be more desirable than the means, 
and of two means, that which lies nearer the end. In general, 
too, a means directed towards the end of life is more desirable 
than a means to anything else, e.g. that which contributes to 
happiness than that which contributes to prudence. Also the 
competent is more desirable than the incompetent. Moreover, of 
two productive agents that one is more desirable whose end is 
better; while between a productive agent and an end we can 
decide by a proportional sum whenever the excess of the one 
end over the other is greater than that of the latter over its own 



378 



productive means: e.g. supposing the excess of happiness over 
health to be greater than that of health over what produces 
health, then what produces happiness is better than health. For 
what produces happiness exceeds what produces health just as 
much as happiness exceeds health. But health exceeds what 
produces health by a smaller amount; ergo, the excess of what 
produces happiness over what produces health is greater than 
that of health over what produces health. Clearly, therefore, 
what produces happiness is more desirable than health: for it 
exceeds the same standard by a greater amount. Moreover, 
what is in itself nobler and more precious and praiseworthy is 
more desirable than what is less so, e.g. friendship than wealth, 
and justice than strength. For the former belong in themselves 
to the class of things precious and praiseworthy, while the latter 
do so not in themselves but for something else: for no one 
prizes wealth for itself but always for something else, whereas 
we prize friendship for itself, even though nothing else is likely 
to come to us from it. 



Moreover, whenever two things are very much like one another, 
and we cannot see any superiority in the one over the other of 
them, we should look at them from the standpoint of their 
consequences. For the one which is followed by the greater good 
is the more desirable: or, if the consequences be evil, that is 
more desirable which is followed by the less evil. For though 
both may be desirable, yet there may possibly be some 
unpleasant consequence involved to turn the scale. Our survey 
from the point of view of consequences lies in two directions, 
for there are prior consequences and later consequences: e.g. if 
a man learns, it follows that he was ignorant before and knows 



379 



afterwards. As a rule, the later consequence is the better to 
consider. You should take, therefore, whichever of the 
consequences suits your purpose. 

Moreover, a greater number of good things is more desirable 
than a smaller, either absolutely or when the one is included in 
the other, viz. the smaller number in the greater. An objection 
may be raised suppose in some particular case the one is valued 
for the sake of the other; for then the two together are not more 
desirable than the one; e.g. recovery of health and health, than 
health alone, inasmuch as we desire recovery of health for the 
sake of health. Also it is quite possible for what is not good, 
together with what is, to be more desirable than a greater 
number of good things, e.g. the combination of happiness and 
something else which is not good may be more desirable than 
the combination of justice and courage. Also, the same things 
are more valuable if accompanied than if unaccompanied by 
pleasure, and likewise when free from pain than when attended 
with pain. 

Also, everything is more desirable at the season when it is of 
greater consequence; e.g. freedom from pain in old age more 
than in youth: for it is of greater consequence in old age. On the 
same principle also, prudence is more desirable in old age; for 
no man chooses the young to guide him, because he does not 
expect them to be prudent. With courage, the converse is the 
case, for it is in youth that the active exercise of courage is more 
imperatively required. Likewise also with temperance; for the 
young are more troubled by their passions than are their elders. 

Also, that is more desirable which is more useful at every 
season or at most seasons, e.g. justice and temperance rather 
than courage: for they are always useful, while courage is only 
useful at times. Also, that one of two things which if all possess, 
we do not need the other thing, is more desirable than that 



380 



which all may possess and still we want the other one as well. 
Take the case of justice and courage; if everybody were just, 
there would be no use for courage, whereas all might be 
courageous, and still justice would be of use. 

Moreover, judge by the destructions and losses and generations 
and acquisitions and contraries of things: for things whose 
destruction is more objectionable are themselves more 
desirable. Likewise also with the losses and contraries of things; 
for a thing whose loss or whose contrary is more objectionable 
is itself more desirable. With the generations or acquisitions of 
things the opposite is the case: for things whose acquisition or 
generation is more desirable are themselves also desirable. 
Another commonplace rule is that what is nearer to the good is 
better and more desirable, i.e. what more nearly resembles the 
good: thus justice is better than a just man. Also, that which is 
more like than another thing to something better than itself, as 
e.g. some say that Ajax was a better man than Odysseus 
because he was more like Achilles. An objection may be raised 
to this that it is not true: for it is quite possible that Ajax did not 
resemble Achilles more nearly than Odysseus in the points 
which made Achilles the best of them, and that Odysseus was a 
good man, though unlike Achilles. Look also to see whether the 
resemblance be that of a caricature, like the resemblance of a 
monkey to a man, whereas a horse bears none: for the monkey 
is not the more handsome creature, despite its nearer 
resemblance to a man. Again, in the case of two things, if one is 
more like the better thing while another is more like the worse, 
then that is likely to be better which is more like the better. This 
too, however, admits of an objection: for quite possibly the one 
only slightly resembles the better, while the other strongly 
resembles the worse, e.g. supposing the resemblance of Ajax to 
Achilles to be slight, while that of Odysseus to Nestor is strong. 
Also it may be that the one which is like the better type shows a 
degrading likeness, whereas the one which is like the worse 



381 



type improves upon it: witness the likeness of a horse to a 
donkey, and that of a monkey to a man. 

Another rule is that the more conspicuous good is more 
desirable than the less conspicuous, and the more difficult than 
the easier: for we appreciate better the possession of things that 
cannot be easily acquired. Also the more personal possession is 
more desirable than the more widely shared. Also, that which is 
more free from connexion with evil: for what is not attended by 
any unpleasantness is more desirable than what is so attended. 

Moreover, if A be without qualification better than B, then also 
the best of the members of A is better than the best of the 
members of B; e.g. if Man be better than Horse, then also the 
best man is better than the best horse. Also, if the best in A be 
better than the best in B, then also A is better than B without 
qualification; e.g. if the best man be better than the best horse, 
then also Man is better than Horse without qualification. 

Moreover, things which our friends can share are more desirable 
than those they cannot. Also, things which we like rather to do 
to our friend are more desirable than those we like to do to the 
man in the street, e.g. just dealing and the doing of good rather 
than the semblance of them: for we would rather really do good 
to our friends than seem to do so, whereas towards the man in 
the street the converse is the case. 

Also, superfluities are better than necessities, and are 
sometimes more desirable as well: for the good life is better 
than mere life, and good life is a superfluity, whereas mere life 
itself is a necessity. Sometimes, though, what is better is not 
also more desirable: for there is no necessity that because it is 
better it should also be more desirable: at least to be a 
philosopher is better than to make money, but it is not more 
desirable for a man who lacks the necessities of life. The 
expression 'superfluity' applies whenever a man possesses the 



382 



necessities of life and sets to work to secure as well other noble 
acquisitions. Roughly speaking, perhaps, necessities are more 
desirable, while superfluities are better. 

Also, what cannot be got from another is more desirable than 
what can be got from another as well, as (e.g.) is the case of 
justice compared with courage. Also, A is more desirable if A is 
desirable without B, but not B without A: power (e.g.) is not 
desirable without prudence, but prudence is desirable without 
power. Also, if of two things we repudiate the one in order to be 
thought to possess the other, then that one is more desirable 
which we wish to be thought to possess; thus (e.g.) we repudiate 
the love of hard work in order that people may think us 
geniuses. 

Moreover, that is more desirable in whose absence it is less 
blameworthy for people to be vexed; and that is more desirable 
in whose absence it is more blameworthy for a man not to be 
vexed. 



Moreover, of things that belong to the same species one which 
possesses the peculiar virtue of the species is more desirable 
than one which does not. If both possess it, then the one which 
possesses it in a greater degree is more desirable. 

Moreover, if one thing makes good whatever it touches, while 
another does not, the former is more desirable, just as also what 
makes things warm is warmer than what does not. If both do 
so, then that one is more desirable which does so in a greater 
degree, or if it render good the better and more important object 
- if (e.g.), the one makes good the soul, and the other the body. 



383 



Moreover, judge things by their inflexions and uses and actions 
and works, and judge these by them: for they go with each 
other: e.g. if 'justly' means something more desirable than 
'courageously', then also justice means something more 
desirable than courage; and if justice be more desirable than 
courage, then also 'justly' means something more desirable 
than 'courageously'. Similarly also in the other cases. 

Moreover, if one thing exceeds while the other falls short of the 
same standard of good, the one which exceeds is the more 
desirable; or if the one exceeds an even higher standard. Nay 
more, if there be two things both preferable to something, the 
one which is more highly preferable to it is more desirable than 
the less highly preferable. Moreover, when the excess of a thing 
is more desirable than the excess of something else, that thing 
is itself also more desirable than the other, as (e.g.) friendship 
than money: for an excess of friendship is more desirable than 
an excess of money. So also that of which a man would rather 
that it were his by his own doing is more desirable than what he 
would rather get by another's doing, e.g. friends than money. 
Moreover, judge by means of an addition, and see if the addition 
of A to the same thing as B makes the whole more desirable 
than does the addition of B. You must, however, beware of 
adducing a case in which the common term uses, or in some 
other way helps the case of, one of the things added to it, but 
not the other, as (e.g.) if you took a saw and a sickle in 
combination with the art of carpentry: for in the combination 
the saw is a more desirable thing, but it is not a more desirable 
thing without qualification. Again, a thing is more desirable if, 
when added to a lesser good, it makes the whole greater good. 
Likewise, also, you should judge by means of subtraction: for 
the thing upon whose subtraction the remainder is a lesser 
good may be taken to be a greater good, whichever it be whose 
subtraction makes the remainder a lesser good. 



384 



Also, if one thing be desirable for itself, and the other for the 
look of it, the former is more desirable, as (e.g.) health than 
beauty. A thing is defined as being desired for the look of it if, 
supposing no one knew of it, you would not care to have it. Also, 
it is more desirable both for itself and for the look of it, while 
the other thing is desirable on the one ground alone. Also, 
whichever is the more precious for itself, is also better and more 
desirable. A thing may be taken to be more precious in itself 
which we choose rather for itself, without anything else being 
likely to come of it. 

Moreover, you should distinguish in how many senses 
'desirable' is used, and with a view to what ends, e.g. 
expediency or honour or pleasure. For what is useful for all or 
most of them may be taken to be more desirable than what is 
not useful in like manner. If the same characters belong to both 
things you should look and see which possesses them more 
markedly, i.e. which of the two is the more pleasant or more 
honourable or more expedient. Again, that is more desirable 
which serves the better purpose, e.g. that which serves to 
promote virtue more than that which serves to promote 
pleasure. Likewise also in the case of objectionable things; for 
that is more objectionable which stands more in the way of 
what is desirable, e.g. disease more than ugliness: for disease is 
a greater hindrance both to pleasure and to being good. 

Moreover, argue by showing that the thing in question is in like 
measure objectionable and desirable: for a thing of such a 
character that a man might well desire and object to it alike is 
less desirable than the other which is desirable only. 



385 



Comparisons of things together should therefore be conducted 
in the manner prescribed. The same commonplace rules are 
useful also for showing that anything is simply desirable or 
objectionable: for we have only to subtract the excess of one 
thing over another. For if what is more precious be more 
desirable, then also what is precious is desirable; and if what is 
more useful be more desirable, then also what is useful is 
desirable. Likewise, also, in the case of other things which admit 
of comparisons of that kind. For in some cases in the very 
course of comparing the things together we at once assert also 
that each of them, or the one of them, is desirable, e.g. 
whenever we call the one good 'by nature' and the other 'not by 
nature': for dearly what is good by nature is desirable. 



The commonplace rules relating to comparative degrees and 
amounts ought to be taken in the most general possible form: 
for when so taken they are likely to be useful in a larger number 
of instances. It is possible to render some of the actual rules 
given above more universal by a slight alteration of the 
expression, e.g. that what by nature exhibits such and such a 
quality exhibits that quality in a greater degree than what 
exhibits it not by nature. Also, if one thing does, and another 
does not, impart such and such a quality to that which 
possesses it, or to which it belongs, then whichever does impart 
it is of that quality in greater degree than the one which does 
not impart it; and if both impart it, then that one exhibits it in a 
greater degree which imparts it in a greater degree. 



386 



Moreover, if in any character one thing exceeds and another 
falls short of the same standard; also, if the one exceeds 
something which exceeds a given standard, while the other 
does not reach that standard, then clearly the first-named thing 
exhibits that character in a greater degree. Moreover, you should 
judge by means of addition, and see if A when added to the 
same thing as B imparts to the whole such and such a character 
in a more marked degree than B, or if, when added to a thing 
which exhibits that character in a less degree, it imparts that 
character to the whole in a greater degree. Likewise, also, you 
may judge by means of subtraction: for a thing upon whose 
subtraction the remainder exhibits such and such a character in 
a less degree, itself exhibits that character in a greater degree. 
Also, things exhibit such and such a character in a greater 
degree if more free from admixture with their contraries; e.g. 
that is whiter which is more free from admixture with black. 
Moreover, apart from the rules given above, that has such and 
such a character in greater degree which admits in a greater 
degree of the definition proper to the given character; e.g. if the 
definition of 'white' be 'a colour which pierces the vision', then 
that is whiter which is in a greater degree a colour that pierces 
the vision. 



If the question be put in a particular and not in a universal 
form, in the first place the universal constructive or destructive 
commonplace rules that have been given may all be brought 
into use. For in demolishing or establishing a thing universally 
we also show it in particular: for if it be true of all, it is true also 
of some, and if untrue of all, it is untrue of some. Especially 
handy and of general application are the commonplace rules 



387 



that are drawn from the opposites and co-ordinates and 
inflexions of a thing: for public opinion grants alike the claim 
that if all pleasure be good, then also all pain is evil, and the 
claim that if some pleasure be good, then also some pain is evil. 
Moreover, if some form of sensation be not a capacity, then also 
some form of failure of sensation is not a failure of capacity. 
Also, if the object of conception is in some cases an object of 
knowledge, then also some form of conceiving is knowledge. 
Again, if what is unjust be in some cases good, then also what is 
just is in some cases evil; and if what happens justly is in some 
cases evil, then also what happens unjustly is in some cases 
good. Also, if what is pleasant is in some cases objectionable, 
then pleasure is in some cases an objectionable thing. On the 
same principle, also, if what is pleasant is in some cases 
beneficial, then pleasure is in some cases a beneficial thing. The 
case is the same also as regards the things that destroy, and the 
processes of generation and destruction. For if anything that 
destroys pleasure or knowledge be in some cases good, then we 
may take it that pleasure or knowledge is in some cases an evil 
thing. Likewise, also, if the destruction of knowledge be in some 
cases a good thing or its production an evil thing, then 
knowledge will be in some cases an evil thing; e.g. if for a man 
to forget his disgraceful conduct be a good thing, and to 
remember it be an evil thing, then the knowledge of his 
disgraceful conduct may be taken to be an evil thing. The same 
holds also in other cases: in all such cases the premiss and the 
conclusion are equally likely to be accepted. 

Moreover you should judge by means of greater or smaller or 
like degrees: for if some member of another genus exhibit such 
and such a character in a more marked degree than your object, 
while no member of that genus exhibits that character at all, 
then you may take it that neither does the object in question 
exhibit it; e.g. if some form of knowledge be good in a greater 
degree than pleasure, while no form of knowledge is good, then 



388 



you may take it that pleasure is not good either. Also, you 
should judge by a smaller or like degree in the same way: for so 
you will find it possible both to demolish and to establish a 
view, except that whereas both are possible by means of like 
degrees, by means of a smaller degree it is possible only to 
establish, not to overthrow. For if a certain form of capacity be 
good in a like degree to knowledge, and a certain form of 
capacity be good, then so also is knowledge; while if no form of 
capacity be good, then neither is knowledge. If, too, a certain 
form of capacity be good in a less degree than knowledge, and a 
certain form of capacity be good, then so also is knowledge; but 
if no form of capacity be good, there is no necessity that no 
form of knowledge either should be good. Clearly, then, it is only 
possible to establish a view by means of a less degree. 

Not only by means of another genus can you overthrow a view, 
but also by means of the same, if you take the most marked 
instance of the character in question; e.g. if it be maintained 
that some form of knowledge is good, then, suppose it to be 
shown that prudence is not good, neither will any other kind be 
good, seeing that not even the kind upon which there is most 
general agreement is so. Moreover, you should go to work by 
means of an hypothesis; you should claim that the attribute, if it 
belongs or does not belong in one case, does so in a like degree 
in all, e.g. that if the soul of man be immortal, so are other souls 
as well, while if this one be not so, neither are the others. If, 
then, it be maintained that in some instance the attribute 
belongs, you must show that in some instance it does not 
belong: for then it will follow, by reason of the hypothesis, that 
it does not belong to any instance at all. If, on the other hand, it 
be maintained that it does not belong in some instance, you 
must show that it does belong in some instance, for in this way 
it will follow that it belongs to all instances. It is clear that the 
maker of the hypothesis universalizes the question, whereas it 
was stated in a particular form: for he claims that the maker of 



389 



a particular admission should make a universal admission, 
inasmuch as he claims that if the attribute belongs in one 
instance, it belongs also in all instances alike. 

If the problem be indefinite, it is possible to overthrow a 
statement in only one way; e.g. if a man has asserted that 
pleasure is good or is not good, without any further definition. 
For if he meant that a particular pleasure is good, you must 
show universally that no pleasure is good, if the proposition in 
question is to be demolished. And likewise, also, if he meant 
that some particular pleasure is not good you must show 
universally that all pleasure is good: it is impossible to demolish 
it in any other way. For if we show that some particular pleasure 
is not good or is good, the proposition in question is not yet 
demolished. It is clear, then, that it is possible to demolish an 
indefinite statement in one way only, whereas it can be 
established in two ways: for whether we show universally that 
all pleasure is good, or whether we show that a particular 
pleasure is good, the proposition in question will have been 
proved. Likewise, also, supposing we are required to argue that 
some particular pleasure is not good, if we show that no 
pleasure is good or that a particular pleasure is not good, we 
shall have produced an argument in both ways, both universally 
and in particular, to show that some particular pleasure is not 
good. If, on the other hand, the statement made be definite, it 
will be possible to demolish it in two ways; e.g. if it be 
maintained that it is an attribute of some particular pleasure to 
be good, while of some it is not: for whether it be shown that all 
pleasure, or that no pleasure, is good, the proposition in 
question will have been demolished. If, however, he has stated 
that only one single pleasure is good, it is possible to demolish 
it in three ways: for by showing that all pleasure, or that no 
pleasure, or that more than one pleasure, is good, we shall have 
demolished the statement in question. If the statement be 
made still more definite, e.g. that prudence alone of the virtues 



390 



is knowledge, there are four ways of demolishing it: for if it be 
shown that all virtue is knowledge, or that no virtue is so, or 
that some other virtue (e.g. justice) is so, or that prudence itself 
is not knowledge, the proposition in question will have been 
demolished. 

It is useful also to take a look at individual instances, in cases 
where some attribute has been said to belong or not to belong, 
as in the case of universal questions. Moreover, you should take 
a glance among genera, dividing them by their species until you 
come to those that are not further divisible, as has been said 
before:' for whether the attribute is found to belong in all cases 
or in none, you should, after adducing several instances, claim 
that he should either admit your point universally, or else bring 
an objection showing in what case it does not hold. Moreover, in 
cases where it is possible to make the accident definite either 
specifically or numerically, you should look and see whether 
perhaps none of them belongs, showing e.g. that time is not 
moved, nor yet a movement, by enumerating how many species 
there are of movement: for if none of these belong to time, 
clearly it does not move, nor yet is a movement. Likewise, also, 
you can show that the soul is not a number, by dividing all 
numbers into either odd or even: for then, if the soul be neither 
odd nor even, clearly it is not a number. 

In regard then to Accident, you should set to work by means like 
these, and in this manner. 



Book IV 



391 



Next we must go on to examine questions relating to Genus and 
Property. These are elements in the questions that relate to 
definitions, but dialecticians seldom address their inquiries to 
these by themselves. If, then, a genus be suggested for 
something that is, first take a look at all objects which belong to 
the same genus as the thing mentioned, and see whether the 
genus suggested is not predicated of one of them, as happens in 
the case of an accident: e.g. if 'good' be laid down to be the 
genus of 'pleasure', see whether some particular pleasure be not 
good: for, if so, clearly good' is not the genus of pleasure: for the 
genus is predicated of all the members of the same species. 
Secondly, see whether it be predicated not in the category of 
essence, but as an accident, as 'white' is predicated of 'snow', or 
'self-moved' of the soul. For 'snow' is not a kind of 'white', and 
therefore 'white' is not the genus of snow, nor is the soul a kind 
of 'moving object': its motion is an accident of it, as it often is of 
an animal to walk or to be walking. Moreover, 'moving' does not 
seem to indicate the essence, but rather a state of doing or of 
having something done to it. Likewise, also, 'white': for it 
indicates not the essence of snow, but a certain quality of it. So 
that neither of them is predicated in the category of 'essence'. 

Especially you should take a look at the definition of Accident, 
and see whether it fits the genus mentioned, as (e.g.) is also the 
case in the instances just given. For it is possible for a thing to 
be and not to be self-moved, and likewise, also, for it to be and 
not to be white. So that neither of these attributes is the genus 
but an accident, since we were saying that an accident is an 
attribute which can belong to a thing and also not belong. 

Moreover, see whether the genus and the species be not found 
in the same division, but the one be a substance while the other 



392 



is a quality, or the one be a relative while the other is a quality, 
as (e.g.) 'slow' and 'swan' are each a substance, while 'white' is 
not a substance but a quality, so that 'white' is not the genus 
either of 'snow' or of 'swan'. Again, knowledge' is a relative, 
while 'good' and 'noble' are each a quality, so that good, or 
noble, is not the genus of knowledge. For the genera of relatives 
ought themselves also to be relatives, as is the case with 
'double': for multiple', which is the genus of 'double', is itself 
also a relative. To speak generally, the genus ought to fall under 
the same division as the species: for if the species be a 
substance, so too should be the genus, and if the species be a 
quality, so too the genus should be a quality; e.g. if white be a 
quality, so too should colour be. Likewise, also, in other cases. 

Again, see whether it be necessary or possible for the genus to 
partake of the object which has been placed in the genus. 'To 
partake' is defined as 'to admit the definition of that which is 
partaken. Clearly, therefore, the species partake of the genera, 
but not the genera of the species: for the species admits the 
definition of the genus, whereas the genus does not admit that 
of the species. You must look, therefore, and see whether the 
genus rendered partakes or can possibly partake of the species, 
e.g. if any one were to render anything as genus of 'being' or of 
'unity': for then the result will be that the genus partakes of the 
species: for of everything that is, 'being' and 'unity' are 
predicated, and therefore their definition as well. 

Moreover, see if there be anything of which the species rendered 
is true, while the genus is not so, e.g. supposing 'being' or 'object 
of knowledge' were stated to be the genus of 'object of opinion'. 
For 'object of opinion' will be a predicate of what does not exist; 
for many things which do not exist are objects of opinion; 
whereas that 'being' or 'object of knowledge' is not predicated 
of what does not exist is clear. So that neither 'being' nor 'object 
of knowledge' is the genus of 'object of opinion': for of the 



393 



objects of which the species is predicated, the genus ought to be 
predicated as well. 

Again, see whether the object placed in the genus be quite 
unable to partake of any of its species: for it is impossible that it 
should partake of the genus if it do not partake of any of its 
species, except it be one of the species reached by the first 
division: these do partake of the genus alone. If, therefore, 
'Motion' be stated as the genus of pleasure, you should look and 
see if pleasure be neither locomotion nor alteration, nor any of 
the rest of the given modes of motion: for clearly you may then 
take it that it does not partake of any of the species, and 
therefore not of the genus either, since what partakes of the 
genus must necessarily partake of one of the species as well: so 
that pleasure could not be a species of Motion, nor yet be one of 
the individual phenomena comprised under the term 'motion'. 
For individuals as well partake in the genus and the species, as 
(e.g.) an individual man partakes of both 'man' and 'animal'. 

Moreover, see if the term placed in the genus has a wider 
denotation than the genus, as (e.g.) 'object of opinion' has, as 
compared with 'being': for both what is and what is not are 
objects of opinion, so that 'object of opinion' could not be a 
species of being: for the genus is always of wider denotation 
than the species. Again, see if the species and its genus have an 
equal denotation; suppose, for instance, that of the attributes 
which go with everything, one were to be stated as a species 
and the other as its genus, as for example Being and Unity: for 
everything has being and unity, so that neither is the genus of 
the other, since their denotation is equal. Likewise, also, if the 
'first' of a series and the 'beginning' were to be placed one 
under the other: for the beginning is first and the first is the 
beginning, so that either both expressions are identical or at 
any rate neither is the genus of the other. The elementary 
principle in regard to all such cases is that the genus has a 



394 



wider denotation than the species and its differentia: for the 
differentia as well has a narrower denotation than the genus. 

See also whether the genus mentioned fails, or might be 
generally thought to fail, to apply to some object which is not 
specifically different from the thing in question; or, if your 
argument be constructive, whether it does so apply. For all 
things that are not specifically different have the same genus. If, 
therefore, it be shown to apply to one, then clearly it applies to 
all, and if it fails to apply to one, clearly it fails to apply to any; 
e.g. if any one who assumes 'indivisible lines' were to say that 
the 'indivisible' is their genus. For the aforesaid term is not the 
genus of divisible lines, and these do not differ as regards their 
species from indivisible: for straight lines are never different 
from each other as regards their species. 



Look and see, also, if there be any other genus of the given 
species which neither embraces the genus rendered nor yet 
falls under it, e.g. suppose any one were to lay down that 
'knowledge' is the genus of justice. For virtue is its genus as 
well, and neither of these genera embraces the remaining one, 
so that knowledge could not be the genus of justice: for it is 
generally accepted that whenever one species falls under two 
genera, the one is embraced by the other. Yet a principle of this 
kind gives rise to a difficulty in some cases. For some people 
hold that prudence is both virtue and knowledge, and that 
neither of its genera is embraced by the other: although 
certainly not everybody admits that prudence is knowledge. If, 
however, any one were to admit the truth of this assertion, yet it 
would still be generally agreed to be necessary that the genera 



395 



of the same object must at any rate be subordinate either the 
one to the other or both to the same, as actually is the case with 
virtue and knowledge. For both fall under the same genus; for 
each of them is a state and a disposition. You should look, 
therefore, and see whether neither of these things is true of the 
genus rendered; for if the genera be subordinate neither the one 
to the other nor both to the same, then what is rendered could 
not be the true genus. 

Look, also, at the genus of the genus rendered, and so 
continually at the next higher genus, and see whether all are 
predicated of the species, and predicated in the category of 
essence: for all the higher genera should be predicated of the 
species in the category of essence. If, then, there be anywhere a 
discrepancy, clearly what is rendered is not the true genus. 
[Again, see whether either the genus itself, or one of its higher 
genera, partakes of the species: for the higher genus does not 
partake of any of the lower.] If, then, you are overthrowing a 
view, follow the rule as given: if establishing one, then - suppose 
that what has been named as genus be admitted to belong to 
the species, only it be disputed whether it belongs as genus - it 
is enough to show that one of its higher genera is predicated of 
the species in the category of essence. For if one of them be 
predicated in the category of essence, all of them, both higher 
and lower than this one, if predicated at all of the species, will 
be predicated of it in the category of essence: so that what has 
been rendered as genus is also predicated in the category of 
essence. The premiss that when one genus is predicated in the 
category of essence, all the rest, if predicated at all, will be 
predicated in the category of essence, should be secured by 
induction. Supposing, however, that it be disputed whether 
what has been rendered as genus belongs at all, it is not enough 
to show that one of the higher genera is predicated of the 
species in the category of essence: e.g. if any one has rendered 
'locomotion' as the genus of walking, it is not enough to show 



396 



that walking is 'motion' in order to show that it is 'locomotion', 
seeing that there are other forms of motion as well; but one 
must show in addition that walking does not partake of any of 
the species of motion produced by the same division except 
locomotion. For of necessity what partakes of the genus 
partakes also of one of the species produced by the first division 
of the genus. If, therefore, walking does not partake either of 
increase or decrease or of the other kinds of motion, clearly it 
would partake of locomotion, so that locomotion would be the 
genus of walking. 

Again, look among the things of which the given species is 
predicated as genus, and see if what is rendered as its genus be 
also predicated in the category of essence of the very things of 
which the species is so predicated, and likewise if all the genera 
higher than this genus are so predicated as well. For if there be 
anywhere a discrepancy, clearly what has been rendered is not 
the true genus: for had it been the genus, then both the genera 
higher than it, and it itself, would all have been predicated in 
the category of essence of those objects of which the species too 
is predicated in the category of essence. If, then, you are 
overthrowing a view, it is useful to see whether the genus fails 
to be predicated in the category of essence of those things of 
which the species too is predicated. If establishing a view, it is 
useful to see whether it is predicated in the category of essence: 
for if so, the result will be that the genus and the species will be 
predicated of the same object in the category of essence, so that 
the same object falls under two genera: the genera must 
therefore of necessity be subordinate one to the other, and 
therefore if it be shown that the one we wish to establish as 
genus is not subordinate to the species, clearly the species 
would be subordinate to it, so that you may take it as shown 
that it is the genus. 



397 



Look, also, at the definitions of the genera, and see whether 
they apply both to the given species and to the objects which 
partake of the species. For of necessity the definitions of its 
genera must be predicated of the species and of the objects 
which partake of the species: if, then, there be anywhere a 
discrepancy, clearly what has been rendered is not the genus. 

Again, see if he has rendered the differentia as the genus, e.g. 
'immortal' as the genus of 'God'. For 'immortal' is a differentia 
of 'living being', seeing that of living beings some are mortal 
and others immortal. Clearly, then, a bad mistake has been 
made; for the differentia of a thing is never its genus. And that 
this is true is clear: for a thing's differentia never signifies its 
essence, but rather some quality, as do 'walking' and 'biped'. 

Also, see whether he has placed the differentia inside the 
genus, e.g. by taking 'odd' as a number'. For 'odd' is a differentia 
of number, not a species. Nor is the differentia generally 
thought to partake of the genus: for what partakes of the genus 
is always either a species or an individual, whereas the 
differentia is neither a species nor an individual. Clearly, 
therefore, the differentia does not partake of the genus, so that 
'odd' too is no species but a differentia, seeing that it does not 
partake of the genus. 

Moreover, see whether he has placed the genus inside the 
species, e.g. by taking 'contact' to be a 'juncture', or 'mixture' a 
'fusion', or, as in Plato's definition,' 'locomotion' to be the same 
as 'carriage'. For there is no necessity that contact should be 
juncture: rather, conversely, juncture must be contact: for what 
is in contact is not always joined, though what is joined is 
always in contact. Likewise, also, in the remaining instances: for 
mixture is not always a 'fusion' (for to mix dry things does not 
fuse them), nor is locomotion always 'carriage'. For walking is 
not generally thought to be carriage: for 'carriage' is mostly used 



398 



of things that change one place for another involuntarily, as 
happens in the case of inanimate things. Clearly, also, the 
species, in the instances given, has a wider denotation than the 
genus, whereas it ought to be vice versa. Again, see whether he 
has placed the differentia inside the species, by taking (e.g.) 
'immortal' to be 'a god'. For the result will be that the species 
has an equal or wider denotation: and this cannot be, for always 
the differentia has an equal or a wider denotation than the 
species. Moreover, see whether he has placed the genus inside 
the differentia, by making 'colour' (e.g.) to be a thing that 
'pierces', or 'number' a thing that is 'odd'. Also, see if he has 
mentioned the genus as differentia: for it is possible for a man 
to bring forward a statement of this kind as well, e.g. that 
'mixture' is the differentia of 'fusion', or that change of place' is 
the differentia of 'carriage'. All such cases should be examined 
by means of the same principles: for they depend upon 
common rules: for the genus should have a wider denotation 
that its differentia, and also should not partake of its 
differentia; whereas, if it be rendered in this manner, neither of 
the aforesaid requirements can be satisfied: for the genus will 
both have a narrower denotation than its differentia, and will 
partake of it. 

Again, if no differentia belonging to the genus be predicated of 
the given species, neither will the genus be predicated of it; e.g. 
of 'soul' neither 'odd' nor 'even' is predicated: neither therefore 
is 'number'. Moreover, see whether the species is naturally prior 
and abolishes the genus along with itself: for the contrary is the 
general view. Moreover, if it be possible for the genus stated, or 
for its differentia, to be absent from the alleged species, e.g. for 
'movement' to be absent from the 'soul', or 'truth and falsehood' 
from 'opinion', then neither of the terms stated could be its 
genus or its differentia: for the general view is that the genus 
and the differentia accompany the species, as long as it exists. 



399 



Look and see, also, if what is placed in the genus partakes or 
could possibly partake of any contrary of the genus: for in that 
case the same thing will at the same time partake of contrary 
things, seeing that the genus is never absent from it, while it 
partakes, or can possibly partake, of the contrary genus as well. 
Moreover, see whether the species shares in any character 
which it is utterly impossible for any member of the genus to 
have. Thus (e.g.) if the soul has a share in life, while it is 
impossible for any number to live, then the soul could not be a 
species of number. 

You should look and see, also, if the species be a homonym of 
the genus, and employ as your elementary principles those 
already stated for dealing with homonymity: for the genus and 
the species are synonymous. 

Seeing that of every genus there is more than one species, look 
and see if it be impossible that there should be another species 
than the given one belonging to the genus stated: for if there 
should be none, then clearly what has been stated could not be 
a genus at all. 

Look and see, also, if he has rendered as genus a metaphorical 
expression, describing (e.g. 'temperance' as a 'harmony': a 
'harmony': for a genus is always predicated of its species in its 
literal sense, whereas 'harmony' is predicated of temperance 
not in a literal sense but metaphorically: for a harmony always 
consists in notes. 

Moreover, if there be any contrary of the species, examine it. 
The examination may take different forms; first of all see if the 



400 



contrary as well be found in the same genus as the species, 
supposing the genus to have no contrary; for contraries ought to 
be found in the same genus, if there be no contrary to the 
genus. Supposing, on the other hand, that there is a contrary to 
the genus, see if the contrary of the species be found in the 
contrary genus: for of necessity the contrary species must be in 
the contrary genus, if there be any contrary to the genus. Each 
of these points is made plain by means of induction. Again, see 
whether the contrary of the species be not found in any genus 
at all, but be itself a genus, e.g. 'good': for if this be not found in 
any genus, neither will its contrary be found in any genus, but 
will itself be a genus, as happens in the case of 'good' and 'evil': 
for neither of these is found in a genus, but each of them is a 
genus. Moreover, see if both genus and species be contrary to 
something, and one pair of contraries have an intermediary, but 
not the other. For if the genera have an intermediary, so should 
their species as well, and if the species have, so should their 
genera as well, as is the case with (1) virtue and vice and (2) 
justice and injustice: for each pair has an intermediary. An 
objection to this is that there is no intermediary between health 
and disease, although there is one between evil and good. Or 
see whether, though there be indeed an intermediary between 
both pairs, i.e. both between the species and between the 
genera, yet it be not similarly related, but in one case be a mere 
negation of the extremes, whereas in the other case it is a 
subject. For the general view is that the relation should be 
similar in both cases, as it is in the cases of virtue and vice and 
of justice and injustice: for the intermediaries between both are 
mere negations. Moreover, whenever the genus has no contrary, 
look and see not merely whether the contrary of the species be 
found in the same genus, but the intermediate as well: for the 
genus containing the extremes contains the intermediates as 
well, as (e.g.) in the case of white and black: for 'colour' is the 
genus both of these and of all the intermediate colours as well. 



401 



An objection may be raised that 'defect' and 'excess' are found 
in the same genus (for both are in the genus 'evil'), whereas 
moderate amount', the intermediate between them, is found 
not in 'evil' but in 'good'. Look and see also whether, while the 
genus has a contrary, the species has none; for if the genus be 
contrary to anything, so too is the species, as virtue to vice and 
justice to injustice. 

Likewise, also, if one were to look at other instances, one would 
come to see clearly a fact like this. An objection may be raised 
in the case of health and disease: for health in general is the 
contrary of disease, whereas a particular disease, being a 
species of disease, e.g. fever and ophthalmia and any other 
particular disease, has no contrary. 

If, therefore, you are demolishing a view, there are all these 
ways in which you should make your examination: for if the 
aforesaid characters do not belong to it, clearly what has been 
rendered is not the genus. If, on the other hand, you are 
establishing a view, there are three ways: in the first place, see 
whether the contrary of the species be found in the genus 
stated, suppose the genus have no contrary: for if the contrary 
be found in it, clearly the species in question is found in it as 
well. Moreover, see if the intermediate species is found in the 
genus stated: for whatever genus contains the intermediate 
contains the extremes as well. Again, if the genus have a 
contrary, look and see whether also the contrary species is 
found in the contrary genus: for if so, clearly also the species in 
question is found in the genus in question. 

Again, consider in the case of the inflexions and the co- 
ordinates of species and genus, and see whether they follow 
likewise, both in demolishing and in establishing a view. For 
whatever attribute belongs or does not belong to one belongs or 
does not belong at the same time to all; e.g. if justice be a 



402 



particular form of knowledge, then also 'justly' is 'knowingly' 
and the just man is a man of knowledge: whereas if any of 
these things be not so, then neither is any of the rest of them. 



Again, consider the case of things that bear a like relation to 
one another. Thus (e.g.) the relation of the pleasant to pleasure 
is like that of the useful to the good: for in each case the one 
produces the other. If therefore pleasure be a kind of 'good', 
then also the pleasant will be a kind of 'useful': for clearly it 
may be taken to be productive of good, seeing that pleasure is 
good. In the same way also consider the case of processes of 
generation and destruction; if (e.g.) to build be to be active, then 
to have built is to have been active, and if to learn be to 
recollect, then also to have learnt is to have recollected, and if to 
be decomposed be to be destroyed, then to have been 
decomposed is to have been destroyed, and decomposition is a 
kind of destruction. Consider also in the same way the case of 
things that generate or destroy, and of the capacities and uses 
of things; and in general, both in demolishing and in 
establishing an argument, you should examine things in the 
light of any resemblance of whatever description, as we were 
saying in the case of generation and destruction. For if what 
tends to destroy tends to decompose, then also to be destroyed 
is to be decomposed: and if what tends to generate tends to 
produce, then to be generated is to be produced, and generation 
is production. Likewise, also, in the case of the capacities and 
uses of things: for if a capacity be a disposition, then also to be 
capable of something is to be disposed to it, and if the use of 
anything be an activity, then to use it is to be active, and to have 
used it is to have been active. 



403 



If the opposite of the species be a privation, there are two ways 
of demolishing an argument, first of all by looking to see if the 
opposite be found in the genus rendered: for either the 
privation is to be found absolutely nowhere in the same genus, 
or at least not in the same ultimate genus: e.g. if the ultimate 
genus containing sight be sensation, then blindness will not be 
a sensation. Secondly, if there be a sensation. Secondly, if there 
be a privation opposed to both genus and species, but the 
opposite of the species be not found in the opposite of the 
genus, then neither could the species rendered be in the genus 
rendered. If, then, you are demolishing a view, you should follow 
the rule as stated; but if establishing one there is but one way: 
for if the opposite species be found in the opposite genus, then 
also the species in question would be found in the genus in 
question: e.g. if 'blindness' be a form of 'insensibility', then 
'sight' is a form of 'sensation'. 

Again, look at the negations of the genus and species and 
convert the order of terms, according to the method described 
in the case of Accident: e.g. if the pleasant be a kind of good, 
what is not good is not pleasant. For were this no something not 
good as well would then be pleasant. That, however, cannot be, 
for it is impossible, if 'good' be the genus of pleasant, that 
anything not good should be pleasant: for of things of which the 
genus is not predicated, none of the species is predicated either. 
Also, in establishing a view, you should adopt the same method 
of examination: for if what is not good be not pleasant, then 
what is pleasant is good, so that 'good' is the genus of 
'pleasant'. 

If the species be a relative term, see whether the genus be a 
relative term as well: for if the species be a relative term, so too 
is the genus, as is the case with 'double' and 'multiple': for each 
is a relative term. If, on the other hand, the genus be a relative 
term, there is no necessity that the species should be so as well: 



404 



for 'knowledge 'is a relative term, but not so 'grammar'. Or 
possibly not even the first statement would be generally 
considered true: for virtue is a kind of 'noble' and a kind of 
'good' thing, and yet, while 'virtue' is a relative term, 'good' and 
'noble' are not relatives but qualities. Again, see whether the 
species fails to be used in the same relation when called by its 
own name, and when called by the name of its genus: e.g. if the 
term 'double' be used to mean the double of a 'half, then also 
the term 'multiple' ought to be used to mean multiple of a 'half. 
Otherwise 'multiple' could not be the genus of 'double'. 

Moreover, see whether the term fail to be used in the same 
relation both when called by the name of its genus, and also 
when called by those of all the genera of its genus. For if the 
double be a multiple of a half, then 'in excess of 'will also be 
used in relation to a 'half: and, in general, the double will be 
called by the names of all the higher genera in relation to a 
'half. An objection may be raised that there is no necessity for a 
term to be used in the same relation when called by its own 
name and when called by that of its genus: for 'knowledge' is 
called knowledge 'of an object', whereas it is called a 'state' and 
'disposition' not of an 'object' but of the 'soul'. 

Again, see whether the genus and the species be used in the 
same way in respect of the inflexions they take, e.g. datives and 
genitives and all the rest. For as the species is used, so should 
the genus be as well, as in the case of 'double' and its higher 
genera: for we say both 'double of and 'multiple of a thing. 
Likewise, also, in the case of 'knowledge': for both knowledge' 
itself and its genera, e.g. 'disposition' and 'state', are said to be 
'of something. An objection may be raised that in some cases it 
is not so: for we say 'superior to' and 'contrary to' so and so, 
whereas 'other', which is the genus of these terms, demands 
not 'to' but 'than': for the expression is 'other than' so and so. 



405 



Again, see whether terms used in like case relationships fail to 
yield a like construction when converted, as do 'double' and 
'multiple'. For each of these terms takes a genitive both in itself 
and in its converted form: for we say both a half of and 'a 
fraction of something. The case is the same also as regards 
both 'knowledge' and 'conception': for these take a genitive, and 
by conversion an 'object of knowledge' and an 'object of 
conception' are both alike used with a dative. If, then, in any 
cases the constructions after conversion be not alike, clearly the 
one term is not the genus of the other. 

Again, see whether the species and the genus fail to be used in 
relation to an equal number of things: for the general view is 
that the uses of both are alike and equal in number, as is the 
case with 'present' and 'grant'. For a present' is of something or 
to some one, and also a 'grant' is of something and to some one: 
and 'grant' is the genus of 'present', for a 'present' is a 'grant 
that need not be returned'. In some cases, however, the number 
of relations in which the terms are used happens not to be 
equal, for while 'double' is double of something, we speak of 'in 
excess' or 'greater' in something, as well as of or than 
something: for what is in excess or greater is always in excess 
in something, as well as in excess of something. Hence the 
terms in question are not the genera of 'double', inasmuch as 
they are not used in relation to an equal number of things with 
the species. Or possibly it is not universally true that species 
and genus are used in relation to an equal number of things. 

See, also, if the opposite of the species have the opposite of the 
genus as its genus, e.g. whether, if 'multiple' be the genus of 
'double', 'fraction' be also the genus of 'half. For the opposite of 
the genus should always be the genus of the opposite species. If, 
then, any one were to assert that knowledge is a kind of 
sensation, then also the object of knowledge will have to be a 
kind of object of sensation, whereas it is not: for an object of 



406 



knowledge is not always an object of sensation: for objects of 
knowledge include some of the objects of intuition as well. 
Hence 'object of sensation' is not the genus of 'object of 
knowledge': and if this be so, neither is 'sensation' the genus of 
'knowledge'. 

Seeing that of relative terms some are of necessity found in, or 
used of, the things in relation to which they happen at any time 
to be used (e.g. 'disposition' and 'state' and 'balance'; for in 
nothing else can the aforesaid terms possibly be found except 
in the things in relation to which they are used), while others 
need not be found in the things in relation to which they are 
used at any time, though they still may be (e.g. if the term 
'object of knowledge' be applied to the soul: for it is quite 
possible that the knowledge of itself should be possessed by the 
soul itself, but it is not necessary, for it is possible for this same 
knowledge to be found in some one else), while for others, 
again, it is absolutely impossible that they should be found in 
the things in relation to which they happen at any time to be 
used (as e.g. that the contrary should be found in the contrary 
or knowledge in the object of knowledge, unless the object of 
knowledge happen to be a soul or a man) - you should look, 
therefore, and see whether he places a term of one kind inside a 
genus that is not of that kind, e.g. suppose he has said that 
'memory' is the 'abiding of knowledge'. For 'abiding' is always 
found in that which abides, and is used of that, so that the 
abiding of knowledge also will be found in knowledge. Memory, 
then, is found in knowledge, seeing that it is the abiding of 
knowledge. But this is impossible, for memory is always found 
in the soul. The aforesaid commonplace rule is common to the 
subject of Accident as well: for it is all the same to say that 
'abiding' is the genus of memory, or to allege that it is an 
accident of it. For if in any way whatever memory be the abiding 
of knowledge, the same argument in regard to it will apply. 



407 



Again, see if he has placed what is a 'state' inside the genus 
'activity', or an activity inside the genus 'state', e.g. by defining 
'sensation' as 'movement communicated through the body': for 
sensation is a 'state', whereas movement is an 'activity'. 
Likewise, also, if he has said that memory is a 'state that is 
retentive of a conception', for memory is never a state, but 
rather an activity. 

They also make a bad mistake who rank a 'state' within the 
'capacity' that attends it, e.g. by defining 'good temper' as the 
'control of anger', and 'courage' and 'justice' as 'control of fears' 
and of 'gains': for the terms 'courageous' and 'good-tempered' 
are applied to a man who is immune from passion, whereas 
'self-controlled' describes the man who is exposed to passion 
and not led by it. Quite possibly, indeed, each of the former is 
attended by a capacity such that, if he were exposed to passion, 
he would control it and not be led by it: but, for all that, this is 
not what is meant by being 'courageous' in the one case, and 
'good tempered' in the other; what is meant is an absolute 
immunity from any passions of that kind at all. 

Sometimes, also, people state any kind of attendant feature as 
the genus, e.g. 'pain' as the genus of 'anger' and 'conception' as 
that of conviction'. For both of the things in question follow in a 
certain sense upon the given species, but neither of them is 
genus to it. For when the angry man feels pain, the pain bas 
appeared in him earlier than the anger: for his anger is not the 
cause of his pain, but his pain of his anger, so that anger 
emphatically is not pain. By the same reasoning, neither is 
conviction conception: for it is possible to have the same 



408 



conception even without being convinced of it, whereas this is 
impossible if conviction be a species of conception: for it is 
impossible for a thing still to remain the same if it be entirely 
transferred out of its species, just as neither could the same 
animal at one time be, and at another not be, a man. If, on the 
other hand, any one says that a man who has a conception 
must of necessity be also convinced of it, then 'conception' and 
'conviction' will be used with an equal denotation, so that not 
even so could the former be the genus of the latter: for the 
denotation of the genus should be wider. 

See, also, whether both naturally come to be anywhere in the 
same thing: for what contains the species contains the genus as 
well: e.g. what contains 'white' contains 'colour' as well, and 
what contains 'knowledge of grammar' contains 'knowledge' as 
well. If, therefore, any one says that 'shame' is 'fear', or that 
'anger' is 'pain', the result will be that genus and species are not 
found in the same thing: for shame is found in the 'reasoning' 
faculty, whereas fear is in the 'spirited' faculty, and 'pain' is 
found in the faculty of 'desires', (for in this pleasure also is 
found), whereas 'anger' is found in the 'spirited' faculty. Hence 
the terms rendered are not the genera, seeing that they do not 
naturally come to be in the same faculty as the species. 
Likewise, also, if 'friendship' be found in the faculty of desires, 
you may take it that it is not a form of 'wishing': for wishing is 
always found in the 'reasoning' faculty. This commonplace rule 
is useful also in dealing with Accident: for the accident and that 
of which it is an accident are both found in the same thing, so 
that if they do not appear in the same thing, clearly it is not an 
accident. 

Again, see if the species partakes of the genus attributed only in 
some particular respect: for it is the general view that the genus 
is not thus imparted only in some particular respect: for a man 
is not an animal in a particular respect, nor is grammar 



409 



knowledge in a particular respect only. Likewise also in other 
instances. Look, therefore, and see if in the case of any of its 
species the genus be imparted only in a certain respect; e.g. if 
'animal' has been described as an 'object of perception' or of 
'sight'. For an animal is an object of perception or of sight in a 
particular respect only; for it is in respect of its body that it is 
perceived and seen, not in respect of its soul, so that - 'object of 
sight' and 'object of perception' could not be the genus of 
'animal'. 

Sometimes also people place the whole inside the part without 
detection, defining (e.g.) 'animal' as an 'animate body'; whereas 
the part is not predicated in any sense of the whole, so that 
'body' could not be the genus of animal, seeing that it is a part. 

See also if he has put anything that is blameworthy or 
objectionable into the class 'capacity' or 'capable', e.g. by 
defining a 'sophist' or a 'slanderer', or a 'thief as 'one who is 
capable of secretly thieving other people's property'. For none of 
the aforesaid characters is so called because he is 'capable' in 
one of these respects: for even God and the good man are 
capable of doing bad things, but that is not their character: for it 
is always in respect of their choice that bad men are so called. 
Moreover, a capacity is always a desirable thing: for even the 
capacities for doing bad things are desirable, and therefore it is 
we say that even God and the good man possess them; for they 
are capable (we say) of doing evil. So then 'capacity' can never 
be the genus of anything blameworthy. Else, the result will be 
that what is blameworthy is sometimes desirable: for there will 
be a certain form of capacity that is blameworthy. 

Also, see if he has put anything that is precious or desirable for 
its own sake into the class 'capacity' or 'capable' or 'productive' 
of anything. For capacity, and what is capable or productive of 
anything, is always desirable for the sake of something else. 



410 



Or see if he has put anything that exists in two genera or more 
into one of them only. For some things it is impossible to place 
in a single genus, e.g. the 'cheat' and the 'slanderer': for neither 
he who has the will without the capacity, nor he who has the 
capacity without the will, is a slanderer or cheat, but he who 
has both of them. Hence he must be put not into one genus, but 
into both the aforesaid genera. 

Moreover, people sometimes in converse order render genus as 
differentia, and differentia as genus, defining (e.g.) 
astonishment as 'excess of wonderment' and conviction as 
'vehemence of conception'. For neither 'excess' nor 'vehemence' 
is the genus, but the differentia: for astonishment is usually 
taken to be an 'excessive wonderment', and conviction to be a 
'vehement conception', so that 'wonderment' and 'conception' 
are the genus, while 'excess' and 'vehemence' are the 
differentia. Moreover, if any one renders 'excess' and 
'vehemence' as genera, then inanimate things will be convinced 
and astonished. For 'vehemence' and 'excess' of a thing are 
found in a thing which is thus vehement and in excess. If, 
therefore, astonishment be excess of wonderment the 
astonishment will be found in the wonderment, so that 
'wonderment' will be astonished! Likewise, also, conviction will 
be found in the conception, if it be 'vehemence of conception', 
so that the conception will be convinced. Moreover, a man who 
renders an answer in this style will in consequence find himself 
calling vehemence vehement and excess excessive: for there is 
such a thing as a vehement conviction: if then conviction be 
'vehemence', there would be a 'vehement vehemence'. Likewise, 
also, there is such a thing as excessive astonishment: if then 
astonishment be an excess, there would be an 'excessive 
excess'. Whereas neither of these things is generally believed, 
any more than that knowledge is a knower or motion a moving 
thing. 



411 



Sometimes, too, people make the bad mistake of putting an 
affection into that which is affected, as its genus, e.g. those who 
say that immortality is everlasting life: for immortality seems to 
be a certain affection or accidental feature of life. That this 
saying is true would appear clear if any one were to admit that a 
man can pass from being mortal and become immortal: for no 
one will assert that he takes another life, but that a certain 
accidental feature or affection enters into this one as it is. So 
then 'life' is not the genus of immortality. 

Again, see if to an affection he has ascribed as genus the object 
of which it is an affection, by defining (e.g.) wind as 'air in 
motion'. Rather, wind is 'a movement of air': for the same air 
persists both when it is in motion and when it is still. Hence 
wind is not 'air' at all: for then there would also have been wind 
when the air was not in motion, seeing that the same air which 
formed the wind persists. Likewise, also, in other cases of the 
kind. Even, then, if we ought in this instance to admit the point 
that wind is 'air in motion', yet we should accept a definition of 
the kind, not about all those things of which the genus is not 
true, but only in cases where the genus rendered is a true 
predicate. For in some cases, e.g. 'mud' or 'snow', it is not 
generally held to be true. For people tell you that snow is 'frozen 
water' and mud is earth mixed with moisture', whereas snow is 
not water, nor mud earth, so that neither of the terms rendered 
could be the genus: for the genus should be true of all its 
species. Likewise neither is wine 'fermented water', as 
Empedocles speaks of 'water fermented in wood';' for it simply 
is not water at all. 



412 



Moreover, see whether the term rendered fail to be the genus of 
anything at all; for then clearly it also fails to be the genus of 
the species mentioned. Examine the point by seeing whether 
the objects that partake of the genus fail to be specifically 
different from one another, e.g. white objects: for these do not 
differ specifically from one another, whereas of a genus the 
species are always different, so that 'white' could not be the 
genus of anything. 

Again, see whether he has named as genus or differentia some 
feature that goes with everything: for the number of attributes 
that follow everything is comparatively large: thus (e.g.) 'Being' 
and 'Unity' are among the number of attributes that follow 
everything. If, therefore, he has rendered 'Being' as a genus, 
clearly it would be the genus of everything, seeing that it is 
predicated of everything; for the genus is never predicated of 
anything except of its species. Hence Unity, inter alia, will be a 
species of Being. The result, therefore, is that of all things of 
which the genus is predicated, the species is predicated as well, 
seeing that Being and Unity are predicates of absolutely 
everything, whereas the predication of the species ought to be 
of narrower range. If, on the other hand, he has named as 
differentia some attribute that follows everything, clearly the 
denotation of the differentia will be equal to, or wider than, that 
of the genus. For if the genus, too, be some attribute that follows 
everything, the denotation of the differentia will be equal to its 
denotation, while if the genus do not follow everything, it will 
be still wider. 

Moreover, see if the description 'inherent in S' be used of the 
genus rendered in relation to its species, as it is used of 'white' 
in the case of snow, thus showing clearly that it could not be the 
genus: for 'true of S' is the only description used of the genus in 



413 



relation to its species. Look and see also if the genus fails to be 
synonymous with its species. For the genus is always predicated 
of its species synonymously. 

Moreover, beware, whenever both species and genus have a 
contrary, and he places the better of the contraries inside the 
worse genus: for the result will be that the remaining species 
will be found in the remaining genus, seeing that contraries are 
found in contrary genera, so that the better species will be 
found in the worse genus and the worse in the better: whereas 
the usual view is that of the better species the genus too is 
better. Also see if he has placed the species inside the worse 
and not inside the better genus, when it is at the same time 
related in like manner to both, as (e.g.) if he has defined the 
'soul' as a 'form of motion' or 'a form of moving thing'. For the 
same soul is usually thought to be a principle alike of rest and 
of motion, so that, if rest is the better of the two, this is the 
genus into which the soul should have been put. 

Moreover, judge by means of greater and less degrees: if 
overthrowing a view, see whether the genus admits of a greater 
degree, whereas neither the species itself does so, nor any term 
that is called after it: e.g. if virtue admits of a greater degree, so 
too does justice and the just man: for one man is called 'more 
just than another'. If, therefore, the genus rendered admits of a 
greater degree, whereas neither the species does so itself nor 
yet any term called after it, then what has been rendered could 
not be the genus. 

Again, if what is more generally, or as generally, thought to be 
the genus be not so, clearly neither is the genus rendered. The 
commonplace rule in question is useful especially in cases 
where the species appears to have several predicates in the 
category of essence, and where no distinction has been drawn 
between them, and we cannot say which of them is genus; e.g. 



414 



both 'pain' and the 'conception of a slight' are usually thought 
to be predicates of 'anger in the category of essence: for the 
angry man is both in pain and also conceives that he is slighted. 
The same mode of inquiry may be applied also to the case of 
the species, by comparing it with some other species: for if the 
one which is more generally, or as generally, thought to be 
found in the genus rendered be not found therein, then clearly 
neither could the species rendered be found therein. 

In demolishing a view, therefore, you should follow the rule as 
stated. In establishing one, on the other hand, the 
commonplace rule that you should see if both the genus 
rendered and the species admit of a greater degree will not 
serve: for even though both admit it, it is still possible for one 
not to be the genus of the other. For both 'beautiful' and 'white' 
admit of a greater degree, and neither is the genus of the other. 
On the other hand, the comparison of the genera and of the 
species one with another is of use: e.g. supposing A and B to 
have a like claim to be genus, then if one be a genus, so also is 
the other. Likewise, also, if what has less claim be a genus, so 
also is what has more claim: e.g. if 'capacity' have more claim 
than 'virtue' to be the genus of self-control, and virtue be the 
genus, so also is capacity. The same observations will apply also 
in the case of the species. For instance, supposing A and B to 
have a like claim to be a species of the genus in question, then if 
the one be a species, so also is the other: and if that which is 
less generally thought to be so be a species, so also is that 
which is more generally thought to be so. 

Moreover, to establish a view, you should look and see if the 
genus is predicated in the category of essence of those things of 
which it has been rendered as the genus, supposing the species 
rendered to be not one single species but several different ones: 
for then clearly it will be the genus. If, on the other, the species 
rendered be single, look and see whether the genus be 



415 



predicated in the category of essence of other species as well: 
for then, again, the result will be that it is predicated of several 
different species. 

Since some people think that the differentia, too, is a predicate 
of the various species in the category of essence, you should 
distinguish the genus from the differentia by employing the 
aforesaid elementary principles - (a) that the genus has a wider 
denotation than the differentia; (b) that in rendering the 
essence of a thing it is more fitting to state the genus than the 
differentia: for any one who says that 'man' is an 'animal' 
shows what man is better than he who describes him as 
'walking'; also (c) that the differentia always signifies a quality 
of the genus, whereas the genus does not do this of the 
differentia: for he who says 'walking' describes an animal of a 
certain quality, whereas he who says 'animal' describes an 
animal of a certain quality, whereas he who says 'animal' does 
not describe a walking thing of a certain quality 

The differentia, then, should be distinguished from the genus in 
this manner. Now seeing it is generally held that if what is 
musical, in being musical, possesses knowledge in some 
respect, then also 'music' is a particular kind of 'knowledge'; 
and also that if what walks is moved in walking, then 'walking' 
is a particular kind of 'movement'; you should therefore 
examine in the aforesaid manner any genus in which you want 
to establish the existence of something; e.g. if you wish to prove 
that 'knowledge' is a form of 'conviction', see whether the 
knower in knowing is convinced: for then clearly knowledge 
would be a particular kind of conviction. You should proceed in 
the same way also in regard to the other cases of this kind. 

Moreover, seeing that it is difficult to distinguish whatever 
always follows along with a thing, and is not convertible with it, 
from its genus, if A follows B universally, whereas B does not 



416 



follow A universally - as e.g. 'rest' always follows a 'calm' and 
'divisibility' follows 'number', but not conversely (for the 
divisible is not always a number, nor rest a calm) - you may 
yourself assume in your treatment of them that the one which 
always follows is the genus, whenever the other is not 
convertible with it: if, on the other hand, some one else puts 
forward the proposition, do not accept it universally. An 
objection to it is that 'not-being' always follows what is 'coming 
to be' (for what is coming to be is not) and is not convertible 
with it (for what is not is not always coming to be), and that still 
'not-being' is not the genus of 'coming to be': for 'not-being' has 
not any species at all. Questions, then, in regard to Genus 
should be investigated in the ways described. 



BookV 



The question whether the attribute stated is or is not a property, 
should be examined by the following methods: 

Any 'property' rendered is always either essential and 
permanent or relative and temporary: e.g. it is an 'essential 
property' of man to be 'by nature a civilized animal': a 'relative 
property' is one like that of the soul in relation to the body, viz. 
that the one is fitted to command, and the other to obey: a 
'permanent property' is one like the property which belongs to 
God, of being an 'immortal living being': a 'temporary property' 



417 



is one like the property which belongs to any particular man of 
walking in the gymnasium. 

[The rendering of a property 'relatively' gives rise either to two 
problems or to four. For if he at the same time render this 
property of one thing and deny it of another, only two problems 
arise, as in the case of a statement that it is a property of a man, 
in relation to a horse, to be a biped. For one might try both to 
show that a man is not a biped, and also that a horse is a biped: 
in both ways the property would be upset. If on the other hand 
he render one apiece of two attributes to each of two things, 
and deny it in each case of the other, there will then be four 
problems; as in the case of a statement that it is a property of a 
man in relation to a horse for the former to be a biped and the 
latter a quadruped. For then it is possible to try to show both 
that a man is not naturally a biped, and that he is a quadruped, 
and also that the horse both is a biped, and is not a quadruped. 
If you show any of these at all, the intended attribute is 
demolished.] 

An 'essential' property is one which is rendered of a thing in 
comparison with everything else and distinguishes the said 
thing from everything else, as does 'a mortal living being 
capable of receiving knowledge' in the case of man. A 'relative' 
property is one which separates its subject off not from 
everything else but only from a particular definite thing, as does 
the property which virtue possesses, in comparison with 
knowledge, viz. that the former is naturally produced in more 
than one faculty, whereas the latter is produced in that of 
reason alone, and in those who have a reasoning faculty. A 
'permanent' property is one which is true at every time, and 
never fails, like being' compounded of soul and body', in the 
case of a living creature. A 'temporary' property is one which is 
true at some particular time, and does not of necessity always 



418 



follow; as, of some particular man, that he walks in the market- 
place. 

To render a property 'relatively' to something else means to 
state the difference between them as it is found either 
universally and always, or generally and in most cases: thus a 
difference that is found universally and always, is one such as 
man possesses in comparison with a horse, viz. being a biped: 
for a man is always and in every case a biped, whereas a horse 
is never a biped at any time. On the other hand, a difference 
that is found generally and in most cases, is one such as the 
faculty of reason possesses in comparison with that of desire 
and spirit, in that the former commands, while the latter obeys: 
for the reasoning faculty does not always command, but 
sometimes also is under command, nor is that of desire and 
spirit always under command, but also on occasion assumes 
the command, whenever the soul of a man is vicious. 

Of 'properties' the most 'arguable' are the essential and 
permanent and the relative. For a relative property gives rise, as 
we said before, to several questions: for of necessity the 
questions arising are either two or four, or that arguments in 
regard to these are several. An essential and a permanent 
property you can discuss in relation to many things, or can 
observe in relation to many periods of time: if essential', discuss 
it in comparison with many things: for the property ought to 
belong to its subject in comparison with every single thing that 
is, so that if the subject be not distinguished by it in comparison 
with everything else, the property could not have been rendered 
correctly. So a permanent property you should observe in 
relation to many periods of time; for if it does not or did not, or 
is not going to, belong, it will not be a property. On the other 
hand, about a temporary property we do not inquire further 
than in regard to the time called 'the present'; and so 
arguments in regard to it are not many; whereas an arguable' 



419 



question is one in regard to which it is possible for arguments 
both numerous and good to arise. 

The so-called 'relative' property, then, should be examined by 
means of the commonplace arguments relating to Accident, to 
see whether it belongs to the one thing and not to the other: on 
the other hand, permanent and essential properties should be 
considered by the following methods. 



First, see whether the property has or has not been rendered 
correctly. Of a rendering being incorrect or correct, one test is to 
see whether the terms in which the property is stated are not or 
are more intelligible - for destructive purposes, whether they 
are not so, and for constructive purposes, whether they are so. 
Of the terms not being more intelligible, one test is to see 
whether the property which he renders is altogether more 
unintelligible than the subject whose property he has stated: 
for, if so, the property will not have been stated correctly. For the 
object of getting a property constituted is to be intelligible: the 
terms therefore in which it is rendered should be more 
intelligible: for in that case it will be possible to conceive it more 
adequately, e.g. any one who has stated that it is a property of 
'fire' to 'bear a very close resemblance to the soul', uses the 
term 'soul', which is less intelligible than 'fire' - for we know 
better what fire is than what soul is -, and therefore a 'very 
close resemblance to the soul' could not be correctly stated to 
be a property of fire. Another test is to see whether the 
attribution of A (property) to B (subject) fails to be more 
intelligible. For not only should the property be more intelligible 
than its subject, but also it should be something whose 



420 



attribution to the particular subject is a more intelligible 
attribution. For he who does not know whether it is an attribute 
of the particular subject at all, will not know either whether it 
belongs to it alone, so that whichever of these results happens, 
its character as a property becomes obscure. Thus (e.g.) a man 
who has stated that it is a property of fire to be 'the primary 
element wherein the soul is naturally found', has introduced a 
subject which is less intelligible than 'fire', viz. whether the soul 
is found in it, and whether it is found there primarily; and 
therefore to be 'the primary element in which the soul is 
naturally found' could not be correctly stated to be a property of 
'fire'. On the other hand, for constructive purposes, see whether 
the terms in which the property is stated are more intelligible, 
and if they are more intelligible in each of the aforesaid ways. 
For then the property will have been correctly stated in this 
respect: for of constructive arguments, showing the correctness 
of a rendering, some will show the correctness merely in this 
respect, while others will show it without qualification. Thus 
(e.g.) a man who has said that the 'possession of sensation' is a 
property of 'animal' has both used more intelligible terms and 
has rendered the property more intelligible in each of the 
aforesaid senses; so that to 'possess sensation' would in this 
respect have been correctly rendered as a property of 'animal'. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see whether any of the terms 
rendered in the property is used in more than one sense, or 
whether the whole expression too signifies more than one 
thing. For then the property will not have been correctly stated. 
Thus (e.g.) seeing that to 'being natural sentient' signifies more 
than one thing, viz. (1) to possess sensation, (2) to use one's 
sensation, being naturally sentient' could not be a correct 
statement of a property of 'animal'. The reason why the term 
you use, or the whole expression signifying the property, should 
not bear more than one meaning is this, that an expression 
bearing more than one meaning makes the object described 



421 



obscure, because the man who is about to attempt an argument 
is in doubt which of the various senses the expression bears: 
and this will not do, for the object of rendering the property is 
that he may understand. Moreover, in addition to this, it is 
inevitable that those who render a property after this fashion 
should be somehow refuted whenever any one addresses his 
syllogism to that one of the term's several meanings which does 
not agree. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see 
whether both all the terms and also the expression as a whole 
avoid bearing more than one sense: for then the property will 
have been correctly stated in this respect. Thus (e.g.) seeing that 
'body' does not bear several meanings, nor quickest to move 
upwards in space', nor yet the whole expression made by 
putting them together, it would be correct in this respect to say 
that it is a property of fire to be the 'body quickest to move 
upwards in space'. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if the term of which he 
renders the property is used in more than one sense, and no 
distinction has been drawn as to which of them it is whose 
property he is stating: for then the property will not have been 
correctly rendered. The reasons why this is so are quite clear 
from what has been said above: for the same results are bound 
to follow. Thus (e.g.) seeing that 'the knowledge of this' signifies 
many things for it means (1) the possession of knowledge by it, 
(2) the use of its knowledge by it, (3) the existence of knowledge 
about it, (4) the use of knowledge about it - no property of the 
'knowledge of this' could be rendered correctly unless he draw a 
distinction as to which of these it is whose property he is 
rendering. For constructive purposes, a man should see if the 
term of which he is rendering the property avoids bearing many 
senses and is one and simple: for then the property will have 
been correctly stated in this respect. Thus (e.g.) seeing that 
'man' is used in a single sense, 'naturally civilized animal' 
would be correctly stated as a property of man. 



422 



Next, for destructive purposes, see whether the same term has 
been repeated in the property. For people often do this 
undetected in rendering 'properties' also, just as they do in their 
'definitions' as well: but a property to which this has happened 
will not have been correctly stated: for the repetition of it 
confuses the hearer; thus inevitably the meaning becomes 
obscure, and further, such people are thought to babble. 
Repetition of the same term is likely to happen in two ways; one 
is, when a man repeatedly uses the same word, as would 
happen if any one were to render, as a property of fire, 'the body 
which is the most rarefied of bodies' (for he has repeated the 
word 'body'); the second is, if a man replaces words by their 
definitions, as would happen if any one were to render, as a 
property of earth, 'the substance which is by its nature most 
easily of all bodies borne downwards in space', and were then to 
substitute 'substances of such and such a kind' for the word 
'bodies': for 'body' and 'a substance of such and such a kind' 
mean one and the same thing. For he will have repeated the 
word 'substance', and accordingly neither of the properties 
would be correctly stated. For constructive purposes, on the 
other hand, see whether he avoids ever repeating the same 
term; for then the property will in this respect have been 
correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) seeing that he who has stated 
'animal capable of acquiring knowledge' as a property of man 
has avoided repeating the same term several times, the 
property would in this respect have been correctly rendered of 
man. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered in 
the property any such term as is a universal attribute. For one 
which does not distinguish its subject from other things is 
useless, and it is the business of the language Of 'properties', as 
also of the language of definitions, to distinguish. In the case 
contemplated, therefore, the property will not have been 
correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) a man who has stated that it is a 



423 



property of knowledge to be a 'conception incontrovertible by 
argument, because of its unity', has used in the property a term 
of that kind, viz. 'unity', which is a universal attribute; and 
therefore the property of knowledge could not have been 
correctly stated. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, 
see whether he has avoided all terms that are common to 
everything and used a term that distinguishes the subject from 
something: for then the property will in this respect have been 
correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as he who has said that it 
is a property of a 'living creature' to 'have a soul' has used no 
term that is common to everything, it would in this respect 
have been correctly stated to be a property of a 'living creature' 
to 'have a soul'. 

Next, for destructive purposes see whether he renders more 
than one property of the same thing, without a definite proviso 
that he is stating more than one: for then the property will not 
have been correctly stated. For just as in the case of definitions 
too there should be no further addition beside the expression 
which shows the essence, so too in the case of properties 
nothing further should be rendered beside the expression that 
constitutes the property mentioned: for such an addition is 
made to no purpose. Thus (e.g.) a man who has said that it is a 
property of fire to be 'the most rarefied and lightest body' has 
rendered more than one property (for each term is a true 
predicate of fire alone); and so it could not be a correctly stated 
property of fire to be 'the most rarefied and lightest body'. On 
the other hand, for constructive purposes, see whether he has 
avoided rendering more than one property of the same thing, 
and has rendered one only: for then the property will in this 
respect have been correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) a man who has 
said that it is a property of a liquid to be a 'body adaptable to 
every shape' has rendered as its property a single character and 
not several, and so the property of 'liquid' would in this respect 
have been correctly stated. 



424 



Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has employed 
either the actual subject whose property he is rendering, or any 
of its species: for then the property will not have been correctly 
stated. For the object of rendering the property is that people 
may understand: now the subject itself is just as unintelligible 
as it was to start with, while any one of its species is posterior 
to it, and so is no more intelligible. Accordingly it is impossible 
to understand anything further by the use of these terms. Thus 
(e.g.) any one who has said that it is property of 'animal' to be 
'the substance to which «man» belongs as a species' has 
employed one of its species, and therefore the property could 
not have been correctly stated. For constructive purposes, on 
the other hand, see whether he avoids introducing either the 
subject itself or any of its species: for then the property will in 
this respect have been correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) a man who 
has stated that it is a property of a living creature to be 
'compounded of soul and body' has avoided introducing among 
the rest either the subject itself or any of its species, and 
therefore in this respect the property of a 'living creature' would 
have been correctly rendered. 

You should inquire in the same way also in the case of other 
terms that do or do not make the subject more intelligible: thus, 
for destructive purposes, see whether he has employed 
anything either opposite to the subject or, in general, anything 
simultaneous by nature with it or posterior to it: for then the 
property will not have been correctly stated. For an opposite is 
simultaneous by nature with its opposite, and what is 
simultaneous by nature or is posterior to it does not make its 
subject more intelligible. Thus (e.g.) any one who has said that it 



425 



is a property of good to be 'the most direct opposite of evil', has 
employed the opposite of good, and so the property of good 
could not have been correctly rendered. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, see whether he has avoided 
employing anything either opposite to, or, in general, 
simultaneous by nature with the subject, or posterior to it: for 
then the property will in this respect have been correctly 
rendered. Thus (e.g.) a man who has stated that it is a property 
of knowledge to be 'the most convincing conception' has 
avoided employing anything either opposite to, or simultaneous 
by nature with, or posterior to, the subject; and so the property 
of knowledge would in this respect have been correctly stated. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered as 
property something that does not always follow the subject but 
sometimes ceases to be its property: for then the property will 
not have been correctly described. For there is no necessity 
either that the name of the subject must also be true of 
anything to which we find such an attribute belonging; nor yet 
that the name of the subject will be untrue of anything to which 
such an attribute is found not to belong. Moreover, in addition 
to this, even after he has rendered the property it will not be 
clear whether it belongs, seeing that it is the kind of attribute 
that may fall: and so the property will not be clear. Thus (e.g.) a 
man who has stated that it is a property of animal 'sometimes 
to move and sometimes to stand still' rendered the kind of 
property which sometimes is not a property, and so the 
property could not have been correctly stated. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, see whether he has rendered 
something that of necessity must always be a property: for then 
the property will have been in this respect correctly stated. Thus 
(e.g.) a man who has stated that it is a property of virtue to be 
'what makes its possessor good' has rendered as property 
something that always follows, and so the property of virtue 
would in this respect have been correctly rendered. 



426 



Next, for destructive purposes, see whether in rendering the 
property of the present time he has omitted to make a definite 
proviso that it is the property of the present time which he is 
rendering: for else the property will not have been correctly 
stated. For in the first place, any unusual procedure always 
needs a definite proviso: and it is the usual procedure for 
everybody to render as property some attribute that always 
follows. In the second place, a man who omits to provide 
definitely whether it was the property of the present time 
which he intended to state, is obscure: and one should not give 
any occasion for adverse criticism. Thus (e.g.) a man who has 
stated it as the property of a particular man 'to be sitting with a 
particular man', states the property of the present time, and so 
he cannot have rendered the property correctly, seeing that he 
has described it without any definite proviso. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, see whether, in rendering the 
property of the present time, he has, in stating it, made a 
definite proviso that it is the property of the present time that 
he is stating: for then the property will in this respect have been 
correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) a man who has said that it is the 
property of a particular man 'to be walking now', has made this 
distinction in his statement, and so the property would have 
been correctly stated. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered a 
property of the kind whose appropriateness is not obvious 
except by sensation: for then the property will not have been 
correctly stated. For every sensible attribute, once it is taken 
beyond the sphere of sensation, becomes uncertain. For it is not 
clear whether it still belongs, because it is evidenced only by 
sensation. This principle will be true in the case of any 
attributes that do not always and necessarily follow. Thus (e.g.) 
any one who has stated that it is a property of the sun to be 'the 
brightest star that moves over the earth', has used in describing 
the property an expression of that kind, viz. 'to move over the 



427 



earth', which is evidenced by sensation; and so the sun's 
property could not have been correctly rendered: for it will be 
uncertain, whenever the sun sets, whether it continues to move 
over the earth, because sensation then fails us. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, see whether he has rendered the 
property of a kind that is not obvious to sensation, or, if it be 
sensible, must clearly belong of necessity: for then the property 
will in this respect have been correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) a man 
who has stated that it is a property of a surface to be 'the 
primary thing that is coloured', has introduced amongst the rest 
a sensible quality, 'to be coloured', but still a quality such as 
manifestly always belongs, and so the property of 'surface' 
would in this respect have been correctly rendered. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered the 
definition as a property: for then the property will not have 
been correctly stated: for the property of a thing ought not to 
show its essence. Thus (e.g.) a man who has said that it is the 
property of man to be 'a walking, biped animal' has rendered a 
property of man so as to signify his essence, and so the property 
of man could not have been correctly rendered. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, see whether the property which 
he has rendered forms a predicate convertible with its subject, 
without, however, signifying its essence: for then the property 
will in this respect have been correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) he 
who has stated that it is a property of man to be a 'naturally 
civilized animal' has rendered the property so as to be 
convertible with its subject, without, however, showing its 
essence, and so the property of man' would in this respect have 
been correctly rendered. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see whether he has rendered the 
property without having placed the subject within its essence. 
For of properties, as also of definitions, the first term to be 
rendered should be the genus, and then the rest of it should be 



428 



appended immediately afterwards, and should distinguish its 
subject from other things. Hence a property which is not stated 
in this way could not have been correctly rendered. Thus (e.g.) a 
man who has said that it is a property of a living creature to 
'have a soul' has not placed 'living creature' within its essence, 
and so the property of a living creature could not have been 
correctly stated. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, 
see whether a man first places within its essence the subject 
whose property he is rendering, and then appends the rest: for 
then the property will in this respect have been correctly 
rendered. Thus (e.g.) he who has stated that is a property of 
man to be an 'animal capable of receiving knowledge', has 
rendered the property after placing the subject within its 
essence, and so the property of 'man' would in this respect have 
been correctly rendered. 



The inquiry, then, whether the property has been correctly 
rendered or no, should be made by these means. The question, 
on the other hand, whether what is stated is or is not a property 
at all, you should examine from the following points of view. For 
the commonplace arguments which establish absolutely that 
the property is accurately stated will be the same as those that 
constitute it a property at all: accordingly they will be described 
in the course of them. 

Firstly, then, for destructive purposes, take a look at each 
subject of which he has rendered the property, and see (e.g.) if it 
fails to belong to any of them at all, or to be true of them in that 
particular respect, or to be a property of each of them in respect 
of that character of which he has rendered the property: for 



429 



then what is stated to be a property will not be a property. Thus, 
for example, inasmuch as it is not true of the geometrician that 
he 'cannot be deceived by an argument' (for a geometrician is 
deceived when his figure is misdrawn), it could not be a 
property of the man of science that he is not deceived by an 
argument. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see 
whether the property rendered be true of every instance, and 
true in that particular respect: for then what is stated not to be 
a property will be a property. Thus, for example, in as much as 
the description 'an animal capable of receiving knowledge' is 
true of every man, and true of him qua man, it would be a 
property of man to be 'an animal capable of receiving 
knowledge', commonplace rule means - for destructive 
purposes, see if the description fails to be true of that of which 
the name is true; and if the name fails to be true of that of 
which the description is true: for constructive purposes, on the 
other hand, see if the description too is predicated of that of 
which the name is predicated, and if the name too is predicated 
of that of which the description is predicated.] 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if the description fails to 
apply to that to which the name applies, and if the name fails to 
apply to that to which the description applies: for then what is 
stated to be a property will not be a property. Thus (e.g.) 
inasmuch as the description 'a living being that partakes of 
knowledge' is true of God, while 'man' is not predicated of God, 
to be a living being that partakes of knowledge' could not be a 
property of man. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, 
see if the name as well be predicated of that of which the 
description is predicated, and if the description as well be 
predicated of that of which the name is predicated. For then 
what is stated not to be a property will be a property. Thus (e.g.) 
the predicate 'living creature' is true of that of which 'having a 
soul' is true, and 'having a soul' is true of that of which the 



430 



predicate 'living creature' is true; and so 'having a soul would be 
a property of 'living creature'. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has rendered a subject 
as a property of that which is described as 'in the subject': for 
then what has been stated to be a property will not be a 
property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as he who has rendered 'fire' as 
the property of 'the body with the most rarefied particles', has 
rendered the subject as the property of its predicate, 'fire' could 
not be a property of 'the body with the most rarefied particles'. 
The reason why the subject will not be a property of that which 
is found in the subject is this, that then the same thing will be 
the property of a number of things that are specifically 
different. For the same thing has quite a number of specifically 
different predicates that belong to it alone, and the subject will 
be a property of all of these, if any one states the property in 
this way. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if he 
has rendered what is found in the subject as a property of the 
subject: for then what has been stated not to be a property will 
be a property, if it be predicated only of the things of which it 
has been stated to be the property. Thus (e.g.) he who has said 
that it is a property of 'earth' to be 'specifically the heaviest 
body' has rendered of the subject as its property something that 
is said of the thing in question alone, and is said of it in the 
manner in which a property is predicated, and so the property 
of earth would have been rightly stated. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has rendered the 
property as partaken of: for then what is stated to be a property 
will not be a property. For an attribute of which the subject 
partakes is a constituent part of its essence: and an attribute of 
that kind would be a differentia applying to some one species. 
E.g. inasmuch as he who has said that 'walking on two feet' is 
property of man has rendered the property as partaken of, 
'walking on two feet' could not be a property of 'man'. For 



431 



constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if he has avoided 
rendering the property as partaken of, or as showing the 
essence, though the subject is predicated convertibly with it: for 
then what is stated not to be a property will be a property. Thus 
(e.g.) he who has stated that to be 'naturally sentient' is a 
property of 'animal' has rendered the property neither as 
partaken of nor as showing the essence, though the subject is 
predicated convertibly with it; and so to be 'naturally sentient' 
would be a property of 'animal'. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if the property cannot 
possibly belong simultaneously, but must belong either as 
posterior or as prior to the attribute described in the name: for 
then what is stated to be a property will not be a property either 
never, or not always. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is possible for 
the attribute 'walking through the market-place' to belong to an 
object as prior and as posterior to the attribute 'man', 'walking 
through the market-place' could not be a property of 'man' 
either never, or not always. For constructive purposes, on the 
other hand, see if it always and of necessity belongs 
simultaneously, without being either a definition or a 
differentia: for then what is stated not to be a property will be a 
property. Thus (e.g.) the attribute 'an animal capable of receiving 
knowledge' always and of necessity belongs simultaneously 
with the attribute 'man', and is neither differentia nor definition 
of its subject, and so 'an animal capable of receiving knowledge' 
would be a property of 'man'. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if the same thing fails to be a 
property of things that are the same as the subject, so far as 
they are the same: for then what is stated to be a property will 
not be a property. Thus, for example, inasmuch as it is no 
property of a 'proper object of pursuit' to 'appear good to certain 
persons', it could not be a property of the 'desirable' either to 
'appear good to certain persons': for 'proper object of pursuit' 



432 



and 'desirable' mean the same. For constructive purposes, on 
the other hand, see if the same thing be a property of 
something that is the same as the subject, in so far as it is the 
same. For then is stated not to be a property will be a property. 
Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is called a property of a man, in so far 
as he is a man, 'to have a tripartite soul', it would also be a 
property of a mortal, in so far as he is a mortal, to have a 
tripartite soul. This commonplace rule is useful also in dealing 
with Accident: for the same attributes ought either to belong or 
not belong to the same things, in so far as they are the same. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if the property of things that 
are the same in kind as the subject fails to be always the same 
in kind as the alleged property: for then neither will what is 
stated to be the property of the subject in question. Thus (e.g.) 
inasmuch as a man and a horse are the same in kind, and it is 
not always a property of a horse to stand by its own initiative, it 
could not be a property of a man to move by his own initiative; 
for to stand and to move by his own initiative are the same in 
kind, because they belong to each of them in so far as each is an 
'animal'. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if of 
things that are the same in kind as the subject the property that 
is the same as the alleged property is always true: for then what 
is stated not to be a property will be a property. Thus (e.g.) since 
it is a property of man to be a 'walking biped,' it would also be a 
property of a bird to be a 'flying biped': for each of these is the 
same in kind, in so far as the one pair have the sameness of 
species that fall under the same genus, being under the genus 
'animal', while the other pair have that of differentiae of the 
genus, viz. of 'animal'. This commonplace rule is deceptive 
whenever one of the properties mentioned belongs to some one 
species only while the other belongs to many, as does 'walking 
quadruped'. 



433 



Inasmuch as 'same' and 'different' are terms used in several 
senses, it is a job to render to a sophistical questioner a 
property that belongs to one thing and that only. For an 
attribute that belongs to something qualified by an accident will 
also belong to the accident taken along with the subject which 
it qualifies; e.g. an attribute that belongs to 'man' will belong 
also to 'white man', if there be a white man, and one that 
belongs to 'white man' will belong also to 'man'. One might, 
then, bring captious criticism against the majority of properties, 
by representing the subject as being one thing in itself, and 
another thing when combined with its accident, saying, for 
example, that 'man' is one thing, and white man' another, and 
moreover by representing as different a certain state and what 
is called after that state. For an attribute that belongs to the 
state will belong also to what is called after that state, and one 
that belongs to what is called after a state will belong also to 
the state: e.g. inasmuch as the condition of the scientist is 
called after his science, it could not be a property of 'science' 
that it is 'incontrovertible by argument'; for then the scientist 
also will be incontrovertible by argument. For constructive 
purposes, however, you should say that the subject of an 
accident is not absolutely different from the accident taken 
along with its subject; though it is called 'another' thing 
because the mode of being of the two is different: for it is not 
the same thing for a man to be a man and for a white man to be 
a white man. Moreover, you should take a look along at the 
inflections, and say that the description of the man of science is 
wrong: one should say not 'it' but 'he is incontrovertible by 
argument'; while the description of Science is wrong too: one 
should say not 'it' but 'she is incontrovertible by argument'. For 
against an objector who sticks at nothing the defence should 
stick at nothing. 



434 



Next, for destructive purposes, see if, while intending to render 
an attribute that naturally belongs, he states it in his language 
in such a way as to indicate one that invariably belongs: for 
then it would be generally agreed that what has been stated to 
be a property is upset. Thus (e.g.) the man who has said that 
'biped' is a property of man intends to render the attribute that 
naturally belongs, but his expression actually indicates one that 
invariably belongs: accordingly, 'biped' could not be a property 
of man: for not every man is possessed of two feet. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if he intends to 
render the property that naturally belongs, and indicates it in 
that way in his language: for then the property will not be upset 
in this respect. Thus (e.g.) he who renders as a property of 'man' 
the phrase 'an animal capable of receiving knowledge' both 
intends, and by his language indicates, the property that 
belongs by nature, and so 'an animal capable of receiving 
knowledge' would not be upset or shown in that respect not to 
be a property of man. 

Moreover, as regards all the things that are called as they are 
primarily after something else, or primarily in themselves, it is a 
job to render the property of such things. For if you render a 
property as belonging to the subject that is so called after 
something else, then it will be true of its primary subject as 
well; whereas if you state it of its primary subject, then it will be 
predicated also of the thing that is so called after this other. 
Thus (e.g.) if any one renders , coloured' as the property of 
'surface', 'coloured' will be true of body as well; whereas if he 
render it of 'body', it will be predicated also of 'surface'. Hence 
the name as well will not be true of that of which the 
description is true. 



435 



In the case of some properties it mostly happens that some 
error is incurred because of a failure to define how as well as to 
what things the property is stated to belong. For every one tries 
to render as the property of a thing something that belongs to it 
either naturally, as 'biped' belongs to 'man', or actually, as 
'having four fingers' belongs to a particular man, or specifically, 
as 'consisting of most rarefied particles' belongs to 'fire', or 
absolutely, as 'life' to 'living being', or one that belongs to a 
thing only as called after something else, as 'wisdom' to the 
'soul', or on the other hand primarily, as 'wisdom' to the 
'rational faculty', or because the thing is in a certain state, as 
'incontrovertible by argument' belongs to a 'scientist' (for simply 
and solely by reason of his being in a certain state will he be 
'incontrovertible by argument'), or because it is the state 
possessed by something, as 'incontrovertible by argument' 
belongs to 'science', or because it is partaken of, as 'sensation' 
belongs to 'animal' (for other things as well have sensation, e.g. 
man, but they have it because they already partake of 'animal'), 
or because it partakes of something else, as 'life' belongs to a 
particular kind of 'living being'. Accordingly he makes a mistake 
if he has failed to add the word 'naturally', because what 
belongs naturally may fail to belong to the thing to which it 
naturally belongs, as (e.g.) it belongs to a man to have two feet: 
so too he errs if he does not make a definite proviso that he is 
rendering what actually belongs, because one day that attribute 
will not be what it now is, e.g. the man's possession of four 
fingers. So he errs if he has not shown that he states a thing to 
be such and such primarily, or that he calls it so after something 
else, because then its name too will not be true of that of which 
the description is true, as is the case with 'coloured', whether 
rendered as a property of 'surface' or of 'body'. So he errs if he 
has not said beforehand that he has rendered a property to a 
thing either because that thing possesses a state, or because it 
is a state possessed by something; because then it will not be a 



436 



property. For, supposing he renders the property to something 
as being a state possessed, it will belong to what possesses that 
state; while supposing he renders it to what possesses the state, 
it will belong to the state possessed, as did 'incontrovertible by 
argument' when stated as a property of 'science' or of the 
'scientist'. So he errs if he has not indicated beforehand that the 
property belongs because the thing partakes of, or is partaken 
of by, something; because then the property will belong to 
certain other things as well. For if he renders it because its 
subject is partaken of, it will belong to the things which partake 
of it; whereas if he renders it because its subject partakes of 
something else, it will belong to the things partaken of, as (e.g.) 
if he were to state 'life' to be a property of a 'particular kind of 
living being', or just of 'living being. So he errs if he has not 
expressly distinguished the property that belongs specifically, 
because then it will belong only to one of the things that fall 
under the term of which he states the property: for the 
superlative belongs only to one of them, e.g. 'lightest' as applied 
to 'fire'. Sometimes, too, a man may even add the word 
'specifically', and still make a mistake. For the things in 
question should all be of one species, whenever the word 
'specifically' is added: and in some cases this does not occur, as 
it does not, in fact, in the case of fire. For fire is not all of one 
species; for live coals and flame and light are each of them 'fire', 
but are of different species. The reason why, whenever 
'specifically' is added, there should not be any species other 
than the one mentioned, is this, that if there be, then the 
property in question will belong to some of them in a greater 
and to others in a less degree, as happens with 'consisting of 
most rarefied particles' in the case of fire: for 'light' consists of 
more rarefied particles than live coals and flame. And this 
should not happen unless the name too be predicated in a 
greater degree of that of which the description is truer; 
otherwise the rule that where the description is truer the name 



437 



too should be truer is not fulfilled. Moreover, in addition to this, 
the same attribute will be the property both of the term which 
has it absolutely and of that element therein which has it in the 
highest degree, as is the condition of the property 'consisting of 
most rarefied particles' in the case of 'fire': for this same 
attribute will be the property of 'light' as well: for it is 'light' that 
'consists of the most rarefied particles'. If, then, any one else 
renders a property in this way one should attack it; for oneself, 
one should not give occasion for this objection, but should 
define in what manner one states the property at the actual 
time of making the statement. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has stated a thing as a 
property of itself: for then what has been stated to be a property 
will not be a property. For a thing itself always shows its own 
essence, and what shows the essence is not a property but a 
definition. Thus (e.g.) he who has said that 'becoming' is a 
property of 'beautiful' has rendered the term as a property of 
itself (for 'beautiful' and 'becoming' are the same); and so 
'becoming' could not be a property of 'beautiful'. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if he has avoided 
rendering a thing as a property of itself, but has yet stated a 
convertible predicate: for then what is stated not to be a 
property will be a property. Thus he who has stated 'animate 
substance' as a property of 'living-creature' has not stated 
'living-creature' as a property of itself, but has rendered a 
convertible predicate, so that 'animate substance' would be a 
property of 'living-creature'. 

Next, in the case of things consisting of like parts, you should 
look and see, for destructive purposes, if the property of the 
whole be not true of the part, or if that of the part be not 
predicated of the whole: for then what has been stated to be the 
property will not be a property. In some cases it happens that 
this is so: for sometimes in rendering a property in the case of 



438 



things that consist of like parts a man may have his eye on the 
whole, while sometimes he may address himself to what is 
predicated of the part: and then in neither case will it have been 
rightly rendered. Take an instance referring to the whole: the 
man who has said that it is a property of the 'sea' to be 'the 
largest volume of salt water', has stated the property of 
something that consists of like parts, but has rendered an 
attribute of such a kind as is not true of the part (for a particular 
sea is not 'the largest volume of salt water'); and so the largest 
volume of salt water' could not be a property of the 'sea'. Now 
take one referring to the part: the man who has stated that it is 
a property of 'air' to be 'breathable' has stated the property of 
something that consists of like parts, but he has stated an 
attribute such as, though true of some air, is still not predicable 
of the whole (for the whole of the air is not breathable); and so 
'breathable' could not be a property of 'air'. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, see whether, while it is true of 
each of the things with similar parts, it is on the other hand a 
property of them taken as a collective whole: for then what has 
been stated not to be a property will be a property. Thus (e.g.) 
while it is true of earth everywhere that it naturally falls 
downwards, it is a property of the various particular pieces of 
earth taken as 'the Earth', so that it would be a property of 
'earth' 'naturally to fall downwards'. 



Next, look from the point of view of the respective opposites, 
and first (a) from that of the contraries, and see, for destructive 
purposes, if the contrary of the term rendered fails to be a 
property of the contrary subject. For then neither will the 
contrary of the first be a property of the contrary of the second. 



439 



Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as injustice is contrary to justice, and the 
lowest evil to the highest good, but 'to be the highest good' is 
not a property of 'justice', therefore 'to be the lowest evil' could 
not be a property of 'injustice'. For constructive purposes, on the 
other hand, see if the contrary is the property of the contrary: 
for then also the contrary of the first will be the property of the 
contrary of the second. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as evil is contrary 
to good, and objectionable to desirable, and 'desirable' is a 
property of 'good', 'objectionable' would be a property of 'evil'. 

Secondly (h) look from the point of view of relative opposites 
and see, for destructive purposes, if the correlative of the term 
rendered fails to be a property of the correlative of the subject: 
for then neither will the correlative of the first be a property of 
the correlative of the second. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'double' is 
relative to 'half, and 'in excess' to 'exceeded', while 'in excess' 
is not a property of 'double', exceeded' could not be a property 
of 'half. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the 
correlative of the alleged property is a property of the subject's 
correlative: for then also the correlative of the first will be a 
property of the correlative of the second: e.g. inasmuch as 
'double' is relative to 'half, and the proportion 1:2 is relative to 
the proportion 2:1, while it is a property of 'double' to be 'in the 
proportion of 2 to 1', it would be a property of 'half to be 'in the 
proportion of 1 to 2'. 

Thirdly (c) for destructive purposes, see if an attribute described 
in terms of a state (X) fails to be a property of the given state (Y): 
for then neither will the attribute described in terms of the 
privation (of X) be a property of the privation (of Y). Also if, on 
the other hand, an attribute described in terms of the privation 
(of X) be not a property of the given privation (of Y), neither will 
the attribute described in terms of the state (X) be a property of 
the state (Y).Thus, for example, inasmuch as it is not predicated 
as a property of 'deafness' to be a 'lack of sensation', neither 



440 



could it be a property of 'hearing' to be a 'sensation'. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if an attribute 
described in terms of a state (X) is a property of the given state 
(Y): for then also the attribute that is described in terms of the 
privation (of X) will be a property of the privation (of Y). Also, if 
an attribute described in terms of a privation (of X) be a 
property of the privation (of Y), then also the attribute that is 
described in terms of the state (X) will be a property of the state 
(Y). Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'to see' is a property of 'sight', 
inasmuch as we have sight, 'failure to see' would be a property 
of 'blindness', inasmuch as we have not got the sight we should 
naturally have. 

Next, look from the point of view of positive and negative terms; 
and first (a) from the point of view of the predicates taken by 
themselves. This common-place rule is useful only for a 
destructive purpose. Thus (e.g.) see if the positive term or the 
attribute described in terms of it is a property of the subject: for 
then the negative term or the attribute described in terms of it 
will not be a property of the subject. Also if, on the other hand, 
the negative term or the attribute described in terms of it is a 
property of the subject, then the positive term or the attribute 
described in terms of it will not be a property of the subject: e.g. 
inasmuch as 'animate' is a property of 'living creature', 
'inanimate' could not be a property of 'living creature'. 

Secondly (b) look from the point of view of the predicates, 
positive or negative, and their respective subjects; and see, for 
destructive purposes, if the positive term falls to be a property 
of the positive subject: for then neither will the negative term 
be a property of the negative subject. Also, if the negative term 
fails to be a property of the negative subject, neither will the 
positive term be a property of the positive subject. Thus (e.g.) 
inasmuch as 'animal' is not a property of 'man', neither could 
'not-animal' be a property of 'not-man'. Also if 'not-animal' 



441 



seems not to be a property of 'not-man', neither will 'animal' be 
a property of 'man'. For constructive purposes, on the other 
hand, see if the positive term is a property of the positive 
subject: for then the negative term will be a property of the 
negative subject as well. Also if the negative term be a property 
of the negative subject, the positive will be a property of the 
positive as well. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is a property of 'not- 
living being' 'not to live', it would be a property of 'living being' 
'to live': also if it seems to be a property of 'living being' 'to live', 
it will also seem to be a property of 'not-living being' 'not to 
live'. 

Thirdly (c) look from the point of view of the subjects taken by 
themselves, and see, for destructive purposes, if the property 
rendered is a property of the positive subject: for then the same 
term will not be a property of the negative subject as well. Also, 
if the term rendered be a property of the negative subject, it will 
not be a property of the positive. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 
'animate' is a property of 'living creature', 'animate' could not 
be a property of 'not-living creature'. For constructive purposes, 
on the other hand, if the term rendered fails to be a property of 
the affirmative subject it would be a property of the negative. 
This commonplace rule is, however, deceptive: for a positive 
term is not a property of a negative, or a negative of a positive. 
For a positive term does not belong at all to a negative, while a 
negative term, though it belongs to a positive, does not belong 
as a property. 

Next, look from the point of view of the coordinate members of 
a division, and see, for destructive purposes, if none of the co- 
ordinate members (parallel with the property rendered) be a 
property of any of the remaining set of co-ordinate members 
(parallel with the subject): for then neither will the term stated 
be a property of that of which it is stated to be a property. Thus 
(e.g.) inasmuch as 'sensible living being' is not a property of any 



442 



of the other living beings, 'intelligible living being' could not be 
a property of God. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, 
see if some one or other of the remaining co-ordinate members 
(parallel with the property rendered) be a property of each of 
these co-ordinate members (parallel with the subject): for then 
the remaining one too will be a property of that of which it has 
been stated not to be a property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is a 
property of 'wisdom' to be essentially 'the natural virtue of the 
rational faculty', then, taking each of the other virtues as well in 
this way, it would be a property of 'temperance' to be essentially 
'the natural virtue of the faculty of desire'. 

Next, look from the point of view of the inflexions, and see, for 
destructive purposes, if the inflexion of the property rendered 
fails to be a property of the inflexion of the subject: for then 
neither will the other inflexion be a property of the other 
inflexion. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'beautifully' is not a property 
of 'justly', neither could 'beautiful' be a property of 'just'. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the inflexion of 
the property rendered is a property of the inflexion of the 
subject: for then also the other inflexion will be a property of 
the other inflexion. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'walking biped' is a 
property of man, it would also be any one's property 'as a man' 
to be described 'as a walking biped'. Not only in the case of the 
actual term mentioned should one look at the inflexions, but 
also in the case of its opposites, just as has been laid down in 
the case of the former commonplace rules as well.' Thus, for 
destructive purposes, see if the inflexion of the opposite of the 
property rendered fails to be the property of the inflexion of the 
opposite of the subject: for then neither will the inflexion of the 
other opposite be a property of the inflexion of the other 
opposite. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'well' is not a property of 
'justly', neither could 'badly' be a property of 'unjustly'. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the inflexion of 
the opposite of the property originally suggested is a property of 



443 



the inflexion of the opposite of the original subject: for then 
also the inflexion of the other opposite will be a property of the 
inflexion of the other opposite. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'best' is 
a property of 'the good', 'worst' also will be a property of 'the 
evil'. 



Next, look from the point of view of things that are in a like 
relation, and see, for destructive purposes, if what is in a 
relation like that of the property rendered fails to be a property 
of what is in a relation like that of the subject: for then neither 
will what is in a relation like that of the first be a property of 
what is in a relation like that of the second. Thus (e.g.) 
inasmuch as the relation of the builder towards the production 
of a house is like that of the doctor towards the production of 
health, and it is not a property of a doctor to produce health, it 
could not be a property of a builder to produce a house. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if what is in a 
relation like that of the property rendered is a property of what 
is in a relation like that of the subject: for then also what is in a 
relation like that of the first will be a property of what is in a 
relation like that of the second. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as the 
relation of a doctor towards the possession of ability to produce 
health is like that of a trainer towards the possession of ability 
to produce vigour, and it is a property of a trainer to possess the 
ability to produce vigour, it would be a property of a doctor to 
possess the ability to produce health. 

Next look from the point of view of things that are identically 
related, and see, for destructive purposes, if the predicate that is 
identically related towards two subjects fails to be a property of 



444 



the subject which is identically related to it as the subject in 
question; for then neither will the predicate that is identically 
related to both subjects be a property of the subject which is 
identically related to it as the first. If, on the other hand, the 
predicate which is identically related to two subjects is the 
property of the subject which is identically related to it as the 
subject in question, then it will not be a property of that of 
which it has been stated to be a property, (e.g.) inasmuch as 
prudence is identically related to both the noble and the base, 
since it is knowledge of each of them, and it is not a property of 
prudence to be knowledge of the noble, it could not be a 
property of prudence to be knowledge of the base. If, on the 
other hand, it is a property of prudence to be the knowledge of 
the noble, it could not be a property of it to be the knowledge of 
the base.] For it is impossible for the same thing to be a property 
of more than one subject. For constructive purposes, on the 
other hand, this commonplace rule is of no use: for what is 
'identically related' is a single predicate in process of 
comparison with more than one subject. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if the predicate qualified by 
the verb 'to be' fails to be a property of the subject qualified by 
the verb 'to be': for then neither will the destruction of the one 
be a property of the other qualified by the verb 'to be destroyed', 
nor will the 'becoming'the one be a property of the other 
qualified by the verb 'to become'. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is 
not a property of 'man' to be an animal, neither could it be a 
property of becoming a man to become an animal; nor could 
the destruction of an animal be a property of the destruction of 
a man. In the same way one should derive arguments also from 
'becoming' to 'being' and 'being destroyed', and from 'being 
destroyed' to 'being' and to 'becoming' exactly as they have just 
been given from 'being' to 'becoming' and 'being destroyed'. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the subject set 
down as qualified by the verb 'to be' has the predicate set down 



445 



as so qualified, as its property: for then also the subject 
qualified by the very 'to become' will have the predicate 
qualified by 'to become' as its property, and the subject 
qualified by the verb to be destroyed' will have as its property 
the predicate rendered with this qualification. Thus, for 
example, inasmuch as it is a property of man to be a mortal, it 
would be a property of becoming a man to become a mortal, 
and the destruction of a mortal would be a property of the 
destruction of a man. In the same way one should derive 
arguments also from 'becoming' and 'being destroyed' both to 
'being' and to the conclusions that follow from them, exactly as 
was directed also for the purpose of destruction. 

Next take a look at the 'idea' of the subject stated, and see, for 
destructive purposes, if the suggested property fails to belong to 
the 'idea' in question, or fails to belong to it in virtue of that 
character which causes it to bear the description of which the 
property was rendered: for then what has been stated to be a 
property will not be a property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'being 
motionless' does not belong to 'man-himself qua 'man', but 
qua 'idea', it could not be a property of 'man' to be motionless. 
For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if the property 
in question belongs to the idea, and belongs to it in that respect 
in virtue of which there is predicated of it that character of 
which the predicate in question has been stated not to be a 
property: for then what has been stated not to be a property will 
be a property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it belongs to 'living- 
creature-itself to be compounded of soul and body, and further 
this belongs to it qua 'living-creature', it would be a property of 
'living-creature' to be compounded of soul and body. 



446 



8 

Next look from the point of view of greater and less degrees, 
and first (a) for destructive purposes, see if what is more-P fails 
to be a property of what is more-S: for then neither will what is 
less-P be a property of what is less-S, nor least-P of least-S, nor 
most-P of most-S, nor P simply of S simply. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch 
as being more highly coloured is not a property of what is more 
a body, neither could being less highly coloured be a property of 
what is less a body, nor being coloured be a property of body at 
all. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if what is 
more-P is a property of what is more-S: for then also what is 
less-P will be a property of what is less S, and least-P of least-S, 
and most-P of most-S, and P simply of S simply. Thus (e.g.) 
inasmuch as a higher degree of sensation is a property of a 
higher degree of life, a lower degree of sensation also would be a 
property of a lower degree of life, and the highest of the highest 
and the lowest of the lowest degree, and sensation simply of life 
simply. 

Also you should look at the argument from a simple predication 
to the same qualified types of predication, and see, for 
destructive purposes, if P simply fails to be a property of S 
simply; for then neither will more-P be a property of more-S, 
nor less-P of less-S, nor most-P of most-S, nor least-P of least-S. 
Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'virtuous' is not a property of 'man', 
neither could 'more virtuous' be a property of what is 'more 
human'. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if P 
simply is a property of S simply: for then more P also will be a 
property of more-S, and less-P of less-S, and least-P of least-S, 
and most-P of most-S. Thus (e.g.) a tendency to move upwards 
by nature is a property of fire, and so also a greater tendency to 
move upwards by nature would be a property of what is more 
fiery. In the same way too one should look at all these matters 
from the point of view of the others as well. 



447 



Secondly (b) for destructive purposes, see if the more likely 
property fails to be a property of the more likely subject: for 
then neither will the less likely property be a property of the 
less likely subject. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'perceiving' is more 
likely to be a property of 'animal' than 'knowing' of 'man', and 
'perceiving' is not a property of 'animal', 'knowing' could not be 
a property of 'man'. For constructive purposes, on the other 
hand, see if the less likely property is a property of the less 
likely subject; for then too the more likely property will be a 
property of the more likely subject. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'to 
be naturally civilized' is less likely to be a property of man than 
'to live' of an animal, and it is a property of man to be naturally 
civilized, it would be a property of animal to live. 

Thirdly (c) for destructive purposes, see if the predicate fails to 
be a property of that of which it is more likely to be a property: 
for then neither will it be a property of that of which it is less 
likely to be a property: while if it is a property of the former, it 
will not be a property of the latter. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'to be 
coloured' is more likely to be a property of a 'surface' than of a 
'body', and it is not a property of a surface, 'to be coloured' 
could not be a property of 'body'; while if it is a property of a 
'surface', it could not be a property of a 'body'. For constructive 
purposes, on the other hand, this commonplace rule is not of 
any use: for it is impossible for the same thing to be a property 
of more than one thing. 

Fourthly (d) for destructive purposes, see if what is more likely 
to be a property of a given subject fails to be its property: for 
then neither will what is less likely to be a property of it be its 
property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'sensible' is more likely than 
'divisible' to be a property of 'animal', and 'sensible' is not a 
property of animal, 'divisible' could not be a property of animal. 
For constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if what is less 
likely to be a property of it is a property; for then what is more 



448 



likely to be a property of it will be a property as well. Thus, for 
example, inasmuch as 'sensation' is less likely to be a property 
of 'animal' than life', and 'sensation' is a property of animal, 
'life' would be a property of animal. 

Next, look from the point of view of the attributes that belong in 
a like manner, and first (a) for destructive purposes, see if what 
is as much a property fails to be a property of that of which it is 
as much a property: for then neither will that which is as much 
a property as it be a property of that of which it is as much a 
property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'desiring' is as much a 
property of the faculty of desire as reasoning' is a property of 
the faculty of reason, and desiring is not a property of the 
faculty of desire, reasoning could not be a property of the 
faculty of reason. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, 
see if what is as much a property is a property of that of which 
it is as much a property: for then also what is as much a 
property as it will be a property of that of which it is as much a 
property. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as it is as much a property of 'the 
faculty of reason' to be 'the primary seat of wisdom' as it is of 
'the faculty of desire' to be 'the primary seat of temperance', 
and it is a property of the faculty of reason to be the primary 
seat of wisdom, it would be a property of the faculty of desire to 
be the primary seat of temperance. 

Secondly (b) for destructive purposes, see if what is as much a 
property of anything fails to be a property of it: for then neither 
will what is as much a property be a property of it. Thus (e.g.) 
inasmuch as 'seeing' is as much a property of man as 'hearing', 
and 'seeing' is not a property of man, 'hearing' could not be a 
property of man. For constructive purposes, on the other hand, 
see if what is as much a property of it is its property: for then 
what is as much a property of it as the former will be its 
property as well. Thus (e.g.) it is as much a property of the soul 
to be the primary possessor of a part that desires as of a part 



449 



that reasons, and it is a property of the soul to be the primary- 
possessor of a part that desires, and so it be a property of the 
soul to be the primary possessor of a part that reasons. 

Thirdly (c) for destructive purposes, see if it fails to be a 
property of that of which it is as much a property: for then 
neither will it be a property of that of which it is as much a 
property as of the former, while if it be a property of the former, 
it will not be a property of the other. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as 'to 
burn' is as much a property of 'flame' as of 'live coals', and 'to 
burn' is not a property of flame, 'to burn' could not be a 
property of live coals: while if it is a property of flame, it could 
not be a property of live coals. For constructive purposes, on the 
other hand, this commonplace rule is of no use. 

The rule based on things that are in a like relation' differs from 
the rule based on attributes that belong in a like manner,' 
because the former point is secured by analogy, not from 
reflection on the belonging of any attribute, while the latter is 
judged by a comparison based on the fact that an attribute 
belongs. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if in rendering the property 
potentially, he has also through that potentiality rendered the 
property relatively to something that does not exist, when the 
potentiality in question cannot belong to what does not exist: 
for then what is stated to be a property will not be a property. 
Thus (e.g.) he who has said that 'breathable' is a property of 'air' 
has, on the one hand, rendered the property potentially (for that 
is 'breathable' which is such as can be breathed), and on the 
other hand has also rendered the property relatively to what 
does not exist: - for while air may exist, even though there exist 
no animal so constituted as to breathe the air, it is not possible 
to breathe it if no animal exist: so that it will not, either, be a 
property of air to be such as can be breathed at a time when 



450 



there exists no animal such as to breathe it and so it follows 
that 'breathable' could not be a property of air. 

For constructive purposes, see if in rendering the property 
potentially he renders the property either relatively to 
something that exists, or to something that does not exist, 
when the potentiality in question can belong to what does not 
exist: for then what has been stated not to be a property will be 
a property. Thus e.g.) he who renders it as a property of 'being' 
to be 'capable of being acted upon or of acting', in rendering the 
property potentially, has rendered the property relatively to 
something that exists: for when 'being' exists, it will also be 
capable of being acted upon or of acting in a certain way: so 
that to be 'capable of being acted upon or of acting' would be a 
property of 'being'. 

Next, for destructive purposes, see if he has stated the property 
in the superlative: for then what has been stated to be a 
property will not be a property. For people who render the 
property in that way find that of the object of which the 
description is true, the name is not true as well: for though the 
object perish the description will continue in being none the 
less; for it belongs most nearly to something that is in being. An 
example would be supposing any one were to render 'the 
lightest body' as a property of 'fire': for, though fire perish, there 
eh re will still be some form of body that is the lightest, so that 
'the lightest body' could not be a property of fire. For 
constructive purposes, on the other hand, see if he has avoided 
rendering the property in the superlative: for then the property 
will in this respect have been property of man has not rendered 
the property correctly stated. Thus (e.g.) inasmuch as he in the 
superlative, the property would in who states 'a naturally 
civilized animal' as a this respect have been correctly stated. 



451 



Book VI 



The discussion of Definitions falls into five parts. For you have 
to show either (1) that it is not true at all to apply the expression 
as well to that to which the term is applied (for the definition of 
Man ought to be true of every man); or (2) that though the object 
has a genus, he has failed to put the object defined into the 
genus, or to put it into the appropriate genus (for the framer of a 
definition should first place the object in its genus, and then 
append its differences: for of all the elements of the definition 
the genus is usually supposed to be the principal mark of the 
essence of what is defined): or (3) that the expression is not 
peculiar to the object (for, as we said above as well, a definition 
ought to be peculiar): or else (4) see if, though he has observed 
all the aforesaid cautions, he has yet failed to define the object, 
that is, to express its essence. (5) It remains, apart from the 
foregoing, to see if he has defined it, but defined it incorrectly. 

Whether, then, the expression be not also true of that of which 
the term is true you should proceed to examine according to the 
commonplace rules that relate to Accident. For there too the 
question is always 'Is so and so true or untrue?': for whenever 
we argue that an accident belongs, we declare it to be true, 
while whenever we argue that it does not belong, we declare it 
to be untrue. If, again, he has failed to place the object in the 
appropriate genus, or if the expression be not peculiar to the 



452 



object, we must go on to examine the case according to the 
commonplace rules that relate to genus and property. 

It remains, then, to prescribe how to investigate whether the 
object has been either not defined at all, or else defined 
incorrectly. First, then, we must proceed to examine if it has 
been defined incorrectly: for with anything it is easier to do it 
than to do it correctly. Clearly, then, more mistakes are made in 
the latter task on account of its greater difficulty. Accordingly 
the attack becomes easier in the latter case than in the former. 

Incorrectness falls into two branches: (1) first, the use of obscure 
language (for the language of a definition ought to be the very 
clearest possible, seeing that the whole purpose of rendering it 
is to make something known); (secondly, if the expression used 
be longer than is necessary: for all additional matter in a 
definition is superfluous. Again, each of the aforesaid branches 
is divided into a number of others. 



One commonplace rule, then, in regard to obscurity is, See if the 
meaning intended by the definition involves an ambiguity with 
any other, e.g. 'Becoming is a passage into being', or 'Health is 
the balance of hot and cold elements'. Here 'passage' and 
'balance' are ambiguous terms: it is accordingly not clear which 
of the several possible senses of the term he intends to convey. 
Likewise also, if the term defined be used in different senses 
and he has spoken without distinguishing between them: for 
then it is not clear to which of them the definition rendered 
applies, and one can then bring a captious objection on the 
ground that the definition does not apply to all the things 
whose definition he has rendered: and this kind of thing is 



453 



particularly easy in the case where the definer does not see the 
ambiguity of his terms. Or, again, the questioner may himself 
distinguish the various senses of the term rendered in the 
definition, and then institute his argument against each: for if 
the expression used be not adequate to the subject in any of its 
senses, it is clear that he cannot have defined it in any sense 
aright. 

Another rule is, See if he has used a metaphorical expression, 
as, for instance, if he has defined knowledge as 
'unsupplantable', or the earth as a 'nurse', or temperance as a 
'harmony'. For a metaphorical expression is always obscure. It is 
possible, also, to argue sophistically against the user of a 
metaphorical expression as though he had used it in its literal 
sense: for the definition stated will not apply to the term 
defined, e.g. in the case of temperance: for harmony is always 
found between notes. Moreover, if harmony be the genus of 
temperance, then the same object will occur in two genera of 
which neither contains the other: for harmony does not contain 
virtue, nor virtue harmony. Again, see if he uses terms that are 
unfamiliar, as when Plato describes the eye as 'brow-shaded', or 
a certain spider as poison-fanged', or the marrow as 
'boneformed'. For an unusual phrase is always obscure. 

Sometimes a phrase is used neither ambiguously, nor yet 
metaphorically, nor yet literally, as when the law is said to be 
the 'measure' or 'image' of the things that are by nature just. 
Such phrases are worse than metaphor; for the latter does make 
its meaning to some extent clear because of the likeness 
involved; for those who use metaphors do so always in view of 
some likeness: whereas this kind of phrase makes nothing 
clear; for there is no likeness to justify the description 'measure' 
or 'image', as applied to the law, nor is the law ordinarily so 
called in a literal sense. So then, if a man says that the law is 
literally a 'measure' or an 'image', he speaks falsely: for an 



454 



image is something produced by imitation, and this is not found 
in the case of the law. If, on the other hand, he does not mean 
the term literally, it is clear that he has used an unclear 
expression, and one that is worse than any sort of metaphorical 
expression. 

Moreover, see if from the expression used the definition of the 
contrary be not clear; for definitions that have been correctly 
rendered also indicate their contraries as well. Or, again, see if, 
when it is merely stated by itself, it is not evident what it 
defines: just as in the works of the old painters, unless there 
were an inscription, the figures used to be unrecognizable. 



If, then, the definition be not clear, you should proceed to 
examine on lines such as these. If, on the other hand, he has 
phrased the definition redundantly, first of all look and see 
whether he has used any attribute that belongs universally, 
either to real objects in general, or to all that fall under the 
same genus as the object defined: for the mention of this is sure 
to be redundant. For the genus ought to divide the object from 
things in general, and the differentia from any of the things 
contained in the same genus. Now any term that belongs to 
everything separates off the given object from absolutely 
nothing, while any that belongs to all the things that fall under 
the same genus does not separate it off from the things 
contained in the same genus. Any addition, then, of that kind 
will be pointless. 

Or see if, though the additional matter may be peculiar to the 
given term, yet even when it is struck out the rest of the 
expression too is peculiar and makes clear the essence of the 



455 



term. Thus, in the definition of man, the addition 'capable of 
receiving knowledge' is superfluous; for strike it out, and still 
the expression is peculiar and makes clear his essence. 
Speaking generally, everything is superfluous upon whose 
removal the remainder still makes the term that is being 
defined clear. Such, for instance, would also be the definition of 
the soul, assuming it to be stated as a 'self-moving number'; for 
the soul is just 'the self-moving', as Plato defined it. Or perhaps 
the expression used, though appropriate, yet does not declare 
the essence, if the word 'number' be eliminated. Which of the 
two is the real state of the case it is difficult to determine 
clearly: the right way to treat the matter in all cases is to be 
guided by convenience. Thus (e.g.) it is said that the definition of 
phlegm is the 'undigested moisture that comes first off food'. 
Here the addition of the word 'undigested' is superfluous, 
seeing that 'the first' is one and not many, so that even when 
undigested' is left out the definition will still be peculiar to the 
subject: for it is impossible that both phlegm and also 
something else should both be the first to arise from the food. 
Or perhaps the phlegm is not absolutely the first thing to come 
off the food, but only the first of the undigested matters, so that 
the addition 'undigested' is required; for stated the other way 
the definition would not be true unless the phlegm comes first 
of all. 

Moreover, see if anything contained in the definition fails to 
apply to everything that falls under the same species: for this 
sort of definition is worse than those which include an attribute 
belonging to all things universally. For in that case, if the 
remainder of the expression be peculiar, the whole too will be 
peculiar: for absolutely always, if to something peculiar 
anything whatever that is true be added, the whole too becomes 
peculiar. Whereas if any part of the expression do not apply to 
everything that falls under the same species, it is impossible 
that the expression as a whole should be peculiar: for it will not 



456 



be predicated convertibly with the object; e.g. 'a walking biped 
animal six feet high': for an expression of that kind is not 
predicated convertibly with the term, because the attribute 'six 
feet high' does not belong to everything that falls under the 
same species. 

Again, see if he has said the same thing more than once, saying 
(e.g.) 'desire' is a 'conation for the pleasant'. For 'desire' is 
always 'for the pleasant', so that what is the same as desire will 
also be 'for the pleasant'. Accordingly our definition of desire 
becomes 'conation-for-the-pleasant': for the word 'desire' is the 
exact equivalent of the words 'conation-for-the-pleasant', so 
that both alike will be 'for the pleasant'. Or perhaps there is no 
absurdity in this; for consider this instance: 'Man is a biped': 
therefore, what is the same as man is a biped: but 'a walking 
biped animal' is the same as man, and therefore walking biped 
animal is a biped'. But this involves no real absurdity. For 'biped' 
is not a predicate of 'walking animal': if it were, then we should 
certainly have 'biped' predicated twice of the same thing; but as 
a matter of fact the subject said to be a biped is'a walking biped 
animal', so that the word 'biped' is only used as a predicate 
once. Likewise also in the case of 'desire' as well: for it is not 
'conation' that is said to be 'for the pleasant', but rather the 
whole idea, so that there too the predication is only made once. 
Absurdity results, not when the same word is uttered twice, but 
when the same thing is more than once predicated of a subject; 
e.g. if he says, like Xenocrates, that wisdom defines and 
contemplates reality:' for definition is a certain type of 
contemplation, so that by adding the words 'and contemplates' 
over again he says the same thing twice over. Likewise, too, 
those fail who say that 'cooling' is 'the privation of natural heat'. 
For all privation is a privation of some natural attribute, so that 
the addition of the word 'natural' is superfluous: it would have 
been enough to say 'privation of heat', for the word 'privation' 
shows of itself that the heat meant is natural heat. 



457 



Again, see if a universal have been mentioned and then a 
particular case of it be added as well, e.g. 'Equity is a remission 
of what is expedient and just'; for what is just is a branch of 
what is expedient and is therefore included in the latter term: 
its mention is therefore redundant, an addition of the particular 
after the universal has been already stated. So also, if he defines 
'medicine' as 'knowledge of what makes for health in animals 
and men', or 'the law' as 'the image of what is by nature noble 
and just'; for what is just is a branch of what is noble, so that he 
says the same thing more than once. 



Whether, then, a man defines a thing correctly or incorrectly 
you should proceed to examine on these and similar lines. But 
whether he has mentioned and defined its essence or no, 
should be examined as follows: First of all, see if he has failed to 
make the definition through terms that are prior and more 
intelligible. For the reason why the definition is rendered is to 
make known the term stated, and we make things known by 
taking not any random terms, but such as are prior and more 
intelligible, as is done in demonstrations (for so it is with all 
teaching and learning); accordingly, it is clear that a man who 
does not define through terms of this kind has not defined at 
all. Otherwise, there will be more than one definition of the 
same thing: for clearly he who defines through terms that are 
prior and more intelligible has also framed a definition, and a 
better one, so that both would then be definitions of the same 
object. This sort of view, however, does not generally find 
acceptance: for of each real object the essence is single: if, then, 
there are to be a number of definitions of the same thing, the 
essence of the object will be the same as it is represented to be 



458 



in each of the definitions, and these representations are not the 
same, inasmuch as the definitions are different. Clearly, then, 
any one who has not defined a thing through terms that are 
prior and more intelligible has not defined it at all. 

The statement that a definition has not been made through 
more intelligible terms may be understood in two senses, either 
supposing that its terms are absolutely less intelligible, or 
supposing that they are less intelligible to us: for either sense is 
possible. Thus absolutely the prior is more intelligible than the 
posterior, a point, for instance, than a line, a line than a plane, 
and a plane than a solid; just as also a unit is more intelligible 
than a number; for it is the prius and starting-point of all 
number. Likewise, also, a letter is more intelligible than a 
syllable. Whereas to us it sometimes happens that the converse 
is the case: for the solid falls under perception most of all - 
more than a plane - and a plane more than a line, and a line 
more than a point; for most people learn things like the former 
earlier than the latter; for any ordinary intelligence can grasp 
them, whereas the others require an exact and exceptional 
understanding. 

Absolutely, then, it is better to try to make what is posterior 
known through what is prior, inasmuch as such a way of 
procedure is more scientific. Of course, in dealing with persons 
who cannot recognize things through terms of that kind, it may 
perhaps be necessary to frame the expression through terms 
that are intelligible to them. Among definitions of this kind are 
those of a point, a line, and a plane, all of which explain the 
prior by the posterior; for they say that a point is the limit of a 
line, a line of a plane, a plane of a solid. One must, however, not 
fail to observe that those who define in this way cannot show 
the essential nature of the term they define, unless it so 
happens that the same thing is more intelligible both to us and 
also absolutely, since a correct definition must define a thing 



459 



through its genus and its differentiae, and these belong to the 
order of things which are absolutely more intelligible than, and 
prior to, the species. For annul the genus and differentia, and 
the species too is annulled, so that these are prior to the 
species. They are also more intelligible; for if the species be 
known, the genus and differentia must of necessity be known 
as well (for any one who knows what a man is knows also what 
'animal' and 'walking' are), whereas if the genus or the 
differentia be known it does not follow of necessity that the 
species is known as well: thus the species is less intelligible. 
Moreover, those who say that such definitions, viz. those which 
proceed from what is intelligible to this, that, or the other man, 
are really and truly definitions, will have to say that there are 
several definitions of one and the same thing. For, as it happens, 
different things are more intelligible to different people, not the 
same things to all; and so a different definition would have to 
be rendered to each several person, if the definition is to be 
constructed from what is more intelligible to particular 
individuals. Moreover, to the same people different things are 
more intelligible at different times; first of all the objects of 
sense; then, as they become more sharpwitted, the converse; so 
that those who hold that a definition ought to be rendered 
through what is more intelligible to particular individuals would 
not have to render the same definition at all times even to the 
same person. It is clear, then, that the right way to define is not 
through terms of that kind, but through what is absolutely more 
intelligible: for only in this way could the definition come 
always to be one and the same. Perhaps, also, what is absolutely 
intelligible is what is intelligible, not to all, but to those who are 
in a sound state of understanding, just as what is absolutely 
healthy is what is healthy to those in a sound state of body. All 
such points as this ought to be made very precise, and made 
use of in the course of discussion as occasion requires. The 
demolition of a definition will most surely win a general 



460 



approval if the definer happens to have framed his expression 
neither from what is absolutely more intelligible nor yet from 
what is so to us. 

One form, then, of the failure to work through more intelligible 
terms is the exhibition of the prior through the posterior, as we 
remarked before.' Another form occurs if we find that the 
definition has been rendered of what is at rest and definite 
through what is indefinite and in motion: for what is still and 
definite is prior to what is indefinite and in motion. 

Of the failure to use terms that are prior there are three forms: 

(1) The first is when an opposite has been defined through its 
opposite, e.g.i. good through evil: for opposites are always 
simultaneous by nature. Some people think, also, that both are 
objects of the same science, so that the one is not even more 
intelligible than the other. One must, however, observe that it is 
perhaps not possible to define some things in any other way, 
e.g. the double without the half, and all the terms that are 
essentially relative: for in all such cases the essential being is 
the same as a certain relation to something, so that it is 
impossible to understand the one term without the other, and 
accordingly in the definition of the one the other too must be 
embraced. One ought to learn up all such points as these, and 
use them as occasion may seem to require. 

(2) Another is - if he has used the term defined itself. This 
passes unobserved when the actual name of the object is not 
used, e.g. supposing any one had defined the sun as a star that 
appears by day'. For in bringing in 'day' he brings in the sun. To 
detect errors of this sort, exchange the word for its definition, 
e.g. the definition of 'day' as the 'passage of the sun over the 
earth'. Clearly, whoever has said 'the passage of the sun over 
the earth' has said 'the sun', so that in bringing in the 'day' he 
has brought in the sun. 



461 



(3) Again, see if he has defined one coordinate member of a 
division by another, e.g. 'an odd number' as 'that which is 
greater by one than an even number'. For the co-ordinate 
members of a division that are derived from the same genus are 
simultaneous by nature and 'odd' and 'even' are such terms: for 
both are differentiae of number. 

Likewise also, see if he has defined a superior through a 
subordinate term, e.g. 'An «even number» is «a number divisible 
into halves»', or '«the good» is a «state of virtue» '. For 'half is 
derived from 'two', and 'two' is an even number: virtue also is a 
kind of good, so that the latter terms are subordinate to the 
former. Moreover, in using the subordinate term one is bound to 
use the other as well: for whoever employs the term 'virtue' 
employs the term 'good', seeing that virtue is a certain kind of 
good: likewise, also, whoever employs the term 'half employs 
the term 'even', for to be 'divided in half means to be divided 
into two, and two is even. 



Generally speaking, then, one commonplace rule relates to the 
failure to frame the expression by means of terms that are prior 
and more intelligible: and of this the subdivisions are those 
specified above. A second is, see whether, though the object is in 
a genus, it has not been placed in a genus. This sort of error is 
always found where the essence of the object does not stand 
first in the expression, e.g. the definition of 'body' as 'that which 
has three dimensions', or the definition of 'man', supposing any 
one to give it, as 'that which knows how to count': for it is not 
stated what it is that has three dimensions, or what it is that 



462 



knows how to count: whereas the genus is meant to indicate 
just this, and is submitted first of the terms in the definition. 

Moreover, see if, while the term to be defined is used in relation 
to many things, he has failed to render it in relation to all of 
them; as (e.g.) if he define 'grammar' as the 'knowledge how to 
write from dictation': for he ought also to say that it is a 
knowledge how to read as well. For in rendering it as 
'knowledge of writing' has no more defined it than by rendering 
it as 'knowledge of reading': neither in fact has succeeded, but 
only he who mentions both these things, since it is impossible 
that there should be more than one definition of the same 
thing. It is only, however, in some cases that what has been said 
corresponds to the actual state of things: in some it does not, 
e.g. all those terms which are not used essentially in relation to 
both things: as medicine is said to deal with the production of 
disease and health; for it is said essentially to do the latter, but 
the former only by accident: for it is absolutely alien to 
medicine to produce disease. Here, then, the man who renders 
medicine as relative to both of these things has not defined it 
any better than he who mentions the one only. In fact he has 
done it perhaps worse, for any one else besides the doctor is 
capable of producing disease. 

Moreover, in a case where the term to be defined is used in 
relation to several things, see if he has rendered it as relative to 
the worse rather than to the better; for every form of knowledge 
and potentiality is generally thought to be relative to the best. 

Again, if the thing in question be not placed in its own proper 
genus, one must examine it according to the elementary rules 
in regard to genera, as has been said before.' 

Moreover, see if he uses language which transgresses the genera 
of the things he defines, defining, e.g. justice as a 'state that 
produces equality' or 'distributes what is equal': for by defining 



463 



it so he passes outside the sphere of virtue, and so by leaving 
out the genus of justice he fails to express its essence: for the 
essence of a thing must in each case bring in its genus. It is the 
same thing if the object be not put into its nearest genus; for 
the man who puts it into the nearest one has stated all the 
higher genera, seeing that all the higher genera are predicated 
of the lower. Either, then, it ought to be put into its nearest 
genus, or else to the higher genus all the differentiae ought to 
be appended whereby the nearest genus is defined. For then he 
would not have left out anything: but would merely have 
mentioned the subordinate genus by an expression instead of 
by name. On the other hand, he who mentions merely the 
higher genus by itself, does not state the subordinate genus as 
well: in saying 'plant' a man does not specify 'a tree'. 



Again, in regard to the differentiae, we must examine in like 
manner whether the differentiae, too, that he has stated be 
those of the genus. For if a man has not defined the object by 
the differentiae peculiar to it, or has mentioned something such 
as is utterly incapable of being a differentia of anything, e.g. 
'animal' or 'substance', clearly he has not defined it at all: for 
the aforesaid terms do not differentiate anything at all. Further, 
we must see whether the differentia stated possesses anything 
that is co-ordinate with it in a division; for, if not, clearly the 
one stated could not be a differentia of the genus. For a genus is 
always divided by differentiae that are co-ordinate members of 
a division, as, for instance, by the terms 'walking', 'flying', 
'aquatic', and 'biped'. Or see if, though the contrasted differentia 
exists, it yet is not true of the genus, for then, clearly, neither of 
them could be a differentia of the genus; for differentiae that 



464 



are co-ordinates in a division with the differentia of a thing are 
all true of the genus to which the thing belongs. Likewise, also, 
see if, though it be true, yet the addition of it to the genus fails 
to make a species. For then, clearly, this could not be a specific 
differentia of the genus: for a specific differentia, if added to the 
genus, always makes a species. If, however, this be no true 
differentia, no more is the one adduced, seeing that it is a co- 
ordinate member of a division with this. 

Moreover, see if he divides the genus by a negation, as those do 
who define line as 'length without breadth': for this means 
simply that it has not any breadth. The genus will then be found 
to partake of its own species: for, since of everything either an 
affirmation or its negation is true, length must always either 
lack breadth or possess it, so that 'length' as well, i.e. the genus 
of 'line', will be either with or without breadth. But 'length 
without breadth' is the definition of a species, as also is 'length 
with breadth': for 'without breadth' and 'with breadth' are 
differentiae, and the genus and differentia constitute the 
definition of the species. Hence the genus would admit of the 
definition of its species. Likewise, also, it will admit of the 
definition of the differentia, seeing that one or the other of the 
aforesaid differentiae is of necessity predicated of the genus. 
The usefulness of this principle is found in meeting those who 
assert the existence of 'Ideas': for if absolute length exist, how 
will it be predicable of the genus that it has breadth or that it 
lacks it? For one assertion or the other will have to be true of 
'length' universally, if it is to be true of the genus at all: and this 
is contrary to the fact: for there exist both lengths which have, 
and lengths which have not, breadth. Hence the only people 
against whom the rule can be employed are those who assert 
that a genus is always numerically one; and this is what is done 
by those who assert the real existence of the 'Ideas'; for they 
allege that absolute length and absolute animal are the genus. 



465 



It may be that in some cases the definer is obliged to employ a 
negation as well, e.g. in defining privations. For 'blind' means a 
thing which cannot see when its nature is to see. There is no 
difference between dividing the genus by a negation, and 
dividing it by such an affirmation as is bound to have a negation 
as its co-ordinate in a division, e.g. supposing he had defined 
something as 'length possessed of breadth'; for co-ordinate in 
the division with that which is possessed of breadth is that 
which possesses no breadth and that only, so that again the 
genus is divided by a negation. 

Again, see if he rendered the species as a differentia, as do 
those who define 'contumely' as 'insolence accompanied by 
jeering'; for jeering is a kind of insolence, i.e. it is a species and 
not a differentia. 

Moreover, see if he has stated the genus as the differentia, e.g. 
'Virtue is a good or noble state: for 'good' is the genus of 'virtue'. 
Or possibly 'good' here is not the genus but the differentia, on 
the principle that the same thing cannot be in two genera of 
which neither contains the other: for 'good' does not include 
'state', nor vice versa: for not every state is good nor every good 
a 'state'. Both, then, could not be genera, and consequently, if 
'state' is the genus of virtue, clearly 'good' cannot be its genus: 
it must rather be the differentia'. Moreover, 'a state' indicates 
the essence of virtue, whereas 'good' indicates not the essence 
but a quality: and to indicate a quality is generally held to be 
the function of the differentia. See, further, whether the 
differentia rendered indicates an individual rather than a 
quality: for the general view is that the differentia always 
expresses a quality. 

Look and see, further, whether the differentia belongs only by 
accident to the object defined. For the differentia is never an 



466 



accidental attribute, any more than the genus is: for the 
differentia of a thing cannot both belong and not belong to it. 

Moreover, if either the differentia or the species, or any of the 
things which are under the species, is predicable of the genus, 
then he could not have defined the term. For none of the 
aforesaid can possibly be predicated of the genus, seeing that 
the genus is the term with the widest range of all. Again, see if 
the genus be predicated of the differentia; for the general view 
is that the genus is predicated, not of the differentia, but of the 
objects of which the differentia is predicated. Animal (e.g.) is 
predicated of 'man' or 'ox' or other walking animals, not of the 
actual differentia itself which we predicate of the species. For if 
'animal' is to be predicated of each of its differentiae, then 
'animal' would be predicated of the species several times over; 
for the differentiae are predicates of the species. Moreover, the 
differentiae will be all either species or individuals, if they are 
animals; for every animal is either a species or an individual. 

Likewise you must inquire also if the species or any of the 
objects that come under it is predicated of the differentia: for 
this is impossible, seeing that the differentia is a term with a 
wider range than the various species. Moreover, if any of the 
species be predicated of it, the result will be that the differentia 
is a species: if, for instance, 'man' be predicated, the differentia 
is clearly the human race. Again, see if the differentia fails to be 
prior to the species: for the differentia ought to be posterior to 
the genus, but prior to the species. 

Look and see also if the differentia mentioned belongs to a 
different genus, neither contained in nor containing the genus 
in question. For the general view is that the same differentia 
cannot be used of two non-subaltern genera. Else the result will 
be that the same species as well will be in two non-subaltern 
genera: for each of the differentiae imports its own genus, e.g. 



467 



'walking' and 'biped' import with them the genus 'animal'. If, 
then, each of the genera as well is true of that of which the 
differentia is true, it clearly follows that the species must be in 
two non-subaltern genera. Or perhaps it is not impossible for 
the same differentia to be used of two non-subaltern genera, 
and we ought to add the words 'except they both be subordinate 
members of the same genus'. Thus 'walking animal' and 'flying 
animal' are non-subaltern genera, and 'biped' is the differentia 
of both. The words 'except they both be subordinate members of 
the same genus' ought therefore to be added; for both these are 
subordinate to 'animal'. From this possibility, that the same 
differentia may be used of two non-subaltern genera, it is clear 
also that there is no necessity for the differentia to carry with it 
the whole of the genus to which it belongs, but only the one or 
the other of its limbs together with the genera that are higher 
than this, as 'biped' carries with it either 'flying' or 'walking 
animal'. 

See, too, if he has rendered 'existence in' something as the 
differentia of a thing's essence: for the general view is that 
locality cannot differentiate between one essence and another. 
Hence, too, people condemn those who divide animals by 
means of the terms 'walking' and 'aquatic', on the ground that 
'walking' and 'aquatic' indicate mere locality. Or possibly in this 
case the censure is undeserved; for 'aquatic' does not mean 'in' 
anything; nor does it denote a locality, but a certain quality: for 
even if the thing be on the dry land, still it is aquatic: and 
likewise a land-animal, even though it be in the water, will still 
be a and not an aquatic-animal. But all the same, if ever the 
differentia does denote existence in something, clearly he will 
have made a bad mistake. 

Again, see if he has rendered an affection as the differentia: for 
every affection, if intensified, subverts the essence of the thing, 
while the differentia is not of that kind: for the differentia is 



468 



generally considered rather to preserve that which it 
differentiates; and it is absolutely impossible for a thing to exist 
without its own special differentia: for if there be no 'walking', 
there will be no 'man'. In fact, we may lay down absolutely that 
a thing cannot have as its differentia anything in respect of 
which it is subject to alteration: for all things of that kind, if 
intensified, destroy its essence. If, then, a man has rendered any 
differentia of this kind, he has made a mistake: for we undergo 
absolutely no alteration in respect of our differentiae. 

Again, see if he has failed to render the differentia of a relative 
term relatively to something else; for the differentiae of relative 
terms are themselves relative, as in the case also of knowledge. 
This is classed as speculative, practical and productive; and 
each of these denotes a relation: for it speculates upon 
something, and produces something and does something. 

Look and see also if the definer renders each relative term 
relatively to its natural purpose: for while in some cases the 
particular relative term can be used in relation to its natural 
purpose only and to nothing else, some can be used in relation 
to something else as well. Thus sight can only be used for 
seeing, but a strigil can also be used to dip up water. Still, if any 
one were to define a strigil as an instrument for dipping water, 
he has made a mistake: for that is not its natural function. The 
definition of a thing's natural function is 'that for which it 
would be used by the prudent man, acting as such, and by the 
science that deals specially with that thing'. 

Or see if, whenever a term happens to be used in a number of 
relations, he has failed to introduce it in its primary relation: e.g. 
by defining 'wisdom' as the virtue of 'man' or of the 'soul,' 
rather than of the 'reasoning faculty': for 'wisdom' is the virtue 
primarily of the reasoning faculty: for it is in virtue of this that 
both the man and his soul are said to be wise. 



469 



Moreover, if the thing of which the term defined has been 
stated to be an affection or disposition, or whatever it may be, 
be unable to admit it, the definer has made a mistake. For every 
disposition and every affection is formed naturally in that of 
which it is an affection or disposition, as knowledge, too, is 
formed in the soul, being a disposition of soul. Sometimes, 
however, people make bad mistakes in matters of this sort, e.g. 
all those who say that 'sleep' is a 'failure of sensation', or that 
'perplexity' is a state of 'equality between contrary reasonings', 
or that 'pain' is a 'violent disruption of parts that are naturally 
conjoined'. For sleep is not an attribute of sensation, whereas it 
ought to be, if it is a failure of sensation. Likewise, perplexity is 
not an attribute of opposite reasonings, nor pain of parts 
naturally conjoined: for then inanimate things will be in pain, 
since pain will be present in them. Similar in character, too, is 
the definition of 'health', say, as a 'balance of hot and cold 
elements': for then health will be necessarily exhibited by the 
hot and cold elements: for balance of anything is an attribute 
inherent in those things of which it is the balance, so that 
health would be an attribute of them. Moreover, people who 
define in this way put effect for cause, or cause for effect. For 
the disruption of parts naturally conjoined is not pain, but only 
a cause of pain: nor again is a failure of sensation sleep, but the 
one is the cause of the other: for either we go to sleep because 
sensation fails, or sensation fails because we go to sleep. 
Likewise also an equality between contrary reasonings would be 
generally considered to be a cause of perplexity: for it is when 
we reflect on both sides of a question and find everything alike 
to be in keeping with either course that we are perplexed which 
of the two we are to do. 

Moreover, with regard to all periods of time look and see 
whether there be any discrepancy between the differentia and 
the thing defined: e.g. supposing the 'immortal' to be defined as 
a 'living thing immune at present from destruction'. For a living 



470 



thing that is immune 'at present' from destruction will be 
immortal 'at present'. Possibly, indeed, in this case this result 
does not follow, owing to the ambiguity of the words 'immune 
at present from destruction': for it may mean either that the 
thing has not been destroyed at present, or that it cannot be 
destroyed at present, or that at present it is such that it never 
can be destroyed. Whenever, then, we say that a living thing is 
at present immune from destruction, we mean that it is at 
present a living thing of such a kind as never to be destroyed: 
and this is equivalent to saying that it is immortal, so that it is 
not meant that it is immortal only at present. Still, if ever it does 
happen that what has been rendered according to the definition 
belongs in the present only or past, whereas what is meant by 
the word does not so belong, then the two could not be the 
same. So, then, this commonplace rule ought to be followed, as 
we have said. 



You should look and see also whether the term being defined is 
applied in consideration of something other than the definition 
rendered. Suppose (e.g.) a definition of 'justice' as the 'ability to 
distribute what is equal'. This would not be right, for 'just' 
describes rather the man who chooses, than the man who is 
able to distribute what is equal: so that justice could not be an 
ability to distribute what is equal: for then also the most just 
man would be the man with the most ability to distribute what 
is equal. 

Moreover, see if the thing admits of degrees, whereas what is 
rendered according to the definition does not, or, vice versa, 
what is rendered according to the definition admits of degrees 



471 



while the thing does not. For either both must admit them or 
else neither, if indeed what is rendered according to the 
definition is the same as the thing. Moreover, see if, while both 
of them admit of degrees, they yet do not both become greater 
together: e.g. suppose sexual love to be the desire for 
intercourse: for he who is more intensely in love has not a more 
intense desire for intercourse, so that both do not become 
intensified at once: they certainly should, however, had they 
been the same thing. 

Moreover, suppose two things to be before you, see if the term 
to be defined applies more particularly to the one to which the 
content of the definition is less applicable. Take, for instance, 
the definition of 'fire' as the 'body that consists of the most 
rarefied particles'. For 'fire' denotes flame rather than light, but 
flame is less the body that consists of the most rarefied 
particles than is light: whereas both ought to be more applicable 
to the same thing, if they had been the same. Again, see if the 
one expression applies alike to both the objects before you, 
while the other does not apply to both alike, but more 
particularly to one of them. 

Moreover, see if he renders the definition relative to two things 
taken separately: thus, the beautiful' is 'what is pleasant to the 
eyes or to the ears»: or 'the real' is 'what is capable of being 
acted upon or of acting'. For then the same thing will be both 
beautiful and not beautiful, and likewise will be both real and 
not real. For 'pleasant to the ears' will be the same as 'beautiful', 
so that 'not pleasant to the ears' will be the same as 'not 
beautiful': for of identical things the opposites, too, are 
identical, and the opposite of 'beautiful' is 'not beautiful', while 
of 'pleasant to the ears' the opposite is not pleasant to the cars': 
clearly, then, 'not pleasant to the ears' is the same thing as 'not 
beautiful'. If, therefore, something be pleasant to the eyes but 
not to the ears, it will be both beautiful and not beautiful. In like 



472 



manner we shall show also that the same thing is both real and 
unreal. 

Moreover, of both genera and differentiae and all the other 
terms rendered in definitions you should frame definitions in 
lieu of the terms, and then see if there be any discrepancy 
between them. 



8 

If the term defined be relative, either in itself or in respect of its 
genus, see whether the definition fails to mention that to which 
the term, either in itself or in respect of its genus, is relative, e.g. 
if he has defined 'knowledge' as an 'incontrovertible conception' 
or 'wishing' as 'painless conation'. For of everything relative the 
essence is relative to something else, seeing that the being of 
every relative term is identical with being in a certain relation to 
something. He ought, therefore, to have said that knowledge is 
'conception of a knowable' and that wishing is 'conation for a 
good'. Likewise, also, if he has defined 'grammar' as 'knowledge 
of letters': whereas in the definition there ought to be rendered 
either the thing to which the term itself is relative, or that, 
whatever it is, to which its genus is relative. Or see if a relative 
term has been described not in relation to its end, the end in 
anything being whatever is best in it or gives its purpose to the 
rest. Certainly it is what is best or final that should be stated, 
e.g. that desire is not for the pleasant but for pleasure: for this is 
our purpose in choosing what is pleasant as well. 

Look and see also if that in relation to which he has rendered 
the term be a process or an activity: for nothing of that kind is 
an end, for the completion of the activity or process is the end 
rather than the process or activity itself. Or perhaps this rule is 



473 



not true in all cases, for almost everybody prefers the present 
experience of pleasure to its cessation, so that they would count 
the activity as the end rather than its completion. 

Again see in some cases if he has failed to distinguish the 
quantity or quality or place or other differentiae of an object; 
e.g. the quality and quantity of the honour the striving for 
which makes a man ambitious: for all men strive for honour, so 
that it is not enough to define the ambitious man as him who 
strives for honour, but the aforesaid differentiae must be added. 
Likewise, also, in defining the covetous man the quantity of 
money he aims at, or in the case of the incontinent man the 
quality of the pleasures, should be stated. For it is not the man 
who gives way to any sort of pleasure whatever who is called 
incontinent, but only he who gives way to a certain kind of 
pleasure. Or again, people sometimes define night as a 'shadow 
on the earth', or an earthquake as a movement of the earth', or 
a cloud as 'condensation of the air', or a wind as a 'movement of 
the air'; whereas they ought to specify as well quantity, quality, 
place, and cause. Likewise, also, in other cases of the kind: for by 
omitting any differentiae whatever he fails to state the essence 
of the term. One should always attack deficiency. For a 
movement of the earth does not constitute an earthquake, nor a 
movement of the air a wind, irrespective of its manner and the 
amount involved. 

Moreover, in the case of conations, and in any other cases 
where it applies, see if the word 'apparent' is left out, e.g. 
'wishing is a conation after the good', or 'desire is a conation 
after the pleasant' - instead of saying 'the apparently good', or 
'pleasant'. For often those who exhibit the conation do not 
perceive what is good or pleasant, so that their aim need not be 
really good or pleasant, but only apparently so. They ought, 
therefore, to have rendered the definition also accordingly. On 
the other hand, any one who maintains the existence of Ideas 



474 



ought to be brought face to face with his Ideas, even though he 
does render the word in question: for there can be no Idea of 
anything merely apparent: the general view is that an Idea is 
always spoken of in relation to an Idea: thus absolute desire is 
for the absolutely pleasant, and absolute wishing is for the 
absolutely good; they therefore cannot be for an apparent good 
or an apparently pleasant: for the existence of an absolutely - 
apparently - good or pleasant would be an absurdity. 



Moreover, if the definition be of the state of anything, look at 
what is in the state, while if it be of what is in the state, look at 
the state: and likewise also in other cases of the kind. Thus if 
the pleasant be identical with the beneficial, then, too, the man 
who is pleased is benefited. Speaking generally, in definitions of 
this sort it happens that what the definer defines is in a sense 
more than one thing: for in defining knowledge, a man in a 
sense defines ignorance as well, and likewise also what has 
knowledge and what lacks it, and what it is to know and to be 
ignorant. For if the first be made clear, the others become in a 
certain sense clear as well. We have, then, to be on our guard in 
all such cases against discrepancy, using the elementary 
principles drawn from consideration of contraries and of 
coordinates. 

Moreover, in the case of relative terms, see if the species is 
rendered as relative to a species of that to which the genus is 
rendered as relative, e.g. supposing belief to be relative to some 
object of belief, see whether a particular belief is made relative 
to some particular object of belief: and, if a multiple be relative 
to a fraction, see whether a particular multiple be made relative 



475 



to a particular fraction. For if it be not so rendered, clearly a 
mistake has been made. 

See, also, if the opposite of the term has the opposite definition, 
whether (e.g.) the definition of 'half is the opposite of that of 
'double': for if 'double' is 'that which exceeds another by an 
equal amount to that other', 'half is 'that which is exceeded by 
an amount equal to itself. In the same way, too, with contraries. 
For to the contrary term will apply the definition that is 
contrary in some one of the ways in which contraries are 
conjoined. Thus (e.g.) if 'useful'='productive of good', 
'injurious'=productive of evil' or 'destructive of good', for one or 
the other of thee is bound to be contrary to the term originally 
used. Suppose, then, neither of these things to be the contrary 
of the term originally used, then clearly neither of the 
definitions rendered later could be the definition of the contrary 
of the term originally defined: and therefore the definition 
originally rendered of the original term has not been rightly 
rendered either. Seeing, moreover, that of contraries, the one is 
sometimes a word forced to denote the privation of the other, as 
(e.g.) inequality is generally held to be the privation of equality 
(for 'unequal' merely describes things that are not equal'), it is 
therefore clear that that contrary whose form denotes the 
privation must of necessity be defined through the other; 
whereas the other cannot then be defined through the one 
whose form denotes the privation; for else we should find that 
each is being interpreted by the other. We must in the case of 
contrary terms keep an eye on this mistake, e.g. supposing any 
one were to define equality as the contrary of inequality: for 
then he is defining it through the term which denotes privation 
of it. Moreover, a man who so defines is bound to use in his 
definition the very term he is defining; and this becomes clear, 
if for the word we substitute its definition. For to say 'inequality' 
is the same as to say 'privation of equality'. Therefore equality 
so defined will be 'the contrary of the privation of equality', so 



476 



that he would have used the very word to be defined. Suppose, 
however, that neither of the contraries be so formed as to 
denote privation, but yet the definition of it be rendered in a 
manner like the above, e.g. suppose 'good' to be defined as 'the 
contrary of evil', then, since it is clear that 'evil' too will be 'the 
contrary of good' (for the definition of things that are contrary 
in this must be rendered in a like manner), the result again is 
that he uses the very term being defined: for 'good' is inherent 
in the definition of 'evil'. If, then, 'good' be the contrary of evil, 
and evil be nothing other than the 'contrary of good', then 
'good' will be the 'contrary of the contrary of good'. Clearly, 
then, he has used the very word to be defined. 

Moreover, see if in rendering a term formed to denote privation, 
he has failed to render the term of which it is the privation, e.g. 
the state, or contrary, or whatever it may be whose privation it 
is: also if he has omitted to add either any term at all in which 
the privation is naturally formed, or else that in which it is 
naturally formed primarily, e.g. whether in defining 'ignorance' 
a privation he has failed to say that it is the privation of 
'knowledge'; or has failed to add in what it is naturally formed, 
or, though he has added this, has failed to render the thing in 
which it is primarily formed, placing it (e.g.) in 'man' or in 'the 
soul', and not in the 'reasoning faculty': for if in any of these 
respects he fails, he has made a mistake. Likewise, also, if he 
has failed to say that 'blindness' is the 'privation of sight in an 
eye': for a proper rendering of its essence must state both of 
what it is the privation and what it is that is deprived. 

Examine further whether he has defined by the expression 'a 
privation' a term that is not used to denote a privation: thus a 
mistake of this sort also would be generally thought to be 
incurred in the case of 'error' by any one who is not using it as a 
merely negative term. For what is generally thought to be in 
error is not that which has no knowledge, but rather that which 



477 



has been deceived, and for this reason we do not talk of 
inanimate things or of children as 'erring'. 'Error', then, is not 
used to denote a mere privation of knowledge. 



10 

Moreover, see whether the like inflexions in the definition apply 
to the like inflexions of the term; e.g. if 'beneficial' means 
'productive of health', does 'beneficially' mean productively of 
health' and a 'benefactor' a 'producer of health? 

Look too and see whether the definition given will apply to the 
Idea as well. For in some cases it will not do so; e.g. in the 
Platonic definition where he adds the word 'mortal' in his 
definitions of living creatures: for the Idea (e.g. the absolute 
Man) is not mortal, so that the definition will not fit the Idea. So 
always wherever the words 'capable of acting on' or 'capable of 
being acted upon' are added, the definition and the Idea are 
absolutely bound to be discrepant: for those who assert the 
existence of Ideas hold that they are incapable of being acted 
upon, or of motion. In dealing with these people even 
arguments of this kind are useful. 

Further, see if he has rendered a single common definition of 
terms that are used ambiguously. For terms whose definition 
corresponding their common name is one and the same, are 
synonymous; if, then, the definition applies in a like manner to 
the whole range of the ambiguous term, it is not true of any one 
of the objects described by the term. This is, moreover, what 
happens to Dionysius' definition of 'life' when stated as 'a 
movement of a creature sustained by nutriment, congenitally 
present with it': for this is found in plants as much as in 
animals, whereas 'life' is generally understood to mean not one 



478 



kind of thing only, but to be one thing in animals and another in 
plants. It is possible to hold the view that life is a synonymous 
term and is always used to describe one thing only, and 
therefore to render the definition in this way on purpose: or it 
may quite well happen that a man may see the ambiguous 
character of the word, and wish to render the definition of the 
one sense only, and yet fail to see that he has rendered a 
definition common to both senses instead of one peculiar to the 
sense he intends. In either case, whichever course he pursues, 
he is equally at fault. Since ambiguous terms sometimes pass 
unobserved, it is best in questioning to treat such terms as 
though they were synonymous (for the definition of the one 
sense will not apply to the other, so that the answerer will be 
generally thought not to have defined it correctly, for to a 
synonymous term the definition should apply in its full range), 
whereas in answering you should yourself distinguish between 
the senses. Further, as some answerers call 'ambiguous' what is 
really synonymous, whenever the definition rendered fails to 
apply universally, and, vice versa, call synonymous what is 
really ambiguous supposing their definition applies to both 
senses of the term, one should secure a preliminary admission 
on such points, or else prove beforehand that so-and-so is 
ambiguous or synonymous, as the case may be: for people are 
more ready to agree when they do not foresee what the 
consequence will be. If, however, no admission has been made, 
and the man asserts that what is really synonymous is 
ambiguous because the definition he has rendered will not 
apply to the second sense as well, see if the definition of this 
second meaning applies also to the other meanings: for if so, 
this meaning must clearly be synonymous with those others. 
Otherwise, there will be more than one definition of those other 
meanings, for there are applicable to them two distinct 
definitions in explanation of the term, viz. the one previously 
rendered and also the later one. Again, if any one were to define 



479 



a term used in several senses, and, finding that his definition 
does not apply to them all, were to contend not that the term is 
ambiguous, but that even the term does not properly apply to 
all those senses, just because his definition will not do so either, 
then one may retort to such a man that though in some things 
one must not use the language of the people, yet in a question 
of terminology one is bound to employ the received and 
traditional usage and not to upset matters of that sort. 



11 

Suppose now that a definition has been rendered of some 
complex term, take away the definition of one of the elements 
in the complex, and see if also the rest of the definition defines 
the rest of it: if not, it is clear that neither does the whole 
definition define the whole complex. Suppose, e.g. that some 
one has defined a 'finite straight line' as 'the limit of a finite 
plane, such that its centre is in a line with its extremes'; if now 
the definition of a finite line' be the 'limit of a finite plane', the 
rest (viz. 'such that its centre is in a line with its extremes') 
ought to be a definition of straight'. But an infinite straight line 
has neither centre nor extremes and yet is straight so that this 
remainder does not define the remainder of the term. 

Moreover, if the term defined be a compound notion, see if the 
definition rendered be equimembral with the term defined. A 
definition is said to be equimembral with the term defined 
when the number of the elements compounded in the latter is 
the same as the number of nouns and verbs in the definition. 
For the exchange in such cases is bound to be merely one of 
term for term, in the case of some if not of all, seeing that there 
are no more terms used now than formerly; whereas in a 



480 



definition terms ought to be rendered by phrases, if possible in 
every case, or if not, in the majority. For at that rate, simple 
objects too could be defined by merely calling them by a 
different name, e.g. 'cloak' instead of 'doublet'. 

The mistake is even worse, if actually a less well known term be 
substituted, e.g. 'pellucid mortal' for 'white man': for it is no 
definition, and moreover is less intelligible when put in that 
form. 

Look and see also whether, in the exchange of words, the sense 
fails still to be the same. Take, for instance, the explanation of 
'speculative knowledge' as 'speculative conception': for 
conception is not the same as knowledge - as it certainly ought 
to be if the whole is to be the same too: for though the word 
'speculative' is common to both expressions, yet the remainder 
is different. 

Moreover, see if in replacing one of the terms by something else 
he has exchanged the genus and not the differentia, as in the 
example just given: for 'speculative' is a less familiar term than 
knowledge; for the one is the genus and the other the 
differentia, and the genus is always the most familiar term of 
all; so that it is not this, but the differentia, that ought to have 
been changed, seeing that it is the less familiar. It might be held 
that this criticism is ridiculous: because there is no reason why 
the most familiar term should not describe the differentia, and 
not the genus; in which case, clearly, the term to be altered 
would also be that denoting the genus and not the differentia. 
If, however, a man is substituting for a term not merely another 
term but a phrase, clearly it is of the differentia rather than of 
the genus that a definition should be rendered, seeing that the 
object of rendering the definition is to make the subject 
familiar; for the differentia is less familiar than the genus. 



481 



If he has rendered the definition of the differentia, see whether 
the definition rendered is common to it and something else as 
well: e.g. whenever he says that an odd number is a 'number 
with a middle', further definition is required of how it has a 
middle: for the word 'number' is common to both expressions, 
and it is the word 'odd' for which the phrase has been 
substituted. Now both a line and a body have a middle, yet they 
are not 'odd'; so that this could not be a definition of 'odd'. If, on 
the other hand, the phrase 'with a middle' be used in several 
senses, the sense here intended requires to be defined. So that 
this will either discredit the definition or prove that it is no 
definition at all. 



12 

Again, see if the term of which he renders the definition is a 
reality, whereas what is contained in the definition is not, e.g. 
Suppose 'white' to be defined as 'colour mingled with fire': for 
what is bodiless cannot be mingled with body, so that 'colour' 
'mingled with fire' could not exist, whereas 'white' does exist. 

Moreover, those who in the case of relative terms do not 
distinguish to what the object is related, but have described it 
only so as to include it among too large a number of things, are 
wrong either wholly or in part; e.g. suppose some one to have 
defined 'medicine' as a science of Reality'. For if medicine be 
not a science of anything that is real, the definition is clearly 
altogether false; while if it be a science of some real thing, but 
not of another, it is partly false; for it ought to hold of all reality, 
if it is said to be of Reality essentially and not accidentally: as is 
the case with other relative terms: for every object of knowledge 
is a term relative to knowledge: likewise, also, with other 



482 



relative terms, inasmuch as all such are convertible. Moreover, if 
the right way to render account of a thing be to render it as it is 
not in itself but accidentally, then each and every relative term 
would be used in relation not to one thing but to a number of 
things. For there is no reason why the same thing should not be 
both real and white and good, so that it would be a correct 
rendering to render the object in relation to any one whatsoever 
of these, if to render what it is accidentally be a correct way to 
render it. It is, moreover, impossible that a definition of this sort 
should be peculiar to the term rendered: for not only but the 
majority of the other sciences too, have for their object some 
real thing, so that each will be a science of reality. Clearly, then, 
such a definition does not define any science at all; for a 
definition ought to be peculiar to its own term, not general. 

Sometimes, again, people define not the thing but only the 
thing in a good or perfect condition. Such is the definition of a 
rhetorician as 'one who can always see what will persuade in 
the given circumstances, and omit nothing'; or of a thief, as 'one 
who pilfers in secret': for clearly, if they each do this, then the 
one will be a good rhetorician, and the other a good thief: 
whereas it is not the actual pilfering in secret, but the wish to 
do it, that constitutes the thief. 

Again, see if he has rendered what is desirable for its own sake 
as desirable for what it produces or does, or as in any way 
desirable because of something else, e.g. by saying that justice is 
'what preserves the laws' or that wisdom is 'what produces 
happiness'; for what produces or preserves something else is 
one of the things desirable for something else. It might be said 
that it is possible for what is desirable in itself to be desirable 
for something else as well: but still to define what is desirable in 
itself in such a way is none the less wrong: for the essence 
contains par excellence what is best in anything, and it is better 
for a thing to be desirable in itself than to be desirable for 



483 



something else, so that this is rather what the definition too 
ought to have indicated. 



13 

See also whether in defining anything a man has defined it as 
an 'A and B', or as a 'product of A and B' or as an A+B\ If he 
defines it as and B', the definition will be true of both and yet of 
neither of them; suppose, e.g. justice to be defined as 
'temperance and courage.' For if of two persons each has one of 
the two only, both and yet neither will be just: for both together 
have justice, and yet each singly fails to have it. Even if the 
situation here described does not so far appear very absurd 
because of the occurrence of this kind of thing in other cases 
also (for it is quite possible for two men to have a mina between 
them, though neither of them has it by himself), yet least that 
they should have contrary attributes surely seems quite absurd; 
and yet this will follow if the one be temperate and yet a 
coward, and the other, though brave, be a profligate; for then 
both will exhibit both justice and injustice: for if justice be 
temperance and bravery, then injustice will be cowardice and 
profligacy. In general, too, all the ways of showing that the 
whole is not the same as the sum of its parts are useful in 
meeting the type just described; for a man who defines in this 
way seems to assert that the parts are the same as the whole. 
The arguments are particularly appropriate in cases where the 
process of putting the parts together is obvious, as in a house 
and other things of that sort: for there, clearly, you may have the 
parts and yet not have the whole, so that parts and whole 
cannot be the same. 



484 



If, however, he has said that the term being defined is not 'A and 
B' but the 'product of A and B', look and see in the first place if A 
and B cannot in the nature of things have a single product: for 
some things are so related to one another that nothing can 
come of them, e.g. a line and a number. Moreover, see if the 
term that has been defined is in the nature of things found 
primarily in some single subject, whereas the things which he 
has said produce it are not found primarily in any single subject, 
but each in a separate one. If so, clearly that term could not be 
the product of these things: for the whole is bound to be in the 
same things wherein its parts are, so that the whole will then be 
found primarily not in one subject only, but in a number of 
them. If, on the other hand, both parts and whole are found 
primarily in some single subject, see if that medium is not the 
same, but one thing in the case of the whole and another in 
that of the parts. Again, see whether the parts perish together 
with the whole: for it ought to happen, vice versa, that the 
whole perishes when the parts perish; when the whole 
perishes, there is no necessity that the parts should perish too. 
Or again, see if the whole be good or evil, and the parts neither, 
or, vice versa, if the parts be good or evil and the whole neither. 
For it is impossible either for a neutral thing to produce 
something good or bad, or for things good or bad to produce a 
neutral thing. Or again, see if the one thing is more distinctly 
good than the other is evil, and yet the product be no more good 
than evil, e.g. suppose shamelessness be defined as 'the product 
of courage and false opinion': here the goodness of courage 
exceeds the evil of false opinion; accordingly the product of 
these ought to have corresponded to this excess, and to be 
either good without qualification, or at least more good than 
evil. Or it may be that this does not necessarily follow, unless 
each be in itself good or bad; for many things that are 
productive are not good in themselves, but only in combination; 
or, per contra, they are good taken singly, and bad or neutral in 



485 



combination. What has just been said is most clearly illustrated 
in the case of things that make for health or sickness; for some 
drugs are such that each taken alone is good, but if they are 
both administered in a mixture, bad. 

Again, see whether the whole, as produced from a better and 
worse, fails to be worse than the better and better than the 
worse element. This again, however, need not necessarily be the 
case, unless the elements compounded be in themselves good; 
if they are not, the whole may very well not be good, as in the 
cases just instanced. 

Moreover, see if the whole be synonymous with one of the 
elements: for it ought not to be, any more than in the case of 
syllables: for the syllable is not synonymous with any of the 
letters of which it is made up. 

Moreover, see if he has failed to state the manner of their 
composition: for the mere mention of its elements is not 
enough to make the thing intelligible. For the essence of any 
compound thing is not merely that it is a product of so-and-so, 
but that it is a product of them compounded in such and such a 
way, just as in the case of a house: for here the materials do not 
make a house irrespective of the way they are put together. 

If a man has defined an object as 'A+B', the first thing to be said 
is that A+B' means the same either as A and B', or as the 
'product of A and B.' for 'honey+water' means either the honey 
and the water, or the 'drink made of honey and water'. If, then, 
he admits that A+B' is + B' is the same as either of these two 
things, the same criticisms will apply as have already been 
given for meeting each of them. Moreover, distinguish between 
the different senses in which one thing may be said to be '+' 
another, and see if there is none of them in which A could be 
said to exist '+ B.' Thus e.g. supposing the expression to mean 
that they exist either in some identical thing capable of 



486 



containing them (as e.g. justice and courage are found in the 
soul), or else in the same place or in the same time, and if this 
be in no way true of the A and B in question, clearly the 
definition rendered could not hold of anything, as there is no 
possible way in which A can exist B'. If, however, among the 
various senses above distinguished, it be true that A and B are 
each found in the same time as the other, look and see if 
possibly the two are not used in the same relation. Thus e.g. 
suppose courage to have been defined as 'daring with right 
reasoning': here it is possible that the person exhibits daring in 
robbery, and right reasoning in regard to the means of health: 
but he may have 'the former quality+the latter' at the same 
time, and not as yet be courageous! Moreover, even though both 
be used in the same relation as well, e.g. in relation to medical 
treatment (for a man may exhibit both daring and right 
reasoning in respect of medical treatment), still, none the less, 
not even this combination of 'the one+the other 'makes him 
'courageous'. For the two must not relate to any casual object 
that is the same, any more than each to a different object; 
rather, they must relate to the function of courage, e.g. meeting 
the perils of war, or whatever is more properly speaking its 
function than this. 

Some definitions rendered in this form fail to come under the 
aforesaid division at all, e.g. a definition of anger as 'pain with a 
consciousness of being slighted'. For what this means to say is 
that it is because of a consciousness of this sort that the pain 
occurs; but to occur 'because of a thing is not the same as to 
occur '+ a thing' in any of its aforesaid senses. 



487 



14 

Again, if he have described the whole compounded as the 
'composition' of these things (e.g. 'a living creature' as a 
'composition of soul and body'), first of all see whether he has 
omitted to state the kind of composition, as (e.g.) in a definition 
of 'flesh' or 'bone' as the 'composition of fire, earth, and air'. For 
it is not enough to say it is a composition, but you should also 
go on to define the kind of composition: for these things do not 
form flesh irrespective of the manner of their composition, but 
when compounded in one way they form flesh, when in 
another, bone. It appears, moreover, that neither of the 
aforesaid substances is the same as a 'composition' at all: for a 
composition always has a decomposition as its contrary, 
whereas neither of the aforesaid has any contrary. Moreover, if 
it is equally probable that every compound is a composition or 
else that none is, and every kind of living creature, though a 
compound, is never a composition, then no other compound 
could be a composition either. 

Again, if in the nature of a thing two contraries are equally 
liable to occur, and the thing has been defined through the one, 
clearly it has not been defined; else there will be more than one 
definition of the same thing; for how is it any more a definition 
to define it through this one than through the other, seeing that 
both alike are naturally liable to occur in it? Such is the 
definition of the soul, if defined as a substance capable of 
receiving knowledge: for it has a like capacity for receiving 
ignorance. 

Also, even when one cannot attack the definition as a whole for 
lack of acquaintance with the whole, one should attack some 
part of it, if one knows that part and sees it to be incorrectly 
rendered: for if the part be demolished, so too is the whole 
definition. Where, again, a definition is obscure, one should first 



488 



of all correct and reshape it in order to make some part of it 
clear and get a handle for attack, and then proceed to examine 
it. For the answerer is bound either to accept the sense as taken 
by the questioner, or else himself to explain clearly whatever it 
is that his definition means. Moreover, just as in the assemblies 
the ordinary practice is to move an emendation of the existing 
law and, if the emendation is better, they repeal the existing 
law, so one ought to do in the case of definitions as well: one 
ought oneself to propose a second definition: for if it is seen to 
be better, and more indicative of the object defined, clearly the 
definition already laid down will have been demolished, on the 
principle that there cannot be more than one definition of the 
same thing. 

In combating definitions it is always one of the chief 
elementary principles to take by oneself a happy shot at a 
definition of the object before one, or to adopt some correctly 
expressed definition. For one is bound, with the model (as it 
were) before one's eyes, to discern both any shortcoming in any 
features that the definition ought to have, and also any 
superfluous addition, so that one is better supplied with lines of 
attack. 

As to definitions, then, let so much suffice. 



Book VII 



489 



Whether two things are 'the same' or 'different', in the most 
literal of the meanings ascribed to 'sameness' (and we said' that 
'the same' applies in the most literal sense to what is 
numerically one), may be examined in the light of their 
inflexions and coordinates and opposites. For if justice be the 
same as courage, then too the just man is the same as the brave 
man, and 'justly' is the same as 'bravely'. Likewise, too, in the 
case of their opposites: for if two things be the same, their 
opposites also will be the same, in any of the recognized forms 
of opposition. For it is the same thing to take the opposite of the 
one or that of the other, seeing that they are the same. Again it 
may be examined in the light of those things which tend to 
produce or to destroy the things in question of their formation 
and destruction, and in general of any thing that is related in 
like manner to each. For where things are absolutely the same, 
their formations and destructions also are the same, and so are 
the things that tend to produce or to destroy them. Look and 
see also, in a case where one of two things is said to be 
something or other in a superlative degree, if the other of these 
alleged identical things can also be described by a superlative in 
the same respect. Thus Xenocrates argues that the happy life 
and the good life are the same, seeing that of all forms of life 
the good life is the most desirable and so also is the happy life: 
for 'the most desirable' and the greatest' apply but to one thing.' 
Likewise also in other cases of the kind. Each, however, of the 
two things termed 'greatest' or most desirable' must be 
numerically one: otherwise no proof will have been given that 
they are the same; for it does not follow because 
Peloponnesians and Spartans are the bravest of the Greeks, that 
Peloponnesians are the same as Spartans, seeing that 
'Peloponnesian' is not any one person nor yet 'Spartan'; it only 
follows that the one must be included under the other as 
'Spartans' are under 'Peloponnesians': for otherwise, if the one 



490 



class be not included under the other, each will be better than 
the other. For then the Peloponnesians are bound to be better 
than the Spartans, seeing that the one class is not included 
under the other; for they are better than anybody else. Likewise 
also the Spartans must perforce be better than the 
Peloponnesians; for they too are better than anybody else; each 
then is better than the other! Clearly therefore what is styled 
'best' and 'greatest' must be a single thing, if it is to be proved to 
be 'the same' as another. This also is why Xenocrates fails to 
prove his case: for the happy life is not numerically single, nor 
yet the good life, so that it does not follow that, because they are 
both the most desirable, they are therefore the same, but only 
that the one falls under the other. 

Again, look and see if, supposing the one to be the same as 
something, the other also is the same as it: for if they be not 
both the same as the same thing, clearly neither are they the 
same as one another. 

Moreover, examine them in the light of their accidents or of the 
things of which they are accidents: for any accident belonging 
to the one must belong also to the other, and if the one belong 
to anything as an accident, so must the other also. If in any of 
these respects there is a discrepancy, clearly they are not the 
same. 

See further whether, instead of both being found in one class of 
predicates, the one signifies a quality and the other a quantity 
or relation. Again, see if the genus of each be not the same, the 
one being 'good' and the other evil', or the one being 'virtue' and 
the other 'knowledge': or see if, though the genus is the same, 
the differentiae predicted of either be not the same, the one 
(e.g.) being distinguished as a 'speculative' science, the other as 
a 'practical' science. Likewise also in other cases. 



491 



Moreover, from the point of view of 'degrees', see if the one 
admits an increase of degree but not the other, or if though both 
admit it, they do not admit it at the same time; just as it is not 
the case that a man desires intercourse more intensely, the 
more intensely he is in love, so that love and the desire for 
intercourse are not the same. 

Moreover, examine them by means of an addition, and see 
whether the addition of each to the same thing fails to make 
the same whole; or if the subtraction of the same thing from 
each leaves a different remainder. Suppose (e.g.) that he has 
declared 'double a half to be the same as 'a multiple of a half: 
then, subtracting the words 'a half from each, the remainders 
ought to have signified the same thing: but they do not; for 
'double' and 'a multiple of do not signify the same thing. 

Inquire also not only if some impossible consequence results 
directly from the statement made, that A and B are the same, 
but also whether it is possible for a supposition to bring it 
about; as happens to those who assert that 'empty' is the same 
as 'full of air': for clearly if the air be exhausted, the vessel will 
not be less but more empty, though it will no longer be full of 
air. So that by a supposition, which may be true or may be false 
(it makes no difference which), the one character is annulled 
and not the other, showing that they are not the same. 

Speaking generally, one ought to be on the look-out for any 
discrepancy anywhere in any sort of predicate of each term, and 
in the things of which they are predicated. For all that is 
predicated of the one should be predicated also of the other, 
and of whatever the one is a predicate, the other should be a 
predicate of it as well. 

Moreover, as 'sameness' is a term used in many senses, see 
whether things that are the same in one way are the same also 
in a different way. For there is either no necessity or even no 



492 



possibility that things that are the same specifically or 
generically should be numerically the same, and it is with the 
question whether they are or are not the same in that sense 
that we are concerned. 

Moreover, see whether the one can exist without the other; for, 
if so, they could not be the same. 



Such is the number of the commonplace rules that relate to 
'sameness'. It is clear from what has been said that all the 
destructive commonplaces relating to sameness are useful also 
in questions of definition, as was said before:' for if what is 
signified by the term and by the expression be not the same, 
clearly the expression rendered could not be a definition. None 
of the constructive commonplaces, on the other hand, helps in 
the matter of definition; for it is not enough to show the 
sameness of content between the expression and the term, in 
order to establish that the former is a definition, but a definition 
must have also all the other characters already announced. 



This then is the way, and these the arguments, whereby the 
attempt to demolish a definition should always be made. If, on 
the other hand, we desire to establish one, the first thing to 
observe is that few if any who engage in discussion arrive at a 
definition by reasoning: they always assume something of the 
kind as their starting points - both in geometry and in 



493 



arithmetic and the other studies of that kind. In the second 
place, to say accurately what a definition is, and how it should 
be given, belongs to another inquiry. At present it concerns us 
only so far as is required for our present purpose, and 
accordingly we need only make the bare statement that to 
reason to a thing's definition and essence is quite possible. For if 
a definition is an expression signifying the essence of the thing 
and the predicates contained therein ought also to be the only 
ones which are predicated of the thing in the category of 
essence; and genera and differentiae are so predicated in that 
category: it is obvious that if one were to get an admission that 
so and so are the only attributes predicated in that category, the 
expression containing so and so would of necessity be a 
definition; for it is impossible that anything else should be a 
definition, seeing that there is not anything else predicated of 
the thing in the category of essence. 

That a definition may thus be reached by a process of reasoning 
is obvious. The means whereby it should be established have 
been more precisely defined elsewhere, but for the purposes of 
the inquiry now before us the same commonplace rules serve. 
For we have to examine into the contraries and other opposites 
of the thing, surveying the expressions used both as wholes and 
in detail: for if the opposite definition defines that opposite 
term, the definition given must of necessity be that of the term 
before us. Seeing, however, that contraries may be conjoined in 
more than one way, we have to select from those contraries the 
one whose contrary definition seems most obvious. The 
expressions, then, have to be examined each as a whole in the 
way we have said, and also in detail as follows. First of all, see 
that the genus rendered is correctly rendered; for if the contrary 
thing be found in the contrary genus to that stated in the 
definition, and the thing before you is not in that same genus, 
then it would clearly be in the contrary genus: for contraries 
must of necessity be either in the same genus or in contrary 



494 



genera. The differentiae, too, that are predicated of contraries 
we expect to be contrary, e.g. those of white and black, for the 
one tends to pierce the vision, while the other tends to 
compress it. So that if contrary differentiae to those in the 
definition are predicated of the contrary term, then those 
rendered in the definition would be predicated of the term 
before us. Seeing, then, that both the genus and the differentiae 
have been rightly rendered, clearly the expression given must 
be the right definition. It might be replied that there is no 
necessity why contrary differentiae should be predicated of 
contraries, unless the contraries be found within the same 
genus: of things whose genera are themselves contraries it may 
very well be that the same differentia is used of both, e.g. of 
justice and injustice; for the one is a virtue and the other a vice 
of the soul: 'of the soul', therefore, is the differentia in both 
cases, seeing that the body as well has its virtue and vice. But 
this much at least is true, that the differentiae of contraries are 
either contrary or else the same. If, then, the contrary 
differentia to that given be predicated of the contrary term and 
not of the one in hand, clearly the differentia stated must be 
predicated of the latter. Speaking generally, seeing that the 
definition consists of genus and differentiae, if the definition of 
the contrary term be apparent, the definition of the term before 
you will be apparent also: for since its contrary is found either 
in the same genus or in the contrary genus, and likewise also 
the differentiae predicated of opposites are either contrary to, or 
the same as, each other, clearly of the term before you there will 
be predicated either the same genus as of its contrary, while, of 
its differentiae, either all are contrary to those of its contrary, or 
at least some of them are so while the rest remain the same; or, 
vice versa, the differentiae will be the same and the genera 
contrary; or both genera and differentiae will be contrary. And 
that is all; for that both should be the same is not possible; else 
contraries will have the same definition. 



495 



Moreover, look at it from the point of view of its inflexions and 
coordinates. For genera and definitions are bound to correspond 
in either case. Thus if forgetfulness be the loss of knowledge, to 
forget is to lose knowledge, and to have forgotten is to have lost 
knowledge. If, then, any one whatever of these is agreed to, the 
others must of necessity be agreed to as well. Likewise, also, if 
destruction is the decomposition of the thing's essence, then to 
be destroyed is to have its essence decomposed, and 
'destructively' means 'in such a way as to decompose its 
essence'; if again 'destructive' means 'apt to decompose 
something's essence', then also 'destruction' means 'the 
decomposition of its essence'. Likewise also with the rest: an 
admission of any one of them whatever, and all the rest are 
admitted too. 

Moreover, look at it from the point of view of things that stand 
in relations that are like each other. For if 'healthy' means 
'productive of health', 'vigorous' too will mean 'productive of 
vigour', and 'useful' will mean 'productive of good.' For each of 
these things is related in like manner to its own peculiar end, so 
that if one of them is defined as 'productive of that end, this 
will also be the definition of each of the rest as well. 

Moreover, look at it from the point of and like degrees, in all the 
ways in which it is possible to establish a result by comparing 
two and two together. Thus if A defines a better than B defines 
and B is a definition of so too is A of a. Further, if As claim to 
define a is like B's to define B, and B defines B, then A too 
defines a. This examination from the point of view of greater 
degrees is of no use when a single definition is compared with 
two things, or two definitions with one thing; for there cannot 
possibly be one definition of two things or two of the same 
thing. 



496 



The most handy of all the commonplace arguments are those 
just mentioned and those from co-ordinates and inflexions, and 
these therefore are those which it is most important to master 
and to have ready to hand: for they are the most useful on the 
greatest number of occasions. Of the rest, too, the most 
important are those of most general application: for these are 
the most effective, e.g. that you should examine the individual 
cases, and then look to see in the case of their various species 
whether the definition applies. For the species is synonymous 
with its individuals. This sort of inquiry is of service against 
those who assume the existence of Ideas, as has been said 
before.' Moreover see if a man has used a term metaphorically, 
or predicated it of itself as though it were something different. 
So too if any other of the commonplace rules is of general 
application and effective, it should be employed. 



That it is more difficult to establish than to overthrow a 
definition, is obvious from considerations presently to be urged. 
For to see for oneself, and to secure from those whom one is 
questioning, an admission of premisses of this sort is no simple 
matter, e.g. that of the elements of the definition rendered the 
one is genus and the other differentia, and that only the genus 
and differentiae are predicated in the category of essence. Yet 
without these premisses it is impossible to reason to a 
definition; for if any other things as well are predicated of the 
thing in the category of essence, there is no telling whether the 
formula stated or some other one is its definition, for a 



497 



definition is an expression indicating the essence of a thing. The 
point is clear also from the following: It is easier to draw one 
conclusion than many. Now in demolishing a definition it is 
sufficient to argue against one point only (for if we have 
overthrown any single point whatsoever, we shall have 
demolished the definition); whereas in establishing a definition, 
one is bound to bring people to the view that everything 
contained in the definition is attributable. Moreover, in 
establishing a case, the reasoning brought forward must be 
universal: for the definition put forward must be predicated of 
everything of which the term is predicated, and must moreover 
be convertible, if the definition rendered is to be peculiar to the 
subject. In overthrowing a view, on the other hand, there is no 
longer any necessity to show one's point universally: for it is 
enough to show that the formula is untrue of any one of the 
things embraced under the term. 

Further, even supposing it should be necessary to overthrow 
something by a universal proposition, not even so is there any 
need to prove the converse of the proposition in the process of 
overthrowing the definition. For merely to show that the 
definition fails to be predicated of every one of the things of 
which the term is predicated, is enough to overthrow it 
universally: and there is no need to prove the converse of this in 
order to show that the term is predicated of things of which the 
expression is not predicated. Moreover, even if it applies to 
everything embraced under the term, but not to it alone, the 
definition is thereby demolished. 

The case stands likewise in regard to the property and genus of 
a term also. For in both cases it is easier to overthrow than to 
establish. As regards the property this is clear from what has 
been said: for as a rule the property is rendered in a complex 
phrase, so that to overthrow it, it is only necessary to demolish 
one of the terms used, whereas to establish it is necessary to 



498 



reason to them all. Then, too, nearly all the other rules that 
apply to the definition will apply also to the property of a thing. 
For in establishing a property one has to show that it is true of 
everything included under the term in question, whereas to 
overthrow one it is enough to show in a single case only that it 
fails to belong: further, even if it belongs to everything falling 
under the term, but not to that only, it is overthrown in this case 
as well, as was explained in the case of the definition. In regard 
to the genus, it is clear that you are bound to establish it in one 
way only, viz. by showing that it belongs in every case, while of 
overthrowing it there are two ways: for if it has been shown that 
it belongs either never or not in a certain case, the original 
statement has been demolished. Moreover, in establishing a 
genus it is not enough to show that it belongs, but also that it 
belongs as genus has to be shown; whereas in overthrowing it, 
it is enough to show its failure to belong either in some 
particular case or in every case. It appears, in fact, as though, 
just as in other things to destroy is easier than to create, so in 
these matters too to overthrow is easier than to establish. 

In the case of an accidental attribute the universal proposition 
is easier to overthrow than to establish; for to establish it, one 
has to show that it belongs in every case, whereas to overthrow 
it, it is enough to show that it does not belong in one single 
case. The particular proposition is, on the contrary, easier to 
establish than to overthrow: for to establish it, it is enough to 
show that it belongs in a particular instance, whereas to 
overthrow it, it has to be shown that it never belongs at all. 

It is clear also that the easiest thing of all is to overthrow a 
definition. For on account of the number of statements involved 
we are presented in the definition with the greatest number of 
points for attack, and the more plentiful the material, the 
quicker an argument comes: for there is more likelihood of a 
mistake occurring in a large than in a small number of things. 



499 



Moreover, the other rules too may be used as means for 
attacking a definition: for if either the formula be not peculiar, 
or the genus rendered be the wrong one, or something included 
in the formula fail to belong, the definition is thereby 
demolished. On the other hand, against the others we cannot 
bring all of the arguments drawn from definitions, nor yet of the 
rest: for only those relating to accidental attributes apply 
generally to all the aforesaid kinds of attribute. For while each 
of the aforesaid kinds of attribute must belong to the thing in 
question, yet the genus may very well not belong as a property 
without as yet being thereby demolished. Likewise also the 
property need not belong as a genus, nor the accident as a 
genus or property, so long as they do belong. So that it is 
impossible to use one set as a basis of attack upon the other 
except in the case of definition. Clearly, then, it is the easiest of 
all things to demolish a definition, while to establish one is the 
hardest. For there one both has to establish all those other 
points by reasoning (i.e. that the attributes stated belong, and 
that the genus rendered is the true genus, and that the formula 
is peculiar to the term), and moreover, besides this, that the 
formula indicates the essence of the thing; and this has to be 
done correctly. 

Of the rest, the property is most nearly of this kind: for it is 
easier to demolish, because as a rule it contains several terms; 
while it is the hardest to establish, both because of the number 
of things that people must be brought to accept, and, besides 
this, because it belongs to its subject alone and is predicated 
convertibly with its subject. 

The easiest thing of all to establish is an accidental predicate: 
for in other cases one has to show not only that the predicate 
belongs, but also that it belongs in such and such a particular 
way: whereas in the case of the accident it is enough to show 
merely that it belongs. On the other hand, an accidental 



500 



predicate is the hardest thing to overthrow, because it affords 
the least material: for in stating accident a man does not add 
how the predicate belongs; and accordingly, while in other cases 
it is possible to demolish what is said in two ways, by showing 
either that the predicate does not belong, or that it does not 
belong in the particular way stated, in the case of an accidental 
predicate the only way to demolish it is to show that it does not 
belong at all. 

The commonplace arguments through which we shall be well 
supplied with lines of argument with regard to our several 
problems have now been enumerated at about sufficient length. 



Book VIII 



Next there fall to be discussed the problems of arrangement 
and method in pitting questions. Any one who intends to frame 
questions must, first of all, select the ground from which he 
should make his attack; secondly, he must frame them and 
arrange them one by one to himself; thirdly and lastly, he must 
proceed actually to put them to the other party. Now so far as 
the selection of his ground is concerned the problem is one 
alike for the philosopher and the dialectician; but how to go on 
to arrange his points and frame his questions concerns the 
dialectician only: for in every problem of that kind a reference 
to another party is involved. Not so with the philosopher, and 



501 



the man who is investigating by himself: the premisses of his 
reasoning, although true and familiar, may be refused by the 
answerer because they lie too near the original statement and 
so he foresees what will follow if he grants them: but for this 
the philosopher does not care. Nay, he may possibly be even 
anxious to secure axioms as familiar and as near to the 
question in hand as possible: for these are the bases on which 
scientific reasonings are built up. 

The sources from which one's commonplace arguments should 
be drawn have already been described:' we have now to discuss 
the arrangement and formation of questions and first to 
distinguish the premisses, other than the necessary premisses, 
which have to be adopted. By necessary premisses are meant 
those through which the actual reasoning is constructed. Those 
which are secured other than these are of four kinds; they serve 
either inductively to secure the universal premiss being granted, 
or to lend weight to the argument, or to conceal the conclusion, 
or to render the argument more clear. Beside these there is no 
other premiss which need be secured: these are the ones 
whereby you should try to multiply and formulate your 
questions. Those which are used to conceal the conclusion 
serve a controversial purpose only; but inasmuch as an 
undertaking of this sort is always conducted against another 
person, we are obliged to employ them as well. 

The necessary premisses through which the reasoning is 
effected, ought not to be propounded directly in so many words. 
Rather one should soar as far aloof from them as possible. Thus 
if one desires to secure an admission that the knowledge of 
contraries is one, one should ask him to admit it not of 
contraries, but of opposites: for, if he grants this, one will then 
argue that the knowledge of contraries is also the same, seeing 
that contraries are opposites; if he does not, one should secure 
the admission by induction, by formulating a proposition to that 



502 



effect in the case of some particular pair of contraries. For one 
must secure the necessary premisses either by reasoning or by 
induction, or else partly by one and partly by the other, 
although any propositions which are too obvious to be denied 
may be formulated in so many words. This is because the 
coming conclusion is less easily discerned at the greater 
distance and in the process of induction, while at the same 
time, even if one cannot reach the required premisses in this 
way, it is still open to one to formulate them in so many words. 
The premisses, other than these, that were mentioned above, 
must be secured with a view to the latter. The way to employ 
them respectively is as follows: Induction should proceed from 
individual cases to the universal and from the known to the 
unknown; and the objects of perception are better known, to 
most people if not invariably. Concealment of one's plan is 
obtained by securing through prosyllogisms the premisses 
through which the proof of the original proposition is going to 
be constructed - and as many of them as possible. This is likely 
to be effected by making syllogisms to prove not only the 
necessary premisses but also some of those which are required 
to establish them. Moreover, do not state the conclusions of 
these premisses but draw them later one after another; for this 
is likely to keep the answerer at the greatest possible distance 
from the original proposition. Speaking generally, a man who 
desires to get information by a concealed method should so put 
his questions that when he has put his whole argument and 
has stated the conclusion, people still ask 'Well, but why is 
that?' This result will be secured best of all by the method above 
described: for if one states only the final conclusion, it is 
unclear how it comes about; for the answerer does not foresee 
on what grounds it is based, because the previous syllogisms 
have not been made articulate to him: while the final syllogism, 
showing the conclusion, is likely to be kept least articulate if we 



503 



lay down not the secured propositions on which it is based, but 
only the grounds on which we reason to them. 

It is a useful rule, too, not to secure the admissions claimed as 
the bases of the syllogisms in their proper order, but alternately 
those that conduce to one conclusion and those that conduce to 
another; for, if those which go together are set side by side, the 
conclusion that will result from them is more obvious in 
advance. 

One should also, wherever possible, secure the universal 
premiss by a definition relating not to the precise terms 
themselves but to their co-ordinates; for people deceive 
themselves, whenever the definition is taken in regard to a co- 
ordinate, into thinking that they are not making the admission 
universally. An instance would be, supposing one had to secure 
the admission that the angry man desires vengeance on 
account of an apparent slight, and were to secure this, that 
'anger' is a desire for vengeance on account of an apparent 
slight: for, clearly, if this were secured, we should have 
universally what we intend. If, on the other hand, people 
formulate propositions relating to the actual terms themselves, 
they often find that the answerer refuses to grant them because 
on the actual term itself he is readier with his objection, e.g. 
that the 'angry man' does not desire vengeance, because we 
become angry with our parents, but we do not desire vengeance 
on them. Very likely the objection is not valid; for upon some 
people it is vengeance enough to cause them pain and make 
them sorry; but still it gives a certain plausibility and air of 
reasonableness to the denial of the proposition. In the case, 
however, of the definition of 'anger' it is not so easy to find an 
objection. 

Moreover, formulate your proposition as though you did so not 
for its own sake, but in order to get at something else: for people 



504 



are shy of granting what an opponent's case really requires. 
Speaking generally, a questioner should leave it as far as 
possible doubtful whether he wishes to secure an admission of 
his proposition or of its opposite: for if it be uncertain what 
their opponent's argument requires, people are more ready to 
say what they themselves think. 

Moreover, try to secure admissions by means of likeness: for 
such admissions are plausible, and the universal involved is less 
patent; e.g. make the other person admit that as knowledge and 
ignorance of contraries is the same, so too perception of 
contraries is the same; or vice versa, that since the perception is 
the same, so is the knowledge also. This argument resembles 
induction, but is not the same thing; for in induction it is the 
universal whose admission is secured from the particulars, 
whereas in arguments from likeness, what is secured is not the 
universal under which all the like cases fall. 

It is a good rule also, occasionally to bring an objection against 
oneself: for answerers are put off their guard against those who 
appear to be arguing impartially. It is useful too, to add that 'So 
and so is generally held or commonly said'; for people are shy of 
upsetting the received opinion unless they have some positive 
objection to urge: and at the same time they are cautious about 
upsetting such things because they themselves too find them 
useful. Moreover, do not be insistent, even though you really 
require the point: for insistence always arouses the more 
opposition. Further, formulate your premiss as though it were a 
mere illustration: for people admit the more readily a 
proposition made to serve some other purpose, and not 
required on its own account. Moreover, do not formulate the 
very proposition you need to secure, but rather something from 
which that necessarily follows: for people are more willing to 
admit the latter, because it is not so clear from this what the 
result will be, and if the one has been secured, the other has 



505 



been secured also. Again, one should put last the point which 
one most wishes to have conceded; for people are specially 
inclined to deny the first questions put to them, because most 
people in asking questions put first the points which they are 
most eager to secure. On the other hand, in dealing with some 
people propositions of this sort should be put forward first: for 
ill-tempered men admit most readily what comes first, unless 
the conclusion that will result actually stares them in the face, 
while at the close of an argument they show their ill-temper. 
Likewise also with those who consider themselves smart at 
answering: for when they have admitted most of what you want 
they finally talk clap-trap to the effect that the conclusion does 
not follow from their admissions: yet they say 'Yes' readily, 
confident in their own character, and imagining that they 
cannot suffer any reverse. Moreover, it is well to expand the 
argument and insert things that it does not require at all, as do 
those who draw false geometrical figures: for in the multitude 
of details the whereabouts of the fallacy is obscured. For this 
reason also a questioner sometimes evades observation as he 
adds in a corner what, if he formulated it by itself, would not be 
granted. 

For concealment, then, the rules which should be followed are 
the above. Ornament is attained by induction and distinction of 
things closely akin. What sort of process induction is obvious: as 
for distinction, an instance of the kind of thing meant is the 
distinction of one form of knowledge as better than another by 
being either more accurate, or concerned with better objects; or 
the distinction of sciences into speculative, practical, and 
productive. For everything of this kind lends additional 
ornament to the argument, though there is no necessity to say 
them, so far as the conclusion goes. 

For clearness, examples and comparisons should be adduced, 
and let the illustrations be relevant and drawn from things that 



506 



we know, as in Homer and not as in Choerilus; for then the 
proposition is likely to become clearer. 



In dialectics, syllogism should be employed in reasoning against 
dialecticians rather than against the crowd: induction, on the 
other hand, is most useful against the crowd. This point has 
been treated previously as well.' In induction, it is possible in 
some cases to ask the question in its universal form, but in 
others this is not easy, because there is no established general 
term that covers all the resemblances: in this case, when people 
need to secure the universal, they use the phrase 'in all cases of 
this sort'. But it is one of the very hardest things to distinguish 
which of the things adduced are 'of this sort', and which are 
not: and in this connexion people often throw dust in each 
others' eyes in their discussion, the one party asserting the 
likeness of things that are not alike, and the other disputing the 
likeness of things that are. One ought, therefore, to try oneself 
to coin a word to cover all things of the given sort, so as to leave 
no opportunity either to the answerer to dispute, and say that 
the thing advanced does not answer to a like description, or to 
the questioner to suggest falsely that it does answer to a like 
description, for many things appear to answer to like 
descriptions that do not really do so. 

If one has made an induction on the strength of several cases 
and yet the answerer refuses to grant the universal proposition, 
then it is fair to demand his objection. But until one has oneself 
stated in what cases it is so, it is not fair to demand that he 
shall say in what cases it is not so: for one should make the 
induction first, and then demand the objection. One ought, 



507 



moreover, to claim that the objections should not be brought in 
reference to the actual subject of the proposition, unless that 
subject happen to be the one and only thing of the kind, as for 
instance two is the one prime number among the even 
numbers: for, unless he can say that this subject is unique of its 
kind, the objector ought to make his objection in regard to some 
other. People sometimes object to a universal proposition, and 
bring their objection not in regard to the thing itself, but in 
regard to some homonym of it: thus they argue that a man can 
very well have a colour or a foot or a hand other than his own, 
for a painter may have a colour that is not his own, and a cook 
may have a foot that is not his own. To meet them, therefore, 
you should draw the distinction before putting your question in 
such cases: for so long as the ambiguity remains undetected, so 
long will the objection to the proposition be deemed valid. If, 
however, he checks the series of questions by an objection in 
regard not to some homonym, but to the actual thing asserted, 
the questioner should withdraw the point objected to, and form 
the remainder into a universal proposition, until he secures 
what he requires; e.g. in the case of forgetfulness and having 
forgotten: for people refuse to admit that the man who has lost 
his knowledge of a thing has forgotten it, because if the thing 
alters, he has lost knowledge of it, but he has not forgotten it. 
Accordingly the thing to do is to withdraw the part objected to, 
and assert the remainder, e.g. that if a person have lost 
knowledge of a thing while it still remains, he then has 
forgotten it. One should similarly treat those who object to the 
statement that 'the greater the good, the greater the evil that is 
its opposite': for they allege that health, which is a less good 
thing than vigour, has a greater evil as its opposite: for disease 
is a greater evil than debility. In this case too, therefore, we have 
to withdraw the point objected to; for when it has been 
withdrawn, the man is more likely to admit the proposition, e.g. 
that 'the greater good has the greater evil as its opposite, unless 



508 



the one good involves the other as well', as vigour involves 
health. This should be done not only when he formulates an 
objection, but also if, without so doing, he refuses to admit the 
point because he foresees something of the kind: for if the point 
objected to be withdrawn, he will be forced to admit the 
proposition because he cannot foresee in the rest of it any case 
where it does not hold true: if he refuse to admit it, then when 
asked for an objection he certainly will be unable to render one. 
Propositions that are partly false and partly true are of this type: 
for in the case of these it is possible by withdrawing a part to 
leave the rest true. If, however, you formulate the proposition on 
the strength of many cases and he has no objection to bring, 
you may claim that he shall admit it: for a premiss is valid in 
dialectics which thus holds in several instances and to which 
no objection is forthcoming. 

Whenever it is possible to reason to the same conclusion either 
through or without a reduction per impossibile, if one is 
demonstrating and not arguing dialectically it makes no 
difference which method of reasoning be adopted, but in 
argument with another reasoning per impossibile should be 
avoided. For where one has reasoned without the reduction per 
impossibile, no dispute can arise; if, on the other hand, one does 
reason to an impossible conclusion, unless its falsehood is too 
plainly manifest, people deny that it is impossible, so that the 
questioners do not get what they want. 

One should put forward all propositions that hold true of 
several cases, and to which either no objection whatever 
appears or at least not any on the surface: for when people 
cannot see any case in which it is not so, they admit it for true. 

The conclusion should not be put in the form of a question; if it 
be, and the man shakes his head, it looks as if the reasoning 
had failed. For often, even if it be not put as a question but 



509 



advanced as a consequence, people deny it, and then those who 
do not see that it follows upon the previous admissions do not 
realize that those who deny it have been refuted: when, then, 
the one man merely asks it as a question without even saying 
that it so follows, and the other denies it, it looks altogether as if 
the reasoning had failed. 

Not every universal question can form a dialectical proposition 
as ordinarily understood, e.g. 'What is man?' or 'How many 
meanings has «the good»?' For a dialectical premiss must be of 
a form to which it is possible to reply 'Yes' or 'No', whereas to 
the aforesaid it is not possible. For this reason questions of this 
kind are not dialectical unless the questioner himself draws 
distinctions or divisions before expressing them, e.g. 'Good 
means this, or this, does it not?' For questions of this sort are 
easily answered by a Yes or a No. Hence one should endeavour 
to formulate propositions of this kind in this form. It is at the 
same time also perhaps fair to ask the other man how many 
meanings of 'the good' there are, whenever you have yourself 
distinguished and formulated them, and he will not admit them 
at all. 

Any one who keeps on asking one thing for a long time is a bad 
inquirer. For if he does so though the person questioned keeps 
on answering the questions, clearly he asks a large number of 
questions, or else asks the same question a large number of 
times: in the one case he merely babbles, in the other he fails to 
reason: for reasoning always consists of a small number of 
premisses. If, on the other hand, he does it because the person 
questioned does not answer the questions, he is at fault in not 
taking him to task or breaking off the discussion. 



510 



There are certain hypotheses upon which it is at once difficult 
to bring, and easy to stand up to, an argument. Such (e.g.) are 
those things which stand first and those which stand last in the 
order of nature. For the former require definition, while the 
latter have to be arrived at through many steps if one wishes to 
secure a continuous proof from first principles, or else all 
discussion about them wears the air of mere sophistry: for to 
prove anything is impossible unless one begins with the 
appropriate principles, and connects inference with inference 
till the last are reached. Now to define first principles is just 
what answerers do not care to do, nor do they pay any attention 
if the questioner makes a definition: and yet until it is clear 
what it is that is proposed, it is not easy to discuss it. This sort 
of thing happens particularly in the case of the first principles: 
for while the other propositions are shown through these, these 
cannot be shown through anything else: we are obliged to 
understand every item of that sort by a definition. The 
inferences, too, that lie too close to the first principle are hard to 
treat in argument: for it is not possible to bring many arguments 
in regard to them, because of the small number of those steps, 
between the conclusion and the principle, whereby the 
succeeding propositions have to be shown. The hardest, 
however, of all definitions to treat in argument are those that 
employ terms about which, in the first place, it is uncertain 
whether they are used in one sense or several, and, further, 
whether they are used literally or metaphorically by the definer. 
For because of their obscurity, it is impossible to argue upon 
such terms; and because of the impossibility of saying whether 
this obscurity is due to their being used metaphorically, it is 
impossible to refute them. 

In general, it is safe to suppose that, whenever any problem 
proves intractable, it either needs definition or else bears either 



511 



several senses, or a metaphorical sense, or it is not far removed 
from the first principles; or else the reason is that we have yet 
to discover in the first place just this - in which of the aforesaid 
directions the source of our difficulty lies: when we have made 
this clear, then obviously our business must be either to define 
or to distinguish, or to supply the intermediate premisses: for it 
is through these that the final conclusions are shown. 

It often happens that a difficulty is found in discussing or 
arguing a given position because the definition has not been 
correctly rendered: e.g. 'Has one thing one contrary or many?': 
here when the term 'contraries' has been properly defined, it is 
easy to bring people to see whether it is possible for the same 
thing to have several contraries or not: in the same way also 
with other terms requiring definition. It appears also in 
mathematics that the difficulty in using a figure is sometimes 
due to a defect in definition; e.g. in proving that the line which 
cuts the plane parallel to one side divides similarly both the line 
which it cuts and the area; whereas if the definition be given, 
the fact asserted becomes immediately clear: for the areas have 
the same fraction subtracted from them as have the sides: and 
this is the definition of 'the same ratio'. The most primary of the 
elementary principles are without exception very easy to show, 
if the definitions involved, e.g. the nature of a line or of a circle, 
be laid down; only the arguments that can be brought in regard 
to each of them are not many, because there are not many 
intermediate steps. If, on the other hand, the definition of the 
starting-points be not laid down, to show them is difficult and 
may even prove quite impossible. The case of the significance of 
verbal expressions is like that of these mathematical 
conceptions. 

One may be sure then, whenever a position is hard to discuss, 
that one or other of the aforesaid things has happened to it. 
Whenever, on the other hand, it is a harder task to argue to the 



512 



point claimed, i.e. the premiss, than to the resulting position, a 
doubt may arise whether such claims should be admitted or 
not: for if a man is going to refuse to admit it and claim that you 
shall argue to it as well, he will be giving the signal for a harder 
undertaking than was originally proposed: if, on the other hand, 
he grants it, he will be giving the original thesis credence on the 
strength of what is less credible than itself. If, then, it is 
essential not to enhance the difficulty of the problem, he had 
better grant it; if, on the other hand, it be essential to reason 
through premisses that are better assured, he had better refuse. 
In other words, in serious inquiry he ought not to grant it, 
unless he be more sure about it than about the conclusion; 
whereas in a dialectical exercise he may do so if he is merely 
satisfied of its truth. Clearly, then, the circumstances under 
which such admissions should be claimed are different for a 
mere questioner and for a serious teacher. 



As to the formulation, then, and arrangement of one's 
questions, about enough has been said. 

With regard to the giving of answers, we must first define what 
is the business of a good answerer, as of a good questioner. The 
business of the questioner is so to develop the argument as to 
make the answerer utter the most extrvagant paradoxes that 
necessarily follow because of his position: while that of the 
answerer is to make it appear that it is not he who is 
responsible for the absurdity or paradox, but only his position: 
for one may, perhaps, distinguish between the mistake of taking 
up a wrong position to start with, and that of not maintaining it 
properly, when once taken up. 



513 



Inasmuch as no rules are laid down for those who argue for the 
sake of training and of examination: - and the aim of those 
engaged in teaching or learning is quite different from that of 
those engaged in a competition; as is the latter from that of 
those who discuss things together in the spirit of inquiry: for a 
learner should always state what he thinks: for no one is even 
trying to teach him what is false; whereas in a competition the 
business of the questioner is to appear by all means to produce 
an effect upon the other, while that of the answerer is to appear 
unaffected by him; on the other hand, in an assembly of 
disputants discussing in the spirit not of a competition but of 
an examination and inquiry, there are as yet no articulate rules 
about what the answerer should aim at, and what kind of things 
he should and should not grant for the correct or incorrect 
defence of his position: - inasmuch, then, as we have no 
tradition bequeathed to us by others, let us try to say something 
upon the matter for ourselves. 

The thesis laid down by the answerer before facing the 
questioner's argument is bound of necessity to be one that is 
either generally accepted or generally rejected or else is neither: 
and moreover is so accepted or rejected either absolutely or else 
with a restriction, e.g. by some given person, by the speaker or 
by some one else. The manner, however, of its acceptance or 
rejection, whatever it be, makes no difference: for the right way 
to answer, i.e. to admit or to refuse to admit what has been 
asked, will be the same in either case. If, then, the statement 
laid down by the answerer be generally rejected, the conclusion 
aimed at by the questioner is bound to be one generally 
accepted, whereas if the former be generally accepted, the latter 



514 



is generally rejected: for the conclusion which the questioner 
tries to draw is always the opposite of the statement laid down. 
If, on the other hand, what is laid down is generally neither 
rejected nor accepted, the conclusion will be of the same type 
as well. Now since a man who reasons correctly demonstrates 
his proposed conclusion from premisses that are more 
generally accepted, and more familiar, it is clear that (1) where 
the view laid down by him is one that generally is absolutely 
rejected, the answerer ought not to grant either what is thus 
absolutely not accepted at all, or what is accepted indeed, but 
accepted less generally than the questioner's conclusion. For if 
the statement laid down by the answerer be generally rejected, 
the conclusion aimed at by the questioner will be one that is 
generally accepted, so that the premisses secured by the 
questioner should all be views generally accepted, and more 
generally accepted than his proposed conclusion, if the less 
familiar is to be inferred through the more familiar. 
Consequently, if any of the questions put to him be not of this 
character, the answerer should not grant them. (2) If, on the 
other hand, the statement laid down by the answerer be 
generally accepted without qualification, clearly the conclusion 
sought by the questioner will be one generally rejected without 
qualification. Accordingly, the answerer should admit all views 
that are generally accepted and, of those that are not generally 
accepted, all that are less generally rejected than the conclusion 
sought by the questioner. For then he will probably be thought 
to have argued sufficiently well. (3) Likewise, too, if the 
statement laid down by the answerer be neither rejected 
generally nor generally accepted; for then, too, anything that 
appears to be true should be granted, and, of the views not 
generally accepted, any that are more generally accepted than 
the questioner's conclusion; for in that case the result will be 
that the arguments will be more generally accepted. If, then, the 
view laid down by the answerer be one that is generally 



515 



accepted or rejected without qualification, then the views that 
are accepted absolutely must be taken as the standard of 
comparison: whereas if the view laid down be one that is not 
generally accepted or rejected, but only by the answerer, then 
the standard whereby the latter must judge what is generally 
accepted or not, and must grant or refuse to grant the point 
asked, is himself. If, again, the answerer be defending some one 
else's opinion, then clearly it will be the latter's judgement to 
which he must have regard in granting or denying the various 
points. This is why those, too, who introduce other's opinions, 
e.g. that 'good and evil are the same thing, as Heraclitus says,' 
refuse to admit the impossibility of contraries belonging at the 
same time to the same thing; not because they do not 
themselves believe this, but because on Heraclitus' principles 
one has to say so. The same thing is done also by those who 
take on the defence of one another's positions; their aim being 
to speak as would the man who stated the position. 



It is clear, then, what the aims of the answerer should be, 
whether the position he lays down be a view generally accepted 
without qualification or accepted by some definite person. Now 
every question asked is bound to involve some view that is 
either generally held or generally rejected or neither, and is also 
bound to be either relevant to the argument or irrelevant: if 
then it be a view generally accepted and irrelevant, the 
answerer should grant it and remark that it is the accepted 
view: if it be a view not generally accepted and irrelevant, he 
should grant it but add a comment that it is not generally 
accepted, in order to avoid the appearance of being a simpleton. 
If it be relevant and also be generally accepted, he should admit 



516 



that it is the view generally accepted but say that it lies too 
close to the original proposition, and that if it be granted the 
problem proposed collapses. If what is claimed by the 
questioner be relevant but too generally rejected, the answerer, 
while admitting that if it be granted the conclusion sought 
follows, should yet protest that the proposition is too absurd to 
be admitted. Suppose, again, it be a view that is neither rejected 
generally nor generally accepted, then, if it be irrelevant to the 
argument, it may be granted without restriction; if, however, it 
be relevant, the answerer should add the comment that, if it be 
granted, the original problem collapses. For then the answerer 
will not be held to be personally accountable for what happens 
to him, if he grants the several points with his eyes open, and 
also the questioner will be able to draw his inference, seeing 
that all the premisses that are more generally accepted than the 
conclusion are granted him. Those who try to draw an inference 
from premisses more generally rejected than the conclusion 
clearly do not reason correctly: hence, when men ask these 
things, they ought not to be granted. 



The questioner should be met in a like manner also in the case 
of terms used obscurely, i.e. in several senses. For the answerer, 
if he does not understand, is always permitted to say 'I do not 
understand': he is not compelled to reply 'Yes' or 'No' to a 
question which may mean different things. Clearly, then, in the 
first place, if what is said be not clear, he ought not to hesitate 
to say that he does not understand it; for often people 
encounter some difficulty from assenting to questions that are 
not clearly put. If he understands the question and yet it covers 
many senses, then supposing what it says to be universally true 



517 



or false, he should give it an unqualified assent or denial: if, on 
the other hand, it be partly true and partly false, he should add 
a comment that it bears different senses, and also that in one it 
is true, in the other false: for if he leave this distinction till later, 
it becomes uncertain whether originally as well he perceived 
the ambiguity or not. If he does not foresee the ambiguity, but 
assents to the question having in view the one sense of the 
words, then, if the questioner takes it in the other sense, he 
should say, 'That was not what I had in view when I admitted it; 
I meant the other sense': for if a term or expression covers more 
than one thing, it is easy to disagree. If, however, the question is 
both clear and simple, he should answer either 'Yes' or 'No'. 



8 

A premiss in reasoning always either is one of the constituent 
elements in the reasoning, or else goes to establish one of these: 
(and you can always tell when it is secured in order to establish 
something else by the fact of a number of similar questions 
being put: for as a rule people secure their universal by means 
either of induction or of likeness): - accordingly the particular 
propositions should all be admitted, if they are true and 
generally held. On the other hand, against the universal one 
should try to bring some negative instance; for to bring the 
argument to a standstill without a negative instance, either real 
or apparent, shows ill-temper. If, then, a man refuses to grant 
the universal when supported by many instances, although he 
has no negative instance to show, he obviously shows ill- 
temper. If, moreover, he cannot even attempt a counter-proof 
that it is not true, far more likely is he to be thought ill- 
tempered - although even counter-proof is not enough: for we 
often hear arguments that are contrary to common opinions, 



518 



whose solution is yet difficult, e.g. the argument of Zeno that it 
is impossible to move or to traverse the stadium; - but still, this 
is no reason for omitting to assert the opposites of these views. 
If, then, a man refuses to admit the proposition without having 
either a negative instance or some counter-argument to bring 
against it, clearly he is ill-tempered: for ill-temper in argument 
consists in answering in ways other than the above, so as to 
wreck the reasoning. 



Before maintaining either a thesis or a definition the answerer 
should try his hand at attacking it by himself; for clearly his 
business is to oppose those positions from which questioners 
demolish what he has laid down. 

He should beware of maintaining a hypothesis that is generally 
rejected: and this it may be in two ways: for it may be one 
which results in absurd statements, e.g. suppose any one were 
to say that everything is in motion or that nothing is; and also 
there are all those which only a bad character would choose, 
and which are implicitly opposed to men's wishes, e.g. that 
pleasure is the good, and that to do injustice is better than to 
suffer it. For people then hate him, supposing him to maintain 
them not for the sake of argument but because he really thinks 
them. 

10 

Of all arguments that reason to a false conclusion the right 
solution is to demolish the point on which the fallacy that 
occurs depends: for the demolition of any random point is no 
solution, even though the point demolished be false. For the 



519 



argument may contain many falsehoods, e.g. suppose some one 
to secure the premisses, 'He who sits, writes' and 'Socrates is 
sitting': for from these it follows that 'Socrates is writing'. Now 
we may demolish the proposition 'Socrates is sitting', and still 
be no nearer a solution of the argument; it may be true that the 
point claimed is false; but it is not on that that fallacy of the 
argument depends: for supposing that any one should happen 
to be sitting and not writing, it would be impossible in such a 
case to apply the same solution. Accordingly, it is not this that 
needs to be demolished, but rather that 'He who sits, writes': for 
he who sits does not always write. He, then, who has 
demolished the point on which the fallacy depends, has given 
the solution of the argument completely. Any one who knows 
that it is on such and such a point that the argument depends, 
knows the solution of it, just as in the case of a figure falsely 
drawn. For it is not enough to object, even if the point 
demolished be a falsehood, but the reason of the fallacy should 
also be proved: for then it would be clear whether the man 
makes his objection with his eyes open or not. 

There are four possible ways of preventing a man from working 
his argument to a conclusion. It can be done either by 
demolishing the point on which the falsehood that comes about 
depends, or by stating an objection directed against the 
questioner: for often when a solution has not as a matter of fact 
been brought, yet the questioner is rendered thereby unable to 
pursue the argument any farther. Thirdly, one may object to the 
questions asked: for it may happen that what the questioner 
wants does not follow from the questions he has asked because 
he has asked them badly, whereas if something additional be 
granted the conclusion comes about. If, then, the questioner be 
unable to pursue his argument farther, the objection would 
properly be directed against the questioner; if he can do so, then 
it would be against his questions. The fourth and worst kind of 
objection is that which is directed to the time allowed for 



520 



discussion: for some people bring objections of a kind which 
would take longer to answer than the length of the discussion 
in hand. 

There are then, as we said, four ways of making objections: but 
of them the first alone is a solution: the others are just 
hindrances and stumbling-blocks to prevent the conclusions. 



11 

Adverse criticism of an argument on its own merits, and of it 
when presented in the form of questions, are two different 
things. For often the failure to carry through the argument 
correctly in discussion is due to the person questioned, because 
he will not grant the steps of which a correct argument might 
have been made against his position: for it is not in the power of 
the one side only to effect properly a result that depends on 
both alike. Accordingly it sometimes becomes necessary to 
attack the speaker and not his position, when the answerer lies 
in wait for the points that are contrary to the questioner and 
becomes abusive as well: when people lose their tempers in this 
way, their argument becomes a contest, not a discussion. 
Moreover, since arguments of this kind are held not for the sake 
of instruction but for purposes of practice and examination, 
clearly one has to reason not only to true conclusions, but also 
to false ones, and not always through true premisses, but 
sometimes through false as well. For often, when a true 
proposition is put forward, the dialectician is compelled to 
demolish it: and then false propositions have to be formulated. 
Sometimes also when a false proposition is put forward, it has 
to be demolished by means of false propositions: for it is 
possible for a given man to believe what is not the fact more 



521 



firmly than the truth. Accordingly, if the argument be made to 
depend on something that he holds, it will be easier to persuade 
or help him. He, however, who would rightly convert any one to 
a different opinion should do so in a dialectical and not in a 
contentious manner, just as a geometrician should reason 
geometrically, whether his conclusion be false or true: what 
kind of syllogisms are dialectical has already been said. The 
principle that a man who hinders the common business is a 
bad partner, clearly applies to an argument as well; for in 
arguments as well there is a common aim in view, except with 
mere contestants, for these cannot both reach the same goal; 
for more than one cannot possibly win. It makes no difference 
whether he effects this as answerer or as questioner: for both 
he who asks contentious questions is a bad dialectician, and 
also he who in answering fails to grant the obvious answer or to 
understand the point of the questioner's inquiry. What has been 
said, then, makes it clear that adverse criticism is not to be 
passed in a like strain upon the argument on its own merits, 
and upon the questioner: for it may very well be that the 
argument is bad, but that the questioner has argued with the 
answerer in the best possible way: for when men lose their 
tempers, it may perhaps be impossible to make one's inferences 
straight-forwardly as one would wish: we have to do as we can. 

Inasmuch as it is indeterminate when people are claiming the 
admission of contrary things, and when they are claiming what 
originally they set out to prove - for often when they are talking 
by themselves they say contrary things, and admit afterwards 
what they have previously denied; for which reason they often 
assent, when questioned, to contrary things and to what 
originally had to be proved - the argument is sure to become 
vitiated. The responsibility, however, for this rests with the 
answerer, because while refusing to grant other points, he does 
grant points of that kind. It is, then, clear that adverse criticism 



522 



is not to be passed in a like manner upon questioners and upon 
their arguments. 

In itself an argument is liable to five kinds of adverse criticism: 

(1) The first is when neither the proposed conclusion nor indeed 
any conclusion at all is drawn from the questions asked, and 
when most, if not all, of the premisses on which the conclusion 
rests are false or generally rejected, when, moreover, neither 
any withdrawals nor additions nor both together can bring the 
conclusions about. 

(2) The second is, supposing the reasoning, though constructed 
from the premisses, and in the manner, described above, were 
to be irrelevant to the original position. 

(3) The third is, supposing certain additions would bring an 
inference about but yet these additions were to be weaker than 
those that were put as questions and less generally held than 
the conclusion. 

(4) Again, supposing certain withdrawals could effect the same: 
for sometimes people secure more premisses than are 
necessary, so that it is not through them that the inference 
comes about. 

(5) Moreover, suppose the premisses be less generally held and 
less credible than the conclusion, or if, though true, they require 
more trouble to prove than the proposed view. 

One must not claim that the reasoning to a proposed view shall 
in every case equally be a view generally accepted and 
convincing: for it is a direct result of the nature of things that 
some subjects of inquiry shall be easier and some harder, so 
that if a man brings people to accept his point from opinions 
that are as generally received as the case admits, he has argued 
his case correctly. Clearly, then, not even the argument itself is 



523 



open to the same adverse criticism when taken in relation to 
the proposed conclusion and when taken by itself. For there is 
nothing to prevent the argument being open to reproach in 
itself, and yet commendable in relation to the proposed 
conclusion, or again, vice versa, being commendable in itself, 
and yet open to reproach in relation to the proposed conclusion, 
whenever there are many propositions both generally held and 
also true whereby it could easily be proved. It is possible also 
that an argument, even though brought to a conclusion, may 
sometimes be worse than one which is not so concluded, 
whenever the premisses of the former are silly, while its 
conclusion is not so; whereas the latter, though requiring 
certain additions, requires only such as are generally held and 
true, and moreover does not rest as an argument on these 
additions. With those which bring about a true conclusion by 
means of false premisses, it is not fair to find fault: for a false 
conclusion must of necessity always be reached from a false 
premiss, but a true conclusion may sometimes be drawn even 
from false premisses; as is clear from the Analytics. 

Whenever by the argument stated something is demonstrated, 
but that something is other than what is wanted and has no 
bearing whatever on the conclusion, then no inference as to the 
latter can be drawn from it: and if there appears to be, it will be 
a sophism, not a proof. A philosopheme is a demonstrative 
inference: an epichireme is a dialectical inference: a sophism is 
a contentious inference: an aporeme is an inference that 
reasons dialectically to a contradiction. 

If something were to be shown from premisses, both of which 
are views generally accepted, but not accepted with like 
conviction, it may very well be that the conclusion shown is 
something held more strongly than either. If, on the other hand, 
general opinion be for the one and neither for nor against the 
other, or if it be for the one and against the other, then, if the 



524 



pro and con be alike in the case of the premisses, they will be 
alike for the conclusion also: if, on the other hand, the one 
preponderates, the conclusion too will follow suit. 

It is also a fault in reasoning when a man shows something 
through a long chain of steps, when he might employ fewer 
steps and those already included in his argument: suppose him 
to be showing (e.g.) that one opinion is more properly so called 
than another, and suppose him to make his postulates as 
follows: 'x-in-itself is more fully x than anything else': 'there 
genuinely exists an object of opinion in itself: therefore 'the 
object-of-opinion-in-itself is more fully an object of opinion 
than the particular objects of opinion'. Now 'a relative term is 
more fully itself when its correlate is more fully itself: and 
'there exists a genuine opinion-in-itself, which will be «opinion» 
in a more accurate sense than the particular opinions': and it 
has been postulated both that 'a genuine opinion-in-itself 
exists', and that 'x-in-itself is more fully x than anything else': 
therefore 'this will be opinion in a more accurate sense'. 
Wherein lies the viciousness of the reasoning? Simply in that it 
conceals the ground on which the argument depends. 



12 

An argument is clear in one, and that the most ordinary, sense, 
if it be so brought to a conclusion as to make no further 
questions necessary: in another sense, and this is the type most 
usually advanced, when the propositions secured are such as 
compel the conclusion, and the argument is concluded through 
premisses that are themselves conclusions: moreover, it is so 
also if some step is omitted that generally is firmly accepted. 



525 



An argument is called fallacious in four senses: (1) when it 
appears to be brought to a conclusion, and is not really so - 
what is called 'contentious' reasoning: (2) when it comes to a 
conclusion but not to the conclusion proposed - which happens 
principally in the case of reductiones ad impossibile: (3) when it 
comes to the proposed conclusion but not according to the 
mode of inquiry appropriate to the case, as happens when a 
non-medical argument is taken to be a medical one, or one 
which is not geometrical for a geometrical argument, or one 
which is not dialectical for dialectical, whether the result 
reached be true or false: (4) if the conclusion be reached through 
false premisses: of this type the conclusion is sometimes false, 
sometimes true: for while a false conclusion is always the result 
of false premisses, a true conclusion may be drawn even from 
premisses that are not true, as was said above as well. 

Fallacy in argument is due to a mistake of the arguer rather 
than of the argument: yet it is not always the fault of the arguer 
either, but only when he is not aware of it: for we often accept 
on its merits in preference to many true ones an argument 
which demolishes some true proposition if it does so from 
premisses as far as possible generally accepted. For an 
argument of that kind does demonstrate other things that are 
true: for one of the premisses laid down ought never to be there 
at all, and this will then be demonstrated. If, however, a true 
conclusion were to be reached through premisses that are false 
and utterly childish, the argument is worse than many 
arguments that lead to a false conclusion, though an argument 
which leads to a false conclusion may also be of this type. 
Clearly then the first thing to ask in regard to the argument in 
itself is, 'Has it a conclusion?'; the second, 'Is the conclusion 
true or false?'; the third, 'Of what kind of premisses does it 
consist?': for if the latter, though false, be generally accepted, 
the argument is dialectical, whereas if, though true, they be 
generally rejected, it is bad: if they be both false and also 



526 



entirely contrary to general opinion, clearly it is bad, either 
altogether or else in relation to the particular matter in hand. 



13 

Of the ways in which a questioner may beg the original 
question and also beg contraries the true account has been 
given in the Analytics:' but an account on the level of general 
opinion must be given now. 

People appear to beg their original question in five ways: the 
first and most obvious being if any one begs the actual point 
requiring to be shown: this is easily detected when put in so 
many words; but it is more apt to escape detection in the case 
of different terms, or a term and an expression, that mean the 
same thing. A second way occurs whenever any one begs 
universally something which he has to demonstrate in a 
particular case: suppose (e.g.) he were trying to prove that the 
knowledge of contraries is one and were to claim that the 
knowledge of opposites in general is one: for then he is 
generally thought to be begging, along with a number of other 
things, that which he ought to have shown by itself. A third way 
is if any one were to beg in particular cases what he undertakes 
to show universally: e.g. if he undertook to show that the 
knowledge of contraries is always one, and begged it of certain 
pairs of contraries: for he also is generally considered to be 
begging independently and by itself what, together with a 
number of other things, he ought to have shown. Again, a man 
begs the question if he begs his conclusion piecemeal: 
supposing e.g. that he had to show that medicine is a science of 
what leads to health and to disease, and were to claim first the 
one, then the other; or, fifthly, if he were to beg the one or the 



527 



other of a pair of statements that necessarily involve one other; 
e.g. if he had to show that the diagonal is incommensurable 
with the side, and were to beg that the side is incommensurable 
with the diagonal. 

The ways in which people assume contraries are equal in 
number to those in which they beg their original question. For it 
would happen, firstly, if any one were to beg an opposite 
affirmation and negation; secondly, if he were to beg the 
contrary terms of an antithesis, e.g. that the same thing is good 
and evil; thirdly, suppose any one were to claim something 
universally and then proceed to beg its contradictory in some 
particular case, e.g. if having secured that the knowledge of 
contraries is one, he were to claim that the knowledge of what 
makes for health or for disease is different; or, fourthly, suppose 
him, after postulating the latter view, to try to secure universally 
the contradictory statement. Again, fifthly, suppose a man begs 
the contrary of the conclusion which necessarily comes about 
through the premisses laid down; and this would happen 
suppose, even without begging the opposites in so many words, 
he were to beg two premisses such that this contradictory 
statement that is opposite to the first conclusion will follow 
from them. The securing of contraries differs from begging the 
original question in this way: in the latter case the mistake lies 
in regard to the conclusion; for it is by a glance at the 
conclusion that we tell that the original question has been 
begged: whereas contrary views lie in the premisses, viz. in a 
certain relation which they bear to one another. 



528 



14 

The best way to secure training and practice in arguments of 
this kind is in the first place to get into the habit of converting 
the arguments. For in this way we shall be better equipped for 
dealing with the proposition stated, and after a few attempts we 
shall know several arguments by heart. For by 'conversion' of an 
argument is meant the taking the reverse of the conclusion 
together with the remaining propositions asked and so 
demolishing one of those that were conceded: for it follows 
necessarily that if the conclusion be untrue, some one of the 
premisses is demolished, seeing that, given all the premisses, 
the conclusion was bound to follow. Always, in dealing with any 
proposition, be on the look-out for a line of argument both pro 
and con: and on discovering it at once set about looking for the 
solution of it: for in this way you will soon find that you have 
trained yourself at the same time in both asking questions and 
answering them. If we cannot find any one else to argue with, 
we should argue with ourselves. Select, moreover, arguments 
relating to the same thesis and range them side by side: for this 
produces a plentiful supply of arguments for carrying a point by 
sheer force, and in refutation also it is of great service, 
whenever one is well stocked with arguments pro and con: for 
then you find yourself on your guard against contrary 
statements to the one you wish to secure. Moreover, as 
contributing to knowledge and to philosophic wisdom the 
power of discerning and holding in one view the results of 
either of two hypotheses is no mean instrument; for it then 
only remains to make a right choice of one of them. For a task of 
this kind a certain natural ability is required: in fact real natural 
ability just is the power right to choose the true and shun the 
false. Men of natural ability can do this; for by a right liking or 
disliking for whatever is proposed to them they rightly select 
what is best. 



529 



It is best to know by heart arguments upon those questions 
which are of most frequent occurrence, and particularly in 
regard to those propositions which are ultimate: for in 
discussing these answerers frequently give up in despair. 
Moreover, get a good stock of definitions: and have those of 
familiar and primary ideas at your fingers' ends: for it is 
through these that reasonings are effected. You should try, 
moreover, to master the heads under which other arguments 
mostly tend to fall. For just as in geometry it is useful to be 
practised in the elements, and in arithmetic to have the 
multiplication table up to ten at one's fingers' ends - and indeed 
it makes a great difference in one's knowledge of the multiples 
of other numbers too - likewise also in arguments it is a great 
advantage to be well up in regard to first principles, and to have 
a thorough knowledge of premisses at the tip of one's tongue. 
For just as in a person with a trained memory, a memory of 
things themselves is immediately caused by the mere mention 
of their loci, so these habits too will make a man readier in 
reasoning, because he has his premisses classified before his 
mind's eye, each under its number. It is better to commit to 
memory a premiss of general application than an argument: for 
it is difficult to be even moderately ready with a first principle, 
or hypothesis. 

Moreover, you should get into the habit of turning one 
argument into several, and conceal your procedure as darkly as 
you can: this kind of effect is best produced by keeping as far as 
possible away from topics akin to the subject of the argument. 
This can be done with arguments that are entirely universal, e.g. 
the statement that 'there cannot be one knowledge of more 
than one thing': for that is the case with both relative terms and 
contraries and co-ordinates. 

Records of discussions should be made in a universal form, 
even though one has argued only some particular case: for this 



530 



will enable one to turn a single rule into several. A like rule 
applies in Rhetoric as well to enthymemes. For yourself, 
however, you should as far as possible avoid universalizing your 
reasonings. You should, moreover, always examine arguments 
to see whether they rest on principles of general application: for 
all particular arguments really reason universally, as well, i.e. a 
particular demonstration always contains a universal 
demonstration, because it is impossible to reason at all without 
using universals. 

You should display your training in inductive reasoning against 
a young man, in deductive against an expert. You should try, 
moreover, to secure from those skilled in deduction their 
premisses, from inductive reasoners their parallel cases; for this 
is the thing in which they are respectively trained. In general, 
too, from your exercises in argumentation you should try to 
carry away either a syllogism on some subject or a refutation or 
a proposition or an objection, or whether some one put his 
question properly or improperly (whether it was yourself or 
some one else) and the point which made it the one or the 
other. For this is what gives one ability, and the whole object of 
training is to acquire ability, especially in regard to propositions 
and objections. For it is the skilled propounder and objector 
who is, speaking generally, a dialectician. To formulate a 
proposition is to form a number of things into one - for the 
conclusion to which the argument leads must be taken 
generally, as a single thing - whereas to formulate an objection 
is to make one thing into many; for the objector either 
distinguishes or demolishes, partly granting, partly denying the 
statements proposed. 

Do not argue with every one, nor practise upon the man in the 
street: for there are some people with whom any argument is 
bound to degenerate. For against any one who is ready to try all 
means in order to seem not to be beaten, it is indeed fair to try 



531 



all means of bringing about one's conclusion: but it is not good 
form. Wherefore the best rule is, not lightly to engage with 
casual acquaintances, or bad argument is sure to result. For you 
see how in practising together people cannot refrain from 
contentious argument. 

It is best also to have ready-made arguments relating to those 
questions in which a very small stock will furnish us with 
arguments serviceable on a very large number of occasions. 
These are those that are universal, and those in regard to which 
it is rather difficult to produce points for ourselves from matters 
of everyday experience. 



532 



Aristotle - On Sophistical Refutations 
[Translated by W. A. Pickard-Cambridge] 



Let us now discuss sophistic refutations, i.e. what appear to be 
refutations but are really fallacies instead. We will begin in the 
natural order with the first. 

That some reasonings are genuine, while others seem to be so 
but are not, is evident. This happens with arguments, as also 
elsewhere, through a certain likeness between the genuine and 
the sham. For physically some people are in a vigorous 
condition, while others merely seem to be so by blowing and 
rigging themselves out as the tribesmen do their victims for 
sacrifice; and some people are beautiful thanks to their beauty, 
while others seem to be so, by dint of embellishing themselves. 
So it is, too, with inanimate things; for of these, too, some are 
really silver and others gold, while others are not and merely 
seem to be such to our sense; e.g. things made of litharge and 
tin seem to be of silver, while those made of yellow metal look 
golden. In the same way both reasoning and refutation are 
sometimes genuine, sometimes not, though inexperience may 
make them appear so: for inexperienced people obtain only, as 
it were, a distant view of these things. For reasoning rests on 
certain statements such that they involve necessarily the 
assertion of something other than what has been stated, 
through what has been stated: refutation is reasoning involving 
the contradictory of the given conclusion. Now some of them do 
not really achieve this, though they seem to do so for a number 
of reasons; and of these the most prolific and usual domain is 



533 



the argument that turns upon names only. It is impossible in a 
discussion to bring in the actual things discussed: we use their 
names as symbols instead of them; and therefore we suppose 
that what follows in the names, follows in the things as well, 
just as people who calculate suppose in regard to their counters. 
But the two cases (names and things) are not alike. For names 
are finite and so is the sum-total of formulae, while things are 
infinite in number. Inevitably, then, the same formulae, and a 
single name, have a number of meanings. Accordingly just as, in 
counting, those who are not clever in manipulating their 
counters are taken in by the experts, in the same way in 
arguments too those who are not well acquainted with the force 
of names misreason both in their own discussions and when 
they listen to others. For this reason, then, and for others to be 
mentioned later, there exists both reasoning and refutation that 
is apparent but not real. Now for some people it is better worth 
while to seem to be wise, than to be wise without seeming to be 
(for the art of the sophist is the semblance of wisdom without 
the reality, and the sophist is one who makes money from an 
apparent but unreal wisdom); for them, then, it is clearly 
essential also to seem to accomplish the task of a wise man 
rather than to accomplish it without seeming to do so. To 
reduce it to a single point of contrast it is the business of one 
who knows a thing, himself to avoid fallacies in the subjects 
which he knows and to be able to show up the man who makes 
them; and of these accomplishments the one depends on the 
faculty to render an answer, and the other upon the securing of 
one. Those, then, who would be sophists are bound to study the 
class of arguments aforesaid: for it is worth their while: for a 
faculty of this kind will make a man seem to be wise, and this is 
the purpose they happen to have in view. 

Clearly, then, there exists a class of arguments of this kind, and 
it is at this kind of ability that those aim whom we call sophists. 
Let us now go on to discuss how many kinds there are of 



534 



sophistical arguments, and how many in number are the 
elements of which this faculty is composed, and how many 
branches there happen to be of this inquiry, and the other 
factors that contribute to this art. 



Of arguments in dialogue form there are four classes: 

Didactic, Dialectical, Examination-arguments, and Contentious 
arguments. Didactic arguments are those that reason from the 
principles appropriate to each subject and not from the 
opinions held by the answerer (for the learner should take 
things on trust): dialectical arguments are those that reason 
from premisses generally accepted, to the contradictory of a 
given thesis: examination-arguments are those that reason 
from premisses which are accepted by the answerer and which 
any one who pretends to possess knowledge of the subject is 
bound to know-in what manner, has been defined in another 
treatise: contentious arguments are those that reason or appear 
to reason to a conclusion from premisses that appear to be 
generally accepted but are not so. The subject, then, of 
demonstrative arguments has been discussed in the Analytics, 
while that of dialectic arguments and examination-arguments 
has been discussed elsewhere: let us now proceed to speak of 
the arguments used in competitions and contests. 



535 



First we must grasp the number of aims entertained by those 
who argue as competitors and rivals to the death. These are five 
in number, refutation, fallacy, paradox, solecism, and fifthly to 
reduce the opponent in the discussion to babbling - i.e. to 
constrain him to repeat himself a number of times: or it is to 
produce the appearance of each of these things without the 
reality. For they choose if possible plainly to refute the other 
party, or as the second best to show that he is committing some 
fallacy, or as a third best to lead him into paradox, or fourthly to 
reduce him to solecism, i.e. to make the answerer, in 
consequence of the argument, to use an ungrammatical 
expression; or, as a last resort, to make him repeat himself. 



There are two styles of refutation: for some depend on the 
language used, while some are independent of language. Those 
ways of producing the false appearance of an argument which 
depend on language are six in number: they are ambiguity, 
amphiboly, combination, division of words, accent, form of 
expression. Of this we may assure ourselves both by induction, 
and by syllogistic proof based on this - and it may be on other 
assumptions as well - that this is the number of ways in which 
we might fall to mean the same thing by the same names or 
expressions. Arguments such as the following depend upon 
ambiguity. 'Those learn who know: for it is those who know 
their letters who learn the letters dictated to them'. For to 
'learn' is ambiguous; it signifies both 'to understand' by the use 
of knowledge, and also 'to acquire knowledge'. Again, 'Evils are 
good: for what needs to be is good, and evils must needs be'. For 



536 



'what needs to be' has a double meaning: it means what is 
inevitable, as often is the case with evils, too (for evil of some 
kind is inevitable), while on the other hand we say of good 
things as well that they 'need to be'. Moreover, 'The same man 
is both seated and standing and he is both sick and in health: 
for it is he who stood up who is standing, and he who is 
recovering who is in health: but it is the seated man who stood 
up, and the sick man who was recovering'. For 'The sick man 
does so and so', or 'has so and so done to him' is not single in 
meaning: sometimes it means 'the man who is sick or is seated 
now', sometimes 'the man who was sick formerly'. Of course, 
the man who was recovering was the sick man, who really was 
sick at the time: but the man who is in health is not sick at the 
same time: he is 'the sick man' in the sense not that he is sick 
now, but that he was sick formerly. Examples such as the 
following depend upon amphiboly: 'I wish that you the enemy 
may capture'. Also the thesis, 'There must be knowledge of 
what one knows': for it is possible by this phrase to mean that 
knowledge belongs to both the knower and the known. Also, 
'There must be sight of what one sees: one sees the pillar: ergo 
the pillar has sight'. Also, 'What you profess to-be, that you 
profess to-be: you profess a stone to-be: ergo you profess-to-be 
a stone'. Also, 'Speaking of the silent is possible': for 'speaking of 
the silent' also has a double meaning: it may mean that the 
speaker is silent or that the things of which he speaks are so. 
There are three varieties of these ambiguities and amphibolies: 
(1) When either the expression or the name has strictly more 
than one meaning, e.g. aetos and the 'dog'; (2) when by custom 
we use them so; (3) when words that have a simple sense taken 
alone have more than one meaning in combination; e.g. 
'knowing letters'. For each word, both 'knowing' and 'letters', 
possibly has a single meaning: but both together have more 
than one - either that the letters themselves have knowledge or 
that someone else has it of them. 



537 



Amphiboly and ambiguity, then, depend on these modes of 
speech. Upon the combination of words there depend instances 
such as the following: 'A man can walk while sitting, and can 
write while not writing'. For the meaning is not the same if one 
divides the words and if one combines them in saying that 'it is 
possible to walk-while-sitting' and write while not writing. The 
same applies to the latter phrase, too, if one combines the 
words 'to write-while-not-writing': for then it means that he has 
the power to write and not to write at once; whereas if one does 
not combine them, it means that when he is not writing he has 
the power to write. Also, 'He now if he has learnt his letters'. 
Moreover, there is the saying that 'One single thing if you can 
carry a crowd you can carry too'. 

Upon division depend the propositions that 5 is 2 and 3, and 
odd, and that the greater is equal: for it is that amount and 
more besides. For the same phrase would not be thought always 
to have the same meaning when divided and when combined, 
e.g. 'I made thee a slave once a free man', and 'God-like Achilles 
left fifty a hundred men'. 

An argument depending upon accent it is not easy to construct 
in unwritten discussion; in written discussions and in poetry it 
is easier. Thus (e.g.) some people emend Homer against those 
who criticize as unnatural his expression to men ou 
kataputhetai ombro. For they solve the difficulty by a change of 
accent, pronouncing the ou with an acuter accent. Also, in the 
passage about Agamemnon's dream, they say that Zeus did not 
himself say 'We grant him the fulfilment of his prayer', but that 
he bade the dream grant it. Instances such as these, then, turn 
upon the accentuation. 

Others come about owing to the form of expression used, when 
what is really different is expressed in the same form, e.g. a 
masculine thing by a feminine termination, or a feminine thing 



538 



by a masculine, or a neuter by either a masculine or a feminine; 
or, again, when a quality is expressed by a termination proper to 
quantity or vice versa, or what is active by a passive word, or a 
state by an active word, and so forth with the other divisions 
previously' laid down. For it is possible to use an expression to 
denote what does not belong to the class of actions at all as 
though it did so belong. Thus (e.g.) 'flourishing' is a word which 
in the form of its expression is like 'cutting' or 'building': yet the 
one denotes a certain quality - i.e. a certain condition - while 
the other denotes a certain action. In the same manner also in 
the other instances. 

Refutations, then, that depend upon language are drawn from 
these common-place rules. Of fallacies, on the other hand, that 
are independent of language there are seven kinds: 

(1) that which depends upon Accident: 

(2) the use of an expression absolutely or not absolutely but 
with some qualification of respect or place, or time, or relation: 

(3) that which depends upon ignorance of what 'refutation' is: 

(4) that which depends upon the consequent: 

(5) that which depends upon assuming the original conclusion: 

(6) stating as cause what is not the cause: 

(7) the making of more than one question into one. 



Fallacies, then, that depend on Accident occur whenever any 
attribute is claimed to belong in like manner to a thing and to 



539 



its accident. For since the same thing has many accidents there 
is no necessity that all the same attributes should belong to all 
of a thing's predicates and to their subject as well. Thus (e.g.), 'If 
Coriscus be different from «man», he is different from himself: 
for he is a man': or 'If he be different from Socrates, and 
Socrates be a man, then', they say, 'he has admitted that 
Coriscus is different from a man, because it so happens (accidit) 
that the person from whom he said that he (Coriscus) is 
different is a man'. 

Those that depend on whether an expression is used absolutely 
or in a certain respect and not strictly, occur whenever an 
expression used in a particular sense is taken as though it were 
used absolutely, e.g. in the argument 'If what is not is the object 
of an opinion, then what is not is': for it is not the same thing 
'to be x' and 'to be' absolutely. Or again, 'What is, is not, if it is 
not a particular kind of being, e.g. if it is not a man.' For it is not 
the same thing 'not to be x' and 'not to be' at all: it looks as if it 
were, because of the closeness of the expression, i.e. because 'to 
be x' is but little different from 'to be', and 'not to be x' from 'not 
to be'. Likewise also with any argument that turns upon the 
point whether an expression is used in a certain respect or used 
absolutely. Thus e.g. 'Suppose an Indian to be black all over, but 
white in respect of his teeth; then he is both white and not 
white.' Or if both characters belong in a particular respect, then, 
they say, 'contrary attributes belong at the same time'. This kind 
of thing is in some cases easily seen by any one, e.g. suppose a 
man were to secure the statement that the Ethiopian is black, 
and were then to ask whether he is white in respect of his 
teeth; and then, if he be white in that respect, were to suppose 
at the conclusion of his questions that therefore he had proved 
dialectically that he was both white and not white. But in some 
cases it often passes undetected, viz. in all cases where, 
whenever a statement is made of something in a certain 
respect, it would be generally thought that the absolute 



540 



statement follows as well; and also in all cases where it is not 
easy to see which of the attributes ought to be rendered strictly. 
A situation of this kind arises, where both the opposite 
attributes belong alike: for then there is general support for the 
view that one must agree absolutely to the assertion of both, or 
of neither: e.g. if a thing is half white and half black, is it white 
or black? 

Other fallacies occur because the terms 'proof or 'refutation' 
have not been defined, and because something is left out in 
their definition. For to refute is to contradict one and the same 
attribute - not merely the name, but the reality - and a name 
that is not merely synonymous but the same name - and to 
confute it from the propositions granted, necessarily, without 
including in the reckoning the original point to be proved, in the 
same respect and relation and manner and time in which it was 
asserted. A 'false assertion' about anything has to be defined in 
the same way. Some people, however, omit some one of the said 
conditions and give a merely apparent refutation, showing (e.g.) 
that the same thing is both double and not double: for two is 
double of one, but not double of three. Or, it may be, they show 
that it is both double and not double of the same thing, but not 
that it is so in the same respect: for it is double in length but not 
double in breadth. Or, it may be, they show it to be both double 
and not double of the same thing and in the same respect and 
manner, but not that it is so at the same time: and therefore 
their refutation is merely apparent. One might, with some 
violence, bring this fallacy into the group of fallacies dependent 
on language as well. 

Those that depend on the assumption of the original point to be 
proved, occur in the same way, and in as many ways, as it is 
possible to beg the original point; they appear to refute because 
men lack the power to keep their eyes at once upon what is the 
same and what is different. 



541 



The refutation which depends upon the consequent arises 
because people suppose that the relation of consequence is 
convertible. For whenever, suppose A is, B necessarily is, they 
then suppose also that if B is, A necessarily is. This is also the 
source of the deceptions that attend opinions based on sense- 
perception. For people often suppose bile to be honey because 
honey is attended by a yellow colour: also, since after rain the 
ground is wet in consequence, we suppose that if the ground is 
wet, it has been raining; whereas that does not necessarily 
follow. In rhetoric proofs from signs are based on consequences. 
For when rhetoricians wish to show that a man is an adulterer, 
they take hold of some consequence of an adulterous life, viz. 
that the man is smartly dressed, or that he is observed to 
wander about at night. There are, however, many people of 
whom these things are true, while the charge in question is 
untrue. It happens like this also in real reasoning; e.g. Melissus' 
argument, that the universe is eternal, assumes that the 
universe has not come to be (for from what is not nothing could 
possibly come to be) and that what has come to be has done so 
from a first beginning. If, therefore, the universe has not come 
to be, it has no first beginning, and is therefore eternal. But this 
does not necessarily follow: for even if what has come to be 
always has a first beginning, it does not also follow that what 
has a first beginning has come to be; any more than it follows 
that if a man in a fever be hot, a man who is hot must be in a 
fever. 

The refutation which depends upon treating as cause what is 
not a cause, occurs whenever what is not a cause is inserted in 
the argument, as though the refutation depended upon it. This 
kind of thing happens in arguments that reason ad impossible: 
for in these we are bound to demolish one of the premisses. If, 
then, the false cause be reckoned in among the questions that 
are necessary to establish the resulting impossibility, it will 
often be thought that the refutation depends upon it, e.g. in the 



542 



proof that the 'soul' and 'life' are not the same: for if coming-to- 
be be contrary to perishing, then a particular form of perishing 
will have a particular form of coming-to-be as its contrary: now 
death is a particular form of perishing and is contrary to life: 
life, therefore, is a coming to-be, and to live is to come-to-be. But 
this is impossible: accordingly, the 'soul' and 'life' are not the 
same. Now this is not proved: for the impossibility results all 
the same, even if one does not say that life is the same as the 
soul, but merely says that life is contrary to death, which is a 
form of perishing, and that perishing has 'coming-to-be' as its 
contrary. Arguments of that kind, then, though not inconclusive 
absolutely, are inconclusive in relation to the proposed 
conclusion. Also even the questioners themselves often fail 
quite as much to see a point of that kind. 

Such, then, are the arguments that depend upon the 
consequent and upon false cause. Those that depend upon the 
making of two questions into one occur whenever the plurality 
is undetected and a single answer is returned as if to a single 
question. Now, in some cases, it is easy to see that there is more 
than one, and that an answer is not to be given, e.g. 'Does the 
earth consist of sea, or the sky?' But in some cases it is less 
easy, and then people treat the question as one, and either 
confess their defeat by failing to answer the question, or are 
exposed to an apparent refutation. Thus 'Is A and is B a man?' 
'Yes.' 'Then if any one hits A and B, he will strike a man' 
(singular), 'not men' (plural). Or again, where part is good and 
part bad, 'is the whole good or bad?' For whichever he says, it is 
possible that he might be thought to expose himself to an 
apparent refutation or to make an apparently false statement: 
for to say that something is good which is not good, or not good 
which is good, is to make a false statement. Sometimes, 
however, additional premisses may actually give rise to a 
genuine refutation; e.g. suppose a man were to grant that the 
descriptions 'white' and 'naked' and 'blind' apply to one thing 



543 



and to a number of things in a like sense. For if 'blind' describes 
a thing that cannot see though nature designed it to see, it will 
also describe things that cannot see though nature designed 
them to do so. Whenever, then, one thing can see while another 
cannot, they will either both be able to see or else both be blind; 
which is impossible. 



The right way, then, is either to divide apparent proofs and 
refutations as above, or else to refer them all to ignorance of 
what 'refutation' is, and make that our starting-point: for it is 
possible to analyse all the aforesaid modes of fallacy into 
breaches of the definition of a refutation. In the first place, we 
may see if they are inconclusive: for the conclusion ought to 
result from the premisses laid down, so as to compel us 
necessarily to state it and not merely to seem to compel us. 
Next we should also take the definition bit by bit, and try the 
fallacy thereby. For of the fallacies that consist in language, 
some depend upon a double meaning, e.g. ambiguity of words 
and of phrases, and the fallacy of like verbal forms (for we 
habitually speak of everything as though it were a particular 
substance) - while fallacies of combination and division and 
accent arise because the phrase in question or the term as 
altered is not the same as was intended. Even this, however, 
should be the same, just as the thing signified should be as well, 
if a refutation or proof is to be effected; e.g. if the point concerns 
a doublet, then you should draw the conclusion of a 'doublet', 
not of a 'cloak'. For the former conclusion also would be true, 
but it has not been proved; we need a further question to show 
that 'doublet' means the same thing, in order to satisfy any one 
who asks why you think your point proved. 



544 



Fallacies that depend on Accident are clear cases of ignoratio 
elenchi when once 'proof has been defined. For the same 
definition ought to hold good of 'refutation' too, except that a 
mention of 'the contradictory' is here added: for a refutation is a 
proof of the contradictory. If, then, there is no proof as regards 
an accident of anything, there is no refutation. For supposing, 
when A and B are, C must necessarily be, and C is white, there is 
no necessity for it to be white on account of the syllogism. So, if 
the triangle has its angles equal to two right-angles, and it 
happens to be a figure, or the simplest element or starting 
point, it is not because it is a figure or a starting point or 
simplest element that it has this character. For the 
demonstration proves the point about it not qua figure or qua 
simplest element, but qua triangle. Likewise also in other cases. 
If, then, refutation is a proof, an argument which argued per 
accidens could not be a refutation. It is, however, just in this 
that the experts and men of science generally suffer refutation 
at the hand of the unscientific: for the latter meet the scientists 
with reasonings constituted per accidens; and the scientists for 
lack of the power to draw distinctions either say 'Yes' to their 
questions, or else people suppose them to have said 'Yes', 
although they have not. 

Those that depend upon whether something is said in a certain 
respect only or said absolutely, are clear cases of ignoratio 
elenchi because the affirmation and the denial are not 
concerned with the same point. For of 'white in a certain 
respect' the negation is 'not white in a certain respect', while of 
'white absolutely' it is 'not white, absolutely'. If, then, a man 
treats the admission that a thing is 'white in a certain respect' 
as though it were said to be white absolutely, he does not effect 
a refutation, but merely appears to do so owing to ignorance of 
what refutation is. 



545 



The clearest cases of all, however, are those that were 
previously described' as depending upon the definition of a 
'refutation': and this is also why they were called by that name. 
For the appearance of a refutation is produced because of the 
omission in the definition, and if we divide fallacies in the 
above manner, we ought to set 'Defective definition' as a 
common mark upon them all. 

Those that depend upon the assumption of the original point 
and upon stating as the cause what is not the cause, are clearly 
shown to be cases of ignoratio elenchi through the definition 
thereof. For the conclusion ought to come about 'because these 
things are so', and this does not happen where the premisses 
are not causes of it: and again it should come about without 
taking into account the original point, and this is not the case 
with those arguments which depend upon begging the original 
point. 

Those that depend upon the assumption of the original point 
and upon stating as the cause what is not the cause, are clearly 
shown to be cases of ignoratio elenchi through the definition 
thereof. For the conclusion ought to come about 'because these 
things are so', and this does not happen where the premisses 
are not causes of it: and again it should come about without 
taking into account the original point, and this is not the case 
with those arguments which depend upon begging the original 
point. 

Those that depend upon the consequent are a branch of 
Accident: for the consequent is an accident, only it differs from 
the accident in this, that you may secure an admission of the 
accident in the case of one thing only (e.g. the identity of a 
yellow thing and honey and of a white thing and swan), 
whereas the consequent always involves more than one thing: 
for we claim that things that are the same as one and the same 



546 



thing are also the same as one another, and this is the ground of 
a refutation dependent on the consequent. It is, however, not 
always true, e.g. suppose that and B are the same as C per 
accidens; for both 'snow' and the 'swan' are the same as 
something white'. Or again, as in Melissus' argument, a man 
assumes that to 'have been generated' and to 'have a beginning' 
are the same thing, or to 'become equal' and to 'assume the 
same magnitude'. For because what has been generated has a 
beginning, he claims also that what has a beginning has been 
generated, and argues as though both what has been generated 
and what is finite were the same because each has a beginning. 
Likewise also in the case of things that are made equal he 
assumes that if things that assume one and the same 
magnitude become equal, then also things that become equal 
assume one magnitude: i.e. he assumes the consequent. 
Inasmuch, then, as a refutation depending on accident consists 
in ignorance of what a refutation is, clearly so also does a 
refutation depending on the consequent. We shall have further 
to examine this in another way as well. 

Those fallacies that depend upon the making of several 
questions into one consist in our failure to dissect the definition 
of 'proposition'. For a proposition is a single statement about a 
single thing. For the same definition applies to 'one single thing 
only' and to the 'thing', simply, e.g. to 'man' and to 'one single 
man only' and likewise also in other cases. If, then, a 'single 
proposition' be one which claims a single thing of a single thing, 
a 'proposition', simply, will also be the putting of a question of 
that kind. Now since a proof starts from propositions and 
refutation is a proof, refutation, too, will start from propositions. 
If, then, a proposition is a single statement about a single thing, 
it is obvious that this fallacy too consists in ignorance of what a 
refutation is: for in it what is not a proposition appears to be 
one. If, then, the answerer has returned an answer as though to 
a single question, there will be a refutation; while if he has 



547 



returned one not really but apparently, there will be an 
apparent refutation of his thesis. All the types of fallacy, then, 
fall under ignorance of what a refutation is, some of them 
because the contradiction, which is the distinctive mark of a 
refutation, is merely apparent, and the rest failing to conform to 
the definition of a proof. 



The deception comes about in the case of arguments that 
depend on ambiguity of words and of phrases because we are 
unable to divide the ambiguous term (for some terms it is not 
easy to divide, e.g. 'unity', 'being', and 'sameness'), while in 
those that depend on combination and division, it is because we 
suppose that it makes no difference whether the phrase be 
combined or divided, as is indeed the case with most phrases. 
Likewise also with those that depend on accent: for the 
lowering or raising of the voice upon a phrase is thought not to 
alter its meaning - with any phrase, or not with many. With 
those that depend on the of expression it is because of the 
likeness of expression. For it is hard to distinguish what kind of 
things are signified by the same and what by different kinds of 
expression: for a man who can do this is practically next door to 
the understanding of the truth. A special reason why a man is 
liable to be hurried into assent to the fallacy is that we suppose 
every predicate of everything to be an individual thing, and we 
understand it as being one with the thing: and we therefore 
treat it as a substance: for it is to that which is one with a thing 
or substance, as also to substance itself, that 'individually' and 
'being' are deemed to belong in the fullest sense. For this 
reason, too, this type of fallacy is to be ranked among those that 
depend on language; in the first place, because the deception is 



548 



effected the more readily when we are inquiring into a problem 
in company with others than when we do so by ourselves (for 
an inquiry with another person is carried on by means of 
speech, whereas an inquiry by oneself is carried on quite as 
much by means of the object itself); secondly a man is liable to 
be deceived, even when inquiring by himself, when he takes 
speech as the basis of his inquiry: moreover the deception 
arises out of the likeness (of two different things), and the 
likeness arises out of the language. With those fallacies that 
depend upon Accident, deception comes about because we 
cannot distinguish the sameness and otherness of terms, i.e. 
their unity and multiplicity, or what kinds of predicate have all 
the same accidents as their subject. Likewise also with those 
that depend on the Consequent: for the consequent is a branch 
of Accident. Moreover, in many cases appearances point to this 
- and the claim is made that if is inseparable from B, so also is B 
from With those that depend upon an imperfection in the 
definition of a refutation, and with those that depend upon the 
difference between a qualified and an absolute statement, the 
deception consists in the smallness of the difference involved; 
for we treat the limitation to the particular thing or respect or 
manner or time as adding nothing to the meaning, and so grant 
the statement universally. Likewise also in the case of those 
that assume the original point, and those of false cause, and all 
that treat a number of questions as one: for in all of them the 
deception lies in the smallness of the difference: for our failure 
to be quite exact in our definition of 'premiss' and of 'proof is 
due to the aforesaid reason. 



549 



8 

Since we know on how many points apparent syllogisms 
depend, we know also on how many sophistical syllogisms and 
refutations may depend. By a sophistical refutation and 
syllogism I mean not only a syllogism or refutation which 
appears to be valid but is not, but also one which, though it is 
valid, only appears to be appropriate to the thing in question. 
These are those which fail to refute and prove people to be 
ignorant according to the nature of the thing in question, which 
was the function of the art of examination. Now the art of 
examining is a branch of dialectic: and this may prove a false 
conclusion because of the ignorance of the answerer. Sophistic 
refutations on the other hand, even though they prove the 
contradictory of his thesis, do not make clear whether he is 
ignorant: for sophists entangle the scientist as well with these 
arguments. 

That we know them by the same line of inquiry is clear: for the 
same considerations which make it appear to an audience that 
the points required for the proof were asked in the questions 
and that the conclusion was proved, would make the answerer 
think so as well, so that false proof will occur through all or 
some of these means: for what a man has not been asked but 
thinks he has granted, he would also grant if he were asked. Of 
course, in some cases the moment we add the missing 
question, we also show up its falsity, e.g. in fallacies that depend 
on language and on solecism. If then, fallacious proofs of the 
contradictory of a thesis depend on their appearing to refute, it 
is clear that the considerations on which both proofs of false 
conclusions and an apparent refutation depend must be the 
same in number. Now an apparent refutation depends upon the 
elements involved in a genuine one: for the failure of one or 
other of these must make the refutation merely apparent, e.g. 
that which depends on the failure of the conclusion to follow 



550 



from the argument (the argument ad impossible) and that 
which treats two questions as one and so depends upon a flaw 
in the premiss, and that which depends on the substitution of 
an accident for an essential attribute, and - a branch of the last 
- that which depends upon the consequent: more over, the 
conclusion may follow not in fact but only verbally: then, 
instead of proving the contradictory universally and in the same 
respect and relation and manner, the fallacy may be dependent 
on some limit of extent or on one or other of these 
qualifications: moreover, there is the assumption of the original 
point to be proved, in violation of the clause 'without reckoning 
in the original point'. Thus we should have the number of 
considerations on which the fallacious proofs depend: for they 
could not depend on more, but all will depend on the points 
aforesaid. 

A sophistical refutation is a refutation not absolutely but 
relatively to some one: and so is a proof, in the same way. For 
unless that which depends upon ambiguity assumes that the 
ambiguous term has a single meaning, and that which depends 
on like verbal forms assumes that substance is the only 
category, and the rest in the same way, there will be neither 
refutations nor proofs, either absolutely or relatively to the 
answerer: whereas if they do assume these things, they will 
stand, relatively to the answerer; but absolutely they will not 
stand: for they have not secured a statement that does have a 
single meaning, but only one that appears to have, and that 
only from this particular man. 



551 



The number of considerations on which depend the refutations 
of those who are refuted, we ought not to try to grasp without a 
knowledge of everything that is. This, however, is not the 
province of any special study: for possibly the sciences are 
infinite in number, so that obviously demonstrations may be 
infinite too. Now refutations may be true as well as false: for 
whenever it is possible to demonstrate something, it is also 
possible to refute the man who maintains the contradictory of 
the truth; e.g. if a man has stated that the diagonal is 
commensurate with the side of the square, one might refute 
him by demonstrating that it is incommensurate. Accordingly, 
to exhaust all possible refutations we shall have to have 
scientific knowledge of everything: for some refutations depend 
upon the principles that rule in geometry and the conclusions 
that follow from these, others upon those that rule in medicine, 
and others upon those of the other sciences. For the matter of 
that, the false refutations likewise belong to the number of the 
infinite: for according to every art there is false proof, e.g. 
according to geometry there is false geometrical proof, and 
according to medicine there is false medical proof. By 'according 
to the art', I mean 'according to the principles of it'. Clearly, 
then, it is not of all refutations, but only of those that depend 
upon dialectic that we need to grasp the common-place rules: 
for these stand in a common relation to every art and faculty. 
And as regards the refutation that is according to one or other 
of the particular sciences it is the task of that particular 
scientist to examine whether it is merely apparent without 
being real, and, if it be real, what is the reason for it: whereas it 
is the business of dialecticians so to examine the refutation that 
proceeds from the common first principles that fall under no 
particular special study. For if we grasp the startingpoints of the 
accepted proofs on any subject whatever we grasp those of the 
refutations current on that subject. For a refutation is the proof 



552 



of the contradictory of a given thesis, so that either one or two 
proofs of the contradictory constitute a refutation. We grasp, 
then, the number of considerations on which all such depend: 
if, however, we grasp this, we also grasp their solutions as well; 
for the objections to these are the solutions of them. We also 
grasp the number of considerations on which those refutations 
depend, that are merely apparent - apparent, I mean, not to 
everybody, but to people of a certain stamp; for it is an 
indefinite task if one is to inquire how many are the 
considerations that make them apparent to the man in the 
street. Accordingly it is clear that the dialectician's business is 
to be able to grasp on how many considerations depends the 
formation, through the common first principles, of a refutation 
that is either real or apparent, i.e. either dialectical or 
apparently dialectical, or suitable for an examination. 



10 

It is no true distinction between arguments which some people 
draw when they say that some arguments are directed against 
the expression, and others against the thought expressed: for it 
is absurd to suppose that some arguments are directed against 
the expression and others against the thought, and that they 
are not the same. For what is failure to direct an argument 
against the thought except what occurs whenever a man does 
not in using the expression think it to be used in his question in 
the same sense in which the person questioned granted it? And 
this is the same thing as to direct the argument against the 
expression. On the other hand, it is directed against the thought 
whenever a man uses the expression in the same sense which 
the answerer had in mind when he granted it. If now any (i.e. 
both the questioner and the person questioned), in dealing with 



553 



an expression with more than one meaning, were to suppose it 
to have one meaning - as e.g. it may be that 'Being' and 'One' 
have many meanings, and yet both the answerer answers and 
the questioner puts his question supposing it to be one, and the 
argument is to the effect that 'All things are one' - will this 
discussion be directed any more against the expression than 
against the thought of the person questioned? If, on the other 
hand, one of them supposes the expression to have many 
meanings, it is clear that such a discussion will not be directed 
against the thought. Such being the meanings of the phrases in 
question, they clearly cannot describe two separate classes of 
argument. For, in the first place, it is possible for any such 
argument as bears more than one meaning to be directed 
against the expression and against the thought, and next it is 
possible for any argument whatsoever; for the fact of being 
directed against the thought consists not in the nature of the 
argument, but in the special attitude of the answerer towards 
the points he concedes. Next, all of them may be directed to the 
expression. For 'to be directed against the expression' means in 
this doctrine 'not to be directed against the thought'. For if not 
all are directed against either expression or thought, there will 
be certain other arguments directed neither against the 
expression nor against the thought, whereas they say that all 
must be one or the other, and divide them all as directed either 
against the expression or against the thought, while others 
(they say) there are none. But in point of fact those that depend 
on mere expression are only a branch of those syllogisms that 
depend on a multiplicity of meanings. For the absurd statement 
has actually been made that the description 'dependent on 
mere expression' describes all the arguments that depend on 
language: whereas some of these are fallacies not because the 
answerer adopts a particular attitude towards them, but 
because the argument itself involves the asking of a question 
such as bears more than one meaning. 



554 



It is, too, altogether absurd to discuss Refutation without first 
discussing Proof: for a refutation is a proof, so that one ought to 
discuss proof as well before describing false refutation: for a 
refutation of that kind is a merely apparent proof of the 
contradictory of a thesis. Accordingly, the reason of the falsity 
will be either in the proof or in the contradiction (for mention of 
the 'contradiction' must be added), while sometimes it is in 
both, if the refutation be merely apparent. In the argument that 
speaking of the silent is possible it lies in the contradiction, not 
in the proof; in the argument that one can give what one does 
not possess, it lies in both; in the proof that Homer's poem is a 
figure through its being a cycle it lies in the proof. An argument 
that does not fail in either respect is a true proof. 

But, to return to the point whence our argument digressed, are 
mathematical reasonings directed against the thought, or not? 
And if any one thinks 'triangle' to be a word with many 
meanings, and granted it in some different sense from the 
figure which was proved to contain two right angles, has the 
questioner here directed his argument against the thought of 
the former or not? 

Moreover, if the expression bears many senses, while the 
answerer does not understand or suppose it to have them, 
surely the questioner here has directed his argument against 
his thought! Or how else ought he to put his question except by 
suggesting a distinction - suppose one's question to be speaking 
of the silent possible or not? - as follows, 'Is the answer «No» in 
one sense, but «Yes» in another?' If, then, any one were to 
answer that it was not possible in any sense and the other were 
to argue that it was, has not his argument been directed against 
the thought of the answerer? Yet his argument is supposed to 
be one of those that depend on the expression. There is not, 
then, any definite kind of arguments that is directed against the 
thought. Some arguments are, indeed, directed against the 



555 



expression: but these are not all even apparent refutations, let 
alone all refutations. For there are also apparent refutations 
which do not depend upon language, e.g. those that depend 
upon accident, and others. 

If, however, any one claims that one should actually draw the 
distinction, and say, 'By «speaking of the silent» I mean, in one 
sense this and in the other sense that', surely to claim this is in 
the first place absurd (for sometimes the questioner does not 
see the ambiguity of his question, and he cannot possibly draw 
a distinction which he does not think to be there): in the second 
place, what else but this will didactic argument be? For it will 
make manifest the state of the case to one who has never 
considered, and does not know or suppose that there is any 
other meaning but one. For what is there to prevent the same 
thing also happening to us in cases where there is no double 
meaning? 'Are the units in four equal to the twos? Observe that 
the twos are contained in four in one sense in this way, in 
another sense in that'. Also, 'Is the knowledge of contraries one 
or not? Observe that some contraries are known, while others 
are unknown'. Thus the man who makes this claim seems to be 
unaware of the difference between didactic and dialectical 
argument, and of the fact that while he who argues didactically 
should not ask questions but make things clear himself, the 
other should merely ask questions. 



11 

Moreover, to claim a 'Yes' or 'No' answer is the business not of a 
man who is showing something, but of one who is holding an 
examination. For the art of examining is a branch of dialectic 
and has in view not the man who has knowledge, but the 



556 



ignorant pretender. He, then, is a dialectician who regards the 
common principles with their application to the particular 
matter in hand, while he who only appears to do this is a 
sophist. Now for contentious and sophistical reasoning: (1) one 
such is a merely apparent reasoning, on subjects on which 
dialectical reasoning is the proper method of examination, even 
though its conclusion be true: for it misleads us in regard to the 
cause: also (2) there are those misreasonings which do not 
conform to the line of inquiry proper to the particular subject, 
but are generally thought to conform to the art in question. For 
false diagrams of geometrical figures are not contentious (for 
the resulting fallacies conform to the subject of the art) - any 
more than is any false diagram that may be offered in proof of a 
truth - e.g. Hippocrates' figure or the squaring of the circle by 
means of the lunules. But Bryson's method of squaring the 
circle, even if the circle is thereby squared, is still sophistical 
because it does not conform to the subject in hand. So, then, 
any merely apparent reasoning about these things is a 
contentious argument, and any reasoning that merely appears 
to conform to the subject in hand, even though it be genuine 
reasoning, is a contentious argument: for it is merely apparent 
in its conformity to the subject-matter, so that it is deceptive 
and plays foul. For just as a foul in a race is a definite type of 
fault, and is a kind of foul fighting, so the art of contentious 
reasoning is foul fighting in disputation: for in the former case 
those who are resolved to win at all costs snatch at everything, 
and so in the latter case do contentious reasoners. Those, then, 
who do this in order to win the mere victory are generally 
considered to be contentious and quarrelsome persons, while 
those who do it to win a reputation with a view to making 
money are sophistical. For the art of sophistry is, as we said,' a 
kind of art of money-making from a merely apparent wisdom, 
and this is why they aim at a merely apparent demonstration: 
and quarrelsome persons and sophists both employ the same 



557 



arguments, but not with the same motives: and the same 
argument will be sophistical and contentious, but not in the 
same respect; rather, it will be contentious in so far as its aim is 
an apparent victory, while in so far as its aim is an apparent 
wisdom, it will be sophistical: for the art of sophistry is a certain 
appearance of wisdom without the reality. The contentious 
argument stands in somewhat the same relation to the 
dialectical as the drawer of false diagrams to the geometrician; 
for it beguiles by misreasoning from the same principles as 
dialectic uses, just as the drawer of a false diagram beguiles the 
geometrician. But whereas the latter is not a contentious 
reasoner, because he bases his false diagram on the principles 
and conclusions that fall under the art of geometry, the 
argument which is subordinate to the principles of dialectic will 
yet clearly be contentious as regards other subjects. Thus, e.g. 
though the squaring of the circle by means of the lunules is not 
contentious, Bryson's solution is contentious: and the former 
argument cannot be adapted to any subject except geometry, 
because it proceeds from principles that are peculiar to 
geometry, whereas the latter can be adapted as an argument 
against all the number of people who do not know what is or is 
not possible in each particular context: for it will apply to them 
all. Or there is the method whereby Antiphon squared the circle. 
Or again, an argument which denied that it was better to take a 
walk after dinner, because of Zeno's argument, would not be a 
proper argument for a doctor, because Zeno's argument is of 
general application. If, then, the relation of the contentious 
argument to the dialectical were exactly like that of the drawer 
of false diagrams to the geometrician, a contentious argument 
upon the aforesaid subjects could not have existed. But, as it is, 
the dialectical argument is not concerned with any definite kind 
of being, nor does it show anything, nor is it even an argument 
such as we find in the general philosophy of being. For all 
beings are not contained in any one kind, nor, if they were, 



558 



could they possibly fall under the same principles. Accordingly, 
no art that is a method of showing the nature of anything 
proceeds by asking questions: for it does not permit a man to 
grant whichever he likes of the two alternatives in the question: 
for they will not both of them yield a proof. Dialectic, on the 
other hand, does proceed by questioning, whereas if it were 
concerned to show things, it would have refrained from putting 
questions, even if not about everything, at least about the first 
principles and the special principles that apply to the particular 
subject in hand. For suppose the answerer not to grant these, it 
would then no longer have had any grounds from which to 
argue any longer against the objection. Dialectic is at the same 
time a mode of examination as well. For neither is the art of 
examination an accomplishment of the same kind as geometry, 
but one which a man may possess, even though he has not 
knowledge. For it is possible even for one without knowledge to 
hold an examination of one who is without knowledge, if also 
the latter grants him points taken not from thing that he knows 
or from the special principles of the subject under discussion 
but from all that range of consequences attaching to the subject 
which a man may indeed know without knowing the theory of 
the subject, but which if he do not know, he is bound to be 
ignorant of the theory. So then clearly the art of examining does 
not consist in knowledge of any definite subject. For this reason, 
too, it deals with everything: for every 'theory' of anything 
employs also certain common principles. Hence everybody, 
including even amateurs, makes use in a way of dialectic and 
the practice of examining: for all undertake to some extent a 
rough trial of those who profess to know things. What serves 
them here is the general principles: for they know these of 
themselves just as well as the scientist, even if in what they say 
they seem to the latter to go wildly astray from them. All, then, 
are engaged in refutation; for they take a hand as amateurs in 
the same task with which dialectic is concerned professionally; 



559 



and he is a dialectician who examines by the help of a theory of 
reasoning. Now there are many identical principles which are 
true of everything, though they are not such as to constitute a 
particular nature, i.e. a particular kind of being, but are like 
negative terms, while other principles are not of this kind but 
are special to particular subjects; accordingly it is possible from 
these general principles to hold an examination on everything, 
and that there should be a definite art of so doing, and, 
moreover, an art which is not of the same kind as those which 
demonstrate. This is why the contentious reasoner does not 
stand in the same condition in all respects as the drawer of a 
false diagram: for the contentious reasoner will not be given to 
misreasoning from any definite class of principles, but will deal 
with every class. 

These, then, are the types of sophistical refutations: and that it 
belongs to the dialectician to study these, and to be able to 
effect them, is not difficult to see: for the investigation of 
premisses comprises the whole of this study. 



12 

So much, then, for apparent refutations. As for showing that the 
answerer is committing some fallacy, and drawing his argument 
into paradox - for this was the second item of the sophist's 
programme - in the first place, then, this is best brought about 
by a certain manner of questioning and through the question. 
For to put the question without framing it with reference to any 
definite subject is a good bait for these purposes: for people are 
more inclined to make mistakes when they talk at large, and 
they talk at large when they have no definite subject before 
them. Also the putting of several questions, even though the 



560 



position against which one is arguing be quite definite, and the 
claim that he shall say only what he thinks, create abundant 
opportunity for drawing him into paradox or fallacy, and also, 
whether to any of these questions he replies 'Yes' or replies 'No', 
of leading him on to statements against which one is well off 
for a line of attack. Nowadays, however, men are less able to 
play foul by these means than they were formerly: for people 
rejoin with the question, 'What has that to do with the original 
subject?' It is, too, an elementary rule for eliciting some fallacy 
or paradox that one should never put a controversial question 
straight away, but say that one puts it from the wish for 
information: for the process of inquiry thus invited gives room 
for an attack. 

A rule specially appropriate for showing up a fallacy is the 
sophistic rule, that one should draw the answerer on to the kind 
of statements against which one is well supplied with 
arguments: this can be done both properly and improperly, as 
was said before.' Again, to draw a paradoxical statement, look 
and see to what school of philosophers the person arguing with 
you belongs, and then question him as to some point wherein 
their doctrine is paradoxical to most people: for with every 
school there is some point of that kind. It is an elementary rule 
in these matters to have a collection of the special 'theses' of 
the various schools among your propositions. The solution 
recommended as appropriate here, too, is to point out that the 
paradox does not come about because of the argument: 
whereas this is what his opponent always really wants. 

Moreover, argue from men's wishes and their professed 
opinions. For people do not wish the same things as they say 
they wish: they say what will look best, whereas they wish what 
appears to be to their interest: e.g. they say that a man ought to 
die nobly rather than to live in pleasure, and to live in honest 
poverty rather than in dishonourable riches; but they wish the 



561 



opposite. Accordingly, a man who speaks according to his 
wishes must be led into stating the professed opinions of 
people, while he who speaks according to these must be led into 
admitting those that people keep hidden away: for in either 
case they are bound to introduce a paradox; for they will speak 
contrary either to men's professed or to their hidden opinions. 

The widest range of common-place argument for leading men 
into paradoxical statement is that which depends on the 
standards of Nature and of the Law: it is so that both Callicles is 
drawn as arguing in the Gorgias, and that all the men of old 
supposed the result to come about: for nature (they said) and 
law are opposites, and justice is a fine thing by a legal standard, 
but not by that of nature. Accordingly, they said, the man whose 
statement agrees with the standard of nature you should meet 
by the standard of the law, but the man who agrees with the law 
by leading him to the facts of nature: for in both ways 
paradoxical statements may be committed. In their view the 
standard of nature was the truth, while that of the law was the 
opinion held by the majority. So that it is clear that they, too, 
used to try either to refute the answerer or to make him make 
paradoxical statements, just as the men of to-day do as well. 

Some questions are such that in both forms the answer is 
paradoxical; e.g. 'Ought one to obey the wise or one's father?' 
and 'Ought one to do what is expedient or what is just?' and 'Is 
it preferable to suffer injustice or to do an injury?' You should 
lead people, then, into views opposite to the majority and to the 
philosophers; if any one speaks as do the expert reasoners, lead 
him into opposition to the majority, while if he speaks as do the 
majority, then into opposition to the reasoners. For some say 
that of necessity the happy man is just, whereas it is 
paradoxical to the many that a king should be happy. To lead a 
man into paradoxes of this sort is the same as to lead him into 
the opposition of the standards of nature and law: for the law 



562 



represents the opinion of the majority, whereas philosophers 
speak according to the standard of nature and the truth. 



13 

Paradoxes, then, you should seek to elicit by means of these 
common-place rules. Now as for making any one babble, we 
have already said what we mean by 'to babble'. This is the object 
in view in all arguments of the following kind: If it is all the 
same to state a term and to state its definition, the 'double' and 
'double of half are the same: if then 'double' be the 'double of 
half, it will be the 'double of half of half. And if, instead of 
'double', 'double of half be again put, then the same expression 
will be repeated three times, 'double of half of half of half. Also 
'desire is of the pleasant, isn't it?' desire is conation for the 
pleasant: accordingly, 'desire' is 'conation for the pleasant for 
the pleasant'. 

All arguments of this kind occur in dealing (1) with any relative 
terms which not only have relative genera, but are also 
themselves relative, and are rendered in relation to one and the 
same thing, as e.g. conation is conation for something, and 
desire is desire of something, and double is double of 
something, i.e. double of half: also in dealing (2) with any terms 
which, though they be not relative terms at all, yet have their 
substance, viz. the things of which they are the states or 
affections or what not, indicated as well in their definition, they 
being predicated of these things. Thus e.g. 'odd' is a 'number 
containing a middle': but there is an 'odd number': therefore 
there is a 'number-containing-a-middle number'. Also, if 
snubness be a concavity of the nose, and there be a snub nose, 
there is therefore a 'concave-nose nose'. 



563 



People sometimes appear to produce this result, without really 
producing it, because they do not add the question whether the 
expression 'double', just by itself, has any meaning or no, and if 
so, whether it has the same meaning, or a different one; but 
they draw their conclusion straight away. Still it seems, 
inasmuch as the word is the same, to have the same meaning 
as well. 



14 

We have said before what kind of thing 'solecism' is.' It is 
possible both to commit it, and to seem to do so without doing 
so, and to do so without seeming to do so. Suppose, as 
Protagoras used to say that menis ('wrath') and pelex ('helmet') 
are masculine: according to him a man who calls wrath a 
'destructress' (oulomenen) commits a solecism, though he does 
not seem to do so to other people, where he who calls it a 
'destructor' (oulomenon) commits no solecism though he 
seems to do so. It is clear, then, that any one could produce this 
effect by art as well: and for this reason many arguments seem 
to lead to solecism which do not really do so, as happens in the 
case of refutations. 

Almost all apparent solecisms depend upon the word 'this' 
(tode), and upon occasions when the inflection denotes neither 
a masculine nor a feminine object but a neuter. For 'he' (outos) 
signifies a masculine, and 'she' (aute) feminine; but 'this' 
(touto), though meant to signify a neuter, often also signifies 
one or other of the former: e.g. 'What is this?' 'It is Calliope'; 'it 
is a log'; 'it is Coriscus'. Now in the masculine and feminine the 
inflections are all different, whereas in the neuter some are and 
some are not. Often, then, when 'this' (touto) has been granted, 



564 



people reason as if 'him' (touton) had been said: and likewise 
also they substitute one inflection for another. The fallacy 
comes about because 'this' (touto) is a common form of several 
inflections: for 'this' signifies sometimes 'he' (outos) and 
sometimes 'him' (touton). It should signify them alternately; 
when combined with 'is' (esti) it should be 'he', while with 
'being' it should be 'him': e.g. 'Coriscus (Kopiskos) is', but 'being 
Coriscus' (Kopiskon). It happens in the same way in the case of 
feminine nouns as well, and in the case of the so-called 
'chattels' that have feminine or masculine designations. For 
only those names which end in o and n, have the designation 
proper to a chattel, e.g. xulon ('log'), schoinion ('rope'); those 
which do not end so have that of a masculine or feminine 
object, though some of them we apply to chattels: e.g. askos 
('wineskin') is a masculine noun, and kline ('bed') a feminine. 
For this reason in cases of this kind as well there will be a 
difference of the same sort between a construction with 'is' 
(esti) or with 'being' (to einai). Also, Solecism resembles in a 
certain way those refutations which are said to depend on the 
like expression of unlike things. For, just as there we come upon 
a material solecism, so here we come upon a verbal: for 'man' is 
both a 'matter' for expression and also a 'word': and so is white'. 

It is clear, then, that for solecisms we must try to construct our 
argument out of the aforesaid inflections. 

These, then, are the types of contentious arguments, and the 
subdivisions of those types, and the methods for conducting 
them aforesaid. But it makes no little difference if the materials 
for putting the question be arranged in a certain manner with a 
view to concealment, as in the case of dialectics. Following then 
upon what we have said, this must be discussed first. 



565 



15 

With a view then to refutation, one resource is length - for it is 
difficult to keep several things in view at once; and to secure 
length the elementary rules that have been stated before should 
be employed. One resource, on the other hand, is speed; for 
when people are left behind they look ahead less. Moreover, 
there is anger and contentiousness, for when agitated 
everybody is less able to take care of himself. Elementary rules 
for producing anger are to make a show of the wish to play foul, 
and to be altogether shameless. Moreover, there is the putting 
of one's questions alternately, whether one has more than one 
argument leading to the same conclusion, or whether one has 
arguments to show both that something is so, and that it is not 
so: for the result is that he has to be on his guard at the same 
time either against more than one line, or against contrary 
lines, of argument. In general, all the methods described before 
of producing concealment are useful also for purposes of 
contentious argument: for the object of concealment is to avoid 
detection, and the object of this is to deceive. 

To counter those who refuse to grant whatever they suppose to 
help one's argument, one should put the question negatively, as 
though desirous of the opposite answer, or at any rate as though 
one put the question without prejudice; for when it is obscure 
what answer one wants to secure, people are less refractory. 
Also when, in dealing with particulars, a man grants the 
individual case, when the induction is done you should often 
not put the universal as a question, but take it for granted and 
use it: for sometimes people themselves suppose that they have 
granted it, and also appear to the audience to have done so, for 
they remember the induction and assume that the questions 
could not have been put for nothing. In cases where there is no 
term to indicate the universal, still you should avail yourself of 
the resemblance of the particulars to suit your purpose; for 



566 



resemblance often escapes detection. Also, with a view to 
obtaining your premiss, you ought to put it in your question 
side by side with its contrary. E.g. if it were necessary to secure 
the admission that 'A man should obey his father in everything', 
ask 'Should a man obey his parents in everything, or disobey 
them in everything?'; and to secure that 'A number multiplied 
by a large number is a large number', ask 'Should one agree that 
it is a large number or a small one?' For then, if compelled to 
choose, one will be more inclined to think it a large one: for the 
placing of their contraries close beside them makes things look 
big to men, both relatively and absolutely, and worse and better. 

A strong appearance of having been refuted is often produced 
by the most highly sophistical of all the unfair tricks of 
questioners, when without proving anything, instead of putting 
their final proposition as a question, they state it as a 
conclusion, as though they had proved that 'Therefore so-and- 
so is not true'. 

It is also a sophistical trick, when a paradox has been laid down, 
first to propose at the start some view that is generally 
accepted, and then claim that the answerer shall answer what 
he thinks about it, and to put one's question on matters of that 
kind in the form 'Do you think that...?' For then, if the question 
be taken as one of the premisses of one's argument, either a 
refutation or a paradox is bound to result; if he grants the view, 
a refutation; if he refuses to grant it or even to admit it as the 
received opinion, a paradox; if he refuses to grant it, but admits 
that it is the received opinion, something very like a refutation, 
results. 

Moreover, just as in rhetorical discourses, so also in those aimed 
at refutation, you should examine the discrepancies of the 
answerer's position either with his own statements, or with 
those of persons whom he admits to say and do aright, 



567 



moreover with those of people who are generally supposed to 
bear that kind of character, or who are like them, or with those 
of the majority or of all men. Also just as answerers, too, often, 
when they are in process of being confuted, draw a distinction, 
if their confutation is just about to take place, so questioners 
also should resort to this from time to time to counter objectors, 
pointing out, supposing that against one sense of the words the 
objection holds, but not against the other, that they have taken 
it in the latter sense, as e.g. Cleophon does in the Mandrobulus. 
They should also break off their argument and cut down their 
other lines of attack, while in answering, if a man perceives this 
being done beforehand, he should put in his objection and have 
his say first. One should also lead attacks sometimes against 
positions other than the one stated, on the understood 
condition that one cannot find lines of attack against the view 
laid down, as Lycophron did when ordered to deliver a eulogy 
upon the lyre. To counter those who demand 'Against what are 
you directing your effort?', since one is generally thought bound 
to state the charge made, while, on the other hand, some ways 
of stating it make the defence too easy, you should state as your 
aim only the general result that always happens in refutations, 
namely the contradiction of his thesis - viz. that your effort is to 
deny what he has affirmed, or to affirm what he denied: don't 
say that you are trying to show that the knowledge of contraries 
is, or is not, the same. One must not ask one's conclusion in the 
form of a premiss, while some conclusions should not even be 
put as questions at all; one should take and use it as granted. 



16 

We have now therefore dealt with the sources of questions, and 
the methods of questioning in contentious disputations: next 



568 



we have to speak of answering, and of how solutions should be 
made, and of what requires them, and of what use is served by 
arguments of this kind. 

The use of them, then, is, for philosophy, twofold. For in the first 
place, since for the most part they depend upon the expression, 
they put us in a better condition for seeing in how many senses 
any term is used, and what kind of resemblances and what kind 
of differences occur between things and between their names. 
In the second place they are useful for one's own personal 
researches; for the man who is easily committed to a fallacy by 
some one else, and does not perceive it, is likely to incur this 
fate of himself also on many occasions. Thirdly and lastly, they 
further contribute to one's reputation, viz. the reputation of 
being well trained in everything, and not inexperienced in 
anything: for that a party to arguments should find fault with 
them, if he cannot definitely point out their weakness, creates a 
suspicion, making it seem as though it were not the truth of the 
matter but merely inexperience that put him out of temper. 

Answerers may clearly see how to meet arguments of this kind, 
if our previous account was right of the sources whence 
fallacies came, and also our distinctions adequate of the forms 
of dishonesty in putting questions. But it is not the same thing 
take an argument in one's hand and then to see and solve its 
faults, as it is to be able to meet it quickly while being subjected 
to questions: for what we know, we often do not know in a 
different context. Moreover, just as in other things speed is 
enhanced by training, so it is with arguments too, so that 
supposing we are unpractised, even though a point be clear to 
us, we are often too late for the right moment. Sometimes too it 
happens as with diagrams; for there we can sometimes analyse 
the figure, but not construct it again: so too in refutations, 
though we know the thing on which the connexion of the 



569 



argument depends, we still are at a loss to split the argument 
apart. 



17 

First then, just as we say that we ought sometimes to choose to 
prove something in the general estimation rather than in truth, 
so also we have sometimes to solve arguments rather in the 
general estimation than according to the truth. For it is a 
general rule in fighting contentious persons, to treat them not 
as refuting, but as merely appearing to refute: for we say that 
they don't really prove their case, so that our object in 
correcting them must be to dispel the appearance of it. For if 
refutation be an unambiguous contradiction arrived at from 
certain views, there could be no need to draw distinctions 
against amphiboly and ambiguity: they do not effect a proof. 
The only motive for drawing further distinctions is that the 
conclusion reached looks like a refutation. What, then, we have 
to beware of, is not being refuted, but seeming to be, because of 
course the asking of amphibolies and of questions that turn 
upon ambiguity, and all the other tricks of that kind, conceal 
even a genuine refutation, and make it uncertain who is refuted 
and who is not. For since one has the right at the end, when the 
conclusion is drawn, to say that the only denial made of One's 
statement is ambiguous, no matter how precisely he may have 
addressed his argument to the very same point as oneself, it is 
not clear whether one has been refuted: for it is not clear 
whether at the moment one is speaking the truth. If, on the 
other hand, one had drawn a distinction, and questioned him 
on the ambiguous term or the amphiboly, the refutation would 
not have been a matter of uncertainty. Also what is incidentally 
the object of contentious arguers, though less so nowadays than 



570 



formerly, would have been fulfilled, namely that the person 
questioned should answer either 'Yes' or 'No': whereas 
nowadays the improper forms in which questioners put their 
questions compel the party questioned to add something to his 
answer in correction of the faultiness of the proposition as put: 
for certainly, if the questioner distinguishes his meaning 
adequately, the answerer is bound to reply either 'Yes' or 'No'. 

If any one is going to suppose that an argument which turns 
upon ambiguity is a refutation, it will be impossible for an 
answerer to escape being refuted in a sense: for in the case of 
visible objects one is bound of necessity to deny the term one 
has asserted, and to assert what one has denied. For the remedy 
which some people have for this is quite unavailing. They say, 
not that Coriscus is both musical and unmusical, but that this 
Coriscus is musical and this Coriscus unmusical. But this will 
not do, for to say 'this Coriscus is unmusical', or 'musical', and 
to say 'this Coriscus' is so, is to use the same expression: and 
this he is both affirming and denying at once. 'But perhaps they 
do not mean the same.' Well, nor did the simple name in the 
former case: so where is the difference? If, however, he is to 
ascribe to the one person the simple title 'Coriscus', while to the 
other he is to add the prefix 'one' or 'this', he commits an 
absurdity: for the latter is no more applicable to the one than to 
the other: for to whichever he adds it, it makes no difference. 

All the same, since if a man does not distinguish the senses of 
an amphiboly, it is not clear whether he has been confuted or 
has not been confuted, and since in arguments the right to 
distinguish them is granted, it is evident that to grant the 
question simply without drawing any distinction is a mistake, 
so that, even if not the man himself, at any rate his argument 
looks as though it had been refuted. It often happens, however, 
that, though they see the amphiboly, people hesitate to draw 
such distinctions, because of the dense crowd of persons who 



571 



propose questions of the kind, in order that they may not be 
thought to be obstructionists at every turn: then, though they 
would never have supposed that that was the point on which 
the argument turned, they often find themselves faced by a 
paradox. Accordingly, since the right of drawing the distinction 
is granted, one should not hesitate, as has been said before. 

If people never made two questions into one question, the 
fallacy that turns upon ambiguity and amphiboly would not 
have existed either, but either genuine refutation or none. For 
what is the difference between asking 'Are Callias and 
Themistocles musical?' and what one might have asked if they, 
being different, had had one name? For if the term applied 
means more than one thing, he has asked more than one 
question. If then it be not right to demand simply to be given a 
single answer to two questions, it is evident that it is not proper 
to give a simple answer to any ambiguous question, not even if 
the predicate be true of all the subjects, as some claim that one 
should. For this is exactly as though he had asked Are Coriscus 
and Callias at home or not at home?', supposing them to be 
both in or both out: for in both cases there is a number of 
propositions: for though the simple answer be true, that does 
not make the question one. For it is possible for it to be true to 
answer even countless different questions when put to one, all 
together with either a 'Yes' or a 'No': but still one should not 
answer them with a single answer: for that is the death of 
discussion. Rather, the case is like as though different things 
has actually had the same name applied to them. If then, one 
should not give a single answer to two questions, it is evident 
that we should not say simply 'Yes' or 'No' in the case of 
ambiguous terms either: for the remark is simply a remark, not 
an answer at all, although among disputants such remarks are 
loosely deemed to be answers, because they do not see what the 
consequence is. 



572 



As we said, then, inasmuch as certain refutations are generally 
taken for such, though not such really, in the same way also 
certain solutions will be generally taken for solutions, though 
not really such. Now these, we say, must sometimes be 
advanced rather than the true solutions in contentious 
reasonings and in the encounter with ambiguity. The proper 
answer in saying what one thinks is to say 'Granted'; for in that 
way the likelihood of being refuted on a side issue is minimized. 
If, on the other hand, one is compelled to say something 
paradoxical, one should then be most careful to add that 'it 
seems' so: for in that way one avoids the impression of being 
either refuted or paradoxical. Since it is clear what is meant by 
'begging the original question', and people think that they must 
at all costs overthrow the premisses that lie near the 
conclusion, and plead in excuse for refusing to grant him some 
of them that he is begging the original question, so whenever 
any one claims from us a point such as is bound to follow as a 
consequence from our thesis, but is false or paradoxical, we 
must plead the same: for the necessary consequences are 
generally held to be a part of the thesis itself. Moreover, 
whenever the universal has been secured not under a definite 
name, but by a comparison of instances, one should say that the 
questioner assumes it not in the sense in which it was granted 
nor in which he proposed it in the premiss: for this too is a 
point upon which a refutation often depends. 

If one is debarred from these defences one must pass to the 
argument that the conclusion has not been properly shown, 
approaching it in the light of the aforesaid distinction between 
the different kinds of fallacy. 

In the case, then, of names that are used literally one is bound 
to answer either simply or by drawing a distinction: the tacit 
understandings implied in our statements, e.g. in answer to 
questions that are not put clearly but elliptically - it is upon this 



573 



that the consequent refutation depends. For example, 'Is what 
belongs to Athenians the property of Athenians?' Yes. And so it 
is likewise in other cases. But observe; man belongs to the 
animal kingdom, doesn't he?' Yes. 'Then man is the property of 
the animal kingdom.' But this is a fallacy: for we say that man 
'belongs to' the animal kingdom because he is an animal, just 
as we say that Lysander 'belongs to' the Spartans, because he is 
a Spartan. It is evident, then, that where the premiss put 
forward is not clear, one must not grant it simply. 

Whenever of two things it is generally thought that if the one is 
true the other is true of necessity, whereas, if the other is true, 
the first is not true of necessity, one should, if asked which of 
them is true, grant the smaller one: for the larger the number of 
premisses, the harder it is to draw a conclusion from them. If, 
again, the sophist tries to secure that has a contrary while B has 
not, suppose what he says is true, you should say that each has 
a contrary, only for the one there is no established name. 

Since, again, in regard to some of the views they express, most 
people would say that any one who did not admit them was 
telling a falsehood, while they would not say this in regard to 
some, e.g. to any matters whereon opinion is divided (for most 
people have no distinct view whether the soul of animals is 
destructible or immortal), accordingly (1) it is uncertain in 
which of two senses the premiss proposed is usually meant - 
whether as maxims are (for people call by the name of 'maxims' 
both true opinions and general assertions) or like the doctrine 
'the diagonal of a square is incommensurate with its side': and 
moreover (2) whenever opinions are divided as to the truth, we 
then have subjects of which it is very easy to change the 
terminology undetected. For because of the uncertainty in 
which of the two senses the premiss contains the truth, one will 
not be thought to be playing any trick, while because of the 
division of opinion, one will not be thought to be telling a 



574 



falsehood. Change the terminology therefore, for the change 
will make the position irrefutable. 

Moreover, whenever one foresees any question coming, one 
should put in one's objection and have one's say beforehand: for 
by doing so one is likely to embarrass the questioner most 
effectually. 



18 

Inasmuch as a proper solution is an exposure of false reasoning, 
showing on what kind of question the falsity depends, and 
whereas 'false reasoning' has a double meaning - for it is used 
either if a false conclusion has been proved, or if there is only 
an apparent proof and no real one - there must be both the kind 
of solution just described, and also the correction of a merely 
apparent proof, so as to show upon which of the questions the 
appearance depends. Thus it comes about that one solves 
arguments that are properly reasoned by demolishing them, 
whereas one solves merely apparent arguments by drawing 
distinctions. Again, inasmuch as of arguments that are properly 
reasoned some have a true and others a false conclusion, those 
that are false in respect of their conclusion it is possible to solve 
in two ways; for it is possible both by demolishing one of the 
premisses asked, and by showing that the conclusion is not the 
real state of the case: those, on the other hand, that are false in 
respect of the premisses can be solved only by a demolition of 
one of them; for the conclusion is true. So that those who wish 
to solve an argument should in the first place look and see if it 
is properly reasoned, or is unreasoned; and next, whether the 
conclusion be true or false, in order that we may effect the 
solution either by drawing some distinction or by demolishing 



575 



something, and demolishing it either in this way or in that, as 
was laid down before. There is a very great deal of difference 
between solving an argument when being subjected to 
questions and when not: for to foresee traps is difficult, 
whereas to see them at one's leisure is easier. 



19 

Of the refutations, then, that depend upon ambiguity and 
amphiboly some contain some question with more than one 
meaning, while others contain a conclusion bearing a number 
of senses: e.g. in the proof that 'speaking of the silent' is 
possible, the conclusion has a double meaning, while in the 
proof that 'he who knows does not understand what he knows' 
one of the questions contains an amphiboly. Also the double- 
edged saying is true in one context but not in another: it means 
something that is and something that is not. 

Whenever, then, the many senses lie in the conclusion no 
refutation takes place unless the sophist secures as well the 
contradiction of the conclusion he means to prove; e.g. in the 
proof that 'seeing of the blind' is possible: for without the 
contradiction there was no refutation. Whenever, on the other 
hand, the many senses lie in the questions, there is no necessity 
to begin by denying the double-edged premiss: for this was not 
the goal of the argument but only its support. At the start, then, 
one should reply with regard to an ambiguity, whether of a term 
or of a phrase, in this manner, that 'in one sense it is so, and in 
another not so', as e.g. that 'speaking of the silent' is in one 
sense possible but in another not possible: also that in one 
sense 'one should do what must needs be done', but not in 
another: for 'what must needs be' bears a number of senses. If, 



576 



however, the ambiguity escapes one, one should correct it at the 
end by making an addition to the question: 'Is speaking of the 
silent possible?' 'No, but to speak of while he is silent is 
possible.' Also, in cases which contain the ambiguity in their 
premisses, one should reply in like manner: 'Do people then not 
understand what they know? 'Yes, but not those who know it in 
the manner described': for it is not the same thing to say that 
'those who know cannot understand what they know', and to 
say that 'those who know something in this particular manner 
cannot do so'. In general, too, even though he draws his 
conclusion in a quite unambiguous manner, one should 
contend that what he has negated is not the fact which one has 
asserted but only its name; and that therefore there is no 
refutation. 



20 

It is evident also how one should solve those refutations that 
depend upon the division and combination of words: for if the 
expression means something different when divided and when 
combined, as soon as one's opponent draws his conclusion one 
should take the expression in the contrary way. All such 
expressions as the following depend upon the combination or 
division of the words: 'Was X being beaten with that with which 
you saw him being beaten?' and 'Did you see him being beaten 
with that with which he was being beaten?' This fallacy has also 
in it an element of amphiboly in the questions, but it really 
depends upon combination. For the meaning that depends 
upon the division of the words is not really a double meaning 
(for the expression when divided is not the same), unless also 
the word that is pronounced, according to its breathing, as eros 
and eros is a case of double meaning. (In writing, indeed, a word 



577 



is the same whenever it is written of the same letters and in the 
same manner - and even there people nowadays put marks at 
the side to show the pronunciation - but the spoken words are 
not the same.) Accordingly an expression that depends upon 
division is not an ambiguous one. It is evident also that not all 
refutations depend upon ambiguity as some people say they do. 

The answerer, then, must divide the expression: for 'I-saw-a- 
man-being-beaten with my eyes' is not the same as to say 'I saw 
a man being-beaten-with-my-eyes'. Also there is the argument 
of Euthydemus proving 'Then you know now in Sicily that there 
are triremes in Piraeus': and again, 'Can a good man who is a 
cobbler be bad?' 'No.' 'But a good man may be a bad cobbler: 
therefore a good cobbler will be bad.' Again, 'Things the 
knowledge of which is good, are good things to learn, aren't 
they?' 'Yes.' 'The knowledge, however, of evil is good: therefore 
evil is a good thing to know.' 'Yes. But, you see, evil is both evil 
and a thing-to-learn, so that evil is an evil-thing-to-learn, 
although the knowledge of evils is good.' Again, 'Is it true to say 
in the present moment that you are born?' 'Yes.' 'Then you are 
born in the present moment.' 'No; the expression as divided has 
a different meaning: for it is true to say-in-the-present-moment 
that «you are born», but not «You are born-in-the-present- 
moment».' Again, 'Could you do what you can, and as you can?' 
'Yes.' 'But when not harping, you have the power to harp: and 
therefore you could harp when not harping.' 'No: he has not the 
power to harp-while-not-harping; merely, when he is not doing 
it, he has the power to do it.' Some people solve this last 
refutation in another way as well. For, they say, if he has granted 
that he can do anything in the way he can, still it does not 
follow that he can harp when not harping: for it has not been 
granted that he will do anything in every way in which he can; 
and it is not the same thing' to do a thing in the way he can' 
and 'to do it in every way in which he can'. But evidently they 
do not solve it properly: for of arguments that depend upon the 



578 



same point the solution is the same, whereas this will not fit all 
cases of the kind nor yet all ways of putting the questions: it is 
valid against the questioner, but not against his argument. 



21 

Accentuation gives rise to no fallacious arguments, either as 
written or as spoken, except perhaps some few that might be 
made up; e.g. the following argument. 'Is ou katalueis a house?' 
'Yes.' 'Is then ou katalueis the negation of katalueis?' 'Yes.' 'But 
you said that ou katalueis is a house: therefore the house is a 
negation.' How one should solve this, is clear: for the word does 
not mean the same when spoken with an acuter and when 
spoken with a graver accent. 



22 

It is clear also how one must meet those fallacies that depend 
on the identical expressions of things that are not identical, 
seeing that we are in possession of the kinds of predications. 
For the one man, say, has granted, when asked, that a term 
denoting a substance does not belong as an attribute, while the 
other has shown that some attribute belongs which is in the 
Category of Relation or of Quantity, but is usually thought to 
denote a substance because of its expression; e.g. in the 
following argument: 'Is it possible to be doing and to have done 
the same thing at the same time?' 'No.' 'But, you see, it is surely 
possible to be seeing and to have seen the same thing at the 
same time, and in the same aspect.' Again, 'Is any mode of 



579 



passivity a mode of activity?' 'No.' 'Then «he is cut», «he is 
burnt», «he is struck by some sensible object» are alike in 
expression and all denote some form of passivity, while again 
«to say», «to run», «to see» are like one like one another in 
expression: but, you see, «to see» is surely a form of being struck 
by a sensible object; therefore it is at the same time a form of 
passivity and of activity.' Suppose, however, that in that case 
any one, after granting that it is not possible to do and to have 
done the same thing in the same time, were to say that it is 
possible to see and to have seen it, still he has not yet been 
refuted, suppose him to say that 'to see' is not a form of 'doing' 
(activity) but of 'passivity': for this question is required as well, 
though he is supposed by the listener to have already granted it, 
when he granted that 'to cut' is a form of present, and 'to have 
cut' a form of past, activity, and so on with the other things that 
have a like expression. For the listener adds the rest by himself, 
thinking the meaning to be alike: whereas really the meaning is 
not alike, though it appears to be so because of the expression. 
The same thing happens here as happens in cases of ambiguity: 
for in dealing with ambiguous expressions the tyro in argument 
supposes the sophist to have negated the fact which he (the 
tyro) affirmed, and not merely the name: whereas there still 
wants the question whether in using the ambiguous term he 
had a single meaning in view: for if he grants that that was so, 
the refutation will be effected. 

Like the above are also the following arguments. It is asked if a 
man has lost what he once had and afterwards has not: for a 
man will no longer have ten dice even though he has only lost 
one die. No: rather it is that he has lost what he had before and 
has not now; but there is no necessity for him to have lost as 
much or as many things as he has not now. So then, he asks the 
questions as to what he has, and draws the conclusion as to the 
whole number that he has: for ten is a number. If then he had 
asked to begin with, whether a man no longer having the 



580 



number of things he once had has lost the whole number, no 
one would have granted it, but would have said 'Either the 
whole number or one of them'. Also there is the argument that 
'a man may give what he has not got': for he has not got only 
one die. No: rather it is that he has given not what he had not 
got, but in a manner in which he had not got it, viz. just the one. 
For the word 'only' does not signify a particular substance or 
quality or number, but a manner relation, e.g. that it is not 
coupled with any other. It is therefore just as if he had asked 
'Could a man give what he has not got?' and, on being given the 
answer 'No', were to ask if a man could give a thing quickly 
when he had not got it quickly, and, on this being granted, were 
to conclude that 'a man could give what he had not got'. It is 
quite evident that he has not proved his point: for to 'give 
quickly' is not to give a thing, but to give in a certain manner; 
and a man could certainly give a thing in a manner in which he 
has not got it, e.g. he might have got it with pleasure and give it 
with pain. 

Like these are also all arguments of the following kind: 'Could a 
man strike a blow with a hand which he has not got, or see with 
an eye which he has not got?' For he has not got only one eye. 
Some people solve this case, where a man has more than one 
eye, or more than one of anything else, by saying also that he 
has only one. Others also solve it as they solve the refutation of 
the view that 'what a man has, he has received': for A gave only 
one vote; and certainly B, they say, has only one vote from A. 
Others, again, proceed by demolishing straight away the 
proposition asked, and admitting that it is quite possible to 
have what one has not received; e.g. to have received sweet 
wine, but then, owing to its going bad in the course of receipt, to 
have it sour. But, as was said also above,' all these persons direct 
their solutions against the man, not against his argument. For if 
this were a genuine solution, then, suppose any one to grant the 
opposite, he could find no solution, just as happens in other 



581 



cases; e.g. suppose the true solution to be 'So-and-so is partly 
true and partly not', then, if the answerer grants the expression 
without any qualification, the sophist's conclusion follows. If, on 
the other hand, the conclusion does not follow, then that could 
not be the true solution: and what we say in regard to the 
foregoing examples is that, even if all the sophist's premisses be 
granted, still no proof is effected. 

Moreover, the following too belong to this group of arguments. 
'If something be in writing did some one write it?' 'Yes.' 'But it is 
now in writing that you are seated - a false statement, though it 
was true at the time when it was written: therefore the 
statement that was written is at the same time false and true.' 
But this is fallacious, for the falsity or truth of a statement or 
opinion indicates not a substance but a quality: for the same 
account applies to the case of an opinion as well. Again, 'Is what 
a learner learns what he learns?' 'Yes.' 'But suppose some one 
learns «slow» quick'. Then his (the sophist's) words denote not 
what the learner learns but how he learns it. Also, 'Does a man 
tread upon what he walks through? 'Yes.' 'But X walks through a 
whole day.' No, rather the words denote not what he walks 
through, but when he walks; just as when any one uses the 
words 'to drink the cup' he denotes not what he drinks, but the 
vessel out of which he drinks. Also, 'Is it either by learning or by 
discovery that a man knows what he knows?' 'Yes.' 'But suppose 
that of a pair of things he has discovered one and learned the 
other, the pair is not known to him by either method.' No: 'what' 
he knows, means' every single thing' he knows, individually; but 
this does not mean 'all the things' he knows, collectively. Again, 
there is the proof that there is a 'third man' distinct from Man 
and from individual men. But that is a fallacy, for 'Man', and 
indeed every general predicate, denotes not an individual 
substance, but a particular quality, or the being related to 
something in a particular manner, or something of that sort. 
Likewise also in the case of 'Coriscus' and 'Coriscus the 



582 



musician' there is the problem, Are they the same or different?' 
For the one denotes an individual substance and the other a 
quality, so that it cannot be isolated; though it is not the 
isolation which creates the 'third man', but the admission that 
it is an individual substance. For 'Man' cannot be an individual 
substance, as Callias is. Nor is the case improved one whit even 
if one were to call the clement he has isolated not an individual 
substance but a quality: for there will still be the one beside the 
many, just as 'Man' was. It is evident then that one must not 
grant that what is a common predicate applying to a class 
universally is an individual substance, but must say that 
denotes either a quality, or a relation, or a quantity, or 
something of that kind. 



23 

It is a general rule in dealing with arguments that depend on 
language that the solution always follows the opposite of the 
point on which the argument turns: e.g. if the argument 
depends upon combination, then the solution consists in 
division; if upon division, then in combination. Again, if it 
depends on an acute accent, the solution is a grave accent; if on 
a grave accent, it is an acute. If it depends on ambiguity, one can 
solve it by using the opposite term; e.g. if you find yourself 
calling something inanimate, despite your previous denial that 
it was so, show in what sense it is alive: if, on the other hand, 
one has declared it to be inanimate and the sophist has proved 
it to be animate, say how it is inanimate. Likewise also in a case 
of amphiboly. If the argument depends on likeness of 
expression, the opposite will be the solution. 'Could a man give 
what he has not got? 'No, not what he has not got; but he could 
give it in a way in which he has not got it, e.g. one die by itself.' 



583 



Does a man know either by learning or by discovery each thing 
that he knows, singly? but not the things that he knows, 
collectively.' Also a man treads, perhaps, on any thing he walks 
through, but not on the time he walks through. Likewise also in 
the case of the other examples. 



24 

In dealing with arguments that depend on Accident, one and 
the same solution meets all cases. For since it is indeterminate 
when an attribute should be ascribed to a thing, in cases where 
it belongs to the accident of the thing, and since in some cases 
it is generally agreed and people admit that it belongs, while in 
others they deny that it need belong, we should therefore, as 
soon as the conclusion has been drawn, say in answer to them 
all alike, that there is no need for such an attribute to belong. 
One must, however, be prepared to adduce an example of the 
kind of attribute meant. All arguments such as the following 
depend upon Accident. 'Do you know what I am going to ask 
you? you know the man who is approaching', or 'the man in the 
mask'? 'Is the statue your work of art?' or 'Is the dog your 
father?' 'Is the product of a small number with a small number 
a small number?' For it is evident in all these cases that there is 
no necessity for the attribute which is true of the thing's 
accident to be true of the thing as well. For only to things that 
are indistinguishable and one in essence is it generally agreed 
that all the same attributes belong; whereas in the case of a 
good thing, to be good is not the same as to be going to be the 
subject of a question; nor in the case of a man approaching, or 
wearing a mask, is 'to be approaching' the same thing as 'to be 
Coriscus', so that suppose I know Coriscus, but do not know the 
man who is approaching, it still isn't the case that I both know 



584 



and do not know the same man; nor, again, if this is mine and is 
also a work of art, is it therefore my work of art, but my property 
or thing or something else. (The solution is after the same 
manner in the other cases as well.) 

Some solve these refutations by demolishing the original 
proposition asked: for they say that it is possible to know and 
not to know the same thing, only not in the same respect: 
accordingly, when they don't know the man who is coming 
towards them, but do know Corsicus, they assert that they do 
know and don't know the same object, but not in the same 
respect. Yet, as we have already remarked, the correction of 
arguments that depend upon the same point ought to be the 
same, whereas this one will not stand if one adopts the same 
principle in regard not to knowing something, but to being, or to 
being is a in a certain state, e.g. suppose that X is father, and is 
also yours: for if in some cases this is true and it is possible to 
know and not to know the same thing, yet with that case the 
solution stated has nothing to do. Certainly there is nothing to 
prevent the same argument from having a number of flaws; but 
it is not the exposition of any and every fault that constitutes a 
solution: for it is possible for a man to show that a false 
conclusion has been proved, but not to show on what it 
depends, e.g. in the case of Zeno's argument to prove that 
motion is impossible. So that even if any one were to try to 
establish that this doctrine is an impossible one, he still is 
mistaken, and even if he proved his case ten thousand times 
over, still this is no solution of Zeno's argument: for the solution 
was all along an exposition of false reasoning, showing on what 
its falsity depends. If then he has not proved his case, or is 
trying to establish even a true proposition, or a false one, in a 
false manner, to point this out is a true solution. Possibly, 
indeed, the present suggestion may very well apply in some 
cases: but in these cases, at any rate, not even this would be 
generally agreed: for he knows both that Coriscus is Coriscus 



585 



and that the approaching figure is approaching. To know and 
not to know the same thing is generally thought to be possible, 
when e.g. one knows that X is white, but does not realize that 
he is musical: for in that way he does know and not know the 
same thing, though not in the same respect. But as to the 
approaching figure and Coriscus he knows both that it is 
approaching and that he is Coriscus. 

A like mistake to that of those whom we have mentioned is that 
of those who solve the proof that every number is a small 
number: for if, when the conclusion is not proved, they pass this 
over and say that a conclusion has been proved and is true, on 
the ground that every number is both great and small, they 
make a mistake. 

Some people also use the principle of ambiguity to solve the 
aforesaid reasonings, e.g. the proof that 'X is your father', or 
'son', or 'slave'. Yet it is evident that if the appearance a proof 
depends upon a plurality of meanings, the term, or the 
expression in question, ought to bear a number of literal senses, 
whereas no one speaks of A as being 'B's child' in the literal 
sense, if B is the child's master, but the combination depends 
upon Accident. 'Is A yours?' 'Yes.' 'And is A a child?' 'Yes.' 'Then 
the child A is yours,' because he happens to be both yours and a 
child; but he is not 'your child'. 

There is also the proof that 'something «of evils» is good'; for 
wisdom is a 'knowledge «of evils»'. But the expression that this 
is 'of so-and-so' (='so-and-so's') has not a number of meanings: 
it means that it is 'so-and-so's property'. We may suppose of 
course, on the other hand, that it has a number of meanings - 
for we also say that man is 'of the animals', though not their 
property; and also that any term related to 'evils' in a way 
expressed by a genitive case is on that account a so-and-so 'of 
evils', though it is not one of the evils - but in that case the 



586 



apparently different meanings seem to depend on whether the 
term is used relatively or absolutely. 'Yet it is conceivably 
possible to find a real ambiguity in the phrase «Something of 
evils is good».' Perhaps, but not with regard to the phrase in 
question. It would occur more nearly, suppose that 'A servant is 
good of the wicked'; though perhaps it is not quite found even 
there: for a thing may be 'good' and be 'X's' without being at the 
same time 'X's good'. Nor is the saying that 'Man is of the 
animals' a phrase with a number of meanings: for a phrase does 
not become possessed of a number of meanings merely 
suppose we express it elliptically: for we express 'Give me the 
Iliad' by quoting half a line of it, e.g. 'Give me «Sing, goddess, of 
the wrath. ..»' 



25 

Those arguments which depend upon an expression that is 
valid of a particular thing, or in a particular respect, or place, or 
manner, or relation, and not valid absolutely, should be solved 
by considering the conclusion in relation to its contradictory, to 
see if any of these things can possibly have happened to it. For 
it is impossible for contraries and opposites and an affirmative 
and a negative to belong to the same thing absolutely; there is, 
however, nothing to prevent each from belonging in a particular 
respect or relation or manner, or to prevent one of them from 
belonging in a particular respect and the other absolutely. So 
that if this one belongs absolutely and that one in a particular 
respect, there is as yet no refutation. This is a feature one has to 
find in the conclusion by examining it in comparison with its 
contradictory. 



587 



All arguments of the following kind have this feature: 'Is it 
possible for what is-not to be? «No.» But, you see, it is 
something, despite its not being.' Likewise also, Being will not 
be; for it will not he some particular form of being. Is it possible 
for the same man at the same time to be a keeper and a breaker 
of his oath?' 'Can the same man at the same time both obey 
and disobey the same man?' Or isn't it the case that being 
something in particular and Being are not the same? On the 
other hand, Not-being, even if it be something, need not also 
have absolute 'being' as well. Nor if a man keeps his oath in this 
particular instance or in this particular respect, is he bound also 
to be a keeper of oaths absolutely, but he who swears that he 
will break his oath, and then breaks it, keeps this particular 
oath only; he is not a keeper of his oath: nor is the disobedient 
man 'obedient', though he obeys one particular command. The 
argument is similar, also, as regards the problem whether the 
same man can at the same time say what is both false and true: 
but it appears to be a troublesome question because it is not 
easy to see in which of the two connexions the word 
'absolutely' is to be rendered - with 'true' or with 'false'. There 
is, however, nothing to prevent it from being false absolutely, 
though true in some particular respect or relation, i.e. being true 
in some things, though not 'true' absolutely. Likewise also in 
cases of some particular relation and place and time. For all 
arguments of the following kind depend upon this.' Is health, or 
wealth, a good thing?' 'Yes.' 'But to the fool who does not use it 
aright it is not a good thing: therefore it is both good and not 
good.' 'Is health, or political power, a good thing?' 'Yes. «But 
sometimes it is not particularly good: therefore the same thing 
is both good and not good to the same man.' Or rather there is 
nothing to prevent a thing, though good absolutely, being not 
good to a particular man, or being good to a particular man, and 
yet not good or here. 'Is that which the prudent man would not 
wish, an evil?' 'Yes.' 'But to get rid of, he would not wish the 



588 



good: therefore the good is an evil.' But that is a mistake; for it is 
not the same thing to say 'The good is an evil' and 'to get rid of 
the good is an evil'. Likewise also the argument of the thief is 
mistaken. For it is not the case that if the thief is an evil thing, 
acquiring things is also evil: what he wishes, therefore, is not 
what is evil but what is good; for to acquire something good is 
good. Also, disease is an evil thing, but not to get rid of disease. 
'Is the just preferable to the unjust, and what takes place justly 
to what takes place unjustly? 'Yes.' 'But to to be put to death 
unjustly is preferable.' 'Is it just that each should have his own?' 
'Yes.' 'But whatever decisions a man comes to on the strength of 
his personal opinion, even if it be a false opinion, are valid in 
law: therefore the same result is both just and unjust.' Also, 
should one decide in favour of him who says what is unjust?' 
'The former.' 'But you see, it is just for the injured party to say 
fully the things he has suffered; and these are fallacies. For 
because to suffer a thing unjustly is preferable, unjust ways are 
not therefore preferable, though in this particular case the 
unjust may very well be better than the just. Also, to have one's 
own is just, while to have what is another's is not just: all the 
same, the decision in question may very well be a just decision, 
whatever it be that the opinion of the man who gave the 
decision supports: for because it is just in this particular case or 
in this particular manner, it is not also just absolutely. Likewise 
also, though things are unjust, there is nothing to prevent the 
speaking of them being just: for because to speak of things is 
just, there is no necessity that the things should be just, any 
more than because to speak of things be of use, the things need 
be of use. Likewise also in the case of what is just. So that it is 
not the case that because the things spoken of are unjust, the 
victory goes to him who speaks unjust things: for he speaks of 
things that are just to speak of, though absolutely, i.e. to suffer, 
they are unjust. 



589 



26 

Refutations that depend on the definition of a refutation must, 
according to the plan sketched above, be met by comparing 
together the conclusion with its contradictory, and seeing that it 
shall involve the same attribute in the same respect and 
relation and manner and time. If this additional question be put 
at the start, you should not admit that it is impossible for the 
same thing to be both double and not double, but grant that it is 
possible, only not in such a way as was agreed to constitute a 
refutation of your case. All the following arguments depend 
upon a point of that kind. 'Does a man who knows A to be A, 
know the thing called A?' and in the same way, 'is one who is 
ignorant that A is A ignorant of the thing called A?' 'Yes.' 'But 
one who knows that Coriscus is Coriscus might be ignorant of 
the fact that he is musical, so that he both knows and is 
ignorant of the same thing.' Is a thing four cubits long greater 
than a thing three cubits long?' 'Yes.' 'But a thing might grow 
from three to four cubits in length; 'now what is 'greater' is 
greater than a 'less': accordingly the thing in question will be 
both greater and less than itself in the same respect. 



27 

As to refutations that depend on begging and assuming the 
original point to be proved, suppose the nature of the question 
to be obvious, one should not grant it, even though it be a view 
generally held, but should tell him the truth. Suppose, however, 
that it escapes one, then, thanks to the badness of arguments of 
that kind, one should make one's error recoil upon the 
questioner, and say that he has brought no argument: for a 



590 



refutation must be proved independently of the original point. 
Secondly, one should say that the point was granted under the 
impression that he intended not to use it as a premiss, but to 
reason against it, in the opposite way from that adopted in 
refutations on side issues. 



28 

Also, those refutations that bring one to their conclusion 
through the consequent you should show up in the course of 
the argument itself. The mode in which consequences follow is 
twofold. For the argument either is that as the universal follows 
on its particular - as (e.g.) 'animal' follows from 'man' - so does 
the particular on its universal: for the claim is made that if A is 
always found with B, then B also is always found with A. Or else 
it proceeds by way of the opposites of the terms involved: for if 
A follows B, it is claimed that A's opposite will follow B's 
opposite. On this latter claim the argument of Melissus also 
depends: for he claims that because that which has come to be 
has a beginning, that which has not come to be has none, so 
that if the heaven has not come to be, it is also eternal. But that 
is not so; for the sequence is vice versa. 



29 

In the case of any refutations whose reasoning depends on 
some addition, look and see if upon its subtraction the 
absurdity follows none the less: and then if so, the answerer 
should point this out, and say that he granted the addition not 



591 



because he really thought it, but for the sake of the argument, 
whereas the questioner has not used it for the purpose of his 
argument at all. 



30 

To meet those refutations which make several questions into 
one, one should draw a distinction between them straight away 
at the start. For a question must be single to which there is a 
single answer, so that one must not affirm or deny several 
things of one thing, nor one thing of many, but one of one. But 
just as in the case of ambiguous terms, an attribute belongs to a 
term sometimes in both its senses, and sometimes in neither, 
so that a simple answer does one, as it happens, no harm 
despite the fact that the question is not simple, so it is in these 
cases of double questions too. Whenever, then, the several 
attributes belong to the one subject, or the one to the many, the 
man who gives a simple answer encounters no obstacle even 
though he has committed this mistake: but whenever an 
attribute belongs to one subject but not to the other, or there is 
a question of a number of attributes belonging to a number of 
subjects and in one sense both belong to both, while in another 
sense, again, they do not, then there is trouble, so that one must 
beware of this. Thus (e.g.) in the following arguments: 
Supposing to be good and B evil, you will, if you give a single 
answer about both, be compelled to say that it is true to call 
these good, and that it is true to call them evil and likewise to 
call them neither good nor evil (for each of them has not each 
character), so that the same thing will be both good and evil and 
neither good nor evil. Also, since everything is the same as itself 
and different from anything else, inasmuch as the man who 
answers double questions simply can be made to say that 



592 



several things are 'the same' not as other things but 'as 
themselves', and also that they are different from themselves, it 
follows that the same things must be both the same as and 
different from themselves. Moreover, if what is good becomes 
evil while what is evil is good, then they must both become two. 
So of two unequal things each being equal to itself, it will follow 
that they are both equal and unequal to themselves. 

Now these refutations fall into the province of other solutions 
as well: for 'both' and 'all' have more than one meaning, so that 
the resulting affirmation and denial of the same thing does not 
occur, except verbally: and this is not what we meant by a 
refutation. But it is clear that if there be not put a single 
question on a number of points, but the answerer has affirmed 
or denied one attribute only of one subject only, the absurdity 
will not come to pass. 



31 

With regard to those who draw one into repeating the same 
thing a number of times, it is clear that one must not grant that 
predications of relative terms have any meaning in abstraction 
by themselves, e.g. that 'double' is a significant term apart from 
the whole phrase 'double of half merely on the ground that it 
figures in it. For ten figures in 'ten minus one' and in 'not do', 
and generally the affirmation in the negation; but for all that, 
suppose any one were to say, 'This is not white', he does not say 
that it is white. The bare word 'double', one may perhaps say, 
has not even any meaning at all, any more than has 'the' in 'the 
half: and even if it has a meaning, yet it has not the same 
meaning as in the combination. Nor is 'knowledge' the same 
thing in a specific branch of it (suppose it, e.g. to be 'medical 



593 



knowledge') as it is in general: for in general it was the 
'knowledge of the knowable'. In the case of terms that are 
predicated of the terms through which they are defined, you 
should say the same thing, that the term defined is not the 
same in abstraction as it is in the whole phrase. For 'concave' 
has a general meaning which is the same in the case of a snub 
nose, and of a bandy leg, but when added to either substantive 
nothing prevents it from differentiating its meaning; in fact it 
bears one sense as applied to the nose, and another as applied 
to the leg: for in the former connexion it means 'snub' and in 
the latter 'bandyshaped'; i.e. it makes no difference whether you 
say 'a snub nose' or 'a concave nose'. Moreover, the expression 
must not be granted in the nominative case: for it is a 
falsehood. For snubness is not a concave nose but something 
(e.g. an affection) belonging to a nose: hence, there is no 
absurdity in supposing that the snub nose is a nose possessing 
the concavity that belongs to a nose. 



32 

With regard to solecisms, we have previously said what it is that 
appears to bring them about; the method of their solution will 
be clear in the course of the arguments themselves. Solecism is 
the result aimed at in all arguments of the following kind: 'Is a 
thing truly that which you truly call it?' 'Yes'. 'But, speaking of a 
stone, you call him real: therefore of a stone it follows that «him 
is real».' No: rather, talking of a stone means not saying which' 
but 'whom', and not 'that' but 'him'. If, then, any one were to 
ask, 'Is a stone him whom you truly call him?' he would be 
generally thought not to be speaking good Greek, any more than 
if he were to ask, 'Is he what you call her?' Speak in this way of 
a 'stick' or any neuter word, and the difference does not break 



594 



out. For this reason, also, no solecism is incurred, suppose any- 
one asks, 'Is a thing what you say it to be?' 'Yes'. 'But, speaking 
of a stick, you call it real: therefore, of a stick it follows that it is 
real.' 'Stone', however, and 'he' have masculine designations. 
Now suppose some one were to ask, 'Can «he» be a «she» (a 
female)?', and then again, 'Well, but is not he Coriscus?' and 
then were to say, 'Then he is a «she»,' he has not proved the 
solecism, even if the name 'Coriscus' does signify a 'she', if, on 
the other hand, the answerer does not grant this: this point 
must be put as an additional question: while if neither is it the 
fact nor does he grant it, then the sophist has not proved his 
case either in fact or as against the person he has been 
questioning. In like manner, then, in the above instance as well 
it must be definitely put that 'he' means the stone. If, however, 
this neither is so nor is granted, the conclusion must not be 
stated: though it follows apparently, because the case (the 
accusative), that is really unlike, appears to be like the 
nominative. 'Is it true to say that this object is what you call it 
by name?' 'Yes'. 'But you call it by the name of a shield: this 
object therefore is «of a shield».' No: not necessarily, because the 
meaning of 'this object' is not 'of a shield' but 'a shield': 'of a 
shield' would be the meaning of 'this object's'. Nor again if 'He is 
what you call him by name', while 'the name you call him by is 
Cleon's', is he therefore 'Cleon's': for he is not 'Cleon's', for what 
was said was that 'He, not his, is what I call him by name'. For 
the question, if put in the latter way, would not even be Greek. 
'Do you know this?' 'Yes.' 'But this is he: therefore you know he'. 
No: rather 'this' has not the same meaning in 'Do you know 
this?' as in 'This is a stone'; in the first it stands for an 
accusative, in the second for a nominative case. 'When you have 
understanding of anything, do you understand it?' 'Yes.' 'But 
you have understanding of a stone: therefore you understand of 
a stone.' No: the one phrase is in the genitive, 'of a stone', while 
the other is in the accusative, 'a stone': and what was granted 



595 



was that 'you understand that, not of that, of which you have 
understanding', so that you understand not 'of a stone', but 'the 
stone'. 

Thus that arguments of this kind do not prove solecism but 
merely appear to do so, and both why they so appear and how 
you should meet them, is clear from what has been said. 



33 

We must also observe that of all the arguments aforesaid it is 
easier with some to see why and where the reasoning leads the 
hearer astray, while with others it is more difficult, though often 
they are the same arguments as the former. For we must call an 
argument the same if it depends upon the same point; but the 
same argument is apt to be thought by some to depend on 
diction, by others on accident, and by others on something else, 
because each of them, when worked with different terms, is not 
so clear as it was. Accordingly, just as in fallacies that depend 
on ambiguity, which are generally thought to be the silliest form 
of fallacy, some are clear even to the man in the street (for 
humorous phrases nearly all depend on diction; e.g. 'The man 
got the cart down from the stand'; and 'Where are you bound?' 
'To the yard arm'; and 'Which cow will calve afore?' 'Neither, but 
both behind;' and 'Is the North wind clear?' 'No, indeed; for it 
has murdered the beggar and the merchant. » Is he a Good 
enough-King?' 'No, indeed; a Rob-son': and so with the great 
majority of the rest as well), while others appear to elude the 
most expert (and it is a symptom of this that they often fight 
about their terms, e.g. whether the meaning of 'Being' and 'One' 
is the same in all their applications or different; for some think 
that 'Being' and 'One' mean the same; while others solve the 



596 



argument of Zeno and Parmenides by asserting that 'One' and 
'Being' are used in a number of senses), likewise also as regards 
fallacies of Accident and each of the other types, some of the 
arguments will be easier to see while others are more difficult; 
also to grasp to which class a fallacy belongs, and whether it is a 
refutation or not a refutation, is not equally easy in all cases. 

An incisive argument is one which produces the greatest 
perplexity: for this is the one with the sharpest fang. Now 
perplexity is twofold, one which occurs in reasoned arguments, 
respecting which of the propositions asked one is to demolish, 
and the other in contentious arguments, respecting the manner 
in which one is to assent to what is propounded. Therefore it is 
in syllogistic arguments that the more incisive ones produce the 
keenest heart-searching. Now a syllogistic argument is most 
incisive if from premisses that are as generally accepted as 
possible it demolishes a conclusion that is accepted as generally 
as possible. For the one argument, if the contradictory is 
changed about, makes all the resulting syllogisms alike in 
character: for always from premisses that are generally 
accepted it will prove a conclusion, negative or positive as the 
case may be, that is just as generally accepted; and therefore 
one is bound to feel perplexed. An argument, then, of this kind 
is the most incisive, viz. the one that puts its conclusion on all 
fours with the propositions asked; and second comes the one 
that argues from premisses, all of which are equally convincing: 
for this will produce an equal perplexity as to what kind of 
premiss, of those asked, one should demolish. Herein is a 
difficulty: for one must demolish something, but what one must 
demolish is uncertain. Of contentious arguments, on the other 
hand, the most incisive is the one which, in the first place, is 
characterized by an initial uncertainty whether it has been 
properly reasoned or not; and also whether the solution 
depends on a false premiss or on the drawing of a distinction; 
while, of the rest, the second place is held by that whose 



597 



solution clearly depends upon a distinction or a demolition, and 
yet it does not reveal clearly which it is of the premisses asked, 
whose demolition, or the drawing of a distinction within it, will 
bring the solution about, but even leaves it vague whether it is 
on the conclusion or on one of the premisses that the deception 
depends. 

Now sometimes an argument which has not been properly 
reasoned is silly, supposing the assumptions required to be 
extremely contrary to the general view or false; but sometimes 
it ought not to be held in contempt. For whenever some 
question is left out, of the kind that concerns both the subject 
and the nerve of the argument, the reasoning that has both 
failed to secure this as well, and also failed to reason properly, is 
silly; but when what is omitted is some extraneous question, 
then it is by no means to be lightly despised, but the argument 
is quite respectable, though the questioner has not put his 
questions well. 

Just as it is possible to bring a solution sometimes against the 
argument, at others against the questioner and his mode of 
questioning, and at others against neither of these, likewise also 
it is possible to marshal one's questions and reasoning both 
against the thesis, and against the answerer and against the 
time, whenever the solution requires a longer time to examine 
than the period available. 



34 

As to the number, then, and kind of sources whence fallacies 
arise in discussion, and how we are to show that our opponent 
is committing a fallacy and make him utter paradoxes; 
moreover, by the use of what materials solescism is brought 



598 



about, and how to question and what is the way to arrange the 
questions; moreover, as to the question what use is served by all 
arguments of this kind, and concerning the answerer's part, 
both as a whole in general, and in particular how to solve 
arguments and solecisms - on all these things let the foregoing 
discussion suffice. It remains to recall our original proposal and 
to bring our discussion to a close with a few words upon it. 

Our programme was, then, to discover some faculty of 
reasoning about any theme put before us from the most 
generally accepted premisses that there are. For that is the 
essential task of the art of discussion (dialectic) and of 
examination (peirastic). Inasmuch, however, as it is annexed to 
it, on account of the near presence of the art of sophistry 
(sophistic), not only to be able to conduct an examination 
dialectically but also with a show of knowledge, we therefore 
proposed for our treatise not only the aforesaid aim of being 
able to exact an account of any view, but also the aim of 
ensuring that in standing up to an argument we shall defend 
our thesis in the same manner by means of views as generally 
held as possible. The reason of this we have explained; for this, 
too, was why Socrates used to ask questions and not to answer 
them; for he used to confess that he did not know. We have 
made clear, in the course of what precedes, the number both of 
the points with reference to which, and of the materials from 
which, this will be accomplished, and also from what sources 
we can become well supplied with these: we have shown, 
moreover, how to question or arrange the questioning as a 
whole, and the problems concerning the answers and solutions 
to be used against the reasonings of the questioner. We have 
also cleared up the problems concerning all other matters that 
belong to the same inquiry into arguments. In addition to this 
we have been through the subject of Fallacies, as we have 
already stated above. 



599 



That our programme, then, has been adequately completed is 
clear. But we must not omit to notice what has happened in 
regard to this inquiry. For in the case of all discoveries the 
results of previous labours that have been handed down from 
others have been advanced bit by bit by those who have taken 
them on, whereas the original discoveries generally make 
advance that is small at first though much more useful than the 
development which later springs out of them. For it may be that 
in everything, as the saying is, 'the first start is the main part': 
and for this reason also it is the most difficult; for in proportion 
as it is most potent in its influence, so it is smallest in its 
compass and therefore most difficult to see: whereas when this 
is once discovered, it is easier to add and develop the remainder 
in connexion with it. This is in fact what has happened in 
regard to rhetorical speeches and to practically all the other 
arts: for those who discovered the beginnings of them advanced 
them in all only a little way, whereas the celebrities of to-day 
are the heirs (so to speak) of a long succession of men who have 
advanced them bit by bit, and so have developed them to their 
present form, Tisias coming next after the first founders, then 
Thrasymachus after Tisias, and Theodorus next to him, while 
several people have made their several contributions to it: and 
therefore it is not to be wondered at that the art has attained 
considerable dimensions. Of this inquiry, on the other hand, it 
was not the case that part of the work had been thoroughly 
done before, while part had not. Nothing existed at all. For the 
training given by the paid professors of contentious arguments 
was like the treatment of the matter by Gorgias. For they used 
to hand out speeches to be learned by heart, some rhetorical, 
others in the form of question and answer, each side supposing 
that their arguments on either side generally fall among them. 
And therefore the teaching they gave their pupils was ready but 
rough. For they used to suppose that they trained people by 
imparting to them not the art but its products, as though any 



600 



one professing that he would impart a form of knowledge to 
obviate any pain in the feet, were then not to teach a man the 
art of shoe-making or the sources whence he can acquire 
anything of the kind, but were to present him with several kinds 
of shoes of all sorts: for he has helped him to meet his need, but 
has not imparted an art to him. Moreover, on the subject of 
Rhetoric there exists much that has been said long ago, whereas 
on the subject of reasoning we had nothing else of an earlier 
date to speak of at all, but were kept at work for a long time in 
experimental researches. If, then, it seems to you after 
inspection that, such being the situation as it existed at the 
start, our investigation is in a satisfactory condition compared 
with the other inquiries that have been developed by tradition, 
there must remain for all of you, or for our students, the task of 
extending us your pardon for the shortcomings of the inquiry, 
and for the discoveries thereof your warm thanks. 



601 



Aristotle - Physics 
[Translated by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye] 



Book I 



When the objects of an inquiry, in any department, have 
principles, conditions, or elements, it is through acquaintance 
with these that knowledge, that is to say scientific knowledge, is 
attained. For we do not think that we know a thing until we are 
acquainted with its primary conditions or first principles, and 
have carried our analysis as far as its simplest elements. Plainly 
therefore in the science of Nature, as in other branches of study, 
our first task will be to try to determine what relates to its 
principles. 

The natural way of doing this is to start from the things which 
are more knowable and obvious to us and proceed towards 
those which are clearer and more knowable by nature; for the 
same things are not 'knowable relatively to us' and 'knowable' 
without qualification. So in the present inquiry we must follow 
this method and advance from what is more obscure by nature, 
but clearer to us, towards what is more clear and more 
knowable by nature. 

Now what is to us plain and obvious at first is rather confused 
masses, the elements and principles of which become known to 
us later by analysis. Thus we must advance from generalities to 
particulars; for it is a whole that is best known to sense- 
perception, and a generality is a kind of whole, comprehending 



602 



many things within it, like parts. Much the same thing happens 
in the relation of the name to the formula. A name, e.g. 'round', 
means vaguely a sort of whole: its definition analyses this into 
its particular senses. Similarly a child begins by calling all men 
'father', and all women 'mother', but later on distinguishes each 
of them. 



The principles in question must be either (a) one or (b) more 
than one. If (a) one, it must be either (i) motionless, as 
Parmenides and Melissus assert, or (ii) in motion, as the 
physicists hold, some declaring air to be the first principle, 
others water. If (b) more than one, then either (i) a finite or (ii) 
an infinite plurality. If (i) finite (but more than one), then either 
two or three or four or some other number. If (ii) infinite, then 
either as Democritus believed one in kind, but differing in shape 
or form; or different in kind and even contrary. 

A similar inquiry is made by those who inquire into the number 
of existents: for they inquire whether the ultimate constituents 
of existing things are one or many, and if many, whether a finite 
or an infinite plurality. So they too are inquiring whether the 
principle or element is one or many. 

Now to investigate whether Being is one and motionless is not a 
contribution to the science of Nature. For just as the geometer 
has nothing more to say to one who denies the principles of his 
science - this being a question for a different science or for or 
common to all - so a man investigating principles cannot argue 
with one who denies their existence. For if Being is just one, and 
one in the way mentioned, there is a principle no longer, since a 
principle must be the principle of some thing or things. 



603 



To inquire therefore whether Being is one in this sense would be 
like arguing against any other position maintained for the sake 
of argument (such as the Heraclitean thesis, or such a thesis as 
that Being is one man) or like refuting a merely contentious 
argument - a description which applies to the arguments both 
of Melissus and of Parmenides: their premisses are false and 
their conclusions do not follow. Or rather the argument of 
Melissus is gross and palpable and offers no difficulty at all: 
accept one ridiculous proposition and the rest follows - a simple 
enough proceeding. 

We physicists, on the other hand, must take for granted that the 
things that exist by nature are, either all or some of them, in 
motion which is indeed made plain by induction. Moreover, no 
man of science is bound to solve every kind of difficulty that 
may be raised, but only as many as are drawn falsely from the 
principles of the science: it is not our business to refute those 
that do not arise in this way: just as it is the duty of the 
geometer to refute the squaring of the circle by means of 
segments, but it is not his duty to refute Antiphon's proof. At 
the same time the holders of the theory of which we are 
speaking do incidentally raise physical questions, though 
Nature is not their subject: so it will perhaps be as well to spend 
a few words on them, especially as the inquiry is not without 
scientific interest. 

The most pertinent question with which to begin will be this: In 
what sense is it asserted that all things are one? For 'is' is used 
in many senses. Do they mean that all things 'are' substance or 
quantities or qualities? And, further, are all things one 
substance - one man, one horse, or one soul - or quality and 
that one and the same - white or hot or something of the kind? 
These are all very different doctrines and all impossible to 
maintain. 



604 



For if both substance and quantity and quality are, then, 
whether these exist independently of each other or not, Being 
will be many. 

If on the other hand it is asserted that all things are quality or 
quantity, then, whether substance exists or not, an absurdity 
results, if the impossible can properly be called absurd. For none 
of the others can exist independently: substance alone is 
independent: for everything is predicated of substance as 
subject. Now Melissus says that Being is infinite. It is then a 
quantity. For the infinite is in the category of quantity, whereas 
substance or quality or affection cannot be infinite except 
through a concomitant attribute, that is, if at the same time 
they are also quantities. For to define the infinite you must use 
quantity in your formula, but not substance or quality. If then 
Being is both substance and quantity, it is two, not one: if only 
substance, it is not infinite and has no magnitude; for to have 
that it will have to be a quantity. 

Again, 'one' itself, no less than 'being', is used in many senses, 
so we must consider in what sense the word is used when it is 
said that the All is one. 

Now we say that (a) the continuous is one or that (b) the 
indivisible is one, or (c) things are said to be 'one', when their 
essence is one and the same, as 'liquor' and 'drink'. 

If (a) their One is one in the sense of continuous, it is many, for 
the continuous is divisible ad infinitum. 

There is, indeed, a difficulty about part and whole, perhaps not 
relevant to the present argument, yet deserving consideration 
on its own account - namely, whether the part and the whole 
are one or more than one, and how they can be one or many, 
and, if they are more than one, in what sense they are more 
than one. (Similarly with the parts of wholes which are not 



605 



continuous.) Further, if each of the two parts is indivisibly one 
with the whole, the difficulty arises that they will be indivisibly 
one with each other also. 

But to proceed: If (b) their One is one as indivisible, nothing will 
have quantity or quality, and so the one will not be infinite, as 
Melissus says - nor, indeed, limited, as Parmenides says, for 
though the limit is indivisible, the limited is not. 

But if (c) all things are one in the sense of having the same 
definition, like 'raiment' and 'dress', then it turns out that they 
are maintaining the Heraclitean doctrine, for it will be the same 
thing 'to be good' and 'to be bad', and 'to be good' and 'to be not 
good', and so the same thing will be 'good' and 'not good', and 
man and horse; in fact, their view will be, not that all things are 
one, but that they are nothing; and that 'to be of such-and-such 
a quality' is the same as 'to be of such-and-such a size'. 

Even the more recent of the ancient thinkers were in a pother 
lest the same thing should turn out in their hands both one and 
many. So some, like Lycophron, were led to omit 'is', others to 
change the mode of expression and say 'the man has been 
whitened' instead of 'is white', and 'walks' instead of 'is 
walking', for fear that if they added the word 'is' they should be 
making the one to be many - as if 'one' and 'being' were always 
used in one and the same sense. What 'is' may be many either 
in definition (for example 'to be white' is one thing, 'to be 
musical' another, yet the same thing be both, so the one is 
many) or by division, as the whole and its parts. On this point, 
indeed, they were already getting into difficulties and admitted 
that the one was many - as if there was any difficulty about the 
same thing being both one and many, provided that these are 
not opposites; for 'one' may mean either 'potentially one' or 
'actually one'. 



606 



If, then, we approach the thesis in this way it seems impossible 
for all things to be one. Further, the arguments they use to prove 
their position are not difficult to expose. For both of them 
reason contentiously - I mean both Melissus and Parmenides. 
[Their premisses are false and their conclusions do not follow. 
Or rather the argument of Melissus is gross and palpable and 
offers no difficulty at all: admit one ridiculous proposition and 
the rest follows - a simple enough proceeding.] The fallacy of 
Melissus is obvious. For he supposes that the assumption 'what 
has come into being always has a beginning' justifies the 
assumption 'what has not come into being has no beginning'. 
Then this also is absurd, that in every case there should be a 
beginning of the thing - not of the time and not only in the case 
of coming to be in the full sense but also in the case of coming 
to have a quality - as if change never took place suddenly. 
Again, does it follow that Being, if one, is motionless? Why 
should it not move, the whole of it within itself, as parts of it do 
which are unities, e.g. this water? Again, why is qualitative 
change impossible? But, further, Being cannot be one in form, 
though it may be in what it is made of. (Even some of the 
physicists hold it to be one in the latter way, though not in the 
former.) Man obviously differs from horse in form, and 
contraries from each other. 

The same kind of argument holds good against Parmenides 
also, besides any that may apply specially to his view: the 
answer to him being that 'this is not true' and 'that does not 
follow'. His assumption that one is used in a single sense only is 
false, because it is used in several. His conclusion does not 
follow, because if we take only white things, and if 'white' has a 
single meaning, none the less what is white will be many and 
not one. For what is white will not be one either in the sense 
that it is continuous or in the sense that it must be defined in 



607 



only one way. 'Whiteness' will be different from 'what has 
whiteness'. Nor does this mean that there is anything that can 
exist separately, over and above what is white. For 'whiteness' 
and 'that which is white' differ in definition, not in the sense 
that they are things which can exist apart from each other. But 
Parmenides had not come in sight of this distinction. 

It is necessary for him, then, to assume not only that 'being' has 
the same meaning, of whatever it is predicated, but further that 
it means (1) what just is and (2) what is just one. 

It must be so, for (1) an attribute is predicated of some subject, 
so that the subject to which 'being' is attributed will not be, as it 
is something different from 'being'. Something, therefore, which 
is not will be. Hence 'substance' will not be a predicate of 
anything else. For the subject cannot be a being, unless 'being' 
means several things, in such a way that each is something. But 
ex hypothesi 'being' means only one thing. 

If, then, 'substance' is not attributed to anything, but other 
things are attributed to it, how does 'substance' mean what is 
rather than what is not? For suppose that 'substance' is also 
'white'. Since the definition of the latter is different (for being 
cannot even be attributed to white, as nothing is which is not 
'substance'), it follows that 'white' is not-being - and that not in 
the sense of a particular not-being, but in the sense that it is not 
at all. Hence 'substance' is not; for it is true to say that it is 
white, which we found to mean not-being. If to avoid this we 
say that even 'white' means substance, it follows that 'being' 
has more than one meaning. 

In particular, then, Being will not have magnitude, if it is 
substance. For each of the two parts must he in a different 
sense. 



608 



(2) Substance is plainly divisible into other substances, if we 
consider the mere nature of a definition. For instance, if 'man' is 
a substance, 'animal' and 'biped' must also be substances. For if 
not substances, they must be attributes - and if attributes, 
attributes either of (a) man or of (b) some other subject. But 
neither is possible. 

(a) An attribute is either that which may or may not belong to 
the subject or that in whose definition the subject of which it is 
an attribute is involved. Thus 'sitting' is an example of a 
separable attribute, while 'snubness' contains the definition of 
'nose', to which we attribute snubness. Further, the definition of 
the whole is not contained in the definitions of the contents or 
elements of the definitory formula; that of 'man' for instance in 
'biped', or that of 'white man' in 'white'. If then this is so, and if 
'biped' is supposed to be an attribute of 'man', it must be either 
separable, so that 'man' might possibly not be 'biped', or the 
definition of 'man' must come into the definition of 'biped' - 
which is impossible, as the converse is the case. 

(b) If, on the other hand, we suppose that 'biped' and 'animal' 
are attributes not of man but of something else, and are not 
each of them a substance, then 'man' too will be an attribute of 
something else. But we must assume that substance is not the 
attribute of anything, that the subject of which both 'biped' and 
'animal' and each separately are predicated is the subject also 
of the complex 'biped animal'. 

Are we then to say that the All is composed of indivisible 
substances? Some thinkers did, in point of fact, give way to both 
arguments. To the argument that all things are one if being 
means one thing, they conceded that not-being is; to that from 
bisection, they yielded by positing atomic magnitudes. But 
obviously it is not true that if being means one thing, and 
cannot at the same time mean the contradictory of this, there 



609 



will be nothing which is not, for even if what is not cannot be 
without qualification, there is no reason why it should not be a 
particular not-being. To say that all things will be one, if there is 
nothing besides Being itself, is absurd. For who understands 
'being itself to be anything but a particular substance? But if 
this is so, there is nothing to prevent there being many beings, 
as has been said. 

It is, then, clearly impossible for Being to be one in this sense. 



The physicists on the other hand have two modes of 
explanation. 

The first set make the underlying body one either one of the 
three or something else which is denser than fire and rarer than 
air then generate everything else from this, and obtain 
multiplicity by condensation and rarefaction. Now these are 
contraries, which may be generalized into 'excess and defect'. 
(Compare Plato's 'Great and Small' - except that he make these 
his matter, the one his form, while the others treat the one 
which underlies as matter and the contraries as differentiae, i.e. 
forms). 

The second set assert that the contrarieties are contained in the 
one and emerge from it by segregation, for example 
Anaximander and also all those who assert that 'what is' is one 
and many, like Empedocles and Anaxagoras; for they too 
produce other things from their mixture by segregation. These 
differ, however, from each other in that the former imagines a 
cycle of such changes, the latter a single series. Anaxagoras 
again made both his 'homceomerous' substances and his 



610 



contraries infinite in multitude, whereas Empedocles posits 
only the so-called elements. 

The theory of Anaxagoras that the principles are infinite in 
multitude was probably due to his acceptance of the common 
opinion of the physicists that nothing comes into being from 
not-being. For this is the reason why they use the phrase 'all 
things were together' and the coming into being of such and 
such a kind of thing is reduced to change of quality, while some 
spoke of combination and separation. Moreover, the fact that 
the contraries proceed from each other led them to the 
conclusion. The one, they reasoned, must have already existed 
in the other; for since everything that comes into being must 
arise either from what is or from what is not, and it is 
impossible for it to arise from what is not (on this point all the 
physicists agree), they thought that the truth of the alternative 
necessarily followed, namely that things come into being out of 
existent things, i.e. out of things already present, but 
imperceptible to our senses because of the smallness of their 
bulk. So they assert that everything has been mixed in every, 
thing, because they saw everything arising out of everything. 
But things, as they say, appear different from one another and 
receive different names according to the nature of the particles 
which are numerically predominant among the innumerable 
constituents of the mixture. For nothing, they say, is purely and 
entirely white or black or sweet, bone or flesh, but the nature of 
a thing is held to be that of which it contains the most. 

Now (1) the infinite qua infinite is unknowable, so that what is 
infinite in multitude or size is unknowable in quantity, and 
what is infinite in variety of kind is unknowable in quality. But 
the principles in question are infinite both in multitude and in 
kind. Therefore it is impossible to know things which are 
composed of them; for it is when we know the nature and 



611 



quantity of its components that we suppose we know a 
complex. 

Further (2) if the parts of a whole may be of any size in the 
direction either of greatness or of smallness (by 'parts' I mean 
components into which a whole can be divided and which are 
actually present in it), it is necessary that the whole thing itself 
may be of any size. Clearly, therefore, since it is impossible for 
an animal or plant to be indefinitely big or small, neither can its 
parts be such, or the whole will be the same. But flesh, bone, 
and the like are the parts of animals, and the fruits are the parts 
of plants. Hence it is obvious that neither flesh, bone, nor any 
such thing can be of indefinite size in the direction either of the 
greater or of the less. 

Again (3) according to the theory all such things are already 
present in one another and do not come into being but are 
constituents which are separated out, and a thing receives its 
designation from its chief constituent. Further, anything may 
come out of anything - water by segregation from flesh and 
flesh from water. Hence, since every finite body is exhausted by 
the repeated abstraction of a finite body, it seems obviously to 
follow that everything cannot subsist in everything else. For let 
flesh be extracted from water and again more flesh be produced 
from the remainder by repeating the process of separation: 
then, even though the quantity separated out will continually 
decrease, still it will not fall below a certain magnitude. If, 
therefore, the process comes to an end, everything will not be in 
everything else (for there will be no flesh in the remaining 
water); if on the other hand it does not, and further extraction is 
always possible, there will be an infinite multitude of finite 
equal particles in a finite quantity - which is impossible. 
Another proof may be added: Since every body must diminish in 
size when something is taken from it, and flesh is quantitatively 
definite in respect both of greatness and smallness, it is clear 



612 



that from the minimum quantity of flesh no body can be 
separated out; for the flesh left would be less than the 
minimum of flesh. 

Lastly (4) in each of his infinite bodies there would be already 
present infinite flesh and blood and brain - having a distinct 
existence, however, from one another, and no less real than the 
infinite bodies, and each infinite: which is contrary to reason. 

The statement that complete separation never will take place is 
correct enough, though Anaxagoras is not fully aware of what it 
means. For affections are indeed inseparable. If then colours 
and states had entered into the mixture, and if separation took 
place, there would be a 'white' or a 'healthy' which was nothing 
but white or healthy, i.e. was not the predicate of a subject. So 
his 'Mind' is an absurd person aiming at the impossible, if he is 
supposed to wish to separate them, and it is impossible to do 
so, both in respect of quantity and of quality - of quantity, 
because there is no minimum magnitude, and of quality, 
because affections are inseparable. 

Nor is Anaxagoras right about the coming to be of homogeneous 
bodies. It is true there is a sense in which clay is divided into 
pieces of clay, but there is another in which it is not. Water and 
air are, and are generated 'from' each other, but not in the way 
in which bricks come 'from' a house and again a house 'from' 
bricks; and it is better to assume a smaller and finite number of 
principles, as Empedocles does. 



All thinkers then agree in making the contraries principles, both 
those who describe the All as one and unmoved (for even 



613 



Parmenides treats hot and cold as principles under the names 
of fire and earth) and those too who use the rare and the dense. 
The same is true of Democritus also, with his plenum and void, 
both of which exist, be says, the one as being, the other as not- 
being. Again he speaks of differences in position, shape, and 
order, and these are genera of which the species are contraries, 
namely, of position, above and below, before and behind; of 
shape, angular and angle-less, straight and round. 

It is plain then that they all in one way or another identify the 
contraries with the principles. And with good reason. For first 
principles must not be derived from one another nor from 
anything else, while everything has to be derived from them. 
But these conditions are fulfilled by the primary contraries, 
which are not derived from anything else because they are 
primary, nor from each other because they are contraries. 

But we must see how this can be arrived at as a reasoned result, 
as well as in the way just indicated. 

Our first presupposition must be that in nature nothing acts on, 
or is acted on by, any other thing at random, nor may anything 
come from anything else, unless we mean that it does so in 
virtue of a concomitant attribute. For how could 'white' come 
from 'musical', unless 'musical' happened to be an attribute of 
the not-white or of the black? No, 'white' comes from 'not- 
white' - and not from any 'not-white', but from black or some 
intermediate colour. Similarly, 'musical' comes to be from 'not- 
musical', but not from any thing other than musical, but from 
'unmusical' or any intermediate state there may be. 

Nor again do things pass into the first chance thing; 'white' 
does not pass into 'musical' (except, it may be, in virtue of a 
concomitant attribute), but into 'not-white' - and not into any 
chance thing which is not white, but into black or an 
intermediate colour; 'musical' passes into 'not-musical' - and 



614 



not into any chance thing other than musical, but into 
'unmusical' or any intermediate state there may be. 

The same holds of other things also: even things which are not 
simple but complex follow the same principle, but the opposite 
state has not received a name, so we fail to notice the fact. What 
is in tune must come from what is not in tune, and vice versa; 
the tuned passes into untunedness - and not into any 
untunedness, but into the corresponding opposite. It does not 
matter whether we take attunement, order, or composition for 
our illustration; the principle is obviously the same in all, and in 
fact applies equally to the production of a house, a statue, or 
any other complex. A house comes from certain things in a 
certain state of separation instead of conjunction, a statue (or 
any other thing that has been shaped) from shapelessness - 
each of these objects being partly order and partly composition. 

If then this is true, everything that comes to be or passes away 
from, or passes into, its contrary or an intermediate state. But 
the intermediates are derived from the contraries - colours, for 
instance, from black and white. Everything, therefore, that 
comes to be by a natural process is either a contrary or a 
product of contraries. 

Up to this point we have practically had most of the other 
writers on the subject with us, as I have said already: for all of 
them identify their elements, and what they call their 
principles, with the contraries, giving no reason indeed for the 
theory, but contrained as it were by the truth itself. They differ, 
however, from one another in that some assume contraries 
which are more primary, others contraries which are less so: 
some those more knowable in the order of explanation, others 
those more familiar to sense. For some make hot and cold, or 
again moist and dry, the conditions of becoming; while others 



615 



make odd and even, or again Love and Strife; and these differ 
from each other in the way mentioned. 

Hence their principles are in one sense the same, in another 
different; different certainly, as indeed most people think, but 
the same inasmuch as they are analogous; for all are taken from 
the same table of columns, some of the pairs being wider, 
others narrower in extent. In this way then their theories are 
both the same and different, some better, some worse; some, as 
I have said, take as their contraries what is more knowable in 
the order of explanation, others what is more familiar to sense. 
(The universal is more knowable in the order of explanation, the 
particular in the order of sense: for explanation has to do with 
the universal, sense with the particular.) 'The great and the 
small', for example, belong to the former class, 'the dense and 
the rare' to the latter. 

It is clear then that our principles must be contraries. 



The next question is whether the principles are two or three or 
more in number. 

One they cannot be, for there cannot be one contrary. Nor can 
they be innumerable, because, if so, Being will not be knowable: 
and in any one genus there is only one contrariety, and 
substance is one genus: also a finite number is sufficient, and a 
finite number, such as the principles of Empedocles, is better 
than an infinite multitude; for Empedocles professes to obtain 
from his principles all that Anaxagoras obtains from his 
innumerable principles. Lastly, some contraries are more 
primary than others, and some arise from others - for example 



616 



sweet and bitter, white and black - whereas the principles must 
always remain principles. 

This will suffice to show that the principles are neither one nor 
innumerable. 

Granted, then, that they are a limited number, it is plausible to 
suppose them more than two. For it is difficult to see how either 
density should be of such a nature as to act in any way on rarity 
or rarity on density. The same is true of any other pair of 
contraries; for Love does not gather Strife together and make 
things out of it, nor does Strife make anything out of Love, but 
both act on a third thing different from both. Some indeed 
assume more than one such thing from which they construct 
the world of nature. 

Other objections to the view that it is not necessary to assume a 
third principle as a substratum may be added. (1) We do not find 
that the contraries constitute the substance of any thing. But 
what is a first principle ought not to be the predicate of any 
subject. If it were, there would be a principle of the supposed 
principle: for the subject is a principle, and prior presumably to 
what is predicated of it. Again (2) we hold that a substance is 
not contrary to another substance. How then can substance be 
derived from what are not substances? Or how can non- 
substances be prior to substance? 

If then we accept both the former argument and this one, we 
must, to preserve both, assume a third somewhat as the 
substratum of the contraries, such as is spoken of by those who 
describe the All as one nature - water or fire or what is 
intermediate between them. What is intermediate seems 
preferable; for fire, earth, air, and water are already involved 
with pairs of contraries. There is, therefore, much to be said for 
those who make the underlying substance different from these 
four; of the rest, the next best choice is air, as presenting 



617 



sensible differences in a less degree than the others; and after 
air, water. All, however, agree in this, that they differentiate their 
One by means of the contraries, such as density and rarity and 
more and less, which may of course be generalized, as has 
already been said into excess and defect. Indeed this doctrine 
too (that the One and excess and defect are the principles of 
things) would appear to be of old standing, though in different 
forms; for the early thinkers made the two the active and the 
one the passive principle, whereas some of the more recent 
maintain the reverse. 

To suppose then that the elements are three in number would 
seem, from these and similar considerations, a plausible view, 
as I said before. On the other hand, the view that they are more 
than three in number would seem to be untenable. 

For the one substratum is sufficient to be acted on; but if we 
have four contraries, there will be two contrarieties, and we 
shall have to suppose an intermediate nature for each pair 
separately. If, on the other hand, the contrarieties, being two, 
can generate from each other, the second contrariety will be 
superfluous. Moreover, it is impossible that there should be 
more than one primary contrariety. For substance is a single 
genus of being, so that the principles can differ only as prior 
and posterior, not in genus; in a single genus there is always a 
single contrariety, all the other contrarieties in it being held to 
be reducible to one. 

It is clear then that the number of elements is neither one nor 
more than two or three; but whether two or three is, as I said, a 
question of considerable difficulty. 



618 



We will now give our own account, approaching the question 
first with reference to becoming in its widest sense: for we shall 
be following the natural order of inquiry if we speak first of 
common characteristics, and then investigate the 
characteristics of special cases. 

We say that one thing comes to be from another thing, and one 
sort of thing from another sort of thing, both in the case of 
simple and of complex things. I mean the following. We can say 
(1) 'man becomes musical', (2) what is 'not-musical becomes 
musical', or (3), the 'not-musical man becomes a musical man'. 
Now what becomes in (1) and (2) - 'man' and 'not musical' - I 
call simple, and what each becomes - 'musical' - simple also. 
But when (3) we say the 'not-musical man becomes a musical 
man', both what becomes and what it becomes are complex. 

As regards one of these simple 'things that become' we say not 
only 'this becomes so-and-so', but also 'from being this, comes 
to be so-and-so', as 'from being not-musical comes to be 
musical'; as regards the other we do not say this in all cases, as 
we do not say (1) 'from being a man he came to be musical' but 
only 'the man became musical'. 

When a 'simple' thing is said to become something, in one case 
(1) it survives through the process, in the other (2) it does not. 
For man remains a man and is such even when he becomes 
musical, whereas what is not musical or is unmusical does not 
continue to exist, either simply or combined with the subject. 

These distinctions drawn, one can gather from surveying the 
various cases of becoming in the way we are describing that, as 
we say, there must always be an underlying something, namely 
that which becomes, and that this, though always one 
numerically, in form at least is not one. (By that I mean that it 



619 



can be described in different ways.) For 'to be man' is not the 
same as 'to be unmusical'. One part survives, the other does 
not: what is not an opposite survives (for 'man' survives), but 
'not-musical' or 'unmusical' does not survive, nor does the 
compound of the two, namely 'unmusical man'. 

We speak of 'becoming that from this' instead of 'this becoming 
that' more in the case of what does not survive the change - 
'becoming musical from unmusical', not 'from man' - but there 
are exceptions, as we sometimes use the latter form of 
expression even of what survives; we speak of 'a statue coming 
to be from bronze', not of the 'bronze becoming a statue'. The 
change, however, from an opposite which does not survive is 
described indifferently in both ways, 'becoming that from this' 
or 'this becoming that'. We say both that 'the unmusical 
becomes musical', and that 'from unmusical he becomes 
musical'. And so both forms are used of the complex, 'becoming 
a musical man from an unmusical man', and unmusical man 
becoming a musical man'. 

But there are different senses of 'coming to be'. In some cases 
we do not use the expression 'come to be', but 'come to be so- 
and-so'. Only substances are said to 'come to be' in the 
unqualified sense. 

Now in all cases other than substance it is plain that there must 
be some subject, namely, that which becomes. For we know that 
when a thing comes to be of such a quantity or quality or in 
such a relation, time, or place, a subject is always presupposed, 
since substance alone is not predicated of another subject, but 
everything else of substance. 

But that substances too, and anything else that can be said 'to 
be' without qualification, come to be from some substratum, 
will appear on examination. For we find in every case 



620 



something that underlies from which proceeds that which 
comes to be; for instance, animals and plants from seed. 

Generally things which come to be, come to be in different 
ways: (1) by change of shape, as a statue; (2) by addition, as 
things which grow; (3) by taking away, as the Hermes from the 
stone; (4) by putting together, as a house; (5) by alteration, as 
things which 'turn' in respect of their material substance. 

It is plain that these are all cases of coming to be from a 
substratum. 

Thus, clearly, from what has been said, whatever comes to be is 
always complex. There is, on the one hand, (a) something which 
comes into existence, and again (b) something which becomes 
that - the latter (b) in two senses, either the subject or the 
opposite. By the 'opposite' I mean the 'unmusical', by the 
'subject' 'man', and similarly I call the absence of shape or form 
or order the 'opposite', and the bronze or stone or gold the 
'subject'. 

Plainly then, if there are conditions and principles which 
constitute natural objects and from which they primarily are or 
have come to be - have come to be, I mean, what each is said to 
be in its essential nature, not what each is in respect of a 
concomitant attribute - plainly, I say, everything comes to be 
from both subject and form. For 'musical man' is composed (in a 
way) of 'man' and 'musical': you can analyse it into the 
definitions of its elements. It is clear then that what comes to 
be will come to be from these elements. 

Now the subject is one numerically, though it is two in form. 
(For it is the man, the gold - the 'matter' generally - that is 
counted, for it is more of the nature of a 'this', and what comes 
to be does not come from it in virtue of a concomitant attribute; 
the privation, on the other hand, and the contrary are incidental 



621 



in the process.) And the positive form is one - the order, the 
acquired art of music, or any similar predicate. 

There is a sense, therefore, in which we must declare the 
principles to be two, and a sense in which they are three; a 
sense in which the contraries are the principles - say for 
example the musical and the unmusical, the hot and the cold, 
the tuned and the untuned - and a sense in which they are not, 
since it is impossible for the contraries to be acted on by each 
other. But this difficulty also is solved by the fact that the 
substratum is different from the contraries, for it is itself not a 
contrary. The principles therefore are, in a way, not more in 
number than the contraries, but as it were two, nor yet precisely 
two, since there is a difference of essential nature, but three. For 
'to be man' is different from 'to be unmusical', and 'to be 
unformed' from 'to be bronze'. 

We have now stated the number of the principles of natural 
objects which are subject to generation, and how the number is 
reached: and it is clear that there must be a substratum for the 
contraries, and that the contraries must be two. (Yet in another 
way of putting it this is not necessary, as one of the contraries 
will serve to effect the change by its successive absence and 
presence.) 

The underlying nature is an object of scientific knowledge, by 
an analogy. For as the bronze is to the statue, the wood to the 
bed, or the matter and the formless before receiving form to any 
thing which has form, so is the underlying nature to substance, 
i.e. the 'this' or existent. 

This then is one principle (though not one or existent in the 
same sense as the 'this'), and the definition was one as we 
agreed; then further there is its contrary, the privation. In what 
sense these are two, and in what sense more, has been stated 
above. Briefly, we explained first that only the contraries were 



622 



principles, and later that a substratum was indispensable, and 
that the principles were three; our last statement has elucidated 
the difference between the contraries, the mutual relation of 
the principles, and the nature of the substratum. Whether the 
form or the substratum is the essential nature of a physical 
object is not yet clear. But that the principles are three, and in 
what sense, and the way in which each is a principle, is clear. 

So much then for the question of the number and the nature of 
the principles. 



8 

We will now proceed to show that the difficulty of the early 
thinkers, as well as our own, is solved in this way alone. 

The first of those who studied science were misled in their 
search for truth and the nature of things by their inexperience, 
which as it were thrust them into another path. So they say that 
none of the things that are either comes to be or passes out of 
existence, because what comes to be must do so either from 
what is or from what is not, both of which are impossible. For 
what is cannot come to be (because it is already), and from what 
is not nothing could have come to be (because something must 
be present as a substratum). So too they exaggerated the 
consequence of this, and went so far as to deny even the 
existence of a plurality of things, maintaining that only Being 
itself is. Such then was their opinion, and such the reason for its 
adoption. 

Our explanation on the other hand is that the phrases 
'something comes to be from what is or from what is not', 'what 
is not or what is does something or has something done to it or 



623 



becomes some particular thing', are to be taken (in the first way 
of putting our explanation) in the same sense as 'a doctor does 
something or has something done to him', 'is or becomes 
something from being a doctor.' These expressions may be 
taken in two senses, and so too, clearly, may 'from being', and 
'being acts or is acted on'. A doctor builds a house, not qua 
doctor, but qua housebuilder, and turns gray, not qua doctor, but 
qua dark-haired. On the other hand he doctors or fails to doctor 
qua doctor. But we are using words most appropriately when we 
say that a doctor does something or undergoes something, or 
becomes something from being a doctor, if he does, undergoes, 
or becomes qua doctor. Clearly then also 'to come to be so-and- 
so from not-being' means 'qua not-being'. 

It was through failure to make this distinction that those 
thinkers gave the matter up, and through this error that they 
went so much farther astray as to suppose that nothing else 
comes to be or exists apart from Being itself, thus doing away 
with all becoming. 

We ourselves are in agreement with them in holding that 
nothing can be said without qualification to come from what is 
not. But nevertheless we maintain that a thing may 'come to be 
from what is not' - that is, in a qualified sense. For a thing 
comes to be from the privation, which in its own nature is not- 
being, - this not surviving as a constituent of the result. Yet this 
causes surprise, and it is thought impossible that something 
should come to be in the way described from what is not. 

In the same way we maintain that nothing comes to be from 
being, and that being does not come to be except in a qualified 
sense. In that way, however, it does, just as animal might come 
to be from animal, and an animal of a certain kind from an 
animal of a certain kind. Thus, suppose a dog to come to be 
from a horse. The dog would then, it is true, come to be from 



624 



animal (as well as from an animal of a certain kind) but not as 
animal, for that is already there. But if anything is to become an 
animal, not in a qualified sense, it will not be from animal: and 
if being, not from being - nor from not-being either, for it has 
been explained that by 'from not being' we mean from not- 
being qua not-being. 

Note further that we do not subvert the principle that 
everything either is or is not. 

This then is one way of solving the difficulty. Another consists 
in pointing out that the same things can be explained in terms 
of potentiality and actuality. But this has been done with 
greater precision elsewhere. So, as we said, the difficulties 
which constrain people to deny the existence of some of the 
things we mentioned are now solved. For it was this reason 
which also caused some of the earlier thinkers to turn so far 
aside from the road which leads to coming to be and passing 
away and change generally. If they had come in sight of this 
nature, all their ignorance would have been dispelled. 



Others, indeed, have apprehended the nature in question, but 
not adequately. 

In the first place they allow that a thing may come to be 
without qualification from not being, accepting on this point 
the statement of Parmenides. Secondly, they think that if the 
substratum is one numerically, it must have also only a single 
potentiality - which is a very different thing. 



625 



Now we distinguish matter and privation, and hold that one of 
these, namely the matter, is not-being only in virtue of an 
attribute which it has, while the privation in its own nature is 
not-being; and that the matter is nearly, in a sense is, substance, 
while the privation in no sense is. They, on the other hand, 
identify their Great and Small alike with not being, and that 
whether they are taken together as one or separately. Their triad 
is therefore of quite a different kind from ours. For they got so 
far as to see that there must be some underlying nature, but 
they make it one - for even if one philosopher makes a dyad of 
it, which he calls Great and Small, the effect is the same, for he 
overlooked the other nature. For the one which persists is a 
joint cause, with the form, of what comes to be - a mother, as it 
were. But the negative part of the contrariety may often seem, if 
you concentrate your attention on it as an evil agent, not to 
exist at all. 

For admitting with them that there is something divine, good, 
and desirable, we hold that there are two other principles, the 
one contrary to it, the other such as of its own nature to desire 
and yearn for it. But the consequence of their view is that the 
contrary desires its wtextinction. Yet the form cannot desire 
itself, for it is not defective; nor can the contrary desire it, for 
contraries are mutually destructive. The truth is that what 
desires the form is matter, as the female desires the male and 
the ugly the beautiful - only the ugly or the female not per se 
but per accidens. 

The matter comes to be and ceases to be in one sense, while in 
another it does not. As that which contains the privation, it 
ceases to be in its own nature, for what ceases to be - the 
privation - is contained within it. But as potentiality it does not 
cease to be in its own nature, but is necessarily outside the 
sphere of becoming and ceasing to be. For if it came to be, 
something must have existed as a primary substratum from 



626 



which it should come and which should persist in it; but this is 
its own special nature, so that it will be before coming to be. (For 
my definition of matter is just this-the primary substratum of 
each thing, from which it comes to be without qualification, and 
which persists in the result.) And if it ceases to be it will pass 
into that at the last, so it will have ceased to be before ceasing 
to be. 

The accurate determination of the first principle in respect of 
form, whether it is one or many and what it is or what they are, 
is the province of the primary type of science; so these 
questions may stand over till then. But of the natural, i.e. 
perishable, forms we shall speak in the expositions which 
follow. 

The above, then, may be taken as sufficient to establish that 
there are principles and what they are and how many there are. 
Now let us make a fresh start and proceed. 



Book II 



Of things that exist, some exist by nature, some from other 
causes. 



627 



'By nature' the animals and their parts exist, and the plants and 
the simple bodies (earth, fire, air, water) - for we say that these 
and the like exist 'by nature'. 

All the things mentioned present a feature in which they differ 
from things which are not constituted by nature. Each of them 
has within itself a principle of motion and of stationariness (in 
respect of place, or of growth and decrease, or by way of 
alteration). On the other hand, a bed and a coat and anything 
else of that sort, qua receiving these designations i.e. in so far as 
they are products of art - have no innate impulse to change. But 
in so far as they happen to be composed of stone or of earth or 
of a mixture of the two, they do have such an impulse, and just 
to that extent which seems to indicate that nature is a source or 
cause of being moved and of being at rest in that to which it 
belongs primarily, in virtue of itself and not in virtue of a 
concomitant attribute. 

I say 'not in virtue of a concomitant attribute', because (for 
instance) a man who is a doctor might cure himself. 
Nevertheless it is not in so far as he is a patient that he 
possesses the art of medicine: it merely has happened that the 
same man is doctor and patient - and that is why these 
attributes are not always found together. So it is with all other 
artificial products. None of them has in itself the source of its 
own production. But while in some cases (for instance houses 
and the other products of manual labour) that principle is in 
something else external to the thing, in others those which may 
cause a change in themselves in virtue of a concomitant 
attribute - it lies in the things themselves (but not in virtue of 
what they are). 

'Nature' then is what has been stated. Things 'have a 
nature'which have a principle of this kind. Each of them is a 



628 



substance; for it is a subject, and nature always implies a 
subject in which it inheres. 

The term 'according to nature' is applied to all these things and 
also to the attributes which belong to them in virtue of what 
they are, for instance the property of fire to be carried upwards 
- which is not a 'nature' nor 'has a nature' but is 'by nature' or 
'according to nature'. 

What nature is, then, and the meaning of the terms 'by nature' 
and 'according to nature', has been stated. That nature exists, it 
would be absurd to try to prove; for it is obvious that there are 
many things of this kind, and to prove what is obvious by what 
is not is the mark of a man who is unable to distinguish what is 
self-evident from what is not. (This state of mind is clearly 
possible. A man blind from birth might reason about colours. 
Presumably therefore such persons must be talking about words 
without any thought to correspond.) 

Some identify the nature or substance of a natural object with 
that immediate constituent of it which taken by itself is without 
arrangement, e.g. the wood is the 'nature' of the bed, and the 
bronze the 'nature' of the statue. 

As an indication of this Antiphon points out that if you planted 
a bed and the rotting wood acquired the power of sending up a 
shoot, it would not be a bed that would come up, but wood - 
which shows that the arrangement in accordance with the rules 
of the art is merely an incidental attribute, whereas the real 
nature is the other, which, further, persists continuously 
through the process of making. 

But if the material of each of these objects has itself the same 
relation to something else, say bronze (or gold) to water, bones 
(or wood) to earth and so on, that (they say) would be their 
nature and essence. Consequently some assert earth, others fire 



629 



or air or water or some or all of these, to be the nature of the 
things that are. For whatever any one of them supposed to have 
this character - whether one thing or more than one thing - this 
or these he declared to be the whole of substance, all else being 
its affections, states, or dispositions. Every such thing they held 
to be eternal (for it could not pass into anything else), but other 
things to come into being and cease to be times without 
number. 

This then is one account of 'nature', namely that it is the 
immediate material substratum of things which have in 
themselves a principle of motion or change. 

Another account is that 'nature' is the shape or form which is 
specified in the definition of the thing. 

For the word 'nature' is applied to what is according to nature 
and the natural in the same way as 'art' is applied to what is 
artistic or a work of art. We should not say in the latter case that 
there is anything artistic about a thing, if it is a bed only 
potentially, not yet having the form of a bed; nor should we call 
it a work of art. The same is true of natural compounds. What is 
potentially flesh or bone has not yet its own 'nature', and does 
not exist until it receives the form specified in the definition, 
which we name in defining what flesh or bone is. Thus in the 
second sense of 'nature' it would be the shape or form (not 
separable except in statement) of things which have in 
themselves a source of motion. (The combination of the two, 
e.g. man, is not 'nature' but 'by nature' or 'natural'.) 

The form indeed is 'nature' rather than the matter; for a thing is 
more properly said to be what it is when it has attained to 
fulfilment than when it exists potentially. Again man is born 
from man, but not bed from bed. That is why people say that 
the figure is not the nature of a bed, but the wood is - if the bed 
sprouted not a bed but wood would come up. But even if the 



630 



figure is art, then on the same principle the shape of man is his 
nature. For man is born from man. 

We also speak of a thing's nature as being exhibited in the 
process of growth by which its nature is attained. The 'nature' in 
this sense is not like 'doctoring', which leads not to the art of 
doctoring but to health. Doctoring must start from the art, not 
lead to it. But it is not in this way that nature (in the one sense) 
is related to nature (in the other). What grows qua growing 
grows from something into something. Into what then does it 
grow? Not into that from which it arose but into that to which it 
tends. The shape then is nature. 

'Shape' and 'nature', it should be added, are in two senses. For 
the privation too is in a way form. But whether in unqualified 
coming to be there is privation, i.e. a contrary to what comes to 
be, we must consider later. 



We have distinguished, then, the different ways in which the 
term 'nature' is used. 

The next point to consider is how the mathematician differs 
from the physicist. Obviously physical bodies contain surfaces 
and volumes, lines and points, and these are the subject-matter 
of mathematics. 

Further, is astronomy different from physics or a department of 
it? It seems absurd that the physicist should be supposed to 
know the nature of sun or moon, but not to know any of their 
essential attributes, particularly as the writers on physics 



631 



obviously do discuss their shape also and whether the earth 
and the world are spherical or not. 

Now the mathematician, though he too treats of these things, 
nevertheless does not treat of them as the limits of a physical 
body; nor does he consider the attributes indicated as the 
attributes of such bodies. That is why he separates them; for in 
thought they are separable from motion, and it makes no 
difference, nor does any falsity result, if they are separated. The 
holders of the theory of Forms do the same, though they are not 
aware of it; for they separate the objects of physics, which are 
less separable than those of mathematics. This becomes plain if 
one tries to state in each of the two cases the definitions of the 
things and of their attributes. 'Odd' and 'even', 'straight' and 
'curved', and likewise 'number', 'line', and 'figure', do not 
involve motion; not so 'flesh' and 'bone' and 'man' - these are 
defined like 'snub nose', not like 'curved'. 

Similar evidence is supplied by the more physical of the 
branches of mathematics, such as optics, harmonics, and 
astronomy. These are in a way the converse of geometry. While 
geometry investigates physical lines but not qua physical, optics 
investigates mathematical lines, but qua physical, not qua 
mathematical. 

Since 'nature' has two senses, the form and the matter, we must 
investigate its objects as we would the essence of snubness. 
That is, such things are neither independent of matter nor can 
be defined in terms of matter only. Here too indeed one might 
raise a difficulty. Since there are two natures, with which is the 
physicist concerned? Or should he investigate the combination 
of the two? But if the combination of the two, then also each 
severally. Does it belong then to the same or to different 
sciences to know each severally? 



632 



If we look at the ancients, physics would to be concerned with 
the matter. (It was only very slightly that Empedocles and 
Democritus touched on the forms and the essence.) 

But if on the other hand art imitates nature, and it is the part of 
the same discipline to know the form and the matter up to a 
point (e.g. the doctor has a knowledge of health and also of bile 
and phlegm, in which health is realized, and the builder both of 
the form of the house and of the matter, namely that it is bricks 
and beams, and so forth): if this is so, it would be the part of 
physics also to know nature in both its senses. 

Again, 'that for the sake of which', or the end, belongs to the 
same department of knowledge as the means. But the nature is 
the end or 'that for the sake of which'. For if a thing undergoes a 
continuous change and there is a stage which is last, this stage 
is the end or 'that for the sake of which'. (That is why the poet 
was carried away into making an absurd statement when he 
said 'he has the end for the sake of which he was born'. For not 
every stage that is last claims to be an end, but only that which 
is best.) 

For the arts make their material (some simply 'make' it, others 
make it serviceable), and we use everything as if it was there for 
our sake. (We also are in a sense an end. 'That for the sake of 
which' has two senses: the distinction is made in our work On 
Philosophy.) The arts, therefore, which govern the matter and 
have knowledge are two, namely the art which uses the product 
and the art which directs the production of it. That is why the 
using art also is in a sense directive; but it differs in that it 
knows the form, whereas the art which is directive as being 
concerned with production knows the matter. For the 
helmsman knows and prescribes what sort of form a helm 
should have, the other from what wood it should be made and 
by means of what operations. In the products of art, however, 



633 



we make the material with a view to the function, whereas in 
the products of nature the matter is there all along. 

Again, matter is a relative term: to each form there corresponds 
a special matter. How far then must the physicist know the 
form or essence? Up to a point, perhaps, as the doctor must 
know sinew or the smith bronze (i.e. until he understands the 
purpose of each): and the physicist is concerned only with 
things whose forms are separable indeed, but do not exist apart 
from matter. Man is begotten by man and by the sun as well. 
The mode of existence and essence of the separable it is the 
business of the primary type of philosophy to define. 



Now that we have established these distinctions, we must 
proceed to consider causes, their character and number. 
Knowledge is the object of our inquiry, and men do not think 
they know a thing till they have grasped the 'why' of (which is 
to grasp its primary cause). So clearly we too must do this as 
regards both coming to be and passing away and every kind of 
physical change, in order that, knowing their principles, we may 
try to refer to these principles each of our problems. 

In one sense, then, (1) that out of which a thing comes to be and 
which persists, is called 'cause', e.g. the bronze of the statue, the 
silver of the bowl, and the genera of which the bronze and the 
silver are species. 

In another sense (2) the form or the archetype, i.e. the 
statement of the essence, and its genera, are called 'causes' (e.g. 
of the octave the relation of 2:1, and generally number), and the 
parts in the definition. 



634 



Again (3) the primary source of the change or coming to rest; 
e.g. the man who gave advice is a cause, the father is cause of 
the child, and generally what makes of what is made and what 
causes change of what is changed. 

Again (4) in the sense of end or 'that for the sake of which' a 
thing is done, e.g. health is the cause of walking about. ('Why is 
he walking about?' we say. 'To be healthy', and, having said that, 
we think we have assigned the cause.) The same is true also of 
all the intermediate steps which are brought about through the 
action of something else as means towards the end, e.g. 
reduction of flesh, purging, drugs, or surgical instruments are 
means towards health. All these things are 'for the sake of the 
end, though they differ from one another in that some are 
activities, others instruments. 

This then perhaps exhausts the number of ways in which the 
term 'cause' is used. 

As the word has several senses, it follows that there are several 
causes of the same thing not merely in virtue of a concomitant 
attribute), e.g. both the art of the sculptor and the bronze are 
causes of the statue. These are causes of the statue qua statue, 
not in virtue of anything else that it may be - only not in the 
same way, the one being the material cause, the other the cause 
whence the motion comes. Some things cause each other 
reciprocally, e.g. hard work causes fitness and vice versa, but 
again not in the same way, but the one as end, the other as the 
origin of change. Further the same thing is the cause of contrary 
results. For that which by its presence brings about one result is 
sometimes blamed for bringing about the contrary by its 
absence. Thus we ascribe the wreck of a ship to the absence of 
the pilot whose presence was the cause of its safety. 

All the causes now mentioned fall into four familiar divisions. 
The letters are the causes of syllables, the material of artificial 



635 



products, fire, &c, of bodies, the parts of the whole, and the 
premisses of the conclusion, in the sense of 'that from which'. 
Of these pairs the one set are causes in the sense of substratum, 
e.g. the parts, the other set in the sense of essence - the whole 
and the combination and the form. But the seed and the doctor 
and the adviser, and generally the maker, are all sources 
whence the change or stationariness originates, while the 
others are causes in the sense of the end or the good of the rest; 
for 'that for the sake of which' means what is best and the end 
of the things that lead up to it. (Whether we say the 'good itself 
or the 'apparent good' makes no difference.) 

Such then is the number and nature of the kinds of cause. 

Now the modes of causation are many, though when brought 
under heads they too can be reduced in number. For 'cause' is 
used in many senses and even within the same kind one may 
be prior to another (e.g. the doctor and the expert are causes of 
health, the relation 2:1 and number of the octave), and always 
what is inclusive to what is particular. Another mode of 
causation is the incidental and its genera, e.g. in one way 
'Polyclitus', in another 'sculptor' is the cause of a statue, 
because 'being Polyclitus' and 'sculptor' are incidentally 
conjoined. Also the classes in which the incidental attribute is 
included; thus 'a man' could be said to be the cause of a statue 
or, generally, 'a living creature'. An incidental attribute too may 
be more or less remote, e.g. suppose that 'a pale man' or 'a 
musical man' were said to be the cause of the statue. 

All causes, both proper and incidental, may be spoken of either 
as potential or as actual; e.g. the cause of a house being built is 
either 'house-builder' or 'house-builder building'. 

Similar distinctions can be made in the things of which the 
causes are causes, e.g. of 'this statue' or of 'statue' or of 'image' 
generally, of 'this bronze' or of 'bronze' or of 'material' generally. 



636 



So too with the incidental attributes. Again we may use a 
complex expression for either and say, e.g. neither 'Polyclitus' 
nor 'sculptor' but 'Polyclitus, sculptor'. 

All these various uses, however, come to six in number, under 
each of which again the usage is twofold. Cause means either 
what is particular or a genus, or an incidental attribute or a 
genus of that, and these either as a complex or each by itself; 
and all six either as actual or as potential. The difference is this 
much, that causes which are actually at work and particular 
exist and cease to exist simultaneously with their effect, e.g. 
this healing person with this being-healed person and that 
house-building man with that being-built house; but this is not 
always true of potential causes - the house and the 
housebuilder do not pass away simultaneously. 

In investigating the cause of each thing it is always necessary to 
seek what is most precise (as also in other things): thus man 
builds because he is a builder, and a builder builds in virtue of 
his art of building. This last cause then is prior: and so generally. 

Further, generic effects should be assigned to generic causes, 
particular effects to particular causes, e.g. statue to sculptor, 
this statue to this sculptor; and powers are relative to possible 
effects, actually operating causes to things which are actually 
being effected. 

This must suffice for our account of the number of causes and 
the modes of causation. 



637 



But chance also and spontaneity are reckoned among causes: 
many things are said both to be and to come to be as a result of 
chance and spontaneity. We must inquire therefore in what 
manner chance and spontaneity are present among the causes 
enumerated, and whether they are the same or different, and 
generally what chance and spontaneity are. 

Some people even question whether they are real or not. They 
say that nothing happens by chance, but that everything which 
we ascribe to chance or spontaneity has some definite cause, 
e.g. coming 'by chance' into the market and finding there a man 
whom one wanted but did not expect to meet is due to one's 
wish to go and buy in the market. Similarly in other cases of 
chance it is always possible, they maintain, to find something 
which is the cause; but not chance, for if chance were real, it 
would seem strange indeed, and the question might be raised, 
why on earth none of the wise men of old in speaking of the 
causes of generation and decay took account of chance; whence 
it would seem that they too did not believe that anything is by 
chance. But there is a further circumstance that is surprising. 
Many things both come to be and are by chance and 
spontaneity, and although know that each of them can be 
ascribed to some cause (as the old argument said which denied 
chance), nevertheless they speak of some of these things as 
happening by chance and others not. For this reason also they 
ought to have at least referred to the matter in some way or 
other. 

Certainly the early physicists found no place for chance among 
the causes which they recognized - love, strife, mind, fire, or the 
like. This is strange, whether they supposed that there is no 
such thing as chance or whether they thought there is but 
omitted to mention it - and that too when they sometimes used 



638 



it, as Empedocles does when he says that the air is not always 
separated into the highest region, but 'as it may chance'. At any 
rate he says in his cosmogony that 'it happened to run that way 
at that time, but it often ran otherwise.' He tells us also that 
most of the parts of animals came to be by chance. 

There are some too who ascribe this heavenly sphere and all 
the worlds to spontaneity. They say that the vortex arose 
spontaneously, i.e. the motion that separated and arranged in 
its present order all that exists. This statement might well cause 
surprise. For they are asserting that chance is not responsible 
for the existence or generation of animals and plants, nature or 
mind or something of the kind being the cause of them (for it is 
not any chance thing that comes from a given seed but an olive 
from one kind and a man from another); and yet at the same 
time they assert that the heavenly sphere and the divinest of 
visible things arose spontaneously, having no such cause as is 
assigned to animals and plants. Yet if this is so, it is a fact which 
deserves to be dwelt upon, and something might well have been 
said about it. For besides the other absurdities of the statement, 
it is the more absurd that people should make it when they see 
nothing coming to be spontaneously in the heavens, but much 
happening by chance among the things which as they say are 
not due to chance; whereas we should have expected exactly 
the opposite. 

Others there are who, indeed, believe that chance is a cause, but 
that it is inscrutable to human intelligence, as being a divine 
thing and full of mystery. 

Thus we must inquire what chance and spontaneity are, 
whether they are the same or different, and how they fit into 
our division of causes. 



639 



First then we observe that some things always come to pass in 
the same way, and others for the most part. It is clearly of 
neither of these that chance is said to be the cause, nor can the 
'effect of chance' be identified with any of the things that come 
to pass by necessity and always, or for the most part. But as 
there is a third class of events besides these two - events which 
all say are 'by chance' - it is plain that there is such a thing as 
chance and spontaneity; for we know that things of this kind 
are due to chance and that things due to chance are of this 
kind. 

But, secondly, some events are for the sake of something, others 
not. Again, some of the former class are in accordance with 
deliberate intention, others not, but both are in the class of 
things which are for the sake of something. Hence it is clear 
that even among the things which are outside the necessary 
and the normal, there are some in connexion withwhich the 
phrase 'for the sake of something' is applicable. (Events that are 
for the sake of something include whatever may be done as a 
result of thought or of nature.) Things of this kind, then, when 
they come to pass incidental are said to be 'by chance'. For just 
as a thing is something either in virtue of itself or incidentally, 
so may it be a cause. For instance, the housebuilding faculty is 
in virtue of itself the cause of a house, whereas the pale or the 
musical is the incidental cause. That which is per se cause of 
the effect is determinate, but the incidental cause is 
indeterminable, for the possible attributes of an individual are 
innumerable. To resume then; when a thing of this kind comes 
to pass among events which are for the sake of something, it is 
said to be spontaneous or by chance. (The distinction between 
the two must be made later - for the present it is sufficient if it 



640 



is plain that both are in the sphere of things done for the sake 
of something.) 

Example: A man is engaged in collecting subscriptions for a 
feast. He would have gone to such and such a place for the 
purpose of getting the money, if he had known. He actually 
went there for another purpose and it was only incidentally that 
he got his money by going there; and this was not due to the 
fact that he went there as a rule or necessarily, nor is the end 
effected (getting the money) a cause present in himself - it 
belongs to the class of things that are intentional and the result 
of intelligent deliberation. It is when these conditions are 
satisfied that the man is said to have gone 'by chance'. If he had 
gone of deliberate purpose and for the sake of this - if he always 
or normally went there when he was collecting payments - he 
would not be said to have gone 'by chance'. 

It is clear then that chance is an incidental cause in the sphere 
of those actions for the sake of something which involve 
purpose. Intelligent reflection, then, and chance are in the same 
sphere, for purpose implies intelligent reflection. 

It is necessary, no doubt, that the causes of what comes to pass 
by chance be indefinite; and that is why chance is supposed to 
belong to the class of the indefinite and to be inscrutable to 
man, and why it might be thought that, in a way, nothing occurs 
by chance. For all these statements are correct, because they are 
well grounded. Things do, in a way, occur by chance, for they 
occur incidentally and chance is an incidental cause. But strictly 
it is not the cause - without qualification - of anything; for 
instance, a housebuilder is the cause of a house; incidentally, a 
fluteplayer may be so. 

And the causes of the man's coming and getting the money 
(when he did not come for the sake of that) are innumerable. He 
may have wished to see somebody or been following somebody 



641 



or avoiding somebody, or may have gone to see a spectacle. 
Thus to say that chance is a thing contrary to rule is correct. For 
'rule' applies to what is always true or true for the most part, 
whereas chance belongs to a third type of event. Hence, to 
conclude, since causes of this kind are indefinite, chance too is 
indefinite. (Yet in some cases one might raise the question 
whether any incidental fact might be the cause of the chance 
occurrence, e.g. of health the fresh air or the sun's heat may be 
the cause, but having had one's hair cut cannot; for some 
incidental causes are more relevant to the effect than others.) 

Chance or fortune is called 'good' when the result is good, 'evil' 
when it is evil. The terms 'good fortune' and 'ill fortune' are 
used when either result is of considerable magnitude. Thus one 
who comes within an ace of some great evil or great good is 
said to be fortunate or unfortunate. The mind affirms the 
essence of the attribute, ignoring the hair's breadth of 
difference. Further, it is with reason that good fortune is 
regarded as unstable; for chance is unstable, as none of the 
things which result from it can be invariable or normal. 

Both are then, as I have said, incidental causes - both chance 
and spontaneity - in the sphere of things which are capable of 
coming to pass not necessarily, nor normally, and with 
reference to such of these as might come to pass for the sake of 
something. 



They differ in that 'spontaneity' is the wider term. Every result 
of chance is from what is spontaneous, but not everything that 
is from what is spontaneous is from chance. 



642 



Chance and what results from chance are appropriate to agents 
that are capable of good fortune and of moral action generally. 
Therefore necessarily chance is in the sphere of moral actions. 
This is indicated by the fact that good fortune is thought to be 
the same, or nearly the same, as happiness, and happiness to be 
a kind of moral action, since it is well-doing. Hence what is not 
capable of moral action cannot do anything by chance. Thus an 
inanimate thing or a lower animal or a child cannot do anything 
by chance, because it is incapable of deliberate intention; nor 
can 'good fortune' or 'ill fortune' be ascribed to them, except 
metaphorically, as Protarchus, for example, said that the stones 
of which altars are made are fortunate because they are held in 
honour, while their fellows are trodden under foot. Even these 
things, however, can in a way be affected by chance, when one 
who is dealing with them does something to them by chance, 
but not otherwise. 

The spontaneous on the other hand is found both in the lower 
animals and in many inanimate objects. We say, for example, 
that the horse came 'spontaneously', because, though his 
coming saved him, he did not come for the sake of safety. Again, 
the tripod fell 'of itself, because, though when it fell it stood on 
its feet so as to serve for a seat, it did not fall for the sake of 
that. 

Hence it is clear that events which (1) belong to the general 
class of things that may come to pass for the sake of something, 

(2) do not come to pass for the sake of what actually results, and 

(3) have an external cause, may be described by the phrase 
'from spontaneity'. These 'spontaneous' events are said to be 
'from chance' if they have the further characteristics of being 
the objects of deliberate intention and due to agents capable of 
that mode of action. This is indicated by the phrase 'in vain', 
which is used when A which is for the sake of B, does not result 
in B. For instance, taking a walk is for the sake of evacuation of 



643 



the bowels; if this does not follow after walking, we say that we 
have walked 'in vain' and that the walking was 'vain'. This 
implies that what is naturally the means to an end is 'in vain', 
when it does not effect the end towards which it was the 
natural means - for it would be absurd for a man to say that he 
had bathed in vain because the sun was not eclipsed, since the 
one was not done with a view to the other. Thus the 
spontaneous is even according to its derivation the case in 
which the thing itself happens in vain. The stone that struck the 
man did not fall for the purpose of striking him; therefore it fell 
spontaneously, because it might have fallen by the action of an 
agent and for the purpose of striking. The difference between 
spontaneity and what results by chance is greatest in things 
that come to be by nature; for when anything comes to be 
contrary to nature, we do not say that it came to be by chance, 
but by spontaneity. Yet strictly this too is different from the 
spontaneous proper; for the cause of the latter is external, that 
of the former internal. 

We have now explained what chance is and what spontaneity 
is, and in what they differ from each other. Both belong to the 
mode of causation 'source of change', for either some natural or 
some intelligent agent is always the cause; but in this sort of 
causation the number of possible causes is infinite. 

Spontaneity and chance are causes of effects which though they 
might result from intelligence or nature, have in fact been 
caused by something incidentally. Now since nothing which is 
incidental is prior to what is per se, it is clear that no incidental 
cause can be prior to a cause per se. Spontaneity and chance, 
therefore, are posterior to intelligence and nature. Hence, 
however true it may be that the heavens are due to spontaneity, 
it will still be true that intelligence and nature will be prior 
causes of this All and of many things in it besides. 



644 



It is clear then that there are causes, and that the number of 
them is what we have stated. The number is the same as that of 
the things comprehended under the question 'why'. The 'why' is 
referred ultimately either (1), in things which do not involve 
motion, e.g. in mathematics, to the 'what' (to the definition of 
'straight line' or 'commensurable', &c), or (2) to what initiated a 
motion, e.g. 'why did they go to war? - because there had been a 
raid'; or (3) we are inquiring 'for the sake of what?' - 'that they 
may rule'; or (4), in the case of things that come into being, we 
are looking for the matter. The causes, therefore, are these and 
so many in number. 

Now, the causes being four, it is the business of the physicist to 
know about them all, and if he refers his problems back to all of 
them, he will assign the 'why' in the way proper to his science - 
the matter, the form, the mover, 'that for the sake of which'. The 
last three often coincide; for the 'what' and 'that for the sake of 
which' are one, while the primary source of motion is the same 
in species as these (for man generates man), and so too, in 
general, are all things which cause movement by being 
themselves moved; and such as are not of this kind are no 
longer inside the province of physics, for they cause motion not 
by possessing motion or a source of motion in themselves, but 
being themselves incapable of motion. Hence there are three 
branches of study, one of things which are incapable of motion, 
the second of things in motion, but indestructible, the third of 
destructible things. 

The question 'why', then, is answered by reference to the 
matter, to the form, and to the primary moving cause. For in 



645 



respect of coming to be it is mostly in this last way that causes 
are investigated - 'what comes to be after what? what was the 
primary agent or patient?' and so at each step of the series. 

Now the principles which cause motion in a physical way are 
two, of which one is not physical, as it has no principle of 
motion in itself. Of this kind is whatever causes movement, not 
being itself moved, such as (1) that which is completely 
unchangeable, the primary reality, and (2) the essence of that 
which is coming to be, i.e. the form; for this is the end or 'that 
for the sake of which'. Hence since nature is for the sake of 
something, we must know this cause also. We must explain the 
'why' in all the senses of the term, namely, (1) that from this 
that will necessarily result ('from this' either without 
qualification or in most cases); (2) that 'this must be so if that is 
to be so' (as the conclusion presupposes the premisses); (3) that 
this was the essence of the thing; and (4) because it is better 
thus (not without qualification, but with reference to the 
essential nature in each case). 



8 

We must explain then (1) that Nature belongs to the class of 
causes which act for the sake of something; (2) about the 
necessary and its place in physical problems, for all writers 
ascribe things to this cause, arguing that since the hot and the 
cold, &c, are of such and such a kind, therefore certain things 
necessarily are and come to be - and if they mention any other 
cause (one his 'friendship and strife', another his 'mind'), it is 
only to touch on it, and then good-bye to it. 

A difficulty presents itself: why should not nature work, not for 
the sake of something, nor because it is better so, but just as the 



646 



sky rains, not in order to make the corn grow, but of necessity? 
What is drawn up must cool, and what has been cooled must 
become water and descend, the result of this being that the 
corn grows. Similarly if a man's crop is spoiled on the threshing- 
floor, the rain did not fall for the sake of this - in order that the 
crop might be spoiled - but that result just followed. Why then 
should it not be the same with the parts in nature, e.g. that our 
teeth should come up of necessity - the front teeth sharp, fitted 
for tearing, the molars broad and useful for grinding down the 
food - since they did not arise for this end, but it was merely a 
coincident result; and so with all other parts in which we 
suppose that there is purpose? Wherever then all the parts 
came about just what they would have been if they had come be 
for an end, such things survived, being organized spontaneously 
in a fitting way; whereas those which grew otherwise perished 
and continue to perish, as Empedocles says his 'man-faced ox- 
progeny' did. 

Such are the arguments (and others of the kind) which may 
cause difficulty on this point. Yet it is impossible that this 
should be the true view. For teeth and all other natural things 
either invariably or normally come about in a given way; but of 
not one of the results of chance or spontaneity is this true. We 
do not ascribe to chance or mere coincidence the frequency of 
rain in winter, but frequent rain in summer we do; nor heat in 
the dog-days, but only if we have it in winter. If then, it is agreed 
that things are either the result of coincidence or for an end, 
and these cannot be the result of coincidence or spontaneity, it 
follows that they must be for an end; and that such things are 
all due to nature even the champions of the theory which is 
before us would agree. Therefore action for an end is present in 
things which come to be and are by nature. 

Further, where a series has a completion, all the preceding steps 
are for the sake of that. Now surely as in intelligent action, so in 



647 



nature; and as in nature, so it is in each action, if nothing 
interferes. Now intelligent action is for the sake of an end; 
therefore the nature of things also is so. Thus if a house, e.g. had 
been a thing made by nature, it would have been made in the 
same way as it is now by art; and if things made by nature were 
made also by art, they would come to be in the same way as by 
nature. Each step then in the series is for the sake of the next; 
and generally art partly completes what nature cannot bring to 
a finish, and partly imitates her. If, therefore, artificial products 
are for the sake of an end, so clearly also are natural products. 
The relation of the later to the earlier terms of the series is the 
same in both. This is most obvious in the animals other than 
man: they make things neither by art nor after inquiry or 
deliberation. Wherefore people discuss whether it is by 
intelligence or by some other faculty that these creatures 
work.spiders, ants, and the like. By gradual advance in this 
direction we come to see clearly that in plants too that is 
produced which is conducive to the end-leaves, e.g. grow to 
provide shade for the fruit. If then it is both by nature and for an 
end that the swallow makes its nest and the spider its web, and 
plants grow leaves for the sake of the fruit and send their roots 
down (not up) for the sake of nourishment, it is plain that this 
kind of cause is operative in things which come to be and are by 
nature. And since 'nature' means two things, the matter and the 
form, of which the latter is the end, and since all the rest is for 
the sake of the end, the form must be the cause in the sense of 
'that for the sake of which'. 

Now mistakes come to pass even in the operations of art: the 
grammarian makes a mistake in writing and the doctor pours 
out the wrong dose. Hence clearly mistakes are possible in the 
operations of nature also. If then in art there are cases in which 
what is rightly produced serves a purpose, and if where 
mistakes occur there was a purpose in what was attempted, 
only it was not attained, so must it be also in natural products, 



648 



and monstrosities will be failures in the purposive effort. Thus 
in the original combinations the 'ox-progeny' if they failed to 
reach a determinate end must have arisen through the 
corruption of some principle corresponding to what is now the 
seed. 

Further, seed must have come into being first, and not 
straightway the animals: the words 'whole-natured first...' must 
have meant seed. 

Again, in plants too we find the relation of means to end, 
though the degree of organization is less. Were there then in 
plants also 'olive-headed vine-progeny', like the 'man-headed 
ox-progeny', or not? An absurd suggestion; yet there must have 
been, if there were such things among animals. 

Moreover, among the seeds anything must have come to be at 
random. But the person who asserts this entirely does away 
with 'nature' and what exists 'by nature'. For those things are 
natural which, by a continuous movement originated from an 
internal principle, arrive at some completion: the same 
completion is not reached from every principle; nor any chance 
completion, but always the tendency in each is towards the 
same end, if there is no impediment. 

The end and the means towards it may come about by chance. 
We say, for instance, that a stranger has come by chance, paid 
the ransom, and gone away, when he does so as if he had come 
for that purpose, though it was not for that that he came. This is 
incidental, for chance is an incidental cause, as I remarked 
before. But when an event takes place always or for the most 
part, it is not incidental or by chance. In natural products the 
sequence is invariable, if there is no impediment. 

It is absurd to suppose that purpose is not present because we 
do not observe the agent deliberating. Art does not deliberate. If 



649 



the ship-building art were in the wood, it would produce the 
same results by nature. If, therefore, purpose is present in art, it 
is present also in nature. The best illustration is a doctor 
doctoring himself: nature is like that. 

It is plain then that nature is a cause, a cause that operates for a 
purpose. 



As regards what is 'of necessity', we must ask whether the 
necessity is 'hypothetical', or 'simple' as well. The current view 
places what is of necessity in the process of production, just as 
if one were to suppose that the wall of a house necessarily 
comes to be because what is heavy is naturally carried 
downwards and what is light to the top, wherefore the stones 
and foundations take the lowest place, with earth above 
because it is lighter, and wood at the top of all as being the 
lightest. Whereas, though the wall does not come to be without 
these, it is not due to these, except as its material cause: it 
comes to be for the sake of sheltering and guarding certain 
things. Similarly in all other things which involve production for 
an end; the product cannot come to be without things which 
have a necessary nature, but it is not due to these (except as its 
material); it comes to be for an end. For instance, why is a saw 
such as it is? To effect so-and-so and for the sake of so-and-so. 
This end, however, cannot be realized unless the saw is made of 
iron. It is, therefore, necessary for it to be of iron, it we are to 
have a saw and perform the operation of sawing. What is 
necessary then, is necessary on a hypothesis; it is not a result 
necessarily determined by antecedents. Necessity is in the 
matter, while 'that for the sake of which' is in the definition. 



650 



Necessity in mathematics is in a way similar to necessity in 
things which come to be through the operation of nature. Since 
a straight line is what it is, it is necessary that the angles of a 
triangle should equal two right angles. But not conversely; 
though if the angles are not equal to two right angles, then the 
straight line is not what it is either. But in things which come to 
be for an end, the reverse is true. If the end is to exist or does 
exist, that also which precedes it will exist or does exist; 
otherwise just as there, if - the conclusion is not true, the 
premiss will not be true, so here the end or 'that for the sake of 
which' will not exist. For this too is itself a starting-point, but of 
the reasoning, not of the action; while in mathematics the 
starting-point is the starting-point of the reasoning only, as 
there is no action. If then there is to be a house, such-and-such 
things must be made or be there already or exist, or generally 
the matter relative to the end, bricks and stones if it is a house. 
But the end is not due to these except as the matter, nor will it 
come to exist because of them. Yet if they do not exist at all, 
neither will the house, or the saw - the former in the absence of 
stones, the latter in the absence of iron - just as in the other 
case the premisses will not be true, if the angles of the triangle 
are not equal to two right angles. 

The necessary in nature, then, is plainly what we call by the 
name of matter, and the changes in it. Both causes must be 
stated by the physicist, but especially the end; for that is the 
cause of the matter, not vice versa; and the end is 'that for the 
sake of which', and the beginning starts from the definition or 
essence; as in artificial products, since a house is of such-and- 
such a kind, certain things must necessarily come to be or be 
there already, or since health is this, these things must 
necessarily come to be or be there already. Similarly if man is 
this, then these; if these, then those. Perhaps the necessary is 
present also in the definition. For if one defines the operation of 
sawing as being a certain kind of dividing, then this cannot 



651 



come about unless the saw has teeth of a certain kind; and 
these cannot be unless it is of iron. For in the definition too 
there are some parts that are, as it were, its matter. 



Book III 



Nature has been defined as a 'principle of motion and change', 
and it is the subject of our inquiry. We must therefore see that 
we understand the meaning of 'motion'; for if it were unknown, 
the meaning of 'nature' too would be unknown. 

When we have determined the nature of motion, our next task 
will be to attack in the same way the terms which are involved 
in it. Now motion is supposed to belong to the class of things 
which are continuous; and the infinite presents itself first in the 
continuous - that is how it comes about that 'infinite' is often 
used in definitions of the continuous ('what is infinitely 
divisible is continuous'). Besides these, place, void, and time are 
thought to be necessary conditions of motion. 

Clearly, then, for these reasons and also because the attributes 
mentioned are common to, and coextensive with, all the objects 
of our science, we must first take each of them in hand and 
discuss it. For the investigation of special attributes comes after 
that of the common attributes. 



652 



To begin then, as we said, with motion. 

We may start by distinguishing (1) what exists in a state of 
fulfilment only, (2) what exists as potential, (3) what exists as 
potential and also in fulfilment - one being a 'this', another 'so 
much', a third 'such', and similarly in each of the other modes 
of the predication of being. 

Further, the word 'relative' is used with reference to (1) excess 
and defect, (2) agent and patient and generally what can move 
and what can be moved. For 'what can cause movement' is 
relative to 'what can be moved', and vice versa. 

Again, there is no such thing as motion over and above the 
things. It is always with respect to substance or to quantity or to 
quality or to place that what changes changes. But it is 
impossible, as we assert, to find anything common to these 
which is neither 'this' nor quantum nor quale nor any of the 
other predicates. Hence neither will motion and change have 
reference to something over and above the things mentioned, 
for there is nothing over and above them. 

Now each of these belongs to all its subjects in either of two 
ways: namely (1) substance - the one is positive form, the other 
privation; (2) in quality, white and black; (3) in quantity, 
complete and incomplete; (4) in respect of locomotion, upwards 
and downwards or light and heavy. Hence there are as many 
types of motion or change as there are meanings of the word 



'is'. 



We have now before us the distinctions in the various classes of 
being between what is full real and what is potential. 

Def. The fulfilment of what exists potentially, in so far as it 
exists potentially, is motion - namely, of what is alterable qua 
alterable, alteration: of what can be increased and its opposite 
what can be decreased (there is no common name), increase 



653 



and decrease: of what can come to be and can pass away, 
coming to he and passing away: of what can be carried along, 
locomotion. 

Examples will elucidate this definition of motion. When the 
buildable, in so far as it is just that, is fully real, it is being built, 
and this is building. Similarly, learning, doctoring, rolling, 
leaping, ripening, ageing. 

The same thing, if it is of a certain kind, can be both potential 
and fully real, not indeed at the same time or not in the same 
respect, but e.g. potentially hot and actually cold. Hence at once 
such things will act and be acted on by one another in many 
ways: each of them will be capable at the same time of causing 
alteration and of being altered. Hence, too, what effects motion 
as a physical agent can be moved: when a thing of this kind 
causes motion, it is itself also moved. This, indeed, has led some 
people to suppose that every mover is moved. But this question 
depends on another set of arguments, and the truth will be 
made clear later, is possible for a thing to cause motion, though 
it is itself incapable of being moved. 

It is the fulfilment of what is potential when it is already fully 
real and operates not as itself but as movable, that is motion. 
What I mean by 'as' is this: Bronze is potentially a statue. But it 
is not the fulfilment of bronze as bronze which is motion. For 'to 
be bronze' and 'to be a certain potentiality' are not the same. 

If they were identical without qualification, i.e. in definition, the 
fulfilment of bronze as bronze would have been motion. But 
they are not the same, as has been said. (This is obvious in 
contraries. 'To be capable of health' and 'to be capable of illness' 
are not the same, for if they were there would be no difference 
between being ill and being well. Yet the subject both of health 
and of sickness - whether it is humour or blood - is one and the 
same.) 



654 



We can distinguish, then, between the two - just as, to give 
another example, 'colour' and visible' are different - and clearly 
it is the fulfilment of what is potential as potential that is 
motion. So this, precisely, is motion. 

Further it is evident that motion is an attribute of a thing just 
when it is fully real in this way, and neither before nor after. For 
each thing of this kind is capable of being at one time actual, at 
another not. Take for instance the buildable as buildable. The 
actuality of the buildable as buildable is the process of building. 
For the actuality of the buildable must be either this or the 
house. But when there is a house, the buildable is no longer 
buildable. On the other hand, it is the buildable which is being 
built. The process then of being built must be the kind of 
actuality required But building is a kind of motion, and the 
same account will apply to the other kinds also. 



The soundness of this definition is evident both when we 
consider the accounts of motion that the others have given, and 
also from the difficulty of defining it otherwise. 

One could not easily put motion and change in another genus - 
this is plain if we consider where some people put it; they 
identify motion with or 'inequality' or 'not being'; but such 
things are not necessarily moved, whether they are 'different' or 
'unequal' or 'non-existent'; Nor is change either to or from 
these rather than to or from their opposites. 

The reason why they put motion into these genera is that it is 
thought to be something indefinite, and the principles in the 
second column are indefinite because they are privative: none 



655 



of them is either 'this' or 'such' or comes under any of the other 
modes of predication. The reason in turn why motion is thought 
to be indefinite is that it cannot be classed simply as a 
potentiality or as an actuality - a thing that is merely capable of 
having a certain size is not undergoing change, nor yet a thing 
that is actually of a certain size, and motion is thought to be a 
sort of actuality, but incomplete, the reason for this view being 
that the potential whose actuality it is is incomplete. This is 
why it is hard to grasp what motion is. It is necessary to class it 
with privation or with potentiality or with sheer actuality, yet 
none of these seems possible. There remains then the suggested 
mode of definition, namely that it is a sort of actuality, or 
actuality of the kind described, hard to grasp, but not incapable 
of existing. 

The mover too is moved, as has been said - every mover, that is, 
which is capable of motion, and whose immobility is rest - 
when a thing is subject to motion its immobility is rest. For to 
act on the movable as such is just to move it. But this it does by 
contact, so that at the same time it is also acted on. Hence we 
can define motion as the fulfilment of the movable qua 
movable, the cause of the attribute being contact with what can 
move so that the mover is also acted on. The mover or agent 
will always be the vehicle of a form, either a 'this' or 'such', 
which, when it acts, will be the source and cause of the change, 
e.g. the full-formed man begets man from what is potentially 
man. 



The solution of the difficulty that is raised about the motion - 
whether it is in the movable - is plain. It is the fulfilment of this 



656 



potentiality, and by the action of that which has the power of 
causing motion; and the actuality of that which has the power 
of causing motion is not other than the actuality of the 
movable, for it must be the fulfilment of both. A thing is capable 
of causing motion because it can do this, it is a mover because it 
actually does it. But it is on the movable that it is capable of 
acting. Hence there is a single actuality of both alike, just as one 
to two and two to one are the same interval, and the steep 
ascent and the steep descent are one - for these are one and the 
same, although they can be described in different ways. So it is 
with the mover and the moved. 

This view has a dialectical difficulty. Perhaps it is necessary that 
the actuality of the agent and that of the patient should not be 
the same. The one is 'agency' and the other 'patiency'; and the 
outcome and completion of the one is an 'action', that of the 
other a 'passion'. Since then they are both motions, we may ask: 
in what are they, if they are different? Either (a) both are in what 
is acted on and moved, or (b) the agency is in the agent and the 
patiency in the patient. (If we ought to call the latter also 
'agency', the word would be used in two senses.) 

Now, in alternative (b), the motion will be in the mover, for the 
same statement will hold of 'mover' and 'moved'. Hence either 
every mover will be moved, or, though having motion, it will not 
be moved. 

If on the other hand (a) both are in what is moved and acted on 
- both the agency and the patiency (e.g. both teaching and 
learning, though they are two, in the learner), then, first, the 
actuality of each will not be present in each, and, a second 
absurdity, a thing will have two motions at the same time. How 
will there be two alterations of quality in one subject towards 
one definite quality? The thing is impossible: the actualization 
will be one. 



657 



But (some one will say) it is contrary to reason to suppose that 
there should be one identical actualization of two things which 
are different in kind. Yet there will be, if teaching and learning 
are the same, and agency and patiency. To teach will be the 
same as to learn, and to act the same as to be acted on - the 
teacher will necessarily be learning everything that he teaches, 
and the agent will be acted on. One may reply: 

(1) It is not absurd that the actualization of one thing should be 
in another. Teaching is the activity of a person who can teach, 
yet the operation is performed on some patient - it is not cut 
adrift from a subject, but is of A on B. 

(2) There is nothing to prevent two things having one and the 
same actualization, provided the actualizations are not 
described in the same way, but are related as what can act to 
what is acting. 

(3) Nor is it necessary that the teacher should learn, even if to 
act and to be acted on are one and the same, provided they are 
not the same in definition (as 'raiment' and 'dress'), but are the 
same merely in the sense in which the road from Thebes to 
Athens and the road from Athens to Thebes are the same, as 
has been explained above. For it is not things which are in a way 
the same that have all their attributes the same, but only such 
as have the same definition. But indeed it by no means follows 
from the fact that teaching is the same as learning, that to learn 
is the same as to teach, any more than it follows from the fact 
that there is one distance between two things which are at a 
distance from each other, that the two vectors AB and BA, are 
one and the same. To generalize, teaching is not the same as 
learning, or agency as patiency, in the full sense, though they 
belong to the same subject, the motion; for the 'actualization of 
X in Y' and the 'actualization ofY through the action of X' differ 
in definition. 



658 



What then Motion is, has been stated both generally and 
particularly. It is not difficult to see how each of its types will be 
defined - alteration is the fulfillment of the alterable qua 
alterable (or, more scientifically, the fulfilment of what can act 
and what can be acted on, as such) - generally and again in 
each particular case, building, healing, &c. A similar definition 
will apply to each of the other kinds of motion. 



The science of nature is concerned with spatial magnitudes and 
motion and time, and each of these at least is necessarily 
infinite or finite, even if some things dealt with by the science 
are not, e.g. a quality or a point - it is not necessary perhaps 
that such things should be put under either head. Hence it is 
incumbent on the person who specializes in physics to discuss 
the infinite and to inquire whether there is such a thing or not, 
and, if there is, what it is. 

The appropriateness to the science of this problem is clearly 
indicated. All who have touched on this kind of science in a way 
worth considering have formulated views about the infinite, and 
indeed, to a man, make it a principle of things. 

(1) Some, as the Pythagoreans and Plato, make the infinite a 
principle in the sense of a self-subsistent substance, and not as 
a mere attribute of some other thing. Only the Pythagoreans 
place the infinite among the objects of sense (they do not regard 
number as separable from these), and assert that what is 
outside the heaven is infinite. Plato, on the other hand, holds 
that there is no body outside (the Forms are not outside because 
they are nowhere), yet that the infinite is present not only in the 
objects of sense but in the Forms also. 



659 



Further, the Pythagoreans identify the infinite with the even. For 
this, they say, when it is cut off and shut in by the odd, provides 
things with the element of infinity. An indication of this is what 
happens with numbers. If the gnomons are placed round the 
one, and without the one, in the one construction the figure 
that results is always different, in the other it is always the 
same. But Plato has two infinites, the Great and the Small. 

The physicists, on the other hand, all of them, always regard the 
infinite as an attribute of a substance which is different from it 
and belongs to the class of the so-called elements - water or air 
or what is intermediate between them. Those who make them 
limited in number never make them infinite in amount. But 
those who make the elements infinite in number, as 
Anaxagoras and Democritus do, say that the infinite is 
continuous by contact - compounded of the homogeneous parts 
according to the one, of the seed-mass of the atomic shapes 
according to the other. 

Further, Anaxagoras held that any part is a mixture in the same 
way as the All, on the ground of the observed fact that anything 
comes out of anything. For it is probably for this reason that he 
maintains that once upon a time all things were together. (This 
flesh and this bone were together, and so of any thing: therefore 
all things: and at the same time too.) For there is a beginning of 
separation, not only for each thing, but for all. Each thing that 
comes to be comes from a similar body, and there is a coming to 
be of all things, though not, it is true, at the same time. Hence 
there must also be an origin of coming to be. One such source 
there is which he calls Mind, and Mind begins its work of 
thinking from some starting-point. So necessarily all things 
must have been together at a certain time, and must have 
begun to be moved at a certain time. 



660 



Democritus, for his part, asserts the contrary, namely that no 
element arises from another element. Nevertheless for him the 
common body is a source of all things, differing from part to 
part in size and in shape. 

It is clear then from these considerations that the inquiry 
concerns the physicist. Nor is it without reason that they all 
make it a principle or source. We cannot say that the infinite 
has no effect, and the only effectiveness which we can ascribe 
to it is that of a principle. Everything is either a source or 
derived from a source. But there cannot be a source of the 
infinite or limitless, for that would be a limit of it. Further, as it 
is a beginning, it is both uncreatable and indestructible. For 
there must be a point at which what has come to be reaches 
completion, and also a termination of all passing away. That is 
why, as we say, there is no principle of this, but it is this which 
is held to be the principle of other things, and to encompass all 
and to steer all, as those assert who do not recognize, alongside 
the infinite, other causes, such as Mind or Friendship. Further 
they identify it with the Divine, for it is 'deathless and 
imperishable' as Anaximander says, with the majority of the 
physicists. 

Belief in the existence of the infinite comes mainly from five 
considerations: 

(1) From the nature of time - for it is infinite. 

(2) From the division of magnitudes - for the mathematicians 
also use the notion of the infinite. 

(3) If coming to be and passing away do not give out, it is only 
because that from which things come to be is infinite. 

(4) Because the limited always finds its limit in something, so 
that there must be no limit, if everything is always limited by 
something different from itself. 



661 



(5) Most of all, a reason which is peculiarly appropriate and 
presents the difficulty that is felt by everybody - not only 
number but also mathematical magnitudes and what is outside 
the heaven are supposed to be infinite because they never give 
out in our thought. 

The last fact (that what is outside is infinite) leads people to 
suppose that body also is infinite, and that there is an infinite 
number of worlds. Why should there be body in one part of the 
void rather than in another? Grant only that mass is anywhere 
and it follows that it must be everywhere. Also, if void and place 
are infinite, there must be infinite body too, for in the case of 
eternal things what may be must be. But the problem of the 
infinite is difficult: many contradictions result whether we 
suppose it to exist or not to exist. If it exists, we have still to ask 
how it exists; as a substance or as the essential attribute of 
some entity? Or in neither way, yet none the less is there 
something which is infinite or some things which are infinitely 
many? 

The problem, however, which specially belongs to the physicist 
is to investigate whether there is a sensible magnitude which is 
infinite. 

We must begin by distinguishing the various senses in which 
the term 'infinite' is used. 

(1) What is incapable of being gone through, because it is not in 
its nature to be gone through (the sense in which the voice is 
'invisible'). 

(2) What admits of being gone through, the process however 
having no termination, or what scarcely admits of being gone 
through. 

(3) What naturally admits of being gone through, but is not 
actually gone through or does not actually reach an end. 



662 



Further, everything that is infinite may be so in respect of 
addition or division or both. 



Now it is impossible that the infinite should be a thing which is 
itself infinite, separable from sensible objects. If the infinite is 
neither a magnitude nor an aggregate, but is itself a substance 
and not an attribute, it will be indivisible; for the divisible must 
be either a magnitude or an aggregate. But if indivisible, then 
not infinite, except in the sense (1) in which the voice is 
'invisible'. But this is not the sense in which it is used by those 
who say that the infinite exists, nor that in which we are 
investigating it, namely as (2) 'that which cannot be gone 
through'. But if the infinite exists as an attribute, it would not 
be, qua infinite an element in substances, any more than the 
invisible would be an element of speech, though the voice is 
invisible. 

Further, how can the infinite be itself any thing, unless both 
number and magnitude, of which it is an essential attribute, 
exist in that way? If they are not substances, a fortiori the 
infinite is not. 

It is plain, too, that the infinite cannot be an actual thing and a 
substance and principle. For any part of it that is taken will be 
infinite, if it has parts: for 'to be infinite' and 'the infinite' are 
the same, if it is a substance and not predicated of a subject. 
Hence it will be either indivisible or divisible into infinites. But 
the same thing cannot be many infinites. (Yet just as part of air 
is air, so a part of the infinite would be infinite, if it is supposed 
to be a substance and principle.) Therefore the infinite must be 



663 



without parts and indivisible. But this cannot be true of what is 
infinite in full completion: for it must be a definite quantity. 

Suppose then that infinity belongs to substance as an attribute. 
But, if so, it cannot, as we have said, be described as a principle, 
but rather that of which it is an attribute - the air or the even 
number. 

Thus the view of those who speak after the manner of the 
Pythagoreans is absurd. With the same breath they treat the 
infinite as substance, and divide it into parts. 

This discussion, however, involves the more general question 
whether the infinite can be present in mathematical objects 
and things which are intelligible and do not have extension, as 
well as among sensible objects. Our inquiry (as physicists) is 
limited to its special subject-matter, the objects of sense, and 
we have to ask whether there is or is not among them a body 
which is infinite in the direction of increase. 

We may begin with a dialectical argument and show as follows 
that there is no such thing. If 'bounded by a surface' is the 
definition of body there cannot be an infinite body either 
intelligible or sensible. Nor can number taken in abstraction be 
infinite, for number or that which has number is numerable. If 
then the numerable can be numbered, it would also be possible 
to go through the infinite. 

If, on the other hand, we investigate the question more in 
accordance with principles appropriate to physics, we are led as 
follows to the same result. 

The infinite body must be either (1) compound, or (2) simple; yet 
neither alternative is possible. 

(1) Compound the infinite body will not be, if the elements are 
finite in number. For they must be more than one, and the 



664 



contraries must always balance, and no one of them can be 
infinite. If one of the bodies falls in any degree short of the 
other in potency - suppose fire is finite in amount while air is 
infinite and a given quantity of fire exceeds in power the same 
amount of air in any ratio provided it is numerically definite - 
the infinite body will obviously prevail over and annihilate the 
finite body. On the other hand, it is impossible that each should 
be infinite. 'Body' is what has extension in all directions and the 
infinite is what is boundlessly extended, so that the infinite 
body would be extended in all directions ad infinitum. 

Nor (2) can the infinite body be one and simple, whether it is, as 
some hold, a thing over and above the elements (from which 
they generate the elements) or is not thus qualified. 

(a) We must consider the former alternative; for there are some 
people who make this the infinite, and not air or water, in order 
that the other elements may not be annihilated by the element 
which is infinite. They have contrariety with each other - air is 
cold, water moist, fire hot; if one were infinite, the others by 
now would have ceased to be. As it is, they say, the infinite is 
different from them and is their source. 

It is impossible, however, that there should be such a body; not 
because it is infinite on that point a general proof can be given 
which applies equally to all, air, water, or anything else - but 
simply because there is, as a matter of fact, no such sensible 
body, alongside the so-called elements. Everything can be 
resolved into the elements of which it is composed. Hence the 
body in question would have been present in our world here, 
alongside air and fire and earth and water: but nothing of the 
kind is observed. 

(b) Nor can fire or any other of the elements be infinite. For 
generally, and apart from the question of how any of them 
could be infinite, the All, even if it were limited, cannot either be 



665 



or become one of them, as Heraclitus says that at some time all 
things become fire. (The same argument applies also to the one 
which the physicists suppose to exist alongside the elements: 
for everything changes from contrary to contrary, e.g. from hot 
to cold). 

The preceding consideration of the various cases serves to show 
us whether it is or is not possible that there should be an 
infinite sensible body. The following arguments give a general 
demonstration that it is not possible. 

It is the nature of every kind of sensible body to be somewhere, 
and there is a place appropriate to each, the same for the part 
and for the whole, e.g. for the whole earth and for a single clod, 
and for fire and for a spark. 

Suppose (a) that the infinite sensible body is homogeneous. 
Then each part will be either immovable or always being carried 
along. Yet neither is possible. For why downwards rather than 
upwards or in any other direction? I mean, e.g, if you take a 
clod, where will it be moved or where will it be at rest? For ex 
hypothesi the place of the body akin to it is infinite. Will it 
occupy the whole place, then? And how? What then will be the 
nature of its rest and of its movement, or where will they be? It 
will either be at home everywhere - then it will not be moved; 
or it will be moved everywhere - then it will not come to rest. 

But if (b) the All has dissimilar parts, the proper places of the 
parts will be dissimilar also, and the body of the All will have no 
unity except that of contact. Then, further, the parts will be 
either finite or infinite in variety of kind, (i) Finite they cannot 
be, for if the All is to be infinite, some of them would have to be 
infinite, while the others were not, e.g. fire or water will be 
infinite. But, as we have seen before, such an element would 
destroy what is contrary to it. (This indeed is the reason why 
none of the physicists made fire or earth the one infinite body, 



666 



but either water or air or what is intermediate between them, 
because the abode of each of the two was plainly determinate, 
while the others have an ambiguous place between up and 
down.) 

But (ii) if the parts are infinite in number and simple, their 
proper places too will be infinite in number, and the same will 
be true of the elements themselves. If that is impossible, and 
the places are finite, the whole too must be finite; for the place 
and the body cannot but fit each other. Neither is the whole 
place larger than what can be filled by the body (and then the 
body would no longer be infinite), nor is the body larger than 
the place; for either there would be an empty space or a body 
whose nature it is to be nowhere. 

Anaxagoras gives an absurd account of why the infinite is at 
rest. He says that the infinite itself is the cause of its being 
fixed. This because it is in itself, since nothing else contains it - 
on the assumption that wherever anything is, it is there by its 
own nature. But this is not true: a thing could be somewhere by 
compulsion, and not where it is its nature to be. 

Even if it is true as true can be that the whole is not moved (for 
what is fixed by itself and is in itself must be immovable), yet 
we must explain why it is not its nature to be moved. It is not 
enough just to make this statement and then decamp. Anything 
else might be in a state of rest, but there is no reason why it 
should not be its nature to be moved. The earth is not carried 
along, and would not be carried along if it were infinite, 
provided it is held together by the centre. But it would not be 
because there was no other region in which it could be carried 
along that it would remain at the centre, but because this is its 
nature. Yet in this case also we may say that it fixes itself. If 
then in the case of the earth, supposed to be infinite, it is at rest, 
not because it is infinite, but because it has weight and what is 



667 



heavy rests at the centre and the earth is at the centre, similarly 
the infinite also would rest in itself, not because it is infinite 
and fixes itself, but owing to some other cause. 

Another difficulty emerges at the same time. Any part of the 
infinite body ought to remain at rest. Just as the infinite 
remains at rest in itself because it fixes itself, so too any part of 
it you may take will remain in itself. The appropriate places of 
the whole and of the part are alike, e.g. of the whole earth and 
of a clod the appropriate place is the lower region; of fire as a 
whole and of a spark, the upper region. If, therefore, to be in 
itself is the place of the infinite, that also will be appropriate to 
the part. Therefore it will remain in itself. 

In general, the view that there is an infinite body is plainly 
incompatible with the doctrine that there is necessarily a 
proper place for each kind of body, if every sensible body has 
either weight or lightness, and if a body has a natural 
locomotion towards the centre if it is heavy, and upwards if it is 
light. This would need to be true of the infinite also. But neither 
character can belong to it: it cannot be either as a whole, nor 
can it be half the one and half the other. For how should you 
divide it? or how can the infinite have the one part up and the 
other down, or an extremity and a centre? 

Further, every sensible body is in place, and the kinds or 
differences of place are up-down, before-behind, right-left; and 
these distinctions hold not only in relation to us and by 
arbitrary agreement, but also in the whole itself. But in the 
infinite body they cannot exist. In general, if it is impossible 
that there should be an infinite place, and if every body is in 
place, there cannot be an infinite body. 

Surely what is in a special place is in place, and what is in place 
is in a special place. Just, then, as the infinite cannot be quantity 
- that would imply that it has a particular quantity, e,g, two or 



668 



three cubits; quantity just means these - so a thing's being in 
place means that it is somewhere, and that is either up or down 
or in some other of the six differences of position: but each of 
these is a limit. 

It is plain from these arguments that there is no body which is 
actually infinite. 



But on the other hand to suppose that the infinite does not 
exist in any way leads obviously to many impossible 
consequences: there will be a beginning and an end of time, a 
magnitude will not be divisible into magnitudes, number will 
not be infinite. If, then, in view of the above considerations, 
neither alternative seems possible, an arbiter must be called in; 
and clearly there is a sense in which the infinite exists and 
another in which it does not. 

We must keep in mind that the word 'is' means either what 
potentially is or what fully is. Further, a thing is infinite either 
by addition or by division. 

Now, as we have seen, magnitude is not actually infinite. But by 
division it is infinite. (There is no difficulty in refuting the 
theory of indivisible lines.) The alternative then remains that 
the infinite has a potential existence. 

But the phrase 'potential existence' is ambiguous. When we 
speak of the potential existence of a statue we mean that there 
will be an actual statue. It is not so with the infinite. There will 
not be an actual infinite. The word 'is' has many senses, and we 
say that the infinite 'is' in the sense in which we say 'it is day' or 



669 



'it is the games', because one thing after another is always 
coming into existence. For of these things too the distinction 
between potential and actual existence holds. We say that there 
are Olympic games, both in the sense that they may occur and 
that they are actually occurring. 

The infinite exhibits itself in different ways - in time, in the 
generations of man, and in the division of magnitudes. For 
generally the infinite has this mode of existence: one thing is 
always being taken after another, and each thing that is taken is 
always finite, but always different. Again, 'being' has more than 
one sense, so that we must not regard the infinite as a 'this', 
such as a man or a horse, but must suppose it to exist in the 
sense in which we speak of the day or the games as existing 
things whose being has not come to them like that of a 
substance, but consists in a process of coming to be or passing 
away; definite if you like at each stage, yet always different. 

But when this takes place in spatial magnitudes, what is taken 
perists, while in the succession of time and of men it takes 
place by the passing away of these in such a way that the source 
of supply never gives out. 

In a way the infinite by addition is the same thing as the infinite 
by division. In a finite magnitude, the infinite by addition comes 
about in a way inverse to that of the other. For in proportion as 
we see division going on, in the same proportion we see 
addition being made to what is already marked off. For if we 
take a determinate part of a finite magnitude and add another 
part determined by the same ratio (not taking in the same 
amount of the original whole), and so on, we shall not traverse 
the given magnitude. But if we increase the ratio of the part, so 
as always to take in the same amount, we shall traverse the 
magnitude, for every finite magnitude is exhausted by means of 
any determinate quantity however small. 



670 



The infinite, then, exists in no other way, but in this way it does 
exist, potentially and by reduction. It exists fully in the sense in 
which we say 'it is day' or 'it is the games'; and potentially as 
matter exists, not independently as what is finite does. 

By addition then, also, there is potentially an infinite, namely, 
what we have described as being in a sense the same as the 
infinite in respect of division. For it will always be possible to 
take something ah extra. Yet the sum of the parts taken will not 
exceed every determinate magnitude, just as in the direction of 
division every determinate magnitude is surpassed in smallness 
and there will be a smaller part. 

But in respect of addition there cannot be an infinite which 
even potentially exceeds every assignable magnitude, unless it 
has the attribute of being actually infinite, as the physicists hold 
to be true of the body which is outside the world, whose 
essential nature is air or something of the kind. But if there 
cannot be in this way a sensible body which is infinite in the 
full sense, evidently there can no more be a body which is 
potentially infinite in respect of addition, except as the inverse 
of the infinite by division, as we have said. It is for this reason 
that Plato also made the infinites two in number, because it is 
supposed to be possible to exceed all limits and to proceed ad 
infinitum in the direction both of increase and of reduction. Yet 
though he makes the infinites two, he does not use them. For in 
the numbers the infinite in the direction of reduction is not 
present, as the monad is the smallest; nor is the infinite in the 
direction of increase, for the parts number only up to the decad. 

The infinite turns out to be the contrary of what it is said to be. 
It is not what has nothing outside it that is infinite, but what 
always has something outside it. This is indicated by the fact 
that rings also that have no bezel are described as 'endless', 
because it is always possible to take a part which is outside a 



671 



given part. The description depends on a certain similarity, but 
it is not true in the full sense of the word. This condition alone 
is not sufficient: it is necessary also that the next part which is 
taken should never be the same. In the circle, the latter 
condition is not satisfied: it is only the adjacent part from which 
the new part is different. 

Our definition then is as follows: 

A quantity is infinite if it is such that we can always take a part 
outside what has been already taken. On the other hand, what 
has nothing outside it is complete and whole. For thus we 
define the whole - that from which nothing is wanting, as a 
whole man or a whole box. What is true of each particular is 
true of the whole as such - the whole is that of which nothing is 
outside. On the other hand that from which something is 
absent and outside, however small that may be, is not 'all'. 
'Whole' and 'complete' are either quite identical or closely akin. 
Nothing is complete (teleion) which has no end (telos); and the 
end is a limit. 

Hence Parmenides must be thought to have spoken better than 
Melissus. The latter says that the whole is infinite, but the 
former describes it as limited, 'equally balanced from the 
middle'. For to connect the infinite with the all and the whole is 
not like joining two pieces of string; for it is from this they get 
the dignity they ascribe to the infinite - its containing all things 
and holding the all in itself - from its having a certain similarity 
to the whole. It is in fact the matter of the completeness which 
belongs to size, and what is potentially a whole, though not in 
the full sense. It is divisible both in the direction of reduction 
and of the inverse addition. It is a whole and limited; not, 
however, in virtue of its own nature, but in virtue of what is 
other than it. It does not contain, but, in so far as it is infinite, is 
contained. Consequently, also, it is unknowable, qua infinite; for 



672 



the matter has no form. (Hence it is plain that the infinite 
stands in the relation of part rather than of whole. For the 
matter is part of the whole, as the bronze is of the bronze 
statue.) If it contains in the case of sensible things, in the case 
of intelligible things the great and the small ought to contain 
them. But it is absurd and impossible to suppose that the 
unknowable and indeterminate should contain and determine. 



It is reasonable that there should not be held to be an infinite in 
respect of addition such as to surpass every magnitude, but that 
there should be thought to be such an infinite in the direction of 
division. For the matter and the infinite are contained inside 
what contains them, while it is the form which contains. It is 
natural too to suppose that in number there is a limit in the 
direction of the minimum, and that in the other direction every 
assigned number is surpassed. In magnitude, on the contrary, 
every assigned magnitude is surpassed in the direction of 
smallness, while in the other direction there is no infinite 
magnitude. The reason is that what is one is indivisible 
whatever it may be, e.g. a man is one man, not many. Number 
on the other hand is a plurality of 'ones' and a certain quantity 
of them. Hence number must stop at the indivisible: for 'two' 
and 'three' are merely derivative terms, and so with each of the 
other numbers. But in the direction of largeness it is always 
possible to think of a larger number: for the number of times a 
magnitude can be bisected is infinite. Hence this infinite is 
potential, never actual: the number of parts that can be taken 
always surpasses any assigned number. But this number is not 
separable from the process of bisection, and its infinity is not a 



673 



permanent actuality but consists in a process of coming to be, 
like time and the number of time. 

With magnitudes the contrary holds. What is continuous is 
divided ad infinitum, but there is no infinite in the direction of 
increase. For the size which it can potentially be, it can also 
actually be. Hence since no sensible magnitude is infinite, it is 
impossible to exceed every assigned magnitude; for if it were 
possible there would be something bigger than the heavens. 

The infinite is not the same in magnitude and movement and 
time, in the sense of a single nature, but its secondary sense 
depends on its primary sense, i.e. movement is called infinite in 
virtue of the magnitude covered by the movement (or alteration 
or growth), and time because of the movement. (I use these 
terms for the moment. Later I shall explain what each of them 
means, and also why every magnitude is divisible into 
magnitudes.) 

Our account does not rob the mathematicians of their science, 
by disproving the actual existence of the infinite in the direction 
of increase, in the sense of the untraversable. In point of fact 
they do not need the infinite and do not use it. They postulate 
only that the finite straight line may be produced as far as they 
wish. It is possible to have divided in the same ratio as the 
largest quantity another magnitude of any size you like. Hence, 
for the purposes of proof, it will make no difference to them to 
have such an infinite instead, while its existence will be in the 
sphere of real magnitudes. 

In the fourfold scheme of causes, it is plain that the infinite is a 
cause in the sense of matter, and that its essence is privation, 
the subject as such being what is continuous and sensible. All 
the other thinkers, too, evidently treat the infinite as matter - 
that is why it is inconsistent in them to make it what contains, 
and not what is contained. 



674 



8 

It remains to dispose of the arguments which are supposed to 
support the view that the infinite exists not only potentially but 
as a separate thing. Some have no cogency; others can be met 
by fresh objections that are valid. 

(1) In order that coming to be should not fail, it is not necessary 
that there should be a sensible body which is actually infinite. 
The passing away of one thing may be the coming to be of 
another, the All being limited. 

(2) There is a difference between touching and being limited. 
The former is relative to something and is the touching of 
something (for everything that touches touches something), and 
further is an attribute of some one of the things which are 
limited. On the other hand, what is limited is not limited in 
relation to anything. Again, contact is not necessarily possible 
between any two things taken at random. 

(3) To rely on mere thinking is absurd, for then the excess or 
defect is not in the thing but in the thought. One might think 
that one of us is bigger than he is and magnify him ad 
infinitum. But it does not follow that he is bigger than the size 
we are, just because some one thinks he is, but only because he 
is the size he is. The thought is an accident. 

(a) Time indeed and movement are infinite, and also thinking, in 
the sense that each part that is taken passes in succession out 
of existence. 

(b) Magnitude is not infinite either in the way of reduction or of 
magnification in thought. 



675 



This concludes my account of the way in which the infinite 
exists, and of the way in which it does not exist, and of what it 
is. 



Book IV 



The physicist must have a knowledge of Place, too, as well as of 
the infinite - namely, whether there is such a thing or not, and 
the manner of its existence and what it is - both because all 
suppose that things which exist are somewhere (the non- 
existent is nowhere - where is the goat-stag or the sphinx?), 
and because 'motion' in its most general and primary sense is 
change of place, which we call 'locomotion'. 

The question, what is place? presents many difficulties. An 
examination of all the relevant facts seems to lead to divergent 
conclusions. Moreover, we have inherited nothing from previous 
thinkers, whether in the way of a statement of difficulties or of 
a solution. 

The existence of place is held to be obvious from the fact of 
mutual replacement. Where water now is, there in turn, when 
the water has gone out as from a vessel, air is present. When 
therefore another body occupies this same place, the place is 
thought to be different from all the bodies which come to be in 
it and replace one another. What now contains air formerly 



676 



contained water, so that clearly the place or space into which 
and out of which they passed was something different from 
both. 

Further, the typical locomotions of the elementary natural 
bodies - namely, fire, earth, and the like - show not only that 
place is something, but also that it exerts a certain influence. 
Each is carried to its own place, if it is not hindered, the one up, 
the other down. Now these are regions or kinds of place - up 
and down and the rest of the six directions. Nor do such 
distinctions (up and down and right and left, &c.) hold only in 
relation to us. To us they are not always the same but change 
with the direction in which we are turned: that is why the same 
thing may be both right and left, up and down, before and 
behind. But in nature each is distinct, taken apart by itself. It is 
not every chance direction which is 'up', but where fire and 
what is light are carried; similarly, too, 'down' is not any chance 
direction but where what has weight and what is made of earth 
are carried - the implication being that these places do not 
differ merely in relative position, but also as possessing distinct 
potencies. This is made plain also by the objects studied by 
mathematics. Though they have no real place, they 
nevertheless, in respect of their position relatively to us, have a 
right and left as attributes ascribed to them only in 
consequence of their relative position, not having by nature 
these various characteristics. Again, the theory that the void 
exists involves the existence of place: for one would define void 
as place bereft of body. 

These considerations then would lead us to suppose that place 
is something distinct from bodies, and that every sensible body 
is in place. Hesiod too might be held to have given a correct 
account of it when he made chaos first. At least he says: 



677 



'First of all things came chaos to being, then broad-breasted 
earth,' implying that things need to have space first, because he 
thought, with most people, that everything is somewhere and in 
place. If this is its nature, the potency of place must be a 
marvellous thing, and take precedence of all other things. For 
that without which nothing else can exist, while it can exist 
without the others, must needs be first; for place does not pass 
out of existence when the things in it are annihilated. 

True, but even if we suppose its existence settled, the question 
of its nature presents difficulty - whether it is some sort of 
'bulk' of body or some entity other than that, for we must first 
determine its genus. 

(1) Now it has three dimensions, length, breadth, depth, the 
dimensions by which all body also is bounded. But the place 
cannot be body; for if it were there would be two bodies in the 
same place. 

(2) Further, if body has a place and space, clearly so too have 
surface and the other limits of body; for the same statement 
will apply to them: where the bounding planes of the water 
were, there in turn will be those of the air. But when we come to 
a point we cannot make a distinction between it and its place. 
Hence if the place of a point is not different from the point, no 
more will that of any of the others be different, and place will 
not be something different from each of them. 

(3) What in the world then are we to suppose place to be? If it 
has the sort of nature described, it cannot be an element or 
composed of elements, whether these be corporeal or 
incorporeal: for while it has size, it has not body. But the 
elements of sensible bodies are bodies, while nothing that has 
size results from a combination of intelligible elements. 



678 



(4) Also we may ask: of what in things is space the cause? None 
of the four modes of causation can be ascribed to it. It is neither 
in the sense of the matter of existents (for nothing is composed 
of it), nor as the form and definition of things, nor as end, nor 
does it move existents. 

(5) Further, too, if it is itself an existent, where will it be? Zeno's 
difficulty demands an explanation: for if everything that exists 
has a place, place too will have a place, and so on ad infinitum. 

(6) Again, just as every body is in place, so, too, every place has a 
body in it. What then shall we say about growing things? It 
follows from these premisses that their place must grow with 
them, if their place is neither less nor greater than they are. 

By asking these questions, then, we must raise the whole 
problem about place - not only as to what it is, but even 
whether there is such a thing. 



We may distinguish generally between predicating B of A 
because it (A) is itself, and because it is something else; and 
particularly between place which is common and in which all 
bodies are, and the special place occupied primarily by each. I 
mean, for instance, that you are now in the heavens because 
you are in the air and it is in the heavens; and you are in the air 
because you are on the earth; and similarly on the earth 
because you are in this place which contains no more than you. 

Now if place is what primarily contains each body, it would be a 
limit, so that the place would be the form or shape of each body 



679 



by which the magnitude or the matter of the magnitude is 
defined: for this is the limit of each body. 

If, then, we look at the question in this way the place of a thing 
is its form. But, if we regard the place as the extension of the 
magnitude, it is the matter. For this is different from the 
magnitude: it is what is contained and defined by the form, as 
by a bounding plane. Matter or the indeterminate is of this 
nature; when the boundary and attributes of a sphere are taken 
away, nothing but the matter is left. 

This is why Plato in the Timaeus says that matter and space are 
the same; for the 'participant' and space are identical. (It is true, 
indeed, that the account he gives there of the 'participant' is 
different from what he says in his so-called 'unwritten 
teaching'. Nevertheless, he did identify place and space.) I 
mention Plato because, while all hold place to be something, he 
alone tried to say what it is. 

In view of these facts we should naturally expect to find 
difficulty in determining what place is, if indeed it is one of 
these two things, matter or form. They demand a very close 
scrutiny, especially as it is not easy to recognize them apart. 

But it is at any rate not difficult to see that place cannot be 
either of them. The form and the matter are not separate from 
the thing, whereas the place can be separated. As we pointed 
out, where air was, water in turn comes to be, the one replacing 
the other; and similarly with other bodies. Hence the place of a 
thing is neither a part nor a state of it, but is separable from it. 
For place is supposed to be something like a vessel - the vessel 
being a transportable place. But the vessel is no part of the 
thing. 

In so far then as it is separable from the thing, it is not the form: 
qua containing, it is different from the matter. 



680 



Also it is held that what is anywhere is both itself something 
and that there is a different thing outside it. (Plato of course, if 
we may digress, ought to tell us why the form and the numbers 
are not in place, if 'what participates' is place - whether what 
participates is the Great and the Small or the matter, as he 
called it in writing in the Timaeus.) 

Further, how could a body be carried to its own place, if place 
was the matter or the form? It is impossible that what has no 
reference to motion or the distinction of up and down can be 
place. So place must be looked for among things which have 
these characteristics. 

If the place is in the thing (it must be if it is either shape or 
matter) place will have a place: for both the form and the 
indeterminate undergo change and motion along with the 
thing, and are not always in the same place, but are where the 
thing is. Hence the place will have a place. 

Further, when water is produced from air, the place has been 
destroyed, for the resulting body is not in the same place. What 
sort of destruction then is that? 

This concludes my statement of the reasons why space must be 
something, and again of the difficulties that may be raised 
about its essential nature. 



The next step we must take is to see in how many senses one 
thing is said to be 'in' another. 

(1) As the finger is 'in' the hand and generally the part 'in' the 
whole. 



681 



(2) As the whole is 'in' the parts: for there is no whole over and 
above the parts. 

(3) As man is 'in' animal and generally species 'in' genus. 

(4) As the genus is 'in' the species and generally the part of the 
specific form 'in' the definition of the specific form. 

(5) As health is 'in' the hot and the cold and generally the form 
'in' the matter. 

(6) As the affairs of Greece centre 'in' the king, and generally 
events centre 'in' their primary motive agent. 

(7) As the existence of a thing centres 'in its good and generally 
'in' its end, i.e. in 'that for the sake of which' it exists. 

(8) In the strictest sense of all, as a thing is 'in' a vessel, and 
generally 'in' place. 

One might raise the question whether a thing can be in itself, or 
whether nothing can be in itself - everything being either 
nowhere or in something else. 

The question is ambiguous; we may mean the thing qua itself 
or qua something else. 

When there are parts of a whole - the one that in which a thing 
is, the other the thing which is in it - the whole will be 
described as being in itself. For a thing is described in terms of 
its parts, as well as in terms of the thing as a whole, e.g. a man 
is said to be white because the visible surface of him is white, or 
to be scientific because his thinking faculty has been trained. 
The jar then will not be in itself and the wine will not be in 
itself. But the jar of wine will: for the contents and the container 
are both parts of the same whole. 



682 



In this sense then, but not primarily, a thing can be in itself, 
namely, as 'white' is in body (for the visible surface is in body), 
and science is in the mind. 

It is from these, which are 'parts' (in the sense at least of being 
'in' the man), that the man is called white, &c. But the jar and 
the wine in separation are not parts of a whole, though together 
they are. So when there are parts, a thing will be in itself, as 
'white' is in man because it is in body, and in body because it 
resides in the visible surface. We cannot go further and say that 
it is in surface in virtue of something other than itself. (Yet it is 
not in itself: though these are in a way the same thing,) they 
differ in essence, each having a special nature and capacity, 
'surface' and 'white'. 

Thus if we look at the matter inductively we do not find 
anything to be 'in' itself in any of the senses that have been 
distinguished; and it can be seen by argument that it is 
impossible. For each of two things will have to be both, e.g. the 
jar will have to be both vessel and wine, and the wine both wine 
and jar, if it is possible for a thing to be in itself; so that, 
however true it might be that they were in each other, the jar 
will receive the wine in virtue not of its being wine but of the 
wine's being wine, and the wine will be in the jar in virtue not 
of its being a jar but of the jar's being a jar. Now that they are 
different in respect of their essence is evident; for 'that in which 
something is' and 'that which is in it' would be differently 
defined. 

Nor is it possible for a thing to be in itself even incidentally: for 
two things would at the same time in the same thing. The jar 
would be in itself- if a thing whose nature it is to receive can be 
in itself; and that which it receives, namely (if wine) wine, will 
be in it. 

Obviously then a thing cannot be in itself primarily. 



683 



Zeno's problem - that if Place is something it must be in 
something - is not difficult to solve. There is nothing to prevent 
the first place from being 'in' something else - not indeed in 
that as 'in' place, but as health is 'in' the hot as a positive 
determination of it or as the hot is 'in' body as an affection. So 
we escape the infinite regress. 

Another thing is plain: since the vessel is no part of what is in it 
(what contains in the strict sense is different from what is 
contained), place could not be either the matter or the form of 
the thing contained, but must different - for the latter, both the 
matter and the shape, are parts of what is contained. 

This then may serve as a critical statement of the difficulties 
involved. 



What then after all is place? The answer to this question may be 
elucidated as follows. 

Let us take for granted about it the various characteristics which 
are supposed correctly to belong to it essentially. We assume 
then- 

(1) Place is what contains that of which it is the place. 

(2) Place is no part of the thing. 

(3) The immediate place of a thing is neither less nor greater 
than the thing. 

(4) Place can be left behind by the thing and is separable. In 
addition: 



684 



(5) All place admits of the distinction of up and down, and each 
of the bodies is naturally carried to its appropriate place and 
rests there, and this makes the place either up or down. 

Having laid these foundations, we must complete the theory. 
We ought to try to make our investigation such as will render an 
account of place, and will not only solve the difficulties 
connected with it, but will also show that the attributes 
supposed to belong to it do really belong to it, and further will 
make clear the cause of the trouble and of the difficulties about 
it. Such is the most satisfactory kind of exposition. 

First then we must understand that place would not have been 
thought of, if there had not been a special kind of motion, 
namely that with respect to place. It is chiefly for this reason 
that we suppose the heaven also to be in place, because it is in 
constant movement. Of this kind of change there are two 
species - locomotion on the one hand and, on the other, 
increase and diminution. For these too involve variation of 
place: what was then in this place has now in turn changed to 
what is larger or smaller. 

Again, when we say a thing is 'moved', the predicate either (1) 
belongs to it actually, in virtue of its own nature, or (2) in virtue 
of something conjoined with it. In the latter case it may be 
either (a) something which by its own nature is capable of being 
moved, e.g. the parts of the body or the nail in the ship, or (b) 
something which is not in itself capable of being moved, but is 
always moved through its conjunction with something else, as 
'whiteness' or 'science'. These have changed their place only 
because the subjects to which they belong do so. 

We say that a thing is in the world, in the sense of in place, 
because it is in the air, and the air is in the world; and when we 
say it is in the air, we do not mean it is in every part of the air, 
but that it is in the air because of the outer surface of the air 



685 



which surrounds it; for if all the air were its place, the place of a 
thing would not be equal to the thing - which it is supposed to 
be, and which the primary place in which a thing is actually is. 

When what surrounds, then, is not separate from the thing, but 
is in continuity with it, the thing is said to be in what surrounds 
it, not in the sense of in place, but as a part in a whole. But 
when the thing is separate and in contact, it is immediately 'in' 
the inner surface of the surrounding body, and this surface is 
neither a part of what is in it nor yet greater than its extension, 
but equal to it; for the extremities of things which touch are 
coincident. 

Further, if one body is in continuity with another, it is not 
moved in that but with that. On the other hand it is moved in 
that if it is separate. It makes no difference whether what 
contains is moved or not. 

Again, when it is not separate it is described as a part in a 
whole, as the pupil in the eye or the hand in the body: when it is 
separate, as the water in the cask or the wine in the jar. For the 
hand is moved with the body and the water in the cask. 

It will now be plain from these considerations what place is. 
There are just four things of which place must be one - the 
shape, or the matter, or some sort of extension between the 
bounding surfaces of the containing body, or this boundary 
itself if it contains no extension over and above the bulk of the 
body which comes to be in it. 

Three of these it obviously cannot be: 

(1) The shape is supposed to be place because it surrounds, for 
the extremities of what contains and of what is contained are 
coincident. Both the shape and the place, it is true, are 
boundaries. But not of the same thing: the form is the boundary 



686 



of the thing, the place is the boundary of the body which 
contains it. 

(2) The extension between the extremities is thought to be 
something, because what is contained and separate may often 
be changed while the container remains the same (as water 
may be poured from a vessel) - the assumption being that the 
extension is something over and above the body displaced. But 
there is no such extension. One of the bodies which change 
places and are naturally capable of being in contact with the 
container falls in whichever it may chance to be. 

If there were an extension which were such as to exist 
independently and be permanent, there would be an infinity of 
places in the same thing. For when the water and the air change 
places, all the portions of the two together will play the same 
part in the whole which was previously played by all the water 
in the vessel; at the same time the place too will be undergoing 
change; so that there will be another place which is the place of 
the place, and many places will be coincident. There is not a 
different place of the part, in which it is moved, when the whole 
vessel changes its place: it is always the same: for it is in the 
(proximate) place where they are that the air and the water (or 
the parts of the water) succeed each other, not in that place in 
which they come to be, which is part of the place which is the 
place of the whole world. 

(3) The matter, too, might seem to be place, at least if we 
consider it in what is at rest and is thus separate but in 
continuity. For just as in change of quality there is something 
which was formerly black and is now white, or formerly soft 
and now hard - this is just why we say that the matter exists - 
so place, because it presents a similar phenomenon, is thought 
to exist - only in the one case we say so because what was air is 
now water, in the other because where air formerly was there a 



687 



is now water. But the matter, as we said before, is neither 
separable from the thing nor contains it, whereas place has 
both characteristics. 

Well, then, if place is none of the three - neither the form nor 
the matter nor an extension which is always there, different 
from, and over and above, the extension of the thing which is 
displaced - place necessarily is the one of the four which is left, 
namely, the boundary of the containing body at which it is in 
contact with the contained body. (By the contained body is 
meant what can be moved by way of locomotion.) 

Place is thought to be something important and hard to grasp, 
both because the matter and the shape present themselves 
along with it, and because the displacement of the body that is 
moved takes place in a stationary container, for it seems 
possible that there should be an interval which is other than the 
bodies which are moved. The air, too, which is thought to be 
incorporeal, contributes something to the belief: it is not only 
the boundaries of the vessel which seem to be place, but also 
what is between them, regarded as empty. Just, in fact, as the 
vessel is transportable place, so place is a non-portable vessel. 
So when what is within a thing which is moved, is moved and 
changes its place, as a boat on a river, what contains plays the 
part of a vessel rather than that of place. Place on the other 
hand is rather what is motionless: so it is rather the whole river 
that is place, because as a whole it is motionless. 

Hence we conclude that the innermost motionless boundary of 
what contains is place. 

This explains why the middle of the heaven and the surface 
which faces us of the rotating system are held to be 'up' and 
'down' in the strict and fullest sense for all men: for the one is 
always at rest, while the inner side of the rotating body remains 
always coincident with itself. Hence since the light is what is 



688 



naturally carried up, and the heavy what is carried down, the 
boundary which contains in the direction of the middle of the 
universe, and the middle itself, are down, and that which 
contains in the direction of the outermost part of the universe, 
and the outermost part itself, are up. 

For this reason, too, place is thought to be a kind of surface, and 
as it were a vessel, i.e. a container of the thing. 

Further, place is coincident with the thing, for boundaries are 
coincident with the bounded. 



If then a body has another body outside it and containing it, it is 
in place, and if not, not. That is why, even if there were to be 
water which had not a container, the parts of it, on the one 
hand, will be moved (for one part is contained in another), 
while, on the other hand, the whole will be moved in one sense, 
but not in another. For as a whole it does not simultaneously 
change its place, though it will be moved in a circle: for this 
place is the place of its parts. (Some things are moved, not up 
and down, but in a circle; others up and down, such things 
namely as admit of condensation and rarefaction.) 

As was explained, some things are potentially in place, others 
actually. So, when you have a homogeneous substance which is 
continuous, the parts are potentially in place: when the parts 
are separated, but in contact, like a heap, they are actually in 
place. 

Again, (1) some things are per se in place, namely every body 
which is movable either by way of locomotion or by way of 



689 



increase is per se somewhere, but the heaven, as has been said, 
is not anywhere as a whole, nor in any place, if at least, as we 
must suppose, no body contains it. On the line on which it is 
moved, its parts have place: for each is contiguous the next. 

But (2) other things are in place indirectly, through something 
conjoined with them, as the soul and the heaven. The latter is, 
in a way, in place, for all its parts are: for on the orb one part 
contains another. That is why the upper part is moved in a 
circle, while the All is not anywhere. For what is somewhere is 
itself something, and there must be alongside it some other 
thing wherein it is and which contains it. But alongside the All 
or the Whole there is nothing outside the All, and for this 
reason all things are in the heaven; for the heaven, we may say, 
is the All. Yet their place is not the same as the heaven. It is part 
of it, the innermost part of it, which is in contact with the 
movable body; and for this reason the earth is in water, and this 
in the air, and the air in the aether, and the aether in heaven, 
but we cannot go on and say that the heaven is in anything else. 

It is clear, too, from these considerations that all the problems 
which were raised about place will be solved when it is 
explained in this way: 

(1) There is no necessity that the place should grow with the 
body in it, 

(2) Nor that a point should have a place, 

(3) Nor that two bodies should be in the same place, 

(4) Nor that place should be a corporeal interval: for what is 
between the boundaries of the place is any body which may 
chance to be there, not an interval in body. 



690 



Further, (5) place is also somewhere, not in the sense of being in 
a place, but as the limit is in the limited; for not everything that 
is is in place, but only movable body. 

Also (6) it is reasonable that each kind of body should be carried 
to its own place. For a body which is next in the series and in 
contact (not by compulsion) is akin, and bodies which are 
united do not affect each other, while those which are in 
contact interact on each other. 

Nor (7) is it without reason that each should remain naturally in 
its proper place. For this part has the same relation to its place, 
as a separable part to its whole, as when one moves a part of 
water or air: so, too, air is related to water, for the one is like 
matter, the other form - water is the matter of air, air as it were 
the actuality of water, for water is potentially air, while air is 
potentially water, though in another way. 

These distinctions will be drawn more carefully later. On the 
present occasion it was necessary to refer to them: what has 
now been stated obscurely will then be made more clear. If the 
matter and the fulfilment are the same thing (for water is both, 
the one potentially, the other completely), water will be related 
to air in a way as part to whole. That is why these have contact: 
it is organic union when both become actually one. 

This concludes my account of place - both of its existence and 
of its nature. 



The investigation of similar questions about the void, also, must 
be held to belong to the physicist - namely whether it exists or 



691 



not, and how it exists or what it is - just as about place. The 
views taken of it involve arguments both for and against, in 
much the same sort of way. For those who hold that the void 
exists regard it as a sort of place or vessel which is supposed to 
be 'full' when it holds the bulk which it is capable of containing, 
'void' when it is deprived of that - as if 'void' and 'full' and 
'place' denoted the same thing, though the essence of the three 
is different. 

We must begin the inquiry by putting down the account given 
by those who say that it exists, then the account of those who 
say that it does not exist, and third the current view on these 
questions. 

Those who try to show that the void does not exist do not 
disprove what people really mean by it, but only their erroneous 
way of speaking; this is true of Anaxagoras and of those who 
refute the existence of the void in this way. They merely give an 
ingenious demonstration that air is something - by straining 
wine-skins and showing the resistance of the air, and by cutting 
it off in clepsydras. But people really mean that there is an 
empty interval in which there is no sensible body. They hold 
that everything which is in body is body and say that what has 
nothing in it at all is void (so what is full of air is void). It is not 
then the existence of air that needs to be proved, but the non- 
existence of an interval, different from the bodies, either 
separable or actual - an interval which divides the whole body 
so as to break its continuity, as Democritus and Leucippus hold, 
and many other physicists - or even perhaps as something 
which is outside the whole body, which remains continuous. 

These people, then, have not reached even the threshold of the 
problem, but rather those who say that the void exists. 

(1) They argue, for one thing, that change in place (i.e. 
locomotion and increase) would not be. For it is maintained that 



692 



motion would seem not to exist, if there were no void, since 
what is full cannot contain anything more. If it could, and there 
were two bodies in the same place, it would also be true that 
any number of bodies could be together; for it is impossible to 
draw a line of division beyond which the statement would 
become untrue. If this were possible, it would follow also that 
the smallest body would contain the greatest; for 'many a little 
makes a mickle': thus if many equal bodies can be together, so 
also can many unequal bodies. 

Melissus, indeed, infers from these considerations that the All is 
immovable; for if it were moved there must, he says, be void, 
but void is not among the things that exist. 

This argument, then, is one way in which they show that there 
is a void. 

(2) They reason from the fact that some things are observed to 
contract and be compressed, as people say that a cask will hold 
the wine which formerly filled it, along with the skins into 
which the wine has been decanted, which implies that the 
compressed body contracts into the voids present in it. 

Again (3) increase, too, is thought to take always by means of 
void, for nutriment is body, and it is impossible for two bodies to 
be together. A proof of this they find also in what happens to 
ashes, which absorb as much water as the empty vessel. 

The Pythagoreans, too, (4) held that void exists and that it 
enters the heaven itself, which as it were inhales it, from the 
infinite air. Further it is the void which distinguishes the 
natures of things, as if it were like what separates and 
distinguishes the terms of a series. This holds primarily in the 
numbers, for the void distinguishes their nature. 

These, then, and so many, are the main grounds on which 
people have argued for and against the existence of the void. 



693 



As a step towards settling which view is true, we must 
determine the meaning of the name. 

The void is thought to be place with nothing in it. The reason 
for this is that people take what exists to be body, and hold that 
while every body is in place, void is place in which there is no 
body, so that where there is no body, there must be void. 

Every body, again, they suppose to be tangible; and of this 
nature is whatever has weight or lightness. 

Hence, by a syllogism, what has nothing heavy or light in it, is 
void. 

This result, then, as I have said, is reached by syllogism. It 
would be absurd to suppose that the point is void; for the void 
must be place which has in it an interval in tangible body. 

But at all events we observe then that in one way the void is 
described as what is not full of body perceptible to touch; and 
what has heaviness and lightness is perceptible to touch. So we 
would raise the question: what would they say of an interval 
that has colour or sound - is it void or not? Clearly they would 
reply that if it could receive what is tangible it was void, and if 
not, not. 

In another way void is that in which there is no 'this' or 
corporeal substance. So some say that the void is the matter of 
the body (they identify the place, too, with this), and in this they 
speak incorrectly; for the matter is not separable from the 
things, but they are inquiring about the void as about something 
separable. 



694 



Since we have determined the nature of place, and void must, if 
it exists, be place deprived of body, and we have stated both in 
what sense place exists and in what sense it does not, it is plain 
that on this showing void does not exist, either unseparated or 
separated; the void is meant to be, not body but rather an 
interval in body. This is why the void is thought to be 
something, viz. because place is, and for the same reasons. For 
the fact of motion in respect of place comes to the aid both of 
those who maintain that place is something over and above the 
bodies that come to occupy it, and of those who maintain that 
the void is something. They state that the void is the condition 
of movement in the sense of that in which movement takes 
place; and this would be the kind of thing that some say place 
is. 

But there is no necessity for there being a void if there is 
movement. It is not in the least needed as a condition of 
movement in general, for a reason which, incidentally, escaped 
Melissus; viz. that the full can suffer qualitative change. 

But not even movement in respect of place involves a void; for 
bodies may simultaneously make room for one another, though 
there is no interval separate and apart from the bodies that are 
in movement. And this is plain even in the rotation of 
continuous things, as in that of liquids. 

And things can also be compressed not into a void but because 
they squeeze out what is contained in them (as, for instance, 
when water is compressed the air within it is squeezed out); 
and things can increase in size not only by the entrance of 
something but also by qualitative change; e.g. if water were to 
be transformed into air. 

In general, both the argument about increase of size and that 
about water poured on to the ashes get in their own way. For 
either not any and every part of the body is increased, or bodies 



695 



may be increased otherwise than by the addition of body, or 
there may be two bodies in the same place (in which case they 
are claiming to solve a quite general difficulty, but are not 
proving the existence of void), or the whole body must be void, 
if it is increased in every part and is increased by means of void. 
The same argument applies to the ashes. 

It is evident, then, that it is easy to refute the arguments by 
which they prove the existence of the void. 



8 

Let us explain again that there is no void existing separately, as 
some maintain. If each of the simple bodies has a natural 
locomotion, e.g. fire upward and earth downward and towards 
the middle of the universe, it is clear that it cannot be the void 
that is the condition of locomotion. What, then, will the void be 
the condition of? It is thought to be the condition of movement 
in respect of place, and it is not the condition of this. 

Again, if void is a sort of place deprived of body, when there is a 
void where will a body placed in it move to? It certainly cannot 
move into the whole of the void. The same argument applies as 
against those who think that place is something separate, into 
which things are carried; viz. how will what is placed in it move, 
or rest? Much the same argument will apply to the void as to 
the 'up' and 'down' in place, as is natural enough since those 
who maintain the existence of the void make it a place. 

And in what way will things be present either in place - or in 
the void? For the expected result does not take place when a 
body is placed as a whole in a place conceived of as separate 
and permanent; for a part of it, unless it be placed apart, will 



696 



not be in a place but in the whole. Further, if separate place 
does not exist, neither will void. 

If people say that the void must exist, as being necessary if 
there is to be movement, what rather turns out to be the case, if 
one the matter, is the opposite, that not a single thing can be 
moved if there is a void; for as with those who for a like reason 
say the earth is at rest, so, too, in the void things must be at rest; 
for there is no place to which things can move more or less than 
to another; since the void in so far as it is void admits no 
difference. 

The second reason is this: all movement is either compulsory or 
according to nature, and if there is compulsory movement there 
must also be natural (for compulsory movement is contrary to 
nature, and movement contrary to nature is posterior to that 
according to nature, so that if each of the natural bodies has not 
a natural movement, none of the other movements can exist); 
but how can there be natural movement if there is no difference 
throughout the void or the infinite? For in so far as it is infinite, 
there will be no up or down or middle, and in so far as it is a 
void, up differs no whit from down; for as there is no difference 
in what is nothing, there is none in the void (for the void seems 
to be a non-existent and a privation of being), but natural 
locomotion seems to be differentiated, so that the things that 
exist by nature must be differentiated. Either, then, nothing has 
a natural locomotion, or else there is no void. 

Further, in point of fact things that are thrown move though 
that which gave them their impulse is not touching them, either 
by reason of mutual replacement, as some maintain, or because 
the air that has been pushed pushes them with a movement 
quicker than the natural locomotion of the projectile wherewith 
it moves to its proper place. But in a void none of these things 



697 



can take place, nor can anything be moved save as that which is 
carried is moved. 

Further, no one could say why a thing once set in motion should 
stop anywhere; for why should it stop here rather than here? So 
that a thing will either be at rest or must be moved ad 
infinitum, unless something more powerful get in its way. 

Further, things are now thought to move into the void because it 
yields; but in a void this quality is present equally everywhere, 
so that things should move in all directions. 

Further, the truth of what we assert is plain from the following 
considerations. We see the same weight or body moving faster 
than another for two reasons, either because there is a 
difference in what it moves through, as between water, air, and 
earth, or because, other things being equal, the moving body 
differs from the other owing to excess of weight or of lightness. 

Now the medium causes a difference because it impedes the 
moving thing, most of all if it is moving in the opposite 
direction, but in a secondary degree even if it is at rest; and 
especially a medium that is not easily divided, i.e. a medium 
that is somewhat dense. A, then, will move through B in time G, 
and through D, which is thinner, in time E (if the length of B is 
egual to D), in proportion to the density of the hindering body. 
For let B be water and D air; then by so much as air is thinner 
and more incorporeal than water, A will move through D faster 
than through B. Let the speed have the same ratio to the speed, 
then, that air has to water. Then if air is twice as thin, the body 
will traverse B in twice the time that it does D, and the time G 
will be twice the time E. And always, by so much as the medium 
is more incorporeal and less resistant and more easily divided, 
the faster will be the movement. 



698 



Now there is no ratio in which the void is exceeded by body, as 
there is no ratio of to a number. For if 4 exceeds 3 by 1, and 2 
by more than 1, and 1 by still more than it exceeds 2, still there 
is no ratio by which it exceeds 0; for that which exceeds must 
be divisible into the excess + that which is exceeded, so that will 
be what it exceeds by + 0. For this reason, too, a line does not 
exceed a point unless it is composed of points! Similarly the 
void can bear no ratio to the full, and therefore neither can 
movement through the one to movement through the other, but 
if a thing moves through the thickest medium such and such a 
distance in such and such a time, it moves through the void 
with a speed beyond any ratio. For let Z be void, equal in 
magnitude to B and to D. Then if A is to traverse and move 
through it in a certain time, H, a time less than E, however, the 
void will bear this ratio to the full. But in a time equal to H, A 
will traverse the part of A. And it will surely also traverse in 
that time any substance Z which exceeds air in thickness in the 
ratio which the time E bears to the time H. For if the body Z be 
as much thinner than D as E exceeds H, A, if it moves through Z, 
will traverse it in a time inverse to the speed of the movement, 
i.e. in a time equal to H. If, then, there is no body in Z, A will 
traverse Z still more quickly. But we supposed that its traverse 
of Z when Z was void occupied the time H. So that it will 
traverse Z in an equal time whether Z be full or void. But this is 
impossible. It is plain, then, that if there is a time in which it 
will move through any part of the void, this impossible result 
will follow: it will be found to traverse a certain distance, 
whether this be full or void, in an equal time; for there will be 
some body which is in the same ratio to the other body as the 
time is to the time. 

To sum the matter up, the cause of this result is obvious, viz. 
that between any two movements there is a ratio (for they 
occupy time, and there is a ratio between any two times, so long 
as both are finite), but there is no ratio of void to full. 



699 



These are the consequences that result from a difference in the 
media; the following depend upon an excess of one moving 
body over another. We see that bodies which have a greater 
impulse either of weight or of lightness, if they are alike in other 
respects, move faster over an equal space, and in the ratio 
which their magnitudes bear to each other. Therefore they will 
also move through the void with this ratio of speed. But that is 
impossible; for why should one move faster? (In moving 
through plena it must be so; for the greater divides them faster 
by its force. For a moving thing cleaves the medium either by its 
shape, or by the impulse which the body that is carried along or 
is projected possesses.) Therefore all will possess equal velocity. 
But this is impossible. 

It is evident from what has been said, then, that, if there is a 
void, a result follows which is the very opposite of the reason 
for which those who believe in a void set it up. They think that if 
movement in respect of place is to exist, the void cannot exist, 
separated all by itself; but this is the same as to say that place is 
a separate cavity; and this has already been stated to be 
impossible. 

But even if we consider it on its own merits the so-called 
vacuum will be found to be really vacuous. For as, if one puts a 
cube in water, an amount of water equal to the cube will be 
displaced; so too in air; but the effect is imperceptible to sense. 
And indeed always in the case of any body that can be 
displaced, must, if it is not compressed, be displaced in the 
direction in which it is its nature to be displaced - always either 
down, if its locomotion is downwards as in the case of earth, or 
up, if it is fire, or in both directions - whatever be the nature of 
the inserted body. Now in the void this is impossible; for it is not 
body; the void must have penetrated the cube to a distance 
equal to that which this portion of void formerly occupied in 



700 



the void, just as if the water or air had not been displaced by the 
wooden cube, but had penetrated right through it. 

But the cube also has a magnitude equal to that occupied by the 
void; a magnitude which, if it is also hot or cold, or heavy or 
light, is none the less different in essence from all its attributes, 
even if it is not separable from them; I mean the volume of the 
wooden cube. So that even if it were separated from everything 
else and were neither heavy nor light, it will occupy an equal 
amount of void, and fill the same place, as the part of place or of 
the void equal to itself. How then will the body of the cube differ 
from the void or place that is equal to it? And if there can be 
two such things, why cannot there be any number coinciding? 

This, then, is one absurd and impossible implication of the 
theory. It is also evident that the cube will have this same 
volume even if it is displaced, which is an attribute possessed 
by all other bodies also. Therefore if this differs in no respect 
from its place, why need we assume a place for bodies over and 
above the volume of each, if their volume be conceived of as 
free from attributes? It contributes nothing to the situation if 
there is an equal interval attached to it as well. [Further it ought 
to be clear by the study of moving things what sort of thing void 
is. But in fact it is found nowhere in the world. For air is 
something, though it does not seem to be so - nor, for that 
matter, would water, if fishes were made of iron; for the 
discrimination of the tangible is by touch.] 

It is clear, then, from these considerations that there is no 
separate void. 



701 



There are some who think that the existence of rarity and 
density shows that there is a void. If rarity and density do not 
exist, they say, neither can things contract and be compressed. 
But if this were not to take place, either there would be no 
movement at all, or the universe would bulge, as Xuthus said, or 
air and water must always change into equal amounts (e.g. if air 
has been made out of a cupful of water, at the same time out of 
an equal amount of air a cupful of water must have been made), 
or void must necessarily exist; for compression and expansion 
cannot take place otherwise. 

Now, if they mean by the rare that which has many voids 
existing separately, it is plain that if void cannot exist separate 
any more than a place can exist with an extension all to itself, 
neither can the rare exist in this sense. But if they mean that 
there is void, not separately existent, but still present in the 
rare, this is less impossible, yet, first, the void turns out not to 
be a condition of all movement, but only of movement upwards 
(for the rare is light, which is the reason why they say fire is 
rare); second, the void turns out to be a condition of movement 
not as that in which it takes place, but in that the void carries 
things up as skins by being carried up themselves carry up what 
is continuous with them. Yet how can void have a local 
movement or a place? For thus that into which void moves is till 
then void of a void. 

Again, how will they explain, in the case of what is heavy, its 
movement downwards? And it is plain that if the rarer and 
more void a thing is the quicker it will move upwards, if it were 
completely void it would move with a maximum speed! But 
perhaps even this is impossible, that it should move at all; the 
same reason which showed that in the void all things are 



702 



incapable of moving shows that the void cannot move, viz. the 
fact that the speeds are incomparable. 

Since we deny that a void exists, but for the rest the problem 
has been truly stated, that either there will be no movement, if 
there is not to be condensation and rarefaction, or the universe 
will bulge, or a transformation of water into air will always be 
balanced by an equal transformation of air into water (for it is 
clear that the air produced from water is bulkier than the 
water): it is necessary therefore, if compression does not exist, 
either that the next portion will be pushed outwards and make 
the outermost part bulge, or that somewhere else there must be 
an equal amount of water produced out of air, so that the entire 
bulk of the whole may be equal, or that nothing moves. For 
when anything is displaced this will always happen, unless it 
comes round in a circle; but locomotion is not always circular, 
but sometimes in a straight line. 

These then are the reasons for which they might say that there 
is a void; our statement is based on the assumption that there is 
a single matter for contraries, hot and cold and the other 
natural contrarieties, and that what exists actually is produced 
from a potential existent, and that matter is not separable from 
the contraries but its being is different, and that a single matter 
may serve for colour and heat and cold. 

The same matter also serves for both a large and a small body. 
This is evident; for when air is produced from water, the same 
matter has become something different, not by acquiring an 
addition to it, but has become actually what it was potentially, 
and, again, water is produced from air in the same way, the 
change being sometimes from smallness to greatness, and 
sometimes from greatness to smallness. Similarly, therefore, if 
air which is large in extent comes to have a smaller volume, or 



703 



becomes greater from being smaller, it is the matter which is 
potentially both that comes to be each of the two. 

For as the same matter becomes hot from being cold, and cold 
from being hot, because it was potentially both, so too from hot 
it can become more hot, though nothing in the matter has 
become hot that was not hot when the thing was less hot; just 
as, if the arc or curve of a greater circle becomes that of a 
smaller, whether it remains the same or becomes a different 
curve, convexity has not come to exist in anything that was not 
convex but straight (for differences of degree do not depend on 
an intermission of the quality); nor can we get any portion of a 
flame, in which both heat and whiteness are not present. So too, 
then, is the earlier heat related to the later. So that the 
greatness and smallness, also, of the sensible volume are 
extended, not by the matter's acquiring anything new, but 
because the matter is potentially matter for both states; so that 
the same thing is dense and rare, and the two qualities have 
one matter. 

The dense is heavy, and the rare is light. [Again, as the arc of a 
circle when contracted into a smaller space does not acquire a 
new part which is convex, but what was there has been 
contracted; and as any part of fire that one takes will be hot; so, 
too, it is all a question of contraction and expansion of the same 
matter.] There are two types in each case, both in the dense and 
in the rare; for both the heavy and the hard are thought to be 
dense, and contrariwise both the light and the soft are rare; and 
weight and hardness fail to coincide in the case of lead and 
iron. 

From what has been said it is evident, then, that void does not 
exist either separate (either absolutely separate or as a separate 
element in the rare) or potentially, unless one is willing to call 
the condition of movement void, whatever it may be. At that 



704 



rate the matter of the heavy and the light, qua matter of them, 
would be the void; for the dense and the rare are productive of 
locomotion in virtue of this contrariety, and in virtue of their 
hardness and softness productive of passivity and impassivity, 
i.e. not of locomotion but rather of qualitative change. 

So much, then, for the discussion of the void, and of the sense 
in which it exists and the sense in which it does not exist. 



10 

Next for discussion after the subjects mentioned is Time. The 
best plan will be to begin by working out the difficulties 
connected with it, making use of the current arguments. First, 
does it belong to the class of things that exist or to that of 
things that do not exist? Then secondly, what is its nature? To 
start, then: the following considerations would make one 
suspect that it either does not exist at all or barely, and in an 
obscure way. One part of it has been and is not, while the other 
is going to be and is not yet. Yet time - both infinite time and 
any time you like to take - is made up of these. One would 
naturally suppose that what is made up of things which do not 
exist could have no share in reality. 

Further, if a divisible thing is to exist, it is necessary that, when 
it exists, all or some of its parts must exist. But of time some 
parts have been, while others have to be, and no part of it is 
though it is divisible. For what is 'now' is not a part: a part is a 
measure of the whole, which must be made up of parts. Time, 
on the other hand, is not held to be made up of 'nows'. 



705 



Again, the 'now' which seems to bound the past and the future 
- does it always remain one and the same or is it always other 
and other? It is hard to say. 

(1) If it is always different and different, and if none of the parts 
in time which are other and other are simultaneous (unless the 
one contains and the other is contained, as the shorter time is 
by the longer), and if the 'now' which is not, but formerly was, 
must have ceased-to-be at some time, the 'nows' too cannot be 
simultaneous with one another, but the prior 'now' must always 
have ceased-to-be. But the prior 'now' cannot have ceased-to-be 
in itself (since it then existed); yet it cannot have ceased-to-be 
in another 'now'. For we may lay it down that one 'now' cannot 
be next to another, any more than point to point. If then it did 
not cease-to-be in the next 'now' but in another, it would exist 
simultaneously with the innumerable 'nows' between the two - 
which is impossible. 

Yes, but (2) neither is it possible for the 'now' to remain always 
the same. No determinate divisible thing has a single 
termination, whether it is continuously extended in one or in 
more than one dimension: but the 'now' is a termination, and it 
is possible to cut off a determinate time. Further, if coincidence 
in time (i.e. being neither prior nor posterior) means to be 'in 
one and the same «now»', then, if both what is before and what 
is after are in this same 'now', things which happened ten 
thousand years ago would be simultaneous with what has 
happened to-day, and nothing would be before or after anything 
else. 

This may serve as a statement of the difficulties about the 
attributes of time. 

As to what time is or what is its nature, the traditional accounts 
give us as little light as the preliminary problems which we 
have worked through. 



706 



Some assert that it is (1) the movement of the whole, others 
that it is (2) the sphere itself. 

(1) Yet part, too, of the revolution is a time, but it certainly is not 
a revolution: for what is taken is part of a revolution, not a 
revolution. Besides, if there were more heavens than one, the 
movement of any of them equally would be time, so that there 
would be many times at the same time. 

(2) Those who said that time is the sphere of the whole thought 
so, no doubt, on the ground that all things are in time and all 
things are in the sphere of the whole. The view is too naive for it 
to be worth while to consider the impossibilities implied in it. 

But as time is most usually supposed to be (3) motion and a 
kind of change, we must consider this view. 

Now (a) the change or movement of each thing is only in the 
thing which changes or where the thing itself which moves or 
changes may chance to be. But time is present equally 
everywhere and with all things. 

Again, (b) change is always faster or slower, whereas time is not: 
for 'fast' and 'slow' are defined by time - 'fast' is what moves 
much in a short time, 'slow' what moves little in a long time; 
but time is not defined by time, by being either a certain 
amount or a certain kind of it. 

Clearly then it is not movement. (We need not distinguish at 
present between 'movement' and 'change'.) 



707 



11 

But neither does time exist without change; for when the state 
of our own minds does not change at all, or we have not noticed 
its changing, we do not realize that time has elapsed, any more 
than those who are fabled to sleep among the heroes in 
Sardinia do when they are awakened; for they connect the 
earlier 'now' with the later and make them one, cutting out the 
interval because of their failure to notice it. So, just as, if the 
'now' were not different but one and the same, there would not 
have been time, so too when its difference escapes our notice 
the interval does not seem to be time. If, then, the non- 
realization of the existence of time happens to us when we do 
not distinguish any change, but the soul seems to stay in one 
indivisible state, and when we perceive and distinguish we say 
time has elapsed, evidently time is not independent of 
movement and change. It is evident, then, that time is neither 
movement nor independent of movement. 

We must take this as our starting-point and try to discover - 
since we wish to know what time is - what exactly it has to do 
with movement. 

Now we perceive movement and time together: for even when it 
is dark and we are not being affected through the body, if any 
movement takes place in the mind we at once suppose that 
some time also has elapsed; and not only that but also, when 
some time is thought to have passed, some movement also 
along with it seems to have taken place. Hence time is either 
movement or something that belongs to movement. Since then 
it is not movement, it must be the other. 

But what is moved is moved from something to something, and 
all magnitude is continuous. Therefore the movement goes with 
the magnitude. Because the magnitude is continuous, the 
movement too must be continuous, and if the movement, then 



708 



the time; for the time that has passed is always thought to be in 
proportion to the movement. 

The distinction of 'before' and 'after' holds primarily, then, in 
place; and there in virtue of relative position. Since then 'before' 
and 'after' hold in magnitude, they must hold also in 
movement, these corresponding to those. But also in time the 
distinction of 'before' and 'after' must hold, for time and 
movement always correspond with each other. The 'before' and 
'after' in motion is identical in substratum with motion yet 
differs from it in definition, and is not identical with motion. 

But we apprehend time only when we have marked motion, 
marking it by 'before' and 'after'; and it is only when we have 
perceived 'before' and 'after' in motion that we say that time 
has elapsed. Now we mark them by judging that A and B are 
different, and that some third thing is intermediate to them. 
When we think of the extremes as different from the middle 
and the mind pronounces that the 'nows' are two, one before 
and one after, it is then that we say that there is time, and this 
that we say is time. For what is bounded by the 'now' is thought 
to be time - we may assume this. 

When, therefore, we perceive the 'now' one, and neither as 
before and after in a motion nor as an identity but in relation to 
a 'before' and an 'after', no time is thought to have elapsed, 
because there has been no motion either. On the other hand, 
when we do perceive a 'before' and an 'after', then we say that 
there is time. For time is just this - number of motion in respect 
of 'before' and 'after'. 

Hence time is not movement, but only movement in so far as it 
admits of enumeration. A proof of this: we discriminate the 
more or the less by number, but more or less movement by 
time. Time then is a kind of number. (Number, we must note, is 
used in two senses - both of what is counted or the countable 



709 



and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is 
counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds 
of thing.) Just as motion is a perpetual succession, so also is 
time. But every simultaneous time is self-identical; for the 'now' 
as a subject is an identity, but it accepts different attributes. The 
'now' measures time, in so far as time involves the 'before and 
after'. 

The 'now' in one sense is the same, in another it is not the 
same. In so far as it is in succession, it is different (which is just 
what its being was supposed to mean), but its substratum is an 
identity: for motion, as was said, goes with magnitude, and 
time, as we maintain, with motion. Similarly, then, there 
corresponds to the point the body which is carried along, and by 
which we are aware of the motion and of the 'before and after' 
involved in it. This is an identical substratum (whether a point 
or a stone or something else of the kind), but it has different 
attributes as the sophists assume that Coriscus' being in the 
Lyceum is a different thing from Coriscus' being in the market- 
place. And the body which is carried along is different, in so far 
as it is at one time here and at another there. But the 'now' 
corresponds to the body that is carried along, as time 
corresponds to the motion. For it is by means of the body that is 
carried along that we become aware of the 'before and after' the 
motion, and if we regard these as countable we get the 'now'. 
Hence in these also the 'now' as substratum remains the same 
(for it is what is before and after in movement), but what is 
predicated of it is different; for it is in so far as the 'before and 
after' is numerable that we get the 'now'. This is what is most 
knowable: for, similarly, motion is known because of that which 
is moved, locomotion because of that which is carried, what is 
carried is a real thing, the movement is not. Thus what is called 
'now' in one sense is always the same; in another it is not the 
same: for this is true also of what is carried. 



710 



Clearly, too, if there were no time, there would be no 'now', and 
vice versa, just as the moving body and its locomotion involve 
each other mutually, so too do the number of the moving body 
and the number of its locomotion. For the number of the 
locomotion is time, while the 'now' corresponds to the moving 
body, and is like the unit of number. 

Time, then, also is both made continuous by the 'now' and 
divided at it. For here too there is a correspondence with the 
locomotion and the moving body. For the motion or locomotion 
is made one by the thing which is moved, because it is one - not 
because it is one in its own nature (for there might be pauses in 
the movement of such a thing) - but because it is one in 
definition: for this determines the movement as 'before' and 
'after'. Here, too there is a correspondence with the point; for 
the point also both connects and terminates the length - it is 
the beginning of one and the end of another. But when you take 
it in this way, using the one point as two, a pause is necessary, if 
the same point is to be the beginning and the end. The 'now' on 
the other hand, since the body carried is moving, is always 
different. 

Hence time is not number in the sense in which there is 
'number' of the same point because it is beginning and end, but 
rather as the extremities of a line form a number, and not as the 
parts of the line do so, both for the reason given (for we can use 
the middle point as two, so that on that analogy time might 
stand still), and further because obviously the 'now' is no part of 
time nor the section any part of the movement, any more than 
the points are parts of the line - for it is two lines that are parts 
of one line. 

In so far then as the 'now' is a boundary, it is not time, but an 
attribute of it; in so far as it numbers, it is number; for 
boundaries belong only to that which they bound, but number 



711 



(e.g. ten) is the number of these horses, and belongs also 
elsewhere. 

It is clear, then, that time is 'number of movement in respect of 
the before and after', and is continuous since it is an attribute of 
what is continuous. 



12 

The smallest number, in the strict sense of the word 'number', is 
two. But of number as concrete, sometimes there is a minimum, 
sometimes not: e.g. of a 'line', the smallest in respect of 
multiplicity is two (or, if you like, one), but in respect of size 
there is no minimum; for every line is divided ad infinitum. 
Hence it is so with time. In respect of number the minimum is 
one (or two); in point of extent there is no minimum. 

It is clear, too, that time is not described as fast or slow, but as 
many or few and as long or short. For as continuous it is long or 
short and as a number many or few, but it is not fast or slow - 
any more than any number with which we number is fast or 
slow. 

Further, there is the same time everywhere at once, but not the 
same time before and after, for while the present change is one, 
the change which has happened and that which will happen 
are different. Time is not number with which we count, but the 
number of things which are counted, and this according as it 
occurs before or after is always different, for the 'nows' are 
different. And the number of a hundred horses and a hundred 
men is the same, but the things numbered are different - the 
horses from the men. Further, as a movement can be one and 



712 



the same again and again, so too can time, e.g. a year or a spring 
or an autumn. 

Not only do we measure the movement by the time, but also the 
time by the movement, because they define each other. The 
time marks the movement, since it is its number, and the 
movement the time. We describe the time as much or little, 
measuring it by the movement, just as we know the number by 
what is numbered, e.g. the number of the horses by one horse 
as the unit. For we know how many horses there are by the use 
of the number; and again by using the one horse as unit we 
know the number of the horses itself. So it is with the time and 
the movement; for we measure the movement by the time and 
vice versa. It is natural that this should happen; for the 
movement goes with the distance and the time with the 
movement, because they are quanta and continuous and 
divisible. The movement has these attributes because the 
distance is of this nature, and the time has them because of the 
movement. And we measure both the distance by the 
movement and the movement by the distance; for we say that 
the road is long, if the journey is long, and that this is long, if 
the road is long - the time, too, if the movement, and the 
movement, if the time. 

Time is a measure of motion and of being moved, and it 
measures the motion by determining a motion which will 
measure exactly the whole motion, as the cubit does the length 
by determining an amount which will measure out the whole. 
Further 'to be in time' means for movement, that both it and its 
essence are measured by time (for simultaneously it measures 
both the movement and its essence, and this is what being in 
time means for it, that its essence should be measured). 

Clearly then 'to be in time' has the same meaning for other 
things also, namely, that their being should be measured by 



713 



time. 'To be in time' is one of two things: (1) to exist when time 
exists, (2) as we say of some things that they are 'in number'. 
The latter means either what is a part or mode of number - in 
general, something which belongs to number - or that things 
have a number. 

Now, since time is number, the 'now' and the 'before' and the 
like are in time, just as 'unit' and 'odd' and 'even' are in number, 
i.e. in the sense that the one set belongs to number, the other to 
time. But things are in time as they are in number. If this is so, 
they are contained by time as things in place are contained by 
place. 

Plainly, too, to be in time does not mean to co-exist with time, 
any more than to be in motion or in place means to co-exist 
with motion or place. For if 'to be in something' is to mean this, 
then all things will be in anything, and the heaven will be in a 
grain; for when the grain is, then also is the heaven. But this is a 
merely incidental conjunction, whereas the other is necessarily 
involved: that which is in time necessarily involves that there is 
time when it is, and that which is in motion that there is 
motion when it is. 

Since what is 'in time' is so in the same sense as what is in 
number is so, a time greater than everything in time can be 
found. So it is necessary that all the things in time should be 
contained by time, just like other things also which are 'in 
anything', e.g. the things 'in place' by place. 

A thing, then, will be affected by time, just as we are 
accustomed to say that time wastes things away, and that all 
things grow old through time, and that there is oblivion owing 
to the lapse of time, but we do not say the same of getting to 
know or of becoming young or fair. For time is by its nature the 
cause rather of decay, since it is the number of change, and 
change removes what is. 



714 



Hence, plainly, things which are always are not, as such, in time, 
for they are not contained time, nor is their being measured by 
time. A proof of this is that none of them is affected by time, 
which indicates that they are not in time. 

Since time is the measure of motion, it will be the measure of 
rest too - indirectly. For all rest is in time. For it does not follow 
that what is in time is moved, though what is in motion is 
necessarily moved. For time is not motion, but 'number of 
motion': and what is at rest, also, can be in the number of 
motion. Not everything that is not in motion can be said to be 
'at rest' - but only that which can be moved, though it actually 
is not moved, as was said above. 

'To be in number' means that there is a number of the thing, 
and that its being is measured by the number in which it is. 
Hence if a thing is 'in time' it will be measured by time. But time 
will measure what is moved and what is at rest, the one qua 
moved, the other qua at rest; for it will measure their motion 
and rest respectively. 

Hence what is moved will not be measurable by the time simply 
in so far as it has quantity, but in so far as its motion has 
quantity. Thus none of the things which are neither moved nor 
at rest are in time: for 'to be in time' is 'to be measured by time', 
while time is the measure of motion and rest. 

Plainly, then, neither will everything that does not exist be in 
time, i.e. those non-existent things that cannot exist, as the 
diagonal cannot be commensurate with the side. 

Generally, if time is directly the measure of motion and 
indirectly of other things, it is clear that a thing whose 
existence is measured by it will have its existence in rest or 
motion. Those things therefore which are subject to perishing 
and becoming - generally, those which at one time exist, at 



715 



another do not - are necessarily in time: for there is a greater 
time which will extend both beyond their existence and beyond 
the time which measures their existence. Of things which do 
not exist but are contained by time some were, e.g. Homer once 
was, some will be, e.g. a future event; this depends on the 
direction in which time contains them; if on both, they have 
both modes of existence. As to such things as it does not 
contain in any way, they neither were nor are nor will be. These 
are those nonexistents whose opposites always are, as the 
incommensurability of the diagonal always is - and this will not 
be in time. Nor will the commensurability, therefore; hence this 
eternally is not, because it is contrary to what eternally is. A 
thing whose contrary is not eternal can be and not be, and it is 
of such things that there is coming to be and passing away. 



13 

The 'now' is the link of time, as has been said (for it connects 
past and future time), and it is a limit of time (for it is the 
beginning of the one and the end of the other). But this is not 
obvious as it is with the point, which is fixed. It divides 
potentially, and in so far as it is dividing the 'now' is always 
different, but in so far as it connects it is always the same, as it 
is with mathematical lines. For the intellect it is not always one 
and the same point, since it is other and other when one divides 
the line; but in so far as it is one, it is the same in every respect. 

So the 'now' also is in one way a potential dividing of time, in 
another the termination of both parts, and their unity. And the 
dividing and the uniting are the same thing and in the same 
reference, but in essence they are not the same. 



716 



So one kind of 'now' is described in this way: another is when 
the time is near this kind of 'now'. 'He will come now' because 
he will come to-day; 'he has come now' because he came to-day. 
But the things in the Iliad have not happened 'now', nor is the 
flood 'now' - not that the time from now to them is not 
continuous, but because they are not near. 

'At some time' means a time determined in relation to the first 
of the two types of 'now', e.g. 'at some time' Troy was taken, and 
'at some time' there will be a flood; for it must be determined 
with reference to the 'now'. There will thus be a determinate 
time from this 'now' to that, and there was such in reference to 
the past event. But if there be no time which is not 'sometime', 
every time will be determined. 

Will time then fail? Surely not, if motion always exists. Is time 
then always different or does the same time recur? Clearly time 
is, in the same way as motion is. For if one and the same motion 
sometimes recurs, it will be one and the same time, and if not, 
not. 

Since the 'now' is an end and a beginning of time, not of the 
same time however, but the end of that which is past and the 
beginning of that which is to come, it follows that, as the circle 
has its convexity and its concavity, in a sense, in the same thing, 
so time is always at a beginning and at an end. And for this 
reason it seems to be always different; for the 'now' is not the 
beginning and the end of the same thing; if it were, it would be 
at the same time and in the same respect two opposites. And 
time will not fail; for it is always at a beginning. 

'Presently' or 'just' refers to the part of future time which is near 
the indivisible present 'now' ('When do you walk? 'Presently', 
because the time in which he is going to do so is near), and to 
the part of past time which is not far from the 'now' ('When do 
you walk?' 'I have just been walking'). But to say that Troy has 



717 



just been taken - we do not say that, because it is too far from 
the 'now'. 'Lately', too, refers to the part of past time which is 
near the present 'now'. 'When did you go?' 'Lately', if the time is 
near the existing now. 'Long ago' refers to the distant past. 

'Suddenly' refers to what has departed from its former 
condition in a time imperceptible because of its smallness; but 
it is the nature of all change to alter things from their former 
condition. In time all things come into being and pass away; for 
which reason some called it the wisest of all things, but the 
Pythagorean Paron called it the most stupid, because in it we 
also forget; and his was the truer view. It is clear then that it 
must be in itself, as we said before, the condition of destruction 
rather than of coming into being (for change, in itself, makes 
things depart from their former condition), and only 
incidentally of coming into being, and of being. A sufficient 
evidence of this is that nothing comes into being without itself 
moving somehow and acting, but a thing can be destroyed even 
if it does not move at all. And this is what, as a rule, we chiefly 
mean by a thing's being destroyed by time. Still, time does not 
work even this change; even this sort of change takes place 
incidentally in time. 

We have stated, then, that time exists and what it is, and in how 
many senses we speak of the 'now', and what 'at some time', 
'lately', 'presently' or 'just', 'long ago', and 'suddenly' mean. 



14 

These distinctions having been drawn, it is evident that every 
change and everything that moves is in time; for the distinction 
of faster and slower exists in reference to all change, since it is 
found in every instance. In the phrase 'moving faster' I refer to 



718 



that which changes before another into the condition in 
question, when it moves over the same interval and with a 
regular movement; e.g. in the case of locomotion, if both things 
move along the circumference of a circle, or both along a 
straight line; and similarly in all other cases. But what is before 
is in time; for we say 'before' and 'after' with reference to the 
distance from the 'now', and the 'now' is the boundary of the 
past and the future; so that since 'nows' are in time, the before 
and the after will be in time too; for in that in which the 'now' 
is, the distance from the 'now' will also be. But 'before' is used 
contrariwise with reference to past and to future time; for in the 
past we call 'before' what is farther from the 'now', and 'after' 
what is nearer, but in the future we call the nearer 'before' and 
the farther 'after'. So that since the 'before' is in time, and every 
movement involves a 'before', evidently every change and every 
movement is in time. 

It is also worth considering how time can be related to the soul; 
and why time is thought to be in everything, both in earth and 
in sea and in heaven. Is because it is an attribute, or state, or 
movement (since it is the number of movement) and all these 
things are movable (for they are all in place), and time and 
movement are together, both in respect of potentiality and in 
respect of actuality? 

Whether if soul did not exist time would exist or not, is a 
question that may fairly be asked; for if there cannot be some 
one to count there cannot be anything that can be counted, so 
that evidently there cannot be number; for number is either 
what has been, or what can be, counted. But if nothing but soul, 
or in soul reason, is qualified to count, there would not be time 
unless there were soul, but only that of which time is an 
attribute, i.e. if movement can exist without soul, and the before 
and after are attributes of movement, and time is these qua 
numerable. 



719 



One might also raise the question what sort of movement time 
is the number of. Must we not say 'of any kind? For things both 
come into being in time and pass away, and grow, and are 
altered in time, and are moved locally; thus it is of each 
movement qua movement that time is the number. And so it is 
simply the number of continuous movement, not of any 
particular kind of it. 

But other things as well may have been moved now, and there 
would be a number of each of the two movements. Is there 
another time, then, and will there be two equal times at once? 
Surely not. For a time that is both equal and simultaneous is 
one and the same time, and even those that are not 
simultaneous are one in kind; for if there were dogs, and horses, 
and seven of each, it would be the same number. So, too, 
movements that have simultaneous limits have the same time, 
yet the one may in fact be fast and the other not, and one may 
be locomotion and the other alteration; still the time of the two 
changes is the same if their number also is equal and 
simultaneous; and for this reason, while the movements are 
different and separate, the time is everywhere the same, 
because the number of equal and simultaneous movements is 
everywhere one and the same. 

Now there is such a thing as locomotion, and in locomotion 
there is included circular movement, and everything is 
measured by some one thing homogeneous with it, units by a 
unit, horses by a horse, and similarly times by some definite 
time, and, as we said, time is measured by motion as well as 
motion by time (this being so because by a motion definite in 
time the quantity both of the motion and of the time is 
measured): if, then, what is first is the measure of everything 
homogeneous with it, regular circular motion is above all else 
the measure, because the number of this is the best known. 
Now neither alteration nor increase nor coming into being can 



720 



be regular, but locomotion can be. This also is why time is 
thought to be the movement of the sphere, viz. because the 
other movements are measured by this, and time by this 
movement. 

This also explains the common saying that human affairs form 
a circle, and that there is a circle in all other things that have a 
natural movement and coming into being and passing away. 
This is because all other things are discriminated by time, and 
end and begin as though conforming to a cycle; for even time 
itself is thought to be a circle. And this opinion again is held 
because time is the measure of this kind of locomotion and is 
itself measured by such. So that to say that the things that 
come into being form a circle is to say that there is a circle of 
time; and this is to say that it is measured by the circular 
movement; for apart from the measure nothing else to be 
measured is observed; the whole is just a plurality of measures. 

It is said rightly, too, that the number of the sheep and of the 
dogs is the same number if the two numbers are equal, but not 
the same decad or the same ten; just as the equilateral and the 
scalene are not the same triangle, yet they are the same figure, 
because they are both triangles. For things are called the same 
so-and-so if they do not differ by a differentia of that thing, but 
not if they do; e.g. triangle differs from triangle by a differentia 
of triangle, therefore they are different triangles; but they do not 
differ by a differentia of figure, but are in one and the same 
division of it. For a figure of the one kind is a circle and a figure 
of another kind of triangle, and a triangle of one kind is 
equilateral and a triangle of another kind scalene. They are the 
same figure, then, that, triangle, but not the same triangle. 
Therefore the number of two groups also - is the same number 
(for their number does not differ by a differentia of number), but 
it is not the same decad; for the things of which it is asserted 
differ; one group are dogs, and the other horses. 



721 



We have now discussed time - both time itself and the matters 
appropriate to the consideration of it. 



BookV 



Everything which changes does so in one of three senses. It may 
change (1) accidentally, as for instance when we say that 
something musical walks, that which walks being something in 
which aptitude for music is an accident. Again (2) a thing is said 
without qualification to change because something belonging to 
it changes, i.e. in statements which refer to part of the thing in 
question: thus the body is restored to health because the eye or 
the chest, that is to say a part of the whole body, is restored to 
health. And above all there is (3) the case of a thing which is in 
motion neither accidentally nor in respect of something else 
belonging to it, but in virtue of being itself directly in motion. 
Here we have a thing which is essentially movable: and that 
which is so is a different thing according to the particular 
variety of motion: for instance it may be a thing capable of 
alteration: and within the sphere of alteration it is again a 
different thing according as it is capable of being restored to 
health or capable of being heated. And there are the same 
distinctions in the case of the mover: (1) one thing causes 
motion accidentally, (2) another partially (because something 
belonging to it causes motion), (3) another of itself directly, as, 



722 



for instance, the physician heals, the hand strikes. We have, 
then, the following factors: (a) on the one hand that which 
directly causes motion, and (b) on the other hand that which is 
in motion: further, we have (c) that in which motion takes place, 
namely time, and (distinct from these three) (d) that from which 
and (e) that to which it proceeds: for every motion proceeds 
from something and to something, that which is directly in 
motion being distinct from that to which it is in motion and 
that from which it is in motion: for instance, we may take the 
three things 'wood', 'hot', and 'cold', of which the first is that 
which is in motion, the second is that to which the motion 
proceeds, and the third is that from which it proceeds. This 
being so, it is clear that the motion is in the wood, not in its 
form: for the motion is neither caused nor experienced by the 
form or the place or the quantity. So we are left with a mover, a 
moved, and a goal of motion. I do not include the starting-point 
of motion: for it is the goal rather than the starting-point of 
motion that gives its name to a particular process of change. 
Thus 'perishing' is change to not-being, though it is also true 
that that that which perishes changes from being: and 
'becoming' is change to being, though it is also change from 
not-being. 

Now a definition of motion has been given above, from which it 
will be seen that every goal of motion, whether it be a form, an 
affection, or a place, is immovable, as, for instance, knowledge 
and heat. Here, however, a difficulty may be raised. Affections, it 
may be said, are motions, and whiteness is an affection: thus 
there may be change to a motion. To this we may reply that it is 
not whiteness but whitening that is a motion. Here also the 
same distinctions are to be observed: a goal of motion may be 
so accidentally, or partially and with reference to something 
other than itself, or directly and with no reference to anything 
else: for instance, a thing which is becoming white changes 
accidentally to an object of thought, the colour being only 



723 



accidentally the object of thought; it changes to colour, because 
white is a part of colour, or to Europe, because Athens is a part 
of Europe; but it changes essentially to white colour. It is now 
clear in what sense a thing is in motion essentially, accidentally, 
or in respect of something other than itself, and in what sense 
the phrase 'itself directly' is used in the case both of the mover 
and of the moved: and it is also clear that the motion is not in 
the form but in that which is in motion, that is to say 'the 
movable in activity'. Now accidental change we may leave out of 
account: for it is to be found in everything, at any time, and in 
any respect. Change which is not accidental on the other hand 
is not to be found in everything, but only in contraries, in things 
intermediate contraries, and in contradictories, as may be 
proved by induction. An intermediate may be a starting-point of 
change, since for the purposes of the change it serves as 
contrary to either of two contraries: for the intermediate is in a 
sense the extremes. Hence we speak of the intermediate as in a 
sense a contrary relatively to the extremes and of either 
extreme as a contrary relatively to the intermediate: for 
instance, the central note is low relatively to the highest and 
high relatively to the lowest, and grey is light relatively to black 
and dark relatively to white. 

And since every change is from something to something - as 
the word itself (metabole) indicates, implying something 'after' 
(meta) something else, that is to say something earlier and 
something later - that which changes must change in one of 
four ways: from subject to subject, from subject to nonsubject, 
from non-subject to subject, or from non-subject to non-subject, 
where by 'subject' I mean what is affirmatively expressed. So it 
follows necessarily from what has been said above that there 
are only three kinds of change, that from subject to subject, that 
from subject to non-subject, and that from non-subject to 
subject: for the fourth conceivable kind, that from non-subject 



724 



to non-subject, is not change, as in that case there is no 
opposition either of contraries or of contradictories. 

Now change from non-subject to subject, the relation being that 
of contradiction, is 'coming to be' - 'unqualified coming to be' 
when the change takes place in an unqualified way, 'particular 
coming to be' when the change is change in a particular 
character: for instance, a change from not-white to white is a 
coming to be of the particular thing, white, while change from 
unqualified not-being to being is coming to be in an unqualified 
way, in respect of which we say that a thing 'comes to be' 
without qualification, not that it 'comes to be' some particular 
thing. Change from subject to non-subject is 'perishing' - 
'unqualified perishing' when the change is from being to not- 
being, 'particular perishing' when the change is to the opposite 
negation, the distinction being the same as that made in the 
case of coming to be. 

Now the expression 'not-being' is used in several senses: and 
there can be motion neither of that which 'is not' in respect of 
the affirmation or negation of a predicate, nor of that which 'is 
not' in the sense that it only potentially 'is', that is to say the 
opposite of that which actually 'is' in an unqualified sense: for 
although that which is 'not-white' or 'not-good' may 
nevertheless he in motion accidentally (for example that which 
is 'not-white' might be a man), yet that which is without 
qualification 'not-so-and-so' cannot in any sense be in motion: 
therefore it is impossible for that which is not to be in motion. 
This being so, it follows that 'becoming' cannot be a motion: for 
it is that which 'is not' that 'becomes'. For however true it may 
be that it accidentally 'becomes', it is nevertheless correct to say 
that it is that which 'is not' that in an unqualified sense 
'becomes'. And similarly it is impossible for that which 'is not' 
to be at rest. 



725 



There are these difficulties, then, in the way of the assumption 
that that which 'is not' can be in motion: and it may be further 
objected that, whereas everything which is in motion is in 
space, that which 'is not' is not in space: for then it would be 
somewhere. 

So, too, 'perishing' is not a motion: for a motion has for its 
contrary either another motion or rest, whereas 'perishing' is 
the contrary of 'becoming'. 

Since, then, every motion is a kind of change, and there are only 
the three kinds of change mentioned above, and since of these 
three those which take the form of 'becoming' and 'perishing', 
that is to say those which imply a relation of contradiction, are 
not motions: it necessarily follows that only change from 
subject to subject is motion. And every such subject is either a 
contrary or an intermediate (for a privation may be allowed to 
rank as a contrary) and can be affirmatively expressed, as 
naked, toothless, or black. If, then, the categories are severally 
distinguished as Being, Quality, Place, Time, Relation, Quantity, 
and Activity or Passivity, it necessarily follows that there are 
three kinds of motion - qualitative, quantitative, and local. 



In respect of Substance there is no motion, because Substance 
has no contrary among things that are. Nor is there motion in 
respect of Relation: for it may happen that when one correlative 
changes, the other, although this does not itself change, is no 
longer applicable, so that in these cases the motion is 
accidental. Nor is there motion in respect of Agent and Patient - 
in fact there can never be motion of mover and moved, because 



726 



there cannot be motion of motion or becoming of becoming or 
in general change of change. 

For in the first place there are two senses in which motion of 
motion is conceivable. (1) The motion of which there is motion 
might be conceived as subject; e.g. a man is in motion because 
he changes from fair to dark. Can it be that in this sense motion 
grows hot or cold, or changes place, or increases or decreases? 
Impossible: for change is not a subject. Or (2) can there be 
motion of motion in the sense that some other subject changes 
from a change to another mode of being, as e.g. a man changes 
from falling ill to getting well? Even this is possible only in an 
accidental sense. For, whatever the subject may be, movement 
is change from one form to another. (And the same holds good 
of becoming and perishing, except that in these processes we 
have a change to a particular kind of opposite, while the other, 
motion, is a change to a different kind.) So, if there is to be 
motion of motion, that which is changing from health to 
sickness must simultaneously be changing from this very 
change to another. It is clear, then, that by the time that it has 
become sick, it must also have changed to whatever may be the 
other change concerned (for that it should be at rest, though 
logically possible, is excluded by the theory). Moreover this 
other can never be any casual change, but must be a change 
from something definite to some other definite thing. So in this 
case it must be the opposite change, viz. convalescence. It is 
only accidentally that there can be change of change, e.g. there 
is a change from remembering to forgetting only because the 
subject of this change changes at one time to knowledge, at 
another to ignorance. 

In the second place, if there is to be change of change and 
becoming of becoming, we shall have an infinite regress. Thus if 
one of a series of changes is to be a change of change, the 
preceding change must also be so: e.g. if simple becoming was 



727 



ever in process of becoming, then that which was becoming 
simple becoming was also in process of becoming, so that we 
should not yet have arrived at what was in process of simple 
becoming but only at what was already in process of becoming 
in process of becoming. And this again was sometime in process 
of becoming, so that even then we should not have arrived at 
what was in process of simple becoming. And since in an 
infinite series there is no first term, here there will be no first 
stage and therefore no following stage either. On this 
hypothesis, then, nothing can become or be moved or change. 

Thirdly, if a thing is capable of any particular motion, it is also 
capable of the corresponding contrary motion or the 
corresponding coming to rest, and a thing that is capable of 
becoming is also capable of perishing: consequently, if there be 
becoming of becoming, that which is in process of becoming is 
in process of perishing at the very moment when it has reached 
the stage of becoming: since it cannot be in process of perishing 
when it is just beginning to become or after it has ceased to 
become: for that which is in process of perishing must be in 
existence. 

Fourthly, there must be a substrate underlying all processes of 
becoming and changing. What can this be in the present case? 
It is either the body or the soul that undergoes alteration: what 
is it that correspondingly becomes motion or becoming? And 
again what is the goal of their motion? It must be the motion or 
becoming of something from something to something else. But 
in what sense can this be so? For the becoming of learning 
cannot be learning: so neither can the becoming of becoming be 
becoming, nor can the becoming of any process be that process. 

Finally, since there are three kinds of motion, the substratum 
and the goal of motion must be one or other of these, e.g. 
locomotion will have to be altered or to be locally moved. 



728 



To sum up, then, since everything that is moved is moved in one 
of three ways, either accidentally, or partially, or essentially, 
change can change only accidentally, as e.g. when a man who is 
being restored to health runs or learns: and accidental change 
we have long ago decided to leave out of account. 

Since, then, motion can belong neither to Being nor to Relation 
nor to Agent and Patient, it remains that there can be motion 
only in respect of Quality, Quantity, and Place: for with each of 
these we have a pair of contraries. Motion in respect of Quality 
let us call alteration, a general designation that is used to 
include both contraries: and by Quality I do not here mean a 
property of substance (in that sense that which constitutes a 
specific distinction is a quality) but a passive quality in virtue of 
which a thing is said to be acted on or to be incapable of being 
acted on. Motion in respect of Quantity has no name that 
includes both contraries, but it is called increase or decrease 
according as one or the other is designated: that is to say 
motion in the direction of complete magnitude is increase, 
motion in the contrary direction is decrease. Motion in respect 
of Place has no name either general or particular: but we may 
designate it by the general name of locomotion, though strictly 
the term 'locomotion' is applicable to things that change their 
place only when they have not the power to come to a stand, 
and to things that do not move themselves locally. 

Change within the same kind from a lesser to a greater or from 
a greater to a lesser degree is alteration: for it is motion either 
from a contrary or to a contrary, whether in an unqualified or in 
a qualified sense: for change to a lesser degree of a quality will 
be called change to the contrary of that quality, and change to a 
greater degree of a quality will be regarded as change from the 
contrary of that quality to the quality itself. It makes no 
difference whether the change be qualified or unqualified, 
except that in the former case the contraries will have to be 



729 



contrary to one another only in a qualified sense: and a thing's 
possessing a quality in a greater or in a lesser degree means the 
presence or absence in it of more or less of the opposite quality. 
It is now clear, then, that there are only these three kinds of 
motion. 

The term 'immovable' we apply in the first place to that which 
is absolutely incapable of being moved (just as we 
correspondingly apply the term invisible to sound); in the 
second place to that which is moved with difficulty after a long 
time or whose movement is slow at the start - in fact, what we 
describe as hard to move; and in the third place to that which is 
naturally designed for and capable of motion, but is not in 
motion when, where, and as it naturally would be so. This last is 
the only kind of immovable thing of which I use the term 'being 
at rest': for rest is contrary to motion, so that rest will be 
negation of motion in that which is capable of admitting 
motion. 

The foregoing remarks are sufficient to explain the essential 
nature of motion and rest, the number of kinds of change, and 
the different varieties of motion. 



Let us now proceed to define the terms 'together' and 'apart', 'in 
contact', 'between', 'in succession', 'contiguous', and 
'continuous', and to show in what circumstances each of these 
terms is naturally applicable. 

Things are said to be together in place when they are in one 
place (in the strictest sense of the word 'place') and to be apart 
when they are in different places. 



730 



Things are said to be in contact when their extremities are 
together. 

That which a changing thing, if it changes continuously in a 
natural manner, naturally reaches before it reaches that to 
which it changes last, is between. Thus 'between' implies the 
presence of at least three things: for in a process of change it is 
the contrary that is 'last': and a thing is moved continuously if it 
leaves no gap or only the smallest possible gap in the material - 
not in the time (for a gap in the time does not prevent things 
having a 'between', while, on the other hand, there is nothing to 
prevent the highest note sounding immediately after the 
lowest) but in the material in which the motion takes place. 
This is manifestly true not only in local changes but in every 
other kind as well. (Now every change implies a pair of 
opposites, and opposites may be either contraries or 
contradictories; since then contradiction admits of no mean 
term, it is obvious that 'between' must imply a pair of 
contraries) That is locally contrary which is most distant in a 
straight line: for the shortest line is definitely limited, and that 
which is definitely limited constitutes a measure. 

A thing is 'in succession' when it is after the beginning in 
position or in form or in some other respect in which it is 
definitely so regarded, and when further there is nothing of the 
same kind as itself between it and that to which it is in 
succession, e.g. a line or lines if it is a line, a unit or units if it is 
a unit, a house if it is a house (there is nothing to prevent 
something of a different kind being between). For that which is 
in succession is in succession to a particular thing, and is 
something posterior: for one is not 'in succession' to two, nor is 
the first day of the month to be second: in each case the latter is 
'in succession' to the former. 



731 



A thing that is in succession and touches is 'contiguous'. The 
'continuous' is a subdivision of the contiguous: things are called 
continuous when the touching limits of each become one and 
the same and are, as the word implies, contained in each other: 
continuity is impossible if these extremities are two. This 
definition makes it plain that continuity belongs to things that 
naturally in virtue of their mutual contact form a unity. And in 
whatever way that which holds them together is one, so too will 
the whole be one, e.g. by a rivet or glue or contact or organic 
union. 

It is obvious that of these terms 'in succession' is first in order 
of analysis: for that which touches is necessarily in succession, 
but not everything that is in succession touches: and so 
succession is a property of things prior in definition, e.g. 
numbers, while contact is not. And if there is continuity there is 
necessarily contact, but if there is contact, that alone does not 
imply continuity: for the extremities of things may be 'together' 
without necessarily being one: but they cannot be one without 
being necessarily together. So natural junction is last in coming 
to be: for the extremities must necessarily come into contact if 
they are to be naturally joined: but things that are in contact are 
not all naturally joined, while there is no contact clearly there is 
no natural junction either. Hence, if as some say 'point' and 
'unit' have an independent existence of their own, it is 
impossible for the two to be identical: for points can touch 
while units can only be in succession. Moreover, there can 
always be something between points (for all lines are 
intermediate between points), whereas it is not necessary that 
there should possibly be anything between units: for there can 
be nothing between the numbers one and two. 

We have now defined what is meant by 'together' and 'apart', 
'contact', 'between' and 'in succession', 'contiguous' and 



732 



'continuous': and we have shown in what circumstances each 
of these terms is applicable. 



There are many senses in which motion is said to be 'one': for 
we use the term 'one' in many senses. 

Motion is one generically according to the different categories to 
which it may be assigned: thus any locomotion is one 
generically with any other locomotion, whereas alteration is 
different generically from locomotion. 

Motion is one specifically when besides being one generically it 
also takes place in a species incapable of subdivision: e.g. colour 
has specific differences: therefore blackening and whitening 
differ specifically; but at all events every whitening will be 
specifically the same with every other whitening and every 
blackening with every other blackening. But white is not further 
subdivided by specific differences: hence any whitening is 
specifically one with any other whitening. Where it happens 
that the genus is at the same time a species, it is clear that the 
motion will then in a sense be one specifically though not in an 
unqualified sense: learning is an example of this, knowledge 
being on the one hand a species of apprehension and on the 
other hand a genus including the various knowledges. A 
difficulty, however, may be raised as to whether a motion is 
specifically one when the same thing changes from the same to 
the same, e.g. when one point changes again and again from a 
particular place to a particular place: if this motion is 
specifically one, circular motion will be the same as rectilinear 
motion, and rolling the same as walking. But is not this 
difficulty removed by the principle already laid down that if that 



733 



in which the motion takes place is specifically different (as in 
the present instance the circular path is specifically different 
from the straight) the motion itself is also different? We have 
explained, then, what is meant by saying that motion is one 
generically or one specifically. 

Motion is one in an unqualified sense when it is one essentially 
or numerically: and the following distinctions will make clear 
what this kind of motion is. There are three classes of things in 
connexion with which we speak of motion, the 'that which', the 
'that in which', and the 'that during which'. I mean that there 
must he something that is in motion, e.g. a man or gold, and it 
must be in motion in something, e.g. a place or an affection, and 
during something, for all motion takes place during a time. Of 
these three it is the thing in which the motion takes place that 
makes it one generically or specifically, it is the thing moved 
that makes the motion one in subject, and it is the time that 
makes it consecutive: but it is the three together that make it 
one without qualification: to effect this, that in which the 
motion takes place (the species) must be one and incapable of 
subdivision, that during which it takes place (the time) must be 
one and unintermittent, and that which is in motion must be 
one - not in an accidental sense (i.e. it must be one as the white 
that blackens is one or Coriscus who walks is one, not in the 
accidental sense in which Coriscus and white may be one), nor 
merely in virtue of community of nature (for there might be a 
case of two men being restored to health at the same time in 
the same way, e.g. from inflammation of the eye, yet this motion 
is not really one, but only specifically one). 

Suppose, however, that Socrates undergoes an alteration 
specifically the same but at one time and again at another: in 
this case if it is possible for that which ceased to be again to 
come into being and remain numerically the same, then this 
motion too will be one: otherwise it will be the same but not 



734 



one. And akin to this difficulty there is another; viz. is health 
one? and generally are the states and affections in bodies 
severally one in essence although (as is clear) the things that 
contain them are obviously in motion and in flux? Thus if a 
person's health at daybreak and at the present moment is one 
and the same, why should not this health be numerically one 
with that which he recovers after an interval? The same 
argument applies in each case. There is, however, we may 
answer, this difference: that if the states are two then it follows 
simply from this fact that the activities must also in point of 
number be two (for only that which is numerically one can give 
rise to an activity that is numerically one), but if the state is one, 
this is not in itself enough to make us regard the activity also as 
one: for when a man ceases walking, the walking no longer is, 
but it will again be if he begins to walk again. But, be this as it 
may, if in the above instance the health is one and the same, 
then it must be possible for that which is one and the same to 
come to be and to cease to be many times. However, these 
difficulties lie outside our present inquiry. 

Since every motion is continuous, a motion that is one in an 
unqualified sense must (since every motion is divisible) be 
continuous, and a continuous motion must be one. There will 
not be continuity between any motion and any other 
indiscriminately any more than there is between any two things 
chosen at random in any other sphere: there can be continuity 
only when the extremities of the two things are one. Now some 
things have no extremities at all: and the extremities of others 
differ specifically although we give them the same name of 
'end': how should e.g. the 'end' of a line and the 'end' of walking 
touch or come to be one? Motions that are not the same either 
specifically or generically may, it is true, be consecutive (e.g. a 
man may run and then at once fall ill of a fever), and again, in 
the torch-race we have consecutive but not continuous 
locomotion: for according to our definition there can be 



735 



continuity only when the ends of the two things are one. Hence 
motions may be consecutive or successive in virtue of the time 
being continuous, but there can be continuity only in virtue of 
the motions themselves being continuous, that is when the end 
of each is one with the end of the other. Motion, therefore, that 
is in an unqualified sense continuous and one must be 
specifically the same, of one thing, and in one time. Unity is 
required in respect of time in order that there may be no 
interval of immobility, for where there is intermission of motion 
there must be rest, and a motion that includes intervals of rest 
will be not one but many, so that a motion that is interrupted by 
stationariness is not one or continuous, and it is so interrupted 
if there is an interval of time. And though of a motion that is not 
specifically one (even if the time is unintermittent) the time is 
one, the motion is specifically different, and so cannot really be 
one, for motion that is one must be specifically one, though 
motion that is specifically one is not necessarily one in an 
unqualified sense. We have now explained what we mean when 
we call a motion one without qualification. 

Further, a motion is also said to be one generically, specifically, 
or essentially when it is complete, just as in other cases 
completeness and wholeness are characteristics of what is one: 
and sometimes a motion even if incomplete is said to be one, 
provided only that it is continuous. 

And besides the cases already mentioned there is another in 
which a motion is said to be one, viz. when it is regular: for in a 
sense a motion that is irregular is not regarded as one, that title 
belonging rather to that which is regular, as a straight line is 
regular, the irregular being as such divisible. But the difference 
would seem to be one of degree. In every kind of motion we may 
have regularity or irregularity: thus there may be regular 
alteration, and locomotion in a regular path, e.g. in a circle or on 
a straight line, and it is the same with regard to increase and 



736 



decrease. The difference that makes a motion irregular is 
sometimes to be found in its path: thus a motion cannot be 
regular if its path is an irregular magnitude, e.g. a broken line, a 
spiral, or any other magnitude that is not such that any part of 
it taken at random fits on to any other that may be chosen. 
Sometimes it is found neither in the place nor in the time nor in 
the goal but in the manner of the motion: for in some cases the 
motion is differentiated by quickness and slowness: thus if its 
velocity is uniform a motion is regular, if not it is irregular. So 
quickness and slowness are not species of motion nor do they 
constitute specific differences of motion, because this 
distinction occurs in connexion with all the distinct species of 
motion. The same is true of heaviness and lightness when they 
refer to the same thing: e.g. they do not specifically distinguish 
earth from itself or fire from itself. Irregular motion, therefore, 
while in virtue of being continuous it is one, is so in a lesser 
degree, as is the case with locomotion in a broken line: and a 
lesser degree of something always means an admixture of its 
contrary. And since every motion that is one can be both regular 
and irregular, motions that are consecutive but not specifically 
the same cannot be one and continuous: for how should a 
motion composed of alteration and locomotion be regular? If a 
motion is to be regular its parts ought to fit one another. 



We have further to determine what motions are contrary to 
each other, and to determine similarly how it is with rest. And 
we have first to decide whether contrary motions are motions 
respectively from and to the same thing, e.g. a motion from 
health and a motion to health (where the opposition, it would 
seem, is of the same kind as that between coming to be and 



737 



ceasing to be); or motions respectively from contraries, e.g. a 
motion from health and a motion from disease; or motions 
respectively to contraries, e.g. a motion to health and a motion 
to disease; or motions respectively from a contrary and to the 
opposite contrary, e.g. a motion from health and a motion to 
disease; or motions respectively from a contrary to the opposite 
contrary and from the latter to the former, e.g. a motion from 
health to disease and a motion from disease to health: for 
motions must be contrary to one another in one or more of 
these ways, as there is no other way in which they can be 
opposed. 

Now motions respectively from a contrary and to the opposite 
contrary, e.g. a motion from health and a motion to disease, are 
not contrary motions: for they are one and the same. (Yet their 
essence is not the same, just as changing from health is 
different from changing to disease.) Nor are motion respectively 
from a contrary and from the opposite contrary contrary 
motions, for a motion from a contrary is at the same time a 
motion to a contrary or to an intermediate (of this, however, we 
shall speak later), but changing to a contrary rather than 
changing from a contrary would seem to be the cause of the 
contrariety of motions, the latter being the loss, the former the 
gain, of contrariness. Moreover, each several motion takes its 
name rather from the goal than from the starting-point of 
change, e.g. motion to health we call convalescence, motion to 
disease sickening. Thus we are left with motions respectively to 
contraries, and motions respectively to contraries from the 
opposite contraries. Now it would seem that motions to 
contraries are at the same time motions from contraries 
(though their essence may not be the same; 'to health' is 
distinct, I mean, from 'from disease', and 'from health' from 'to 
disease'). 



738 



Since then change differs from motion (motion being change 
from a particular subject to a particular subject), it follows that 
contrary motions are motions respectively from a contrary to 
the opposite contrary and from the latter to the former, e.g. a 
motion from health to disease and a motion from disease to 
health. Moreover, the consideration of particular examples will 
also show what kinds of processes are generally recognized as 
contrary: thus falling ill is regarded as contrary to recovering 
one's health, these processes having contrary goals, and being 
taught as contrary to being led into error by another, it being 
possible to acquire error, like knowledge, either by one's own 
agency or by that of another. Similarly we have upward 
locomotion and downward locomotion, which are contrary 
lengthwise, locomotion to the right and locomotion to the left, 
which are contrary breadthwise, and forward locomotion and 
backward locomotion, which too are contraries. On the other 
hand, a process simply to a contrary, e.g. that denoted by the 
expression 'becoming white', where no starting-point is 
specified, is a change but not a motion. And in all cases of a 
thing that has no contrary we have as contraries change from 
and change to the same thing. Thus coming to be is contrary to 
ceasing to be, and losing to gaining. But these are changes and 
not motions. And wherever a pair of contraries admit of an 
intermediate, motions to that intermediate must be held to be 
in a sense motions to one or other of the contraries: for the 
intermediate serves as a contrary for the purposes of the 
motion, in whichever direction the change may be, e.g. grey in a 
motion from grey to white takes the place of black as starting- 
point, in a motion from white to grey it takes the place of black 
as goal, and in a motion from black to grey it takes the place of 
white as goal: for the middle is opposed in a sense to either of 
the extremes, as has been said above. Thus we see that two 
motions are contrary to each other only when one is a motion 



739 



from a contrary to the opposite contrary and the other is a 
motion from the latter to the former. 



But since a motion appears to have contrary to it not only 
another motion but also a state of rest, we must determine how 
this is so. A motion has for its contrary in the strict sense of the 
term another motion, but it also has for an opposite a state of 
rest (for rest is the privation of motion and the privation of 
anything may be called its contrary), and motion of one kind 
has for its opposite rest of that kind, e.g. local motion has local 
rest. This statement, however, needs further qualification: there 
remains the question, is the opposite of remaining at a 
particular place motion from or motion to that place? It is 
surely clear that since there are two subjects between which 
motion takes place, motion from one of these (A) to its contrary 
(B) has for its opposite remaining in A while the reverse motion 
has for its opposite remaining in B. At the same time these two 
are also contrary to each other: for it would be absurd to 
suppose that there are contrary motions and not opposite states 
of rest. States of rest in contraries are opposed. To take an 
example, a state of rest in health is (1) contrary to a state of rest 
in disease, and (2) the motion to which it is contrary is that from 
health to disease. For (2) it would be absurd that its contrary 
motion should be that from disease to health, since motion to 
that in which a thing is at rest is rather a coming to rest, the 
coming to rest being found to come into being simultaneously 
with the motion; and one of these two motions it must be. And 
(1) rest in whiteness is of course not contrary to rest in health. 



740 



Of all things that have no contraries there are opposite changes 
(viz. change from the thing and change to the thing, e.g. change 
from being and change to being), but no motion. So, too, of such 
things there is no remaining though there is absence of change. 
Should there be a particular subject, absence of change in its 
being will be contrary to absence of change in its not-being. And 
here a difficulty may be raised: if not-being is not a particular 
something, what is it, it may be asked, that is contrary to 
absence of change in a thing's being? and is this absence of 
change a state of rest? If it is, then either it is not true that every 
state of rest is contrary to a motion or else coming to be and 
ceasing to be are motion. It is clear then that, since we exclude 
these from among motions, we must not say that this absence 
of change is a state of rest: we must say that it is similar to a 
state of rest and call it absence of change. And it will have for its 
contrary either nothing or absence of change in the thing's not- 
being, or the ceasing to be of the thing: for such ceasing to be is 
change from it and the thing's coming to be is change to it. 

Again, a further difficulty may be raised. How is it, it may be 
asked, that whereas in local change both remaining and moving 
may be natural or unnatural, in the other changes this is not so? 
e.g. alteration is not now natural and now unnatural, for 
convalescence is no more natural or unnatural than falling ill, 
whitening no more natural or unnatural than blackening; so, 
too, with increase and decrease: these are not contrary to each 
other in the sense that either of them is natural while the other 
is unnatural, nor is one increase contrary to another in this 
sense; and the same account may be given of becoming and 
perishing: it is not true that becoming is natural and perishing 
unnatural (for growing old is natural), nor do we observe one 
becoming to be natural and another unnatural. We answer that 
if what happens under violence is unnatural, then violent 
perishing is unnatural and as such contrary to natural 
perishing. Are there then also some becomings that are violent 



741 



and not the result of natural necessity, and are therefore 
contrary to natural becomings, and violent increases and 
decreases, e.g. the rapid growth to maturity of profligates and 
the rapid ripening of seeds even when not packed close in the 
earth? And how is it with alterations? Surely just the same: we 
may say that some alterations are violent while others are 
natural, e.g. patients alter naturally or unnaturally according as 
they throw off fevers on the critical days or not. But, it may be 
objected, then we shall have perishings contrary to one another, 
not to becoming. Certainly: and why should not this in a sense 
be so? Thus it is so if one perishing is pleasant and another 
painful: and so one perishing will be contrary to another not in 
an unqualified sense, but in so far as one has this quality and 
the other that. 

Now motions and states of rest universally exhibit contrariety 
in the manner described above, e.g. upward motion and rest 
above are respectively contrary to downward motion and rest 
below, these being instances of local contrariety; and upward 
locomotion belongs naturally to fire and downward to earth, i.e. 
the locomotions of the two are contrary to each other. And 
again, fire moves up naturally and down unnaturally: and its 
natural motion is certainly contrary to its unnatural motion. 
Similarly with remaining: remaining above is contrary to 
motion from above downwards, and to earth this remaining 
comes unnaturally, this motion naturally. So the unnatural 
remaining of a thing is contrary to its natural motion, just as we 
find a similar contrariety in the motion of the same thing: one 
of its motions, the upward or the downward, will be natural, the 
other unnatural. 

Here, however, the question arises, has every state of rest that is 
not permanent a becoming, and is this becoming a coming to a 
standstill? If so, there must be a becoming of that which is at 
rest unnaturally, e.g. of earth at rest above: and therefore this 



742 



earth during the time that it was being carried violently upward 
was coming to a standstill. But whereas the velocity of that 
which comes to a standstill seems always to increase, the 
velocity of that which is carried violently seems always to 
decrease: so it will he in a state of rest without having become 
so. Moreover 'coming to a standstill' is generally recognized to 
be identical or at least concomitant with the locomotion of a 
thing to its proper place. 

There is also another difficulty involved in the view that 
remaining in a particular place is contrary to motion from that 
place. For when a thing is moving from or discarding something, 
it still appears to have that which is being discarded, so that if a 
state of rest is itself contrary to the motion from the state of 
rest to its contrary, the contraries rest and motion will be 
simultaneously predicable of the same thing. May we not say, 
however, that in so far as the thing is still stationary it is in a 
state of rest in a qualified sense? For, in fact, whenever a thing 
is in motion, part of it is at the starting-point while part is at the 
goal to which it is changing: and consequently a motion finds 
its true contrary rather in another motion than in a state of rest. 

With regard to motion and rest, then, we have now explained in 
what sense each of them is one and under what conditions they 
exhibit contrariety. 

[With regard to coming to a standstill the question may be 
raised whether there is an opposite state of rest to unnatural as 
well as to natural motions. It would be absurd if this were not 
the case: for a thing may remain still merely under violence: 
thus we shall have a thing being in a non-permanent state of 
rest without having become so. But it is clear that it must be the 
case: for just as there is unnatural motion, so, too, a thing may 
be in an unnatural state of rest. Further, some things have a 
natural and an unnatural motion, e.g. fire has a natural upward 



743 



motion and an unnatural downward motion: is it, then, this 
unnatural downward motion or is it the natural downward 
motion of earth that is contrary to the natural upward motion? 
Surely it is clear that both are contrary to it though not in the 
same sense: the natural motion of earth is contrary inasmuch 
as the motion of fire is also natural, whereas the upward 
motion of fire as being natural is contrary to the downward 
motion of fire as being unnatural. The same is true of the 
corresponding cases of remaining. But there would seem to be a 
sense in which a state of rest and a motion are opposites.] 



Book VI 



Now if the terms 'continuous', 'in contact', and 'in succession' 
are understood as defined above things being 'continuous' if 
their extremities are one, 'in contact' if their extremities are 
together, and 'in succession' if there is nothing of their own 
kind intermediate between them - nothing that is continuous 
can be composed 'of indivisibles': e.g. a line cannot be 
composed of points, the line being continuous and the point 
indivisible. For the extremities of two points can neither be one 
(since of an indivisible there can be no extremity as distinct 
from some other part) nor together (since that which has no 
parts can have no extremity, the extremity and the thing of 
which it is the extremity being distinct). 



744 



Moreover, if that which is continuous is composed of points, 
these points must be either continuous or in contact with one 
another: and the same reasoning applies in the case of all 
indivisibles. Now for the reason given above they cannot be 
continuous: and one thing can be in contact with another only 
if whole is in contact with whole or part with part or part with 
whole. But since indivisibles have no parts, they must be in 
contact with one another as whole with whole. And if they are 
in contact with one another as whole with whole, they will not 
be continuous: for that which is continuous has distinct parts: 
and these parts into which it is divisible are different in this 
way, i.e. spatially separate. 

Nor, again, can a point be in succession to a point or a moment 
to a moment in such a way that length can be composed of 
points or time of moments: for things are in succession if there 
is nothing of their own kind intermediate between them, 
whereas that which is intermediate between points is always a 
line and that which is intermediate between moments is always 
a period of time. 

Again, if length and time could thus be composed of 
indivisibles, they could be divided into indivisibles, since each is 
divisible into the parts of which it is composed. But, as we saw, 
no continuous thing is divisible into things without parts. Nor 
can there be anything of any other kind intermediate between 
the parts or between the moments: for if there could be any 
such thing it is clear that it must be either indivisible or 
divisible, and if it is divisible, it must be divisible either into 
indivisibles or into divisibles that are infinitely divisible, in 
which case it is continuous. 

Moreover, it is plain that everything continuous is divisible into 
divisibles that are infinitely divisible: for if it were divisible into 
indivisibles, we should have an indivisible in contact with an 



745 



indivisible, since the extremities of things that are continuous 
with one another are one and are in contact. 

The same reasoning applies equally to magnitude, to time, and 
to motion: either all of these are composed of indivisibles and 
are divisible into indivisibles, or none. This may be made clear 
as follows. If a magnitude is composed of indivisibles, the 
motion over that magnitude must be composed of 
corresponding indivisible motions: e.g. if the magnitude ABG is 
composed of the indivisibles A, B, G, each corresponding part of 
the motion DEZ of over ABG is indivisible. Therefore, since 
where there is motion there must be something that is in 
motion, and where there is something in motion there must be 
motion, therefore the being-moved will also be composed of 
indivisibles. So traversed A when its motion was D, B when its 
motion was E, and G similarly when its motion was Z. Now a 
thing that is in motion from one place to another cannot at the 
moment when it was in motion both be in motion and at the 
same time have completed its motion at the place to which it 
was in motion: e.g. if a man is walking to Thebes, he cannot be 
walking to Thebes and at the same time have completed his 
walk to Thebes: and, as we saw, traverses a the partless 
section A in virtue of the presence of the motion D. 
Consequently, if actually passed through A after being in 
process of passing through, the motion must be divisible: for at 
the time when was passing through, it neither was at rest nor 
had completed its passage but was in an intermediate state: 
while if it is passing through and has completed its passage at 
the same moment, then that which is walking will at the 
moment when it is walking have completed its walk and will be 
in the place to which it is walking; that is to say, it will have 
completed its motion at the place to which it is in motion. And 
if a thing is in motion over the whole KBG and its motion is the 
three D, E, and Z, and if it is not in motion at all over the 
partless section A but has completed its motion over it, then the 



746 



motion will consist not of motions but of starts, and will take 
place by a thing's having completed a motion without being in 
motion: for on this assumption it has completed its passage 
through A without passing through it. So it will be possible for a 
thing to have completed a walk without ever walking: for on 
this assumption it has completed a walk over a particular 
distance without walking over that distance. Since, then, 
everything must be either at rest or in motion, and is 
therefore at rest in each of the sections A, B, and G, it follows 
that a thing can be continuously at rest and at the same time in 
motion: for, as we saw, is in motion over the whole ABG and 
at rest in any part (and consequently in the whole) of it. 
Moreover, if the indivisibles composing DEZ are motions, it 
would be possible for a thing in spite of the presence in it of 
motion to be not in motion but at rest, while if they are not 
motions, it would be possible for motion to be composed of 
something other than motions. 

And if length and motion are thus indivisible, it is neither more 
nor less necessary that time also be similarly indivisible, that is 
to say be composed of indivisible moments: for if the whole 
distance is divisible and an equal velocity will cause a thing to 
pass through less of it in less time, the time must also be 
divisible, and conversely, if the time in which a thing is carried 
over the section A is divisible, this section A must also be 
divisible. 



And since every magnitude is divisible into magnitudes - for we 
have shown that it is impossible for anything continuous to be 
composed of indivisible parts, and every magnitude is 



747 



continuous - it necessarily follows that the quicker of two 
things traverses a greater magnitude in an equal time, an equal 
magnitude in less time, and a greater magnitude in less time, in 
conformity with the definition sometimes given of 'the quicker'. 
Suppose that A is quicker than B. Now since of two things that 
which changes sooner is quicker, in the time ZH, in which A has 
changed from G to D, B will not yet have arrived at D but will be 
short of it: so that in an equal time the quicker will pass over a 
greater magnitude. More than this, it will pass over a greater 
magnitude in less time: for in the time in which A has arrived at 
D, B being the slower has arrived, let us say, at E. Then since A 
has occupied the whole time ZH in arriving at D, will have 
arrived at in less time than this, say ZK. Now the magnitude 
GO that A has passed over is greater than the magnitude GE, 
and the time ZK is less than the whole time ZH: so that the 
quicker will pass over a greater magnitude in less time. And 
from this it is also clear that the quicker will pass over an equal 
magnitude in less time than the slower. For since it passes over 
the greater magnitude in less time than the slower, and 
(regarded by itself) passes over LM the greater in more time 
than LX the lesser, the time PRh in which it passes over LM will 
be more than the time PS, which it passes over LX: so that, the 
time PRh being less than the time PCh in which the slower 
passes over LX, the time PS will also be less than the time PX: 
for it is less than the time PRh, and that which is less than 
something else that is less than a thing is also itself less than 
that thing. Hence it follows that the quicker will traverse an 
equal magnitude in less time than the slower. Again, since the 
motion of anything must always occupy either an equal time or 
less or more time in comparison with that of another thing, and 
since, whereas a thing is slower if its motion occupies more 
time and of equal velocity if its motion occupies an equal time, 
the quicker is neither of equal velocity nor slower, it follows 
that the motion of the quicker can occupy neither an equal time 



748 



nor more time. It can only be, then, that it occupies less time, 
and thus we get the necessary consequence that the quicker 
will pass over an equal magnitude (as well as a greater) in less 
time than the slower. 

And since every motion is in time and a motion may occupy any 
time, and the motion of everything that is in motion may be 
either quicker or slower, both quicker motion and slower 
motion may occupy any time: and this being so, it necessarily 
follows that time also is continuous. By continuous I mean that 
which is divisible into divisibles that are infinitely divisible: and 
if we take this as the definition of continuous, it follows 
necessarily that time is continuous. For since it has been shown 
that the quicker will pass over an equal magnitude in less time 
than the slower, suppose that A is quicker and B slower, and 
that the slower has traversed the magnitude GD in the time ZH. 
Now it is clear that the quicker will traverse the same 
magnitude in less time than this: let us say in the time ZO. 
Again, since the quicker has passed over the whole D in the 
time ZO, the slower will in the same time pass over GK, say, 
which is less than GD. And since B, the slower, has passed over 
GK in the time ZO, the quicker will pass over it in less time: so 
that the time ZO will again be divided. And if this is divided the 
magnitude GK will also be divided just as GD was: and again, if 
the magnitude is divided, the time will also be divided. And we 
can carry on this process for ever, taking the slower after the 
quicker and the quicker after the slower alternately, and using 
what has been demonstrated at each stage as a new point of 
departure: for the quicker will divide the time and the slower 
will divide the length. If, then, this alternation always holds 
good, and at every turn involves a division, it is evident that all 
time must be continuous. And at the same time it is clear that 
all magnitude is also continuous; for the divisions of which time 
and magnitude respectively are susceptible are the same and 
equal. 



749 



Moreover, the current popular arguments make it plain that, if 
time is continuous, magnitude is continuous also, inasmuch as 
a thing asses over half a given magnitude in half the time taken 
to cover the whole: in fact without qualification it passes over a 
less magnitude in less time; for the divisions of time and of 
magnitude will be the same. And if either is infinite, so is the 
other, and the one is so in the same way as the other; i.e. if time 
is infinite in respect of its extremities, length is also infinite in 
respect of its extremities: if time is infinite in respect of 
divisibility, length is also infinite in respect of divisibility: and if 
time is infinite in both respects, magnitude is also infinite in 
both respects. 

Hence Zeno's argument makes a false assumption in asserting 
that it is impossible for a thing to pass over or severally to come 
in contact with infinite things in a finite time. For there are two 
senses in which length and time and generally anything 
continuous are called 'infinite': they are called so either in 
respect of divisibility or in respect of their extremities. So while 
a thing in a finite time cannot come in contact with things 
quantitatively infinite, it can come in contact with things 
infinite in respect of divisibility: for in this sense the time itself 
is also infinite: and so we find that the time occupied by the 
passage over the infinite is not a finite but an infinite time, and 
the contact with the infinites is made by means of moments 
not finite but infinite in number. 

The passage over the infinite, then, cannot occupy a finite time, 
and the passage over the finite cannot occupy an infinite time: 
if the time is infinite the magnitude must be infinite also, and if 
the magnitude is infinite, so also is the time. This may be shown 
as follows. Let AB be a finite magnitude, and let us suppose that 
it is traversed in infinite time G, and let a finite period GD of the 
time be taken. Now in this period the thing in motion will pass 
over a certain segment of the magnitude: let BE be the segment 



750 



that it has thus passed over. (This will be either an exact 
measure of AB or less or greater than an exact measure: it 
makes no difference which it is.) Then, since a magnitude equal 
to BE will always be passed over in an equal time, and BE 
measures the whole magnitude, the whole time occupied in 
passing over AB will be finite: for it will be divisible into periods 
equal in number to the segments into which the magnitude is 
divisible. Moreover, if it is the case that infinite time is not 
occupied in passing over every magnitude, but it is possible to 
ass over some magnitude, say BE, in a finite time, and if this BE 
measures the whole of which it is a part, and if an equal 
magnitude is passed over in an equal time, then it follows that 
the time like the magnitude is finite. That infinite time will not 
be occupied in passing over BE is evident if the time be taken as 
limited in one direction: for as the part will be passed over in 
less time than the whole, the time occupied in traversing this 
part must be finite, the limit in one direction being given. The 
same reasoning will also show the falsity of the assumption 
that infinite length can be traversed in a finite time. It is 
evident, then, from what has been said that neither a line nor a 
surface nor in fact anything continuous can be indivisible. 

This conclusion follows not only from the present argument but 
from the consideration that the opposite assumption implies 
the divisibility of the indivisible. For since the distinction of 
quicker and slower may apply to motions occupying any period 
of time and in an equal time the quicker passes over a greater 
length, it may happen that it will pass over a length twice, or 
one and a half times, as great as that passed over by the slower: 
for their respective velocities may stand to one another in this 
proportion. Suppose, then, that the quicker has in the same 
time been carried over a length one and a half times as great as 
that traversed by the slower, and that the respective magnitudes 
are divided, that of the quicker, the magnitude ABGD, into three 
indivisibles, and that of the slower into the two indivisibles EZ, 



751 



ZH. Then the time may also be divided into three indivisibles, 
for an equal magnitude will be passed over in an equal time. 
Suppose then that it is thus divided into KL, LM, MN. Again, 
since in the same time the slower has been carried over EZ, ZH, 
the time may also be similarly divided into two. Thus the 
indivisible will be divisible, and that which has no parts will be 
passed over not in an indivisible but in a greater time. It is 
evident, therefore, that nothing continuous is without parts. 



The present also is necessarily indivisible - the present, that is, 
not in the sense in which the word is applied to one thing in 
virtue of another, but in its proper and primary sense; in which 
sense it is inherent in all time. For the present is something that 
is an extremity of the past (no part of the future being on this 
side of it) and also of the future (no part of the past being on the 
other side of it): it is, as we have said, a limit of both. And if it is 
once shown that it is essentially of this character and one and 
the same, it will at once be evident also that it is indivisible. 

Now the present that is the extremity of both times must be 
one and the same: for if each extremity were different, the one 
could not be in succession to the other, because nothing 
continuous can be composed of things having no parts: and if 
the one is apart from the other, there will be time intermediate 
between them, because everything continuous is such that 
there is something intermediate between its limits and 
described by the same name as itself. But if the intermediate 
thing is time, it will be divisible: for all time has been shown to 
be divisible. Thus on this assumption the present is divisible. 
But if the present is divisible, there will be part of the past in the 



752 



future and part of the future in the past: for past time will be 
marked off from future time at the actual point of division. Also 
the present will be a present not in the proper sense but in 
virtue of something else: for the division which yields it will not 
be a division proper. Furthermore, there will be a part of the 
present that is past and a part that is future, and it will not 
always be the same part that is past or future: in fact one and 
the same present will not be simultaneous: for the time may be 
divided at many points. If, therefore, the present cannot 
possibly have these characteristics, it follows that it must be the 
same present that belongs to each of the two times. But if this is 
so it is evident that the present is also indivisible: for if it is 
divisible it will be involved in the same implications as before. It 
is clear, then, from what has been said that time contains 
something indivisible, and this is what we call a present. 

We will now show that nothing can be in motion in a present. 
For if this is possible, there can be both quicker and slower 
motion in the present. Suppose then that in the present N the 
quicker has traversed the distance AB. That being so, the slower 
will in the same present traverse a distance less than AB, say 
AG. But since the slower will have occupied the whole present 
in traversing AG, the quicker will occupy less than this in 
traversing it. Thus we shall have a division of the present, 
whereas we found it to be indivisible. It is impossible, therefore, 
for anything to be in motion in a present. 

Nor can anything be at rest in a present: for, as we were saying, 
only can be at rest which is naturally designed to be in motion 
but is not in motion when, where, or as it would naturally be so: 
since, therefore, nothing is naturally designed to be in motion in 
a present, it is clear that nothing can be at rest in a present 
either. 



753 



Moreover, inasmuch as it is the same present that belongs to 
both the times, and it is possible for a thing to be in motion 
throughout one time and to be at rest throughout the other, and 
that which is in motion or at rest for the whole of a time will be 
in motion or at rest as the case may be in any part of it in which 
it is naturally designed to be in motion or at rest: this being so, 
the assumption that there can be motion or rest in a present 
will carry with it the implication that the same thing can at the 
same time be at rest and in motion: for both the times have the 
same extremity, viz. the present. 

Again, when we say that a thing is at rest, we imply that its 
condition in whole and in part is at the time of speaking 
uniform with what it was previously: but the present contains 
no 'previously': consequently, there can be no rest in it. 

It follows then that the motion of that which is in motion and 
the rest of that which is at rest must occupy time. 



Further, everything that changes must be divisible. For since 
every change is from something to something, and when a 
thing is at the goal of its change it is no longer changing, and 
when both it itself and all its parts are at the starting-point of 
its change it is not changing (for that which is in whole and in 
part in an unvarying condition is not in a state of change); it 
follows, therefore, that part of that which is changing must be 
at the starting-point and part at the goal: for as a whole it 
cannot be in both or in neither. (Here by 'goal of change' I mean 
that which comes first in the process of change: e.g. in a process 
of change from white the goal in question will be grey, not 
black: for it is not necessary that that that which is changing 



754 



should be at either of the extremes.) It is evident, therefore, that 
everything that changes must be divisible. 

Now motion is divisible in two senses. In the first place it is 
divisible in virtue of the time that it occupies. In the second 
place it is divisible according to the motions of the several parts 
of that which is in motion: e.g. if the whole AG is in motion, 
there will be a motion of AB and a motion of BG. That being so, 
let DE be the motion of the part AB and EZ the motion of the 
part BG. Then the whole DZ must be the motion of AG: for DZ 
must constitute the motion of AG inasmuch as DE and EZ 
severally constitute the motions of each of its parts. But the 
motion of a thing can never be constituted by the motion of 
something else: consequently the whole motion is the motion 
of the whole magnitude. 

Again, since every motion is a motion of something, and the 
whole motion DZ is not the motion of either of the parts (for 
each of the parts DE, EZ is the motion of one of the parts AB, BG) 
or of anything else (for, the whole motion being the motion of a 
whole, the parts of the motion are the motions of the parts of 
that whole: and the parts of DZ are the motions of AB, BG and of 
nothing else: for, as we saw, a motion that is one cannot be the 
motion of more things than one): since this is so, the whole 
motion will be the motion of the magnitude ABG. 

Again, if there is a motion of the whole other than DZ, say the 
the of each of the arts may be subtracted from it: and these 
motions will be equal to DE, EZ respectively: for the motion of 
that which is one must be one. So if the whole motion 01 may 
be divided into the motions of the parts, 01 will be equal to DZ: 
if on the other hand there is any remainder, say KI, this will be a 
motion of nothing: for it can be the motion neither of the whole 
nor of the parts (as the motion of that which is one must be 
one) nor of anything else: for a motion that is continuous must 



755 



be the motion of things that are continuous. And the same 
result follows if the division of 01 reveals a surplus on the side 
of the motions of the parts. Consequently, if this is impossible, 
the whole motion must be the same as and equal to DZ. 

This then is what is meant by the division of motion according 
to the motions of the parts: and it must be applicable to 
everything that is divisible into parts. 

Motion is also susceptible of another kind of division, that 
according to time. For since all motion is in time and all time is 
divisible, and in less time the motion is less, it follows that 
every motion must be divisible according to time. And since 
everything that is in motion is in motion in a certain sphere and 
for a certain time and has a motion belonging to it, it follows 
that the time, the motion, the being-in-motion, the thing that is 
in motion, and the sphere of the motion must all be susceptible 
of the same divisions (though spheres of motion are not all 
divisible in a like manner: thus quantity is essentially, quality 
accidentally divisible). For suppose that A is the time occupied 
by the motion B. Then if all the time has been occupied by the 
whole motion, it will take less of the motion to occupy half the 
time, less again to occupy a further subdivision of the time, and 
so on to infinity. Again, the time will be divisible similarly to the 
motion: for if the whole motion occupies all the time half the 
motion will occupy half the time, and less of the motion again 
will occupy less of the time. 

In the same way the being-in-motion will also be divisible. For 
let G be the whole being-in-motion. Then the being-in-motion 
that corresponds to half the motion will be less than the whole 
being-in-motion, that which corresponds to a quarter of the 
motion will be less again, and so on to infinity. Moreover by 
setting out successively the being-in-motion corresponding to 
each of the two motions DG (say) and GE, we may argue that the 



756 



whole being-in-motion will correspond to the whole motion (for 
if it were some other being-in-motion that corresponded to the 
whole motion, there would be more than one being-in-motion 
corresponding to the same motion), the argument being the 
same as that whereby we showed that the motion of a thing is 
divisible into the motions of the parts of the thing: for if we take 
separately the being-in-motion corresponding to each of the 
two motions, we shall see that the whole being-in-motion is 
continuous. 

The same reasoning will show the divisibility of the length, and 
in fact of everything that forms a sphere of change (though 
some of these are only accidentally divisible because that which 
changes is so): for the division of one term will involve the 
division of all. So, too, in the matter of their being finite or 
infinite, they will all alike be either the one or the other. And we 
now see that in most cases the fact that all the terms are 
divisible or infinite is a direct consequence of the fact that the 
thing that changes is divisible or infinite: for the attributes 
'divisible' and 'infinite' belong in the first instance to the thing 
that changes. That divisibility does so we have already shown: 
that infinity does so will be made clear in what follows? 



Since everything that changes changes from something to 
something, that which has changed must at the moment when 
it has first changed be in that to which it has changed. For that 
which changes retires from or leaves that from which it 
changes: and leaving, if not identical with changing, is at any 
rate a consequence of it. And if leaving is a consequence of 



757 



changing, having left is a consequence of having changed: for 
there is a like relation between the two in each case. 

One kind of change, then, being change in a relation of 
contradiction, where a thing has changed from not-being to 
being it has left not-being. Therefore it will be in being: for 
everything must either be or not be. It is evident, then, that in 
contradictory change that which has changed must be in that to 
which it has changed. And if this is true in this kind of change, 
it will be true in all other kinds as well: for in this matter what 
holds good in the case of one will hold good likewise in the case 
of the rest. 

Moreover, if we take each kind of change separately, the truth of 
our conclusion will be equally evident, on the ground that that 
that which has changed must be somewhere or in something. 
For, since it has left that from which it has changed and must be 
somewhere, it must be either in that to which it has changed or 
in something else. If, then, that which has changed to B is in 
something other than B, say G, it must again be changing from 
G to B: for it cannot be assumed that there is no interval 
between G and B, since change is continuous. Thus we have the 
result that the thing that has changed, at the moment when it 
has changed, is changing to that to which it has changed, which 
is impossible: that which has changed, therefore, must be in 
that to which it has changed. So it is evident likewise that 
which has come to be, at the moment when it has come to be, 
will be, and that which has ceased to be will not-be: for what we 
have said applies universally to every kind of change, and its 
truth is most obvious in the case of contradictory change. It is 
clear, then, that that which has changed, at the moment when 
it has first changed, is in that to which it has changed. 

We will now show that the 'primary when' in which that which 
has changed effected the completion of its change must be 



758 



indivisible, where by 'primary' I mean possessing the 
characteristics in question of itself and not in virtue of the 
possession of them by something else belonging to it. For let AG 
be divisible, and let it be divided at B. If then the completion of 
change has been effected in AB or again in BG, AG cannot be the 
primary thing in which the completion of change has been 
effected. If, on the other hand, it has been changing in both AB 
and BG (for it must either have changed or be changing in each 
of them), it must have been changing in the whole AG: but our 
assumption was that AG contains only the completion of the 
change. It is equally impossible to suppose that one part of AG 
contains the process and the other the completion of the 
change: for then we shall have something prior to what is 
primary. So that in which the completion of change has been 
effected must be indivisible. It is also evident, therefore, that 
that that in which that which has ceased to be has ceased to be 
and that in which that which has come to be has come to be are 
indivisible. 

But there are two senses of the expression 'the primary when in 
which something has changed'. On the one hand it may mean 
the primary when containing the completion of the process of 
change - the moment when it is correct to say 'it has changed': 
on the other hand it may mean the primary when containing 
the beginning of the process of change. Now the primary when 
that has reference to the end of the change is something really 
existent: for a change may really be completed, and there is 
such a thing as an end of change, which we have in fact shown 
to be indivisible because it is a limit. But that which has 
reference to the beginning is not existent at all: for there is no 
such thing as a beginning of a process of change, and the time 
occupied by the change does not contain any primary when in 
which the change began. For suppose that AD is such a primary 
when. Then it cannot be indivisible: for, if it were, the moment 
immediately preceding the change and the moment in which 



759 



the change begins would be consecutive (and moments cannot 
be consecutive). Again, if the changing thing is at rest in the 
whole preceding time GA (for we may suppose that it is at rest), 
it is at rest in A also: so if AD is without parts, it will 
simultaneously be at rest and have changed: for it is at rest in A 
and has changed in D. Since then AD is not without parts, it 
must be divisible, and the changing thing must have changed in 
every part of it (for if it has changed in neither of the two parts 
into which AD is divided, it has not changed in the whole either: 
if, on the other hand, it is in process of change in both parts, it 
is likewise in process of change in the whole: and if, again, it 
has changed in one of the two parts, the whole is not the 
primary when in which it has changed: it must therefore have 
changed in every part). It is evident, then, that with reference to 
the beginning of change there is no primary when in which 
change has been effected: for the divisions are infinite. 

So, too, of that which has changed there is no primary part that 
has changed. For suppose that of AE the primary part that has 
changed is AZ (everything that changes having been shown to 
be divisible): and let 01 be the time in which DZ has changed. If, 
then, in the whole time DZ has changed, in half the time there 
will be a part that has changed, less than and therefore prior to 
DZ: and again there will be another part prior to this, and yet 
another, and so on to infinity. Thus of that which changes there 
cannot be any primary part that has changed. It is evident, then, 
from what has been said, that neither of that which changes 
nor of the time in which it changes is there any primary part. 

With regard, however, to the actual subject of change - that is to 
say that in respect of which a thing changes - there is a 
difference to be observed. For in a process of change we may 
distinguish three terms - that which changes, that in which it 
changes, and the actual subject of change, e.g. the man, the 
time, and the fair complexion. Of these the man and the time 



760 



are divisible: but with the fair complexion it is otherwise 
(though they are all divisible accidentally, for that in which the 
fair complexion or any other quality is an accident is divisible). 
For of actual subjects of change it will be seen that those which 
are classed as essentially, not accidentally, divisible have no 
primary part. Take the case of magnitudes: let AB be a 
magnitude, and suppose that it has moved from B to a primary 
'where' G. Then if BG is taken to be indivisible, two things 
without parts will have to be contiguous (which is impossible): 
if on the other hand it is taken to be divisible, there will be 
something prior to G to which the magnitude has changed, and 
something else again prior to that, and so on to infinity, because 
the process of division may be continued without end. Thus 
there can be no primary 'where' to which a thing has changed. 
And if we take the case of quantitative change, we shall get a 
like result, for here too the change is in something continuous. 
It is evident, then, that only in qualitative motion can there be 
anything essentially indivisible. 



Now everything that changes changes time, and that in two 
senses: for the time in which a thing is said to change may be 
the primary time, or on the other hand it may have an extended 
reference, as e.g. when we say that a thing changes in a 
particular year because it changes in a particular day. That being 
so, that which changes must be changing in any part of the 
primary time in which it changes. This is clear from our 
definition of 'primary', in which the word is said to express just 
this: it may also, however, be made evident by the following 
argument. Let ChRh be the primary time in which that which is 
in motion is in motion: and (as all time is divisible) let it be 



761 



divided at K. Now in the time ChK it either is in motion or is not 
in motion, and the same is likewise true of the time KRh. Then 
if it is in motion in neither of the two parts, it will be at rest in 
the whole: for it is impossible that it should be in motion in a 
time in no part of which it is in motion. If on the other hand it is 
in motion in only one of the two parts of the time, ChRh cannot 
be the primary time in which it is in motion: for its motion will 
have reference to a time other than ChRh. It must, then, have 
been in motion in any part of ChRh. 

And now that this has been proved, it is evident that everything 
that is in motion must have been in motion before. For if that 
which is in motion has traversed the distance KL in the primary 
time ChRh, in half the time a thing that is in motion with equal 
velocity and began its motion at the same time will have 
traversed half the distance. But if this second thing whose 
velocity is equal has traversed a certain distance in a certain 
time, the original thing that is in motion must have traversed 
the same distance in the same time. Hence that which is in 
motion must have been in motion before. 

Again, if by taking the extreme moment of the time - for it is 
the moment that defines the time, and time is that which is 
intermediate between moments-we are enabled to say that 
motion has taken place in the whole time ChRh or in fact in any 
period of it, motion may likewise be said to have taken place in 
every other such period. But half the time finds an extreme in 
the point of division. Therefore motion will have taken place in 
half the time and in fact in any part of it: for as soon as any 
division is made there is always a time defined by moments. If, 
then, all time is divisible, and that which is intermediate 
between moments is time, everything that is changing must 
have completed an infinite number of changes. 



762 



Again, since a thing that changes continuously and has not 
perished or ceased from its change must either be changing or 
have changed in any part of the time of its change, and since it 
cannot be changing in a moment, it follows that it must have 
changed at every moment in the time: consequently, since the 
moments are infinite in number, everything that is changing 
must have completed an infinite number of changes. 

And not only must that which is changing have changed, but 
that which has changed must also previously have been 
changing, since everything that has changed from something to 
something has changed in a period of time. For suppose that a 
thing has changed from A to B in a moment. Now the moment 
in which it has changed cannot be the same as that in which it 
is at A (since in that case it would be in A and B at once): for we 
have shown above that that that which has changed, when it 
has changed, is not in that from which it has changed. If, on the 
other hand, it is a different moment, there will be a period of 
time intermediate between the two: for, as we saw, moments 
are not consecutive. Since, then, it has changed in a period of 
time, and all time is divisible, in half the time it will have 
completed another change, in a quarter another, and so on to 
infinity: consequently when it has changed, it must have 
previously been changing. 

Moreover, the truth of what has been said is more evident in the 
case of magnitude, because the magnitude over which what is 
changing changes is continuous. For suppose that a thing has 
changed from G to D. Then if GD is indivisible, two things 
without parts will be consecutive. But since this is impossible, 
that which is intermediate between them must be a magnitude 
and divisible into an infinite number of segments: consequently, 
before the change is completed, the thing changes to those 
segments. Everything that has changed, therefore, must 
previously have been changing: for the same proof also holds 



763 



good of change with respect to what is not continuous, changes, 
that is to say, between contraries and between contradictories. 
In such cases we have only to take the time in which a thing 
has changed and again apply the same reasoning. So that which 
has changed must have been changing and that which is 
changing must have changed, and a process of change is 
preceded by a completion of change and a completion by a 
process: and we can never take any stage and say that it is 
absolutely the first. The reason of this is that no two things 
without parts can be contiguous, and therefore in change the 
process of division is infinite, just as lines may be infinitely 
divided so that one part is continually increasing and the other 
continually decreasing. 

So it is evident also that that that which has become must 
previously have been in process of becoming, and that which is 
in process of becoming must previously have become, 
everything (that is) that is divisible and continuous: though it is 
not always the actual thing that is in process of becoming of 
which this is true: sometimes it is something else, that is to say, 
some part of the thing in question, e.g. the foundation-stone of 
a house. So, too, in the case of that which is perishing and that 
which has perished: for that which becomes and that which 
perishes must contain an element of infiniteness as an 
immediate consequence of the fact that they are continuous 
things: and so a thing cannot be in process of becoming without 
having become or have become without having been in process 
of becoming. So, too, in the case of perishing and having 
perished: perishing must be preceded by having perished, and 
having perished must be preceded by perishing. It is evident, 
then, that that which has become must previously have been in 
process of becoming, and that which is in process of becoming 
must previously have become: for all magnitudes and all 
periods of time are infinitely divisible. 



764 



Consequently no absolutely first stage of change can be 
represented by any particular part of space or time which the 
changing thing may occupy. 



Now since the motion of everything that is in motion occupies a 
period of time, and a greater magnitude is traversed in a longer 
time, it is impossible that a thing should undergo a finite 
motion in an infinite time, if this is understood to mean not 
that the same motion or a part of it is continually repeated, but 
that the whole infinite time is occupied by the whole finite 
motion. In all cases where a thing is in motion with uniform 
velocity it is clear that the finite magnitude is traversed in a 
finite time. For if we take a part of the motion which shall be a 
measure of the whole, the whole motion is completed in as 
many equal periods of the time as there are parts of the motion. 
Consequently, since these parts are finite, both in size 
individually and in number collectively, the whole time must 
also be finite: for it will be a multiple of the portion, equal to the 
time occupied in completing the aforesaid part multiplied by 
the number of the parts. 

But it makes no difference even if the velocity is not uniform. 
For let us suppose that the line AB represents a finite stretch 
over which a thing has been moved in the given time, and let 
GD be the infinite time. Now if one part of the stretch must have 
been traversed before another part (this is clear, that in the 
earlier and in the later part of the time a different part of the 
stretch has been traversed: for as the time lengthens a different 
part of the motion will always be completed in it, whether the 
thing in motion changes with uniform velocity or not: and 



765 



whether the rate of motion increases or diminishes or remains 
stationary this is none the less so), let us then take AE a part of 
the whole stretch of motion AB which shall be a measure of AB. 
Now this part of the motion occupies a certain period of the 
infinite time: it cannot itself occupy an infinite time, for we are 
assuming that that is occupied by the whole AB. And if again I 
take another part equal to AE, that also must occupy a finite 
time in consequence of the same assumption. And if I go on 
taking parts in this way, on the one hand there is no part which 
will be a measure of the infinite time (for the infinite cannot be 
composed of finite parts whether equal or unequal, because 
there must be some unity which will be a measure of things 
finite in multitude or in magnitude, which, whether they are 
equal or unequal, are none the less limited in magnitude); while 
on the other hand the finite stretch of motion AB is a certain 
multiple of AE: consequently the motion AB must be 
accomplished in a finite time. Moreover it is the same with 
coming to rest as with motion. And so it is impossible for one 
and the same thing to be infinitely in process of becoming or of 
perishing. The reasoning he will prove that in a finite time there 
cannot be an infinite extent of motion or of coming to rest, 
whether the motion is regular or irregular. For if we take a part 
which shall be a measure of the whole time, in this part a 
certain fraction, not the whole, of the magnitude will be 
traversed, because we assume that the traversing of the whole 
occupies all the time. Again, in another equal part of the time 
another part of the magnitude will be traversed: and similarly in 
each part of the time that we take, whether equal or unequal to 
the part originally taken. It makes no difference whether the 
parts are equal or not, if only each is finite: for it is clear that 
while the time is exhausted by the subtraction of its parts, the 
infinite magnitude will not be thus exhausted, since the process 
of subtraction is finite both in respect of the quantity subtracted 
and of the number of times a subtraction is made. Consequently 



766 



the infinite magnitude will not be traversed in finite time: and it 
makes no difference whether the magnitude is infinite in only 
one direction or in both: for the same reasoning will hold good. 

This having been proved, it is evident that neither can a finite 
magnitude traverse an infinite magnitude in a finite time, the 
reason being the same as that given above: in part of the time it 
will traverse a finite magnitude and in each several part 
likewise, so that in the whole time it will traverse a finite 
magnitude. 

And since a finite magnitude will not traverse an infinite in a 
finite time, it is clear that neither will an infinite traverse a 
finite in a finite time. For if the infinite could traverse the finite, 
the finite could traverse the infinite; for it makes no difference 
which of the two is the thing in motion; either case involves the 
traversing of the infinite by the finite. For when the infinite 
magnitude A is in motion a part of it, say GD, will occupy the 
finite and then another, and then another, and so on to infinity. 
Thus the two results will coincide: the infinite will have 
completed a motion over the finite and the finite will have 
traversed the infinite: for it would seem to be impossible for the 
motion of the infinite over the finite to occur in any way other 
than by the finite traversing the infinite either by locomotion 
over it or by measuring it. Therefore, since this is impossible, the 
infinite cannot traverse the finite. 

Nor again will the infinite traverse the infinite in a finite time. 
Otherwise it would also traverse the finite, for the infinite 
includes the finite. We can further prove this in the same way 
by taking the time as our starting-point. 

Since, then, it is established that in a finite time neither will the 
finite traverse the infinite, nor the infinite the finite, nor the 
infinite the infinite, it is evident also that in a finite time there 
cannot be infinite motion: for what difference does it make 



767 



whether we take the motion or the magnitude to be infinite? If 
either of the two is infinite, the other must be so likewise: for all 
locomotion is in space. 



8 

Since everything to which motion or rest is natural is in motion 
or at rest in the natural time, place, and manner, that which is 
coming to a stand, when it is coming to a stand, must be in 
motion: for if it is not in motion it must be at rest: but that 
which is at rest cannot be coming to rest. From this it evidently 
follows that coming to a stand must occupy a period of time: for 
the motion of that which is in motion occupies a period of time, 
and that which is coming to a stand has been shown to be in 
motion: consequently coming to a stand must occupy a period 
of time. 

Again, since the terms 'quicker' and 'slower' are used only of 
that which occupies a period of time, and the process of coming 
to a stand may be quicker or slower, the same conclusion 
follows. 

And that which is coming to a stand must be coming to a stand 
in any part of the primary time in which it is coming to a stand. 
For if it is coming to a stand in neither of two parts into which 
the time may be divided, it cannot be coming to a stand in the 
whole time, with the result that that that which is coming to a 
stand will not be coming to a stand. If on the other hand it is 
coming to a stand in only one of the two parts of the time, the 
whole cannot be the primary time in which it is coming to a 
stand: for it is coming to a stand in the whole time not primarily 
but in virtue of something distinct from itself, the argument 



768 



being the same as that which we used above about things in 
motion. 

And just as there is no primary time in which that which is in 
motion is in motion, so too there is no primary time in which 
that which is coming to a stand is coming to a stand, there 
being no primary stage either of being in motion or of coming to 
a stand. For let AB be the primary time in which a thing is 
coming to a stand. Now AB cannot be without parts: for there 
cannot be motion in that which is without parts, because the 
moving thing would necessarily have been already moved for 
part of the time of its movement: and that which is coming to a 
stand has been shown to be in motion. But since AB is therefore 
divisible, the thing is coming to a stand in every one of the parts 
of AB: for we have shown above that it is coming to a stand in 
every one of the parts in which it is primarily coming to a stand. 
Since then, that in which primarily a thing is coming to a stand 
must be a period of time and not something indivisible, and 
since all time is infinitely divisible, there cannot be anything in 
which primarily it is coming to a stand. 

Nor again can there be a primary time at which the being at rest 
of that which is at rest occurred: for it cannot have occurred in 
that which has no parts, because there cannot be motion in that 
which is indivisible, and that in which rest takes place is the 
same as that in which motion takes place: for we defined a 
state of rest to be the state of a thing to which motion is natural 
but which is not in motion when (that is to say in that in which) 
motion would be natural to it. Again, our use of the phrase 
'being at rest' also implies that the previous state of a thing is 
still unaltered, not one point only but two at least being thus 
needed to determine its presence: consequently that in which a 
thing is at rest cannot be without parts. Since, then it is 
divisible, it must be a period of time, and the thing must be at 



769 



rest in every one of its parts, as may be shown by the same 
method as that used above in similar demonstrations. 

So there can be no primary part of the time: and the reason is 
that rest and motion are always in a period of time, and a period 
of time has no primary part any more than a magnitude or in 
fact anything continuous: for everything continuous is divisible 
into an infinite number of parts. 

And since everything that is in motion is in motion in a period 
of time and changes from something to something, when its 
motion is comprised within a particular period of time 
essentially - that is to say when it fills the whole and not 
merely a part of the time in question - it is impossible that in 
that time that which is in motion should be over against some 
particular thing primarily. For if a thing - itself and each of its 
parts - occupies the same space for a definite period of time, it 
is at rest: for it is in just these circumstances that we use the 
term 'being at rest' - when at one moment after another it can 
be said with truth that a thing, itself and its parts, occupies the 
same space. So if this is being at rest it is impossible for that 
which is changing to be as a whole, at the time when it is 
primarily changing, over against any particular thing (for the 
whole period of time is divisible), so that in one part of it after 
another it will be true to say that the thing, itself and its parts, 
occupies the same space. If this is not so and the aforesaid 
proposition is true only at a single moment, then the thing will 
be over against a particular thing not for any period of time but 
only at a moment that limits the time. It is true that at any 
moment it is always over against something stationary: but it is 
not at rest: for at a moment it is not possible for anything to be 
either in motion or at rest. So while it is true to say that that 
which is in motion is at a moment not in motion and is 
opposite some particular thing, it cannot in a period of time be 



770 



over against that which is at rest: for that would involve the 
conclusion that that which is in locomotion is at rest. 



Zeno's reasoning, however, is fallacious, when he says that if 
everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest, and if that 
which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any 
moment, the flying arrow is therefore motionless. This is false, 
for time is not composed of indivisible moments any more than 
any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles. 

Zeno's arguments about motion, which cause so much 
disquietude to those who try to solve the problems that they 
present, are four in number. The first asserts the non-existence 
of motion on the ground that that which is in locomotion must 
arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal. This we 
have discussed above. 

The second is the so-called 'Achilles', and it amounts to this, 
that in a race the quickest runner can never overtake the 
slowest, since the pursuer must first reach the point whence 
the pursued started, so that the slower must always hold a lead. 
This argument is the same in principle as that which depends 
on bisection, though it differs from it in that the spaces with 
which we successively have to deal are not divided into halves. 
The result of the argument is that the slower is not overtaken: 
but it proceeds along the same lines as the bisection-argument 
(for in both a division of the space in a certain way leads to the 
result that the goal is not reached, though the 'Achilles' goes 
further in that it affirms that even the quickest runner in 
legendary tradition must fail in his pursuit of the slowest), so 
that the solution must be the same. And the axiom that that 



771 



which holds a lead is never overtaken is false: it is not 
overtaken, it is true, while it holds a lead: but it is overtaken 
nevertheless if it is granted that it traverses the finite distance 
prescribed. These then are two of his arguments. 

The third is that already given above, to the effect that the flying 
arrow is at rest, which result follows from the assumption that 
time is composed of moments: if this assumption is not 
granted, the conclusion will not follow. 

The fourth argument is that concerning the two rows of bodies, 
each row being composed of an equal number of bodies of equal 
size, passing each other on a race-course as they proceed with 
equal velocity in opposite directions, the one row originally 
occupying the space between the goal and the middle point of 
the course and the other that between the middle point and the 
starting-post. This, he thinks, involves the conclusion that half a 
given time is equal to double that time. The fallacy of the 
reasoning lies in the assumption that a body occupies an equal 
time in passing with equal velocity a body that is in motion and 
a body of equal size that is at rest; which is false. For instance 
(so runs the argument), let A, A.. .be the stationary bodies of 
equal size, B, EL.the bodies, equal in number and in size to A, 
A..., originally occupying the half of the course from the starting- 
post to the middle of the A's, and G, G... those originally 
occupying the other half from the goal to the middle of the A's, 
equal in number, size, and velocity to B, B....Then three 
consequences follow: 

First, as the B's and the G's pass one another, the first B reaches 
the last G at the same moment as the first G reaches the last B. 
Secondly at this moment the first G has passed all the A's, 
whereas the first B has passed only half the A's, and has 
consequently occupied only half the time occupied by the first 
G, since each of the two occupies an equal time in passing each 



772 



A. Thirdly, at the same moment all the B's have passed all the 
G's: for the first G and the first B will simultaneously reach the 
opposite ends of the course, since (so says Zeno) the time 
occupied by the first G in passing each of the B's is equal to that 
occupied by it in passing each of the A's, because an equal time 
is occupied by both the first B and the first G in passing all the 
A's. This is the argument, but it presupposed the aforesaid 
fallacious assumption. 

Nor in reference to contradictory change shall we find anything 
unanswerable in the argument that if a thing is changing from 
not-white, say, to white, and is in neither condition, then it will 
be neither white nor not-white: for the fact that it is not wholly 
in either condition will not preclude us from calling it white or 
not-white. We call a thing white or not-white not necessarily 
because it is be one or the other, but cause most of its parts or 
the most essential parts of it are so: not being in a certain 
condition is different from not being wholly in that condition. 
So, too, in the case of being and not-being and all other 
conditions which stand in a contradictory relation: while the 
changing thing must of necessity be in one of the two opposites, 
it is never wholly in either. 

Again, in the case of circles and spheres and everything whose 
motion is confined within the space that it occupies, it is not 
true to say the motion can be nothing but rest, on the ground 
that such things in motion, themselves and their parts, will 
occupy the same position for a period of time, and that 
therefore they will be at once at rest and in motion. For in the 
first place the parts do not occupy the same position for any 
period of time: and in the second place the whole also is always 
changing to a different position: for if we take the orbit as 
described from a point A on a circumference, it will not be the 
same as the orbit as described from B or G or any other point on 
the same circumference except in an accidental sense, the 



773 



sense that is to say in which a musical man is the same as a 
man. Thus one orbit is always changing into another, and the 
thing will never be at rest. And it is the same with the sphere 
and everything else whose motion is confined within the space 
that it occupies. 



10 

Our next point is that that which is without parts cannot be in 
motion except accidentally: i.e. it can be in motion only in so far 
as the body or the magnitude is in motion and the partless is in 
motion by inclusion therein, just as that which is in a boat may 
be in motion in consequence of the locomotion of the boat, or a 
part may be in motion in virtue of the motion of the whole. (It 
must be remembered, however, that by 'that which is without 
parts' I mean that which is quantitatively indivisible (and that 
the case of the motion of a part is not exactly parallel): for parts 
have motions belonging essentially and severally to themselves 
distinct from the motion of the whole. The distinction may be 
seen most clearly in the case of a revolving sphere, in which the 
velocities of the parts near the centre and of those on the 
surface are different from one another and from that of the 
whole; this implies that there is not one motion but many). As 
we have said, then, that which is without parts can be in motion 
in the sense in which a man sitting in a boat is in motion when 
the boat is travelling, but it cannot be in motion of itself. For 
suppose that it is changing from AB to BG - either from one 
magnitude to another, or from one form to another, or from 
some state to its contradictory - and let D be the primary time 
in which it undergoes the change. Then in the time in which it 
is changing it must be either in AB or in BG or partly in one and 
partly in the other: for this, as we saw, is true of everything that 



774 



is changing. Now it cannot be partly in each of the two: for then 
it would be divisible into parts. Nor again can it be in BG: for 
then it will have completed the change, whereas the 
assumption is that the change is in process. It remains, then, 
that in the time in which it is changing, it is in AB. That being 
so, it will be at rest: for, as we saw, to be in the same condition 
for a period of time is to be at rest. So it is not possible for that 
which has no parts to be in motion or to change in any way: for 
only one condition could have made it possible for it to have 
motion, viz. that time should be composed of moments, in 
which case at any moment it would have completed a motion 
or a change, so that it would never be in motion, but would 
always have been in motion. But this we have already shown 
above to be impossible: time is not composed of moments, just 
as a line is not composed of points, and motion is not composed 
of starts: for this theory simply makes motion consist of 
indivisibles in exactly the same way as time is made to consist 
of moments or a length of points. 

Again, it may be shown in the following way that there can be 
no motion of a point or of any other indivisible. That which is in 
motion can never traverse a space greater than itself without 
first traversing a space equal to or less than itself. That being so, 
it is evident that the point also must first traverse a space equal 
to or less than itself. But since it is indivisible, there can be no 
space less than itself for it to traverse first: so it will have to 
traverse a distance equal to itself. Thus the line will be 
composed of points, for the point, as it continually traverses a 
distance equal to itself, will be a measure of the whole line. But 
since this is impossible, it is likewise impossible for the 
indivisible to be in motion. 

Again, since motion is always in a period of time and never in a 
moment, and all time is divisible, for everything that is in 
motion there must be a time less than that in which it traverses 



775 



a distance as great as itself. For that in which it is in motion will 
be a time, because all motion is in a period of time; and all time 
has been shown above to be divisible. Therefore, if a point is in 
motion, there must be a time less than that in which it has 
itself traversed any distance. But this is impossible, for in less 
time it must traverse less distance, and thus the indivisible will 
be divisible into something less than itself, just as the time is so 
divisible: the fact being that the only condition under which 
that which is without parts and indivisible could be in motion 
would have been the possibility of the infinitely small being in 
motion in a moment: for in the two questions - that of motion 
in a moment and that of motion of something indivisible - the 
same principle is involved. 

Our next point is that no process of change is infinite: for every 
change, whether between contradictories or between contraries, 
is a change from something to something. Thus in contradictory 
changes the positive or the negative, as the case may be, is the 
limit, e.g. being is the limit of coming to be and not-being is the 
limit of ceasing to be: and in contrary changes the particular 
contraries are the limits, since these are the extreme points of 
any such process of change, and consequently of every process 
of alteration: for alteration is always dependent upon some 
contraries. Similarly contraries are the extreme points of 
processes of increase and decrease: the limit of increase is to be 
found in the complete magnitude proper to the peculiar nature 
of the thing that is increasing, while the limit of decrease is the 
complete loss of such magnitude. Locomotion, it is true, we 
cannot show to be finite in this way, since it is not always 
between contraries. But since that which cannot be cut (in the 
sense that it is inconceivable that it should be cut, the term 
'cannot' being used in several senses) - since it is inconceivable 
that that which in this sense cannot be cut should be in process 
of being cut, and generally that that which cannot come to be 
should be in process of coming to be, it follows that it is 



776 



inconceivable that that which cannot complete a change should 
be in process of changing to that to which it cannot complete a 
change. If, then, it is to be assumed that that which is in 
locomotion is in process of changing, it must be capable of 
completing the change. Consequently its motion is not infinite, 
and it will not be in locomotion over an infinite distance, for it 
cannot traverse such a distance. 

It is evident, then, that a process of change cannot be infinite in 
the sense that it is not defined by limits. But it remains to be 
considered whether it is possible in the sense that one and the 
same process of change may be infinite in respect of the time 
which it occupies. If it is not one process, it would seem that 
there is nothing to prevent its being infinite in this sense; e.g. if 
a process of locomotion be succeeded by a process of alteration 
and that by a process of increase and that again by a process of 
coming to be: in this way there may be motion for ever so far as 
the time is concerned, but it will not be one motion, because all 
these motions do not compose one. If it is to be one process, no 
motion can be infinite in respect of the time that it occupies, 
with the single exception of rotatory locomotion. 



Book VII 



Everything that is in motion must be moved by something. For if 
it has not the source of its motion in itself it is evident that it is 



777 



moved by something other than itself, for there must be 
something else that moves it. If on the other hand it has the 
source of its motion in itself, let AB be taken to represent that 
which is in motion essentially of itself and not in virtue of the 
fact that something belonging to it is in motion. Now in the first 
place to assume that AB, because it is in motion as a whole and 
is not moved by anything external to itself, is therefore moved 
by itself - this is just as if, supposing that KL is moving LM and 
is also itself in motion, we were to deny that KM is moved by 
anything on the ground that it is not evident which is the part 
that is moving it and which the part that is moved. In the 
second place that which is in motion without being moved by 
anything does not necessarily cease from its motion because 
something else is at rest, but a thing must be moved by 
something if the fact of something else having ceased from its 
motion causes it to be at rest. Thus, if this is accepted, 
everything that is in motion must be moved by something. For 
AB, which has been taken to represent that which is in motion, 
must be divisible since everything that is in motion is divisible. 
Let it be divided, then, at G. Now if GB is not in motion, then AB 
will not be in motion: for if it is, it is clear that AG would be in 
motion while BG is at rest, and thus AB cannot be in motion 
essentially and primarily. But ex hypothesi AB is in motion 
essentially and primarily. Therefore if GB is not in motion AB 
will be at rest. But we have agreed that that which is at rest if 
something else is not in motion must be moved by something. 
Consequently, everything that is in motion must be moved by 
something: for that which is in motion will always be divisible, 
and if a part of it is not in motion the whole must be at rest. 

Since everything that is in motion must be moved by 
something, let us take the case in which a thing is in 
locomotion and is moved by something that is itself in motion, 
and that again is moved by something else that is in motion, 
and that by something else, and so on continually: then the 



778 



series cannot go on to infinity, but there must be some first 
movent. For let us suppose that this is not so and take the series 
to be infinite. Let A then be moved by B, B by G, G by D, and so 
on, each member of the series being moved by that which 
comes next to it. Then since ex hypothesi the movent while 
causing motion is also itself in motion, and the motion of the 
moved and the motion of the movent must proceed 
simultaneously (for the movent is causing motion and the 
moved is being moved simultaneously) it is evident that the 
respective motions of A, B, G, and each of the other moved 
movents are simultaneous. Let us take the motion of each 
separately and let E be the motion of A, Z of B, and H and 
respectively the motions of G and D: for though they are all 
moved severally one by another, yet we may still take the 
motion of each as numerically one, since every motion is from 
something to something and is not infinite in respect of its 
extreme points. By a motion that is numerically one I mean a 
motion that proceeds from something numerically one and the 
same to something numerically one and the same in a period of 
time numerically one and the same: for a motion may be the 
same generically, specifically, or numerically: it is generically 
the same if it belongs to the same category, e.g. substance or 
quality: it is specifically the same if it proceeds from something 
specifically the same to something specifically the same, e.g. 
from white to black or from good to bad, which is not of a kind 
specifically distinct: it is numerically the same if it proceeds 
from something numerically one to something numerically one 
in the same period of time, e.g. from a particular white to a 
particular black, or from a particular place to a particular place, 
in a particular period of time: for if the period of time were not 
one and the same, the motion would no longer be numerically 
one though it would still be specifically one. 

We have dealt with this question above. Now let us further take 
the time in which A has completed its motion, and let it be 



779 



represented by K. Then since the motion of A is finite the time 
will also be finite. But since the movents and the things moved 
are infinite, the motion EZHO, i.e. the motion that is composed 
of all the individual motions, must be infinite. For the motions 
of A, B, and the others may be equal, or the motions of the 
others may be greater: but assuming what is conceivable, we 
find that whether they are equal or some are greater, in both 
cases the whole motion is infinite. And since the motion of A 
and that of each of the others are simultaneous, the whole 
motion must occupy the same time as the motion of A: but the 
time occupied by the motion of A is finite: consequently the 
motion will be infinite in a finite time, which is impossible. 

It might be thought that what we set out to prove has thus been 
shown, but our argument so far does not prove it, because it 
does not yet prove that anything impossible results from the 
contrary supposition: for in a finite time there may be an 
infinite motion, though not of one thing, but of many: and in 
the case that we are considering this is so: for each thing 
accomplishes its own motion, and there is no impossibility in 
many things being in motion simultaneously. But if (as we see 
to be universally the case) that which primarily is moved locally 
and corporeally must be either in contact with or continuous 
with that which moves it, the things moved and the movents 
must be continuous or in contact with one another, so that 
together they all form a single unity: whether this unity is finite 
or infinite makes no difference to our present argument; for in 
any case since the things in motion are infinite in number the 
whole motion will be infinite, if, as is theoretically possible, 
each motion is either equal to or greater than that which 
follows it in the series: for we shall take as actual that which is 
theoretically possible. If, then, A, B, G, D form an infinite 
magnitude that passes through the motion EZHO in the finite 
time K, this involves the conclusion that an infinite motion is 
passed through in a finite time: and whether the magnitude in 



780 



question is finite or infinite this is in either case impossible. 
Therefore the series must come to an end, and there must be a 
first movent and a first moved: for the fact that this 
impossibility results only from the assumption of a particular 
case is immaterial, since the case assumed is theoretically 
possible, and the assumption of a theoretically possible case 
ought not to give rise to any impossible result. 



That which is the first movement of a thing - in the sense that 
it supplies not 'that for the sake of which' but the source of the 
motion - is always together with that which is moved by it by 
'together' I mean that there is nothing intermediate between 
them). This is universally true wherever one thing is moved by 
another. And since there are three kinds of motion, local, 
qualitative, and quantitative, there must also be three kinds of 
movent, that which causes locomotion, that which causes 
alteration, and that which causes increase or decrease. 

Let us begin with locomotion, for this is the primary motion. 
Everything that is in locomotion is moved either by itself or by 
something else. In the case of things that are moved by 
themselves it is evident that the moved and the movent are 
together: for they contain within themselves their first movent, 
so that there is nothing in between. The motion of things that 
are moved by something else must proceed in one of four ways: 
for there are four kinds of locomotion caused by something 
other than that which is in motion, viz. pulling, pushing, 
carrying, and twirling. All forms of locomotion are reducible to 
these. Thus pushing on is a form of pushing in which that 
which is causing motion away from itself follows up that which 



781 



it pushes and continues to push it: pushing off occurs when the 
movent does not follow up the thing that it has moved: 
throwing when the movent causes a motion away from itself 
more violent than the natural locomotion of the thing moved, 
which continues its course so long as it is controlled by the 
motion imparted to it. Again, pushing apart and pushing 
together are forms respectively of pushing off and pulling: 
pushing apart is pushing off, which may be a motion either 
away from the pusher or away from something else, while 
pushing together is pulling, which may be a motion towards 
something else as well as the puller. We may similarly classify 
all the varieties of these last two, e.g. packing and combing: the 
former is a form of pushing together, the latter a form of 
pushing apart. The same is true of the other processes of 
combination and separation (they will all be found to be forms 
of pushing apart or of pushing together), except such as are 
involved in the processes of becoming and perishing. (At same 
time it is evident that there is no other kind of motion but 
combination and separation: for they may all be apportioned to 
one or other of those already mentioned.) Again, inhaling is a 
form of pulling, exhaling a form of pushing: and the same is 
true of spitting and of all other motions that proceed through 
the body, whether secretive or assimilative, the assimilative 
being forms of pulling, the secretive of pushing off. All other 
kinds of locomotion must be similarly reduced, for they all fall 
under one or other of our four heads. And again, of these four, 
carrying and twirling are to pulling and pushing. For carrying 
always follows one of the other three methods, for that which is 
carried is in motion accidentally, because it is in or upon 
something that is in motion, and that which carries it is in 
doing so being either pulled or pushed or twirled; thus carrying 
belongs to all the other three kinds of motion in common. And 
twirling is a compound of pulling and pushing, for that which is 
twirling a thing must be pulling one part of the thing and 



782 



pushing another part, since it impels one part away from itself 
and another part towards itself. If, therefore, it can be shown 
that that which is pushing and that which is pushing and 
pulling are adjacent respectively to that which is being pushed 
and that which is being pulled, it will be evident that in all 
locomotion there is nothing intermediate between moved and 
movent. But the former fact is clear even from the definitions of 
pushing and pulling, for pushing is motion to something else 
from oneself or from something else, and pulling is motion from 
something else to oneself or to something else, when the 
motion of that which is pulling is quicker than the motion that 
would separate from one another the two things that are 
continuous: for it is this that causes one thing to be pulled on 
along with the other. (It might indeed be thought that there is a 
form of pulling that arises in another way: that wood, e.g. pulls 
fire in a manner different from that described above. But it 
makes no difference whether that which pulls is in motion or is 
stationary when it is pulling: in the latter case it pulls to the 
place where it is, while in the former it pulls to the place where 
it was.) Now it is impossible to move anything either from 
oneself to something else or something else to oneself without 
being in contact with it: it is evident, therefore, that in all 
locomotion there is nothing intermediate between moved and 
movent. 

Nor again is there anything intermediate between that which 
undergoes and that which causes alteration: this can be proved 
by induction: for in every case we find that the respective 
extremities of that which causes and that which undergoes 
alteration are adjacent. For our assumption is that things that 
are undergoing alteration are altered in virtue of their being 
affected in respect of their so-called affective qualities, since 
that which is of a certain quality is altered in so far as it is 
sensible, and the characteristics in which bodies differ from one 
another are sensible characteristics: for every body differs from 



783 



another in possessing a greater or lesser number of sensible 
characteristics or in possessing the same sensible 
characteristics in a greater or lesser degree. But the alteration of 
that which undergoes alteration is also caused by the above- 
mentioned characteristics, which are affections of some 
particular underlying quality. Thus we say that a thing is altered 
by becoming hot or sweet or thick or dry or white: and we make 
these assertions alike of what is inanimate and of what is 
animate, and further, where animate things are in question, we 
make them both of the parts that have no power of sense- 
perception and of the senses themselves. For in a way even the 
senses undergo alteration, since the active sense is a motion 
through the body in the course of which the sense is affected in 
a certain way. We see, then, that the animate is capable of every 
kind of alteration of which the inanimate is capable: but the 
inanimate is not capable of every kind of alteration of which the 
animate is capable, since it is not capable of alteration in 
respect of the senses: moreover the inanimate is unconscious of 
being affected by alteration, whereas the animate is conscious 
of it, though there is nothing to prevent the animate also being 
unconscious of it when the process of the alteration does not 
concern the senses. Since, then, the alteration of that which 
undergoes alteration is caused by sensible things, in every case 
of such alteration it is evident that the respective extremities of 
that which causes and that which undergoes alteration are 
adjacent. Thus the air is continuous with that which causes the 
alteration, and the body that undergoes alteration is continuous 
with the air. Again, the colour is continuous with the light and 
the light with the sight. And the same is true of hearing and 
smelling: for the primary movent in respect to the moved is the 
air. Similarly, in the case of tasting, the flavour is adjacent to the 
sense of taste. And it is just the same in the case of things that 
are inanimate and incapable of sense-perception. Thus there 



784 



can be nothing intermediate between that which undergoes and 
that which causes alteration. 

Nor, again, can there be anything intermediate between that 
which suffers and that which causes increase: for the part of 
the latter that starts the increase does so by becoming attached 
in such a way to the former that the whole becomes one. Again, 
the decrease of that which suffers decrease is caused by a part 
of the thing becoming detached. So that which causes increase 
and that which causes decrease must be continuous with that 
which suffers increase and that which suffers decrease 
respectively: and if two things are continuous with one another 
there can be nothing intermediate between them. 

It is evident, therefore, that between the extremities of the 
moved and the movent that are respectively first and last in 
reference to the moved there is nothing intermediate. 



Everything, we say, that undergoes alteration is altered by 
sensible causes, and there is alteration only in things that are 
said to be essentially affected by sensible things. The truth of 
this is to be seen from the following considerations. Of all other 
things it would be most natural to suppose that there is 
alteration in figures and shapes, and in acquired states and in 
the processes of acquiring and losing these: but as a matter of 
fact in neither of these two classes of things is there alteration. 

In the first place, when a particular formation of a thing is 
completed, we do not call it by the name of its material: e.g. we 
do not call the statue 'bronze' or the pyramid 'wax' or the bed 
'wood', but we use a derived expression and call them 'of 



785 



bronze', 'waxen', and 'wooden' respectively. But when a thing 
has been affected and altered in any way we still call it by the 
original name: thus we speak of the bronze or the wax being dry 
or fluid or hard or hot. 

And not only so: we also speak of the particular fluid or hot 
substance as being bronze, giving the material the same name 
as that which we use to describe the affection. 

Since, therefore, having regard to the figure or shape of a thing 
we no longer call that which has become of a certain figure by 
the name of the material that exhibits the figure, whereas 
having regard to a thing's affections or alterations we still call it 
by the name of its material, it is evident that becomings of the 
former kind cannot be alterations. 

Moreover it would seem absurd even to speak in this way, to 
speak, that is to say, of a man or house or anything else that has 
come into existence as having been altered. Though it may be 
true that every such becoming is necessarily the result of 
something's being altered, the result, e.g. of the material's being 
condensed or rarefied or heated or cooled, nevertheless it is not 
the things that are coming into existence that are altered, and 
their becoming is not an alteration. 

Again, acquired states, whether of the body or of the soul, are 
not alterations. For some are excellences and others are defects, 
and neither excellence nor defect is an alteration: excellence is 
a perfection (for when anything acquires its proper excellence 
we call it perfect, since it is then if ever that we have a thing in 
its natural state: e.g. we have a perfect circle when we have one 
as good as possible), while defect is a perishing of or departure 
from this condition. So as when speaking of a house we do not 
call its arrival at perfection an alteration (for it would be absurd 
to suppose that the coping or the tiling is an alteration or that 
in receiving its coping or its tiling a house is altered and not 



786 



perfected), the same also holds good in the case of excellences 
and defects and of the persons or things that possess or acquire 
them: for excellences are perfections of a thing's nature and 
defects are departures from it: consequently they are not 
alterations. 

Further, we say that all excellences depend upon particular 
relations. Thus bodily excellences such as health and a good 
state of body we regard as consisting in a blending of hot and 
cold elements within the body in due proportion, in relation 
either to one another or to the surrounding atmosphere: and in 
like manner we regard beauty, strength, and all the other bodily 
excellences and defects. Each of them exists in virtue of a 
particular relation and puts that which possesses it in a good or 
bad condition with regard to its proper affections, where by 
'proper' affections I mean those influences that from the 
natural constitution of a thing tend to promote or destroy its 
existence. Since then, relatives are neither themselves 
alterations nor the subjects of alteration or of becoming or in 
fact of any change whatever, it is evident that neither states nor 
the processes of losing and acquiring states are alterations, 
though it may be true that their becoming or perishing is 
necessarily, like the becoming or perishing of a specific 
character or form, the result of the alteration of certain other 
things, e.g. hot and cold or dry and wet elements or the 
elements, whatever they may be, on which the states primarily 
depend. For each several bodily defect or excellence involves a 
relation with those things from which the possessor of the 
defect or excellence is naturally subject to alteration: thus 
excellence disposes its possessor to be unaffected by these 
influences or to be affected by those of them that ought to be 
admitted, while defect disposes its possessor to be affected by 
them or to be unaffected by those of them that ought to be 
admitted. 



787 



And the case is similar in regard to the states of the soul, all of 
which (like those of body) exist in virtue of particular relations, 
the excellences being perfections of nature and the defects 
departures from it: moreover, excellence puts its possessor in 
good condition, while defect puts its possessor in a bad 
condition, to meet his proper affections. Consequently these 
cannot any more than the bodily states be alterations, nor can 
the processes of losing and acquiring them be so, though their 
becoming is necessarily the result of an alteration of the 
sensitive part of the soul, and this is altered by sensible objects: 
for all moral excellence is concerned with bodily pleasures and 
pains, which again depend either upon acting or upon 
remembering or upon anticipating. Now those that depend 
upon action are determined by sense-perception, i.e. they are 
stimulated by something sensible: and those that depend upon 
memory or anticipation are likewise to be traced to sense- 
perception, for in these cases pleasure is felt either in 
remembering what one has experienced or in anticipating what 
one is going to experience. Thus all pleasure of this kind must 
be produced by sensible things: and since the presence in any 
one of moral defect or excellence involves the presence in him 
of pleasure or pain (with which moral excellence and defect are 
always concerned), and these pleasures and pains are 
alterations of the sensitive part, it is evident that the loss and 
acquisition of these states no less than the loss and acquisition 
of the states of the body must be the result of the alteration of 
something else. Consequently, though their becoming is 
accompanied by an alteration, they are not themselves 
alterations. 

Again, the states of the intellectual part of the soul are not 
alterations, nor is there any becoming of them. In the first place 
it is much more true of the possession of knowledge that it 
depends upon a particular relation. And further, it is evident 
that there is no becoming of these states. For that which is 



788 



potentially possessed of knowledge becomes actually possessed 
of it not by being set in motion at all itself but by reason of the 
presence of something else: i.e. it is when it meets with the 
particular object that it knows in a manner the particular 
through its knowledge of the universal. (Again, there is no 
becoming of the actual use and activity of these states, unless it 
is thought that there is a becoming of vision and touching and 
that the activity in question is similar to these.) And the original 
acquisition of knowledge is not a becoming or an alteration: for 
the terms 'knowing' and 'understanding' imply that the intellect 
has reached a state of rest and come to a standstill, and there is 
no becoming that leads to a state of rest, since, as we have said 
above, change at all can have a becoming. Moreover, just as to 
say, when any one has passed from a state of intoxication or 
sleep or disease to the contrary state, that he has become 
possessed of knowledge again is incorrect in spite of the fact 
that he was previously incapable of using his knowledge, so, too, 
when any one originally acquires the state, it is incorrect to say 
that he becomes possessed of knowledge: for the possession of 
understanding and knowledge is produced by the soul's settling 
down out of the restlessness natural to it. Hence, too, in 
learning and in forming judgements on matters relating to their 
sense-perceptions children are inferior to adults owing to the 
great amount of restlessness and motion in their souls. Nature 
itself causes the soul to settle down and come to a state of rest 
for the performance of some of its functions, while for the 
performance of others other things do so: but in either case the 
result is brought about through the alteration of something in 
the body, as we see in the case of the use and activity of the 
intellect arising from a man's becoming sober or being 
awakened. It is evident, then, from the preceding argument that 
alteration and being altered occur in sensible things and in the 
sensitive part of the soul, and, except accidentally, in nothing 
else. 



789 



A difficulty may be raised as to whether every motion is 
commensurable with every other or not. Now if they are all 
commensurable and if two things to have the same velocity 
must accomplish an equal motion in an equal time, then we 
may have a circumference equal to a straight line, or, of course, 
the one may be greater or less than the other. Further, if one 
thing alters and another accomplishes a locomotion in an equal 
time, we may have an alteration and a locomotion equal to one 
another: thus an affection will be equal to a length, which is 
impossible. But is it not only when an equal motion is 
accomplished by two things in an equal time that the velocities 
of the two are equal? Now an affection cannot be equal to a 
length. Therefore there cannot be an alteration equal to or less 
than a locomotion: and consequently it is not the case that 
every motion is commensurable with every other. 

But how will our conclusion work out in the case of the circle 
and the straight line? It would be absurd to suppose that the 
motion of one in a circle and of another in a straight line cannot 
be similar, but that the one must inevitably move more quickly 
or more slowly than the other, just as if the course of one were 
downhill and of the other uphill. Moreover it does not as a 
matter of fact make any difference to the argument to say that 
the one motion must inevitably be quicker or slower than the 
other: for then the circumference can be greater or less than the 
straight line; and if so it is possible for the two to be equal. For if 
in the time A the quicker (B) passes over the distance B' and the 
slower (G) passes over the distance G', B' will be greater than G': 
for this is what we took 'quicker' to mean: and so quicker 
motion also implies that one thing traverses an equal distance 



790 



in less time than another: consequently there will be a part of A 
in which B will pass over a part of the circle equal to G', while G 
will occupy the whole of A in passing over G'. None the less, if 
the two motions are commensurable, we are confronted with 
the consequence stated above, viz. that there may be a straight 
line equal to a circle. But these are not commensurable: and so 
the corresponding motions are not commensurable either. 

But may we say that things are always commensurable if the 
same terms are applied to them without equivocation? e.g. a 
pen, a wine, and the highest note in a scale are not 
commensurable: we cannot say whether any one of them is 
sharper than any other: and why is this? they are 
incommensurable because it is only equivocally that the same 
term 'sharp' is applied to them: whereas the highest note in a 
scale is commensurable with the leading-note, because the 
term 'sharp' has the same meaning as applied to both. Can it be, 
then, that the term 'quick' has not the same meaning as applied 
to straight motion and to circular motion respectively? If so, far 
less will it have the same meaning as applied to alteration and 
to locomotion. 

Or shall we in the first place deny that things are always 
commensurable if the same terms are applied to them without 
equivocation? For the term 'much' has the same meaning 
whether applied to water or to air, yet water and air are not 
commensurable in respect of it: or, if this illustration is not 
considered satisfactory, 'double' at any rate would seem to have 
the same meaning as applied to each (denoting in each case the 
proportion of two to one), yet water and air are not 
commensurable in respect of it. But here again may we not take 
up the same position and say that the term 'much' is equivocal? 
In fact there are some terms of which even the definitions are 
equivocal; e.g. if 'much' were defined as 'so much and more','so 
much' would mean something different in different cases: 



791 



'equal' is similarly equivocal; and 'one' again is perhaps 
inevitably an equivocal term; and if 'one' is equivocal, so is 
'two'. Otherwise why is it that some things are commensurable 
while others are not, if the nature of the attribute in the two 
cases is really one and the same? 

Can it be that the incommensurability of two things in respect 
of any attribute is due to a difference in that which is primarily 
capable of carrying the attribute? Thus horse and dog are so 
commensurable that we may say which is the whiter, since that 
which primarily contains the whiteness is the same in both, viz. 
the surface: and similarly they are commensurable in respect of 
size. But water and speech are not commensurable in respect of 
clearness, since that which primarily contains the attribute is 
different in the two cases. It would seem, however that we must 
reject this solution, since clearly we could thus make all 
equivocal attributes univocal and say merely that that contains 
each of them is different in different cases: thus 'equality', 
'sweetness', and 'whiteness' will severally always be the same, 
though that which contains them is different in different cases. 
Moreover, it is not any casual thing that is capable of carrying 
any attribute: each single attribute can be carried primarily only 
by one single thing. 

Must we then say that, if two things are to be commensurable in 
respect of any attribute, not only must the attribute in question 
be applicable to both without equivocation, but there must also 
be no specific differences either in the attribute itself or in that 
which contains the attribute - that these, I mean, must not be 
divisible in the way in which colour is divided into kinds? Thus 
in this respect one thing will not be commensurable with 
another, i.e. we cannot say that one is more coloured than the 
other where only colour in general and not any particular colour 
is meant; but they are commensurable in respect of whiteness. 



792 



Similarly in the case of motion: two things are of the same 
velocity if they occupy an equal time in accomplishing a certain 
equal amount of motion. Suppose, then, that in a certain time 
an alteration is undergone by one half of a body's length and a 
locomotion is accomplished the other half: can be say that in 
this case the alteration is equal to the locomotion and of the 
same velocity? That would be absurd, and the reason is that 
there are different species of motion. And if in consequence of 
this we must say that two things are of equal velocity if they 
accomplish locomotion over an equal distance in an equal time, 
we have to admit the equality of a straight line and a 
circumference. What, then, is the reason of this? Is it that 
locomotion is a genus or that line is a genus? (We may leave the 
time out of account, since that is one and the same.) If the lines 
are specifically different, the locomotions also differ specifically 
from one another: for locomotion is specifically differentiated 
according to the specific differentiation of that over which it 
takes place. (It is also similarly differentiated, it would seem, 
accordingly as the instrument of the locomotion is different: 
thus if feet are the instrument, it is walking, if wings it is flying; 
but perhaps we should rather say that this is not so, and that in 
this case the differences in the locomotion are merely 
differences of posture in that which is in motion.) We may say, 
therefore, that things are of equal velocity in an equal time they 
traverse the same magnitude: and when I call it 'the same' I 
mean that it contains no specific difference and therefore no 
difference in the motion that takes place over it. So we have 
now to consider how motion is differentiated: and this 
discussion serves to show that the genus is not a unity but 
contains a plurality latent in it and distinct from it, and that in 
the case of equivocal terms sometimes the different senses in 
which they are used are far removed from one another, while 
sometimes there is a certain likeness between them, and 
sometimes again they are nearly related either generically or 



793 



analogically, with the result that they seem not to be equivocal 
though they really are. 

When, then, is there a difference of species? Is an attribute 
specifically different if the subject is different while the 
attribute is the same, or must the attribute itself be different as 
well? And how are we to define the limits of a species? What 
will enable us to decide that particular instances of whiteness 
or sweetness are the same or different? Is it enough that it 
appears different in one subject from what appears in another? 
Or must there be no sameness at all? And further, where 
alteration is in question, how is one alteration to be of equal 
velocity with another? One person may be cured quickly and 
another slowly, and cures may also be simultaneous: so that, 
recovery of health being an alteration, we have here alterations 
of equal velocity, since each alteration occupies an equal time. 
But what alteration? We cannot here speak of an 'equal' 
alteration: what corresponds in the category of quality to 
equality in the category of quantity is 'likeness'. However, let us 
say that there is equal velocity where the same change is 
accomplished in an equal time. Are we, then, to find the 
commensurability in the subject of the affection or in the 
affection itself? In the case that we have just been considering it 
is the fact that health is one and the same that enables us to 
arrive at the conclusion that the one alteration is neither more 
nor less than the other, but that both are alike. If on the other 
hand the affection is different in the two cases, e.g. when the 
alterations take the form of becoming white and becoming 
healthy respectively, here there is no sameness or equality or 
likeness inasmuch as the difference in the affections at once 
makes the alterations specifically different, and there is no 
unity of alteration any more than there would be unity of 
locomotion under like conditions. So we must find out how 
many species there are of alteration and of locomotion 
respectively. Now if the things that are in motion - that is to say, 



794 



the things to which the motions belong essentially and not 
accidentally - differ specifically, then their respective motions 
will also differ specifically: if on the other hand they differ 
generically or numerically, the motions also will differ 
generically or numerically as the case may be. But there still 
remains the question whether, supposing that two alterations 
are of equal velocity, we ought to look for this equality in the 
sameness (or likeness) of the affections, or in the things altered, 
to see e.g. whether a certain quantity of each has become white. 
Or ought we not rather to look for it in both? That is to say, the 
alterations are the same or different according as the affections 
are the same or different, while they are equal or unequal 
according as the things altered are equal or unequal. 

And now we must consider the same question in the case of 
becoming and perishing: how is one becoming of equal velocity 
with another? They are of equal velocity if in an equal time 
there are produced two things that are the same and 
specifically inseparable, e.g. two men (not merely generically 
inseparable as e.g. two animals). Similarly one is quicker than 
the other if in an equal time the product is different in the two 
cases. I state it thus because we have no pair of terms that will 
convey this 'difference' in the way in which unlikeness is 
conveyed. If we adopt the theory that it is number that 
constitutes being, we may indeed speak of a 'greater number' 
and a 'lesser number' within the same species, but there is no 
common term that will include both relations, nor are there 
terms to express each of them separately in the same way as we 
indicate a higher degree or preponderance of an affection by 
'more', of a quantity by 'greater.' 



795 



Now since wherever there is a movent, its motion always acts 
upon something, is always in something, and always extends to 
something (by 'is always in something' I mean that it occupies a 
time: and by 'extends to something' I mean that it involves the 
traversing of a certain amount of distance: for at any moment 
when a thing is causing motion, it also has caused motion, so 
that there must always be a certain amount of distance that has 
been traversed and a certain amount of time that has been 
occupied), then, A the movement have moved B a distance G in 
a time D, then in the same time the same force A will move 1/2B 
twice the distance G, and in 1/2D it will move 1/2B the whole 
distance for G: thus the rules of proportion will be observed. 
Again if a given force move a given weight a certain distance in 
a certain time and half the distance in half the time, half the 
motive power will move half the weight the same distance in 
the same time. Let E represent half the motive power A and Z 
half the weight B: then the ratio between the motive power and 
the weight in the one case is similar and proportionate to the 
ratio in the other, so that each force will cause the same 
distance to be traversed in the same time. But if E move Z a 
distance G in a time D, it does not necessarily follow that E can 
move twice Z half the distance G in the same time. If, then, A 
move B a distance G in a time D, it does not follow that E, being 
half of A, will in the time D or in any fraction of it cause B to 
traverse a part of G the ratio between which and the whole of G 
is proportionate to that between A and E (whatever fraction of 
AE may be): in fact it might well be that it will cause no motion 
at all; for it does not follow that, if a given motive power causes 
a certain amount of motion, half that power will cause motion 
either of any particular amount or in any length of time: 
otherwise one man might move a ship, since both the motive 
power of the ship-haulers and the distance that they all cause 
the ship to traverse are divisible into as many parts as there are 



796 



men. Hence Zeno's reasoning is false when he argues that there 
is no part of the millet that does not make a sound: for there is 
no reason why any such part should not in any length of time 
fail to move the air that the whole bushel moves in falling. In 
fact it does not of itself move even such a quantity of the air as 
it would move if this part were by itself: for no part even exists 
otherwise than potentially. 

If on the other hand we have two forces each of which 
separately moves one of two weights a given distance in a given 
time, then the forces in combination will move the combined 
weights an equal distance in an equal time: for in this case the 
rules of proportion apply. 

Then does this hold good of alteration and of increase also? 
Surely it does, for in any given case we have a definite thing 
that cause increase and a definite thing that suffers increase, 
and the one causes and the other suffers a certain amount of 
increase in a certain amount of time. Similarly we have a 
definite thing that causes alteration and a definite thing that 
undergoes alteration, and a certain amount, or rather degree, of 
alteration is completed in a certain amount of time: thus in 
twice as much time twice as much alteration will be completed 
and conversely twice as much alteration will occupy twice as 
much time: and the alteration of half of its object will occupy 
half as much time and in half as much time half of the object 
will be altered: or again, in the same amount of time it will be 
altered twice as much. 

On the other hand if that which causes alteration or increase 
causes a certain amount of increase or alteration respectively in 
a certain amount of time, it does not necessarily follow that half 
the force will occupy twice the time in altering or increasing the 
object, or that in twice the time the alteration or increase will be 



797 



completed by it: it may happen that there will be no alteration 
or increase at all, the case being the same as with the weight. 



Book VIII 



It remains to consider the following question. Was there ever a 
becoming of motion before which it had no being, and is it 
perishing again so as to leave nothing in motion? Or are we to 
say that it never had any becoming and is not perishing, but 
always was and always will be? Is it in fact an immortal never- 
failing property of things that are, a sort of life as it were to all 
naturally constituted things? 

Now the existence of motion is asserted by all who have 
anything to say about nature, because they all concern 
themselves with the construction of the world and study the 
question of becoming and perishing, which processes could not 
come about without the existence of motion. But those who say 
that there is an infinite number of worlds, some of which are in 
process of becoming while others are in process of perishing, 
assert that there is always motion (for these processes of 
becoming and perishing of the worlds necessarily involve 
motion), whereas those who hold that there is only one world, 
whether everlasting or not, make corresponding assumptions in 
regard to motion. If then it is possible that at any time nothing 
should be in motion, this must come about in one of two ways: 



798 



either in the manner described by Anaxagoras, who says that all 
things were together and at rest for an infinite period of time, 
and that then Mind introduced motion and separated them; or 
in the manner described by Empedocles, according to whom the 
universe is alternately in motion and at rest-in motion, when 
Love is making the one out of many, or Strife is making many 
out of one, and at rest in the intermediate periods of time - his 
account being as follows: 

'Since One hath learned to spring from Manifold, 

And One disjoined makes manifold arise, 

Thus they Become, nor stable is their life: 

But since their motion must alternate be, 

Thus have they ever Rest upon their round': 

for we must suppose that he means by this that they alternate 
from the one motion to the other. We must consider, then, how 
this matter stands, for the discovery of the truth about it is of 
importance, not only for the study of nature, but also for the 
investigation of the First Principle. 

Let us take our start from what we have already laid down in 
our course on Physics. Motion, we say, is the fulfilment of the 
movable in so far as it is movable. Each kind of motion, 
therefore, necessarily involves the presence of the things that 
are capable of that motion. In fact, even apart from the 
definition of motion, every one would admit that in each kind of 
motion it is that which is capable of that motion that is in 
motion: thus it is that which is capable of alteration that is 
altered, and that which is capable of local change that is in 
locomotion: and so there must be something capable of being 
burned before there can be a process of being burned, and 
something capable of burning before there can be a process of 



799 



burning. Moreover, these things also must either have a 
beginning before which they had no being, or they must be 
eternal. Now if there was a becoming of every movable thing, it 
follows that before the motion in question another change or 
motion must have taken place in which that which was capable 
of being moved or of causing motion had its becoming. To 
suppose, on the other hand, that these things were in being 
throughout all previous time without there being any motion 
appears unreasonable on a moment's thought, and still more 
unreasonable, we shall find, on further consideration. For if we 
are to say that, while there are on the one hand things that are 
movable, and on the other hand things that are motive, there is 
a time when there is a first movent and a first moved, and 
another time when there is no such thing but only something 
that is at rest, then this thing that is at rest must previously 
have been in process of change: for there must have been some 
cause of its rest, rest being the privation of motion. Therefore, 
before this first change there will be a previous change. For 
some things cause motion in only one way, while others can 
produce either of two contrary motions: thus fire causes heating 
but not cooling, whereas it would seem that knowledge may be 
directed to two contrary ends while remaining one and the 
same. Even in the former class, however, there seems to be 
something similar, for a cold thing in a sense causes heating by 
turning away and retiring, just as one possessed of knowledge 
voluntarily makes an error when he uses his knowledge in the 
reverse way. But at any rate all things that are capable 
respectively of affecting and being affected, or of causing 
motion and being moved, are capable of it not under all 
conditions, but only when they are in a particular condition and 
approach one another: so it is on the approach of one thing to 
another that the one causes motion and the other is moved, 
and when they are present under such conditions as rendered 
the one motive and the other movable. So if the motion was not 



800 



always in process, it is clear that they must have been in a 
condition not such as to render them capable respectively of 
being moved and of causing motion, and one or other of them 
must have been in process of change: for in what is relative this 
is a necessary consequence: e.g. if one thing is double another 
when before it was not so, one or other of them, if not both, 
must have been in process of change. It follows then, that there 
will be a process of change previous to the first. 

(Further, how can there be any 'before' and 'after' without the 
existence of time? Or how can there be any time without the 
existence of motion? If, then, time is the number of motion or 
itself a kind of motion, it follows that, if there is always time, 
motion must also be eternal. But so far as time is concerned we 
see that all with one exception are in agreement in saying that 
it is uncreated: in fact, it is just this that enables Democritus to 
show that all things cannot have had a becoming: for time, he 
says, is uncreated. Plato alone asserts the creation of time, 
saying that it had a becoming together with the universe, the 
universe according to him having had a becoming. Now since 
time cannot exist and is unthinkable apart from the moment, 
and the moment a kind of middle-point, uniting as it does in 
itself both a beginning and an end, a beginning of future time 
and an end of past time, it follows that there must always be 
time: for the extremity of the last period of time that we take 
must be found in some moment, since time contains no point 
of contact for us except the moment. Therefore, since the 
moment is both a beginning and an end, there must always be 
time on both sides of it. But if this is true of time, it is evident 
that it must also be true of motion, time being a kind of 
affection of motion.) 

The same reasoning will also serve to show the imperishability 
of motion: just as a becoming of motion would involve, as we 
saw, the existence of a process of change previous to the first, in 



801 



the same way a perishing of motion would involve the existence 
of a process of change subsequent to the last: for when a thing 
ceases to be moved, it does not therefore at the same time cease 
to be movable - e.g. the cessation of the process of being burned 
does not involve the cessation of the capacity of being burned, 
since a thing may be capable of being burned without being in 
process of being burned - nor, when a thing ceases to be 
movent, does it therefore at the same time cease to a be motive. 
Again, the destructive agent will have to be destroyed, after 
what it destroys has been destroyed, and then that which has 
the capacity of destroying it will have to be destroyed 
afterwards, (so that there will be a process of change 
subsequent to the last,) for being destroyed also is a kind of 
change. If, then, view which we are criticizing involves these 
impossible consequences, it is clear that motion is eternal and 
cannot have existed at one time and not at another: in fact such 
a view can hardly be described as anythling else than fantastic. 

And much the same may be said of the view that such is the 
ordinance of nature and that this must be regarded as a 
principle, as would seem to be the view of Empedocles when he 
says that the constitution of the world is of necessity such that 
Love and Strife alternately predominate and cause motion, 
while in the intermediate period of time there is a state of rest. 
Probably also those who like like Anaxagoras, assert a single 
principle (of motion) would hold this view. But that which is 
produced or directed by nature can never be anything 
disorderly: for nature is everywhere the cause of order. 
Moreover, there is no ratio in the relation of the infinite to the 
infinite, whereas order always means ratio. But if we say that 
there is first a state of rest for an infinite time, and then motion 
is started at some moment, and that the fact that it is this 
rather than a previous moment is of no importance, and 
involves no order, then we can no longer say that it is nature's 
work: for if anything is of a certain character naturally, it either 



802 



is so invariably and is not sometimes of this and sometimes of 
another character (e.g. fire, which travels upwards naturally, 
does not sometimes do so and sometimes not) or there is a ratio 
in the variation. It would be better, therefore, to say with 
Empedocles and any one else who may have maintained such a 
theory as his that the universe is alternately at rest and in 
motion: for in a system of this kind we have at once a certain 
order. But even here the holder of the theory ought not only to 
assert the fact: he ought to explain the cause of it: i.e. he should 
not make any mere assumption or lay down any gratuitous 
axiom, but should employ either inductive or demonstrative 
reasoning. The Love and Strife postulated by Empedocles are not 
in themselves causes of the fact in question, nor is it of the 
essence of either that it should be so, the essential function of 
the former being to unite, of the latter to separate. If he is to go 
on to explain this alternate predominance, he should adduce 
cases where such a state of things exists, as he points to the 
fact that among mankind we have something that unites men, 
namely Love, while on the other hand enemies avoid one 
another: thus from the observed fact that this occurs in certain 
cases comes the assumption that it occurs also in the universe. 
Then, again, some argument is needed to explain why the 
predominance of each of the two forces lasts for an equal period 
of time. But it is a wrong assumption to suppose universally 
that we have an adequate first principle in virtue of the fact that 
something always is so or always happens so. Thus Democritus 
reduces the causes that explain nature to the fact that things 
happened in the past in the same way as they happen now: but 
he does not think fit to seek for a first principle to explain this 
'always': so, while his theory is right in so far as it is applied to 
certain individual cases, he is wrong in making it of universal 
application. Thus, a triangle always has its angles equal to two 
right angles, but there is nevertheless an ulterior cause of the 
eternity of this truth, whereas first principles are eternal and 



803 



have no ulterior cause. Let this conclude what we have to say in 
support of our contention that there never was a time when 
there was not motion, and never will be a time when there will 
not be motion. 



The arguments that may be advanced against this position are 
not difficult to dispose of. The chief considerations that might 
be thought to indicate that motion may exist though at one 
time it had not existed at all are the following: 

First, it may be said that no process of change is eternal: for the 
nature of all change is such that it proceeds from something to 
something, so that every process of change must be bounded by 
the contraries that mark its course, and no motion can go on to 
infinity. 

Secondly, we see that a thing that neither is in motion nor 
contains any motion within itself can be set in motion; e.g. 
inanimate things that are (whether the whole or some part is in 
question) not in motion but at rest, are at some moment set in 
motion: whereas, if motion cannot have a becoming before 
which it had no being, these things ought to be either always or 
never in motion. 

Thirdly, the fact is evident above all in the case of animate 
beings: for it sometimes happens that there is no motion in us 
and we are quite still, and that nevertheless we are then at 
some moment set in motion, that is to say it sometimes 
happens that we produce a beginning of motion in ourselves 
spontaneously without anything having set us in motion from 
without. We see nothing like this in the case of inanimate 



804 



things, which are always set in motion by something else from 
without: the animal, on the other hand, we say, moves itself: 
therefore, if an animal is ever in a state of absolute rest, we have 
a motionless thing in which motion can be produced from the 
thing itself, and not from without. Now if this can occur in an 
animal, why should not the same be true also of the universe as 
a whole? If it can occur in a small world it could also occur in a 
great one: and if it can occur in the world, it could also occur in 
the infinite; that is, if the infinite could as a whole possibly be in 
motion or at rest. 

Of these objections, then, the first-mentioned motion to 
opposites is not always the same and numerically one a correct 
statement; in fact, this may be said to be a necessary 
conclusion, provided that it is possible for the motion of that 
which is one and the same to be not always one and the same. 
(I mean that e.g. we may question whether the note given by a 
single string is one and the same, or is different each time the 
string is struck, although the string is in the same condition and 
is moved in the same way.) But still, however this may be, there 
is nothing to prevent there being a motion that is the same in 
virtue of being continuous and eternal: we shall have something 
to say later that will make this point clearer. 

As regards the second objection, no absurdity is involved in the 
fact that something not in motion may be set in motion, that 
which caused the motion from without being at one time 
present, and at another absent. Nevertheless, how this can be so 
remains matter for inquiry; how it comes about, I mean, that 
the same motive force at one time causes a thing to be in 
motion, and at another does not do so: for the difficulty raised 
by our objector really amounts to this - why is it that some 
things are not always at rest, and the rest always in motion? 



805 



The third objection may be thought to present more difficulty 
than the others, namely, that which alleges that motion arises 
in things in which it did not exist before, and adduces in proof 
the case of animate things: thus an animal is first at rest and 
afterwards walks, not having been set in motion apparently by 
anything from without. This, however, is false: for we observe 
that there is always some part of the animal's organism in 
motion, and the cause of the motion of this part is not the 
animal itself, but, it may be, its environment. Moreover, we say 
that the animal itself originates not all of its motions but its 
locomotion. So it may well be the case - or rather we may 
perhaps say that it must necessarily be the case - that many 
motions are produced in the body by its environment, and some 
of these set in motion the intellect or the appetite, and this 
again then sets the whole animal in motion: this is what 
happens when animals are asleep: though there is then no 
perceptive motion in them, there is some motion that causes 
them to wake up again. But we will leave this point also to be 
elucidated at a later stage in our discussion. 



Our enquiry will resolve itself at the outset into a consideration 
of the above-mentioned problem - what can be the reason why 
some things in the world at one time are in motion and at 
another are at rest again? Now one of three things must be true: 
either all things are always at rest, or all things are always in 
motion, or some things are in motion and others at rest: and in 
this last case again either the things that are in motion are 
always in motion and the things that are at rest are always at 
rest, or they are all constituted so as to be capable alike of 
motion and of rest; or there is yet a third possibility remaining - 



806 



it may be that some things in the world are always motionless, 
others always in motion, while others again admit of both 
conditions. This last is the account of the matter that we must 
give: for herein lies the solution of all the difficulties raised and 
the conclusion of the investigation upon which we are engaged. 

To maintain that all things are at rest, and to disregard sense- 
perception in an attempt to show the theory to be reasonable, 
would be an instance of intellectual weakness: it would call in 
question a whole system, not a particular detail: moreover, it 
would be an attack not only on the physicist but on almost all 
sciences and all received opinions, since motion plays a part in 
all of them. Further, just as in arguments about mathematics 
objections that involve first principles do not affect the 
mathematician - and the other sciences are in similar case - so, 
too, objections involving the point that we have just raised do 
not affect the physicist: for it is a fundamental assumption with 
him that motion is ultimately referable to nature herself. 

The assertion that all things are in motion we may fairly regard 
as equally false, though it is less subversive of physical science: 
for though in our course on physics it was laid down that rest 
no less than motion is ultimately referable to nature herself, 
nevertheless motion is the characteristic fact of nature: 
moreover, the view is actually held by some that not merely 
some things but all things in the world are in motion and 
always in motion, though we cannot apprehend the fact by 
sense-perception. Although the supporters of this theory do not 
state clearly what kind of motion they mean, or whether they 
mean all kinds, it is no hard matter to reply to them: thus we 
may point out that there cannot be a continuous process either 
of increase or of decrease: that which comes between the two 
has to be included. The theory resembles that about the stone 
being worn away by the drop of water or split by plants growing 
out of it: if so much has been extruded or removed by the drop, 



807 



it does not follow that half the amount has previously been 
extruded or removed in half the time: the case of the hauled 
ship is exactly comparable: here we have so many drops setting 
so much in motion, but a part of them will not set as much in 
motion in any period of time. The amount removed is, it is true, 
divisible into a number of parts, but no one of these was set in 
motion separately: they were all set in motion together. It is 
evident, then, that from the fact that the decrease is divisible 
into an infinite number of parts it does not follow that some 
part must always be passing away: it all passes away at a 
particular moment. Similarly, too, in the case of any alteration 
whatever if that which suffers alteration is infinitely divisible it 
does not follow from this that the same is true of the alteration 
itself, which often occurs all at once, as in freezing. Again, when 
any one has fallen ill, there must follow a period of time in 
which his restoration to health is in the future: the process of 
change cannot take place in an instant: yet the change cannot 
be a change to anything else but health. The assertion, 
therefore, that alteration is continuous is an extravagant calling 
into question of the obvious: for alteration is a change from one 
contrary to another. Moreover, we notice that a stone becomes 
neither harder nor softer. Again, in the matter of locomotion, it 
would be a strange thing if a stone could be falling or resting on 
the ground without our being able to perceive the fact. Further, 
it is a law of nature that earth and all other bodies should 
remain in their proper places and be moved from them only by 
violence: from the fact then that some of them are in their 
proper places it follows that in respect of place also all things 
cannot be in motion. These and other similar arguments, then, 
should convince us that it is impossible either that all things are 
always in motion or that all things are always at rest. 

Nor again can it be that some things are always at rest, others 
always in motion, and nothing sometimes at rest and 
sometimes in motion. This theory must be pronounced 



808 



impossible on the same grounds as those previously mentioned: 
viz. that we see the above-mentioned changes occurring in the 
case of the same things. We may further point out that the 
defender of this position is fighting against the obvious, for on 
this theory there can be no such thing as increase: nor can there 
be any such thing as compulsory motion, if it is impossible that 
a thing can be at rest before being set in motion unnaturally. 
This theory, then, does away with becoming and perishing. 
Moreover, motion, it would seem, is generally thought to be a 
sort of becoming and perishing, for that to which a thing 
changes comes to be, or occupancy of it comes to be, and that 
from which a thing changes ceases to be, or there ceases to be 
occupancy of it. It is clear, therefore, that there are cases of 
occasional motion and occasional rest. 

We have now to take the assertion that all things are sometimes 
at rest and sometimes in motion and to confront it with the 
arguments previously advanced. We must take our start as 
before from the possibilities that we distinguished just above. 
Either all things are at rest, or all things are in motion, or some 
things are at rest and others in motion. And if some things are 
at rest and others in motion, then it must be that either all 
things are sometimes at rest and sometimes in motion, or some 
things are always at rest and the remainder always in motion, 
or some of the things are always at rest and others always in 
motion while others again are sometimes at rest and 
sometimes in motion. Now we have said before that it is 
impossible that all things should be at rest: nevertheless we 
may now repeat that assertion. We may point out that, even if it 
is really the case, as certain persons assert, that the existent is 
infinite and motionless, it certainly does not appear to be so if 
we follow sense-perception: many things that exist appear to be 
in motion. Now if there is such a thing as false opinion or 
opinion at all, there is also motion; and similarly if there is such 
a thing as imagination, or if it is the case that anything seems to 



809 



be different at different times: for imagination and opinion are 
thought to be motions of a kind. But to investigate this question 
at all - to seek a reasoned justification of a belief with regard to 
which we are too well off to require reasoned justification - 
implies bad judgement of what is better and what is worse, 
what commends itself to belief and what does not, what is 
ultimate and what is not. It is likewise impossible that all things 
should be in motion or that some things should be always in 
motion and the remainder always at rest. We have sufficient 
ground for rejecting all these theories in the single fact that we 
see some things that are sometimes in motion and sometimes 
at rest. It is evident, therefore, that it is no less impossible that 
some things should be always in motion and the remainder 
always at rest than that all things should be at rest or that all 
things should be in motion continuously. It remains, then, to 
consider whether all things are so constituted as to be capable 
both of being in motion and of being at rest, or whether, while 
some things are so constituted, some are always at rest and 
some are always in motion: for it is this last view that we have 
to show to be true. 



Now of things that cause motion or suffer motion, to some the 
motion is accidental, to others essential: thus it is accidental to 
what merely belongs to or contains as a part a thing that causes 
motion or suffers motion, essential to a thing that causes 
motion or suffers motion not merely by belonging to such a 
thing or containing it as a part. 

Of things to which the motion is essential some derive their 
motion from themselves, others from something else: and in 



810 



some cases their motion is natural, in others violent and 
unnatural. Thus in things that derive their motion from 
themselves, e.g. all animals, the motion is natural (for when an 
animal is in motion its motion is derived from itself): and 
whenever the source of the motion of a thing is in the thing 
itself we say that the motion of that thing is natural. Therefore 
the animal as a whole moves itself naturally: but the body of 
the animal may be in motion unnaturally as well as naturally: it 
depends upon the kind of motion that it may chance to be 
suffering and the kind of element of which it is composed. And 
the motion of things that derive their motion from something 
else is in some cases natural, in other unnatural: e.g. upward 
motion of earthy things and downward motion of fire are 
unnatural. Moreover the parts of animals are often in motion in 
an unnatural way, their positions and the character of the 
motion being abnormal. The fact that a thing that is in motion 
derives its motion from something is most evident in things 
that are in motion unnaturally, because in such cases it is clear 
that the motion is derived from something other than the thing 
itself. Next to things that are in motion unnaturally those 
whose motion while natural is derived from themselves - e.g. 
animals - make this fact clear: for here the uncertainty is not as 
to whether the motion is derived from something but as to how 
we ought to distinguish in the thing between the movent and 
the moved. It would seem that in animals, just as in ships and 
things not naturally organized, that which causes motion is 
separate from that which suffers motion, and that it is only in 
this sense that the animal as a whole causes its own motion. 

The greatest difficulty, however, is presented by the remaining 
case of those that we last distinguished. Where things derive 
their motion from something else we distinguished the cases in 
which the motion is unnatural: we are left with those that are 
to be contrasted with the others by reason of the fact that the 
motion is natural. It is in these cases that difficulty would be 



811 



experienced in deciding whence the motion is derived, e.g. in 
the case of light and heavy things. When these things are in 
motion to positions the reverse of those they would properly 
occupy, their motion is violent: when they are in motion to their 
proper positions - the light thing up and the heavy thing down - 
their motion is natural; but in this latter case it is no longer 
evident, as it is when the motion is unnatural, whence their 
motion is derived. It is impossible to say that their motion is 
derived from themselves: this is a characteristic of life and 
peculiar to living things. Further, if it were, it would have been 
in their power to stop themselves (I mean that if e.g. a thing can 
cause itself to walk it can also cause itself not to walk), and so, 
since on this supposition fire itself possesses the power of 
upward locomotion, it is clear that it should also possess the 
power of downward locomotion. Moreover if things move 
themselves, it would be unreasonable to suppose that in only 
one kind of motion is their motion derived from themselves. 
Again, how can anything of continuous and naturally connected 
substance move itself? In so far as a thing is one and 
continuous not merely in virtue of contact, it is impassive: it is 
only in so far as a thing is divided that one part of it is by nature 
active and another passive. Therefore none of the things that we 
are now considering move themselves (for they are of naturally 
connected substance), nor does anything else that is 
continuous: in each case the movent must be separate from the 
moved, as we see to be the case with inanimate things when an 
animate thing moves them. It is the fact that these things also 
always derive their motion from something: what it is would 
become evident if we were to distinguish the different kinds of 
cause. 

The above-mentioned distinctions can also be made in the case 
of things that cause motion: some of them are capable of 
causing motion unnaturally (e.g. the lever is not naturally 
capable of moving the weight), others naturally (e.g. what is 



812 



actually hot is naturally capable of moving what is potentially 
hot): and similarly in the case of all other things of this kind. 

In the same way, too, what is potentially of a certain quality or 
of a certain quantity in a certain place is naturally movable 
when it contains the corresponding principle in itself and not 
accidentally (for the same thing may be both of a certain quality 
and of a certain quantity, but the one is an accidental, not an 
essential property of the other). So when fire or earth is moved 
by something the motion is violent when it is unnatural, and 
natural when it brings to actuality the proper activities that 
they potentially possess. But the fact that the term 'potentially' 
is used in more than one sense is the reason why it is not 
evident whence such motions as the upward motion of fire and 
the downward motion of earth are derived. One who is learning 
a science potentially knows it in a different sense from one who 
while already possessing the knowledge is not actually 
exercising it. Wherever we have something capable of acting 
and something capable of being correspondingly acted on, in 
the event of any such pair being in contact what is potential 
becomes at times actual: e.g. the learner becomes from one 
potential something another potential something: for one who 
possesses knowledge of a science but is not actually exercising 
it knows the science potentially in a sense, though not in the 
same sense as he knew it potentially before he learnt it. And 
when he is in this condition, if something does not prevent him, 
he actively exercises his knowledge: otherwise he would be in 
the contradictory state of not knowing. In regard to natural 
bodies also the case is similar. Thus what is cold is potentially 
hot: then a change takes place and it is fire, and it burns, unless 
something prevents and hinders it. So, too, with heavy and 
light: light is generated from heavy, e.g. air from water (for 
water is the first thing that is potentially light), and air is 
actually light, and will at once realize its proper activity as such 
unless something prevents it. The activity of lightness consists 



813 



in the light thing being in a certain situation, namely high up: 
when it is in the contrary situation, it is being prevented from 
rising. The case is similar also in regard to quantity and quality. 
But, be it noted, this is the question we are trying to answer - 
how can we account for the motion of light things and heavy 
things to their proper situations? The reason for it is that they 
have a natural tendency respectively towards a certain position: 
and this constitutes the essence of lightness and heaviness, the 
former being determined by an upward, the latter by a 
downward, tendency. As we have said, a thing may be 
potentially light or heavy in more senses than one. Thus not 
only when a thing is water is it in a sense potentially light, but 
when it has become air it may be still potentially light: for it 
may be that through some hindrance it does not occupy an 
upper position, whereas, if what hinders it is removed, it 
realizes its activity and continues to rise higher. The process 
whereby what is of a certain quality changes to a condition of 
active existence is similar: thus the exercise of knowledge 
follows at once upon the possession of it unless something 
prevents it. So, too, what is of a certain quantity extends itself 
over a certain space unless something prevents it. The thing in a 
sense is and in a sense is not moved by one who moves what is 
obstructing and preventing its motion (e.g. one who pulls away 
a pillar from under a roof or one who removes a stone from a 
wineskin in the water is the accidental cause of motion): and in 
the same way the real cause of the motion of a ball rebounding 
from a wall is not the wall but the thrower. So it is clear that in 
all these cases the thing does not move itself, but it contains 
within itself the source of motion - not of moving something or 
of causing motion, but of suffering it. 

If then the motion of all things that are in motion is either 
natural or unnatural and violent, and all things whose motion is 
violent and unnatural are moved by something, and something 
other than themselves, and again all things whose motion is 



814 



natural are moved by something - both those that are moved by 
themselves and those that are not moved by themselves (e.g. 
light things and heavy things, which are moved either by that 
which brought the thing into existence as such and made it 
light and heavy, or by that which released what was hindering 
and preventing it); then all things that are in motion must be 
moved by something. 



Now this may come about in either of two ways. Either the 
movent is not itself responsible for the motion, which is to be 
referred to something else which moves the movent, or the 
movent is itself responsible for the motion. Further, in the latter 
case, either the movent immediately precedes the last thing in 
the series, or there may be one or more intermediate links: e.g. 
the stick moves the stone and is moved by the hand, which 
again is moved by the man: in the man, however, we have 
reached a movent that is not so in virtue of being moved by 
something else. Now we say that the thing is moved both by the 
last and by the first movent in the series, but more strictly by 
the first, since the first movent moves the last, whereas the last 
does not move the first, and the first will move the thing 
without the last, but the last will not move it without the first: 
e.g. the stick will not move anything unless it is itself moved by 
the man. If then everything that is in motion must be moved by 
something, and the movent must either itself be moved by 
something else or not, and in the former case there must be 
some first movent that is not itself moved by anything else, 
while in the case of the immediate movent being of this kind 
there is no need of an intermediate movent that is also moved 
(for it is impossible that there should be an infinite series of 



815 



movents, each of which is itself moved by something else, since 
in an infinite series there is no first term) - if then everything 
that is in motion is moved by something, and the first movent is 
moved but not by anything else, it much be moved by itself. 

This same argument may also be stated in another way as 
follows. Every movent moves something and moves it with 
something, either with itself or with something else: e.g. a man 
moves a thing either himself or with a stick, and a thing is 
knocked down either by the wind itself or by a stone propelled 
by the wind. But it is impossible for that with which a thing is 
moved to move it without being moved by that which imparts 
motion by its own agency: on the other hand, if a thing imparts 
motion by its own agency, it is not necessary that there should 
be anything else with which it imparts motion, whereas if there 
is a different thing with which it imparts motion, there must be 
something that imparts motion not with something else but 
with itself, or else there will be an infinite series. If, then, 
anything is a movent while being itself moved, the series must 
stop somewhere and not be infinite. Thus, if the stick moves 
something in virtue of being moved by the hand, the hand 
moves the stick: and if something else moves with the hand, 
the hand also is moved by something different from itself. So 
when motion by means of an instrument is at each stage 
caused by something different from the instrument, this must 
always be preceded by something else which imparts motion 
with itself. Therefore, if this last movent is in motion and there 
is nothing else that moves it, it must move itself. So this 
reasoning also shows that when a thing is moved, if it is not 
moved immediately by something that moves itself, the series 
brings us at some time or other to a movent of this kind. 

And if we consider the matter in yet a third wa Ly we shall get 
this same result as follows. If everything that is in motion is 
moved by something that is in motion, ether this being in 



816 



motion is an accidental attribute of the movents in question, so 
that each of them moves something while being itself in 
motion, but not always because it is itself in motion, or it is not 
accidental but an essential attribute. Let us consider the former 
alternative. If then it is an accidental attribute, it is not 
necessary that that is in motion should be in motion: and if this 
is so it is clear that there may be a time when nothing that 
exists is in motion, since the accidental is not necessary but 
contingent. Now if we assume the existence of a possibility, any 
conclusion that we thereby reach will not be an impossibility 
though it may be contrary to fact. But the nonexistence of 
motion is an impossibility: for we have shown above that there 
must always be motion. 

Moreover, the conclusion to which we have been led is a 
reasonable one. For there must be three things - the moved, the 
movent, and the instrument of motion. Now the moved must be 
in motion, but it need not move anything else: the instrument 
of motion must both move something else and be itself in 
motion (for it changes together with the moved, with which it is 
in contact and continuous, as is clear in the case of things that 
move other things locally, in which case the two things must up 
to a certain point be in contact): and the movent - that is to say, 
that which causes motion in such a manner that it is not 
merely the instrument of motion - must be unmoved. Now we 
have visual experience of the last term in this series, namely 
that which has the capacity of being in motion, but does not 
contain a motive principle, and also of that which is in motion 
but is moved by itself and not by anything else: it is reasonable, 
therefore, not to say necessary, to suppose the existence of the 
third term also, that which causes motion but is itself unmoved. 
So, too, Anaxagoras is right when he says that Mind is impassive 
and unmixed, since he makes it the principle of motion: for it 
could cause motion in this sense only by being itself unmoved, 
and have supreme control only by being unmixed. 



817 



We will now take the second alternative. If the movement is not 
accidentally but necessarily in motion - so that, if it were not in 
motion, it would not move anything - then the movent, in so far 
as it is in motion, must be in motion in one of two ways: it is 
moved either as that is which is moved with the same kind of 
motion, or with a different kind - either that which is heating, I 
mean, is itself in process of becoming hot, that which is making 
healthy in process of becoming healthy, and that which is 
causing locomotion in process of locomotion, or else that which 
is making healthy is, let us say, in process of locomotion, and 
that which is causing locomotion in process of, say, increase. 
But it is evident that this is impossible. For if we adopt the first 
assumption we have to make it apply within each of the very 
lowest species into which motion can be divided: e.g. we must 
say that if some one is teaching some lesson in geometry, he is 
also in process of being taught that same lesson in geometry, 
and that if he is throwing he is in process of being thrown in 
just the same manner. Or if we reject this assumption we must 
say that one kind of motion is derived from another; e.g. that 
that which is causing locomotion is in process of increase, that 
which is causing this increase is in process of being altered by 
something else, and that which is causing this alteration is in 
process of suffering some different kind of motion. But the 
series must stop somewhere, since the kinds of motion are 
limited; and if we say that the process is reversible, and that 
that which is causing alteration is in process of locomotion, we 
do no more than if we had said at the outset that that which is 
causing locomotion is in process of locomotion, and that one 
who is teaching is in process of being taught: for it is clear that 
everything that is moved is moved by the movent that is further 
back in the series as well as by that which immediately moves 
it: in fact the earlier movent is that which more strictly moves 
it. But this is of course impossible: for it involves the 
consequence that one who is teaching is in process of learning 



818 



what he is teaching, whereas teaching necessarily implies 
possessing knowledge, and learning not possessing it. Still more 
unreasonable is the consequence involved that, since 
everything that is moved is moved by something that is itself 
moved by something else, everything that has a capacity for 
causing motion has as such a corresponding capacity for being 
moved: i.e. it will have a capacity for being moved in the sense 
in which one might say that everything that has a capacity for 
making healthy, and exercises that capacity, has as such a 
capacity for being made healthy, and that which has a capacity 
for building has as such a capacity for being built. It will have 
the capacity for being thus moved either immediately or 
through one or more links (as it will if, while everything that 
has a capacity for causing motion has as such a capacity for 
being moved by something else, the motion that it has the 
capacity for suffering is not that with which it affects what is 
next to it, but a motion of a different kind; e.g. that which has a 
capacity for making healthy might as such have a capacity for 
learn, the series, however, could be traced back, as we said 
before, until at some time or other we arrived at the same kind 
of motion). Now the first alternative is impossible, and the 
second is fantastic: it is absurd that that which has a capacity 
for causing alteration should as such necessarily have a 
capacity, let us say, for increase. It is not necessary, therefore, 
that that which is moved should always be moved by something 
else that is itself moved by something else: so there will be an 
end to the series. Consequently the first thing that is in motion 
will derive its motion either from something that is at rest or 
from itself. But if there were any need to consider which of the 
two, that which moves itself or that which is moved by 
something else, is the cause and principle of motion, every one 
would decide the former: for that which is itself independently 
a cause is always prior as a cause to that which is so only in 



819 



virtue of being itself dependent upon something else that 
makes it so. 

We must therefore make a fresh start and consider the 
question; if a thing moves itself, in what sense and in what 
manner does it do so? Now everything that is in motion must be 
infinitely divisible, for it has been shown already in our general 
course on Physics, that everything that is essentially in motion 
is continuous. Now it is impossible that that which moves itself 
should in its entirety move itself: for then, while being 
specifically one and indivisible, it would as a Whole both 
undergo and cause the same locomotion or alteration: thus it 
would at the same time be both teaching and being taught (the 
same thing), or both restoring to and being restored to the same 
health. Moreover, we have established the fact that it is the 
movable that is moved; and this is potentially, not actually, in 
motion, but the potential is in process to actuality, and motion 
is an incomplete actuality of the movable. The movent on the 
other hand is already in activity: e.g. it is that which is hot that 
produces heat: in fact, that which produces the form is always 
something that possesses it. Consequently (if a thing can move 
itself as a whole), the same thing in respect of the same thing 
may be at the same time both hot and not hot. So, too, in every 
other case where the movent must be described by the same 
name in the same sense as the moved. Therefore when a thing 
moves itself it is one part of it that is the movent and another 
part that is moved. But it is not self-moving in the sense that 
each of the two parts is moved by the other part: the following 
considerations make this evident. In the first place, if each of 
the two parts is to move the other, there will be no first movent. 
If a thing is moved by a series of movents, that which is earlier 
in the series is more the cause of its being moved than that 
which comes next, and will be more truly the movent: for we 
found that there are two kinds of movent, that which is itself 
moved by something else and that which derives its motion 



820 



from itself: and that which is further from the thing that is 
moved is nearer to the principle of motion than that which is 
intermediate. In the second place, there is no necessity for the 
movent part to be moved by anything but itself: so it can only be 
accidentally that the other part moves it in return. I take then 
the possible case of its not moving it: then there will be a part 
that is moved and a part that is an unmoved movent. In the 
third place, there is no necessity for the movent to be moved in 
return: on the contrary the necessity that there should always 
be motion makes it necessary that there should be some 
movent that is either unmoved or moved by itself. In the fourth 
place we should then have a thing undergoing the same motion 
that it is causing - that which is producing heat, therefore, being 
heated. But as a matter of fact that which primarily moves itself 
cannot contain either a single part that moves itself or a 
number of parts each of which moves itself. For, if the whole is 
moved by itself, it must be moved either by some part of itself 
or as a whole by itself as a whole. If, then, it is moved in virtue 
of some part of it being moved by that part itself, it is this part 
that will be the primary self-movent, since, if this part is 
separated from the whole, the part will still move itself, but the 
whole will do so no longer. If on the other hand the whole is 
moved by itself as a whole, it must be accidentally that the parts 
move themselves: and therefore, their self-motion not being 
necessary, we may take the case of their not being moved by 
themselves. Therefore in the whole of the thing we may 
distinguish that which imparts motion without itself being 
moved and that which is moved: for only in this way is it 
possible for a thing to be self-moved. Further, if the whole 
moves itself we may distinguish in it that which imparts the 
motion and that which is moved: so while we say that AB is 
moved by itself, we may also say that it is moved by A. And 
since that which imparts motion may be either a thing that is 
moved by something else or a thing that is unmoved, and that 



821 



which is moved may be either a thing that imparts motion to 
something else or a thing that does not, that which moves itself 
must be composed of something that is unmoved but imparts 
motion and also of something that is moved but does not 
necessarily impart motion but may or may not do so. Thus let A 
be something that imparts motion but is unmoved, B something 
that is moved by A and moves G, G something that is moved by 
B but moves nothing (granted that we eventually arrive at G we 
may take it that there is only one intermediate term, though 
there may be more). Then the whole ABG moves itself. But if I 
take away G, AB will move itself, A imparting motion and B 
being moved, whereas G will not move itself or in fact be moved 
at all. Nor again will BG move itself apart from A: for B imparts 
motion only through being moved by something else, not 
through being moved by any part of itself. So only AB moves 
itself. That which moves itself, therefore, must comprise 
something that imparts motion but is unmoved and something 
that is moved but does not necessarily move anything else: and 
each of these two things, or at any rate one of them, must be in 
contact with the other. If, then, that which imparts motion is a 
continuous substance - that which is moved must of course be 
so - it is clear that it is not through some part of the whole 
being of such a nature as to be capable of moving itself that the 
whole moves itself: it moves itself as a whole, both being moved 
and imparting motion through containing a part that imparts 
motion and a part that is moved. It does not impart motion as a 
whole nor is it moved as a whole: it is A alone that imparts 
motion and B alone that is moved. It is not true, further, that G 
is moved by A, which is impossible. 

Here a difficulty arises: if something is taken away from A 
(supposing that that which imparts motion but is unmoved is a 
continuous substance), or from B the part that is moved, will the 
remainder of A continue to impart motion or the remainder of B 
continue to be moved? If so, it will not be AB primarily that is 



822 



moved by itself, since, when something is taken away from AB, 
the remainder of AB will still continue to move itself. Perhaps 
we may state the case thus: there is nothing to prevent each of 
the two parts, or at any rate one of them, that which is moved, 
being divisible though actually undivided, so that if it is divided 
it will not continue in the possession of the same capacity: and 
so there is nothing to prevent self-motion residing primarily in 
things that are potentially divisible. 

From what has been said, then, it is evident that that which 
primarily imparts motion is unmoved: for, whether the series is 
closed at once by that which is in motion but moved by 
something else deriving its motion directly from the first 
unmoved, or whether the motion is derived from what is in 
motion but moves itself and stops its own motion, on both 
suppositions we have the result that in all cases of things being 
in motion that which primarily imparts motion is unmoved. 



Since there must always be motion without intermission, there 
must necessarily be something, one thing or it may be a 
plurality, that first imparts motion, and this first movent must 
be unmoved. Now the question whether each of the things that 
are unmoved but impart motion is eternal is irrelevant to our 
present argument: but the following considerations will make it 
clear that there must necessarily be some such thing, which, 
while it has the capacity of moving something else, is itself 
unmoved and exempt from all change, which can affect it 
neither in an unqualified nor in an accidental sense. Let us 
suppose, if any one likes, that in the case of certain things it is 
possible for them at different times to be and not to be, without 



823 



any process of becoming and perishing (in fact it would seem to 
be necessary, if a thing that has not parts at one time is and at 
another time is not, that any such thing should without 
undergoing any process of change at one time be and at another 
time not be). And let us further suppose it possible that some 
principles that are unmoved but capable of imparting motion at 
one time are and at another time are not. Even so, this cannot 
be true of all such principles, since there must clearly be 
something that causes things that move themselves at one time 
to be and at another not to be. For, since nothing that has not 
parts can be in motion, that which moves itself must as a whole 
have magnitude, though nothing that we have said makes this 
necessarily true of every movent. So the fact that some things 
become and others perish, and that this is so continuously, 
cannot be caused by any one of those things that, though they 
are unmoved, do not always exist: nor again can it be caused by 
any of those which move certain particular things, while others 
move other things. The eternity and continuity of the process 
cannot be caused either by any one of them singly or by the 
sum of them, because this causal relation must be eternal and 
necessary, whereas the sum of these movents is infinite and 
they do not all exist together. It is clear, then, that though there 
may be countless instances of the perishing of some principles 
that are unmoved but impart motion, and though many things 
that move themselves perish and are succeeded by others that 
come into being, and though one thing that is unmoved moves 
one thing while another moves another, nevertheless there is 
something that comprehends them all, and that as something 
apart from each one of them, and this it is that is the cause of 
the fact that some things are and others are not and of the 
continuous process of change: and this causes the motion of 
the other movents, while they are the causes of the motion of 
other things. Motion, then, being eternal, the first movent, if 
there is but one, will be eternal also: if there are more than one, 



824 



there will be a plurality of such eternal movents. We ought, 
however, to suppose that there is one rather than many, and a 
finite rather than an infinite number. When the consequences 
of either assumption are the same, we should always assume 
that things are finite rather than infinite in number, since in 
things constituted by nature that which is finite and that which 
is better ought, if possible, to be present rather than the reverse: 
and here it is sufficient to assume only one movent, the first of 
unmoved things, which being eternal will be the principle of 
motion to everything else. 

The following argument also makes it evident that the first 
movent must be something that is one and eternal. We have 
shown that there must always be motion. That being so, motion 
must also be continuous, because what is always is continuous, 
whereas what is merely in succession is not continuous. But 
further, if motion is continuous, it is one: and it is one only if 
the movent and the moved that constitute it are each of them 
one, since in the event of a thing's being moved now by one 
thing and now by another the whole motion will not be 
continuous but successive. 

Moreover a conviction that there is a first unmoved something 
may be reached not only from the foregoing arguments, but also 
by considering again the principles operative in movents. Now it 
is evident that among existing things there are some that are 
sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest. This fact has 
served above to make it clear that it is not true either that all 
things are in motion or that all things are at rest or that some 
things are always at rest and the remainder always in motion: 
on this matter proof is supplied by things that fluctuate 
between the two and have the capacity of being sometimes in 
motion and sometimes at rest. The existence of things of this 
kind is clear to all: but we wish to explain also the nature of 
each of the other two kinds and show that there are some 



825 



things that are always unmoved and some things that are 
always in motion. In the course of our argument directed to this 
end we established the fact that everything that is in motion is 
moved by something, and that the movent is either unmoved or 
in motion, and that, if it is in motion, it is moved either by itself 
or by something else and so on throughout the series: and so we 
proceeded to the position that the first principle that directly 
causes things that are in motion to be moved is that which 
moves itself, and the first principle of the whole series is the 
unmoved. Further it is evident from actual observation that 
there are things that have the characteristic of moving 
themselves, e.g. the animal kingdom and the whole class of 
living things. This being so, then, the view was suggested that 
perhaps it may be possible for motion to come to be in a thing 
without having been in existence at all before, because we see 
this actually occurring in animals: they are unmoved at one 
time and then again they are in motion, as it seems. We must 
grasp the fact, therefore, that animals move themselves only 
with one kind of motion, and that this is not strictly originated 
by them. The cause of it is not derived from the animal itself: it 
is connected with other natural motions in animals, which they 
do not experience through their own instrumentality, e.g. 
increase, decrease, and respiration: these are experienced by 
every animal while it is at rest and not in motion in respect of 
the motion set up by its own agency: here the motion is caused 
by the atmosphere and by many things that enter into the 
animal: thus in some cases the cause is nourishment: when it is 
being digested animals sleep, and when it is being distributed 
through the system they awake and move themselves, the first 
principle of this motion being thus originally derived from 
outside. Therefore animals are not always in continuous motion 
by their own agency: it is something else that moves them, itself 
being in motion and changing as it comes into relation with 
each several thing that moves itself. (Moreover in all these self- 



826 



moving things the first movent and cause of their self-motion is 
itself moved by itself, though in an accidental sense: that is to 
say, the body changes its place, so that that which is in the body 
changes its place also and is a self-movent through its exercise 
of leverage.) Hence we may confidently conclude that if a thing 
belongs to the class of unmoved movents that are also 
themselves moved accidentally, it is impossible that it should 
cause continuous motion. So the necessity that there should be 
motion continuously requires that there should be a first 
movent that is unmoved even accidentally, if, as we have said, 
there is to be in the world of things an unceasing and undying 
motion, and the world is to remain permanently self-contained 
and within the same limits: for if the first principle is 
permanent, the universe must also be permanent, since it is 
continuous with the first principle. (We must distinguish, 
however, between accidental motion of a thing by itself and 
such motion by something else, the former being confined to 
perishable things, whereas the latter belongs also to certain first 
principles of heavenly bodies, of all those, that is to say, that 
experience more than one locomotion.) 

And further, if there is always something of this nature, a 
movent that is itself unmoved and eternal, then that which is 
first moved by it must be eternal. Indeed this is clear also from 
the consideration that there would otherwise be no becoming 
and perishing and no change of any kind in other things, which 
require something that is in motion to move them: for the 
motion imparted by the unmoved will always be imparted in 
the same way and be one and the same, since the unmoved 
does not itself change in relation to that which is moved by it. 
But that which is moved by something that, though it is in 
motion, is moved directly by the unmoved stands in varying 
relations to the things that it moves, so that the motion that it 
causes will not be always the same: by reason of the fact that it 
occupies contrary positions or assumes contrary forms at 



827 



different times it will produce contrary motions in each several 
thing that it moves and will cause it to be at one time at rest 
and at another time in motion. 

The foregoing argument, then, has served to clear up the point 
about which we raised a difficulty at the outset - why is it that 
instead of all things being either in motion or at rest, or some 
things being always in motion and the remainder always at rest, 
there are things that are sometimes in motion and sometimes 
not? The cause of this is now plain: it is because, while some 
things are moved by an eternal unmoved movent and are 
therefore always in motion, other things are moved by a movent 
that is in motion and changing, so that they too must change. 
But the unmoved movent, as has been said, since it remains 
permanently simple and unvarying and in the same state, will 
cause motion that is one and simple. 



This matter will be made clearer, however, if we start afresh 
from another point. We must consider whether it is or is not 
possible that there should be a continuous motion, and, if it is 
possible, which this motion is, and which is the primary motion: 
for it is plain that if there must always be motion, and a 
particular motion is primary and continuous, then it is this 
motion that is imparted by the first movent, and so it is 
necessarily one and the same and continuous and primary. 

Now of the three kinds of motion that there are - motion in 
respect of magnitude, motion in respect of affection, and 
motion in respect of place - it is this last, which we call 
locomotion, that must be primary. This may be shown as 
follows. It is impossible that there should be increase without 



828 



the previous occurrence of alteration: for that which is 
increased, although in a sense it is increased by what is like 
itself, is in a sense increased by what is unlike itself: thus it is 
said that contrary is nourishment to contrary: but growth is 
effected only by things becoming like to like. There must be 
alteration, then, in that there is this change from contrary to 
contrary. But the fact that a thing is altered requires that there 
should be something that alters it, something e.g. that makes 
the potentially hot into the actually hot: so it is plain that the 
movent does not maintain a uniform relation to it but is at one 
time nearer to and at another farther from that which is altered: 
and we cannot have this without locomotion. If, therefore, there 
must always be motion, there must also always be locomotion 
as the primary motion, and, if there is a primary as 
distinguished from a secondary form of locomotion, it must be 
the primary form. Again, all affections have their origin in 
condensation and rarefaction: thus heavy and light, soft and 
hard, hot and cold, are considered to be forms of density and 
rarity. But condensation and rarefaction are nothing more than 
combination and separation, processes in accordance with 
which substances are said to become and perish: and in being 
combined and separated things must change in respect of place. 
And further, when a thing is increased or decreased its 
magnitude changes in respect of place. 

Again, there is another point of view from which it will be 
clearly seen that locomotion is primary. As in the case of other 
things so too in the case of motion the word 'primary' may be 
used in several senses. A thing is said to be prior to other things 
when, if it does not exist, the others will not exist, whereas it 
can exist without the others: and there is also priority in time 
and priority in perfection of existence. Let us begin, then, with 
the first sense. Now there must be motion continuously, and 
there may be continuously either continuous motion or 
successive motion, the former, however, in a higher degree than 



829 



the latter: moreover it is better that it should be continuous 
rather than successive motion, and we always assume the 
presence in nature of the better, if it be possible: since, then, 
continuous motion is possible (this will be proved later: for the 
present let us take it for granted), and no other motion can be 
continuous except locomotion, locomotion must be primary. For 
there is no necessity for the subject of locomotion to be the 
subject either of increase or of alteration, nor need it become or 
perish: on the other hand there cannot be any one of these 
processes without the existence of the continuous motion 
imparted by the first movent. 

Secondly, locomotion must be primary in time: for this is the 
only motion possible for things. It is true indeed that, in the 
case of any individual thing that has a becoming, locomotion 
must be the last of its motions: for after its becoming it first 
experiences alteration and increase, and locomotion is a motion 
that belongs to such things only when they are perfected. But 
there must previously be something else that is in process of 
locomotion to be the cause even of the becoming of things that 
become, without itself being in process of becoming, as e.g. the 
begotten is preceded by what begot it: otherwise becoming 
might be thought to be the primary motion on the ground that 
the thing must first become. But though this is so in the case of 
any individual thing that becomes, nevertheless before anything 
becomes, something else must be in motion, not itself 
becoming but being, and before this there must again be 
something else. And since becoming cannot be primary - for, if 
it were, everything that is in motion would be perishable - it is 
plain that no one of the motions next in order can be prior to 
locomotion. By the motions next in order I mean increase and 
then alteration, decrease, and perishing. All these are posterior 
to becoming: consequently, if not even becoming is prior to 
locomotion, then no one of the other processes of change is so 
either. 



830 



Thirdly, that which is in process of becoming appears 
universally as something imperfect and proceeding to a first 
principle: and so what is posterior in the order of becoming is 
prior in the order of nature. Now all things that go through the 
process of becoming acquire locomotion last. It is this that 
accounts for the fact that some living things, e.g. plants and 
many kinds of animals, owing to lack of the requisite organ, are 
entirely without motion, whereas others acquire it in the course 
of their being perfected. Therefore, if the degree in which things 
possess locomotion corresponds to the degree in which they 
have realized their natural development, then this motion must 
be prior to all others in respect of perfection of existence: and 
not only for this reason but also because a thing that is in 
motion loses its essential character less in the process of 
locomotion than in any other kind of motion: it is the only 
motion that does not involve a change of being in the sense in 
which there is a change in quality when a thing is altered and a 
change in quantity when a thing is increased or decreased. 
Above all it is plain that this motion, motion in respect of place, 
is what is in the strictest sense produced by that which moves 
itself; but it is the self-movent that we declare to be the first 
principle of things that are moved and impart motion and the 
primary source to which things that are in motion are to be 
referred. 

It is clear, then, from the foregoing arguments that locomotion 
is the primary motion. We have now to show which kind of 
locomotion is primary. The same process of reasoning will also 
make clear at the same time the truth of the assumption we 
have made both now and at a previous stage that it is possible 
that there should be a motion that is continuous and eternal. 
Now it is clear from the following considerations that no other 
than locomotion can be continuous. Every other motion and 
change is from an opposite to an opposite: thus for the 
processes of becoming and perishing the limits are the existent 



831 



and the non-existent, for alteration the various pairs of contrary 
affections, and for increase and decrease either greatness and 
smallness or perfection and imperfection of magnitude: and 
changes to the respective contraries are contrary changes. Now 
a thing that is undergoing any particular kind of motion, but 
though previously existent has not always undergone it, must 
previously have been at rest so far as that motion is concerned. 
It is clear, then, that for the changing thing the contraries will 
be states of rest. And we have a similar result in the case of 
changes that are not motions: for becoming and perishing, 
whether regarded simply as such without qualification or as 
affecting something in particular, are opposites: therefore 
provided it is impossible for a thing to undergo opposite 
changes at the same time, the change will not be continuous, 
but a period of time will intervene between the opposite 
processes. The question whether these contradictory changes 
are contraries or not makes no difference, provided only it is 
impossible for them both to be present to the same thing at the 
same time: the point is of no importance to the argument. Nor 
does it matter if the thing need not rest in the contradictory 
state, or if there is no state of rest as a contrary to the process of 
change: it may be true that the non-existent is not at rest, and 
that perishing is a process to the non-existent. All that matters 
is the intervention of a time: it is this that prevents the change 
from being continuous: so, too, in our previous instances the 
important thing was not the relation of contrariety but the 
impossibility of the two processes being present to a thing at 
the same time. And there is no need to be disturbed by the fact 
that on this showing there may be more than one contrary to 
the same thing, that a particular motion will be contrary both to 
rest and to motion in the contrary direction. We have only to 
grasp the fact that a particular motion is in a sense the opposite 
both of a state of rest and of the contrary motion, in the same 
way as that which is of equal or standard measure is the 



832 



opposite both of that which surpasses it and of that which it 
surpasses, and that it is impossible for the opposite motions or 
changes to be present to a thing at the same time. Furthermore, 
in the case of becoming and perishing it would seem to be an 
utterly absurd thing if as soon as anything has become it must 
necessarily perish and cannot continue to exist for any time: 
and, if this is true of becoming and perishing, we have fair 
grounds for inferring the same to be true of the other kinds of 
change, since it would be in the natural order of things that they 
should be uniform in this respect. 



8 

Let us now proceed to maintain that it is possible that there 
should be an infinite motion that is single and continuous, and 
that this motion is rotatory motion. The motion of everything 
that is in process of locomotion is either rotatory or rectilinear 
or a compound of the two: consequently, if one of the former 
two is not continuous, that which is composed of them both 
cannot be continuous either. Now it is plain that if the 
locomotion of a thing is rectilinear and finite it is not 
continuous locomotion: for the thing must turn back, and that 
which turns back in a straight line undergoes two contrary 
locomotions, since, so far as motion in respect of place is 
concerned, upward motion is the contrary of downward motion, 
forward motion of backward motion, and motion to the left of 
motion to the right, these being the pairs of contraries in the 
sphere of place. But we have already defined single and 
continuous motion to be motion of a single thing in a single 
period of time and operating within a sphere admitting of no 
further specific differentiation (for we have three things to 
consider, first that which is in motion, e.g. a man or a god, 



833 



secondly the 'when' of the motion, that is to say, the time, and 
thirdly the sphere within which it operates, which may be 
either place or affection or essential form or magnitude): and 
contraries are specifically not one and the same but distinct: 
and within the sphere of place we have the above-mentioned 
distinctions. Moreover we have an indication that motion from 
A to B is the contrary of motion from B to A in the fact that, if 
they occur at the same time, they arrest and stop each other. 
And the same is true in the case of a circle: the motion from A 
towards B is the contrary of the motion from A towards G: for 
even if they are continuous and there is no turning back they 
arrest each other, because contraries annihilate or obstruct one 
another. On the other hand lateral motion is not the contrary of 
upward motion. But what shows most clearly that rectilinear 
motion cannot be continuous is the fact that turning back 
necessarily implies coming to a stand, not only when it is a 
straight line that is traversed, but also in the case of locomotion 
in a circle (which is not the same thing as rotatory locomotion: 
for, when a thing merely traverses a circle, it may either proceed 
on its course without a break or turn back again when it has 
reached the same point from which it started). We may assure 
ourselves of the necessity of this coming to a stand not only on 
the strength of observation, but also on theoretical grounds. We 
may start as follows: we have three points, starting-point, 
middle-point, and finishing-point, of which the middle-point in 
virtue of the relations in which it stands severally to the other 
two is both a starting-point and a finishing-point, and though 
numerically one is theoretically two. We have further the 
distinction between the potential and the actual. So in the 
straight line in question any one of the points lying between the 
two extremes is potentially a middle-point: but it is not actually 
so unless that which is in motion divides the line by coming to 
a stand at that point and beginning its motion again: thus the 
middle-point becomes both a starting-point and a goal, the 



834 



starting-point of the latter part and the finishing-point of the 
first part of the motion. This is the case e.g. when A in the 
course of its locomotion comes to a stand at B and starts again 
towards G: but when its motion is continuous A cannot either 
have come to be or have ceased to be at the point B: it can only 
have been there at the moment of passing, its passage not being 
contained within any period of time except the whole of which 
the particular moment is a dividing-point. To maintain that it 
has come to be and ceased to be there will involve the 
consequence that A in the course of its locomotion will always 
be coming to a stand: for it is impossible that A should 
simultaneously have come to be at B and ceased to be there, so 
that the two things must have happened at different points of 
time, and therefore there will be the intervening period of time: 
consequently A will be in a state of rest at B, and similarly at all 
other points, since the same reasoning holds good in every case. 
When to A, that which is in process of locomotion, B, the 
middle-point, serves both as a finishing-point and as a starting- 
point for its motion, A must come to a stand at B, because it 
makes it two just as one might do in thought. However, the 
point A is the real starting-point at which the moving body has 
ceased to be, and it is at G that it has really come to be when its 
course is finished and it comes to a stand. So this is how we 
must meet the difficulty that then arises, which is as follows. 
Suppose the line E is equal to the line Z, that A proceeds in 
continuous locomotion from the extreme point of E to G, and 
that, at the moment when A is at the point B, D is proceeding in 
uniform locomotion and with the same velocity as A from the 
extremity of Z to H: then, says the argument, D will have 
reached H before A has reached G for that which makes an 
earlier start and departure must make an earlier arrival: the 
reason, then, for the late arrival of A is that it has not 
simultaneously come to be and ceased to be at B: otherwise it 
will not arrive later: for this to happen it will be necessary that 



835 



it should come to a stand there. Therefore we must not hold 
that there was a moment when A came to be at B and that at 
the same moment D was in motion from the extremity of Z: for 
the fact of A's having come to be at B will involve the fact of its 
also ceasing to be there, and the two events will not be 
simultaneous, whereas the truth is that A is at B at a sectional 
point of time and does not occupy time there. In this case, 
therefore, where the motion of a thing is continuous, it is 
impossible to use this form of expression. On the other hand in 
the case of a thing that turns back in its course we must do so. 
For suppose H in the course of its locomotion proceeds to D and 
then turns back and proceeds downwards again: then the 
extreme point D has served as finishing-point and as starting- 
point for it, one point thus serving as two: therefore H must 
have come to a stand there: it cannot have come to be at D and 
departed from D simultaneously, for in that case it would 
simultaneously be there and not be there at the same moment. 
And here we cannot apply the argument used to solve the 
difficulty stated above: we cannot argue that H is at D at a 
sectional point of time and has not come to be or ceased to be 
there. For here the goal that is reached is necessarily one that is 
actually, not potentially, existent. Now the point in the middle is 
potential: but this one is actual, and regarded from below it is a 
finishing-point, while regarded from above it is a starting-point, 
so that it stands in these same two respective relations to the 
two motions. Therefore that which turns back in traversing a 
rectilinear course must in so doing come to a stand. 
Consequently there cannot be a continuous rectilinear motion 
that is eternal. 

The same method should also be adopted in replying to those 
who ask, in the terms of Zeno's argument, whether we admit 
that before any distance can be traversed half the distance must 
be traversed, that these half-distances are infinite in number, 
and that it is impossible to traverse distances infinite in number 



836 



- or some on the lines of this same argument put the questions 
in another form, and would have us grant that in the time 
during which a motion is in progress it should be possible to 
reckon a half-motion before the whole for every half-distance 
that we get, so that we have the result that when the whole 
distance is traversed we have reckoned an infinite number, 
which is admittedly impossible. Now when we first discussed 
the question of motion we put forward a solution of this 
difficulty turning on the fact that the period of time occupied in 
traversing the distance contains within itself an infinite number 
of units: there is no absurdity, we said, in supposing the 
traversing of infinite distances in infinite time, and the element 
of infinity is present in the time no less than in the distance. 
But, although this solution is adequate as a reply to the 
questioner (the question asked being whether it is possible in a 
finite time to traverse or reckon an infinite number of units), 
nevertheless as an account of the fact and explanation of its 
true nature it is inadequate. For suppose the distance to be left 
out of account and the question asked to be no longer whether 
it is possible in a finite time to traverse an infinite number of 
distances, and suppose that the inquiry is made to refer to the 
time taken by itself (for the time contains an infinite number of 
divisions): then this solution will no longer be adequate, and we 
must apply the truth that we enunciated in our recent 
discussion, stating it in the following way. In the act of dividing 
the continuous distance into two halves one point is treated as 
two, since we make it a starting-point and a finishing-point: 
and this same result is also produced by the act of reckoning 
halves as well as by the act of dividing into halves. But if 
divisions are made in this way, neither the distance nor the 
motion will be continuous: for motion if it is to be continuous 
must relate to what is continuous: and though what is 
continuous contains an infinite number of halves, they are not 
actual but potential halves. If the halves are made actual, we 



837 



shall get not a continuous but an intermittent motion. In the 
case of reckoning the halves, it is clear that this result follows: 
for then one point must be reckoned as two: it will be the 
finishing-point of the one half and the starting-point of the 
other, if we reckon not the one continuous whole but the two 
halves. Therefore to the question whether it is possible to pass 
through an infinite number of units either of time or of distance 
we must reply that in a sense it is and in a sense it is not. If the 
units are actual, it is not possible: if they are potential, it is 
possible. For in the course of a continuous motion the traveller 
has traversed an infinite number of units in an accidental sense 
but not in an unqualified sense: for though it is an accidental 
characteristic of the distance to be an infinite number of half- 
distances, this is not its real and essential character. It is also 
plain that unless we hold that the point of time that divides 
earlier from later always belongs only to the later so far as the 
thing is concerned, we shall be involved in the consequence 
that the same thing is at the same moment existent and not 
existent, and that a thing is not existent at the moment when it 
has become. It is true that the point is common to both times, 
the earlier as well as the later, and that, while numerically one 
and the same, it is theoretically not so, being the finishing-point 
of the one and the starting-point of the other: but so far as the 
thing is concerned it belongs to the later stage of what happens 
to it. Let us suppose a time ABG and a thing D, D being white in 
the time A and not-white in the time B. Then D is at the 
moment G white and not-white: for if we were right in saying 
that it is white during the whole time A, it is true to call it white 
at any moment of A, and not-white in B, and G is in both A and 
B. We must not allow, therefore, that it is white in the whole of 
A, but must say that it is so in all of it except the last moment G. 
G belongs already to the later period, and if in the whole of A 
not-white was in process of becoming and white of perishing, at 
G the process is complete. And so G is the first moment at 



838 



which it is true to call the thing white or not white respectively. 
Otherwise a thing may be non-existent at the moment when it 
has become and existent at the moment when it has perished: 
or else it must be possible for a thing at the same time to be 
white and not white and in fact to be existent and non-existent. 
Further, if anything that exists after having been previously 
non-existent must become existent and does not exist when it 
is becoming, time cannot be divisible into time-atoms. For 
suppose that D was becoming white in the time A and that at 
another time B, a time-atom consecutive with the last atom of 
A, D has already become white and so is white at that moment: 
then, inasmuch as in the time A it was becoming white and so 
was not white and at the moment B it is white, there must have 
been a becoming between A and B and therefore also a time in 
which the becoming took place. On the other hand, those who 
deny atoms of time (as we do) are not affected by this 
argument: according to them D has become and so is white at 
the last point of the actual time in which it was becoming 
white: and this point has no other point consecutive with or in 
succession to it, whereas time-atoms are conceived as 
successive. Moreover it is clear that if D was becoming white in 
the whole time A, the time occupied by it in having become 
white in addition to having been in process of becoming white 
is no more than all that it occupied in the mere process of 
becoming white. 

These and such-like, then, are the arguments for our conclusion 
that derive cogency from the fact that they have a special 
bearing on the point at issue. If we look at the question from the 
point of view of general theory, the same result would also 
appear to be indicated by the following arguments. Everything 
whose motion is continuous must, on arriving at any point in 
the course of its locomotion, have been previously also in 
process of locomotion to that point, if it is not forced out of its 
path by anything: e.g. on arriving at B a thing must also have 



839 



been in process of locomotion to B, and that not merely when it 
was near to B, but from the moment of its starting on its course, 
since there can be, no reason for its being so at any particular 
stage rather than at an earlier one. So, too, in the case of the 
other kinds of motion. Now we are to suppose that a thing 
proceeds in locomotion from A to G and that at the moment of 
its arrival at G the continuity of its motion is unbroken and will 
remain so until it has arrived back at A. Then when it is 
undergoing locomotion from A to G it is at the same time 
undergoing also its locomotion to A from G: consequently it is 
simultaneously undergoing two contrary motions, since the two 
motions that follow the same straight line are contrary to each 
other. With this consequence there also follows another: we 
have a thing that is in process of change from a position in 
which it has not yet been: so, inasmuch as this is impossible, 
the thing must come to a stand at G. Therefore the motion is 
not a single motion, since motion that is interrupted by 
stationariness is not single. 

Further, the following argument will serve better to make this 
point clear universally in respect of every kind of motion. If the 
motion undergone by that which is in motion is always one of 
those already enumerated, and the state of rest that it 
undergoes is one of those that are the opposites of the motions 
(for we found that there could be no other besides these), and 
moreover that which is undergoing but does not always 
undergo a particular motion (by this I mean one of the various 
specifically distinct motions, not some particular part of the 
whole motion) must have been previously undergoing the state 
of rest that is the opposite of the motion, the state of rest being 
privation of motion; then, inasmuch as the two motions that 
follow the same straight line are contrary motions, and it is 
impossible for a thing to undergo simultaneously two contrary 
motions, that which is undergoing locomotion from A to G 
cannot also simultaneously be undergoing locomotion from G 



840 



to A: and since the latter locomotion is not simultaneous with 
the former but is still to be undergone, before it is undergone 
there must occur a state of rest at G: for this, as we found, is the 
state of rest that is the opposite of the motion from G. The 
foregoing argument, then, makes it plain that the motion in 
question is not continuous. 

Our next argument has a more special bearing than the 
foregoing on the point at issue. We will suppose that there has 
occurred in something simultaneously a perishing of not-white 
and a becoming of white. Then if the alteration to white and 
from white is a continuous process and the white does not 
remain any time, there must have occurred simultaneously a 
perishing of not-white, a becoming of white, and a becoming of 
not-white: for the time of the three will be the same. 

Again, from the continuity of the time in which the motion 
takes place we cannot infer continuity in the motion, but only 
successiveness: in fact, how could contraries, e.g. whiteness and 
blackness, meet in the same extreme point? 

On the other hand, in motion on a circular line we shall find 
singleness and continuity: for here we are met by no impossible 
consequence: that which is in motion from A will in virtue of 
the same direction of energy be simultaneously in motion to A 
(since it is in motion to the point at which it will finally arrive), 
and yet will not be undergoing two contrary or opposite 
motions: for a motion to a point and a motion from that point 
are not always contraries or opposites: they are contraries only 
if they are on the same straight line (for then they are contrary 
to one another in respect of place, as e.g. the two motions along 
the diameter of the circle, since the ends of this are at the 
greatest possible distance from one another), and they are 
opposites only if they are along the same line. Therefore in the 
case we are now considering there is nothing to prevent the 



841 



motion being continuous and free from all intermission: for 
rotatory motion is motion of a thing from its place to its place, 
whereas rectilinear motion is motion from its place to another 
place. 

Moreover the progress of rotatory motion is never localized 
within certain fixed limits, whereas that of rectilinear motion 
repeatedly is so. Now a motion that is always shifting its ground 
from moment to moment can be continuous: but a motion that 
is repeatedly localized within certain fixed limits cannot be so, 
since then the same thing would have to undergo 
simultaneously two opposite motions. So, too, there cannot be 
continuous motion in a semicircle or in any other arc of a circle, 
since here also the same ground must be traversed repeatedly 
and two contrary processes of change must occur. The reason is 
that in these motions the starting-point and the termination do 
not coincide, whereas in motion over a circle they do coincide, 
and so this is the only perfect motion. 

This differentiation also provides another means of showing 
that the other kinds of motion cannot be continuous either: for 
in all of them we find that there is the same ground to be 
traversed repeatedly; thus in alteration there are the 
intermediate stages of the process, and in quantitative change 
there are the intervening degrees of magnitude: and in 
becoming and perishing the same thing is true. It makes no 
difference whether we take the intermediate stages of the 
process to be few or many, or whether we add or subtract one: 
for in either case we find that there is still the same ground to 
be traversed repeatedly. Moreover it is plain from what has been 
said that those physicists who assert that all sensible things are 
always in motion are wrong: for their motion must be one or 
other of the motions just mentioned: in fact they mostly 
conceive it as alteration (things are always in flux and decay, 
they say), and they go so far as to speak even of becoming and 



842 



perishing as a process of alteration. On the other hand, our 
argument has enabled us to assert the fact, applying universally 
to all motions, that no motion admits of continuity except 
rotatory motion: consequently neither alteration nor increase 
admits of continuity. We need now say no more in support of 
the position that there is no process of change that admits of 
infinity or continuity except rotatory locomotion. 



It can now be shown plainly that rotation is the primary 
locomotion. Every locomotion, as we said before, is either 
rotatory or rectilinear or a compound of the two: and the two 
former must be prior to the last, since they are the elements of 
which the latter consists. Moreover rotatory locomotion is prior 
to rectilinear locomotion, because it is more simple and 
complete, which may be shown as follows. The straight line 
traversed in rectilinear motion cannot be infinite: for there is no 
such thing as an infinite straight line; and even if there were, it 
would not be traversed by anything in motion: for the 
impossible does not happen and it is impossible to traverse an 
infinite distance. On the other hand rectilinear motion on a 
finite straight line is if it turns back a composite motion, in fact 
two motions, while if it does not turn back it is incomplete and 
perishable: and in the order of nature, of definition, and of time 
alike the complete is prior to the incomplete and the 
imperishable to the perishable. Again, a motion that admits of 
being eternal is prior to one that does not. Now rotatory motion 
can be eternal: but no other motion, whether locomotion or 
motion of any other kind, can be so, since in all of them rest 
must occur and with the occurrence of rest the motion has 
perished. Moreover the result at which we have arrived, that 



843 



rotatory motion is single and continuous, and rectilinear motion 
is not, is a reasonable one. In rectilinear motion we have a 
definite starting-point, finishing-point, middle-point, which all 
have their place in it in such a way that there is a point from 
which that which is in motion can be said to start and a point at 
which it can be said to finish its course (for when anything is at 
the limits of its course, whether at the starting-point or at the 
finishing-point, it must be in a state of rest). On the other hand 
in circular motion there are no such definite points: for why 
should any one point on the line be a limit rather than any 
other? Any one point as much as any other is alike starting- 
point, middle-point, and finishing-point, so that we can say of 
certain things both that they are always and that they never are 
at a starting-point and at a finishing-point (so that a revolving 
sphere, while it is in motion, is also in a sense at rest, for it 
continues to occupy the same place). The reason of this is that 
in this case all these characteristics belong to the centre: that is 
to say, the centre is alike starting-point, middle-point, and 
finishing-point of the space traversed; consequently since this 
point is not a point on the circular line, there is no point at 
which that which is in process of locomotion can be in a state of 
rest as having traversed its course, because in its locomotion it 
is proceeding always about a central point and not to an 
extreme point: therefore it remains still, and the whole is in a 
sense always at rest as well as continuously in motion. Our next 
point gives a convertible result: on the one hand, because 
rotation is the measure of motions it must be the primary 
motion (for all things are measured by what is primary): on the 
other hand, because rotation is the primary motion it is the 
measure of all other motions. Again, rotatory motion is also the 
only motion that admits of being regular. In rectilinear 
locomotion the motion of things in leaving the starting-point is 
not uniform with their motion in approaching the finishing- 
point, since the velocity of a thing always increases 



844 



proportionately as it removes itself farther from its position of 
rest: on the other hand rotatory motion is the only motion 
whose course is naturally such that it has no starting-point or 
finishing-point in itself but is determined from elsewhere. 

As to locomotion being the primary motion, this is a truth that 
is attested by all who have ever made mention of motion in 
their theories: they all assign their first principles of motion to 
things that impart motion of this kind. Thus 'separation' and 
'combination' are motions in respect of place, and the motion 
imparted by 'Love' and 'Strife' takes these forms, the latter 
'separating' and the former 'combining'. Anaxagoras, too, says 
that 'Mind', his first movent, 'separates'. Similarly those who 
assert no cause of this kind but say that 'void' accounts for 
motion - they also hold that the motion of natural substance is 
motion in respect of place: for their motion that is accounted 
for by 'void' is locomotion, and its sphere of operation may be 
said to be place. Moreover they are of opinion that the primary 
substances are not subject to any of the other motions, though 
the things that are compounds of these substances are so 
subject: the processes of increase and decrease and alteration, 
they say, are effects of the 'combination' and 'separation' of 
atoms. It is the same, too, with those who make out that the 
becoming or perishing of a thing is accounted for by 'density' or 
'rarity': for it is by 'combination' and 'separation' that the place 
of these things in their systems is determined. Moreover to 
these we may add those who make Soul the cause of motion: 
for they say that things that undergo motion have as their first 
principle 'that which moves itself: and when animals and all 
living things move themselves, the motion is motion in respect 
of place. Finally it is to be noted that we say that a thing 'is in 
motion' in the strict sense of the term only when its motion is 
motion in respect of place: if a thing is in process of increase or 
decrease or is undergoing some alteration while remaining at 
rest in the same place, we say that it is in motion in some 



845 



particular respect: we do not say that it 'is in motion' without 
qualification. 

Our present position, then, is this: We have argued that there 
always was motion and always will be motion throughout all 
time, and we have explained what is the first principle of this 
eternal motion: we have explained further which is the primary 
motion and which is the only motion that can be eternal: and 
we have pronounced the first movent to be unmoved. 



10 

We have now to assert that the first movent must be without 
parts and without magnitude, beginning with the establishment 
of the premisses on which this conclusion depends. 

One of these premisses is that nothing finite can cause motion 
during an infinite time. We have three things, the movent, the 
moved, and thirdly that in which the motion takes place, 
namely the time: and these are either all infinite or all finite or 
partly - that is to say two of them or one of them - finite and 
partly infinite. Let A be the movement, B the moved, and G the 
infinite time. Now let us suppose that D moves E, a part of B. 
Then the time occupied by this motion cannot be equal to G: for 
the greater the amount moved, the longer the time occupied. It 
follows that the time Z is not infinite. Now we see that by 
continuing to add to D, I shall use up A and by continuing to add 
to E, I shall use up B: but I shall not use up the time by 
continually subtracting a corresponding amount from it, 
because it is infinite. Consequently the duration of the part of G 
which is occupied by all A in moving the whole of B, will be 
finite. Therefore a finite thing cannot impart to anything an 



846 



infinite motion. It is clear, then, that it is impossible for the 
finite to cause motion during an infinite time. 

It has now to be shown that in no case is it possible for an 
infinite force to reside in a finite magnitude. This can be shown 
as follows: we take it for granted that the greater force is always 
that which in less time than another does an equal amount of 
work when engaged in any activity - in heating, for example, or 
sweetening or throwing; in fact, in causing any kind of motion. 
Then that on which the forces act must be affected to some 
extent by our supposed finite magnitude possessing an infinite 
force as well as by anything else, in fact to a greater extent than 
by anything else, since the infinite force is greater than any 
other. But then there cannot be any time in which its action 
could take place. Suppose that A is the time occupied by the 
infinite power in the performance of an act of heating or 
pushing, and that AB is the time occupied by a finite power in 
the performance of the same act: then by adding to the latter 
another finite power and continually increasing the magnitude 
of the power so added I shall at some time or other reach a 
point at which the finite power has completed the motive act in 
the time A: for by continual addition to a finite magnitude I 
must arrive at a magnitude that exceeds any assigned limit, and 
in the same way by continual subtraction I must arrive at one 
that falls short of any assigned limit. So we get the result that 
the finite force will occupy the same amount of time in 
performing the motive act as the infinite force. But this is 
impossible. Therefore nothing finite can possess an infinite 
force. So it is also impossible for a finite force to reside in an 
infinite magnitude. It is true that a greater force can reside in a 
lesser magnitude: but the superiority of any such greater force 
can be still greater if the magnitude in which it resides is 
greater. Now let AB be an infinite magnitude. Then BG possesses 
a certain force that occupies a certain time, let us say the time Z 
in moving D. Now if I take a magnitude twice as great at BG, the 



847 



time occupied by this magnitude in moving D will be half of EZ 
(assuming this to be the proportion): so we may call this time 
ZH. That being so, by continually taking a greater magnitude in 
this way I shall never arrive at the full AB, whereas I shall 
always be getting a lesser fraction of the time given. Therefore 
the force must be infinite, since it exceeds any finite force. 
Moreover the time occupied by the action of any finite force 
must also be finite: for if a given force moves something in a 
certain time, a greater force will do so in a lesser time, but still a 
definite time, in inverse proportion. But a force must always be 
infinite - just as a number or a magnitude is - if it exceeds all 
definite limits. This point may also be proved in another way - 
by taking a finite magnitude in which there resides a force the 
same in kind as that which resides in the infinite magnitude, so 
that this force will be a measure of the finite force residing in 
the infinite magnitude. 

It is plain, then, from the foregoing arguments that it is 
impossible for an infinite force to reside in a finite magnitude or 
for a finite force to reside in an infinite magnitude. But before 
proceeding to our conclusion it will be well to discuss a 
difficulty that arises in connexion with locomotion. If 
everything that is in motion with the exception of things that 
move themselves is moved by something else, how is it that 
some things, e.g. things thrown, continue to be in motion when 
their movent is no longer in contact with them? If we say that 
the movent in such cases moves something else at the same 
time, that the thrower e.g. also moves the air, and that this in 
being moved is also a movent, then it would be no more 
possible for this second thing than for the original thing to be in 
motion when the original movent is not in contact with it or 
moving it: all the things moved would have to be in motion 
simultaneously and also to have ceased simultaneously to be in 
motion when the original movent ceases to move them, even if, 
like the magnet, it makes that which it has moved capable of 



848 



being a movent. Therefore, while we must accept this 
explanation to the extent of saying that the original movent 
gives the power of being a movent either to air or to water or to 
something else of the kind, naturally adapted for imparting and 
undergoing motion, we must say further that this thing does 
not cease simultaneously to impart motion and to undergo 
motion: it ceases to be in motion at the moment when its 
movent ceases to move it, but it still remains a movent, and so 
it causes something else consecutive with it to be in motion, 
and of this again the same may be said. The motion begins to 
cease when the motive force produced in one member of the 
consecutive series is at each stage less than that possessed by 
the preceding member, and it finally ceases when one member 
no longer causes the next member to be a movent but only 
causes it to be in motion. The motion of these last two - of the 
one as movent and of the other as moved - must cease 
simultaneously, and with this the whole motion ceases. Now 
the things in which this motion is produced are things that 
admit of being sometimes in motion and sometimes at rest, and 
the motion is not continuous but only appears so: for it is 
motion of things that are either successive or in contact, there 
being not one movent but a number of movents consecutive 
with one another: and so motion of this kind takes place in air 
and water. Some say that it is 'mutual replacement': but we 
must recognize that the difficulty raised cannot be solved 
otherwise than in the way we have described. So far as they are 
affected by 'mutual replacement', all the members of the series 
are moved and impart motion simultaneously, so that their 
motions also cease simultaneously: but our present problem 
concerns the appearance of continuous motion in a single 
thing, and therefore, since it cannot be moved throughout its 
motion by the same movent, the question is, what moves it? 

Resuming our main argument, we proceed from the positions 
that there must be continuous motion in the world of things, 



849 



that this is a single motion, that a single motion must be a 
motion of a magnitude (for that which is without magnitude 
cannot be in motion), and that the magnitude must be a single 
magnitude moved by a single movent (for otherwise there will 
not be continuous motion but a consecutive series of separate 
motions), and that if the movement is a single thing, it is either 
itself in motion or itself unmoved: if, then, it is in motion, it will 
have to be subject to the same conditions as that which it 
moves, that is to say it will itself be in process of change and in 
being so will also have to be moved by something: so we have a 
series that must come to an end, and a point will be reached at 
which motion is imparted by something that is unmoved. Thus 
we have a movent that has no need to change along with that 
which it moves but will be able to cause motion always (for the 
causing of motion under these conditions involves no effort): 
and this motion alone is regular, or at least it is so in a higher 
degree than any other, since the movent is never subject to any 
change. So, too, in order that the motion may continue to be of 
the same character, the moved must not be subject to change in 
respect of its relation to the movent. Moreover the movent must 
occupy either the centre or the circumference, since these are 
the first principles from which a sphere is derived. But the 
things nearest the movent are those whose motion is quickest, 
and in this case it is the motion of the circumference that is the 
quickest: therefore the movent occupies the circumference. 

There is a further difficulty in supposing it to be possible for 
anything that is in motion to cause motion continuously and 
not merely in the way in which it is caused by something 
repeatedly pushing (in which case the continuity amounts to no 
more than successiveness). Such a movent must either itself 
continue to push or pull or perform both these actions, or else 
the action must be taken up by something else and be passed 
on from one movent to another (the process that we described 
before as occurring in the case of things thrown, since the air or 



850 



the water, being divisible, is a movent only in virtue of the fact 
that different parts of the air are moved one after another): and 
in either case the motion cannot be a single motion, but only a 
consecutive series of motions. The only continuous motion, 
then, is that which is caused by the unmoved movent: and this 
motion is continuous because the movent remains always 
invariable, so that its relation to that which it moves remains 
also invariable and continuous. 

Now that these points are settled, it is clear that the first 
unmoved movent cannot have any magnitude. For if it has 
magnitude, this must be either a finite or an infinite magnitude. 
Now we have already'proved in our course on Physics that there 
cannot be an infinite magnitude: and we have now proved that 
it is impossible for a finite magnitude to have an infinite force, 
and also that it is impossible for a thing to be moved by a finite 
magnitude during an infinite time. But the first movent causes a 
motion that is eternal and does cause it during an infinite time. 
It is clear, therefore, that the first movent is indivisible and is 
without parts and without magnitude. 



851 



Aristotle - On the Heavens 
[Translated by J. L. Stocks] 



Book I 



The science which has to do with nature clearly concerns itself for 
the most part with bodies and magnitudes and their properties and 
movements, but also with the principles of this sort of substance, as 
many as they may be. For of things constituted by nature some are 
bodies and magnitudes, some possess body and magnitude, and 
some are principles of things which possess these. Now a continuum 
is that which is divisible into parts always capable of subdivision, and 
a body is that which is every way divisible. A magnitude if divisible 
one way is a line, if two ways a surface, and if three a body. Beyond 
these there is no other magnitude, because the three dimensions are 
all that there are, and that which is divisible in three directions is 
divisible in all. For, as the Pythagoreans say, the world and all that is 
in it is determined by the number three, since beginning and middle 
and end give the number of an 'all', and the number they give is the 
triad. And so, having taken these three from nature as (so to speak) 
laws of it, we make further use of the number three in the worship of 
the Gods. Further, we use the terms in practice in this way. Of two 
things, or men, we say 'both', but not 'all': three is the first number to 
which the term 'all' has been appropriated. And in this, as we have 
said, we do but follow the lead which nature gives. Therefore, since 
'every' and 'all' and 'complete' do not differ from one another in 
respect of form, but only, if at all, in their matter and in that to which 
they are applied, body alone among magnitudes can be complete. For 
it alone is determined by the three dimensions, that is, is an 'all'. But 
if it is divisible in three dimensions it is every way divisible, while the 
other magnitudes are divisible in one dimension or in two alone: for 



852 



the divisibility and continuity of magnitudes depend upon the 
number of the dimensions, one sort being continuous in one 
direction, another in two, another in all. All magnitudes, then, which 
are divisible are also continuous. Whether we can also say that 
whatever is continuous is divisible does not yet, on our present 
grounds, appear. One thing, however, is clear. We cannot pass beyond 
body to a further kind, as we passed from length to surface, and from 
surface to body. For if we could, it would cease to be true that body is 
complete magnitude. We could pass beyond it only in virtue of a 
defect in it; and that which is complete cannot be defective, since it 
has being in every respect. Now bodies which are classed as parts of 
the whole are each complete according to our formula, since each 
possesses every dimension. But each is determined relatively to that 
part which is next to it by contact, for which reason each of them is 
in a sense many bodies. But the whole of which they are parts must 
necessarily be complete, and thus, in accordance with the meaning of 
the word, have being, not in some respect only, but in every respect. 



The question as to the nature of the whole, whether it is infinite in 
size or limited in its total mass, is a matter for subsequent inquiry. 
We will now speak of those parts of the whole which are specifically 
distinct. Let us take this as our starting-point. All natural bodies and 
magnitudes we hold to be, as such, capable of locomotion; for nature, 
we say, is their principle of movement. But all movement that is in 
place, all locomotion, as we term it, is either straight or circular or a 
combination of these two, which are the only simple movements. 
And the reason of this is that these two, the straight and the circular 
line, are the only simple magnitudes. Now revolution about the 
centre is circular motion, while the upward and downward 
movements are in a straight line, 'upward' meaning motion away 
from the centre, and 'downward' motion towards it. All simple 
motion, then, must be motion either away from or towards or about 
the centre. This seems to be in exact accord with what we said above: 



853 



as body found its completion in three dimensions, so its movement 
completes itself in three forms. 

Bodies are either simple or compounded of such; and by simple 
bodies I mean those which possess a principle of movement in their 
own nature, such as fire and earth with their kinds, and whatever is 
akin to them. Necessarily, then, movements also will be either simple 
or in some sort compound - simple in the case of the simple bodies, 
compound in that of the composite - and in the latter case the 
motion will be that of the simple body which prevails in the 
composition. Supposing, then, that there is such a thing as simple 
movement, and that circular movement is an instance of it, and that 
both movement of a simple body is simple and simple movement is 
of a simple body (for if it is movement of a compound it will be in 
virtue of a prevailing simple element), then there must necessarily be 
some simple body which revolves naturally and in virtue of its own 
nature with a circular movement. By constraint, of course, it may be 
brought to move with the motion of something else different from 
itself, but it cannot so move naturally, since there is one sort of 
movement natural to each of the simple bodies. Again, if the 
unnatural movement is the contrary of the natural and a thing can 
have no more than one contrary, it will follow that circular 
movement, being a simple motion, must be unnatural, if it is not 
natural, to the body moved. If then (1) the body, whose movement is 
circular, is fire or some other element, its natural motion must be the 
contrary of the circular motion. But a single thing has a single 
contrary; and upward and downward motion are the contraries of 
one another. If, on the other hand, (2) the body moving with this 
circular motion which is unnatural to it is something different from 
the elements, there will be some other motion which is natural to it. 
But this cannot be. For if the natural motion is upward, it will be fire 
or air, and if downward, water or earth. Further, this circular motion 
is necessarily primary. For the perfect is naturally prior to the 
imperfect, and the circle is a perfect thing. This cannot be said of any 
straight line: - not of an infinite line; for, if it were perfect, it would 
have a limit and an end: nor of any finite line; for in every case there 
is something beyond it, since any finite line can be extended. And so, 
since the prior movement belongs to the body which naturally prior, 



854 



and circular movement is prior to straight, and movement in a 
straight line belongs to simple bodies - fire moving straight upward 
and earthy bodies straight downward towards the centre - since this 
is so, it follows that circular movement also must be the movement 
of some simple body. For the movement of composite bodies is, as we 
said, determined by that simple body which preponderates in the 
composition. These premises clearly give the conclusion that there is 
in nature some bodily substance other than the formations we know, 
prior to them all and more divine than they. But it may also be proved 
as follows. We may take it that all movement is either natural or 
unnatural, and that the movement which is unnatural to one body is 
natural to another - as, for instance, is the case with the upward and 
downward movements, which are natural and unnatural to fire and 
earth respectively. It necessarily follows that circular movement, 
being unnatural to these bodies, is the natural movement of some 
other. Further, if, on the one hand, circular movement is natural to 
something, it must surely be some simple and primary body which is 
ordained to move with a natural circular motion, as fire is ordained to 
fly up and earth down. If, on the other hand, the movement of the 
rotating bodies about the centre is unnatural, it would be remarkable 
and indeed quite inconceivable that this movement alone should be 
continuous and eternal, being nevertheless contrary to nature. At any 
rate the evidence of all other cases goes to show that it is the 
unnatural which quickest passes away. And so, if, as some say, the 
body so moved is fire, this movement is just as unnatural to it as 
downward movement; for any one can see that fire moves in a 
straight line away from the centre. On all these grounds, therefore, 
we may infer with confidence that there is something beyond the 
bodies that are about us on this earth, different and separate from 
them; and that the superior glory of its nature is proportionate to its 
distance from this world of ours. 



855 



In consequence of what has been said, in part by way of assumption 
and in part by way of proof, it is clear that not every body either 
possesses lightness or heaviness. As a preliminary we must explain 
in what sense we are using the words 'heavy' and 'light', sufficiently, 
at least, for our present purpose: we can examine the terms more 
closely later, when we come to consider their essential nature. Let us 
then apply the term 'heavy' to that which naturally moves towards 
the centre, and 'light' to that which moves naturally away from the 
centre. The heaviest thing will be that which sinks to the bottom of 
all things that move downward, and the lightest that which rises to 
the surface of everything that moves upward. Now, necessarily, 
everything which moves either up or down possesses lightness or 
heaviness or both - but not both relatively to the same thing: for 
things are heavy and light relatively to one another; air, for instance, 
is light relatively to water, and water light relatively to earth. The 
body, then, which moves in a circle cannot possibly possess either 
heaviness or lightness. For neither naturally nor unnaturally can it 
move either towards or away from the centre. Movement in a straight 
line certainly does not belong to it naturally, since one sort of 
movement is, as we saw, appropriate to each simple body, and so we 
should be compelled to identify it with one of the bodies which move 
in this way. Suppose, then, that the movement is unnatural. In that 
case, if it is the downward movement which is unnatural, the upward 
movement will be natural; and if it is the upward which is unnatural, 
the downward will be natural. For we decided that of contrary 
movements, if the one is unnatural to anything, the other will be 
natural to it. But since the natural movement of the whole and of its 
part of earth, for instance, as a whole and of a small clod - have one 
and the same direction, it results, in the first place, that this body can 
possess no lightness or heaviness at all (for that would mean that it 
could move by its own nature either from or towards the centre, 
which, as we know, is impossible); and, secondly, that it cannot 
possibly move in the way of locomotion by being forced violently 
aside in an upward or downward direction. For neither naturally nor 
unnaturally can it move with any other motion but its own, either 



856 



itself or any part of it, since the reasoning which applies to the whole 
applies also to the part. 

It is equally reasonable to assume that this body will be ungenerated 
and indestructible and exempt from increase and alteration, since 
everything that comes to be comes into being from its contrary and 
in some substrate, and passes away likewise in a substrate by the 
action of the contrary into the contrary, as we explained in our 
opening discussions. Now the motions of contraries are contrary. If 
then this body can have no contrary, because there can be no 
contrary motion to the circular, nature seems justly to have 
exempted from contraries the body which was to be ungenerated and 
indestructible. For it is in contraries that generation and decay 
subsist. Again, that which is subject to increase increases upon 
contact with a kindred body, which is resolved into its matter. But 
there is nothing out of which this body can have been generated. And 
if it is exempt from increase and diminution, the same reasoning 
leads us to suppose that it is also unalterable. For alteration is 
movement in respect of quality; and qualitative states and 
dispositions, such as health and disease, do not come into being 
without changes of properties. But all natural bodies which change 
their properties we see to be subject without exception to increase 
and diminution. This is the case, for instance, with the bodies of 
animals and their parts and with vegetable bodies, and similarly also 
with those of the elements. And so, if the body which moves with a 
circular motion cannot admit of increase or diminution, it is 
reasonable to suppose that it is also unalterable. 

The reasons why the primary body is eternal and not subject to 
increase or diminution, but unaging and unalterable and unmodified, 
will be clear from what has been said to any one who believes in our 
assumptions. Our theory seems to confirm experience and to be 
confirmed by it. For all men have some conception of the nature of 
the gods, and all who believe in the existence of gods at all, whether 
barbarian or Greek, agree in allotting the highest place to the deity, 
surely because they suppose that immortal is linked with immortal 
and regard any other supposition as inconceivable. If then there is, as 
there certainly is, anything divine, what we have just said about the 



857 



primary bodily substance was well said. The mere evidence of the 
senses is enough to convince us of this, at least with human 
certainty. For in the whole range of time past, so far as our inherited 
records reach, no change appears to have taken place either in the 
whole scheme of the outermost heaven or in any of its proper parts. 
The common name, too, which has been handed down from our 
distant ancestors even to our own day, seems to show that they 
conceived of it in the fashion which we have been expressing. The 
same ideas, one must believe, recur in men's minds not once or twice 
but again and again. And so, implying that the primary body is 
something else beyond earth, fire, air, and water, they gave the 
highest place a name of its own, aither, derived from the fact that it 
'runs always' for an eternity of time. Anaxagoras, however, 
scandalously misuses this name, taking aither as equivalent to fire. 

It is also clear from what has been said why the number of what we 
call simple bodies cannot be greater than it is. The motion of a simple 
body must itself be simple, and we assert that there are only these 
two simple motions, the circular and the straight, the latter being 
subdivided into motion away from and motion towards the centre. 



That there is no other form of motion opposed as contrary to the 
circular may be proved in various ways. In the first place, there is an 
obvious tendency to oppose the straight line to the circular. For 
concave and convex are a not only regarded as opposed to one 
another, but they are also coupled together and treated as a unity in 
opposition to the straight. And so, if there is a contrary to circular 
motion, motion in a straight line must be recognized as having the 
best claim to that name. But the two forms of rectilinear motion are 
opposed to one another by reason of their places; for up and down is 
a difference and a contrary opposition in place. Secondly, it may be 
thought that the same reasoning which holds good of the rectilinear 
path applies also the circular, movement from A to B being opposed 



858 



as contrary to movement from B to A. But what is meant is still 
rectilinear motion. For that is limited to a single path, while the 
circular paths which pass through the same two points are infinite in 
number. Even if we are confined to the single semicircle and the 
opposition is between movement from C to D and from D to C along 
that semicircle, the case is no better. For the motion is the same as 
that along the diameter, since we invariably regard the distance 
between two points as the length of the straight line which joins 
them. It is no more satisfactory to construct a circle and treat motion 
'along one semicircle as contrary to motion along the other. For 
example, taking a complete circle, motion from E to F on the 
semicircle G may be opposed to motion from F to E on the semicircle 
H. But even supposing these are contraries, it in no way follows that 
the reverse motions on the complete circumference contraries. Nor 
again can motion along the circle from A to B be regarded as the 
contrary of motion from A to C: for the motion goes from the same 
point towards the same point, and contrary motion was 
distinguished as motion from a contrary to its contrary. And even if 
the motion round a circle is the contrary of the reverse motion, one 
of the two would be ineffective: for both move to the same point, 
because that which moves in a circle, at whatever point it begins, 
must necessarily pass through all the contrary places alike. (By 
contrarieties of place I mean up and down, back and front, and right 
and left; and the contrary oppositions of movements are determined 
by those of places.) One of the motions, then, would be ineffective, for 
if the two motions were of equal strength, there would be no 
movement either way, and if one of the two were preponderant, the 
other would be inoperative. So that if both bodies were there, one of 
them, inasmuch as it would not be moving with its own movement, 
would be useless, in the sense in which a shoe is useless when it is 
not worn. But God and nature create nothing that has not its use. 



859 



This being clear, we must go on to consider the questions which 
remain. First, is there an infinite body, as the majority of the ancient 
philosophers thought, or is this an impossibility? The decision of this 
question, either way, is not unimportant, but rather all-important, to 
our search for the truth. It is this problem which has practically 
always been the source of the differences of those who have written 
about nature as a whole. So it has been and so it must be; since the 
least initial deviation from the truth is multiplied later a 
thousandfold. Admit, for instance, the existence of a minimum 
magnitude, and you will find that the minimum which you have 
introduced, small as it is, causes the greatest truths of mathematics 
to totter. The reason is that a principle is great rather in power than 
in extent; hence that which was small at the start turns out a giant at 
the end. Now the conception of the infinite possesses this power of 
principles, and indeed in the sphere of quantity possesses it in a 
higher degree than any other conception; so that it is in no way 
absurd or unreasonable that the assumption that an infinite body 
exists should be of peculiar moment to our inquiry. The infinite, then, 
we must now discuss, opening the whole matter from the beginning. 

Every body is necessarily to be classed either as simple or as 
composite; the infinite body, therefore, will be either simple or 
composite. 

But it is clear, further, that if the simple bodies are finite, the 
composite must also be finite, since that which is composed of 
bodies finite both in number and in magnitude is itself finite in 
respect of number and magnitude: its quantity is in fact the same as 
that of the bodies which compose it. What remains for us to consider, 
then, is whether any of the simple bodies can be infinite in 
magnitude, or whether this is impossible. Let us try the primary body 
first, and then go on to consider the others. 

The body which moves in a circle must necessarily be finite in every 
respect, for the following reasons. (1) If the body so moving is infinite, 
the radii drawn from the centre will be infinite. But the space 
between infinite radii is infinite: and by the space between the radii I 



860 



mean the area outside which no magnitude which is in contact with 
the two lines can be conceived as falling. This, I say, will be infinite: 
first, because in the case of finite radii it is always finite; and 
secondly, because in it one can always go on to a width greater than 
any given width; thus the reasoning which forces us to believe in 
infinite number, because there is no maximum, applies also to the 
space between the radii. Now the infinite cannot be traversed, and if 
the body is infinite the interval between the radii is necessarily 
infinite: circular motion therefore is an impossibility. Yet our eyes tell 
us that the heavens revolve in a circle, and by argument also we have 
determined that there is something to which circular movement 
belongs. 

(2) Again, if from a finite time a finite time be subtracted, what 
remains must be finite and have a beginning. And if the time of a 
journey has a beginning, there must be a beginning also of the 
movement, and consequently also of the distance traversed. This 
applies universally. Take a line, ACE, infinite in one direction, E, and 
another line, BB, infinite in both directions. Let ACE describe a circle, 
revolving upon C as centre. In its movement it will cut BB 
continuously for a certain time. This will be a finite time, since the 
total time is finite in which the heavens complete their circular orbit, 
and consequently the time subtracted from it, during which the one 
line in its motion cuts the other, is also finite. Therefore there will be 
a point at which ACE began for the first time to cut BB. This, however, 
is impossible. The infinite, then, cannot revolve in a circle; nor could 
the world, if it were infinite. 

(3) That the infinite cannot move may also be shown as follows. Let A 
be a finite line moving past the finite line, B. Of necessity A will pass 
clear of B and B of A at the same moment; for each overlaps the other 
to precisely the same extent. Now if the two were both moving, and 
moving in contrary directions, they would pass clear of one another 
more rapidly; if one were still and the other moving past it, less 
rapidly; provided that the speed of the latter were the same in both 
cases. This, however, is clear: that it is impossible to traverse an 
infinite line in a finite time. Infinite time, then, would be required. 
(This we demonstrated above in the discussion of movement.) And it 



861 



makes no difference whether a finite is passing by an infinite or an 
infinite by a finite. For when A is passing B, then B overlaps A and it 
makes no difference whether B is moved or unmoved, except that, if 
both move, they pass clear of one another more quickly. It is, 
however, quite possible that a moving line should in certain cases 
pass one which is stationary quicker than it passes one moving in an 
opposite direction. One has only to imagine the movement to be slow 
where both move and much faster where one is stationary. To 
suppose one line stationary, then, makes no difficulty for our 
argument, since it is quite possible for A to pass B at a slower rate 
when both are moving than when only one is. If, therefore, the time 
which the finite moving line takes to pass the other is infinite, then 
necessarily the time occupied by the motion of the infinite past the 
finite is also infinite. For the infinite to move at all is thus absolutely 
impossible; since the very smallest movement conceivable must take 
an infinity of time. Moreover the heavens certainly revolve, and they 
complete their circular orbit in a finite time; so that they pass round 
the whole extent of any line within their orbit, such as the finite line 
AB. The revolving body, therefore, cannot be infinite. 

(4) Again, as a line which has a limit cannot be infinite, or, if it is 
infinite, is so only in length, so a surface cannot be infinite in that 
respect in which it has a limit; or, indeed, if it is completely 
determinate, in any respect whatever. Whether it be a square or a 
circle or a sphere, it cannot be infinite, any more than a foot-rule can. 
There is then no such thing as an infinite sphere or square or circle, 
and where there is no circle there can be no circular movement, and 
similarly where there is no infinite at all there can be no infinite 
movement; and from this it follows that, an infinite circle being itself 
an impossibility, there can be no circular motion of an infinite body. 

(5) Again, take a centre C, an infinite line, AB, another infinite line at 
right angles to it, E, and a moving radius, CD. CD will never cease 
contact with E, but the position will always be something like CE, CD 
cutting E at F. The infinite line, therefore, refuses to complete the 
circle. 



862 



(6) Again, if the heaven is infinite and moves in a circle, we shall have 
to admit that in a finite time it has traversed the infinite. For suppose 
the fixed heaven infinite, and that which moves within it equal to it. 
It results that when the infinite body has completed its revolution, it 
has traversed an infinite equal to itself in a finite time. But that we 
know to be impossible. 

(7) It can also be shown, conversely, that if the time of revolution is 
finite, the area traversed must also be finite; but the area traversed 
was equal to itself; therefore, it is itself finite. 

We have now shown that the body which moves in a circle is not 
endless or infinite, but has its limit. 



Further, neither that which moves towards nor that which moves 
away from the centre can be infinite. For the upward and downward 
motions are contraries and are therefore motions towards contrary 
places. But if one of a pair of contraries is determinate, the other 
must be determinate also. Now the centre is determined; for, from 
whatever point the body which sinks to the bottom starts its 
downward motion, it cannot go farther than the centre. The centre, 
therefore, being determinate, the upper place must also be 
determinate. But if these two places are determined and finite, the 
corresponding bodies must also be finite. Further, if up and down are 
determinate, the intermediate place is also necessarily determinate. 
For, if it is indeterminate, the movement within it will be infinite; and 
that we have already shown to be an impossibility. The middle region 
then is determinate, and consequently any body which either is in it, 
or might be in it, is determinate. But the bodies which move up and 
down may be in it, since the one moves naturally away from the 
centre and the other towards it. 



863 



From this alone it is clear that an infinite body is an impossibility; but 
there is a further point. If there is no such thing as infinite weight, 
then it follows that none of these bodies can be infinite. For the 
supposed infinite body would have to be infinite in weight. (The same 
argument applies to lightness: for as the one supposition involves 
infinite weight, so the infinity of the body which rises to the surface 
involves infinite lightness.) This is proved as follows. Assume the 
weight to be finite, and take an infinite body, AB, of the weight C. 
Subtract from the infinite body a finite mass, BD, the weight of which 
shall be E. E then is less than C, since it is the weight of a lesser mass. 
Suppose then that the smaller goes into the greater a certain number 
of times, and take BF bearing the same proportion to BD which the 
greater weight bears to the smaller. For you may subtract as much as 
you please from an infinite. If now the masses are proportionate to 
the weights, and the lesser weight is that of the lesser mass, the 
greater must be that of the greater. The weights, therefore, of the 
finite and of the infinite body are equal. Again, if the weight of a 
greater body is greater than that of a less, the weight of GB will be 
greater than that of FB; and thus the weight of the finite body is 
greater than that of the infinite. And, further, the weight of unequal 
masses will be the same, since the infinite and the finite cannot be 
equal. It does not matter whether the weights are commensurable or 
not. If (a) they are incommensurable the same reasoning holds. For 
instance, suppose E multiplied by three is rather more than C: the 
weight of three masses of the full size of BD will be greater than C. 
We thus arrive at the same impossibility as before. Again (b) we may 
assume weights which are commensurate; for it makes no difference 
whether we begin with the weight or with the mass. For example, 
assume the weight E to be commensurate with C, and take from the 
infinite mass a part BD of weight E. Then let a mass BF be taken 
having the same proportion to BD which the two weights have to one 
another. (For the mass being infinite you may subtract from it as 
much as you please.) These assumed bodies will be commensurate in 
mass and in weight alike. Nor again does it make any difference to 
our demonstration whether the total mass has its weight equally or 
unequally distributed. For it must always be Possible to take from the 



864 



infinite mass a body of equal weight to BD by diminishing or 
increasing the size of the section to the necessary extent. 

From what we have said, then, it is clear that the weight of the 
infinite body cannot be finite. It must then be infinite. We have 
therefore only to show this to be impossible in order to prove an 
infinite body impossible. But the impossibility of infinite weight can 
be shown in the following way. A given weight moves a given 
distance in a given time; a weight which is as great and more moves 
the same distance in a less time, the times being in inverse 
proportion to the weights. For instance, if one weight is twice 
another, it will take half as long over a given movement. Further, a 
finite weight traverses any finite distance in a finite time. It 
necessarily follows from this that infinite weight, if there is such a 
thing, being, on the one hand, as great and more than as great as the 
finite, will move accordingly, but being, on the other hand, compelled 
to move in a time inversely proportionate to its greatness, cannot 
move at all. The time should be less in proportion as the weight is 
greater. But there is no proportion between the infinite and the finite: 
proportion can only hold between a less and a greater finite time. 
And though you may say that the time of the movement can be 
continually diminished, yet there is no minimum. Nor, if there were, 
would it help us. For some finite body could have been found greater 
than the given finite in the same proportion which is supposed to 
hold between the infinite and the given finite; so that an infinite and 
a finite weight must have traversed an equal distance in equal time. 
But that is impossible. Again, whatever the time, so long as it is finite, 
in which the infinite performs the motion, a finite weight must 
necessarily move a certain finite distance in that same time. Infinite 
weight is therefore impossible, and the same reasoning applies also 
to infinite lightness. Bodies then of infinite weight and of infinite 
lightness are equally impossible. 

That there is no infinite body may be shown, as we have shown it, by 
a detailed consideration of the various cases. But it may also be 
shown universally, not only by such reasoning as we advanced in our 
discussion of principles (though in that passage we have already 
determined universally the sense in which the existence of an 



865 



infinite is to be asserted or denied), but also suitably to our present 
purpose in the following way. That will lead us to a further question. 
Even if the total mass is not infinite, it may yet be great enough to 
admit a plurality of universes. The question might possibly be raised 
whether there is any obstacle to our believing that there are other 
universes composed on the pattern of our own, more than one, 
though stopping short of infinity. First, however, let us treat of the 
infinite universally. 



Every body must necessarily be either finite or infinite, and if infinite, 
either of similar or of dissimilar parts. If its parts are dissimilar, they 
must represent either a finite or an infinite number of kinds. That the 
kinds cannot be infinite is evident, if our original presuppositions 
remain unchallenged. For the primary movements being finite in 
number, the kinds of simple body are necessarily also finite, since the 
movement of a simple body is simple, and the simple movements are 
finite, and every natural body must always have its proper motion. 
Now if the infinite body is to be composed of a finite number of 
kinds, then each of its parts must necessarily be infinite in quantity, 
that is to say, the water, fire, &c, which compose it. But this is 
impossible, because, as we have already shown, infinite weight and 
lightness do not exist. Moreover it would be necessary also that their 
places should be infinite in extent, so that the movements too of all 
these bodies would be infinite. But this is not possible, if we are to 
hold to the truth of our original presuppositions and to the view that 
neither that which moves downward, nor, by the same reasoning, 
that which moves upward, can prolong its movement to infinity. For 
it is true in regard to quality, quantity, and place alike that any 
process of change is impossible which can have no end. I mean that 
if it is impossible for a thing to have come to be white, or a cubit long, 
or in Egypt, it is also impossible for it to be in process of coming to be 
any of these. It is thus impossible for a thing to be moving to a place 
at which in its motion it can never by any possibility arrive. Again, 



866 



suppose the body to exist in dispersion, it may be maintained none 
the less that the total of all these scattered particles, say, of fire, is 
infinite. But body we saw to be that which has extension every way. 
How can there be several dissimilar elements, each infinite? Each 
would have to be infinitely extended every way. 

It is no more conceivable, again, that the infinite should exist as a 
whole of similar parts. For, in the first place, there is no other 
(straight) movement beyond those mentioned: we must therefore 
give it one of them. And if so, we shall have to admit either infinite 
weight or infinite lightness. Nor, secondly, could the body whose 
movement is circular be infinite, since it is impossible for the infinite 
to move in a circle. This, indeed, would be as good as saying that the 
heavens are infinite, which we have shown to be impossible. 

Moreover, in general, it is impossible that the infinite should move at 
all. If it did, it would move either naturally or by constraint: and if by 
constraint, it possesses also a natural motion, that is to say, there is 
another place, infinite like itself, to which it will move. But that is 
impossible. 

That in general it is impossible for the infinite to be acted upon by 
the finite or to act upon it may be shown as follows. 

(1. The infinite cannot be acted upon by the finite.) Let A be an 
infinite, B a finite, C the time of a given movement produced by one 
in the other. Suppose, then, that A was heated, or impelled, or 
modified in any way, or caused to undergo any sort of movement 
whatever, by in the time C. Let D be less than B; and, assuming that a 
lesser agent moves a lesser patient in an equal time, call the quantity 
thus modified by D, E. Then, as D is to B, so is E to some finite 
quantum. We assume that the alteration of equal by equal takes 
equal time, and the alteration of less by less or of greater by greater 
takes the same time, if the quantity of the patient is such as to keep 
the proportion which obtains between the agents, greater and less. If 
so, no movement can be caused in the infinite by any finite agent in 
any time whatever. For a less agent will produce that movement in a 
less patient in an equal time, and the proportionate equivalent of 



867 



that patient will be a finite quantity, since no proportion holds 
between finite and infinite. 

(2. The infinite cannot act upon the finite.) Nor, again, can the infinite 
produce a movement in the finite in any time whatever. Let A be an 
infinite, B a finite, C the time of action. In the time C, D will produce 
that motion in a patient less than B, say F. Then take E, bearing the 
same proportion to D as the whole BF bears to F. E will produce the 
motion in BF in the time C. Thus the finite and infinite effect the 
same alteration in equal times. But this is impossible; for the 
assumption is that the greater effects it in a shorter time. It will be 
the same with any time that can be taken, so that there will no time 
in which the infinite can effect this movement. And, as to infinite 
time, in that nothing can move another or be moved by it. For such 
time has no limit, while the action and reaction have. 

(3. There is no interaction between infinites.) Nor can infinite be 
acted upon in any way by infinite. Let A and B be infinites, CD being 
the time of the action A of upon B. Now the whole B was modified in 
a certain time, and the part of this infinite, E, cannot be so modified 
in the same time, since we assume that a less quantity makes the 
movement in a less time. Let E then, when acted upon by A, complete 
the movement in the time D. Then, as D is to CD, so is E to some finite 
part of B. This part will necessarily be moved by A in the time CD. For 
we suppose that the same agent produces a given effect on a greater 
and a smaller mass in longer and shorter times, the times and 
masses varying proportionately. There is thus no finite time in which 
infinites can move one another. Is their time then infinite? No, for 
infinite time has no end, but the movement communicated has. 

If therefore every perceptible body possesses the power of acting or of 
being acted upon, or both of these, it is impossible that an infinite 
body should be perceptible. All bodies, however, that occupy place are 
perceptible. There is therefore no infinite body beyond the heaven. 
Nor again is there anything of limited extent beyond it. And so 
beyond the heaven there is no body at all. For if you suppose it an 
object of intelligence, it will be in a place - since place is what 



868 



'within' and 'beyond' denote - and therefore an object of perception. 
But nothing that is not in a place is perceptible. 

The question may also be examined in the light of more general 
considerations as follows. The infinite, considered as a whole of 
similar parts, cannot, on the one hand, move in a circle. For there is 
no centre of the infinite, and that which moves in a circle moves 
about the centre. Nor again can the infinite move in a straight line. 
For there would have to be another place infinite like itself to be the 
goal of its natural movement and another, equally great, for the goal 
of its unnatural movement. Moreover, whether its rectilinear 
movement is natural or constrained, in either case the force which 
causes its motion will have to be infinite. For infinite force is force of 
an infinite body, and of an infinite body the force is infinite. So the 
motive body also will be infinite. (The proof of this is given in our 
discussion of movement, where it is shown that no finite thing 
possesses infinite power, and no infinite thing finite power.) If then 
that which moves naturally can also move unnaturally, there will be 
two infinites, one which causes, and another which exhibits the 
latter motion. Again, what is it that moves the infinite? If it moves 
itself, it must be animate. But how can it possibly be conceived as an 
infinite animal? And if there is something else that moves it, there 
will be two infinites, that which moves and that which is moved, 
differing in their form and power. 

If the whole is not continuous, but exists, as Democritus and 
Leucippus think, in the form of parts separated by void, there must 
necessarily be one movement of all the multitude. They are 
distinguished, we are told, from one another by their figures; but 
their nature is one, like many pieces of gold separated from one 
another. But each piece must, as we assert, have the same motion. 
For a single clod moves to the same place as the whole mass of earth, 
and a spark to the same place as the whole mass of fire. So that if it 
be weight that all possess, no body is, strictly speaking, light: and if 
lightness be universal, none is heavy. Moreover, whatever possesses 
weight or lightness will have its place either at one of the extremes 
or in the middle region. But this is impossible while the world is 
conceived as infinite. And, generally, that which has no centre or 



869 



extreme limit, no up or down, gives the bodies no place for their 
motion; and without that movement is impossible. A thing must 
move either naturally or unnaturally, and the two movements are 
determined by the proper and alien places. Again, a place in which a 
thing rests or to which it moves unnaturally, must be the natural 
place for some other body, as experience shows. Necessarily, 
therefore, not everything possesses weight or lightness, but some 
things do and some do not. From these arguments then it is clear 
that the body of the universe is not infinite. 



8 

We must now proceed to explain why there cannot be more than one 
heaven - the further question mentioned above. For it may be 
thought that we have not proved universal of bodies that none 
whatever can exist outside our universe, and that our argument 
applied only to those of indeterminate extent. 

Now all things rest and move naturally and by constraint. A thing 
moves naturally to a place in which it rests without constraint, and 
rests naturally in a place to which it moves without constraint. On 
the other hand, a thing moves by constraint to a place in which it 
rests by constraint, and rests by constraint in a place to which it 
moves by constraint. Further, if a given movement is due to 
constraint, its contrary is natural. If, then, it is by constraint that 
earth moves from a certain place to the centre here, its movement 
from here to there will be natural, and if earth from there rests here 
without constraint, its movement hither will be natural. And the 
natural movement in each case is one. Further, these worlds, being 
similar in nature to ours, must all be composed of the same bodies as 
it. Moreover each of the bodies, fire, I mean, and earth and their 
intermediates, must have the same power as in our world. For if 
these names are used equivocally, if the identity of name does not 
rest upon an identity of form in these elements and ours, then the 
whole to which they belong can only be called a world by 



870 



equivocation. Clearly, then, one of the bodies will move naturally 
away from the centre and another towards the centre, since fire must 
be identical with fire, earth with earth, and so on, as the fragments of 
each are identical in this world. That this must be the case is evident 
from the principles laid down in our discussion of the movements, 
for these are limited in number, and the distinction of the elements 
depends upon the distinction of the movements. Therefore, since the 
movements are the same, the elements must also be the same 
everywhere. The particles of earth, then, in another world move 
naturally also to our centre and its fire to our circumference. This, 
however, is impossible, since, if it were true, earth must, in its own 
world, move upwards, and fire to the centre; in the same way the 
earth of our world must move naturally away from the centre when it 
moves towards the centre of another universe. This follows from the 
supposed juxtaposition of the worlds. For either we must refuse to 
admit the identical nature of the simple bodies in the various 
universes, or, admitting this, we must make the centre and the 
extremity one as suggested. This being so, it follows that there cannot 
be more worlds than one. 

To postulate a difference of nature in the simple bodies according as 
they are more or less distant from their proper places is 
unreasonable. For what difference can it make whether we say that a 
thing is this distance away or that? One would have to suppose a 
difference proportionate to the distance and increasing with it, but 
the form is in fact the same. Moreover, the bodies must have some 
movement, since the fact that they move is quite evident. Are we to 
say then that all their movements, even those which are mutually 
contrary, are due to constraint? No, for a body which has no natural 
movement at all cannot be moved by constraint. If then the bodies 
have a natural movement, the movement of the particular instances 
of each form must necessarily have for goal a place numerically one, 
i.e. a particular centre or a particular extremity. If it be suggested that 
the goal in each case is one in form but numerically more than one, 
on the analogy of particulars which are many though each 
undifferentiated in form, we reply that the variety of goal cannot be 
limited to this portion or that but must extend to all alike. For all are 
equally undifferentiated in form, but any one is different numerically 



871 



from any other. What I mean is this: if the portions in this world 
behave similarly both to one another and to those in another world, 
then the portion which is taken hence will not behave differently 
either from the portions in another world or from those in the same 
world, but similarly to them, since in form no portion differs from 
another. The result is that we must either abandon our present 
assumption or assert that the centre and the extremity are each 
numerically one. But this being so, the heaven, by the same evidence 
and the same necessary inferences, must be one only and no more. 

A consideration of the other kinds of movement also makes it plain 
that there is some point to which earth and fire move naturally. For 
in general that which is moved changes from something into 
something, the starting-point and the goal being different in form, 
and always it is a finite change. For instance, to recover health is to 
change from disease to health, to increase is to change from 
smallness to greatness. Locomotion must be similar: for it also has its 
goal and starting-point - and therefore the starting-point and the 
goal of the natural movement must differ in form - just as the 
movement of coming to health does not take any direction which 
chance or the wishes of the mover may select. Thus, too, fire and 
earth move not to infinity but to opposite points; and since the 
opposition in place is between above and below, these will be the 
limits of their movement. (Even in circular movement there is a sort 
of opposition between the ends of the diameter, though the 
movement as a whole has no contrary: so that here too the 
movement has in a sense an opposed and finite goal.) There must 
therefore be some end to locomotion: it cannot continue to infinity. 

This conclusion that local movement is not continued to infinity is 
corroborated by the fact that earth moves more quickly the nearer it 
is to the centre, and fire the nearer it is to the upper place. But if 
movement were infinite speed would be infinite also; and if speed 
then weight and lightness. For as superior speed in downward 
movement implies superior weight, so infinite increase of weight 
necessitates infinite increase of speed. 



872 



Further, it is not the action of another body that makes one of these 
bodies move up and the other down; nor is it constraint, like the 
'extrusion' of some writers. For in that case the larger the mass of fire 
or earth the slower would be the upward or downward movement; 
but the fact is the reverse: the greater the mass of fire or earth the 
quicker always is its movement towards its own place. Again, the 
speed of the movement would not increase towards the end if it were 
due to constraint or extrusion; for a constrained movement always 
diminishes in speed as the source of constraint becomes more 
distant, and a body moves without constraint to the place whence it 
was moved by constraint. 

A consideration of these points, then, gives adequate assurance of 
the truth of our contentions. The same could also be shown with the 
aid of the discussions which fall under First Philosophy, as well as 
from the nature of the circular movement, which must be eternal 
both here and in the other worlds. It is plain, too, from the following 
considerations that the universe must be one. 

The bodily elements are three, and therefore the places of the 
elements will be three also; the place, first, of the body which sinks to 
the bottom, namely the region about the centre; the place, secondly, 
of the revolving body, namely the outermost place, and thirdly, the 
intermediate place, belonging to the intermediate body. Here in this 
third place will be the body which rises to the surface; since, if not 
here, it will be elsewhere, and it cannot be elsewhere: for we have 
two bodies, one weightless, one endowed with weight, and below is 
place of the body endowed with weight, since the region about the 
centre has been given to the heavy body. And its position cannot be 
unnatural to it, for it would have to be natural to something else, and 
there is nothing else. It must then occupy the intermediate place. 
What distinctions there are within the intermediate itself we will 
explain later on. 

We have now said enough to make plain the character and number of 
the bodily elements, the place of each, and further, in general, how 
many in number the various places are. 



873 



We must show not only that the heaven is one, but also that more 
than one heaven is and, further, that, as exempt from decay and 
generation, the heaven is eternal. We may begin by raising a 
difficulty. From one point of view it might seem impossible that the 
heaven should be one and unique, since in all formations and 
products whether of nature or of art we can distinguish the shape in 
itself and the shape in combination with matter. For instance the 
form of the sphere is one thing and the gold or bronze sphere 
another; the shape of the circle again is one thing, the bronze or 
wooden circle another. For when we state the essential nature of the 
sphere or circle we do not include in the formula gold or bronze, 
because they do not belong to the essence, but if we are speaking of 
the copper or gold sphere we do include them. We still make the 
distinction even if we cannot conceive or apprehend any other 
example beside the particular thing. This may, of course, sometimes 
be the case: it might be, for instance, that only one circle could be 
found; yet none the less the difference will remain between the being 
of circle and of this particular circle, the one being form, the other 
form in matter, i.e. a particular thing. Now since the universe is 
perceptible it must be regarded as a particular; for everything that is 
perceptible subsists, as we know, in matter. But if it is a particular, 
there will be a distinction between the being of 'this universe' and of 
'universe' unqualified. There is a difference, then, between 'this 
universe' and simple 'universe'; the second is form and shape, the 
first form in combination with matter; and any shape or form has, or 
may have, more than one particular instance. 

On the supposition of Forms such as some assert, this must be the 
case, and equally on the view that no such entity has a separate 
existence. For in every case in which the essence is in matter it is a 
fact of observation that the particulars of like form are several or 
infinite in number. Hence there either are, or may be, more heavens 
than one. On these grounds, then, it might be inferred either that 
there are or that there might be several heavens. We must, however, 



874 



return and ask how much of this argument is correct and how much 
not. 

Now it is quite right to say that the formula of the shape apart from 
the matter must be different from that of the shape in the matter, 
and we may allow this to be true. We are not, however, therefore 
compelled to assert a plurality of worlds. Such a plurality is in fact 
impossible if this world contains the entirety of matter, as in fact it 
does. But perhaps our contention can be made clearer in this way. 
Suppose 'aquilinity' to be curvature in the nose or flesh, and flesh to 
be the matter of aquilinity. Suppose further, that all flesh came 
together into a single whole of flesh endowed with this aquiline 
quality. Then neither would there be, nor could there arise, any other 
thing that was aquiline. Similarly, suppose flesh and bones to be the 
matter of man, and suppose a man to be created of all flesh and all 
bones in indissoluble union. The possibility of another man would be 
removed. Whatever case you took it would be the same. The general 
rule is this: a thing whose essence resides in a substratum of matter 
can never come into being in the absence of all matter. Now the 
universe is certainly a particular and a material thing: if however, it is 
composed not of a part but of the whole of matter, then though the 
being of 'universe' and of 'this universe' are still distinct, yet there is 
no other universe, and no possibility of others being made, because 
all the matter is already included in this. It remains, then, only to 
prove that it is composed of all natural perceptible body. 

First, however, we must explain what we mean by 'heaven' and in 
how many senses we use the word, in order to make clearer the 
object of our inquiry, (a) In one sense, then, we call 'heaven' the 
substance of the extreme circumference of the whole, or that natural 
body whose place is at the extreme circumference. We recognize 
habitually a special right to the name 'heaven' in the extremity or 
upper region, which we take to be the seat of all that is divine, (b) In 
another sense, we use this name for the body continuous with the 
extreme circumference which contains the moon, the sun, and some 
of the stars; these we say are 'in the heaven', (c) In yet another sense 
we give the name to all body included within extreme circumference, 



875 



since we habitually call the whole or totality 'the heaven'. The word, 
then, is used in three senses. 

Now the whole included within the extreme circumference must be 
composed of all physical and sensible body, because there neither is, 
nor can come into being, any body outside the heaven. For if there is 
a natural body outside the extreme circumference it must be either a 
simple or a composite body, and its position must be either natural or 
unnatural. But it cannot be any of the simple bodies. For, first, it has 
been shown that that which moves in a circle cannot change its 
place. And, secondly, it cannot be that which moves from the centre 
or that which lies lowest. Naturally they could not be there, since 
their proper places are elsewhere; and if these are there unnaturally, 
the exterior place will be natural to some other body, since a place 
which is unnatural to one body must be natural to another: but we 
saw that there is no other body besides these. Then it is not possible 
that any simple body should be outside the heaven. But, if no simple 
body, neither can any mixed body be there: for the presence of the 
simple body is involved in the presence of the mixture. Further 
neither can any body come into that place: for it will do so either 
naturally or unnaturally, and will be either simple or composite; so 
that the same argument will apply, since it makes no difference 
whether the question is 'does A exist?' or 'could A come to exist?' 
From our arguments then it is evident not only that there is not, but 
also that there could never come to be, any bodily mass whatever 
outside the circumference. The world as a whole, therefore, includes 
all its appropriate matter, which is, as we saw, natural perceptible 
body. So that neither are there now, nor have there ever been, nor can 
there ever be formed more heavens than one, but this heaven of ours 
is one and unique and complete. 

It is therefore evident that there is also no place or void or time 
outside the heaven. For in every place body can be present; and void 
is said to be that in which the presence of body, though not actual, is 
possible; and time is the number of movement. But in the absence of 
natural body there is no movement, and outside the heaven, as we 
have shown, body neither exists nor can come to exist. It is clear then 
that there is neither place, nor void, nor time, outside the heaven. 



876 



Hence whatever is there, is of such a nature as not to occupy any 
place, nor does time age it; nor is there any change in any of the 
things which lie beyond the outermost motion; they continue 
through their entire duration unalterable and unmodified, living the 
best and most selfsufficient of lives. As a matter of fact, this word 
'duration' possessed a divine significance for the ancients, for the 
fulfilment which includes the period of life of any creature, outside of 
which no natural development can fall, has been called its duration. 
On the same principle the fulfilment of the whole heaven, the 
fulfilment which includes all time and infinity, is 'duration' - a name 
based upon the fact that it is always - duration immortal and divine. 
From it derive the being and life which other things, some more or 
less articulately but others feebly, enjoy. So, too, in its discussions 
concerning the divine, popular philosophy often propounds the view 
that whatever is divine, whatever is primary and supreme, is 
necessarily unchangeable. This fact confirms what we have said. For 
there is nothing else stronger than it to move it - since that would 
mean more divine - and it has no defect and lacks none of its proper 
excellences. Its unceasing movement, then, is also reasonable, since 
everything ceases to move when it comes to its proper place, but the 
body whose path is the circle has one and the same place for 
starting-point and goal. 



10 

Having established these distinctions, we may now proceed to the 
question whether the heaven is ungenerated or generated, 
indestructible or destructible. Let us start with a review of the 
theories of other thinkers; for the proofs of a theory are difficulties 
for the contrary theory. Besides, those who have first heard the pleas 
of our adversaries will be more likely to credit the assertions which 
we are going to make. We shall be less open to the charge of 
procuring judgement by default. To give a satisfactory decision as to 
the truth it is necessary to be rather an arbitrator than a party to the 
dispute. 



877 



That the world was generated all are agreed, but, generation over, 
some say that it is eternal, others say that it is destructible like any 
other natural formation. Others again, with Empedliocles of Acragas 
and Heraclitus of Ephesus, believe that there is alternation in the 
destructive process, which takes now this direction, now that, and 
continues without end. 

Now to assert that it was generated and yet is eternal is to assert the 
impossible; for we cannot reasonably attribute to anything any 
characteristics but those which observation detects in many or all 
instances. But in this case the facts point the other way: generated 
things are seen always to be destroyed. Further, a thing whose 
present state had no beginning and which could not have been other 
than it was at any previous moment throughout its entire duration, 
cannot possibly be changed. For there will have to be some cause of 
change, and if this had been present earlier it would have made 
possible another condition of that to which any other condition was 
impossible. Suppose that the world was formed out of elements 
which were formerly otherwise conditioned than as they are now. 
Then (1) if their condition was always so and could not have been 
otherwise, the world could never have come into being. And (2) if the 
world did come into being, then, clearly, their condition must have 
been capable of change and not eternal: after combination therefore 
they will be dispersed, just as in the past after dispersion they came 
into combination, and this process either has been, or could have 
been, indefinitely repeated. But if this is so, the world cannot be 
indestructible, and it does not matter whether the change of 
condition has actually occurred or remains a possibility. 

Some of those who hold that the world, though indestructible, was 
yet generated, try to support their case by a parallel which is illusory 
They say that in their statements about its generation they are doing 
what geometricians do when they construct their figures, not 
implying that the universe really had a beginning, but for didactic 
reasons facilitating understanding by exhibiting the object, like the 
figure, as in course of formation. The two cases, as we said, are not 
parallel; for, in the construction of the figure, when the various steps 
are completed the required figure forthwith results; but in these 



878 



other demonstrations what results is not that which was required. 
Indeed it cannot be so; for antecedent and consequent, as assumed, 
are in contradiction. The ordered, it is said, arose out of the 
unordered; and the same thing cannot be at the same time both 
ordered and unordered; there must be a process and a lapse of time 
separating the two states. In the figure, on the other hand, there is no 
temporal separation. It is clear then that the universe cannot be at 
once eternal and generated. 

To say that the universe alternately combines and dissolves is no 
more paradoxical than to make it eternal but varying in shape. It is as 
if one were to think that there was now destruction and now 
existence when from a child a man is generated, and from a man a 
child. For it is clear that when the elements come together the result 
is not a chance system and combination, but the very same as before 
- especially on the view of those who hold this theory, since they say 
that the contrary is the cause of each state. So that if the totality of 
body, which is a continuum, is now in this order or disposition and 
now in that, and if the combination of the whole is a world or 
heaven, then it will not be the world that comes into being and is 
destroyed, but only its dispositions. 

If the world is believed to be one, it is impossible to suppose that it 
should be, as a whole, first generated and then destroyed, never to 
reappear; since before it came into being there was always present 
the combination prior to it, and that, we hold, could never change if it 
was never generated. If, on the other hand, the worlds are infinite in 
number the view is more plausible. But whether this is, or is not, 
impossible will be clear from what follows. For there are some who 
think it possible both for the ungenerated to be destroyed and for the 
generated to persist undestroyed. (This is held in the Timaeus, where 
Plato says that the heaven, though it was generated, will none the 
less exist to eternity.) So far as the heaven is concerned we have 
answered this view with arguments appropriate to the nature of the 
heaven: on the general question we shall attain clearness when we 
examine the matter universally. 



879 



11 

We must first distinguish the senses in which we use the words 
'ungenerated' and 'generated', 'destructible' and 'indestructible'. 
These have many meanings, and though it may make no difference 
to the argument, yet some confusion of mind must result from 
treating as uniform in its use a word which has several distinct 
applications. The character which is the ground of the predication 
will always remain obscure. 

The word 'ungenerated' then is used (a) in one sense whenever 
something now is which formerly was not, no process of becoming or 
change being involved. Such is the case, according to some, with 
contact and motion, since there is no process of coming to be in 
contact or in motion, (b) It is used in another sense, when something 
which is capable of coming to be, with or without process, does not 
exist; such a thing is ungenerated in the sense that its generation is 
not a fact but a possibility, (c) It is also applied where there is general 
impossibility of any generation such that the thing now is which 
then was not. And 'impossibility' has two uses: first, where it is 
untrue to say that the thing can ever come into being, and secondly, 
where it cannot do so easily, quickly, or well. In the same way the 
word 'generated' is used, (a) first, where what formerly was not 
afterwards is, whether a process of becoming was or was not 
involved, so long as that which then was not, now is; (b) secondly, of 
anything capable of existing, 'capable' being defined with reference 
either to truth or to facility; (c) thirdly, of anything to which the 
passage from not being to being belongs, whether already actual, if 
its existence is due to a past process of becoming, or not yet actual 
but only possible. The uses of the words 'destructible' and 
'indestructible' are similar. 'Destructible' is applied (a) to that which 
formerly was and afterwards either is not or might not be, whether a 
period of being destroyed and changed intervenes or not; and (b) 
sometimes we apply the word to that which a process of destruction 
may cause not to be; and also (c) in a third sense, to that which is 
easily destructible, to the 'easily destroyed', so to speak. Of the 



880 



indestructible the same account holds good. It is either (a) that which 
now is and now is not, without any process of destruction, like 
contact, which without being destroyed afterwards is not, though 
formerly it was; or (b) that which is but might not be, or which will at 
some time not be, though it now is. For you exist now and so does the 
contact; yet both are destructible, because a time will come when it 
will not be true of you that you exist, nor of these things that they are 
in contact. Thirdly (c) in its most proper use, it is that which is, but is 
incapable of any destruction such that the thing which now is later 
ceases to be or might cease to be; or again, that which has not yet 
been destroyed, but in the future may cease to be. For indestructible 
is also used of that which is destroyed with difficulty. 

This being so, we must ask what we mean by 'possible' and 
'impossible'. For in its most proper use the predicate 'indestructible' 
is given because it is impossible that the thing should be destroyed, 
i.e. exist at one time and not at another. And 'ungenerated' also 
involves impossibility when used for that which cannot be generated, 
in such fashion that, while formerly it was not, later it is. An instance 
is a commensurable diagonal. Now when we speak of a power to 
move or to lift weights, we refer always to the maximum. We speak, 
for instance, of a power to lift a hundred talents or walk a hundred 
stades - though a power to effect the maximum is also a power to 
effect any part of the maximum - since we feel obliged in defining 
the power to give the limit or maximum. A thing, then, which is 
within it. If, for example, a man can lift a hundred talents, he can also 
lift two, and if he can walk a hundred stades, he can also walk two. 
But the power is of the maximum, and a thing said, with reference to 
its maximum, to be incapable of so much is also incapable of any 
greater amount. It is, for instance, clear that a person who cannot 
walk a thousand stades will also be unable to walk a thousand and 
one. This point need not trouble us, for we may take it as settled that 
what is, in the strict sense, possible is determined by a limiting 
maximum. Now perhaps the objection might be raised that there is 
no necessity in this, since he who sees a stade need not see the 
smaller measures contained in it, while, on the contrary, he who can 
see a dot or hear a small sound will perceive what is greater. This, 
however, does not touch our argument. The maximum may be 



881 



determined either in the power or in its object. The application of this 
is plain. Superior sight is sight of the smaller body, but superior speed 
is that of the greater body. 



12 

Having established these distinctions we car now proceed to the 
sequel. If there are thing! capable both of being and of not being, 
there must be some definite maximum time of their being and not 
being; a time, I mean, during which continued existence is possible to 
them and a time during which continued nonexistence is possible. 
And this is true in every category, whether the thing is, for example, 
'man', or 'white', or 'three cubits long', or whatever it may be. For if 
the time is not definite in quantity, but longer than any that can be 
suggested and shorter than none, then it will be possible for one and 
the same thing to exist for infinite time and not to exist for another 
infinity. This, however, is impossible. 

Let us take our start from this point. The impossible and the false 
have not the same significance. One use of 'impossible' and 'possible', 
and 'false' and 'true', is hypothetical. It is impossible, for instance, on 
a certain hypothesis that the triangle should have its angles equal to 
two right angles, and on another the diagonal is commensurable. But 
there are also things possible and impossible, false and true, 
absolutely. Now it is one thing to be absolutely false, and another 
thing to be absolutely impossible. To say that you are standing when 
you are not standing is to assert a falsehood, but not an impossibility. 
Similarly to say that a man who is playing the harp, but not singing, 
is singing, is to say what is false but not impossible. To say, however, 
that you are at once standing and sitting, or that the diagonal is 
commensurable, is to say what is not only false but also impossible. 
Thus it is not the same thing to make a false and to make an 
impossible hypothesis, and from the impossible hypothesis 
impossible results follow. A man has, it is true, the capacity at once of 
sitting and of standing, because when he possesses the one he also 



882 



possesses the other; but it does not follow that he can at once sit and 
stand, only that at another time he can do the other also. But if a 
thing has for infinite time more than one capacity, another time is 
impossible and the times must coincide. Thus if a thing which exists 
for infinite time is destructible, it will have the capacity of not being. 
Now if it exists for infinite time let this capacity be actualized; and it 
will be in actuality at once existent and non-existent. Thus a false 
conclusion would follow because a false assumption was made, but if 
what was assumed had not been impossible its consequence would 
not have been impossible. 

Anything then which always exists is absolutely imperishable. It is 
also ungenerated, since if it was generated it will have the power for 
some time of not being. For as that which formerly was, but now is 
not, or is capable at some future time of not being, is destructible, so 
that which is capable of formerly not having been is generated. But in 
the case of that which always is, there is no time for such a capacity 
of not being, whether the supposed time is finite or infinite; for its 
capacity of being must include the finite time since it covers infinite 
time. 

It is therefore impossible that one and the same thing should be 
capable of always existing and of always not-existing. And 'not 
always existing', the contradictory, is also excluded. Thus it is 
impossible for a thing always to exist and yet to be destructible. Nor, 
similarly, can it be generated. For of two attributes if B cannot be 
present without A, the impossibility A of proves the impossibility of 
B. What always is, then, since it is incapable of ever not being, cannot 
possibly be generated. But since the contradictory of 'that which is 
always capable of being' 'that which is not always capable of being'; 
while 'that which is always capable of not being' is the contrary, 
whose contradictory in turn is 'that which is not always capable of 
not being', it is necessary that the contradictories of both terms 
should be predicable of one and the same thing, and thus that, 
intermediate between what always is and what always is not, there 
should be that to which being and not-being are both possible; for 
the contradictory of each will at times be true of it unless it always 
exists. Hence that which not always is not will sometimes be and 



883 



sometimes not be; and it is clear that this is true also of that which 
cannot always be but sometimes is and therefore sometimes is not. 
One thing, then, will have the power of being, and will thus be 
intermediate between the other two. 

Expresed universally our argument is as follows. Let there be two 
attributes, A and B, not capable of being present in any one thing 
together, while either A or C and either B or D are capable of being 
present in everything. Then C and D must be predicated of everything 
of which neither A nor B is predicated. Let E lie between A and B; for 
that which is neither of two contraries is a mean between them. In E 
both C and D must be present, for either A or C is present everywhere 
and therefore in E. Since then A is impossible, C must be present, and 
the same argument holds of D. 

Neither that which always is, therefore, nor that which always is not 
is either generated or destructible. And clearly whatever is generated 
or destructible is not eternal. If it were, it would be at once capable of 
always being and capable of not always being, but it has already been 
shown that this is impossible. Surely then whatever is ungenerated 
and in being must be eternal, and whatever is indestructible and in 
being must equally be so. (I use the words 'ungenerated' and 
'indestructible' in their proper sense, 'ungenerated' for that which 
now is and could not at any previous time have been truly said not to 
be; 'indestructible' for that which now is and cannot at any future 
time be truly said not to be.) If, again, the two terms are coincident, if 
the ungenerated is indestructible, and the indestructible 
ungenearted, then each of them is coincident with 'eternal'; anything 
ungenerated is eternal and anything indestructible is eternal. This is 
clear too from the definition of the terms, Whatever is destructible 
must be generated; for it is either ungenerated, or generated, but, if 
ungenerated, it is by hypothesis indestructible. Whatever, further, is 
generated must be destructible. For it is either destructible or 
indestructible, but, if indestructible, it is by hypothesis ungenerated. 

If, however, 'indestructible' and 'ungenerated' are not coincident, 
there is no necessity that either the ungenerated or the 
indestructible should be eternal. But they must be coincident, for the 



884 



following reasons. The terms 'generated' and 'destructible' are 
coincident; this is obvious from our former remarks, since between 
what always is and what always is not there is an intermediate 
which is neither, and that intermediate is the generated and 
destructible. For whatever is either of these is capable both of being 
and of not being for a definite time: in either case, I mean, there is a 
certain period of time during which the thing is and another during 
which it is not. Anything therefore which is generated or destructible 
must be intermediate. Now let A be that which always is and B that 
which always is not, C the generated, and D the destructible. Then C 
must be intermediate between A and B. For in their case there is no 
time in the direction of either limit, in which either A is not or B is. 
But for the generated there must be such a time either actually or 
potentially, though not for A and B in either way. C then will be, and 
also not be, for a limited length of time, and this is true also of D, the 
destructible. Therefore each is both generated and destructible. 
Therefore 'generated' and 'destructible' are coincident. Now let E 
stand for the ungenerated, F for the generated, G for the 
indestructible, and H for the destructible. As for F and H, it has been 
shown that they are coincident. But when terms stand to one another 
as these do, F and H coincident, E and F never predicated of the same 
thing but one or other of everything, and G and H likewise, then E and 
G must needs be coincident. For suppose that E is not coincident with 
G, then F will be, since either E or F is predictable of everything. But of 
that of which F is predicated H will be predicable also. H will then be 
coincident with G, but this we saw to be impossible. And the same 
argument shows that G is coincident with E. 

Now the relation of the ungenerated (E) to the generated (F) is the 
same as that of the indestructible (G) to the destructible (H). To say 
then that there is no reason why anything should not be generated 
and yet indestructible or ungenerated and yet destroyed, to imagine 
that in the one case generation and in the other case destruction 
occurs once for all, is to destroy part of the data. For (1) everything is 
capable of acting or being acted upon, of being or not being, either for 
an infinite, or for a definitely limited space of time; and the infinite 
time is only a possible alternative because it is after a fashion 
defined, as a length of time which cannot be exceeded. But infinity in 



885 



one direction is neither infinite or finite. (2) Further, why, after always 
existing, was the thing destroyed, why, after an infinity of not being, 
was it generated, at one moment rather than another? If every 
moment is alike and the moments are infinite in number, it is clear 
that a generated or destructible thing existed for an infinite time. It 
has therefore for an infinite time the capacity of not being (since the 
capacity of being and the capacity of not being will be present 
together), if destructible, in the time before destruction, if generated, 
in the time after generation. If then we assume the two capacities to 
be actualized, opposites will be present together. (3) Further, this 
second capacity will be present like the first at every moment, so that 
the thing will have for an infinite time the capacity both of being and 
of not being; but this has been shown to be impossible. (4) Again, if 
the capacity is present prior to the activity, it will be present for all 
time, even while the thing was as yet ungenerated and non-existent, 
throughout the infinite time in which it was capable of being 
generated. At that time, then, when it was not, at that same time it 
had the capacity of being, both of being then and of being thereafter, 
and therefore for an infinity of time. 

It is clear also on other grounds that it is impossible that the 
destructible should not at some time be destroyed. For otherwise it 
will always be at once destructible and in actuality indestructible, so 
that it will be at the same time capable of always existing and of not 
always existing. Thus the destructible is at some time actually 
destroyed. The generable, similarly, has been generated, for it is 
capable of having been generated and thus also of not always 
existing. 

We may also see in the following way how impossible it is either for a 
thing which is generated to be thenceforward indestructible, or for a 
thing which is ungenerated and has always hitherto existed to be 
destroyed. Nothing that is by chance can be indestructible or 
ungenerated, since the products of chance and fortune are opposed 
to what is, or comes to be, always or usually, while anything which 
exists for a time infinite either absolutely or in one direction, is in 
existence either always or usually. That which is by chance, then, is 
by nature such as to exist at one time and not at another. But in 



886 



things of that character the contradictory states proceed from one 
and the same capacity, the matter of the thing being the cause 
equally of its existence and of its non-existence. Hence 
contradictories would be present together in actuality. 

Further, it cannot truly be said of a thing now that it exists last year, 
nor could it be said last year that it exists now. It is therefore 
impossible for what once did not exist later to be eternal. For in its 
later state it will possess the capacity of not existing, only not of not 
existing at a time when it exists - since then it exists in actuality - 
but of not existing last year or in the past. Now suppose it to be in 
actuality what it is capable of being. It will then be true to say now 
that it does not exist last year. But this is impossible. No capacity 
relates to being in the past, but always to being in the present or 
future. It is the same with the notion of an eternity of existence 
followed later by non-existence. In the later state the capacity will be 
present for that which is not there in actuality. Actualize, then, the 
capacity. It will be true to say now that this exists last year or in the 
past generally. 

Considerations also not general like these but proper to the subject 
show it to be impossible that what was formerly eternal should later 
be destroyed or that what formerly was not should later be eternal. 
Whatever is destructible or generated is always alterable. Now 
alteration is due to contraries, and the things which compose the 
natural body are the very same that destroy it. 



Book II 



887 



That the heaven as a whole neither came into being nor admits of 
destruction, as some assert, but is one and eternal, with no end or 
beginning of its total duration, containing and embracing in itself the 
infinity of time, we may convince ourselves not only by the 
arguments already set forth but also by a consideration of the views 
of those who differ from us in providing for its generation. If our view 
is a possible one, and the manner of generation which they assert is 
impossible, this fact will have great weight in convincing us of the 
immortality and eternity of the world. Hence it is well to persuade 
oneself of the truth of the ancient and truly traditional theories, that 
there is some immortal and divine thing which possesses movement, 
but movement such as has no limit and is rather itself the limit of all 
other movement. A limit is a thing which contains; and this motion, 
being perfect, contains those imperfect motions which have a limit 
and a goal, having itself no beginning or end, but unceasing through 
the infinity of time, and of other movements, to some the cause of 
their beginning, to others offering the goal. The ancients gave to the 
Gods the heaven or upper place, as being alone immortal; and our 
present argument testifies that it is indestructible and ungenerated. 
Further, it is unaffected by any mortal discomfort, and, in addition, 
effortless; for it needs no constraining necessity to keep it to its path, 
and prevent it from moving with some other movement more natural 
to itself. Such a constrained movement would necessarily involve 
effort the more so, the more eternal it were - and would be 
inconsistent with perfection. Hence we must not believe the old tale 
which says that the world needs some Atlas to keep it safe - a tale 
composed, it would seem, by men who, like later thinkers, conceived 
of all the upper bodies as earthy and endowed with weight, and 
therefore supported it in their fabulous way upon animate necessity. 
We must no more believe that than follow Empedocles when he says 
that the world, by being whirled round, received a movement quick 
enough to overpower its own downward tendency, and thus has been 
kept from destruction all this time. Nor, again, is it conceivable that it 
should persist eternally by the necessitation of a soul. For a soul 
could not live in such conditions painlessly or happily, since the 
movement involves constraint, being imposed on the first body, 



888 



whose natural motion is different, and imposed continuously. It must 
therefore be uneasy and devoid of all rational satisfaction; for it could 
not even, like the soul of mortal animals, take recreation in the bodily 
relaxation of sleep. An Ixion's lot must needs possess it, without end 
or respite. If then, as we said, the view already stated of the first 
motion is a possible one, it is not only more appropriate so to 
conceive of its eternity, but also on this hypothesis alone are we able 
to advance a theory consistent with popular divinations of the divine 
nature. But of this enough for the present. 



Since there are some who say that there is a right and a left in the 
heaven, with those who are known as Pythagoreans - to whom 
indeed the view really belongs - we must consider whether, if we are 
to apply these principles to the body of the universe, we should 
follow their statement of the matter or find a better way. At the start 
we may say that, if right and left are applicable, there are prior 
principles which must first be applied. These principles have been 
analysed in the discussion of the movements of animals, for the 
reason that they are proper to animal nature. For in some animals we 
find all such distinctions of parts as this of right and left clearly 
present, and in others some; but in plants we find only above and 
below. Now if we are to apply to the heaven such a distinction of 
parts, we must exect, as we have said, to find in it also the distinction 
which in animals is found first of them all. The distinctions are three, 
namely, above and below, front and its opposite, right and left - all 
these three oppositions we expect to find in the perfect body - and 
each may be called a principle. Above is the principle of length, right 
of breadth, front of depth. Or again we may connect them with the 
various movements, taking principle to mean that part, in a thing 
capable of movement, from which movement first begins. Growth 
starts from above, locomotion from the right, sensemovement from 
in front (for front is simply the part to which the senses are directed). 
Hence we must not look for above and below, right and left, front and 



889 



back, in every kind of body, but only in those which, being animate, 
have a principle of movement within themselves. For in no inanimate 
thing do we observe a part from which movement originates. Some 
do not move at all, some move, but not indifferently in any direction; 
fire, for example, only upward, and earth only to the centre. It is true 
that we speak of above and below, right and left, in these bodies 
relatively to ourselves. The reference may be to our own right hands, 
as with the diviner, or to some similarity to our own members, such 
as the parts of a statue possess; or we may take the contrary spatial 
order, calling right that which is to our left, and left that which is to 
our right. We observe, however, in the things themselves none of 
these distinctions; indeed if they are turned round we proceed to 
speak of the opposite parts as right and left, a boy land below, front 
and back. Hence it is remarkable that the Pythagoreans should have 
spoken of these two principles, right and left, only, to the exclusion of 
the other four, which have as good a title as they. There is no less 
difference between above and below or front and back in animals 
generally than between right and left. The difference is sometimes 
only one of function, sometimes also one of shape; and while the 
distinction of above and below is characteristic of all animate things, 
whether plants or animals, that of right and left is not found in 
plants. Further, inasmuch as length is prior to breadth, if above is the 
principle of length, right of breadth, and if the principle of that which 
is prior is itself prior, then above will be prior to right, or let us say, 
since 'prior' is ambiguous, prior in order of generation. If, in addition, 
above is the region from which movement originates, right the region 
in which it starts, front the region to which it is directed, then on this 
ground too above has a certain original character as compared with 
the other forms of position. On these two grounds, then, they may 
fairly be criticized, first, for omitting the more fundamental 
principles, and secondly, for thinking that the two they mentioned 
were attributable equally to everything. 

Since we have already determined that functions of this kind belong 
to things which possess, a principle of movement, and that the 
heaven is animate and possesses a principle of movement, clearly 
the heaven must also exhibit above and below, right and left. We need 
not be troubled by the question, arising from the spherical shape of 



890 



the world, how there can be a distinction of right and left within it, all 
parts being alike and all for ever in motion. We must think of the 
world as of something in which right differs from left in shape as 
well as in other respects, which subsequently is included in a sphere. 
The difference of function will persist, but will appear not to by 
reason of the regularity of shape. In the same fashion must we 
conceive of the beginning of its movement. For even if it never began 
to move, yet it must possess a principle from which it would have 
begun to move if it had begun, and from which it would begin again if 
it came to a stand. Now by its length I mean the interval between its 
poles, one pole being above and the other below; for two 
hemispheres are specially distinguished from all others by the 
immobility of the poles. Further, by 'transverse' in the universe we 
commonly mean, not above and below, but a direction crossing the 
line of the poles, which, by implication, is length: for transverse 
motion is motion crossing motion up and down. Of the poles, that 
which we see above us is the lower region, and that which we do not 
see is the upper. For right in anything is, as we say, the region in 
which locomotion originates, and the rotation of the heaven 
originates in the region from which the stars rise. So this will be the 
right, and the region where they set the left. If then they begin from 
the right and move round to the right, the upper must be the unseen 
pole. For if it is the pole we see, the movement will be leftward, which 
we deny to be the fact. Clearly then the invisible pole is above. And 
those who live in the other hemisphere are above and to the right, 
while we are below and to the left. This is just the opposite of the 
view of the Pythagoreans, who make us above and on the right side 
and those in the other hemisphere below and on the left side; the 
fact being the exact opposite. Relatively, however, to the secondary 
revolution, I mean that of the planets, we are above and on the right 
and they are below and on the left. For the principle of their 
movement has the reverse position, since the movement itself is the 
contrary of the other: hence it follows that we are at its beginning 
and they at its end. Here we may end our discussion of the 
distinctions of parts created by the three dimensions and of the 
consequent differences of position. 



891 



Since circular motion is not the contrary of the reverse circular 
motion, we must consider why there is more than one motion, 
though we have to pursue our inquiries at a distance - a distance 
created not so much by our spatial position as by the fact that our 
senses enable us to perceive very few of the attributes of the 
heavenly bodies. But let not that deter us. The reason must be sought 
in the following facts. Everything which has a function exists for its 
function. The activity of God is immortality, i.e. eternal life. Therefore 
the movement of that which is divine must be eternal. But such is the 
heaven, viz. a divine body, and for that reason to it is given the 
circular body whose nature it is to move always in a circle. Why, then, 
is not the whole body of the heaven of the same character as that 
part? Because there must be something at rest at the centre of the 
revolving body; and of that body no part can be at rest, either 
elsewhere or at the centre. It could do so only if the body's natural 
movement were towards the centre. But the circular movement is 
natural, since otherwise it could not be eternal: for nothing unnatural 
is eternal. The unnatural is subsequent to the natural, being a 
derangement of the natural which occurs in the course of its 
generation. Earth then has to exist; for it is earth which is at rest at 
the centre. (At present we may take this for granted: it shall be 
explained later.) But if earth must exist, so must fire. For, if one of a 
pair of contraries naturally exists, the other, if it is really contrary, 
exists also naturally. In some form it must be present, since the 
matter of contraries is the same. Also, the positive is prior to its 
privation (warm, for instance, to cold), and rest and heaviness stand 
for the privation of lightness and movement. But further, if fire and 
earth exist, the intermediate bodies must exist also: each element 
stands in a contrary relation to every other. (This, again, we will here 
take for granted and try later to explain.) these four elements 
generation clearly is involved, since none of them can be eternal: for 
contraries interact with one another and destroy one another. 
Further, it is inconceivable that a movable body should be eternal, if 
its movement cannot be regarded as naturally eternal: and these 



892 



bodies we know to possess movement. Thus we see that generation 
is necessarily involved. But if so, there must be at least one other 
circular motion: for a single movement of the whole heaven would 
necessitate an identical relation of the elements of bodies to one 
another. This matter also shall be cleared up in what follows: but for 
the present so much is clear, that the reason why there is more than 
one circular body is the necessity of generation, which follows on the 
presence of fire, which, with that of the other bodies, follows on that 
of earth; and earth is required because eternal movement in one 
body necessitates eternal rest in another. 



The shape of the heaven is of necessity spherical; for that is the 
shape most appropriate to its substance and also by nature primary 

First, let us consider generally which shape is primary among planes 
and solids alike. Every plane figure must be either rectilinear or 
curvilinear. Now the rectilinear is bounded by more than one line, the 
curvilinear by one only. But since in any kind the one is naturally 
prior to the many and the simple to the complex, the circle will be 
the first of plane figures. Again, if by complete, as previously defined, 
we mean a thing outside which no part of itself can be found, and if 
addition is always possible to the straight line but never to the 
circular, clearly the line which embraces the circle is complete. If 
then the complete is prior to the incomplete, it follows on this ground 
also that the circle is primary among figures. And the sphere holds 
the same position among solids. For it alone is embraced by a single 
surface, while rectilinear solids have several. The sphere is among 
solids what the circle is among plane figures. Further, those who 
divide bodies into planes and generate them out of planes seem to 
bear witness to the truth of this. Alone among solids they leave the 
sphere undivided, as not possessing more than one surface: for the 
division into surfaces is not just dividing a whole by cutting it into its 



893 



parts, but division of another fashion into parts different in form. It is 
clear, then, that the sphere is first of solid figures. 

If, again, one orders figures according to their numbers, it is most 
natural to arrange them in this way. The circle corresponds to the 
number one, the triangle, being the sum of two right angles, to the 
number two. But if one is assigned to the triangle, the circle will not 
be a figure at all. 

Now the first figure belongs to the first body, and the first body is that 
at the farthest circumference. It follows that the body which revolves 
with a circular movement must be spherical. The same then will be 
true of the body continuous with it: for that which is continuous with 
the spherical is spherical. The same again holds of the bodies 
between these and the centre. Bodies which are bounded by the 
spherical and in contact with it must be, as wholes, spherical; and 
the bodies below the sphere of the planets are contiguous with the 
sphere above them. The sphere then will be spherical throughout; for 
every body within it is contiguous and continuous with spheres. 

Again, since the whole revolves, palpably and by assumption, in a 
circle, and since it has been shown that outside the farthest 
circumference there is neither void nor place, from these grounds 
also it will follow necessarily that the heaven is spherical. For if it is 
to be rectilinear in shape, it will follow that there is place and body 
and void without it. For a rectilinear figure as it revolves never 
continues in the same room, but where formerly was body, is now 
none, and where now is none, body will be in a moment because of 
the projection at the corners. Similarly, if the world had some other 
figure with unequal radii, if, for instance, it were lentiform, or 
oviform, in every case we should have to admit space and void 
outside the moving body, because the whole body would not always 
occupy the same room. 

Again, if the motion of the heaven is the measure of all movements 
whatever in virtue of being alone continuous and regular and eternal, 
and if, in each kind, the measure is the minimum, and the minimum 
movement is the swiftest, then, clearly, the movement of the heaven 
must be the swiftest of all movements. Now of lines which return 



894 



upon themselves the line which bounds the circle is the shortest; and 
that movement is the swiftest which follows the shortest line. 
Therefore, if the heaven moves in a circle and moves more swiftly 
than anything else, it must necessarily be spherical. 

Corroborative evidence may be drawn from the bodies whose 
position is about the centre. If earth is enclosed by water, water by air, 
air by fire, and these similarly by the upper bodies - which while not 
continuous are yet contiguous with them - and if the surface of 
water is spherical, and that which is continuous with or embraces 
the spherical must itself be spherical, then on these grounds also it is 
clear that the heavens are spherical. But the surface of water is seen 
to be spherical if we take as our starting-point the fact that water 
naturally tends to collect in a hollow place - 'hollow' meaning 'nearer 
the centre'. Draw from the centre the lines AB, AC, and let their 
extremities be joined by the straight line BC. The line AD, drawn to 
the base of the triangle, will be shorter than either of the radii. 
Therefore the place in which it terminates will be a hollow place. The 
water then will collect there until equality is established, that is until 
the line AE is equal to the two radii. Thus water forces its way to the 
ends of the radii, and there only will it rest: but the line which 
connects the extremities of the radii is circular: therefore the surface 
of the water BEC is spherical. 

It is plain from the foregoing that the universe is spherical. It is plain, 
further, that it is turned (so to speak) with a finish which no 
manufactured thing nor anything else within the range of our 
observation can even approach. For the matter of which these are 
composed does not admit of anything like the same regularity and 
finish as the substance of the enveloping body; since with each step 
away from earth the matter manifestly becomes finer in the same 
proportion as water is finer than earth. 



895 



Now there are two ways of moving along a circle, from A to B or from 
A to C, and we have already explained that these movements are not 
contrary to one another. But nothing which concerns the eternal can 
be a matter of chance or spontaneity, and the heaven and its circular 
motion are eternal. We must therefore ask why this motion takes one 
direction and not the other. Either this is itself an ultimate fact or 
there is an ultimate fact behind it. It may seem evidence of excessive 
folly or excessive zeal to try to provide an explanation of some 
things, or of everything, admitting no exception. The criticism, 
however, is not always just: one should first consider what reason 
there is for speaking, and also what kind of certainty is looked for, 
whether human merely or of a more cogent kind. When any one shall 
succeed in finding proofs of greater precision, gratitude will be due to 
him for the discovery, but at present we must be content with a 
probable solution. If nature always follows the best course possible, 
and, just as upward movement is the superior form of rectilinear 
movement, since the upper region is more divine than the lower, so 
forward movement is superior to backward, then front and back 
exhibits, like right and left, as we said before and as the difficulty just 
stated itself suggests, the distinction of prior and posterior, which 
provides a reason and so solves our difficulty. Supposing that nature 
is ordered in the best way possible, this may stand as the reason of 
the fact mentioned. For it is best to move with a movement simple 
and unceasing, and, further, in the superior of two possible 
directions. 



We have next to show that the movement of the heaven is regular 
and not irregular. This applies only to the first heaven and the first 
movement; for the lower spheres exhibit a composition of several 
movements into one. If the movement is uneven, clearly there will be 
acceleration, maximum speed, and retardation, since these appear in 



896 



all irregular motions. The maximum may occur either at the starting- 
point or at the goal or between the two; and we expect natural 
motion to reach its maximum at the goal, unnatural motion at the 
starting-point, and missiles midway between the two. But circular 
movement, having no beginning or limit or middle in the direct sense 
of the words, has neither whence nor whither nor middle: for in time 
it is eternal, and in length it returns upon itself without a break. If 
then its movement has no maximum, it can have no irregularity, 
since irregularity is produced by retardation and acceleration. 
Further, since everything that is moved is moved by something, the 
cause of the irregularity of movement must lie either in the mover or 
in the moved or both. For if the mover moved not always with the 
same force, or if the moved were altered and did not remain the 
same, or if both were to change, the result might well be an irregular 
movement in the moved. But none of these possibilities can be 
conceived as actual in the case of the heavens. As to that which is 
moved, we have shown that it is primary and simple and 
ungenerated and indestructible and generally unchanging; and the 
mover has an even better right to these attributes. It is the primary 
that moves the primary, the simple the simple, the indestructible and 
ungenerated that which is indestructible and ungenerated. Since 
then that which is moved, being a body, is nevertheless unchanging, 
how should the mover, which is incorporeal, be changed? 

It follows then, further, that the motion cannot be irregular. For if 
irregularity occurs, there must be change either in the movement as 
a whole, from fast to slow and slow to fast, or in its parts. That there 
is no irregularity in the parts is obvious, since, if there were, some 
divergence of the stars would have taken place before now in the 
infinity of time, as one moved slower and another faster: but no 
alteration of their intervals is ever observed. Nor again is a change in 
the movement as a whole admissible. Retardation is always due to 
incapacity, and incapacity is unnatural. The incapacities of animals, 
age, decay, and the like, are all unnatural, due, it seems, to the fact 
that the whole animal complex is made up of materials which differ 
in respect of their proper places, and no single part occupies its own 
place. If therefore that which is primary contains nothing unnatural, 
being simple and unmixed and in its proper place and having no 



897 



contrary, then it has no place for incapacity, nor, consequently, for 
retardation or (since acceleration involves retardation) for 
acceleration. Again, it is inconceivable that the mover should first 
show incapacity for an infinite time, and capacity afterwards for 
another infinity. For clearly nothing which, like incapacity, unnatural 
ever continues for an infinity of time; nor does the unnatural endure 
as long as the natural, or any form of incapacity as long as the 
capacity. But if the movement is retarded it must necessarily be 
retarded for an infinite time. Equally impossible is perpetual 
acceleration or perpetual retardation. For such movement would be 
infinite and indefinite, but every movement, in our view, proceeds 
from one point to another and is definite in character. Again, suppose 
one assumes a minimum time in less than which the heaven could 
not complete its movement. For, as a given walk or a given exercise 
on the harp cannot take any and every time, but every performance 
has its definite minimum time which is unsurpassable, so, one might 
suppose, the movement of the heaven could not be completed in any 
and every time. But in that case perpetual acceleration is impossible 
(and, equally, perpetual retardation: for the argument holds of both 
and each), if we may take acceleration to proceed by identical or 
increasing additions of speed and for an infinite time. The remaining 
alternative is to say that the movement exhibits an alternation of 
slower and faster: but this is a mere fiction and quite inconceivable. 
Further, irregularity of this kind would be particularly unlikely to pass 
unobserved, since contrast makes observation easy. 

That there is one heaven, then, only, and that it is ungenerated and 
eternal, and further that its movement is regular, has now been 
sufficiently explained. 



We have next to speak of the stars, as they are called, of their 
composition, shape, and movements. It would be most natural and 
consequent upon what has been said that each of the stars should be 



898 



composed of that substance in which their path lies, since, as we 
said, there is an element whose natural movement is circular. In so 
saying we are only following the same line of thought as those who 
say that the stars are fiery because they believe the upper body to be 
fire, the presumption being that a thing is composed of the same 
stuff as that in which it is situated. The warmth and light which 
proceed from them are caused by the friction set up in the air by their 
motion. Movement tends to create fire in wood, stone, and iron; and 
with even more reason should it have that effect on air, a substance 
which is closer to fire than these. An example is that of missiles, 
which as they move are themselves fired so strongly that leaden balls 
are melted; and if they are fired the surrounding air must be similarly 
affected. Now while the missiles are heated by reason of their motion 
in air, which is turned into fire by the agitation produced by their 
movement, the upper bodies are carried on a moving sphere, so that, 
though they are not themselves fired, yet the air underneath the 
sphere of the revolving body is necessarily heated by its motion, and 
particularly in that part where the sun is attached to it. Hence 
warmth increases as the sun gets nearer or higher or overhead. Of 
the fact, then, that the stars are neither fiery nor move in fire, enough 
has been said. 



8 

Since changes evidently occur not only in the position of the stars 
but also in that of the whole heaven, there are three possibilities. 
Either (1) both are at rest, or (2) both are in motion, or (3) the one is at 
rest and the other in motion. 

(1) That both should be at rest is impossible; for, if the earth is at rest, 
the hypothesis does not account for the observations; and we take it 
as granted that the earth is at rest. It remains either that both are 
moved, or that the one is moved and the other at rest. 



899 



(2) On the view, first, that both are in motion, we have the absurdity 
that the stars and the circles move with the same speed, i.e. that the 
ace of every star is that of the circle in it moves. For star and circle 
are seen to come back to the same place at the same moment; from 
which it follows that the star has traversed the circle and the circle 
has completed its own movement, i.e. traversed its own 
circumference, at one and the same moment. But it is difficult to 
conceive that the pace of each star should be exactly proportioned to 
the size of its circle. That the pace of each circle should be 
proportionate to its size is not absurd but inevitable: but that the 
same should be true of the movement of the stars contained in the 
circles is quite incredible. For if, on the one and, we suppose that the 
star which moves on the greater circle is necessarily swifter, clearly 
we also admit that if stars shifted their position so as to exchange 
circles, the slower would become swifter and the swifter slower. But 
this would show that their movement was not their own, but due to 
the circles. If, on the other hand, the arrangement was a chance 
combination, the coincidence in every case of a greater circle with a 
swifter movement of the star contained in it is too much to believe. In 
one or two cases it might not inconceivably fall out so, but to imagine 
it in every case alike is a mere fiction. Besides, chance has no place in 
that which is natural, and what happens everywhere and in every 
case is no matter of chance. 

(3) The same absurdity is equally plain if it is supposed that the 
circles stand still and that it is the stars themselves which move. For 
it will follow that the outer stars are the swifter, and that the pace of 
the stars corresponds to the size of their circles. 

Since, then, we cannot reasonably suppose either that both are in 
motion or that the star alone moves, the remaining alternative is that 
the circles should move, while the stars are at rest and move with the 
circles to which they are attached. Only on this supposition are we 
involved in no absurd consequence. For, in the first place, the quicker 
movement of the larger circle is natural when all the circles are 
attached to the same centre. Whenever bodies are moving with their 
proper motion, the larger moves quicker. It is the same here with the 
revolving bodies: for the are intercepted by two radii will be larger in 



900 



the larger circle, and hence it is not surprising that the revolution of 
the larger circle should take the same time as that of the smaller. 
And secondly, the fact that the heavens do not break in pieces 
follows not only from this but also from the proof already given of 
the continuity of the whole. 

Again, since the stars are spherical, as our opponents assert and we 
may consistently admit, inasmuch as we construct them out of the 
spherical body, and since the spherical body has two movements 
proper to itself, namely rolling and spinning, it follows that if the 
stars have a movement of their own, it will be one of these. But 
neither is observed. (1) Suppose them to spin. They would then stay 
where they were, and not change their place, as, by observation and 
general consent, they do. Further, one would expect them all to 
exhibit the same movement: but the only star which appears to 
possess this movement is the sun, at sunrise or sunset, and this 
appearance is due not to the sun itself but to the distance from 
which we observe it. The visual ray being excessively prolonged 
becomes weak and wavering. The same reason probably accounts for 
the apparent twinkling of the fixed stars and the absence of 
twinkling in the planets. The planets are near, so that the visual ray 
reaches them in its full vigour, but when it comes to the fixed stars it 
is quivering because of the distance and its excessive extension; and 
its tremor produces an appearance of movement in the star: for it 
makes no difference whether movement is set up in the ray or in the 
object of vision. 

(2) On the other hand, it is also clear that the stars do not roll. For 
rolling involves rotation: but the 'face', as it is called, of the moon is 
always seen. Therefore, since any movement of their own which the 
stars possessed would presumably be one proper to themselves, and 
no such movement is observed in them, clearly they have no 
movement of their own. 

There is, further, the absurdity that nature has bestowed upon them 
no organ appropriate to such movement. For nature leaves nothing to 
chance, and would not, while caring for animals, overlook things so 
precious. Indeed, nature seems deliberately to have stripped them of 



901 



everything which makes selforiginated progression possible, and to 
have removed them as far as possible from things which have organs 
of movement. This is just why it seems proper that the whole heaven 
and every star should be spherical. For while of all shapes the sphere 
is the most convenient for movement in one place, making possible, 
as it does, the swiftest and most selfcontained motion, for forward 
movement it is the most unsuitable, least of all resembling shapes 
which are self-moved, in that it has no dependent or projecting part, 
as a rectilinear figure has, and is in fact as far as possible removed in 
shape from ambulatory bodies. Since, therefore, the heavens have to 
move in one lace, and the stars are not required to move themselves 
forward, it is natural that both should be spherical - a shape which 
best suits the movement of the one and the immobility of the other. 



From all this it is clear that the theory that the movement of the stars 
produces a harmony, i.e. that the sounds they make are concordant, 
in spite of the grace and originality with which it has been stated, is 
nevertheless untrue. Some thinkers suppose that the motion of 
bodies of that size must produce a noise, since on our earth the 
motion of bodies far inferior in size and in speed of movement has 
that effect. Also, when the sun and the moon, they say, and all the 
stars, so great in number and in size, are moving with so rapid a 
motion, how should they not produce a sound immensely great? 
Starting from this argument and from the observation that their 
speeds, as measured by their distances, are in the same ratios as 
musical concordances, they assert that the sound given forth by the 
circular movement of the stars is a harmony. Since, however, it 
appears unaccountable that we should not hear this music, they 
explain this by saying that the sound is in our ears from the very 
moment of birth and is thus indistinguishable from its contrary 
silence, since sound and silence are discriminated by mutual 
contrast. What happens to men, then, is just what happens to 
coppersmiths, who are so accustomed to the noise of the smithy that 



902 



it makes no difference to them. But, as we said before, melodious and 
poetical as the theory is, it cannot be a true account of the facts. 
There is not only the absurdity of our hearing nothing, the ground of 
which they try to remove, but also the fact that no effect other than 
sensitive is produced upon us. Excessive noises, we know, shatter the 
solid bodies even of inanimate things: the noise of thunder, for 
instance, splits rocks and the strongest of bodies. But if the moving 
bodies are so great, and the sound which penetrates to us is 
proportionate to their size, that sound must needs reach us in an 
intensity many times that of thunder, and the force of its action must 
be immense. Indeed the reason why we do not hear, and show in our 
bodies none of the effects of violent force, is easily given: it is that 
there is no noise. But not only is the explanation evident; it is also a 
corroboration of the truth of the views we have advanced. For the 
very difficulty which made the Pythagoreans say that the motion of 
the stars produces a concord corroborates our view. Bodies which are 
themselves in motion, produce noise and friction: but those which 
are attached or fixed to a moving body, as the parts to a ship, can no 
more create noise, than a ship on a river moving with the stream. Yet 
by the same argument one might say it was absurd that on a large 
vessel the motion of mast and poop should not make a great noise, 
and the like might be said of the movement of the vessel itself. But 
sound is caused when a moving body is enclosed in an unmoved 
body, and cannot be caused by one enclosed in, and continuous with, 
a moving body which creates no friction. We may say, then, in this 
matter that if the heavenly bodies moved in a generally diffused 
mass of air or fire, as every one supposes, their motion would 
necessarily cause a noise of tremendous strength and such a noise 
would necessarily reach and shatter us. Since, therefore, this effect is 
evidently not produced, it follows that none of them can move with 
the motion either of animate nature or of constraint. It is as though 
nature had foreseen the result, that if their movement were other 
than it is, nothing on this earth could maintain its character. 

That the stars are spherical and are not selfmoved, has now been 
explained. 



903 



10 

With their order - I mean the position of each, as involving the 
priority of some and the posteriority of others, and their respective 
distances from the extremity - with this astronomy may be left to 
deal, since the astronomical discussion is adequate. This discussion 
shows that the movements of the several stars depend, as regards 
the varieties of speed which they exhibit, on the distance of each 
from the extremity. It is established that the outermost revolution of 
the heavens is a simple movement and the swiftest of all, and that 
the movement of all other bodies is composite and relatively slow, for 
the reason that each is moving on its own circle with the reverse 
motion to that of the heavens. This at once leads us to expect that 
the body which is nearest to that first simple revolution should take 
the longest time to complete its circle, and that which is farthest 
from it the shortest, the others taking a longer time the nearer they 
are and a shorter time the farther away they are. For it is the nearest 
body which is most strongly influenced, and the most remote, by 
reason of its distance, which is least affected, the influence on the 
intermediate bodies varying, as the mathematicians show, with their 
distance. 



11 

With regard to the shape of each star, the most reasonable view is 
that they are spherical. It has been shown that it is not in their 
nature to move themselves, and, since nature is no wanton or 
random creator, clearly she will have given things which possess no 
movement a shape particularly unadapted to movement. Such a 
shape is the sphere, since it possesses no instrument of movement. 
Clearly then their mass will have the form of a sphere. Again, what 
holds of one holds of all, and the evidence of our eyes shows us that 
the moon is spherical. For how else should the moon as it waxes and 



904 



wanes show for the most part a crescent-shaped or gibbous figure, 
and only at one moment a half-moon? And astronomical arguments 
give further confirmation; for no other hypothesis accounts for the 
crescent shape of the sun's eclipses. One, then, of the heavenly 
bodies being spherical, clearly the rest will be spherical also. 



12 

There are two difficulties, which may very reasonably here be raised, 
of which we must now attempt to state the probable solution: for we 
regard the zeal of one whose thirst after philosophy leads him to 
accept even slight indications where it is very difficult to see one's 
way, as a proof rather of modesty than of overconfidence. 

Of many such problems one of the strangest is the problem why we 
find the greatest number of movements in the intermediate bodies, 
and not, rather, in each successive body a variety of movement 
proportionate to its distance from the primary motion. For we should 
expect, since the primary body shows one motion only, that the body 
which is nearest to it should move with the fewest movements, say 
two, and the one next after that with three, or some similar 
arrangement. But the opposite is the case. The movements of the sun 
and moon are fewer than those of some of the planets. Yet these 
planets are farther from the centre and thus nearer to the primary 
body than they, as observation has itself revealed. For we have seen 
the moon, half-full, pass beneath the planet Mars, which vanished on 
its shadow side and came forth by the bright and shining part. 
Similar accounts of other stars are given by the Egyptians and 
Babylonians, whose observations have been kept for very many years 
past, and from whom much of our evidence about particular stars is 
derived. A second difficulty which may with equal justice be raised is 
this. Why is it that the primary motion includes such a multitude of 
stars that their whole array seems to defy counting, while of the 
other stars each one is separated off, and in no case do we find two 
or more attached to the same motion? 



905 



On these questions, I say, it is well that we should seek to increase 
our understanding, though we have but little to go upon, and are 
placed at so great a distance from the facts in question. Nevertheless 
there are certain principles on which if we base our consideration we 
shall not find this difficulty by any means insoluble. We may object 
that we have been thinking of the stars as mere bodies, and as units 
with a serial order indeed but entirely inanimate; but should rather 
conceive them as enjoying life and action. On this view the facts 
cease to appear surprising. For it is natural that the best-conditioned 
of all things should have its good without action, that which is 
nearest to it should achieve it by little and simple action, and that 
which is farther removed by a complexity of actions, just as with 
men's bodies one is in good condition without exercise at all, another 
after a short walk, while another requires running and wrestling and 
hard training, and there are yet others who however hard they 
worked themselves could never secure this good, but only some 
substitute for it. To succeed often or in many things is difficult. For 
instance, to throw ten thousand Coan throws with the dice would be 
impossible, but to throw one or two is comparatively easy. In action, 
again, when A has to be done to get B, B to get C, and C to get D, one 
step or two present little difficulty, but as the series extends the 
difficulty grows. We must, then, think of the action of the lower stars 
as similar to that of animals and plants. For on our earth it is man 
that has the greatest variety of actions - for there are many goods 
that man can secure; hence his actions are various and directed to 
ends beyond them - while the perfectly conditioned has no need of 
action, since it is itself the end, and action always requires two terms, 
end and means. The lower animals have less variety of action than 
man; and plants perhaps have little action and of one kind only. For 
either they have but one attainable good (as indeed man has), or, if 
several, each contributes directly to their ultimate good. One thing 
then has and enjoys the ultimate good, other things attain to it, one 
immediately by few steps, another by many, while yet another does 
not even attempt to secure it but is satisfied to reach a point not far 
removed from that consummation. Thus, taking health as the end, 
there will be one thing that always possesses health, others that 
attain it, one by reducing flesh, another by running and thus reducing 



906 



flesh, another by taking steps to enable himself to run, thus further 
increasing the number of movements, while another cannot attain 
health itself, but only running or reduction of flesh, so that one or 
other of these is for such a being the end. For while it is clearly best 
for any being to attain the real end, yet, if that cannot be, the nearer 
it is to the best the better will be its state. It is for this reason that the 
earth moves not at all and the bodies near to it with few movements. 
For they do not attain the final end, but only come as near to it as 
their share in the divine principle permits. But the first heaven finds 
it immediately with a single movement, and the bodies intermediate 
between the first and last heavens attain it indeed, but at the cost of 
a multiplicity of movement. 

As to the difficulty that into the one primary motion is crowded a 
vast multitude of stars, while of the other stars each has been 
separately given special movements of its own, there is in the first 
place this reason for regarding the arrangement as a natural one. In 
thinking of the life and moving principle of the several heavens one 
must regard the first as far superior to the others. Such a superiority 
would be reasonable. For this single first motion has to move many of 
the divine bodies, while the numerous other motions move only one 
each, since each single planet moves with a variety of motions. Thus, 
then, nature makes matters equal and establishes a certain order, 
giving to the single motion many bodies and to the single body many 
motions. And there is a second reason why the other motions have 
each only one body, in that each of them except the last, i.e. that 
which contains the one star, is really moving many bodies. For this 
last sphere moves with many others, to which it is fixed, each sphere 
being actually a body; so that its movement will be a joint product. 
Each sphere, in fact, has its particular natural motion, to which the 
general movement is, as it were, added. But the force of any limited 
body is only adequate to moving a limited body. 

The characteristics of the stars which move with a circular motion, in 
respect of substance and shape, movement and order, have now been 
sufficiently explained. 



907 



13 

It remains to speak of the earth, of its position, of the question 
whether it is at rest or in motion, and of its shape. 

I. As to its position there is some difference of opinion. Most people - 
all, in fact, who regard the whole heaven as finite - say it lies at the 
centre. But the Italian philosophers known as Pythagoreans take the 
contrary view. At the centre, they say, is fire, and the earth is one of 
the stars, creating night and day by its circular motion about the 
centre. They further construct another earth in opposition to ours to 
which they give the name counterearth. In all this they are not 
seeking for theories and causes to account for observed facts, but 
rather forcing their observations and trying to accommodate them to 
certain theories and opinions of their own. But there are many others 
who would agree that it is wrong to give the earth the central 
position, looking for confirmation rather to theory than to the facts of 
observation. Their view is that the most precious place befits the 
most precious thing: but fire, they say, is more precious than earth, 
and the limit than the intermediate, and the circumference and the 
centre are limits. Reasoning on this basis they take the view that it is 
not earth that lies at the centre of the sphere, but rather fire. The 
Pythagoreans have a further reason. They hold that the most 
important part of the world, which is the centre, should be most 
strictly guarded, and name it, or rather the fire which occupies that 
place, the 'Guardhouse of Zeus', as if the word 'centre' were quite 
unequivocal, and the centre of the mathematical figure were always 
the same with that of the thing or the natural centre. But it is better 
to conceive of the case of the whole heaven as analogous to that of 
animals, in which the centre of the animal and that of the body are 
different. For this reason they have no need to be so disturbed about 
the world, or to call in a guard for its centre: rather let them look for 
the centre in the other sense and tell us what it is like and where 
nature has set it. That centre will be something primary and precious; 
but to the mere position we should give the last place rather than the 
first. For the middle is what is defined, and what defines it is the 



908 



limit, and that which contains or limits is more precious than that 
which is limited, see ing that the latter is the matter and the former 
the essence of the system. 

II. As to the position of the earth, then, this is the view which some 
advance, and the views advanced concerning its rest or motion are 
similar. For here too there is no general agreement. All who deny that 
the earth lies at the centre think that it revolves about the centre, and 
not the earth only but, as we said before, the counter-earth as well. 
Some of them even consider it possible that there are several bodies 
so moving, which are invisible to us owing to the interposition of the 
earth. This, they say, accounts for the fact that eclipses of the moon 
are more frequent than eclipses of the sun: for in addition to the 
earth each of these moving bodies can obstruct it. Indeed, as in any 
case the surface of the earth is not actually a centre but distant from 
it a full hemisphere, there is no more difficulty, they think, in 
accounting for the observed facts on their view that we do not dwell 
at the centre, than on the common view that the earth is in the 
middle. Even as it is, there is nothing in the observations to suggest 
that we are removed from the centre by half the diameter of the 
earth. Others, again, say that the earth, which lies at the centre, is 
'rolled', and thus in motion, about the axis of the whole heaven, So it 
stands written in the Timaeus. 

III. There are similar disputes about the shape of the earth. Some 
think it is spherical, others that it is flat and drum-shaped. For 
evidence they bring the fact that, as the sun rises and sets, the part 
concealed by the earth shows a straight and not a curved edge, 
whereas if the earth were spherical the line of section would have to 
be circular. In this they leave out of account the great distance of the 
sun from the earth and the great size of the circumference, which, 
seen from a distance on these apparently small circles appears 
straight. Such an appearance ought not to make them doubt the 
circular shape of the earth. But they have another argument. They say 
that because it is at rest, the earth must necessarily have this shape. 
For there are many different ways in which the movement or rest of 
the earth has been conceived. 



909 



The difficulty must have occurred to every one. It would indeed be a 
complacent mind that felt no surprise that, while a little bit of earth, 
let loose in mid-air moves and will not stay still, and more there is of 
it the faster it moves, the whole earth, free in midair, should show no 
movement at all. Yet here is this great weight of earth, and it is at 
rest. And again, from beneath one of these moving fragments of 
earth, before it falls, take away the earth, and it will continue its 
downward movement with nothing to stop it. The difficulty then, has 
naturally passed into a common place of philosophy; and one may 
well wonder that the solutions offered are not seen to involve greater 
absurdities than the problem itself. 

By these considerations some have been led to assert that the earth 
below us is infinite, saying, with Xenophanes of Colophon, that it has 
'pushed its roots to infinity', - in order to save the trouble of seeking 
for the cause. Hence the sharp rebuke of Empedocles, in the words 'if 
the deeps of the earth are endless and endless the ample ether - 
such is the vain tale told by many a tongue, poured from the mouths 
of those who have seen but little of the whole. Others say the earth 
rests upon water. This, indeed, is the oldest theory that has been 
preserved, and is attributed to Thales of Miletus. It was supposed to 
stay still because it floated like wood and other similar substances, 
which are so constituted as to rest upon but not upon air. As if the 
same account had not to be given of the water which carries the 
earth as of the earth itself! It is not the nature of water, any more 
than of earth, to stay in mid-air: it must have something to rest upon. 
Again, as air is lighter than water, so is water than earth: how then 
can they think that the naturally lighter substance lies below the 
heavier? Again, if the earth as a whole is capable of floating upon 
water, that must obviously be the case with any part of it. But 
observation shows that this is not the case. Any piece of earth goes to 
the bottom, the quicker the larger it is. These thinkers seem to push 
their inquiries some way into the problem, but not so far as they 
might. It is what we are all inclined to do, to direct our inquiry not by 
the matter itself, but by the views of our opponents: and even when 
interrogating oneself one pushes the inquiry only to the point at 
which one can no longer offer any opposition. Hence a good inquirer 
will be one who is ready in bringing forward the objections proper to 



910 



the genus, and that he will be when he has gained an understanding 
of all the differences. 

Anaximenes and Anaxagoras and Democritus give the flatness of the 
earth as the cause of its staying still. Thus, they say, it does not cut, 
but covers like a lid, the air beneath it. This seems to be the way of 
flat-shaped bodies: for even the wind can scarcely move them 
because of their power of resistance. The same immobility, they say, 
is produced by the flatness of the surface which the earth presents to 
the air which underlies it; while the air, not having room enough to 
change its place because it is underneath the earth, stays there in a 
mass, like the water in the case of the water-clock. And they adduce 
an amount of evidence to prove that air, when cut off and at rest, can 
bear a considerable weight. 

Now, first, if the shape of the earth is not flat, its flatness cannot be 
the cause of its immobility. But in their own account it is rather the 
size of the earth than its flatness that causes it to remain at rest. For 
the reason why the air is so closely confined that it cannot find a 
passage, and therefore stays where it is, is its great amount: and this 
amount great because the body which isolates it, the earth, is very 
large. This result, then, will follow, even if the earth is spherical, so 
long as it retains its size. So far as their arguments go, the earth will 
still be at rest. 

In general, our quarrel with those who speak of movement in this 
way cannot be confined to the parts; it concerns the whole universe. 
One must decide at the outset whether bodies have a natural 
movement or not, whether there is no natural but only constrained 
movement. Seeing, however, that we have already decided this 
matter to the best of our ability, we are entitled to treat our results as 
representing fact. Bodies, we say, which have no natural movement, 
have no constrained movement; and where there is no natural and 
no constrained movement there will be no movement at all. This is a 
conclusion, the necessity of which we have already decided, and we 
have seen further that rest also will be inconceivable, since rest, like 
movement, is either natural or constrained. But if there is any natural 
movement, constraint will not be the sole principle of motion or of 



911 



rest. If, then, it is by constraint that the earth now keeps its place, the 
so-called 'whirling' movement by which its parts came together at 
the centre was also constrained. (The form of causation supposed 
they all borrow from observations of liquids and of air, in which the 
larger and heavier bodies always move to the centre of the whirl. This 
is thought by all those who try to generate the heavens to explain 
why the earth came together at the centre. They then seek a reason 
for its staying there; and some say, in the manner explained, that the 
reason is its size and flatness, others, with Empedocles, that the 
motion of the heavens, moving about it at a higher speed, prevents 
movement of the earth, as the water in a cup, when the cup is given a 
circular motion, though it is often underneath the bronze, is for this 
same reason prevented from moving with the downward movement 
which is natural to it.) But suppose both the 'whirl' and its flatness 
(the air beneath being withdrawn) cease to prevent the earth's 
motion, where will the earth move to then? Its movement to the 
centre was constrained, and its rest at the centre is due to constraint; 
but there must be some motion which is natural to it. Will this be 
upward motion or downward or what? It must have some motion; 
and if upward and downward motion are alike to it, and the air above 
the earth does not prevent upward movement, then no more could 
air below it prevent downward movement. For the same cause must 
necessarily have the same effect on the same thing. 

Further, against Empedocles there is another point which might be 
made. When the elements were separated off by Hate, what caused 
the earth to keep its place? Surely the 'whirl' cannot have been then 
also the cause. It is absurd too not to perceive that, while the whirling 
movement may have been responsible for the original coming 
together of the art of earth at the centre, the question remains, why 
now do all heavy bodies move to the earth. For the whirl surely does 
not come near us. Why, again, does fire move upward? Not, surely, 
because of the whirl. But if fire is naturally such as to move in a 
certain direction, clearly the same may be supposed to hold of earth. 
Again, it cannot be the whirl which determines the heavy and the 
light. Rather that movement caused the pre-existent heavy and light 
things to go to the middle and stay on the surface respectively. Thus, 
before ever the whirl began, heavy and light existed; and what can 



912 



have been the ground of their distinction, or the manner and 
direction of their natural movements? In the infinite chaos there can 
have been neither above nor below, and it is by these that heavy and 
light are determined. 

It is to these causes that most writers pay attention: but there are 
some, Anaximander, for instance, among the ancients, who say that 
the earth keeps its place because of its indifference. Motion upward 
and downward and sideways were all, they thought, equally 
inappropriate to that which is set at the centre and indifferently 
related to every extreme point; and to move in contrary directions at 
the same time was impossible: so it must needs remain still. This 
view is ingenious but not true. The argument would prove that 
everything, whatever it be, which is put at the centre, must stay there. 
Fire, then, will rest at the centre: for the proof turns on no peculiar 
property of earth. But this does not follow. The observed facts about 
earth are not only that it remains at the centre, but also that it moves 
to the centre. The place to which any fragment of earth moves must 
necessarily be the place to which the whole moves; and in the place 
to which a thing naturally moves, it will naturally rest. The reason 
then is not in the fact that the earth is indifferently related to every 
extreme point: for this would apply to any body, whereas movement 
to the centre is peculiar to earth. Again it is absurd to look for a 
reason why the earth remains at the centre and not for a reason why 
fire remains at the extremity. If the extremity is the natural place of 
fire, clearly earth must also have a natural place. But suppose that 
the centre is not its place, and that the reason of its remaining there 
is this necessity of indifference - on the analogy of the hair which, it 
is said, however great the tension, will not break under it, if it be 
evenly distributed, or of the men who, though exceedingly hungry 
and thirsty, and both equally, yet being equidistant from food and 
drink, is therefore bound to stay where he is - even so, it still remains 
to explain why fire stays at the extremities. It is strange, too, to ask 
about things staying still but not about their motion, - why, I mean, 
one thing, if nothing stops it, moves up, and another thing to the 
centre. Again, their statements are not true. It happens, indeed, to be 
the case that a thing to which movement this way and that is equally 
inappropriate is obliged to remain at the centre. But so far as their 



913 



argument goes, instead of remaining there, it will move, only not as a 
mass but in fragments. For the argument applies equally to fire. Fire, 
if set at the centre, should stay there, like earth, since it will be 
indifferently related to every point on the extremity. Nevertheless it 
will move, as in fact it always does move when nothing stops it, away 
from the centre to the extremity. It will not, however, move in a mass 
to a single point on the circumference - the only possible result on 
the lines of the indifference theory - but rather each corresponding 
portion of fire to the corresponding part of the extremity, each fourth 
part, for instance, to a fourth part of the circumference. For since no 
body is a point, it will have parts. The expansion, when the body 
increased the place occupied, would be on the same principle as the 
contraction, in which the place was diminished. Thus, for all the 
indifference theory shows to the contrary, earth also would have 
moved in this manner away from the centre, unless the centre had 
been its natural place. 

We have now outlined the views held as to the shape, position, and 
rest or movement of the earth. 



14 

Let us first decide the question whether the earth moves or is at rest. 
For, as we said, there are some who make it one of the stars, and 
others who, setting it at the centre, suppose it to be 'rolled' and in 
motion about the pole as axis. That both views are untenable will be 
clear if we take as our starting-point the fact that the earth's motion, 
whether the earth be at the centre or away from it, must needs be a 
constrained motion. It cannot be the movement of the earth itself. If 
it were, any portion of it would have this movement; but in fact every 
part moves in a straight line to the centre. Being, then, constrained 
and unnatural, the movement could not be eternal. But the order of 
the universe is eternal. Again, everything that moves with the 
circular movement, except the first sphere, is observed to be passed, 
and to move with more than one motion. The earth, then, also, 



914 



whether it move about the centre or as stationary at it, must 
necessarily move with two motions. But if this were so, there would 
have to be passings and turnings of the fixed stars. Yet no such thing 
is observed. The same stars always rise and set in the same parts of 
the earth. 

Further, the natural movement of the earth, part and whole alike, is 
the centre of the whole - whence the fact that it is now actually 
situated at the centre - but it might be questioned since both centres 
are the same, which centre it is that portions of earth and other 
heavy things move to. Is this their goal because it is the centre of the 
earth or because it is the centre of the whole? The goal, surely, must 
be the centre of the whole. For fire and other light things move to the 
extremity of the area which contains the centre. It happens, however, 
that the centre of the earth and of the whole is the same. Thus they 
do move to the centre of the earth, but accidentally, in virtue of the 
fact that the earth's centre lies at the centre of the whole. That the 
centre of the earth is the goal of their movement is indicated by the 
fact that heavy bodies moving towards the earth do not parallel but 
so as to make equal angles, and thus to a single centre, that of the 
earth. It is clear, then, that the earth must be at the centre and 
immovable, not only for the reasons already given, but also because 
heavy bodies forcibly thrown quite straight upward return to the 
point from which they started, even if they are thrown to an infinite 
distance. From these considerations then it is clear that the earth 
does not move and does not lie elsewhere than at the centre. 

From what we have said the explanation of the earth's immobility is 
also apparent. If it is the nature of earth, as observation shows, to 
move from any point to the centre, as of fire contrariwise to move 
from the centre to the extremity, it is impossible that any portion of 
earth should move away from the centre except by constraint. For a 
single thing has a single movement, and a simple thing a simple: 
contrary movements cannot belong to the same thing, and 
movement away from the centre is the contrary of movement to it. If 
then no portion of earth can move away from the centre, obviously 
still less can the earth as a whole so move. For it is the nature of the 
whole to move to the point to which the part naturally moves. Since, 



915 



then, it would require a force greater than itself to move it, it must 
needs stay at the centre. This view is further supported by the 
contributions of mathematicians to astronomy, since the 
observations made as the shapes change by which the order of the 
stars is determined, are fully accounted for on the hypothesis that 
the earth lies at the centre. Of the position of the earth and of the 
manner of its rest or movement, our discussion may here end. 

Its shape must necessarily be spherical. For every portion of earth has 
weight until it reaches the centre, and the jostling of parts greater 
and smaller would bring about not a waved surface, but rather 
compression and convergence of part and part until the centre is 
reached. The process should be conceived by supposing the earth to 
come into being in the way that some of the natural philosophers 
describe. Only they attribute the downward movement to constraint, 
and it is better to keep to the truth and say that the reason of this 
motion is that a thing which possesses weight is naturally endowed 
with a centripetal movement. When the mixture, then, was merely 
potential, the things that were separated off moved similarly from 
every side towards the centre. Whether the parts which came 
together at the centre were distributed at the extremities evenly, or in 
some other way, makes no difference. If, on the one hand, there were 
a similar movement from each quarter of the extremity to the single 
centre, it is obvious that the resulting mass would be similar on every 
side. For if an equal amount is added on every side the extremity of 
the mass will be everywhere equidistant from its centre, i.e. the 
figure will be spherical. But neither will it in any way affect the 
argument if there is not a similar accession of concurrent fragments 
from every side. For the greater quantity, finding a lesser in front of it, 
must necessarily drive it on, both having an impulse whose goal is 
the centre, and the greater weight driving the lesser forward till this 
goal is reached. In this we have also the solution of a possible 
difficulty. The earth, it might be argued, is at the centre and spherical 
in shape: if, then, a weight many times that of the earth were added 
to one hemisphere, the centre of the earth and of the whole will no 
longer be coincident. So that either the earth will not stay still at the 
centre, or if it does, it will be at rest without having its centre at the 
place to which it is still its nature to move. Such is the difficulty. A 



916 



short consideration will give us an easy answer, if we first give 
precision to our postulate that any body endowed with weight, of 
whatever size, moves towards the centre. Clearly it will not stop 
when its edge touches the centre. The greater quantity must prevail 
until the body's centre occupies the centre. For that is the goal of its 
impulse. Now it makes no difference whether we apply this to a clod 
or common fragment of earth or to the earth as a whole. The fact 
indicated does not depend upon degrees of size but applies 
universally to everything that has the centripetal impulse. Therefore 
earth in motion, whether in a mass or in fragments, necessarily 
continues to move until it occupies the centre equally every way, the 
less being forced to equalize itself by the greater owing to the forward 
drive of the impulse. 

If the earth was generated, then, it must have been formed in this 
way, and so clearly its generation was spherical; and if it is 
ungenerated and has remained so always, its character must be that 
which the initial generation, if it had occurred, would have given it. 
But the spherical shape, necessitated by this argument, follows also 
from the fact that the motions of heavy bodies always make equal 
angles, and are not parallel. This would be the natural form of 
movement towards what is naturally spherical. Either then the earth 
is spherical or it is at least naturally spherical. And it is right to call 
anything that which nature intends it to be, and which belongs to it, 
rather than that which it is by constraint and contrary to nature. The 
evidence of the senses further corroborates this. How else would 
eclipses of the moon show segments shaped as we see them? As it is, 
the shapes which the moon itself each month shows are of every 
kind straight, gibbous, and concave - but in eclipses the outline is 
always curved: and, since it is the interposition of the earth that 
makes the eclipse, the form of this line will be caused by the form of 
the earth's surface, which is therefore spherical. Again, our 
observations of the stars make it evident, not only that the earth is 
circular, but also that it is a circle of no great size. For quite a small 
change of position to south or north causes a manifest alteration of 
the horizon. There is much change, I mean, in the stars which are 
overhead, and the stars seen are different, as one moves northward 
or southward. Indeed there are some stars seen in Egypt and in the 



917 



neighbourhood of Cyprus which are not seen in the northerly 
regions; and stars, which in the north are never beyond the range of 
observation, in those regions rise and set. All of which goes to show 
not only that the earth is circular in shape, but also that it is a sphere 
of no great size: for otherwise the effect of so slight a change of place 
would not be quickly apparent. Hence one should not be too sure of 
the incredibility of the view of those who conceive that there is 
continuity between the parts about the pillars of Hercules and the 
parts about India, and that in this way the ocean is one. As further 
evidence in favour of this they quote the case of elephants, a species 
occurring in each of these extreme regions, suggesting that the 
common characteristic of these extremes is explained by their 
continuity. Also, those mathematicians who try to calculate the size 
of the earth's circumference arrive at the figure 400,000 stades. This 
indicates not only that the earth's mass is spherical in shape, but also 
that as compared with the stars it is not of great size. 



Book III 



We have already discussed the first heaven and its parts, the moving 
stars within it, the matter of which these are composed and their 
bodily constitution, and we have also shown that they are 
ungenerated and indestructible. Now things that we call natural are 
either substances or functions and attributes of substances. As 
substances I class the simple bodies - fire, earth, and the other terms 
of the series - and all things composed of them; for example, the 
heaven as a whole and its parts, animals, again, and plants and their 
parts. By attributes and functions I mean the movements of these 



918 



and of all other things in which they have power in themselves to 
cause movement, and also their alterations and reciprocal 
transformations. It is obvious, then, that the greater part of the 
inquiry into nature concerns bodies: for a natural substance is either 
a body or a thing which cannot come into existence without body 
and magnitude. This appears plainly from an analysis of the 
character of natural things, and equally from an inspection of the 
instances of inquiry into nature. Since, then, we have spoken of the 
primary element, of its bodily constitution, and of its freedom from 
destruction and generation, it remains to speak of the other two. In 
speaking of them we shall be obliged also to inquire into generation 
and destruction. For if there is generation anywhere, it must be in 
these elements and things composed of them. 

This is indeed the first question we have to ask: is generation a fact 
or not? Earlier speculation was at variance both with itself and with 
the views here put forward as to the true answer to this question. 
Some removed generation and destruction from the world altogether. 
Nothing that is, they said, is generated or destroyed, and our 
conviction to the contrary is an illusion. So maintained the school of 
Melissus and Parmenides. But however excellent their theories may 
otherwise be, anyhow they cannot be held to speak as students of 
nature. There may be things not subject to generation or any kind of 
movement, but if so they belong to another and a higher inquiry than 
the study of nature. They, however, had no idea of any form of being 
other than the substance of things perceived; and when they saw, 
what no one previously had seen, that there could be no knowledge 
or wisdom without some such unchanging entities, they naturally 
transferred what was true of them to things perceived. Others, 
perhaps intentionally, maintain precisely the contrary opinion to this. 
It has been asserted that everything in the world was subject to 
generation and nothing was ungenerated, but that after being 
generated some things remained indestructible while the rest were 
again destroyed. This had been asserted in the first instance by 
Hesiod and his followers, but afterwards outside his circle by the 
earliest natural philosophers. But what these thinkers maintained 
was that all else has been generated and, as they said, 'is flowing 
away, nothing having any solidity, except one single thing which 



919 



persists as the basis of all these transformations. So we may interpret 
the statements of Heraclitus of Ephesus and many others. And some 
subject all bodies whatever to generation, by means of the 
composition and separation of planes. 

Discussion of the other views may be postponed. But this last theory 
which composes every body of planes is, as the most superficial 
observation shows, in many respects in plain contradiction with 
mathematics. It is, however, wrong to remove the foundations of a 
science unless you can replace them with others more convincing. 
And, secondly, the same theory which composes solids of planes 
clearly composes planes of lines and lines of points, so that a part of 
a line need not be a line. This matter has been already considered in 
our discussion of movement, where we have shown that an 
indivisible length is impossible. But with respect to natural bodies 
there are impossibilities involved in the view which asserts 
indivisible lines, which we may briefly consider at this point. For the 
impossible consequences which result from this view in the 
mathematical sphere will reproduce themselves when it is applied to 
physical bodies, but there will be difficulties in physics which are not 
present in mathematics; for mathematics deals with an abstract and 
physics with a more concrete object. There are many attributes 
necessarily present in physical bodies which are necessarily excluded 
by indivisibility; all attributes, in fact, which are divisible. There can 
be nothing divisible in an indivisible thing, but the attributes of 
bodies are all divisible in one of two ways. They are divisible into 
kinds, as colour is divided into white and black, and they are divisible 
per accidens when that which has them is divisible. In this latter 
sense attributes which are simple are nevertheless divisible. 
Attributes of this kind will serve, therefore, to illustrate the 
impossibility of the view. It is impossible, if two parts of a thing have 
no weight, that the two together should have weight. But either all 
perceptible bodies or some, such as earth and water, have weight, as 
these thinkers would themselves admit. Now if the point has no 
weight, clearly the lines have not either, and, if they have not, neither 
have the planes. Therefore no body has weight. It is, further, manifest 
that their point cannot have weight. For while a heavy thing may 
always be heavier than something and a light thing lighter than 



920 



something, a thing which is heavier or lighter than something need 
not be itself heavy or light, just as a large thing is larger than others, 
but what is larger is not always large. A thing which, judged 
absolutely, is small may none the less be larger than other things. 
Whatever, then, is heavy and also heavier than something else, must 
exceed this by something which is heavy. A heavy thing therefore is 
always divisible. But it is common ground that a point is indivisible. 
Again, suppose that what is heavy or weight is a dense body, and 
what is light rare. Dense differs from rare in containing more matter 
in the same cubic area. A point, then, if it may be heavy or light, may 
be dense or rare. But the dense is divisible while a point is indivisible. 
And if what is heavy must be either hard or soft, an impossible 
consequence is easy to draw. For a thing is soft if its surface can be 
pressed in, hard if it cannot; and if it can be pressed in it is divisible. 

Moreover, no weight can consist of parts not possessing weight. For 
how, except by the merest fiction, can they specify the number and 
character of the parts which will produce weight? And, further, when 
one weight is greater than another, the difference is a third weight; 
from which it will follow that every indivisible part possesses weight. 
For suppose that a body of four points possesses weight. A body 
composed of more than four points will superior in weight to it, a 
thing which has weight. But the difference between weight and 
weight must be a weight, as the difference between white and whiter 
is white. Here the difference which makes the superior weight 
heavier is the single point which remains when the common number, 
four, is subtracted. A single point, therefore, has weight. 

Further, to assume, on the one hand, that the planes can only be put 
in linear contact would be ridiculous. For just as there are two ways 
of putting lines together, namely, end to and side by side, so there 
must be two ways of putting planes together. Lines can be put 
together so that contact is linear by laying one along the other, 
though not by putting them end to end. But if, similarly, in putting 
the lanes together, superficial contact is allowed as an alternative to 
linear, that method will give them bodies which are not any element 
nor composed of elements. Again, if it is the number of planes in a 
body that makes one heavier than another, as the Timaeus explains, 



921 



clearly the line and the point will have weight. For the three cases 
are, as we said before, analogous. But if the reason of differences of 
weight is not this, but rather the heaviness of earth and the lightness 
of fire, then some of the planes will be light and others heavy (which 
involves a similar distinction in the lines and the points); the 
earthplane, I mean, will be heavier than the fire-plane. In general, the 
result is either that there is no magnitude at all, or that all magnitude 
could be done away with. For a point is to a line as a line is to a plane 
and as a plane is to a body. Now the various forms in passing into one 
another will each be resolved into its ultimate constituents. It might 
happen therefore that nothing existed except points, and that there 
was no body at all. A further consideration is that if time is similarly 
constituted, there would be, or might be, a time at which it was done 
away with. For the indivisible now is like a point in a line. The same 
consequences follow from composing the heaven of numbers, as 
some of the Pythagoreans do who make all nature out of numbers. 
For natural bodies are manifestly endowed with weight and 
lightness, but an assemblage of units can neither be composed to 
form a body nor possess weight. 



The necessity that each of the simple bodies should have a natural 
movement may be shown as follows. They manifestly move, and if 
they have no proper movement they must move by constraint: and 
the constrained is the same as the unnatural. Now an unnatural 
movement presupposes a natural movement which it contravenes, 
and which, however many the unnatural movements, is always one. 
For naturally a thing moves in one way, while its unnatural 
movements are manifold. The same may be shown, from the fact of 
rest. Rest, also, must either be constrained or natural, constrained in 
a place to which movement was constrained, natural in a place 
movement to which was natural. Now manifestly there is a body 
which is at rest at the centre. If then this rest is natural to it, clearly 
motion to this place is natural to it. If, on the other hand, its rest is 



922 



constrained, what is hindering its motion? Something, which is at 
rest: but if so, we shall simply repeat the same argument; and either 
we shall come to an ultimate something to which rest where it is or 
we shall have an infinite process, which is impossible. The hindrance 
to its movement, then, we will suppose, is a moving thing - as 
Empedocles says that it is the vortex which keeps the earth still - : 
but in that case we ask, where would it have moved to but for the 
vortex? It could not move infinitely; for to traverse an infinite is 
impossible, and impossibilities do not happen. So the moving thing 
must stop somewhere, and there rest not by constraint but naturally. 
But a natural rest proves a natural movement to the place of rest. 
Hence Leucippus and Democritus, who say that the primary bodies 
are in perpetual movement in the void or infinite, may be asked to 
explain the manner of their motion and the kind of movement which 
is natural to them. For if the various elements are constrained by one 
another to move as they do, each must still have a natural movement 
which the constrained contravenes, and the prime mover must cause 
motion not by constraint but naturally. If there is no ultimate natural 
cause of movement and each preceding term in the series is always 
moved by constraint, we shall have an infinite process. The same 
difficulty is involved even if it is supposed, as we read in the Timaeus, 
that before the ordered world was made the elements moved without 
order. Their movement must have been due either to constraint or to 
their nature. And if their movement was natural, a moment's 
consideration shows that there was already an ordered world. For the 
prime mover must cause motion in virtue of its own natural 
movement, and the other bodies, moving without constraint, as they 
came to rest in their proper places, would fall into the order in which 
they now stand, the heavy bodies moving towards the centre and the 
light bodies away from it. But that is the order of their distribution in 
our world. There is a further question, too, which might be asked. Is it 
possible or impossible that bodies in unordered movement should 
combine in some cases into combinations like those of which bodies 
of nature's composing are composed, such, I mean, as bones and 
flesh? Yet this is what Empedocles asserts to have occurred under 
Love. 'Many a head', says he, 'came to birth without a neck.' The 
answer to the view that there are infinite bodies moving in an infinite 



923 



is that, if the cause of movement is single, they must move with a 
single motion, and therefore not without order; and if, on the other 
hand, the causes are of infinite variety, their motions too must be 
infinitely varied. For a finite number of causes would produce a kind 
of order, since absence of order is not proved by diversity of direction 
in motions: indeed, in the world we know, not all bodies, but only 
bodies of the same kind, have a common goal of movement. Again, 
disorderly movement means in reality unnatural movement, since 
the order proper to perceptible things is their nature. And there is 
also absurdity and impossibility in the notion that the disorderly 
movement is infinitely continued. For the nature of things is the 
nature which most of them possess for most of the time. Thus their 
view brings them into the contrary position that disorder is natural, 
and order or system unnatural. But no natural fact can originate in 
chance. This is a point which Anaxagoras seems to have thoroughly 
grasped; for he starts his cosmogony from unmoved things. The 
others, it is true, make things collect together somehow before they 
try to produce motion and separation. But there is no sense in 
starting generation from an original state in which bodies are 
separated and in movement. Hence Empedocles begins after the 
process ruled by Love: for he could not have constructed the heaven 
by building it up out of bodies in separation, making them to 
combine by the power of Love, since our world has its constituent 
elements in separation, and therefore presupposes a previous state of 
unity and combination. 

These arguments make it plain that every body has its natural 
movement, which is not constrained or contrary to its nature. We go 
on to show that there are certain bodies whose necessary impetus is 
that of weight and lightness. Of necessity, we assert, they must move, 
and a moved thing which has no natural impetus cannot move either 
towards or away from the centre. Suppose a body A without weight, 
and a body B endowed with weight. Suppose the weightless body to 
move the distance CD, while B in the same time moves the distance 
CE, which will be greater since the heavy thing must move further. 
Let the heavy body then be divided in the proportion CE: CD (for there 
is no reason why a part of B should not stand in this relation to the 
whole). Now if the whole moves the whole distance CE, the part must 



924 



in the same time move the distance CD. A weightless body, therefore, 
and one which has weight will move the same distance, which is 
impossible. And the same argument would fit the case of lightness. 
Again, a body which is in motion but has neither weight nor 
lightness, must be moved by constraint, and must continue its 
constrained movement infinitely. For there will be a force which 
moves it, and the smaller and lighter a body is the further will a given 
force move it. Now let A, the weightless body, be moved the distance 
CE, and B, which has weight, be moved in the same time the distance 
CD. Dividing the heavy body in the proportion CE:CD, we subtract 
from the heavy body a part which will in the same time move the 
distance CE, since the whole moved CD: for the relative speeds of the 
two bodies will be in inverse ratio to their respective sizes. Thus the 
weightless body will move the same distance as the heavy in the 
same time. But this is impossible. Hence, since the motion of the 
weightless body will cover a greater distance than any that is 
suggested, it will continue infinitely. It is therefore obvious that every 
body must have a definite weight or lightness. But since 'nature' 
means a source of movement within the thing itself, while a force is 
a source of movement in something other than it or in itself qua 
other, and since movement is always due either to nature or to 
constraint, movement which is natural, as downward movement is to 
a stone, will be merely accelerated by an external force, while an 
unnatural movement will be due to the force alone. In either case the 
air is as it were instrumental to the force. For air is both light and 
heavy, and thus qua light produces upward motion, being propelled 
and set in motion by the force, and qua heavy produces a downward 
motion. In either case the force transmits the movement to the body 
by first, as it were, impregnating the air. That is why a body moved by 
constraint continues to move when that which gave the impulse 
ceases to accompany it. Otherwise, i.e. if the air were not endowed 
with this function, constrained movement would be impossible. And 
the natural movement of a body may be helped on in the same way. 
This discussion suffices to show (1) that all bodies are either light or 
heavy, and (2) how unnatural movement takes place. 

From what has been said earlier it is plain that there cannot be 
generation either of everything or in an absolute sense of anything. It 



925 



is impossible that everything should be generated, unless an extra- 
corporeal void is possible. For, assuming generation, the place which 
is to be occupied by that which is coming to be, must have been 
previously occupied by void in which no body was. Now it is quite 
possible for one body to be generated out of another, air for instance 
out of fire, but in the absence of any pre-existing mass generation is 
impossible. That which is potentially a certain kind of body may, it is 
true, become such in actuality, But if the potential body was not 
already in actuality some other kind of body, the existence of an 
extra-corporeal void must be admitted. 



It remains to say what bodies are subject to generation, and why. 
Since in every case knowledge depends on what is primary, and the 
elements are the primary constituents of bodies, we must ask which 
of such bodies are elements, and why; and after that what is their 
number and character. The answer will be plain if we first explain 
what kind of substance an element is. An element, we take it, is a 
body into which other bodies may be analysed, present in them 
potentially or in actuality (which of these, is still disputable), and not 
itself divisible into bodies different in form. That, or something like it, 
is what all men in every case mean by element. Now if what we have 
described is an element, clearly there must be such bodies. For flesh 
and wood and all other similar bodies contain potentially fire and 
earth, since one sees these elements exuded from them; and, on the 
other hand, neither in potentiality nor in actuality does fire contain 
flesh or wood, or it would exude them. Similarly, even if there were 
only one elementary body, it would not contain them. For though it 
will be either flesh or bone or something else, that does not at once 
show that it contained these in potentiality: the further question 
remains, in what manner it becomes them. Now Anaxagoras opposes 
Empedocles' view of the elements. Empedocles says that fire and 
earth and the related bodies are elementary bodies of which all 
things are composed; but this Anaxagoras denies. His elements are 



926 



the homoeomerous things, viz. flesh, bone, and the like. Earth and 
fire are mixtures, composed of them and all the other seeds, each 
consisting of a collection of all the homoeomerous bodies, separately 
invisible; and that explains why from these two bodies all others are 
generated. (To him fire and aither are the same thing.) But since 
every natural body has it proper movement, and movements are 
either simple or mixed, mixed in mixed bodies and simple in simple, 
there must obviously be simple bodies; for there are simple 
movements. It is plain, then, that there are elements, and why. 



The next question to consider is whether the elements are finite or 
infinite in number, and, if finite, what their number is. Let us first 
show reason or denying that their number is infinite, as some 
suppose. We begin with the view of Anaxagoras that all the 
homoeomerous bodies are elements. Any one who adopts this view 
misapprehends the meaning of element. Observation shows that 
even mixed bodies are often divisible into homoeomerous parts; 
examples are flesh, bone, wood, and stone. Since then the composite 
cannot be an element, not every homoeomerous body can be an 
element; only, as we said before, that which is not divisible into 
bodies different in form. But even taking 'element' as they do, they 
need not assert an infinity of elements, since the hypothesis of a 
finite number will give identical results. Indeed even two or three 
such bodies serve the purpose as well, as Empedocles' attempt 
shows. Again, even on their view it turns out that all things are not 
composed of homoeomerous bodies. They do not pretend that a face 
is composed of faces, or that any other natural conformation is 
composed of parts like itself. Obviously then it would be better to 
assume a finite number of principles. They should, in fact, be as few 
as possible, consistently with proving what has to be proved. This is 
the common demand of mathematicians, who always assume as 
principles things finite either in kind or in number. Again, if body is 
distinguished from body by the appropriate qualitative difference, 



927 



and there is a limit to the number of differences (for the difference 
lies in qualities apprehended by sense, which are in fact finite in 
number, though this requires proof), then manifestly there is 
necessarily a limit to the number of elements. 

There is, further, another view - that of Leucippus and Democritus of 
Abdera - the implications of which are also unacceptable. The 
primary masses, according to them, are infinite in number and 
indivisible in mass: one cannot turn into many nor many into one; 
and all things are generated by their combination and involution. 
Now this view in a sense makes things out to be numbers or 
composed of numbers. The exposition is not clear, but this is its real 
meaning. And further, they say that since the atomic bodies differ in 
shape, and there is an infinity of shapes, there is an infinity of simple 
bodies. But they have never explained in detail the shapes of the 
various elements, except so far to allot the sphere to fire. Air, water, 
and the rest they distinguished by the relative size of the atom, 
assuming that the atomic substance was a sort of master-seed for 
each and every element. Now, in the first place, they make the 
mistake already noticed. The principles which they assume are not 
limited in number, though such limitation would necessitate no 
other alteration in their theory. Further, if the differences of bodies 
are not infinite, plainly the elements will not be an infinity. Besides, a 
view which asserts atomic bodies must needs come into conflict with 
the mathematical sciences, in addition to invalidating many common 
opinions and apparent data of sense perception. But of these things 
we have already spoken in our discussion of time and movement. 
They are also bound to contradict themselves. For if the elements are 
atomic, air, earth, and water cannot be differentiated by the relative 
sizes of their atoms, since then they could not be generated out of 
one another. The extrusion of the largest atoms is a process that will 
in time exhaust the supply; and it is by such a process that they 
account for the generation of water, air, and earth from one another. 
Again, even on their own presuppositions it does not seem as if the 
elements would be infinite in number. The atoms differ in figure, and 
all figures are composed of pyramids, rectilinear the case of 
rectilinear figures, while the sphere has eight pyramidal parts. The 
figures must have their principles, and, whether these are one or two 



928 



or more, the simple bodies must be the same in number as they. 
Again, if every element has its proper movement, and a simple body 
has a simple movement, and the number of simple movements is not 
infinite, because the simple motions are only two and the number of 
places is not infinite, on these grounds also we should have to deny 
that the number of elements is infinite. 



Since the number of the elements must be limited, it remains to 
inquire whether there is more than one element. Some assume one 
only, which is according to some water, to others air, to others fire, to 
others again something finer than water and denser than air, an 
infinite body - so they say - bracing all the heavens. 

Now those who decide for a single element, which is either water or 
air or a body finer than water and denser than air, and proceed to 
generate other things out of it by use of the attributes density and 
rarity, all alike fail to observe the fact that they are depriving the 
element of its priority. Generation out of the elements is, as they say, 
synthesis, and generation into the elements is analysis, so that the 
body with the finer parts must have priority in the order of nature. 
But they say that fire is of all bodies the finest. Hence fire will be first 
in the natural order. And whether the finest body is fire or not makes 
no difference; anyhow it must be one of the other bodies that is 
primary and not that which is intermediate. Again, density and rarity, 
as instruments of generation, are equivalent to fineness and 
coarseness, since the fine is rare, and coarse in their use means 
dense. But fineness and coarseness, again, are equivalent to 
greatness and smallness, since a thing with small parts is fine and a 
thing with large parts coarse. For that which spreads itself out widely 
is fine, and a thing composed of small parts is so spread out. In the 
end, then, they distinguish the various other substances from the 
element by the greatness and smallness of their parts. This method 
of distinction makes all judgement relative. There will be no absolute 



929 



distinction between fire, water, and air, but one and the same body 
will be relatively to this fire, relatively to something else air. The same 
difficulty is involved equally in the view elements and distinguishes 
them by their greatness and smallness. The principle of distinction 
between bodies being quantity, the various sizes will be in a definite 
ratio, and whatever bodies are in this ratio to one another must be 
air, fire, earth, and water respectively. For the ratios of smaller bodies 
may be repeated among greater bodies. 

Those who start from fire as the single element, while avoiding this 
difficulty, involve themselves in many others. Some of them give fire 
a particular shape, like those who make it a pyramid, and this on one 
of two grounds. The reason given may be - more crudely - that the 
pyramid is the most piercing of figures as fire is of bodies, or - more 
ingeniously - the position may be supported by the following 
argument. As all bodies are composed of that which has the finest 
parts, so all solid figures are composed of pryamids: but the finest 
body is fire, while among figures the pyramid is primary and has the 
smallest parts; and the primary body must have the primary figure: 
therefore fire will be a pyramid. Others, again, express no opinion on 
the subject of its figure, but simply regard it as the of the finest parts, 
which in combination will form other bodies, as the fusing of gold- 
dust produces solid gold. Both of these views involve the same 
difficulties. For (1) if, on the one hand, they make the primary body 
an atom, the view will be open to the objections already advanced 
against the atomic theory. And further the theory is inconsistent with 
a regard for the facts of nature. For if all bodies are quantitatively 
commensurable, and the relative size of the various homoeomerous 
masses and of their several elements are in the same ratio, so that 
the total mass of water, for instance, is related to the total mass of air 
as the elements of each are to one another, and so on, and if there is 
more air than water and, generally, more of the finer body than of the 
coarser, obviously the element of water will be smaller than that of 
air. But the lesser quantity is contained in the greater. Therefore the 
air element is divisible. And the same could be shown of fire and of 
all bodies whose parts are relatively fine. (2) If, on the other hand, the 
primary body is divisible, then (a) those who give fire a special shape 
will have to say that a part of fire is not fire, because a pyramid is not 



930 



composed of pyramids, and also that not every body is either an 
element or composed of elements, since a part of fire will be neither 
fire nor any other element. And (b) those whose ground of distinction 
is size will have to recognize an element prior to the element, a 
regress which continues infinitely, since every body is divisible and 
that which has the smallest parts is the element. Further, they too 
will have to say that the same body is relatively to this fire and 
relatively to that air, to others again water and earth. 

The common error of all views which assume a single element is that 
they allow only one natural movement, which is the same for every 
body. For it is a matter of observation that a natural body possesses a 
principle of movement. If then all bodies are one, all will have one 
movement. With this motion the greater their quantity the more they 
will move, just as fire, in proportion as its quantity is greater, moves 
faster with the upward motion which belongs to it. But the fact is 
that increase of quantity makes many things move the faster 
downward. For these reasons, then, as well as from the distinction 
already established of a plurality of natural movements, it is 
impossible that there should be only one element. But if the elements 
are not an infinity and not reducible to one, they must be several and 
finite in number. 



First we must inquire whether the elements are eternal or subject to 
generation and destruction; for when this question has been 
answered their number and character will be manifest. In the first 
place, they cannot be eternal. It is a matter of observation that fire, 
water, and every simple body undergo a process of analysis, which 
must either continue infinitely or stop somewhere. (1) Suppose it 
infinite. Then the time occupied by the process will be infinite, and 
also that occupied by the reverse process of synthesis. For the 
processes of analysis and synthesis succeed one another in the 
various parts. It will follow that there are two infinite times which are 



931 



mutually exclusive, the time occupied by the synthesis, which is 
infinite, being preceded by the period of analysis. There are thus two 
mutually exclusive infinites, which is impossible. (2) Suppose, on the 
other hand, that the analysis stops somewhere. Then the body at 
which it stops will be either atomic or, as Empedocles seems to have 
intended, a divisible body which will yet never be divided. The 
foregoing arguments show that it cannot be an atom; but neither can 
it be a divisible body which analysis will never reach. For a smaller 
body is more easily destroyed than a larger; and a destructive process 
which succeeds in destroying, that is, in resolving into smaller 
bodies, a body of some size, cannot reasonably be expected to fail 
with the smaller body. Now in fire we observe a destruction of two 
kinds: it is destroyed by its contrary when it is quenched, and by 
itself when it dies out. But the effect is produced by a greater 
quantity upon a lesser, and the more quickly the smaller it is. The 
elements of bodies must therefore be subject to destruction and 
generation. 

Since they are generated, they must be generated either from 
something incorporeal or from a body, and if from a body, either from 
one another or from something else. The theory which generates 
them from something incorporeal requires an extra-corporeal void. 
For everything that comes to be comes to be in something, and that 
in which the generation takes place must either be incorporeal or 
possess body; and if it has body, there will be two bodies in the same 
place at the same time, viz. that which is coming to be and that 
which was previously there, while if it is incorporeal, there must be 
an extra-corporeal void. But we have already shown that this is 
impossible. But, on the other hand, it is equally impossible that the 
elements should be generated from some kind of body. That would 
involve a body distinct from the elements and prior to them. But if 
this body possesses weight or lightness, it will be one of the 
elements; and if it has no tendency to movement, it will be an 
immovable or mathematical entity, and therefore not in a place at all. 
A place in which a thing is at rest is a place in which it might move, 
either by constraint, i.e. unnaturally, or in the absence of constraint, 
i.e. naturally. If, then, it is in a place and somewhere, it will be one of 
the elements; and if it is not in a place, nothing can come from it, 



932 



since that which comes into being and that out of which it comes 
must needs be together. The elements therefore cannot be generated 
from something incorporeal nor from a body which is not an 
element, and the only remaining alternative is that they are 
generated from one another. 



We must, therefore, turn to the question, what is the manner of their 
generation from one another? Is it as Empedocles and Democritus 
say, or as those who resolve bodies into planes say, or is there yet 
another possibility? (1) What the followers of Empedocles do, though 
without observing it themselves, is to reduce the generation of 
elements out of one another to an illusion. They make it a process of 
excretion from a body of what was in it all the time - as though 
generation required a vessel rather than a material - so that it 
involves no change of anything. And even if this were accepted, there 
are other implications equally unsatisfactory. We do not expect a 
mass of matter to be made heavier by compression. But they will be 
bound to maintain this, if they say that water is a body present in air 
and excreted from air, since air becomes heavier when it turns into 
water. Again, when the mixed body is divided, they can show no 
reason why one of the constituents must by itself take up more room 
than the body did: but when water turns into air, the room occupied 
is increased. The fact is that the finer body takes up more room, as is 
obvious in any case of transformation. As the liquid is converted into 
vapour or air the vessel which contains it is often burst because it 
does not contain room enough. Now, if there is no void at all, and if, 
as those who take this view say, there is no expansion of bodies, the 
impossibility of this is manifest: and if there is void and expansion, 
there is no accounting for the fact that the body which results from 
division cfpies of necessity a greater space. It is inevitable, too, that 
generation of one out of another should come to a stop, since a finite 
quantum cannot contain an infinity of finite quanta. When earth 
produces water something is taken away from the earth, for the 



933 



process is one of excretion. The same thing happens again when the 
residue produces water. But this can only go on for ever, if the finite 
body contains an infinity, which is impossible. Therefore the 
generation of elements out of one another will not always continue. 

(2) We have now explained that the mutual transformations of the 
elements cannot take place by means of excretion. The remaining 
alternative is that they should be generated by changing into one 
another. And this in one of two ways, either by change of shape, as 
the same wax takes the shape both of a sphere and of a cube, or, as 
some assert, by resolution into planes, (a) Generation by change of 
shape would necessarily involve the assertion of atomic bodies. For if 
the particles were divisible there would be a part of fire which was 
not fire and a part of earth which was not earth, for the reason that 
not every part of a pyramid is a pyramid nor of a cube a cube. But if 
(b) the process is resolution into planes, the first difficulty is that the 
elements cannot all be generated out of one another. This they are 
obliged to assert, and do assert. It is absurd, because it is 
unreasonable that one element alone should have no part in the 
transformations, and also contrary to the observed data of sense, 
according to which all alike change into one another. In fact their 
explanation of the observations is not consistent with the 
observations. And the reason is that their ultimate principles are 
wrongly assumed: they had certain predetermined views, and were 
resolved to bring everything into line with them. It seems that 
perceptible things require perceptible principles, eternal things 
eternal principles, corruptible things corruptible principles; and, in 
general, every subject matter principles homogeneous with itself. But 
they, owing to their love for their principles, fall into the attitude of 
men who undertake the defence of a position in argument. In the 
confidence that the principles are true they are ready to accept any 
consequence of their application. As though some principles did not 
require to be judged from their results, and particularly from their 
final issue! And that issue, which in the case of productive knowledge 
is the product, in the knowledge of nature is the unimpeachable 
evidence of the senses as to each fact. 



934 



The result of their view is that earth has the best right to the name 
element, and is alone indestructible; for that which is indissoluble is 
indestructible and elementary, and earth alone cannot be dissolved 
into any body but itself. Again, in the case of those elements which 
do suffer dissolution, the 'suspension' of the triangles is 
unsatisfactory. But this takes place whenever one is dissolved into 
another, because of the numerical inequality of the triangles which 
compose them. Further, those who hold these views must needs 
suppose that generation does not start from a body. For what is 
generated out of planes cannot be said to have been generated from a 
body. And they must also assert that not all bodies are divisible, 
coming thus into conflict with our most accurate sciences, namely 
the mathematical, which assume that even the intelligible is 
divisible, while they, in their anxiety to save their hypothesis, cannot 
even admit this of every perceptible thing. For any one who gives 
each element a shape of its own, and makes this the ground of 
distinction between the substances, has to attribute to them 
indivisibility; since division of a pyramid or a sphere must leave 
somewhere at least a residue which is not sphere or a pyramid. 
Either, then, a part of fire is not fire, so that there is a body prior to 
the element - for every body is either an element or composed of 
elements - or not every body is divisible. 



8 

In general, the attempt to give a shape to each of the simple bodies is 
unsound, for the reason, first, that they will not succeed in filling the 
whole. It is agreed that there are only three plane figures which can 
fill a space, the triangle, the square, and the hexagon, and only two 
solids, the pyramid and the cube. But the theory needs more than 
these because the elements which it recognizes are more in number. 
Secondly, it is manifest that the simple bodies are often given a 
shape by the place in which they are included, particularly water and 
air. In such a case the shape of the element cannot persist; for, if it 
did, the contained mass would not be in continuous contact with the 



935 



containing body; while, if its shape is changed, it will cease to be 
water, since the distinctive quality is shape. Clearly, then, their 
shapes are not fixed. Indeed, nature itself seems to offer 
corroboration of this theoretical conclusion. Just as in other cases the 
substratum must be formless and unshapen - for thus the 'all- 
receptive', as we read in the Timaeus, will be best for modelling - so 
the elements should be conceived as a material for composite things; 
and that is why they can put off their qualitative distinctions and 
pass into one another. Further, how can they account for the 
generation of flesh and bone or any other continuous body? The 
elements alone cannot produce them because their collocation 
cannot produce a continuum. Nor can the composition of planes; for 
this produces the elements themselves, not bodies made up of them. 
Any one then who insists upon an exact statement of this kind of 
theory, instead of assenting after a passing glance at it, will see that it 
removes generation from the world. 

Further, the very properties, powers, and motions, to which they paid 
particular attention in allotting shapes, show the shapes not to be in 
accord with the bodies. Because fire is mobile and productive of heat 
and combustion, some made it a sphere, others a pyramid. These 
shapes, they thought, were the most mobile because they offer the 
fewest points of contact and are the least stable of any; they were 
also the most apt to produce warmth and combustion, because the 
one is angular throughout while the other has the most acute angles, 
and the angles, they say, produce warmth and combustion. Now, in 
the first place, with regard to movement both are in error. These may 
be the figures best adapted to movement; they are not, however, well 
adapted to the movement of fire, which is an upward and rectilinear 
movement, but rather to that form of circular movement which we 
call rolling. Earth, again, they call a cube because it is stable and at 
rest. But it rests only in its own place, not anywhere; from any other 
it moves if nothing hinders, and fire and the other bodies do the 
same. The obvious inference, therefore, is that fire and each several 
element is in a foreign place a sphere or a pyramid, but in its own a 
cube. Again, if the possession of angles makes a body produce heat 
and combustion, every element produces heat, though one may do so 
more than another. For they all possess angles, the octahedron and 



936 



dodecahedron as well as the pyramid; and Democritus makes even 
the sphere a kind of angle, which cuts things because of its mobility. 
The difference, then, will be one of degree: and this is plainly false. 
They must also accept the inference that the mathematical produce 
heat and combustion, since they too possess angles and contain 
atomic spheres and pyramids, especially if there are, as they allege, 
atomic figures. Anyhow if these functions belong to some of these 
things and not to others, they should explain the difference, instead 
of speaking in quite general terms as they do. Again, combustion of a 
body produces fire, and fire is a sphere or a pyramid. The body, then, 
is turned into spheres or pyramids. Let us grant that these figures 
may reasonably be supposed to cut and break up bodies as fire does; 
still it remains quite inexplicable that a pyramid must needs produce 
pyramids or a sphere spheres. One might as well postulate that a 
knife or a saw divides things into knives or saws. It is also ridiculous 
to think only of division when allotting fire its shape. Fire is generally 
thought of as combining and connecting rather than as separating. 
For though it separates bodies different in kind, it combines those 
which are the same; and the combining is essential to it, the 
functions of connecting and uniting being a mark of fire, while the 
separating is incidental. For the expulsion of the foreign body is an 
incident in the compacting of the homogeneous. In choosing the 
shape, then, they should have thought either of both functions or 
preferably of the combining function. In addition, since hot and cold 
are contrary powers, it is impossible to allot any shape to the cold. 
For the shape given must be the contrary of that given to the hot, but 
there is no contrariety between figures. That is why they have all left 
the cold out, though properly either all or none should have their 
distinguishing figures. Some of them, however, do attempt to explain 
this power, and they contradict themselves. A body of large particles, 
they say, is cold because instead of penetrating through the passages 
it crushes. Clearly, then, that which is hot is that which penetrates 
these passages, or in other words that which has fine particles. It 
results that hot and cold are distinguished not by the figure but by 
the size of the particles. Again, if the pyramids are unequal in size, 
the large ones will not be fire, and that figure will produce not 
combustion but its contrary. 



937 



From what has been said it is clear that the difference of the 
elements does not depend upon their shape. Now their most 
important differences are those of property, function, and power; for 
every natural body has, we maintain, its own functions, properties, 
and powers. Our first business, then, will be to speak of these, and 
that inquiry will enable us to explain the differences of each from 
each. 



Book IV 



We have now to consider the terms 'heavy' and 'light'. We must ask 
what the bodies so called are, how they are constituted, and what is 
the reason of their possessing these powers. The consideration of 
these questions is a proper part of the theory of movement, since we 
call things heavy and light because they have the power of being 
moved naturally in a certain way. The activities corresponding to 
these powers have not been given any name, unless it is thought that 
'impetus' is such a name. But because the inquiry into nature is 
concerned with movement, and these things have in themselves 
some spark (as it were) of movement, all inquirers avail themselves 
of these powers, though in all but a few cases without exact 
discrimination. We must then first look at whatever others have said, 
and formulate the questions which require settlement in the 
interests of this inquiry, before we go on to state our own view of the 
matter. 

Language recognizes (a) an absolute, (b) a relative heavy and light. Of 
two heavy things, such as wood and bronze, we say that the one is 



938 



relatively light, the other relatively heavy. Our predecessors have not 
dealt at all with the absolute use, of the terms, but only with the 
relative. I mean, they do not explain what the heavy is or what the 
light is, but only the relative heaviness and lightness of things 
possessing weight. This can be made clearer as follows. There are 
things whose constant nature it is to move away from the centre, 
while others move constantly towards the centre; and of these 
movements that which is away from the centre I call upward 
movement and that which is towards it I call downward movement. 
(The view, urged by some, that there is no up and no down in the 
heaven, is absurd. There can be, they say, no up and no down, since 
the universe is similar every way, and from any point on the earth's 
surface a man by advancing far enough will come to stand foot to 
foot with himself. But the extremity of the whole, which we call 
'above', is in position above and in nature primary. And since the 
universe has an extremity and a centre, it must clearly have an up 
and down. Common usage is thus correct, though inadequate. And 
the reason of its inadequacy is that men think that the universe is 
not similar every way. They recognize only the hemisphere which is 
over us. But if they went on to think of the world as formed on this 
pattern all round, with a centre identically related to each point on 
the extremity, they would have to admit that the extremity was above 
and the centre below.) By absolutely light, then, we mean that which 
moves upward or to the extremity, and by absolutely heavy that 
which moves downward or to the centre. By lighter or relatively light 
we mean that one, of two bodies endowed with weight and equal in 
bulk, which is exceeded by the other in the speed of its natural 
downward movement. 



Those of our predecessors who have entered upon this inquiry have 
for the most part spoken of light and heavy things only in the sense 
in which one of two things both endowed with weight is said to be 
the lighter. And this treatment they consider a sufficient analysis also 



939 



of the notions of absolute heaviness, to which their account does not 
apply. This, however, will become clearer as we advance. One use of 
the terms 'lighter' and 'heavier' is that which is set forth in writing in 
the Timaeus, that the body which is composed of the greater number 
of identical parts is relatively heavy, while that which is composed of 
a smaller number is relatively light. As a larger quantity of lead or of 
bronze is heavier than a smaller - and this holds good of all 
homogeneous masses, the superior weight always depending upon a 
numerical superiority of equal parts - in precisely the same way, they 
assert, lead is heavier than wood. For all bodies, in spite of the 
general opinion to the contrary, are composed of identical parts and 
of a single material. But this analysis says nothing of the absolutely 
heavy and light. The facts are that fire is always light and moves 
upward, while earth and all earthy things move downwards or 
towards the centre. It cannot then be the fewness of the triangles (of 
which, in their view, all these bodies are composed) which disposes 
fire to move upward. If it were, the greater the quantity of fire the 
slower it would move, owing to the increase of weight due to the 
increased number of triangles. But the palpable fact, on the contrary, 
is that the greater the quantity, the lighter the mass is and the 
quicker its upward movement: and, similarly, in the reverse 
movement from above downward, the small mass will move quicker 
and the large slower. Further, since to be lighter is to have fewer of 
these homogeneous parts and to be heavier is to have more, and air, 
water, and fire are composed of the same triangles, the only 
difference being in the number of such parts, which must therefore 
explain any distinction of relatively light and heavy between these 
bodies, it follows that there must be a certain quantum of air which 
is heavier than water. But the facts are directly opposed to this. The 
larger the quantity of air the more readily it moves upward, and any 
portion of air without exception will rise up out of the water. 

So much for one view of the distinction between light and heavy. To 
others the analysis seems insufficient; and their views on the subject, 
though they belong to an older generation than ours, have an air of 
novelty. It is apparent that there are bodies which, when smaller in 
bulk than others, yet exceed them in weight. It is therefore obviously 
insufficient to say that bodies of equal weight are composed of an 



940 



equal number of primary parts: for that would give equality of bulk. 
Those who maintain that the primary or atomic parts, of which 
bodies endowed with weight are composed, are planes, cannot so 
speak without absurdity; but those who regard them as solids are in a 
better position to assert that of such bodies the larger is the heavier. 
But since in composite bodies the weight obviously does not 
correspond in this way to the bulk, the lesser bulk being often 
superior in weight (as, for instance, if one be wool and the other 
bronze), there are some who think and say that the cause is to be 
found elsewhere. The void, they say, which is imprisoned in bodies, 
lightens them and sometimes makes the larger body the lighter. The 
reason is that there is more void. And this would also account for the 
fact that a body composed of a number of solid parts equal to, or 
even smaller than, that of another is sometimes larger in bulk than it. 
In short, generally and in every case a body is relatively light when it 
contains a relatively large amount of void. This is the way they put it 
themselves, but their account requires an addition. Relative lightness 
must depend not only on an excess of void, but also an a defect of 
solid: for if the ratio of solid to void exceeds a certain proportion, the 
relative lightness will disappear. Thus fire, they say, is the lightest of 
things just for this reason that it has the most void. But it would 
follow that a large mass of gold, as containing more void than a small 
mass of fire, is lighter than it, unless it also contains many times as 
much solid. The addition is therefore necessary. 

Of those who deny the existence of a void some, like Anaxagoras and 
Empedocles, have not tried to analyse the notions of light and heavy 
at all; and those who, while still denying the existence of a void, have 
attempted this, have failed to explain why there are bodies which are 
absolutely heavy and light, or in other words why some move upward 
and others downward. The fact, again, that the body of greater bulk is 
sometimes lighter than smaller bodies is one which they have passed 
over in silence, and what they have said gives no obvious suggestion 
for reconciling their views with the observed facts. 

But those who attribute the lightness of fire to its containing so much 
void are necessarily involved in practically the same difficulties. For 
though fire be supposed to contain less solid than any other body, as 



941 



well as more void, yet there will be a certain quantum of fire in which 
the amount of solid or plenum is in excess of the solids contained in 
some small quantity of earth. They may reply that there is an excess 
of void also. But the question is, how will they discriminate the 
absolutely heavy? Presumably, either by its excess of solid or by its 
defect of void. On the former view there could be an amount of earth 
so small as to contain less solid than a large mass of fire. And 
similarly, if the distinction rests on the amount of void, there will be a 
body, lighter than the absolutely light, which nevertheless moves 
downward as constantly as the other moves upward. But that cannot 
be so, since the absolutely light is always lighter than bodies which 
have weight and move downward, while, on the other hand, that 
which is lighter need not be light, because in common speech we 
distinguish a lighter and a heavier (viz. water and earth) among 
bodies endowed with weight. Again, the suggestion of a certain ratio 
between the void and the solid in a body is no more equal to solving 
the problem before us. The manner of speaking will issue in a similar 
impossibility. For any two portions of fire, small or great, will exhibit 
the same ratio of solid to void, but the upward movement of the 
greater is quicker than that of the less, just as the downward 
movement of a mass of gold or lead, or of any other body endowed 
with weight, is quicker in proportion to its size. This, however, should 
not be the case if the ratio is the ground of distinction between heavy 
things and light. There is also an absurdity in attributing the upward 
movement of bodies to a void which does not itself move. If, however, 
it is the nature of a void to move upward and of a plenum to move 
downward, and therefore each causes a like movement in other 
things, there was no need to raise the question why composite bodies 
are some light and some heavy; they had only to explain why these 
two things are themselves light and heavy respectively, and to give, 
further, the reason why the plenum and the void are not eternally 
separated. It is also unreasonable to imagine a place for the void, as if 
the void were not itself a kind of place. But if the void is to move, it 
must have a place out of which and into which the change carries it. 
Also what is the cause of its movement? Not, surely, its voidness: for 
it is not the void only which is moved, but also the solid. 



942 



Similar difficulties are involved in all other methods of distinction, 
whether they account for the relative lightness and heaviness of 
bodies by distinctions of size, or proceed on any other principle, so 
long as they attribute to each the same matter, or even if they 
recognize more than one matter, so long as that means only a pair of 
contraries. If there is a single matter, as with those who compose 
things of triangles, nothing can be absolutely heavy or light: and if 
there is one matter and its contrary - the void, for instance, and the 
plenum - no reason can be given for the relative lightness and 
heaviness of the bodies intermediate between the absolutely light 
and heavy when compared either with one another or with these 
themselves. The view which bases the distinction upon differences of 
size is more like a mere fiction than those previously mentioned, but, 
in that it is able to make distinctions between the four elements, it is 
in a stronger position for meeting the foregoing difficulties. Since, 
however, it imagines that these bodies which differ in size are all 
made of one substance, it implies, equally with the view that there is 
but one matter, that there is nothing absolutely light and nothing 
which moves upward (except as being passed by other things or 
forced up by them); and since a multitude of small atoms are heavier 
than a few large ones, it will follow that much air or fire is heavier 
than a little water or earth, which is impossible. 



These, then, are the views which have been advanced by others and 
the terms in which they state them. We may begin our own 
statement by settling a question which to some has been the main 
difficulty - the question why some bodies move always and naturally 
upward and others downward, while others again move both upward 
and downward. After that we will inquire into light and heavy and of 
the various phenomena connected with them. The local movement 
of each body into its own place must be regarded as similar to what 
happens in connexion with other forms of generation and change. 
There are, in fact, three kinds of movement, affecting respectively the 



943 



size, the form, and the place of a thing, and in each it is observable 
that change proceeds from a contrary to a contrary or to something 
intermediate: it is never the change of any chance subject in any 
chance direction, nor, similarly, is the relation of the mover to its 
object fortuitous: the thing altered is different from the thing 
increased, and precisely the same difference holds between that 
which produces alteration and that which produces increase. In the 
same manner it must be thought that produces local motion and that 
which is so moved are not fortuitously related. Now, that which 
produces upward and downward movement is that which produces 
weight and lightness, and that which is moved is that which is 
potentially heavy or light, and the movement of each body to its own 
place is motion towards its own form. (It is best to interpret in this 
sense the common statement of the older writers that 'like moves to 
like'. For the words are not in every sense true to fact. If one were to 
remove the earth to where the moon now is, the various fragments of 
earth would each move not towards it but to the place in which it 
now is. In general, when a number of similar and undifferentiated 
bodies are moved with the same motion this result is necessarily 
produced, viz. that the place which is the natural goal of the 
movement of each single part is also that of the whole. But since the 
place of a thing is the boundary of that which contains it, and the 
continent of all things that move upward or downward is the 
extremity and the centre, and this boundary comes to be, in a sense, 
the form of that which is contained, it is to its like that a body moves 
when it moves to its own place. For the successive members of the 
scries are like one another: water, I mean, is like air and air like fire, 
and between intermediates the relation may be converted, though 
not between them and the extremes; thus air is like water, but water 
is like earth: for the relation of each outer body to that which is next 
within it is that of form to matter.) Thus to ask why fire moves 
upward and earth downward is the same as to ask why the healable, 
when moved and changed qua healable, attains health and not 
whiteness; and similar questions might be asked concerning any 
other subject of aletion. Of course the subject of increase, when 
changed qua increasable, attains not health but a superior size. The 
same applies in the other cases. One thing changes in quality, 



944 



another in quantity: and so in place, a light thing goes upward, a 
heavy thing downward. The only difference is that in the last case, 
viz. that of the heavy and the light, the bodies are thought to have a 
spring of change within themselves, while the subjects of healing 
and increase are thought to be moved purely from without. 
Sometimes, however, even they change of themselves, ie. in response 
to a slight external movement reach health or increase, as the case 
may be. And since the same thing which is healable is also receptive 
of disease, it depends on whether it is moved qua healable or qua 
liable to disease whether the motion is towards health or towards 
disease. But the reason why the heavy and the light appear more 
than these things to contain within themselves the source of their 
movements is that their matter is nearest to being. This is indicated 
by the fact that locomotion belongs to bodies only when isolated 
from other bodies, and is generated last of the several kinds of 
movement; in order of being then it will be first. Now whenever air 
comes into being out of water, light out of heavy, it goes to the upper 
place. It is forthwith light: becoming is at an end, and in that place it 
has being. Obviously, then, it is a potentiality, which, in its passage to 
actuality, comes into that place and quantity and quality which 
belong to its actuality. And the same fact explains why what is 
already actually fire or earth moves, when nothing obstructs it, 
towards its own place. For motion is equally immediate in the case of 
nutriment, when nothing hinders, and in the case of the thing 
healed, when nothing stays the healing. But the movement is also 
due to the original creative force and to that which removes the 
hindrance or off which the moving thing rebounded, as was 
explained in our opening discussions, where we tried to show how 
none of these things moves itself. The reason of the various motions 
of the various bodies, and the meaning of the motion of a body to its 
own place, have now been explained. 



945 



We have now to speak of the distinctive properties of these bodies 
and of the various phenomena connected with them. In accordance 
with general conviction we may distinguish the absolutely heavy, as 
that which sinks to the bottom of all things, from the absolutely light, 
which is that which rises to the surface of all things. I use the term 
'absolutely', in view of the generic character of 'light' and 'heavy', in 
order to confine the application to bodies which do not combine 
lightness and heaviness. It is apparent, I mean, that fire, in whatever 
quantity, so long as there is no external obstacle moves upward, and 
earth downward; and, if the quantity is increased, the movement is 
the same, though swifter. But the heaviness and lightness of bodies 
which combine these qualities is different from this, since while they 
rise to the surface of some bodies they sink to the bottom of others. 
Such are air and water. Neither of them is absolutely either light or 
heavy. Both are lighter than earth - for any portion of either rises to 
the surface of it - but heavier than fire, since a portion of either, 
whatever its quantity, sinks to the bottom of fire; compared together, 
however, the one has absolute weight, the other absolute lightness, 
since air in any quantity rises to the surface of water, while water in 
any quantity sinks to the bottom of air. Now other bodies are 
severally light and heavy, and evidently in them the attributes are 
due to the difference of their uncompounded parts: that is to say, 
according as the one or the other happens to preponderate the bodies 
will be heavy and light respectively. Therefore we need only speak of 
these parts, since they are primary and all else consequential: and in 
so doing we shall be following the advice which we gave to those 
whose attribute heaviness to the presence of plenum and lightness to 
that of void. It is due to the properties of the elementary bodies that a 
body which is regarded as light in one place is regarded as heavy in 
another, and vice versa. In air, for instance, a talent's weight of wood 
is heavier than a mina of lead, but in water the wood is the lighter. 
The reason is that all the elements except fire have weight and all 
but earth lightness. Earth, then, and bodies in which earth 
preponderates, must needs have weight everywhere, while water is 
heavy anywhere but in earth, and air is heavy when not in water or 
earth. In its own place each of these bodies has weight except fire, 



946 



even air. Of this we have evidence in the fact that a bladder when 
inflated weighs more than when empty. A body, then, in which air 
preponderates over earth and water, may well be lighter than 
something in water and yet heavier than it in air, since such a body 
does not rise in air but rises to the surface in water. 

The following account will make it plain that there is an absolutely 
light and an absolutely heavy body. And by absolutely light I mean 
one which of its own nature always moves upward, by absolutely 
heavy one which of its own nature always moves downward, if no 
obstacle is in the way. There are, I say, these two kinds of body, and it 
is not the case, as some maintain, that all bodies have weight. 
Different views are in fact agreed that there is a heavy body, which 
moves uniformly towards the centre. But is also similarly a light body. 
For we see with our eyes, as we said before, that earthy things sink to 
the bottom of all things and move towards the centre. But the centre 
is a fixed point. If therefore there is some body which rises to the 
surface of all things - and we observe fire to move upward even in air 
itself, while the air remains at rest - clearly this body is moving 
towards the extremity. It cannot then have any weight. If it had, there 
would be another body in which it sank: and if that had weight, there 
would be yet another which moved to the extremity and thus rose to 
the surface of all moving things. In fact, however, we have no 
evidence of such a body. Fire, then, has no weight. Neither has earth 
any lightness, since it sinks to the bottom of all things, and that 
which sinks moves to the centre. That there is a centre towards 
which the motion of heavy things, and away from which that of light 
things is directed, is manifest in many ways. First, because no 
movement can continue to infinity. For what cannot be can no more 
come-to-be than be, and movement is a coming-to-be in one place 
from another. Secondly, like the upward movement of fire, the 
downward movement of earth and all heavy things makes equal 
angles on every side with the earth's surface: it must therefore be 
directed towards the centre. Whether it is really the centre of the 
earth and not rather that of the whole to which it moves, may be left 
to another inquiry, since these are coincident. But since that which 
sinks to the bottom of all things moves to the centre, necessarily that 
which rises to the surface moves to the extremity of the region in 



947 



which the movement of these bodies takes place. For the centre is 
opposed as contrary to the extremity, as that which sinks is opposed 
to that which rises to the surface. This also gives a reasonable ground 
for the duality of heavy and light in the spatial duality centre and 
extremity. Now there is also the intermediate region to which each 
name is given in opposition to the other extreme. For that which is 
intermediate between the two is in a sense both extremity and 
centre. For this reason there is another heavy and light; namely, 
water and air. But in our view the continent pertains to form and the 
contained to matter: and this distinction is present in every genus. 
Alike in the sphere of quality and in that of quantity there is that 
which corresponds rather to form and that which corresponds to 
matter. In the same way, among spatial distinctions, the above 
belongs to the determinate, the below to matter. The same holds, 
consequently, also of the matter itself of that which is heavy and 
light: as potentially possessing the one character, it is matter for the 
heavy, and as potentially possessing the other, for the light. It is the 
same matter, but its being is different, as that which is receptive of 
disease is the same as that which is receptive of health, though in 
being different from it, and therefore diseasedness is different from 
healthiness. 



A thing then which has the one kind of matter is light and always 
moves upward, while a thing which has the opposite matter is heavy 
and always moves downward. Bodies composed of kinds of matter 
different from these but having relatively to each other the character 
which these have absolutely, possess both the upward and the 
downward motion. Hence air and water each have both lightness and 
weight, and water sinks to the bottom of all things except earth, 
while air rises to the surface of all things except fire. But since there 
is one body only which rises to the surface of all things and one only 
which sinks to the bottom of all things, there must needs be two 
other bodies which sink in some bodies and rise to the surface of 



948 



others. The kinds of matter, then, must be as numerous as these 
bodies, i.e. four, but though they are four there must be a common 
matter of all - particularly if they pass into one another - which in 
each is in being different. There is no reason why there should not be 
one or more intermediates between the contraries, as in the case of 
colour; for 'intermediate' and 'mean' are capable of more than one 
application. 

Now in its own place every body endowed with both weight and 
lightness has weight - whereas earth has weight everywhere - but 
they only have lightness among bodies to whose surface they rise. 
Hence when a support is withdrawn such a body moves downward 
until it reaches the body next below it, air to the place of water and 
water to that of earth. But if the fire above air is removed, it will not 
move upward to the place of fire, except by constraint; and in that 
way water also may be drawn up, when the upward movement of air 
which has had a common surface with it is swift enough to 
overpower the downward impulse of the water. Nor does water move 
upward to the place of air, except in the manner just described. Earth 
is not so affected at all, because a common surface is not possible to 
it. Hence water is drawn up into the vessel to which fire is applied, 
but not earth. As earth fails to move upward, so fire fails to move 
downward when air is withdrawn from beneath it: for fire has no 
weight even in its own place, as earth has no lightness. The other two 
move downward when the body beneath is withdrawn because, while 
the absolutely heavy is that which sinks to the bottom of all things, 
the relatively heavy sinks to its own place or to the surface of the 
body in which it rises, since it is similar in matter to it. 

It is plain that one must suppose as many distinct species of matter 
as there are bodies. For if, first, there is a single matter of all things, 
as, for instance, the void or the plenum or extension or the triangles, 
either all things will move upward or all things will move downward, 
and the second motion will be abolished. And so, either there will be 
no absolutely light body, if superiority of weight is due to superior 
size or number of the constituent bodies or to the fullness of the 
body: but the contrary is a matter of observation, and it has been 
shown that the downward and upward movements are equally 



949 



constant and universal: or, if the matter in question is the void or 
something similar, which moves uniformly upward, there will be 
nothing to move uniformly downward. Further, it will follow that the 
intermediate bodies move downward in some cases quicker than 
earth: for air in sufficiently large quantity will contain a larger 
number of triangles or solids or particles. It is, however, manifest that 
no portion of air whatever moves downward. And the same 
reasoning applies to lightness, if that is supposed to depend on 
superiority of quantity of matter. But if, secondly, the kinds of matter 
are two, it will be difficult to make the intermediate bodies behave as 
air and water behave. Suppose, for example, that the two asserted are 
void and plenum. Fire, then, as moving upward, will be void, earth, as 
moving downward, plenum; and in air, it will be said, fire 
preponderates, in water, earth. There will then be a quantity of water 
containing more fire than a little air, and a large amount of air will 
contain more earth than a little water: consequently we shall have to 
say that air in a certain quantity moves downward more quickly than 
a little water. But such a thing has never been observed anywhere. 
Necessarily, then, as fire goes up because it has something, e.g. void, 
which other things do not have, and earth goes downward because it 
has plenum, so air goes to its own place above water because it has 
something else, and water goes downward because of some special 
kind of body. But if the two bodies are one matter, or two matters 
both present in each, there will be a certain quantity of each at which 
water will excel a little air in the upward movement and air excel 
water in the downward movement, as we have already often said. 



The shape of bodies will not account for their moving upward or 
downward in general, though it will account for their moving faster 
or slower. The reasons for this are not difficult to see. For the problem 
thus raised is why a flat piece of iron or lead floats upon water, while 
smaller and less heavy things, so long as they are round or long - a 
needle, for instance - sink down; and sometimes a thing floats 



950 



because it is small, as with gold dust and the various earthy and 
dusty materials which throng the air. With regard to these questions, 
it is wrong to accept the explanation offered by Democritus. He says 
that the warm bodies moving up out of the water hold up heavy 
bodies which are broad, while the narrow ones fall through, because 
the bodies which offer this resistance are not numerous. But this 
would be even more likely to happen in air - an objection which he 
himself raises. His reply to the objection is feeble. In the air, he says, 
the 'drive' (meaning by drive the movement of the upward moving 
bodies) is not uniform in direction. But since some continua are 
easily divided and others less easily, and things which produce 
division differ similarly in the case with which they produce it, the 
explanation must be found in this fact. It is the easily bounded, in 
proportion as it is easily bounded, which is easily divided; and air is 
more so than water, water than earth. Further, the smaller the 
quantity in each kind, the more easily it is divided and disrupted. 
Thus the reason why broad things keep their place is because they 
cover so wide a surface and the greater quantity is less easily 
disrupted. Bodies of the opposite shape sink down because they 
occupy so little of the surface, which is therefore easily parted. And 
these considerations apply with far greater force to air, since it is so 
much more easily divided than water. But since there are two factors, 
the force responsible for the downward motion of the heavy body 
and the disruption-resisting force of the continuous surface, there 
must be some ratio between the two. For in proportion as the force 
applied by the heavy thing towards disruption and division exceeds 
that which resides in the continuum, the quicker will it force its way 
down; only if the force of the heavy thing is the weaker, will it ride 
upon the surface. 

We have now finished our examination of the heavy and the light 
and of the phenomena connected with them. 



951 



Aristotle - On Generation and Corruption 
[Translated by H. H.Joachim] 



Book I 



Our next task is to study coming-to-be and passing-away. We 
are to distinguish the causes, and to state the definitions, of 
these processes considered in general - as changes predicable 
uniformly of all the things that come-to-be and pass-away by 
nature. Further, we are to study growth and 'alteration'. We 
must inquire what each of them is; and whether 'alteration' is 
to be identified with coming-to-be, or whether to these different 
names there correspond two separate processes with distinct 
natures. 

On this question, indeed, the early philosophers are divided. 
Some of them assert that the so-called 'unqualified coming-to- 
be' is 'alteration', while others maintain that 'alteration' and 
coming-to-be are distinct. For those who say that the universe is 
one something (i.e. those who generate all things out of one 
thing) are bound to assert that coming-to-be is 'alteration', and 
that whatever 'comes-to-be' in the proper sense of the term is 
'being altered': but those who make the matter of things more 
than one must distinguish coming-to-be from 'alteration'. To 
this latter class belong Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Leucippus. 
And yet Anaxagoras himself failed to understand his own 
utterance. He says, at all events, that coming-to-be and passing- 



952 



away are the same as 'being altered':' yet, in common with 
other thinkers, he affirms that the elements are many. Thus 
Empedocles holds that the corporeal elements are four, while all 
the elements - including those which initiate movement - are 
six in number; whereas Anaxagoras agrees with Leucippus and 
Democritus that the elements are infinite. 

(Anaxagoras posits as elements the 'homoeomeries', viz. bone, 
flesh, marrow, and everything else which is such that part and 
whole are the same in name and nature; while Democritus and 
Leucippus say that there are indivisible bodies, infinite both in 
number and in the varieties of their shapes, of which everything 
else is composed - the compounds differing one from another 
according to the shapes, 'positions', and 'groupings' of their 
constituents.) 

For the views of the school of Anaxagoras seem diametrically 
opposed to those of the followers of Empedocles. Empedocles 
says that Fire, Water, Air, and Earth are four elements, and are 
thus 'simple' rather than flesh, bone, and bodies which, like 
these, are 'homoeomeries'. But the followers of Anaxagoras 
regard the 'homoeomeries' as 'simple' and elements, whilst 
they affirm that Earth, Fire, Water, and Air are composite; for 
each of these is (according to them) a 'common seminary' of all 
the 'homoeomeries'. 

Those, then, who construct all things out of a single element, 
must maintain that coming-to-be and passing-away are 
'alteration'. For they must affirm that the underlying something 
always remains identical and one; and change of such a 
substratum is what we call 'altering' Those, on the other hand, 
who make the ultimate kinds of things more than one, must 
maintain that 'alteration' is distinct from coming-to-be: for 
coming-to-be and passing-away result from the consilience and 
the dissolution of the many kinds. That is why Empedocles too 



953 



uses language to this effect, when he says 'There is no coming- 
to-be of anything, but only a mingling and a divorce of what has 
been mingled'. Thus it is clear (i) that to describe coming-to-be 
and passing-away in these terms is in accordance with their 
fundamental assumption, and (ii) that they do in fact so 
describe them: nevertheless, they too must recognize 
'alteration' as a fact distinct from coming-to-be, though it is 
impossible for them to do so consistently with what they say. 

That we are right in this criticism is easy to perceive. For 
'alteration' is a fact of observation. While the substance of the 
thing remains unchanged, we see it 'altering' just as we see in it 
the changes of magnitude called 'growth' and 'diminution'. 
Nevertheless, the statements of those who posit more 'original 
reals' than one make 'alteration' impossible. For 'alteration, as 
we assert, takes place in respect to certain qualities: and these 
qualities (I mean, e.g. hot-cold, white-black, dry-moist, soft- 
hard, and so forth) are, all of them, differences characterizing 
the 'elements'. The actual words of Empedocles may be quoted 
in illustration : 

The sun everywhere bright to see, and hot, 

The rain everywhere dark and cold; 

and he distinctively characterizes his remaining elements in a 
similar manner. Since, therefore, it is not possible for Fire to 
become Water, or Water to become Earth, neither will it be 
possible for anything white to become black, or anything soft to 
become hard; and the same argument applies to all the other 
qualities. Yet this is what 'alteration' essentially is. 

It follows, as an obvious corollary, that a single matter must 
always be assumed as underlying the contrary 'poles' of any 
change whether change of place, or growth and diminution, or 
'alteration'; further, that the being of this matter and the being 



954 



of 'alteration' stand and fall together. For if the change is 
'alteration', then the substratum is a single element; i.e. all 
things which admit of change into one another have a single 
matter. And, conversely, if the substratum of the changing 
things is one, there is 'alteration'. 

Empedocles, indeed, seems to contradict his own statements as 
well as the observed facts. For he denies that any one of his 
elements comes-to-be out of any other, insisting on the 
contrary that they are the things out of which everything else 
comes-to-be; and yet (having brought the entirety of existing 
things, except Strife, together into one) he maintains, 
simultaneously with this denial, that each thing once more 
comes-to-be out of the One. Hence it was clearly out of a One 
that this came-to-be Water, and that Fire, various portions of it 
being separated off by certain characteristic differences or 
qualities - as indeed he calls the sun 'white and hot', and the 
earth 'heavy and hard'. If, therefore, these characteristic 
differences be taken away (for they can be taken away, since 
they came-to-be), it will clearly be inevitable for Earth to come- 
to-be out of Water and Water out of Earth, and for each of the 
other elements to undergo a similar transformation - not only 
then, but also now - if, and because, they change their qualities. 
And, to judge by what he says, the qualities are such that they 
can be 'attached' to things and can again be 'separated' from 
them, especially since Strife and Love are still fighting with one 
another for the mastery. It was owing to this same conflict that 
the elements were generated from a One at the former period. I 
say 'generated', for presumably Fire, Earth, and Water had no 
distinctive existence at all while merged in one. 

There is another obscurity in the theory Empedocles. Are we to 
regard the One as his 'original real? Or is it the Many - i.e. Fire 
and Earth, and the bodies co-ordinate with these? For the One is 
an 'element' in so far as it underlies the process as matter - as 



955 



that out of which Earth and Fire come-to-be through a change 
of qualities due to 'the motion'. On the other hand, in so far as 
the One results from composition (by a consilience of the 
Many), whereas they result from disintegration the Many are 
more 'elementary' than the One, and prior to it in their nature. 



We have therefore to discuss the whole subject of 'unqualified' 
coming-to-be and passing-away; we have to inquire whether 
these changes do or do not occur and, if they occur, to explain 
the precise conditions of their occurrence. We must also discuss 
the remaining forms of change, viz. growth and 'alteration'. For 
though, no doubt, Plato investigated the conditions under which 
things come-to-be and pass-away, he confined his inquiry to 
these changes; and he discussed not all coming-to-be, but only 
that of the elements. He asked no questions as to how flesh or 
bones, or any of the other similar compound things, come-to- 
be; nor again did he examine the conditions under which 
'alteration' or growth are attributable to things. 

A similar criticism applies to all our predecessors with the 
single exception of Democritus. Not one of them penetrated 
below the surface or made a thorough examination of a single 
one of the problems. Democritus, however, does seem not only 
to have thought carefully about all the problems, but also to be 
distinguished from the outset by his method. For, as we are 
saying, none of the other philosophers made any definite 
statement about growth, except such as any amateur might 
have made. They said that things grow 'by the accession of like 
to like', but they did not proceed to explain the manner of this 
accession. Nor did they give any account of 'combination': and 



956 



they neglected almost every single one of the remaining 
problems, offering no explanation, e.g. of 'action' or 'passion' 
how in physical actions one thing acts and the other undergoes 
action. Democritus and Leucippus, however, postulate the 
'figures', and make 'alteration' and coming-to-be result from 
them. They explain coming-to-be and passing-away by their 
'dissociation' and 'association', but 'alteration' by their 
'grouping' and 'Position'. And since they thought that the 'truth 
lay in the appearance, and the appearances are conflicting and 
infinitely many, they made the 'figures' infinite in number. 
Hence - owing to the changes of the compound - the same 
thing seems different and conflicting to different people: it is 
'transposed' by a small additional ingredient, and appears 
utterly other by the 'transposition' of a single constituent. For 
Tragedy and Comedy are both composed of the same letters. 

Since almost all our predecessors think (i) that coming-to-be is 
distinct from 'alteration', and (ii) that, whereas things 'alter' by 
change of their qualities, it is by 'association' and 'dissociation' 
that they come-to-be and pass-away, we must concentrate our 
attention on these theses. For they lead to many perplexing and 
well-grounded dilemmas. If, on the one hand, coming-to-be is 
'association', many impossible consequences result: and yet 
there are other arguments, not easy to unravel, which force the 
conclusion upon us that coming-to-be cannot possibly be 
anything else. If, on the other hand, coming-to-be is not 
'association', either there is no such thing as coming-to-be at all 
or it is 'alteration': or else we must endeavour to unravel this 
dilemma too - and a stubborn one we shall find it. The 
fundamental question, in dealing with all these difficulties, is 
this: 'Do things come-to-be and «alter» and grow, and undergo 
the contrary changes, because the primary «reals» are 
indivisible magnitudes? Or is no magnitude indivisible?' For the 
answer we give to this question makes the greatest difference. 
And again, if the primary 'reals' are indivisible magnitudes, are 



957 



these bodies, as Democritus and Leucippus maintain? Or are 
they planes, as is asserted in the Timaeus? 

To resolve bodies into planes and no further - this, as we have 
also remarked elsewhere, in itself a paradox. Hence there is 
more to be said for the view that there are indivisible bodies. Yet 
even these involve much of paradox. Still, as we have said, it is 
possible to construct 'alteration' and coming-to-be with them, if 
one 'transposes' the same by 'turning' and 'intercontact', and by 
'the varieties of the figures', as Democritus does. (His denial of 
the reality of colour is a corollary from this position: for, 
according to him, things get coloured by 'turning' of the 
'figures'.) But the possibility of such a construction no longer 
exists for those who divide bodies into planes. For nothing 
except solids results from putting planes together: they do not 
even attempt to generate any quality from them. 

Lack of experience diminishes our power of taking a 
comprehensive view of the admitted facts. Hence those who 
dwell in intimate association with nature and its phenomena 
grow more and more able to formulate, as the foundations of 
their theories, principles such as to admit of a wide and 
coherent development: while those whom devotion to abstract 
discussions has rendered unobservant of the facts are too ready 
to dogmatize on the basis of a few observations. The rival 
treatments of the subject now before us will serve to illustrate 
how great is the difference between a 'scientific' and a 
'dialectical' method of inquiry. For, whereas the Platonists argue 
that there must be atomic magnitudes 'because otherwise «The 
Triangle» will be more than one', Democritus would appear to 
have been convinced by arguments appropriate to the subject, 
i.e. drawn from the science of nature. Our meaning will become 
clear as we proceed. For to suppose that a body (i.e. a 
magnitude) is divisible through and through, and that this 



958 



division is possible, involves a difficulty. What will there be in 
the body which escapes the division? 

If it is divisible through and through, and if this division is 
possible, then it might be, at one and the same moment, divided 
through and through, even though the dividings had not been 
effected simultaneously: and the actual occurrence of this 
result would involve no impossibility. Hence the same principle 
will apply whenever a body is by nature divisible through and 
through, whether by bisection, or generally by any method 
whatever: nothing impossible will have resulted if it has 
actually been divided - not even if it has been divided into 
innumerable parts, themselves divided innumerable times. 
Nothing impossible will have resulted, though perhaps nobody 
in fact could so divide it. 

Since, therefore, the be dy is divisible through and through, let it 
have been divided. What, then, will remain? A magnitude? No: 
that is impossible, since then there will be something not 
divided, whereas ex hypothesis the body was divisible through 
and through. But if it be admitted that neither a body nor a 
magnitude will remain, and yet division is to take place, the 
constituents of the body will either be points (i.e. without 
magnitude) or absolutely nothing. If its constituents are 
nothings, then it might both come-to-be out of nothings and 
exist as a composite of nothings: and thus presumably the 
whole body will be nothing but an appearance. But if it consists 
of points, a similar absurdity will result: it will not possess any 
magnitude. For when the points were in contact and coincided 
to form a single magnitude, they did not make the whole any 
bigger (since, when the body was divided into two or more 
parts, the whole was not a bit smaller or bigger than it was 
before the division): hence, even if all the points be put together, 
they will not make any magnitude. 



959 



But suppose that, as the body is being divided, a minute section 
- a piece of sawdust, as it were - is extracted, and that in this 
sense - a body 'comes away' from the magnitude, evading the 
division. Even then the same argument applies. For in what 
sense is that section divisible? But if what 'came away' was not 
a body but a separable form or quality, and if the magnitude is 
'points or contacts thus qualified': it is paradoxical that a 
magnitude should consist of elements, which are not 
magnitudes. Moreover, where will the points be? And are they 
motionless or moving? And every contact is always a contact of 
two somethings, i.e. there is always something besides the 
contact or the division or the point. 

These, then, are the difficulties resulting from the supposition 
that any and every body, whatever its size, is divisible through 
and through. There is, besides, this further consideration. If, 
having divided a piece of wood or anything else, I put it 
together, it is again equal to what it was, and is one. Clearly this 
is so, whatever the point at which I cut the wood. The wood, 
therefore, has been divided potentially through and through. 
What, then, is there in the wood besides the division? For even 
if we suppose there is some quality, yet how is the wood 
dissolved into such constituents and how does it come-to-be 
out of them? Or how are such constituents separated so as to 
exist apart from one another? Since, therefore, it is impossible 
for magnitudes to consist of contacts or points, there must be 
indivisible bodies and magnitudes. Yet, if we do postulate the 
latter, we are confronted with equally impossible consequences, 
which we have examined in other works.' But we must try to 
disentangle these perplexities, and must therefore formulate 
the whole problem over again. 

On the one hand, then, it is in no way paradoxical that every 
perceptible body should be indivisible as well as divisible at any 
and every point. For the second predicate will at. tach to it 



960 



potentially, but the first actually. On the other hand, it would 
seem to be impossible for a body to be, even potentially, 
divisible at all points simultaneously. For if it were possible, 
then it might actually occur, with the result, not that the body 
would simultaneously be actually both (indivisible and divided), 
but that it would be simultaneously divided at any and every 
point. Consequently, nothing will remain and the body will have 
passed-away into what is incorporeal: and so it might come-to- 
be again either out of points or absolutely out of nothing. And 
how is that possible? 

But now it is obvious that a body is in fact divided into separable 
magnitudes which are smaller at each division - into 
magnitudes which fall apart from one another and are actually 
separated. Hence (it is urged) the process of dividing a body part 
by part is not a 'breaking up' which could continue ad infinitum; 
nor can a body be simultaneously divided at every point, for 
that is not possible; but there is a limit, beyond which the 
'breaking up' cannot proceed. The necessary consequence - 
especially if coming-to-be and passing-away are to take place by 
'association' and 'dissociation' respectively - is that a body must 
contain atomic magnitudes which are invisible. Such is the 
argument which is believed to establish the necessity of atomic 
magnitudes: we must now show that it conceals a faulty 
inference, and exactly where it conceals it. 

For, since point is not 'immediately-next' to point, magnitudes 
are 'divisible through and through' in one sense, and yet not in 
another. When, however, it is admitted that a magnitude is 
'divisible through and through', it is thought there is a point not 
only anywhere, but also everywhere, in it: hence it is supposed 
to follow, from the admission, that the magnitude must be 
divided away into nothing. For it is supposed - there is a point 
everywhere within it, so that it consists either of contacts or of 
points. But it is only in one sense that the magnitude is 



961 



'divisible through and through', viz. in so far as there is one 
point anywhere within it and all its points are everywhere 
within it if you take them singly one by one. But there are not 
more points than one anywhere within it, for the points are not 
'consecutive': hence it is not simultaneously 'divisible through 
and through'. For if it were, then, if it be divisible at its centre, it 
will be divisible also at a point 'immediately-next' to its centre. 
But it is not so divisible: for position is not 'immediately-next' to 
position, nor point to point - in other words, division is not 
'immediately-next' to division, nor composition to composition. 

Hence there are both 'association' and 'dissociation', though 
neither (a) into, and out of, atomic magnitudes (for that involves 
many impossibilities), nor (b) so that division takes place 
through and through - for this would have resulted only if point 
had been 'immediately-next' to point: but 'dissociation' takes 
place into small (i.e. relatively small) parts, and 'association' 
takes place out of relatively small parts. 

It is wrong, however, to suppose, as some assert, that coming- 
to-be and passing-away in the unqualified and complete sense 
are distinctively defined by 'association' and 'dissociation', 
while the change that takes place in what is continuous is 
'alteration'. On the contrary, this is where the whole error lies. 
For unqualified coming-to-be and passing-away are not effected 
by 'association' and 'dissociation'. They take place when a thing 
changes, from this to that, as a whole. But the philosophers we 
are criticizing suppose that all such change is 'alteration': 
whereas in fact there is a difference. For in that which underlies 
the change there is a factor corresponding to the definition and 
there is a material factor. When, then, the change is in these 
constitutive factors, there will be coming-to-be or passing-away: 
but when it is in the thing's qualities, i.e. a change of the thing 
per accidents, there will be 'alteration'. 



962 



'Dissociation' and 'association' affect the thing's susceptibility 
to passing-away. For if water has first been 'dissociated' into 
smallish drops, air comes-to-be out of it more quickly: while, if 
drops of water have first been 'associated', air comes-to-be 
more slowly. Our doctrine will become clearer in the sequel.' 
Meantime, so much may be taken as established - viz. that 
coming-to-be cannot be 'association', at least not the kind of 
'association' some philosophers assert it to be. 



Now that we have established the preceding distinctions, we 
must first consider whether there is anything which comes-to- 
be and passes-away in the unqualified sense: or whether 
nothing comes-to-be in this strict sense, but everything always 
comes-to-be something and out of something - I mean, e.g. 
comes-to-be-healthy out of being-ill and ill out of being-healthy, 
comes-to-be-small out of being-big and big out of being-small, 
and so on in every other instance. For if there is to be coming- 
to-be without qualification, 'something' must - without 
qualification - 'come-to-be out of not-being', so that it would be 
true to say that 'not-being is an attribute of some things'. For 
qualified coming-to-be is a process out of qualified not-being 
(e.g. out of not-white or not-beautiful), but unqualified coming- 
to-be is a process out of unqualified not-being. 

Now 'unqulified' means either (i) the primary predication within 
each Category, or (ii) the universal, i.e. the all-comprehensive, 
predication. Hence, if 'unqualified not-being' means the 
negation of 'being' in the sense of the primary term of the 
Category in question, we shall have, in 'unqualified coming-to- 
be', a coming-to-be of a substance out of not-substance. But 



963 



that which is not a substance or a 'this' clearly cannot possess 
predicates drawn from any of the other Categories either - e.g. 
we cannot attribute to it any quality, quantity, or position. 
Otherwise, properties would admit of existence in separation 
from substances. If, on the other hand, 'unqualified not-being' 
means 'what is not in any sense at all', it will be a universal 
negation of all forms of being, so that what comes-to-be will 
have to come-to-be out of nothing. 

Although we have dealt with these problems at greater length 
in another work.where we have set forth the difficulties and 
established the distinguishing definitions, the following concise 
restatement of our results must here be offered: In one sense 
things come-to-be out of that which has no 'being' without 
qualification: yet in another sense they come-to-be always out 
of what is'. For coming-to-be necessarily implies the pre- 
existence of something which potentially 'is', but actually 'is 
not'; and this something is spoken of both as 'being' and as 
'not-being'. 

These distinctions may be taken as established: but even then it 
is extraordinarily difficult to see how there can be 'unqualified 
coming-to-be' (whether we suppose it to occur out of what 
potentially 'is', or in some other way), and we must recall this 
problem for further examination. For the question might be 
raised whether substance (i.e. the 'this') comes-to-be at all. Is it 
not rather the 'such', the 'so great', or the 'somewhere', which 
comes-to-be? And the same question might be raised about 
'passing-away' also. For if a substantial thing comes-to-be, it is 
clear that there will 'be' (not actually, but potentially) a 
substance, out of which its coming-to-be will proceed and into 
which the thing that is passing-away will necessarily change. 
Then will any predicate belonging to the remaining Categories 
attach actually to this presupposed substance? In other words, 
will that which is only potentially a 'this' (which only 



964 



potentially is), while without the qualification 'potentially' it is 
not a 'this' (i.e. is not), possess, e.g. any determinate size or 
quality or position? For (i) if it possesses none of these 
determinations actually, but all of them only potentially, the 
result is first that a being, which is not a determinate being, is 
capable of separate existence; and in addition that coming-to- 
be proceeds out of nothing pre-existing - a thesis which, more 
than any other, preoccupied and alarmed the earliest 
philosophers. On the other hand (ii) if, although it is not a 'this 
somewhat' or a substance, it is to possess some of the 
remaining determinations quoted above, then (as we said)' 
properties will be separable from substances. 

We must therefore concentrate all our powers on the discussion 
of these difficulties and on the solution of a further question - 
viz. What is the cause of the perpetuity of coming-to-be? Why is 
there always unqualified, as well as partial, coming-to-be? 
Cause' in this connexion has two senses. It means (i) the source 
from which, as we say, the process 'originates', and (ii) the 
matter. It is the material cause that we have here to state. For, 
as to the other cause, we have already explained (in our treatise 
on Motion that it involves (a) something immovable through all 
time and (b) something always being moved. And the accurate 
treatment of the first of these - of the immovable 'originative 
source' - belongs to the province of the other, or 'prior', 
philosophy: while as regards 'that which sets everything else in 
motion by being itself continuously moved', we shall have to 
explain later' which amongst the so-called 'specific' causes 
exhibits this character. But at present we are to state the 
material cause - the cause classed under the head of matter - to 
which it is due that passing-away and coming-to-be never fail 
to occur in Nature. For perhaps, if we succeed in clearing up this 
question, it will simultaneously become clear what account we 
ought to give of that which perplexed us just now, i.e. of 
unqualified passing-away and coming-to-be. 



965 



Our new question too - viz. 'what is the cause of the unbroken 
continuity of coming-to-be?' - is sufficiently perplexing, if in 
fact what passes-away vanishes into 'what is not' and 'what is 
not' is nothing (since 'what is not' is neither a thing, nor 
possessed of a quality or quantity, nor in any place). If, then, 
some one of the things 'which are' constantly disappearing, why 
has not the whole of 'what is' been used up long ago and 
vanished away assuming of course that the material of all the 
several comings-to-be was finite? For, presumably, the unfailing 
continuity of coming-to-be cannot be attributed to the infinity 
of the material. That is impossible, for nothing is actually 
infinite. A thing is infinite only potentially, i.e. the dividing of it 
can continue indefinitely: so that we should have to suppose 
there is only one kind of coming-to-be in the world - viz. one 
which never fails, because it is such that what comes-to-be is 
on each successive occasion smaller than before. But in fact this 
is not what we see occurring. 

Why, then, is this form of change necessarily ceaseless? Is it 
because the passing-away of this is a coming-to-be of 
something else, and the coming-to-be of this a passing-away of 
something else? 

The cause implied in this solution must no doubt be considered 
adequate to account for coming-to-be and passing-away in their 
general character as they occur in all existing things alike. Yet, if 
the same process is a coming-to-be of this but a passing-away 
of that, and a passing-away of this but a coming-to-be of that, 
why are some things said to come-to-be and pass-away without 
qualification, but others only with a qualification? 

The distinction must be investigated once more, for it demands 
some explanation. (It is applied in a twofold manner.) For (i) we 
say 'it is now passing-away' without qualification, and not 
merely 'this is passing-away': and we call this change 'coming- 



966 



to-be', and that 'passing-away', without qualification. And (ii) 
so-and-so 'comes-to-be-something', but does not 'come-to-be' 
without qualification; for we say that the student 'comes-to-be- 
learned', not 'comes-to-be' without qualification. 

(i) Now we often divide terms into those which signify a 'this 
somewhat' and those which do not. And (the first form of) the 
distinction, which we are investigating, results from a similar 
division of terms: for it makes a difference into what the 
changing thing changes. Perhaps, e.g. the passage into Fire is 
'coming-to-be' unqualified, but 'passing-away-of-something' 
(e.g. Earth): whilst the coming-to-be of Earth is qualified (not 
unqualified) 'coming-to-be', though unqualified 'passing-away' 
(e.g. of Fire). This would be the case on the theory set forth in 
Parmenides: for he says that the things into which change takes 
place are two, and he asserts that these two, viz. what is and 
what is not, are Fire and Earth. Whether we postulate these, or 
other things of a similar kind, makes no difference. For we are 
trying to discover not what undergoes these changes, but what 
is their characteristic manner. The passage, then, into what 'is' 
not except with a qualification is unqualified passing-away, 
while the passage into what 'is' without qualification is 
unqualified coming-to-be. Hence whatever the contrasted 
'poles' of the changes may be whether Fire and Earth, or some 
other couple - the one of them will be 'a being' and the other 'a 
not-being'. 

We have thus stated one characteristic manner in which 
unqualified will be distinguished from qualified coming-to-be 
and passing-away: but they are also distinguished according to 
the special nature of the material of the changing thing. For a 
material, whose constitutive differences signify more a 'this 
somewhat', is itself more 'substantial' or 'real': while a material, 
whose constitutive differences signify privation, is 'not real'. 
(Suppose, e.g. that 'the hot' is a positive predication, i.e. a 'form', 



967 



whereas 'cold' is a privation, and that Earth and Fire differ from 
one another by these constitutive differences.) 

The opinion, however, which most people are inclined to prefer, 
is that the distinction depends upon the difference between 'the 
perceptible' and 'the imperceptible'. Thus, when there is a 
change into perceptible material, people say there is 'coming-to- 
be'; but when there is a change into invisible material, they call 
it 'passing-away'. For they distinguish 'what is' and 'what is not' 
by their perceiving and not-perceiving, just as what is knowable 
'is' and what is unknowable 'is not' - perception on their view 
having the force of knowledge. Hence, just as they deem 
themselves to live and to 'be' in virtue of their perceiving or 
their capacity to perceive, so too they deem the things to 'be' 
qua perceived or perceptible - and in this they are in a sense on 
the track of the truth, though what they actually say is not true. 

Thus unqualified coming-to-be and passing-away turn out to be 
different according to common opinion from what they are in 
truth. For Wind and Air are in truth more real more a 'this 
somewhat' or a 'form' - than Earth. But they are less real to 
perception which explains why things are commonly said to 
'pass-away' without qualification when they change into Wind 
and Air, and to 'come-to-be' when they change into what is 
tangible, i.e. into Earth. 

We have now explained why there is 'unqualified coming-to-be' 
(though it is a passing-away-of-something) and 'unqualified 
passing-away' (though it is a coming-to-be-of-something). For 
this distinction of appellation depends upon a difference in the 
material out of which, and into which, the changes are effected. 
It depends either upon whether the material is or is not 
'substantial', or upon whether it is more or less 'substantial', or 
upon whether it is more or less perceptible. 



968 



(ii) But why are some things said to 'come-to-be' without 
qualification, and others only to 'come-to-be-so-and-so', in 
cases different from the one we have been considering where 
two things come-to-be reciprocally out of one another? For at 
present we have explained no more than this: - why, when two 
things change reciprocally into one another, we do not attribute 
coming-to-be and passing-away uniformly to them both, 
although every coming-to-be is a passing-away of something 
else and every passing-away some other thing's coming-to-be. 
But the question subsequently formulated involves a different 
problem - viz. why, although the learning thing is said to 'come- 
to-be-learned' but not to 'come-to-be' without qualification, yet 
the growing thing is said to 'come-to-be'. 

The distinction here turns upon the difference of the Categories. 
For some things signify a this somewhat, others a such, and 
others a so-much. Those things, then, which do not signify 
substance, are not said to 'come-to-be' without qualification, 
but only to 'come-to-be-so-and-so'. Nevertheless, in all 
changing things alike, we speak of 'coming-to-be' when the 
thing comes-to-be something in one of the two Columns - e.g. 
in Substance, if it comes-to-be Fire but not if it comes-to-be 
Earth; and in Quality, if it comes-to-be learned but not when it 
comes-to-be ignorant. 

We have explained why some things come-to-be without 
qualification, but not others both in general, and also when the 
changing things are substances and nothing else; and we have 
stated that the substratum is the material cause of the 
continuous occurrence of coming-to-be, because it is such as to 
change from contrary to contrary and because, in substances, 
the coming-to-be of one thing is always a passing-away of 
another, and the passing-away of one thing is always another's 
coming-to-be. But there is no need even to discuss the other 
question we raised - viz. why coming-to-be continues though 



969 



things are constantly being destroyed. For just as people speak 
of 'a passing-away' without qualification when a thing has 
passed into what is imperceptible and what in that sense 'is 
not', so also they speak of 'a coming-to-be out of a not-being' 
when a thing emerges from an imperceptible. Whether, 
therefore, the substratum is or is not something, what comes- 
to-be emerges out of a 'not-being': so that a thing comes-to-be 
out of a not-being' just as much as it 'passes-away into what is 
not'. Hence it is reasonable enough that coming-to-be should 
never fail. For coming-to-be is a passing-away of 'what is not' 
and passing-away is a coming-to-be of 'what is not'. 

But what about that which 'is' not except with a qualification? 
Is it one of the two contrary poles of the change - e.g. Earth (i.e. 
the heavy) a 'not-being', but Fire (i.e. the light) a 'being? Or, on 
the contrary, does what is 'include Earth as well as Fire, whereas 
what is not' is matter - the matter of Earth and Fire alike? And 
again, is the matter of each different? Or is it the same, since 
otherwise they would not come-to-be reciprocally out of one 
another, i.e. contraries out of contraries? For these things - Fire, 
Earth, Water, Air - are characterized by 'the contraries'. 

Perhaps the solution is that their matter is in one sense the 
same, but in another sense different. For that which underlies 
them, whatever its nature may be qua underlying them, is the 
same: but its actual being is not the same. So much, then, on 
these topics. 



Next we must state what the difference is between coming-to- 
be and 'alteration' - for we maintain that these changes are 
distinct from one another. 



970 



Since, then, we must distinguish (a) the substratum, and (b) the 
property whose nature it is to be predicated of the substratum; 
and since change of each of these occurs; there is 'alteration' 
when the substratum is perceptible and persists, but changes in 
its own properties, the properties in question being opposed to 
one another either as contraries or as intermediates. The body, 
e.g. although persisting as the same body, is now healthy and 
now ill; and the bronze is now spherical and at another time 
angular, and yet remains the same bronze. But when nothing 
perceptible persists in its identity as a substratum, and the 
thing changes as a whole (when e.g. the seed as a whole is 
converted into blood, or water into air, or air as a whole into 
water), such an occurrence is no longer 'alteration'. It is a 
coming-to-be of one substance and a passing-away of the other 
- especially if the change proceeds from an imperceptible 
something to something perceptible (either to touch or to all the 
senses), as when water comes-to-be out of, or passes-away into, 
air: for air is pretty well imperceptible. If, however, in such 
cases, any property (being one of a pair of contraries) persists, in 
the thing that has come-to-be, the same as it was in the thing 
which has passed-away - if, e.g. when water comes-to-be out of 
air, both are transparent or cold - the second thing, into which 
the first changes, must not be a property of this persistent 
identical something. Otherwise the change will be 'alteration.' 
Suppose, e.g. that the musical man passed-away and an 
unmusical man came-to-be, and that the man persists as 
something identical. Now, if 'musicalness and unmusicalness' 
had not been a property essentially inhering in man, these 
changes would have been a coming-to-be of unmusicalness and 
a passing-away of musicalness: but in fact 'musicalness and 
unmusicalness' are a property of the persistent identity, viz. 
man. (Hence, as regards man, these changes are 'modifications'; 
though, as regards musical man and unmusical man, they are a 
passing-away and a coming-to-be.) Consequently such changes 



971 



are 'alteration.' When the change from contrary to contrary is in 
quantity, it is 'growth and diminution'; when it is in place, it is 
'motion'; when it is in property, i.e. in quality, it is 'alteration': 
but, when nothing persists, of which the resultant is a property 
(or an 'accident' in any sense of the term), it is 'coming-to-be', 
and the converse change is 'passing-away'. 

'Matter', in the most proper sense of the term, is to be identified 
with the substratum which is receptive of coming-to-be and 
passing-away: but the substratum of the remaining kinds of 
change is also, in a certain sense, 'matter', because all these 
substrata are receptive of 'contrarieties' of some kind. So much, 
then, as an answer to the questions (i) whether coming-to-be 'is' 
or 'is not' - i.e. what are the precise conditions of its occurrence 
and (ii) what 'alteration' is: but we have still to treat of growth. 



We must explain (i) wherein growth differs from coming-to-be 
and from 'alteration', and ii) what is the process of growing and 
the sprocess of diminishing in each and all of the things that 
grow and diminish. 

Hence our first question is this: Do these changes differ from 
one another solely because of a difference in their respective 
'spheres'? In other words, do they differ because, while a change 
from this to that (viz. from potential to actual substance) is 
coming-to-be, a change in the sphere of magnitude is growth 
and one in the sphere of quality is 'alteration' - both growth and 
'alteration' being changes from what is-potentially to what is- 
actually magnitude and quality respectively? Or is there also a 
difference in the manner of the change, since it is evident that, 
whereas neither what is 'altering' nor what is coming-to-be 



972 



necessarily changes its place, what is growing or diminishing 
changes its spatial position of necessity, though in a different 
manner from that in which the moving thing does so? For that 
which is being moved changes its place as a whole: but the 
growing thing changes its place like a metal that is being 
beaten, retaining its position as a whole while its parts change 
their places. They change their places, but not in the same way 
as the parts of a revolving globe. For the parts of the globe 
change their places while the whole continues to occupy an 
equal place: but the parts of the rowing thing expand over an 
ever-increasing place and the parts of the diminishing thing 
contract within an ever-diminishing area. 

It is clear, then, that these changes - the changes of that which 
is coming-to-be, of that which is 'altering', and of that which is 
growing - differ in manner as well as in sphere. But how are we 
to conceive the 'sphere' of the change which is growth and 
diminution? The sphere' of growing and diminishing is believed 
to be magnitude. Are we to suppose that body and magnitude 
come-to-be out of something which, though potentially 
magnitude and body, is actually incorporeal and devoid of 
magnitude? And since this description may be understood in 
two different ways, in which of these two ways are we to apply 
it to the process of growth? Is the matter, out of which growth 
takes place, (i) 'separate' and existing alone by itself, or (ii) 
'separate' but contained in another body? 

Perhaps it is impossible for growth to take place in either of 
these ways. For since the matter is 'separate', either (a) it will 
occupy no place (as if it were a point), or (b) it will be a 'void', i.e. 
a non-perceptible body. But the first of these alternatives is 
impossible. For since what comes-to-be out of this incorporeal 
and sizeless something will always be 'somewhere', it too must 
be 'somewhere' - either intrinsically or indirectly. And the 
second alternative necessarily implies that the matter is 



973 



contained in some other body. But if it is to be 'in' another body 
and yet remains 'separate' in such a way that it is in no sense a 
part of that body (neither a part of its substantial being nor an 
'accident' of it), many impossibilities will result. It is as if we 
were to suppose that when, e.g. air comes-to-be out of water the 
process were due not to a change of the but to the matter of the 
air being 'contained in' the water as in a vessel. This is 
impossible. For (i) there is nothing to prevent an indeterminate 
number of matters being thus 'contained in' the water, so that 
they might come-to-be actually an indeterminate quantity of 
air; and (ii) we do not in fact see air coming-to-be out of water 
in this fashion, viz. withdrawing out of it and leaving it 
unchanged. 

It is therefore better to suppose that in all instances of coming- 
to-be the matter is inseparable, being numerically identical and 
one with the 'containing' body, though isolable from it by 
definition. But the same reasons also forbid us to regard the 
matter, out of which the body comes-to-be, as points or lines. 
The matter is that of which points and lines are limits, and it is 
something that can never exist without quality and without 
form. 

Now it is no doubt true, as we have also established elsewhere,' 
that one thing 'comes-to-be' (in the unqualified sense) out of 
another thing: and further it is true that the efficient cause of 
its coming-to-be is either (i) an actual thing (which is the same 
as the effect either generically - or the efficient cause of the 
coming-to-be of a hard thing is not a hard thing or specifically, 
as e.g. fire is the efficient cause of the coming-to-be of fire or 
one man of the birth of another), or (ii) an actuality. 
Nevertheless, since there is also a matter out of which corporeal 
substance itself comes-to-be (corporeal substance, however, 
already characterized as such-and-such a determinate body, for 
there is no such thing as body in general), this same matter is 



974 



also the matter of magnitude and quality - being separable from 
these matters by definition, but not separable in place unless 
Qualities are, in their turn, separable. 

It is evident, from the preceding development and discussion of 
difficulties, that growth is not a change out of something which, 
though potentially a magnitude, actually possesses no 
magnitude. For, if it were, the 'void' would exist in separation; 
but we have explained in a former work' that this is impossible. 
Moreover, a change of that kind is not peculiarly distinctive of 
growth, but characterizes coming-to-be as such or in general. 
For growth is an increase, and diminution is a lessening, of the 
magnitude which is there already - that, indeed, is why the 
growing thing must possess some magnitude. Hence growth 
must not be regarded as a process from a matter without 
magnitude to an actuality of magnitude: for this would be a 
body's coming-to-be rather than its growth. 

We must therefore come to closer quarters with the subject of 
our inquiry. We must grapple' with it (as it were) from its 
beginning, and determine the precise character of the growing 
and diminishing whose causes we are investigating. 

It is evident (i) that any and every part of the growing thing has 
increased, and that similarly in diminution every part has 
become smaller: also (ii) that a thing grows by the accession, 
and diminishes by the departure, of something. Hence it must 
grow by the accession either (a) of something incorporeal or (b) 
of a body. Now, if (a) it grows by the accession of something 
incorporeal, there will exist separate a void: but (as we have 
stated before)' is impossible for a matter of magnitude to exist 
'separate'. If, on the other hand (b) it grows by the accession of a 
body, there will be two bodies - that which grows and that 
which increases it - in the same place: and this too is 
impossible. 



975 



But neither is it open to us to say that growth or diminution 
occurs in the way in which e.g. air is generated from water. For, 
although the volume has then become greater, the change will 
not be growth, but a coming-to-be of the one - viz. of that into 
which the change is taking place - and a passing-away of the 
contrasted body. It is not a growth of either. Nothing grows in 
the process; unless indeed there be something common to both 
things (to that which is coming-to-be and to that which passed- 
away), e.g. 'body', and this grows. The water has not grown, nor 
has the air: but the former has passed-away and the latter has 
come-to-be, and - if anything has grown - there has been a 
growth of 'body.' Yet this too is impossible. For our account of 
growth must preserve the characteristics of that which is 
growing and diminishing. And these characteristics are three: (i) 
any and every part of the growing magnitude is made bigger 
(e.g. if flesh grows, every particle of the flesh gets bigger), (ii) by 
the accession of something, and (iii) in such a way that the 
growing thing is preserved and persists. For whereas a thing 
does not persist in the processes of unqualified coming-to-be or 
passing-away, that which grows or 'alters' persists in its identity 
through the 'altering' and through the growing or diminishing, 
though the quality (in 'alteration') and the size (in growth) do 
not remain the same. Now if the generation of air from water is 
to be regarded as growth, a thing might grow without the 
accession (and without the persistence) of anything, and 
diminish without the departure of anything - and that which 
grows need not persist. But this characteristic must be 
preserved: for the growth we are discussing has been assumed 
to be thus characterized. 

One might raise a further difficulty. What is 'that which grows? 
Is it that to which something is added? If, e.g. a man grows in 
his shin, is it the shin which is greater - but not that 'whereby' 
he grows, viz. not the food? Then why have not both 'grown'? 
For when A is added to B, both A and B are greater, as when you 



976 



mix wine with water; for each ingredient is alike increased in 
volume. Perhaps the explanation is that the substance of the 
one remains unchanged, but the substance of the other (viz. of 
the food) does not. For indeed, even in the mixture of wine and 
water, it is the prevailing ingredient which is said to have 
increased in volume. We say, e.g. that the wine has increased, 
because the whole mixture acts as wine but not as water. A 
similar principle applies also to 'alteration'. Flesh is said to have 
been 'altered' if, while its character and substance remain, some 
one of its essential properties, which was not there before, now 
qualifies it: on the other hand, that 'whereby' it has been 
'altered' may have undergone no change, though sometimes it 
too has been affected. The altering agent, however, and the 
originative source of the process are in the growing thing and in 
that which is being 'altered': for the efficient cause is in these. 
No doubt the food, which has come in, may sometimes expand 
as well as the body that has consumed it (that is so, e.g. if, after 
having come in, a food is converted into wind), but when it has 
undergone this change it has passedaway: and the efficient 
cause is not in the food. 

We have now developed the difficulties sufficiently and must 
therefore try to find a solution of the problem. Our solution 
must preserve intact the three characteristics of growth - that 
the growing thing persists, that it grows by the accession (and 
diminishes by the departure) of something, and further that 
every perceptible particle of it has become either larger or 
smaller. We must recognize also (a) that the growing body is not 
'void' and that yet there are not two magnitudes in the same 
place, and (b) that it does not grow by the accession of 
something incorporeal. 

Two preliminary distinctions will prepare us to grasp the cause 
of growth. We must note (i) that the organic parts grow by the 
growth of the tissues (for every organ is composed of these as 



977 



its constituents); and (ii) that flesh, bone, and every such part - 
like every other thing which has its form immersed in matter - 
has a twofold nature: for the form as well as the matter is called 
'flesh' or 'bone'. 

Now, that any and every part of the tissue qua form should grow 
- and grow by the accession of something - is possible, but not 
that any and every part of the tissue qua matter should do so. 
For we must think of the tissue after the image of flowing water 
that is measured by one and the same measure: particle after 
particle comes-to-be, and each successive particle is different. 
And it is in this sense that the matter of the flesh grows, some 
flowing out and some flowing in fresh; not in the sense that 
fresh matter accedes to every particle of it. There is, however, an 
accession to every part of its figure or 'form'. 

That growth has taken place proportionally, is more manifest in 
the organic parts - e.g. in the hand. For there the fact that the 
matter is distinct from the form is more manifest than in flesh, 
i.e. than in the tissues. That is why there is a greater tendency 
to suppose that a corpse still possesses flesh and bone than 
that it still has a hand or an arm. 

Hence in one sense it is true that any and every part of the flesh 
has grown; but in another sense it is false. For there has been an 
accession to every part of the flesh in respect to its form, but 
not in respect to its matter. The whole, however, has become 
larger. And this increase is due (a) on the one hand to the 
accession of something, which is called 'food' and is said to be 
'contrary' to flesh, but (b) on the other hand to the 
transformation of this food into the same form as that of flesh 
as if, e.g. 'moist' were to accede to 'dry' and, having acceded, 
were to be transformed and to become 'dry'. For in one sense 
'Like grows by Like', but in another sense 'Unlike grows by 
Unlike'. 



978 



One might discuss what must be the character of that 'whereby' 
a thing grows. Clearly it must be potentially that which is 
growing - potentially flesh, e.g. if it is flesh that is growing. 
Actually, therefore, it must be 'other' than the growing thing. 
This 'actual other', then, has passed-away and come-to-be flesh. 
But it has not been transformed into flesh alone by itself (for 
that would have been a coming-to-be, not a growth): on the 
contrary, it is the growing thing which has come-to-be flesh 
(and grown) by the food. In what way, then, has the food been 
modified by the growing thing? Perhaps we should say that it 
has been 'mixed' with it, as if one were to pour water into wine 
and the wine were able to convert the new ingredient into wine. 
And as fire lays hold of the inflammable, so the active principle 
of growth, dwelling in the growing thing that which is actually 
flesh), lays hold of an acceding food which is potentially flesh 
and converts it into actual flesh. The acceding food, therefore, 
must be together with the growing thing: for if it were apart 
from it, the change would be a coming-to-be. For it is possible to 
produce fire by piling logs on to the already burning fire. That is 
'growth'. But when the logs themselves are set on fire, that is 
'coming-to-be'. 

'Quantum-in-general' does not come-to-be any more than 
'animal' which is neither man nor any other of the specific 
forms of animal: what 'animal-in-general' is in coming-to-be, 
that 'quantum-in-general' is in growth. But what does come-to- 
be in growth is flesh or bone - or a hand or arm (i.e. the tissues 
of these organic parts). Such things come-to-be, then, by the 
accession not of quantified-flesh but of a quantified-something. 
In so far as this acceding food is potentially the double result 
e.g. is potentially so-much-flesh it produces growth: for it is 
bound to become actually both so-much and flesh. But in so far 
as it is potentially flesh only, it nourishes: for it is thus that 
'nutrition' and 'growth' differ by their definition. That is why a 
body's 'nutrition' continues so long as it is kept alive (even when 



979 



it is diminishing), though not its 'growth'; and why nutrition, 
though 'the same' as growth, is yet different from it in its actual 
being. For in so far as that which accedes is potentially 'so 
much-flesh' it tends to increase flesh: whereas, in so far as it is 
potentially 'flesh' only, it is nourishment. 

The form of which we have spoken is a kind of power immersed 
in matter - a duct, as it were. If, then, a matter accedes - a 
matter, which is potentially a duct and also potentially 
possesses determinate quantity the ducts to which it accedes 
will become bigger. But if it is no longer able to act - if it has 
been weakened by the continued influx of matter, just as water, 
continually mixed in greater and greater quantity with wine, in 
the end makes the wine watery and converts it into water - 
then it will cause a diminution of the quantum; though still the 
form persists. 



(In discussing the causes of coming-to-be) we must first 
investigate the matter, i.e. the so-called 'elements'. We must ask 
whether they really are elements or not, i.e. whether each of 
them is eternal or whether there is a sense in which they come- 
to-be: and, if they do come-to-be, whether all of them come-to- 
be in the same manner reciprocally out of one another, or 
whether one amongst them is something primary. Hence we 
must begin by explaining certain preliminary matters, about 
which the statements now current are vague. 

For all (the pluralist philosophers) - those who generate the 
'elements' as well as those who generate the bodies that are 
compounded of the elements - make use of 'dissociation' and 
'association', and of 'action' and 'passion'. Now 'association' is 



980 



'combination'; but the precise meaning of the process we call 
'combining' has not been explained. Again, (all the monists 
make use of 'alteration': but) without an agent and a patient 
there cannot be 'altering' any more than there can be 
'dissociating' and 'associating'. For not only those who postulate 
a plurality of elements employ their reciprocal action and 
passion to generate the compounds: those who derive things 
from a single element are equally compelled to introduce 
'acting'. And in this respect Diogenes is right when he argues 
that 'unless all things were derived from one, reciprocal action 
and passion could not have occurred'. The hot thing, e.g. would 
not be cooled and the cold thing in turn be warmed: for heat 
and cold do not change reciprocally into one another, but what 
changes (it is clear) is the substratum. Hence, whenever there is 
action and passion between two things, that which underlies 
them must be a single something. No doubt, it is not true to say 
that all things are of this character: but it is true of all things 
between which there is reciprocal action and passion. 

But if we must investigate 'action-passion' and 'combination', 
we must also investigate 'contact'. For action and passion (in 
the proper sense of the terms) can only occur between things 
which are such as to touch one another; nor can things enter 
into combination at all unless they have come into a certain 
kind of contact. Hence we must give a definite account of these 
three things - of 'contact', 'combination', and 'acting'. 

Let us start as follows. All things which admit of 'combination' 
must be capable of reciprocal contact: and the same is true of 
any two things, of which one 'acts' and the other 'suffers action' 
in the proper sense of the terms. For this reason we must treat 
of 'contact' first, every term which possesses a variety of 
meaning includes those various meanings either owing to a 
mere coincidence of language, or owing to a real order of 
derivation in the different things to which it is applied: but, 



981 



though this may be taken to hold of 'contact' as of all such 
terms, it is nevertheless true that contact' in the proper sense 
applies only to things which have 'position'. And 'position' 
belongs only to those things which also have a Place': for in so 
far as we attribute 'contact' to the mathematical things, we 
must also attribute 'place' to them, whether they exist in 
separation or in some other fashion. Assuming, therefore, that 
'to touch' is - as we have defined it in a previous work - 'to have 
the extremes together', only those things will touch one another 
which, being separate magnitudes and possessing position, 
have their extremes 'together'. And since position belongs only 
to those things which also have a 'place', while the primary 
differentiation of 'place' is the above' and 'the below' (and the 
similar pairs of opposites), all things which touch one another 
will have 'weight' or 'lightness' either both these qualities or 
one or the other of them. But bodies which are heavy or light 
are such as to 'act' and 'suffer action'. Hence it is clear that 
those things are by nature such as to touch one another, which 
(being separate magnitudes) have their extremes 'together' and 
are able to move, and be moved by, one another. 

The manner in which the 'mover' moves the moved' not always 
the same: on the contrary, whereas one kind of 'mover' can only 
impart motion by being itself moved, another kind can do so 
though remaining itself unmoved. Clearly therefore we must 
recognize a corresponding variety in speaking of the 'acting' 
thing too: for the 'mover' is said to 'act' (in a sense) and the 
'acting' thing to 'impart motion'. Nevertheless there is a 
difference and we must draw a distinction. For not every 'mover' 
can 'act', if (a) the term 'agent' is to be used in contrast to 
'patient' and (b) 'patient' is to be applied only to those things 
whose motion is a 'qualitative affection' - i.e. a quality, like 
white' or 'hot', in respect to which they are moved' only in the 
sense that they are 'altered': on the contrary, to 'impart motion' 
is a wider term than to 'act'. Still, so much, at any rate, is clear: 



982 



the things which are 'such as to impart motion', if that 
description be interpreted in one sense, will touch the things 
which are 'such as to be moved by them' - while they will not 
touch them, if the description be interpreted in a different 
sense. But the disjunctive definition of 'touching' must include 
and distinguish (a) 'contact in general' as the relation between 
two things which, having position, are such that one is able to 
impart motion and the other to be moved, and (b) 'reciprocal 
contact' as the relation between two things, one able to impart 
motion and the other able to be moved in such a way that 
'action and passion' are predicable of them. 

As a rule, no doubt, if A touches B, B touches A. For indeed 
practically all the 'movers' within our ordinary experience 
impart motion by being moved: in their case, what touches 
inevitably must, and also evidently does, touch something 
which reciprocally touches it. Yet, if A moves B, it is possible - as 
we sometimes express it - for A 'merely to touch' B, and that 
which touches need not touch a something which touches it. 
Nevertheless it is commonly supposed that 'touching' must be 
reciprocal. The reason of this belief is that 'movers' which 
belong to the same kind as the 'moved' impart motion by being 
moved. Hence if anything imparts motion without itself being 
moved, it may touch the 'moved' and yet itself be touched by 
nothing - for we say sometimes that the man who grieves us 
'touches' us, but not that we 'touch' him. 

The account just given may serve to distinguish and define the 
'contact' which occurs in the things of Nature. 



983 



Next in order we must discuss 'action' and 'passion'. The 
traditional theories on the subject are conflicting. For (i) most 
thinkers are unanimous in maintaining (a) that 'like' is always 
unaffected by 'like', because (as they argue) neither of two 'likes' 
is more apt than the other either to act or to suffer action, since 
all the properties which belong to the one belong identically 
and in the same degree to the other; and (b) that 'unlikes', i.e. 
'differents', are by nature such as to act and suffer action 
reciprocally. For even when the smaller fire is destroyed by the 
greater, it suffers this effect (they say) owing to its 'contrariety' 
since the great is contrary to the small. But (ii) Democritus 
dissented from all the other thinkers and maintained a theory 
peculiar to himself. He asserts that agent and patient are 
identical, i.e. 'like'. It is not possible (he says) that 'others', i.e. 
'differents', should suffer action from one another: on the 
contrary, even if two things, being 'others', do act in some way 
on one another, this happens to them not qua 'others' but qua 
possessing an identical property. 

Such, then, are the traditional theories, and it looks as if the 
statements of their advocates were in manifest conflict. But the 
reason of this conflict is that each group is in fact stating a part, 
whereas they ought to have taken a comprehensive view of the 
subject as a whole. For (i) if A and B are 'like' - absolutely and in 
all respects without difference from one another - it is 
reasonable to infer that neither is in any way affected by the 
other. Why, indeed, should either of them tend to act any more 
than the other? Moreover, if 'like' can be affected by 'like', a 
thing can also be affected by itself: and yet if that were so - if 
'like' tended in fact to act qua 'like' - there would be nothing 
indestructible or immovable, for everything would move itself. 
And (ii) the same consequence follows if A and B are absolutely 
'other', i.e. in no respect identical. Whiteness could not be 



984 



affected in any way by line nor line by whiseness - except 
perhaps 'coincidentally', viz. if the line happened to be white or 
black: for unless two things either are, or are composed of, 
'contraries', neither drives the other out of its natural condition. 
But (iii) since only those things which either involve a 
'contrariety' or are 'contraries' - and not any things selected at 
random - are such as to suffer action and to act, agent and 
patient must be 'like' (i.e. identical) in kind and yet 'unlike' (i.e. 
contrary) in species. (For it is a law of nature that body is 
affected by body, flavour by flavour, colour by colour, and so in 
general what belongs to any kind by a member of the same kind 
- the reason being that 'contraries' are in every case within a 
single identical kind, and it is 'contraries' which reciprocally act 
and suffer action.) Hence agent and patient must be in one 
sense identical, but in another sense other than (i.e. 'unlike') 
one another. And since (a) patient and agent are generically 
identical (i.e. 'like') but specifically 'unlike', while (b) it is 
'contraries' that exhibit this character: it is clear that 'contraries' 
and their 'intermediates' are such as to suffer action and to act 
reciprocally - for indeed it is these that constitute the entire 
sphere of passing-away and coming-to-be. 

We can now understand why fire heats and the cold thing cools, 
and in general why the active thing assimilates to itself the 
patient. For agent and patient are contrary to one another, and 
coming-to-be is a process into the contrary: hence the patient 
must change into the agent, since it is only thus that coming-to- 
be will be a process into the contrary. And, again, it is intelligible 
that the advocates of both views, although their theories are not 
the same, are yet in contact with the nature of the facts. For 
sometimes we speak of the substratum as suffering action (e.g. 
of 'the man' as being healed, being warmed and chilled, and 
similarly in all the other cases), but at other times we say 'what 
is cold is 'being warmed', 'what is sick is being healed': and in 
both these ways of speaking we express the truth, since in one 



985 



sense it is the 'matter', while in another sense it is the 
'contrary', which suffers action. (We make the same distinction 
in speaking of the agent: for sometimes we say that 'the man', 
but at other times that 'what is hot', produces heat.) Now the 
one group of thinkers supposed that agent and patient must 
possess something identical, because they fastened their 
attention on the substratum: while the other group maintained 
the opposite because their attention was concentrated on the 
'contraries'. We must conceive the same account to hold of 
action and passion as that which is true of 'being moved' and 
'imparting motion'. For the 'mover', like the 'agent', has two 
meanings. Both (a) that which contains the originative source of 
the motion is thought to 'impart motion' (for the originative 
source is first amongst the causes), and also (b) that which is 
last, i.e. immediately next to the moved thing and to the 
coming-to-be. A similar distinction holds also of the agent: for 
we speak not only (a) of the doctor, but also (b) of the wine, as 
healing. Now, in motion, there is nothing to prevent the firs; 
mover being unmoved (indeed, as regards some 'first' movers' 
this is actually necessary) although the last mover always 
imparts motion by being itself moved: and, in action, there is 
nothing to prevent the first agent being unaffected, while the 
last agent only acts by suffering action itself. For agent and 
patient have not the same matter, agent acts without being 
affected: thus the art of healing produces health without itself 
being acted upon in any way by that which is being healed. But 
(b) the food, in acting, is itself in some way acted upon: for, in 
acting, it is simultaneously heated or cooled or otherwise 
affected. Now the art of healing corresponds to an 'originative 
source', while the food corresponds to 'the last' (i.e. 
'continuous') mover. 

Those active powers, then, whose forms are not embodied in 
matter, are unaffected: but those whose forms are in matter are 
such as to be affected in acting. For we maintain that one and 



986 



the same 'matter' is equally, so to say, the basis of either of the 
two opposed things - being as it were a 'kind'; and that that 
which can he hot must be made hot, provided the heating agent 
is there, i.e. comes near. Hence (as we have said) some of the 
active powers are unaffected while others are such as to be 
affected; and what holds of motion is true also of the active 
powers. For as in motion 'the first mover' is unmoved, so among 
the active powers 'the first agent' is unaffected. 

The active power is a 'cause' in the sense of that from which the 
process originates: but the end, for the sake of which it takes 
place, is not 'active'. (That is why health is not 'active', except 
metaphorically.) For when the agent is there, the patient 
becomes something: but when 'states' are there, the patient no 
longer becomes but already is - and 'forms' (i.e. 'lends') are a 
kind of 'state'. As to the 'matter', it (qua matter) is passive. Now 
fire contains 'the hot' embodied in matter: but a 'hot' separate 
from matter (if such a thing existed) could not suffer any action. 
Perhaps, indeed, it is impossible that 'the hot' should exist in 
separation from matter: but if there are any entities thus 
separable, what we are saying would be true of them. 

We have thus explained what action and passion are, what 
things exhibit them, why they do so, and in what manner. We 
must go on to discuss how it is possible for action and passion 
to take place. 



8 

Some philosophers think that the 'last' agent - the 'agent' in the 
strictest sense - enters in through certain pores, and so the 
patient suffers action. It is in this way, they assert, that we see 
and hear and exercise all our other senses. Moreover, according 



987 



to them, things are seen through air and water and other 
transparent bodies, because such bodies possess pores, invisible 
indeed owing to their minuteness, but close-set and arranged in 
rows: and the more transparent the body, the more frequent 
and serial they suppose its pores to be. Such was the theory 
which some philosophers (induding Empedocles) advanced in 
regard to the structure of certain bodies. They do not restrict it 
to the bodies which act and suffer action: but 'combination' too, 
they say, takes place 'only between bodies whose pores are in 
reciprocal symmetry'. The most systematic and consistent 
theory, however, and one that applied to all bodies, was 
advanced by Leucippus and Democritus: and, in maintaining it, 
they took as their starting-point what naturally comes first. 

For some of the older philosophers thought that 'what is' must 
of necessity be 'one' and immovable. The void, they argue, 'is 
not': but unless there is a void with a separate being of its own, 
'what is' cannot be moved - nor again can it be 'many', since 
there is nothing to keep things apart. And in this respect, they 
insist, the view that the universe is not 'continuous' but 
'discretes-in-contact' is no better than the view that there are 
'many' (and not 'one') and a void. For (suppose that the universe 
is discretes-in-contact. Then), if it is divisible through and 
through, there is no 'one', and therefore no 'many' either, but 
the Whole is void; while to maintain that it is divisible at some 
points, but not at others, looks like an arbitrary fiction. For up to 
what limit is it divisible? And for what reason is part of the 
Whole indivisible, i.e. a plenum, and part divided? Further, they 
maintain, it is equally necessary to deny the existence of 
motion. 

Reasoning in this way, therefore, they were led to transcend 
sense-perception, and to disregard it on the ground that 'one 
ought to follow the argument': and so they assert that the 
universe is 'one' and immovable. Some of them add that it is 



988 



'infinite', since the limit (if it had one) would be a limit against 
the void. 

There were, then, certain thinkers who, for the reasons we have 
stated, enunciated views of this kind as their theory of 'The 
Truth'.... Moreover, although these opinions appear to follow 
logically in a dialectical discussion, yet to believe them seems 
next door to madness when one considers the facts. For indeed 
no lunatic seems to be so far out of his senses as to suppose 
that fire and ice are 'one': it is only between what is right and 
what seems right from habit, that some people are mad enough 
to see no difference. 

Leucippus, however, thought he had a theory which harmonized 
with sense-perception and would not abolish either coming-to- 
be and passing-away or motion and the multiplicity of things. 
He made these concessions to the facts of perception: on the 
other hand, he conceded to the Monists that there could be no 
motion without a void. The result is a theory which he states as 
follows: 'The void is a «not being», and no part of «what is» is a 
«not-being»; for what «is» in the strict sense of the term is an 
absolute plenum. This plenum, however, is not «one»: on the 
contrary, it is a many» infinite in number and invisible owing to 
the minuteness of their bulk. The «many» move in the void (for 
there is a void): and by coming together they produce «coming- 
to-be», while by separating they produce «passing-away». 
Moreover, they act and suffer action wherever they chance to be 
in contact (for there they are not «one»), and they generate by 
being put together and becoming intertwined. From the 
genuinely-one, on the other hand, there never could have come- 
to-be a multiplicity, nor from the genuinely-many a «one»: that 
is impossible. But (just as Empedocles and some of the other 
philosophers say that things suffer action through their pores, 
so) 'all «alteration» and all «passion» take place in the way that 
has been explained: breaking-up (i.e. passing-away) is effected 



989 



by means of the void, and so too is growth-solids creeping in to 
fill the void places.' Empedocles too is practically bound to 
adopt the same theory as Leucippus. For he must say that there 
are certain solids which, however, are indivisible - unless there 
are continuous pores all through the body. But this last 
alternative is impossible: for then there will be nothing solid in 
the body (nothing beside the pores) but all of it will be void. It is 
necessary, therefore, for his 'contiguous discretes' to be 
indivisible, while the intervals between them - which he calls 
'pores' - must be void. But this is precisely Leucippus' theory of 
action and passion. 

Such, approximately, are the current explanations of the 
manner in which some things 'act' while others 'suffer action'. 
And as regards the Atomists, it is not only clear what their 
explanation is: it is also obvious that it follows with tolerable 
consistency from the assumptions they employ. But there is less 
obvious consistency in the explanation offered by the other 
thinkers. It is not clear, for instance, how, on the theory of 
Empedocles, there is to be 'passing-away' as well as 'alteration'. 
For the primary bodies of the Atomists - the primary 
constituents of which bodies are composed, and the ultimate 
elements into which they are dissolved - are indivisible, 
differing from one another only in figure. In the philosophy of 
Empedocles, on the other hand, it is evident that all the other 
bodies down to the 'elements' have their coming-to-be and 
their passing-away: but it is not clear how the 'elements' 
themselves, severally in their aggregated masses, come-to-be 
and pass-away. Nor is it possible for Empedocles to explain how 
they do so, since he does not assert that Fire too (and similarly 
every one of his other 'elements') possesses 'elementary 
constituents' of itself. 

Such an assertion would commit him to doctrines like those 
which Plato has set forth in the Timaeus. For although both 



990 



Plato and Leucippus postulate elementary constituents that are 
indivisible and distinctively characterized by figures, there is 
this great difference between the two theories: the 'indivisibles' 
of Leucippus (i) are solids, while those of Plato are planes, and 
(ii) are characterized by an infinite variety of figures, while the 
characterizing figures employed by Plato are limited in number. 
Thus the 'comings-to-be' and the 'dissociations' result from the 
'indivisibles' (a) according to Leucippus through the void and 
through contact (for it is at the point of contact that each of the 
composite bodies is divisible), but (b) according to Plato in virtue 
of contact alone, since he denies there is a void. 

Now we have discussed 'indivisible planes' in the preceding 
treatise.' But with regard to the assumption of 'indivisible 
solids', although we must not now enter upon a detailed study 
of its consequences, the following criticisms fall within the 
compass of a short digression: i. The Atomists are committed to 
the view that every 'indivisible' is incapable alike of receiving a 
sensible property (for nothing can 'suffer action' except through 
the void) and of producing one - no 'indivisible' can be, e.g. 
either hard or cold. Yet it is surely a paradox that an exception 
is made of 'the hot' - 'the hot' being assigned as peculiar to the 
spherical figure: for, that being so, its 'contrary' also ('the cold') 
is bound to belong to another of the figures. If, however, these 
properties (heat and cold) do belong to the 'indivisibles', it is a 
further paradox that they should not possess heaviness and 
lightness, and hardness and softness. And yet Democritus says 
'the more any indivisible exceeds, the heavier it is' - to which 
we must clearly add 'and the hotter it is'. But if that is their 
character, it is impossible they should not be affected by one 
another: the 'slightly-hot indivisible', e.g. will inevitably suffer 
action from one which far exceeds it in heat. Again, if any 
'indivisible' is 'hard', there must also be one which is 'soft': but 
'the soft' derives its very name from the fact that it suffers a 
certain action - for 'soft' is that which yields to pressure. 



991 



II. But further, not only is it paradoxical (i) that no property 
except figure should belong to the 'indivisibles': it is also 
paradoxical (ii) that, if other properties do belong to them, one 
only of these additional properties should attach to each - e.g. 
that this 'indivisible' should be cold and that 'indivisible' hot. 
For, on that supposition, their substance would not even be 
uniform. And it is equally impossible (iii) that more than one of 
these additional properties should belong to the single 
'indivisible'. For, being indivisible, it will possess these 
properties in the same point - so that, if it 'suffers action' by 
being chilled, it will also, qua chilled, 'act' or 'suffer action' in 
some other way. And the same line of argument applies to all 
the other properties too: for the difficulty we have just raised 
confronts, as a necessary consequence, all who advocate 
'indivisibles' (whether solids or planes), since their 'indivisibles' 
cannot become either 'rarer' or 'derser' inasmuch as there is no 
void in them. 

III. It is a further paradox that there should be small 
'indivisibles', but not large ones. For it is natural enough, from 
the ordinary point of view, that the larger bodies should be more 
liable to fracture than the small ones, since they (viz. the large 
bodies) are easily broken up because they collide with many 
other bodies. But why should indivisibility as such be the 
property of small, rather than of large, bodies? 

IV. Again, is the substance of all those solids uniform, or do they 
fall into sets which differ from one another - as if, e.g. some of 
them, in their aggregated bulk, were 'fiery', others earthy? For 
(i) if all of them are uniform in substance, what is it that 
separated one from another? Or why, when they come into 
contact, do they not coalesce into one, as drops of water run 
together when drop touches drop (for the two cases are 
precisely parallel)? On the other hand (ii) if they fall into 
differing sets, how are these characterized? It is clear, too, that 



992 



these, rather than the 'figures', ought to be postulated as 
'original reals', i.e. causes from which the phenomena result. 
Moreover, if they differed in substance, they would both act and 
suffer action on coming into reciprocal contact. 

V. Again, what is it which sets them moving? For if their 'mover' 
is other than themselves, they are such as to 'suffer action'. If, 
on the other hand, each of them sets itself in motion, either (a) 
it will be divisible ('imparting motion' qua this, 'being moved' 
qua that), or (b) contrary properties will attach to it in the same 
respect - i.e. 'matter' will be identical in-potentiality as well as 
numerically-identical. 

As to the thinkers who explain modification of property 
through the movement facilitated by the pores, if this is 
supposed to occur notwithstanding the fact that the pores are 
filled, their postulate of pores is superfluous. For if the whole 
body suffers action under these conditions, it would suffer 
action in the same way even if it had no pores but were just its 
own continuous self. Moreover, how can their account of 'vision 
through a medium' be correct? It is impossible for (the visual 
ray) to penetrate the transparent bodies at their 'contacts'; and 
impossible for it to pass through their pores if every pore be full. 
For how will that differ from having no pores at all? The body 
will be uniformly 'full' throughout. But, further, even if these 
passages, though they must contain bodies, are 'void', the same 
consequence will follow once more. And if they are 'too minute 
to admit any body', it is absurd to suppose there is a 'minute' 
void and yet to deny the existence of a 'big' one (no matter how 
small the 'big' may be), or to imagine 'the void' means anything 
else than a body's place - whence it clearly follows that to every 
body there will correspond a void of equal cubic capacity. 

As a general criticism we must urge that to postulate pores is 
superfluous. For if the agent produces no effect by touching the 



993 



patient, neither will it produce any by passing through its pores. 
On the other hand, if it acts by contact, then - even without 
pores - some things will 'suffer action' and others will 'act', 
provided they are by nature adapted for reciprocal action and 
passion. Our arguments have shown that it is either false or 
futile to advocate pores in the sense in which some thinkers 
conceive them. But since bodies are divisible through and 
through, the postulate of pores is ridiculous: for, qua divisible, a 
body can fall into separate parts. 



Let explain the way in which things in fact possess the power of 
generating, and of acting and suffering action: and let us start 
from the principle we have often enunciated. For, assuming the 
distinction between (a) that which is potentially and (b) that 
which is actually such-and-such, it is the nature of the first, 
precisely in so far as it is what it is, to suffer action through and 
through, not merely to be susceptible in some parts while 
insusceptible in others. But its susceptibility varies in degree, 
according as it is more or less; such-and-such, and one would 
be more justified in speaking of 'pores' in this connexion: for 
instance, in the metals there are veins of 'the susceptible' 
stretching continuously through the substance. 

So long, indeed, as any body is naturally coherent and one, it is 
insusceptible. So, too, bodies are insusceptible so long as they 
are not in contact either with one another or with other bodies 
which are by nature such as to act and suffer action. (To 
illustrate my meaning: Fire heats not only when in contact, but 
also from a distance. For the fire heats the air, and the air - 
being by nature such as both to act and suffer action - heats the 



994 



body.) But the supposition that a body is 'susceptible in some 
parts, but insusceptible in others' (is only possible for those who 
hold an erroneous view concerning the divisibility of 
magnitudes. For us) the following account results from the 
distinctions we established at the beginning. For (i) if 
magnitudes are not divisible through and through - if, on the 
contrary, there are indivisible solids or planes - then indeed no 
body would be susceptible through and through :but neither 
would any be continuous. Since, however, (ii) this is false, i.e. 
since every body is divisible, there is no difference between 
'having been divided into parts which remain in contact' and 
'being divisible'. For if a body 'can be separated at the contacts' 
(as some thinkers express it), then, even though it has not yet 
been divided, it will be in a state of dividedness - since, as it can 
be divided, nothing inconceivable results. And (iii) the 
suposition is open to this general objection - it is a paradox that 
'passion' should occur in this manner only, viz. by the bodies 
being split. For this theory abolishes 'alteration': but we see the 
same body liquid at one time and solid at another, without 
losing its continuity. It has suffered this change not by 'division' 
and composition', nor yet by 'turning' and 'intercontact' as 
Democritus asserts; for it has passed from the liquid to the solid 
state without any change of 'grouping' or 'position' in the 
constituents of its substance. Nor are there contained within it 
those 'hard' (i.e. congealed) particles 'indivisible in their bulk': 
on the contrary, it is liquid - and again, solid and congealed - 
uniformly all through. This theory, it must be added, makes 
growth and diminution impossible also. For if there is to be 
opposition (instead of the growing thing having changed as a 
whole, either by the admixture of something or by its own 
transformation), increase of size will not have resulted in any 
and every part. 

So much, then, to establish that things generate and are 
generated, act and suffer action, reciprocally; and to distinguish 



995 



the way in which these processes can occur from the 
(impossible) way in which some thinkers say they occur. 



10 

But we have still to explain 'combination', for that was the third 
of the subjects we originally proposed to discuss. Our 
explanation will proceed on the same method as before. We 
must inquire: What is 'combination', and what is that which can 
'combine? Of what things, and under what conditions, is 
'combination' a property? And, further, does 'combination' exist 
in fact, or is it false to assert its existence? 

For, according to some thinkers, it is impossible for one thing to 
be combined with another. They argue that (i) if both the 
'combined' constituents persist unaltered, they are no more 
'combined' now than they were before, but are in the same 
condition: while (ii) if one has been destroyed, the constituents 
have not been 'combined' - on the contrary, one constituent is 
and the other is not, whereas 'combination' demands 
uniformity of condition in them both: and on the same principle 
(iii) even if both the combining constituents have been 
destroyed as the result of their coalescence, they cannot 'have 
been combined' since they have no being at all. 

What we have in this argument is, it would seem, a demand for 
the precise distinction of 'combination' from coming-to-be and 
passing-away (for it is obvious that 'combination', if it exists, 
must differ from these processes) and for the precise distinction 
of the 'combinable' from that which is such as to come-to-be 
and pass-away. As soon, therefore, as these distinctions are 
clear, the difficulties raised by the argument would be solved. 



996 



Now (i) we do not speak of the wood as 'combined' with the fire, 
nor of its burning as a 'combining' either of its particles with 
one another or of itself with the fire: what we say is that 'the 
fire is coming-to-be, but the wood is 'passing-away'. Similarly, 
we speak neither (ii) of the food as 'combining' with the body, 
nor (iii) of the shape as 'combining' with the wax and thus 
fashioning the lump. Nor can body 'combine' with white, nor (to 
generalize) 'properties' and 'states' with 'things': for we see 
them persisting unaltered. But again (iv) white and knowledge 
cannot be 'combined' either, nor any other of the 'adjectivals'. 
(Indeed, this is a blemish in the theory of those who assert that 
'once upon a time all things were together and combined'. For 
not everything can 'combine' with everything. On the contrary, 
both of the constituents that are combined in the compound 
must originally have existed in separation: but no property can 
have separate existence.) 

Since, however, some things are-potentially while others are- 
actually, the constituents combined in a compound can 'be' in a 
sense and yet 'not-be'. The compound may be-actually other 
than the constituents from which it has resulted; nevertheless 
each of them may still be-potentially what it was before they 
were combined, and both of them may survive undestroyed. 
(For this was the difficulty that emerged in the previous 
argument: and it is evident that the combining constituents not 
only coalesce, having formerly existed in separation, but also 
can again be separated out from the compound.) The 
constituents, therefore, neither (a) persist actually, as 'body' and 
'white' persist: nor (b) are they destroyed (either one of them or 
both), for their 'power of action' is preserved. Hence these 
difficulties may be dismissed: but the problem immediately 
connected with them - whether combination is something 
relative to perception' must be set out and discussed. 



997 



When the combining constituents have been divided into parts 
so small, and have been juxtaposed in such a manner, that 
perception fails to discriminate them one from another, have 
they then 'been combined Or ought we to say 'No, not until any 
and every part of one constituent is juxtaposed to a part of the 
other? The term, no doubt, is applied in the former sense: we 
speak, e.g. of wheat having been 'combined' with barley when 
each grain of the one is juxtaposed to a grain of the other. But 
every body is divisible and therefore, since body 'combined' with 
body is uniform in texture throughout, any and every part of 
each constituent ought to be juxtaposed to a part of the other. 

No body, however, can be divided into its 'least' parts: and 
'composition' is not identical with 'combination', but other than 
it. From these premises it clearly follows (i) that so long as the 
constituents are preserved in small particles, we must not 
speak of them as 'combined'. (For this will be a 'composition' 
instead of a 'blending' or 'combination': nor will every portion of 
the resultant exhibit the same ratio between its constituents as 
the whole. But we maintain that, if 'combination' has taken 
place, the compound must be uniform in texture throughout - 
any part of such a compound being the same as the whole, just 
as any part of water is water: whereas, if 'combination' is 
'composition of the small particles', nothing of the kind will 
happen. On the contrary, the constituents will only be 
'combined' relatively to perception: and the same thing will be 
'combined' to one percipient, if his sight is not sharp, (but not to 
another,) while to the eye of Lynceus nothing will be 
'combined'.) It clearly follows (ii) that we must not speak of the 
constituents as 'combined in virtue of a division such that any 
and every part of each is juxtaposed to a part of the other: for it 
is impossible for them to be thus divided. Either, then, there is 
no 'combination', or we have still to explain the manner in 
which it can take place. 



998 



Now, as we maintain, some things are such as to act and others 
such as to suffer action from them. Moreover, some things - viz. 
those which have the same matter - 'reciprocate', i.e. are such 
as to act upon one another and to suffer action from one 
another; while other things, viz. agents which have not the 
same matter as their patients, act without themselves suffering 
action. Such agents cannot 'combine' - that is why neither the 
art of healing nor health produces health by 'combining' with 
the bodies of the patients. Amongst those things, however, 
which are reciprocally active and passive, some are easily- 
divisible. Now (i) if a great quantity (or a large bulk) of one of 
these easily-divisible 'reciprocating' materials be brought 
together with a little (or with a small piece) of another, the 
effect produced is not 'combination', but increase of the 
dominant: for the other material is transformed into the 
dominant. (That is why a drop of wine does not 'combine' with 
ten thousand gallons of water: for its form is dissolved, and it is 
changed so as to merge in the total volume of water.) On the 
other hand (ii) when there is a certain equilibrium between 
their 'powers of action', then each of them changes out of its 
own nature towards the dominant: yet neither becomes the 
other, but both become an intermediate with properties 
common to both. 

Thus it is clear that only those agents are 'combinable' which 
involve a contrariety - for these are such as to suffer action 
reciprocally. And, further, they combine more freely if small 
pieces of each of them are juxtaposed. For in that condition 
they change one another more easily and more quickly; 
whereas this effect takes a long time when agent and patient 
are present in bulk. 

Hence, amongst the divisible susceptible materials, those whose 
shape is readily adaptable have a tendency to combine: for they 
are easily divided into small particles, since that is precisely 



999 



what 'being readily adaptable in shape' implies. For instance, 
liquids are the most 'combinable' of all bodies - because, of all 
divisible materials, the liquid is most readily adaptable in shape, 
unless it be viscous. Viscous liquids, it is true, produce no effect 
except to increase the volume and bulk. But when one of the 
constituents is alone susceptible - or superlatively susceptible, 
the other being susceptible in a very slight degree - the 
compound resulting from their combination is either no greater 
in volume or only a little greater. This is what happens when tin 
is combined with bronze. For some things display a hesitating 
and ambiguous attitude towards one another - showing a slight 
tendency to combine and also an inclination to behave as 
'receptive matter' and 'form' respectively. The behaviour of 
these metals is a case in point. For the tin almost vanishes, 
behaving as if it were an immaterial property of the bronze: 
having been combined, it disappears, leaving no trace except 
the colour it has imparted to the bronze. The same 
phenomenon occurs in other instances too. 

It is clear, then, from the foregoing account, that 'combination' 
occurs, what it is, to what it is due, and what kind of thing is 
'combinable'. The phenomenon depends upon the fact that 
some things are such as to be (a) reciprocally susceptible and (b) 
readily adaptable in shape, i.e. easily divisible. For such things 
can be 'combined' without its being necessary either that they 
should have been destroyed or that they should survive 
absolutely unaltered: and their 'combination' need not be a 
'composition', nor merely 'relative to perception'. On the 
contrary: anything is 'combinable' which, being readily 
adaptable in shape, is such as to suffer action and to act; and it 
is 'combinable with' another thing similarly characterized (for 
the 'combinable' is relative to the 'combinable'); and 
'combination' is unification of the 'combinables', resulting from 
their 'alteration'. 



1000 



Book II 



We have explained under what conditions 'combination', 
'contact', and 'action-passion' are attributable to the things 
which undergo natural change. Further, we have discussed 
'unqualified' coming-to-be and passing-away, and explained 
under what conditions they are predicable, of what subject, and 
owing to what cause. Similarly, we have also discussed 
'alteration', and explained what 'altering' is and how it differs 
from coming-to-be and passing-away. But we have still to 
investigate the so-called 'elements' of bodies. 

For the complex substances whose formation and maintenance 
are due to natural processes all presuppose the perceptible 
bodies as the condition of their coming-to-be and passing-away: 
but philosophers disagree in regard to the matter which 
underlies these perceptible bodies. Some maintain it is single, 
supposing it to be, e.g. Air or Fire, or an 'intermediate' between 
these two (but still a body with a separate existence). Others, on 
the contrary, postulate two or more materials - ascribing to 
their 'association' and 'dissociation', or to their 'alteration', the 
coming-to-be and passing-away of things. (Some, for instance, 
postulate Fire and Earth: some add Air, making three: and some, 
like Empedocles, reckon Water as well, thus postulating four.) 



1001 



Now we may agree that the primary materials, whose change 
(whether it be 'association and dissociation' or a process of 
another kind) results in coming-to-be and passing-away, are 
rightly described as 'originative sources, i.e. elements'. But (i) 
those thinkers are in error who postulate, beside the bodies we 
have mentioned, a single matter - and that corporeal and 
separable matter. For this 'body' of theirs cannot possibly exist 
without a 'perceptible contrariety': this 'Boundless', which some 
thinkers identify with the 'original real', must be either light or 
heavy, either cold or hot. And (ii) what Plato has written in the 
Timaeus is not based on any precisely-articulated conception. 
For he has not stated clearly whether his 'Omnirecipient' exists 
in separation from the 'elements'; nor does he make any use of 
it. He says, indeed, that it is a substratum prior to the so-called 
'elements' - underlying them, as gold underlies the things that 
are fashioned of gold. (And yet this comparison, if thus 
expressed, is itself open to criticism. Things which come-to-be 
and pass-away cannot be called by the name of the material out 
of which they have come-to-be: it is only the results of 
'alteration' which retain the name of the substratum whose 
'alterations' they are. However, he actually says 'that the truest 
account is to affirm that each of them is «gold»'.) Nevertheless 
he carries his analysis of the 'elements' - solids though they are 
- back to 'planes', and it is impossible for 'the Nurse' (i.e. the 
primary matter) to be identical with 'the planes'. 

Our own doctrine is that although there is a matter of the 
perceptible bodies (a matter out of which the so-called 
'elements' come-to-be), it has no separate existence, but is 
always bound up with a contrariety. A more precise account of 
these presuppositions has been given in another work': we 
must, however, give a detailed explanation of the primary 
bodies as well, since they too are similarly derived from the 
matter. We must reckon as an 'originative source' and as 
'primary' the matter which underlies, though it is inseparable 



1002 



from, the contrary qualities: for the hot' is not matter for 'the 
cold' nor 'the cold' for 'the hot', but the substratum is matter for 
them both. We therefore have to recognize three 'originative 
sources': firstly that which potentially perceptible body, 
secondly the contrarieties (I mean, e.g. heat and cold), and 
thirdly Fire, Water, and the like. Only 'thirdly', however: for these 
bodies change into one another (they are not immutable as 
Empedocles and other thinkers assert, since 'alteration' would 
then have been impossible), whereas the contrarieties do not 
change. 

Nevertheless, even so the question remains: What sorts of 
contrarieties, and how many of them, are to be accounted 
'originative sources' of body? For all the other thinkers assume 
and use them without explaining why they are these or why 
they are just so many. 



Since, then, we are looking for 'originative sources' of 
perceptible body; and since 'perceptible' is equivalent to 
'tangible', and 'tangible' is that of which the perception is touch; 
it is clear that not all the contrarieties constitute 'forms' and 
'originative sources' of body, but only those which correspond to 
touch. For it is in accordance with a contrariety - a contrariety, 
moreover, of tangible qualities - that the primary bodies are 
differentiated. That is why neither whiteness (and blackness), 
nor sweetness (and bitterness), nor (similarly) any quality 
belonging to the other perceptible contrarieties either, 
constitutes an 'element'. And yet vision is prior to touch, so that 
its object also is prior to the object of touch. The object of vision, 
however, is a quality of tangible body not qua tangible, but qua 



1003 



something else - qua something which may well be naturally 
prior to the object of touch. 

Accordingly, we must segregate the tangible differences and 
contrarieties, and distinguish which amongst them are primary. 
Contrarieties correlative to touch are the following: hot-cold, 
dry-moist, heavy-light, hard-soft, viscous-brittle, rough-smooth, 
coarse-fine. Of these (i) heavy and light are neither active nor 
susceptible. Things are not called 'heavy' and 'light' because 
they act upon, or suffer action from, other things. But the 
'elements' must be reciprocally active and susceptible, since 
they 'combine' and are transformed into one another. On the 
other hand (ii) hot and cold, and dry and moist, are terms, of 
which the first pair implies power to act and the second pair 
susceptibility. 'Hot' is that which 'associates' things of the same 
kind (for 'dissociating', which people attribute to Fire as its 
function, is 'associating' things of the same class, since its effect 
is to eliminate what is foreign), while 'cold' is that which brings 
together, i.e. 'associates', homogeneous and heterogeneous 
things alike. And moise is that which, being readily adaptable in 
shape, is not determinable by any limit of its own: while 'dry' is 
that which is readily determinable by its own limit, but not 
readily adaptable in shape. 

From moist and dry are derived (iii) the fine and coarse, viscous 
and brittle, hard and soft, and the remaining tangible 
differences. For (a) since the moist has no determinate shape, 
but is readily adaptable and follows the outline of that which is 
in contact with it, it is characteristic of it to be 'such as to fill 
up'. Now 'the fine' is 'such as to fill up'. For the fine' consists of 
subtle particles; but that which consists of small particles is 
'such as to fill up', inasmuch as it is in contact whole with 
whole - and 'the fine' exhibits this character in a superlative 
degree. Hence it is evident that the fine derives from the moist, 
while the coarse derives from the dry. Again (b) the viscous' 



1004 



derives from the moist: for 'the viscous' (e.g. oil) is a 'moist' 
modified in a certain way. 'The brittle', on the other hand, 
derives from the dry: for 'brittle' is that which is completely dry 

- so completely, that its solidification has actually been due to 
failure of moisture. Further (c) 'the soft' derives from the moist. 
For 'soft' is that which yields to pressure by retiring into itself, 
though it does not yield by total displacement as the moist does 

- which explains why the moist is not 'soft', although 'the soft' 
derives from the moist. 'The hard', on the other hand, derives 
from the dry: for 'hard' is that which is solidified, and the 
solidified is dry. 

The terms 'dry' and 'moist' have more senses than one. For 'the 
damp', as well as the moist, is opposed to the dry: and again 
'the solidified', as well as the dry, is opposed to the moist. But 
all these qualities derive from the dry and moist we mentioned 
first.' For (i) the dry is opposed to the damp: i.e. 'damp' is that 
which has foreign moisture on its surface ('sodden' being that 
which is penetrated to its core), while 'dry' is that which has 
lost foreign moisture. Hence it is evident that the damp will 
derive from the moist, and 'the dry' which is opposed to it will 
derive from the primary dry. Again (ii) the 'moist' and the 
solidified derive in the same way from the primary pair. For 
'moist' is that which contains moisture of its own deep within it 
('sodden' being that which is deeply penetrated by foreign 
mosture), whereas 'solidigied' is that which has lost this inner 
moisture. Hence these too derive from the primary pair, the 
'solidified' from the dry and the 'solidified' from the dry the 
'liquefiable' from the moist. 

It is clear, then, that all the other differences reduce to the first 
four, but that these admit of no further reduction. For the hot is 
not essentially moist or dry, nor the moist essentially hot or 
cold: nor are the cold and the dry derivative forms, either of one 
another or of the hot and the moist. Hence these must be four. 



1005 



The elementary qualities are four, and any four terms can be 
combined in six couples. Contraries, however, refuse to be 
coupled: for it is impossible for the same thing to be hot and 
cold, or moist and dry Hence it is evident that the 'couplings' of 
the elementary qualities will be four: hot with dry and moist 
with hot, and again cold with dry and cold with moist. And 
these four couples have attached themselves to the apparently 
'simple' bodies (Fire, Air, Water, and Earth) in a manner 
consonant with theory. For Fire is hot and dry, whereas Air is 
hot and moist (Air being a sort of aqueous vapour); and Water is 
cold and moist, while Earth is cold and dry. Thus the differences 
are reasonably distributed among the primary bodies, and the 
number of the latter is consonant with theory. For all who make 
the simple bodies 'elements' postulate either one, or two, or 
three, or four. Now (i) those who assert there is one only, and 
then generate everything else by condensation and rarefaction, 
are in effect making their 'originative sources' two, viz. the rare 
and the dense, or rather the hot and the cold: for it is these 
which are the moulding forces, while the 'one' underlies them 
as a 'matter'. But (ii) those who postulate two from the start - as 
Parmenides postulated Fire and Earth - make the intermediates 
(e.g. Air and Water) blends of these. The same course is followed 
(iii) by those who advocate three. (We may compare what Plato 
does in Me Divisions': for he makes 'the middle' a blend.) 
Indeed, there is practically no difference between those who 
postulate two and those who postulate three, except that the 
former split the middle 'element' into two, while the latter treat 
it as only one. But (iv) some advocate four from the start, e.g. 



1006 



Empedocles: yet he too draws them together so as to reduce 
them to the two, for he opposes all the others to Fire. 

In fact, however, fire and air, and each of the bodies we have 
mentioned, are not simple, but blended. The 'simple' bodies are 
indeed similar in nature to them, but not identical with them. 
Thus the 'simple' body corresponding to fire is 'such -as -fire, not 
fire: that which corresponds to air is 'such-as-air': and so on 
with the rest of them. But fire is an excess of heat, just as ice is 
an excess of cold. For freezing and boiling are excesses of heat 
and cold respectively. Assuming, therefore, that ice is a freezing 
of moist and cold, fire analogously will be a boiling of dry and 
hot: a fact, by the way, which explains why nothing comes-to-be 
either out of ice or out of fire. 

The 'simple' bodies, since they are four, fall into two pairs which 
belong to the two regions, each to each: for Fire and Air are 
forms of the body moving towards the 'limit', while Earth and 
Water are forms of the body which moves towards the 'centre'. 
Fire and Earth, moreover, are extremes and purest: Water and 
Air, on the contrary are intermediates and more like blends. 
And, further, the members of either pair are contrary to those of 
the other, Water being contrary to Fire and Earth to Air; for the 
qualities constituting Water and Earth are contrary to those that 
constitute Fire and Air. Nevertheless, since they are four, each of 
them is characterized par excellence a single quality: Earth by 
dry rather than by cold, Water by cold rather than by moist, Air 
by moist rather than by hot, and Fire by hot rather than by dry. 



It has been established before' that the coming-to-be of the 
'simple' bodies is reciprocal. At the same time, it is manifest, 



1007 



even on the evidence of perception, that they do come-to-be: for 
otherwise there would not have been 'alteration, since 
'alteration' is change in respect to the qualities of the objects of 
touch. Consequently, we must explain (i) what is the manner of 
their reciprocal transformation, and (ii) whether every one of 
them can come-to-be out of every one - or whether some can 
do so, but not others. 

Now it is evident that all of them are by nature such as to 
change into one another: for coming-to-be is a change into 
contraries and out of contraries, and the 'elements' all involve a 
contrariety in their mutual relations because their distinctive 
qualities are contrary. For in some of them both qualities are 
contrary - e.g. in Fire and Water, the first of these being dry and 
hot, and the second moist and cold: while in others one of the 
qualities (though only one) is contrary - e.g. in Air and Water, 
the first being moist and hot, and the second moist and cold. It 
is evident, therefore, if we consider them in general, that every 
one is by nature such as to come-to-be out of every one: and 
when we come to consider them severally, it is not difficult to 
see the manner in which their transformation is effected. For, 
though all will result from all, both the speed and the facility of 
their conversion will differ in degree. 

Thus (i) the process of conversion will be quick between those 
which have interchangeable 'complementary factors', but slow 
between those which have none. The reason is that it is easier 
for a single thing to change than for many. Air, e.g. will result 
from Fire if a single quality changes: for Fire, as we saw, is hot 
and dry while Air is hot and moist, so that there will be Air if 
the dry be overcome by the moist. Again, Water will result from 
Air if the hot be overcome by the cold: for Air, as we saw, is hot 
and moist while Water is cold and moist, so that, if the hot 
changes, there will be Water. So too, in the same manner, Earth 
will result from Water and Fire from Earth, since the two 



1008 



'elements' in both these couples have interchangeable 
'complementary factors'. For Water is moist and cold while 
Earth is cold and dry - so that, if the moist be overcome, there 
will be Earth: and again, since Fire is dry and hot while Earth is 
cold and dry, Fire will result from Earth if the cold pass-away. 

It is evident, therefore, that the coming-to-be of the 'simple' 
bodies will be cyclical; and that this cyclical method of 
transformation is the easiest, because the consecutive 
'elements' contain interchangeable 'complementary factors'. On 
the other hand (ii) the transformation of Fire into Water and of 
Air into Earth, and again of Water and Earth into Fire and Air 
respectively, though possible, is more difficult because it 
involves the change of more qualities. For if Fire is to result 
from Water, both the cold and the moist must pass-away: and 
again, both the cold and the dry must pass-away if Air is to 
result from Earth. So' too, if Water and Earth are to result from 
Fire and Air respectively - both qualities must change. 

This second method of coming-to-be, then, takes a longer time. 
But (iii) if one quality in each of two 'elements' pass-away, the 
transformation, though easier, is not reciprocal. Still, from Fire 
plus Water there will result Earth and Air, and from Air plus 
Earth Fire and Water. For there will be Air, when the cold of the 
Water and the dry of the Fire have passed-away (since the hot of 
the latter and the moist of the former are left): whereas, when 
the hot of the Fire and the moist of the Water have passed-away, 
there will be Earth, owing to the survival of the dry of the Fire 
and the cold of the Water. So, too, in the same Way, Fire and 
Water will result from Air plus Earth. For there will be Water, 
when the hot of the Air and the dry of the Earth have passed- 
away (since the moist of the former and the cold of the latter 
are left): whereas, when the moist of the Air and the cold of the 
Earth have passed-away, there will be Fire, owing to the survival 
of the hot of the Air and the dry of the Earth - qualities 



1009 



essentially constitutive of Fire. Moreover, this mode of Fire's 
coming-to-be is confirmed by perception. For flame is par 
excellence Fire: but flame is burning smoke, and smoke consists 
of Air and Earth. 

No transformation, however, into any of the 'simple' bodies can 
result from the passing-away of one elementary quality in each 
of two 'elements' when they are taken in their consecutive 
order, because either identical or contrary qualities are left in 
the pair: but no 'simple' body can be formed either out of 
identical, or out of contrary, qualities. Thus no 'simple' body 
would result, if the dry of Fire and the moist of Air were to pass- 
away: for the hot is left in both. On the other hand, if the hot 
pass-away out both, the contraries - dry and moist - are left. A 
similar result will occur in all the others too: for all the 
consecutive 'elements' contain one identical, and one contrary, 
quality. Hence, too, it clearly follows that, when one of the 
consecutive 'elements' is transformed into one, the coming-to- 
be is effected by the passing-away of a single quality: whereas, 
when two of them are transformed into a third, more than one 
quality must have passedaway. 

We have stated that all the 'elements' come-to-be out of any 
one of them; and we have explained the manner in which their 
mutual conversion takes place. Let us nevertheless supplement 
our theory by the following speculations concerning them. 



If Water, Air, and the like are a 'matter' of which the natural 
bodies consist, as some thinkers in fact believe, these 'elements' 
must be either one, or two, or more. Now they cannot all of 
them be one - they cannot, e.g. all be Air or Water or Fire or 



1010 



Earth - because 'Change is into contraries'. For if they all were 
Air, then (assuming Air to persist) there will be 'alteration' 
instead of coming-to-be. Besides, nobody supposes a single 
'element' to persist, as the basis of all, in such a way that it is 
Water as well as Air (or any other 'element') at the same time. 
So there will be a certain contrariety, i.e. a differentiating 
quality: and the other member of this contrariety, e.g. heat, will 
belong to some other 'element', e.g. to Fire. But Fire will 
certainly not be 'hot Air'. For a change of that kind (a) is 
'alteration', and (b) is not what is observed. Moreover (c) if Air is 
again to result out of the Fire, it will do so by the conversion of 
the hot into its contrary: this contrary, therefore, will belong to 
Air, and Air will be a cold something: hence it is impossible for 
Fire to be 'hot Air', since in that case the same thing will be 
simultaneously hot and cold. Both Fire and Air, therefore, will be 
something else which is the same; i.e. there will be some 
'matter', other than either, common to both. 

The same argument applies to all the 'elements', proving that 
there is no single one of them out of which they all originate. 
But neither is there, beside these four, some other body from 
which they originate - a something intermediate, e.g. between 
Air and Water (coarser than Air, but finer than Water), or 
between Air and Fire (coarser than Fire, but finer than Air). For 
the supposed 'intermediate' will be Air and Fire when a pair of 
contrasted qualities is added to it: but, since one of every two 
contrary qualities is a 'privation', the 'intermediate' never can 
exist - as some thinkers assert the 'Boundless' or the 
'Environing' exists - in isolation. It is, therefore, equally and 
indifferently any one of the 'elements', or else it is nothing. 

Since, then, there is nothing - at least, nothing perceptible - 
prior to these, they must be all. That being so, either they must 
always persist and not be transformable into one another: or 
they must undergo transformation - either all of them, or some 



1011 



only (as Plato wrote in the Timaeus). Now it has been proved 
before that they must undergo reciprocal transformation. It has 
also been proved that the speed with which they come-to-be, 
one out of another, is not uniform - since the process of 
reciprocal transformation is relatively quick between the 
'elements' with a 'complementary factor', but relatively slow 
between those which possess no such factor. Assuming, then, 
that the contrariety, in respect to which they are transformed, is 
one, the elements' will inevitably be two: for it is 'matter' that is 
the 'mean' between the two contraries, and matter is 
imperceptible and inseparable from them. Since, however, the 
'elements' are seen to be more than two, the contrarieties must 
at the least be two. But the contrarieties being two, the 
'elements' must be four (as they evidently are) and cannot be 
three: for the couplings' are four, since, though six are possible, 
the two in which the qualities are contrary to one another 
cannot occur. 

These subjects have been discussed before:' but the following 
arguments will make it clear that, since the 'elements' are 
transformed into one another, it is impossible for any one of 
them - whether it be at the end or in the middle - to be an 
'originative source' of the rest. There can be no such 'originative 
element' at the ends: for all of them would then be Fire or Earth, 
and this theory amounts to the assertion that all things are 
made of Fire or Earth. Nor can a 'middle-element' be such an 
originative source - as some thinkers suppose that Air is 
transformed both into Fire and into Water, and Water both into 
Air and into Earth, while the 'end-elements' are not further 
transformed into one another. For the process must come to a 
stop, and cannot continue ad infinitum in a straight line in 
either direction, since otherwise an infinite number of 
contrarieties would attach to the single 'element'. Let E stand 
for Earth, W for Water, A for Air, and F for Fire. Then (i) since A is 
transformed into F and W, there will be a contrariety belonging 



1012 



to A F. Let these contraries be whiteness and blackness. Again 
(ii) since A is transformed into W, there will be another 
contrariety: for W is not the same as F. Let this second 
contrariety be dryness and moistness, D being dryness and M 
moistness. Now if, when A is transformed into W, the 'white' 
persists, Water will be moist and white: but if it does not persist, 
Water will be black since change is into contraries. Water, 
therefore, must be either white or black. Let it then be the first. 
On similar grounds, therefore, D (dryness) will also belong to F. 
Consequently F (Fire) as well as Air will be able to be 
transformed into Water: for it has qualities contrary to those of 
Water, since Fire was first taken to be black and then to be dry, 
while Water was moist and then showed itself white. Thus it is 
evident that all the 'elements' will be able to be transformed out 
of one another; and that, in the instances we have taken, E 
(Earth) also will contain the remaining two 'complementary 
factors', viz. the black and the moist (for these have not yet 
been coupled). 

We have dealt with this last topic before the thesis we set out to 
prove. That thesis - viz. that the process cannot continue ad 
infinitum - will be clear from the following considerations. If 
Fire (which is represented by F) is not to revert, but is to be 
transformed in turn into some other 'element' (e.g. into Q), a 
new contrariety, other than those mentioned, will belong to Fire 
and Q: for it has been assumed that Q is not the same as any of 
the four, E W A and F. Let K, then, belong to F and Y to Q. Then K 
will belong to all four, E W A and F: for they are transformed into 
one another. This last point, however, we may admit, has not yet 
been proved: but at any rate it is clear that if Q is to be 
transformed in turn into yet another 'element', yet another 
contrariety will belong not only to Q but also to F (Fire). And, 
similarly, every addition of a new 'element' will carry with it the 
attachment of a new contrariety to the preceding elements'. 
Consequently, if the 'elements' are infinitely many, there will 



1013 



also belong to the single 'element' an infinite number of 
contrarieties. But if that be so, it will be impossible to define any 
'element': impossible also for any to come-to-be. For if one is to 
result from another, it will have to pass through such a vast 
number of contrarieties - and indeed even more than any 
determinate number. Consequently (i) into some 'elements' 
transformation will never be effected - viz. if the intermediates 
are infinite in number, as they must be if the 'elements' are 
infinitely many: further (ii) there will not even be a 
transformation of Air into Fire, if the contrarieties are infinitely 
many: moreover (iii) all the 'elements' become one. For all the 
contrarieties of the 'elements' above F must belong to those 
below F, and vice versa: hence they will all be one. 



As for those who agree with Empedocles that the 'elements' of 
body are more than one, so that they are not transformed into 
one another - one may well wonder in what sense it is open to 
them to maintain that the 'elements' are comparable. Yet 
Empedocles says 'For these are all not only equal...' 

If it is meant that they are comparable in their amount, all the 
'comparables' must possess an identical something whereby 
they are measured. If, e.g. one pint of Water yields ten of Air, 
both are measured by the same unit; and therefore both were 
from the first an identical something. On the other hand, 
suppose (ii) they are not 'comparable in their amount' in the 
sense that so-much of the one yields so much of the other, but 
comparable in 'power of action (a pint of Water, e.g. having a 
power of cooling equal to that of ten pints of Air); even so, they 
are 'comparable in their amount', though not qua 'amount' but 



1014 



qua 'so-much power'. There is also (iii) a third possibility. 
Instead of comparing their powers by the measure of their 
amount, they might be compared as terms in a 
'correspondence': e.g. 'as x is hot, so correspondingly y is white'. 
But 'correspondence', though it means equality in the quantum, 
means similarity in a quale. Thus it is manifestly absurd that 
the 'simple' bodies, though they are not transformable, are 
comparable not merely as 'corresponding', but by a measure of 
their powers; i.e. that so-much Fire is comparable with many 
times that amount of Air, as being 'equally' or 'similarly' hot. For 
the same thing, if it be greater in amount, will, since it belongs 
to the same kind, have its ratio correspondingly increased. 

A further objection to the theory of Empedocles is that it makes 
even growth impossible, unless it be increase by addition. For 
his Fire increases by Fire: 'And Earth increases its own frame 
and Ether increases Ether.» These, however, are cases of 
addition: but it is not by addition that growing things are 
believed to increase. And it is far more difficult for him to 
account for the coming-to-be which occurs in nature. For the 
things which come-to-be by natural process all exhibit, in their 
coming-to-be, a uniformity either absolute or highly regular: 
while any exceptions any results which are in accordance 
neither with the invariable nor with the general rule are 
products of chance and luck. Then what is the cause 
determining that man comes-to-be from man, that wheat 
(instead of an olive) comes-to-be from wheat, either invariably 
or generally? Are we to say 'Bone comes-to-be if the «elements» 
be put together in such-and-such a manner? For, according to 
his own estatements, nothing comes-to-be from their 
'fortuitous consilience', but only from their 'consilience' in a 
certain proportion. What, then, is the cause of this proportional 
consilience? Presumably not Fire or Earth. But neither is it Love 
and Strife: for the former is a cause of 'association' only, and the 
latter only of 'dissociation'. No: the cause in question is the 



1015 



essential nature of each thing (not merely to quote his words) 'a 
mingling and a divorce of what has been mingled'. And chance, 
not proportion, 'is the name given to these occurrences': for 
things can be 'mingled' fortuitously. 

The cause, therefore, of the coming-to-be of the things which 
owe their existence to nature is that they are in such-and-such 
a determinate condition: and it is this which constitutes, the 
'nature' of each thing - a 'nature' about which he says nothing. 
What he says, therefore, is no explanation of 'nature'. Moreover, 
it is this which is both 'the excellence' of each thing and its 
'good': whereas he assigns the whole credit to the 'mingling'. 
(And yet the 'elements' at all events are 'dissociated' not by 
Strife, but by Love: since the 'elements' are by nature prior to 
the Deity, and they too are Deities.) 

Again, his account of motion is vague. For it is not an adequate 
explanation to say that 'Love and Strife set things moving, 
unless the very nature of Love is a movement of this kind and 
the very nature of Strife a movement of that kind. He ought, 
then, either to have defined or to have postulated these 
characteristic movements, or to have demonstrated them - 
whether strictly or laxly or in some other fashion. Moreover, 
since (a) the 'simple' bodies appear to move 'naturally' as well 
as by compulsion, i.e. in a manner contrary to nature (fire, e.g. 
appears to move upwards without compulsion, though it 
appears to move by compulsion downwards); and since (b) what 
is 'natural' is contrary to that which is due to compulsion, and 
movement by compulsion actually occurs; it follows that 
'natural movement' can also occur in fact. Is this, then, the 
movement that Love sets going? No: for, on the contrary, the 
'natural movement' moves Earth downwards and resembles 
'dissociation', and Strife rather than Love is its cause - so that in 
general, too, Love rather than Strife would seem to be contrary 
to nature. And unless Love or Strife is actually setting them in 



1016 



motion, the 'simple' bodies themselves have absolutely no 
movement or rest. But this is paradoxical: and what is more, 
they do in fact obviously move. For though Strife 'dissociated', it 
was not by Strife that the 'Ether' was borne upwards. On the 
contrary, sometimes he attributes its movement to something 
like chance ('For thus, as it ran, it happened to meet them then, 
though often otherwise»), while at other times he says it is the 
nature of Fire to be borne upwards, but 'the Ether' (to quote his 
words) 'sank down upon the Earth with long roots'. With such 
statements, too, he combines the assertion that the Order of the 
World is the same now, in the reign of Strife, as it was formerly 
in the reign of Love. What, then, is the 'first mover' of the 
'elements'? What causes their motion? Presumably not Love 
and Strife: on the contrary, these are causes of a particular 
motion, if at least we assume that 'first mover' to be an 
originative source'. 

An additional paradox is that the soul should consist of the 
'elements', or that it should be one of them. How are the soul's 
'alterations' to take Place? How, e.g. is the change from being 
musical to being unmusical, or how is memory or forgetting, to 
occur? For clearly, if the soul be Fire, only such modifications 
will happen to it as characterize Fire qua Fire: while if it be 
compounded out of the elements', only the corporeal 
modifications will occur in it. But the changes we have 
mentioned are none of them corporeal. 



The discussion of these difficulties, however, is a task 
appropriate to a different investigation:' let us return to the 
'elements' of which bodies are composed. The theories that 



1017 



'there is something common to all the «elements», and that 
they are reciprocally transformed', are so related that those who 
accept either are bound to accept the other as well. Those, on 
the other hand, who do not make their coming-to-be reciprocal 
- who refuse to suppose that any one of the 'elements' comes- 
to-be out of any other taken singly, except in the sense in which 
bricks come-to-be out of a wall - are faced with a paradox. How, 
on their theory, are flesh and bones or any of the other 
compounds to result from the 'elements' taken together? 

Indeed, the point we have raised constitutes a problem even for 
those who generate the 'elements' out of one another. In what 
manner does anything other than, and beside, the 'elements' 
come-to-be out of them? Let me illustrate my meaning. Water 
can come-to-be out of Fire and Fire out of Water; for their 
substralum is something common to them both. But flesh too, 
presumably, and marrow come-to-be out of them. How, then, do 
such things come-to-be? For (a) how is the manner of their 
coming-to-be to be conceived by those who maintain a theory 
like that of Empedocles? They must conceive it as composition - 
just as a wall comes-to-be out of bricks and stones: and the 
'Mixture', of which they speak, will be composed of the 
'elements', these being preserved in it unaltered but with their 
small particles juxtaposed each to each. That will be the 
manner, presumably, in which flesh and every other compound 
results from the 'elements'. Consequently, it follows that Fire 
and Water do not come-to-be 'out of any and every part of 
flesh'. For instance, although a sphere might come-to-be out of 
this part of a lump of wax and a pyramid out of some other 
part, it was nevertheless possible for either figure to have come- 
to-be out of either part indifferently: that is the manner of 
coming-to-be when 'both Fire and Water come-to-be out of any 
and every part of flesh'. Those, however, who maintain the 
theory in question, are not at liberty to conceive that 'both 
come-to-be out of flesh' in that manner, but only as a stone and 



1018 



a brick 'both come-to-be out of a wall' - viz. each out of a 
different place or part. Similarly (b) even for those who 
postulate a single matter of their 'elements' there is a certain 
difficulty in explaining how anything is to result from two of 
them taken together - e.g. from 'cold' and hot', or from Fire and 
Earth. For if flesh consists of both and is neither of them, nor 
again is a 'composition' of them in which they are preserved 
unaltered, what alternative is left except to identify the 
resultant of the two 'elements' with their matter? For the 
passing-away of either 'element' produces either the other or 
the matter. 

Perhaps we may suggest the following solution, (i) There are 
differences of degree in hot and cold. Although, therefore, when 
either is fully real without qualification, the other will exist 
potentially; yet, when neither exists in the full completeness of 
its being, but both by combining destroy one another's excesses 
so that there exist instead a hot which (for a 'hot') is cold and a 
cold which (for a 'cold') is hot; then what results from these two 
contraries will be neither their matter, nor either of them 
existing in its full reality without qualification. There will result 
instead an 'intermediate': and this 'intermediate', according as 
it is potentially more hot than cold or vice versa, will possess a 
power-of-heating that is double or triple its power-of-cooling, or 
otherwise related thereto in some similar ratio. Thus all the 
other bodies will result from the contraries, or rather from the 
'elements', in so far as these have been 'combined': while the 
elements' will result from the contraries, in so far as these 'exist 
potentially' in a special sense - not as matter 'exists potentially', 
but in the sense explained above. And when a thing comes-to- 
be in this manner, the process is cobination'; whereas what 
comes-to-be in the other manner is matter. Moreover (ii) 
contraries also 'suffer action', in accordance with the 
disjunctively-articulated definition established in the early part 
of this work.' For the actually-hot is potentially-cold and the 



1019 



actually cold potentially-hot; so that hot and cold, unless they 
are equally balanced, are transformed into one another (and all 
the other contraries behave in a similar way). It is thus, then, 
that in the first place the 'elements' are transformed; and that 
(in the second place) out of the 'elements' there come-to-be 
flesh and bones and the like - the hot becoming cold and the 
cold becoming hot when they have been brought to the 'mean'. 
For at the 'mean' is neither hot nor cold. The 'mean', however, is 
of considerable extent and not indivisible. Similarly, it is qua 
reduced to a 'mean' condition that the dry and the moist, as 
well as the contraries we have used as examples, produce flesh 
and bone and the remaining compounds. 



8 

All the compound bodies - all of which exist in the region 
belonging to the central body - are composed of all the 'simple' 
bodies. For they all contain Earth because every 'simple' body is 
to be found specially and most abundantly in its own place. And 
they all contain Water because (a) the compound must possess 
a definite outline and Water, alone of the 'simple' bodies, is 
readily adaptable in shape: moreover (b) Earth has no power of 
cohesion without the moist. On the contrary, the moist is what 
holds it together; for it would fall to pieces if the moist were 
eliminated from it completely. 

They contain Earth and Water, then, for the reasons we have 
given: and they contain Air and Fire, because these are contrary 
to Earth and Water (Earth being contrary to Air and Water to 
Fire, in so far as one Substance can be 'contrary' to another). 
Now all compounds presuppose in their coming-to-be 
constituents which are contrary to one another: and in all 



1020 



compounds there is contained one set of the contrasted 
extremes. Hence the other set must be contained in them also, 
so that every compound will include all the 'simple' bodies. 

Additional evidence seems to be furnished by the food each 
compound takes. For all of them are fed by substances which 
are the same as their constituents, and all of them are fed by 
more substances than one. Indeed, even the plants, though it 
might be thought they are fed by one substance only, viz. by 
Water, are fed by more than one: for Earth has been mixed with 
the Water. That is why farmers too endeavour to mix before 
watering. Although food is akin to the matter, that which is fed 
is the 'figure' - i.e. the 'form' taken along with the matter. This 
fact enables us to understand why, whereas all the 'simple' 
bodies come-to-be out of one another, Fire is the only one of 
them which (as our predecessors also assert) 'is fed'. For Fire 
alone - or more than all the rest - is akin to the 'form' because it 
tends by nature to be borne towards the limit. Now each of 
them naturally tends to be borne towards its own place; but the 
'figure' - i.e. the 'form' - of them all is at the limits. 

Thus we have explained that all the compound bodies are 
composed of all the 'simple' bodies. 



Since some things are such as to come-to-be and pass-away, 
and since coming-to-be in fact occurs in the region about the 
centre, we must explain the number and the nature of the 
'originative sources' of all coming-to-be alike: for a grasp of the 
true theory of any universal facilitates the understanding of its 
specific forms. 



1021 



The 'originative sources', then, of the things which come-to-be 
are equal in number to, and identical in kind with, those in the 
sphere of the eternal and primary things. For there is one in the 
sense of 'matter', and a second in the sense of 'form': and, in 
addition, the third 'originative source' must be present as well. 
For the two first are not sufficient to bring things into being, any 
more than they are adequate to account for the primary things. 

Now cause, in the sense of material origin, for the things which 
are such as to come-to-be is 'that which can be-and-not-be': 
and this is identical with 'that which can come-to-be-and-pass- 
away', since the latter, while it is at one time, at another time is 
not. (For whereas some things are of necessity, viz. the eternal 
things, others of necessity are not. And of these two sets of 
things, since they cannot diverge from the necessity of their 
nature, it is impossible for the first not to he and impossible for 
the second to he. Other things, however, can both be and not 
he.) Hence coming-to-be and passing-away must occur within 
the field of 'that which can be-and-not-be'. This, therefore, is 
cause in the sense of material origin for the things which are 
such as to come-to-be; while cause, in the sense of their 'end', is 
their 'figure' or 'form' - and that is the formula expressing the 
essential nature of each of them. 

But the third 'originative source' must be present as well - the 
cause vaguely dreamed of by all our predecessors, definitely 
stated by none of them. On the contrary (a) some amongst them 
thought the nature of 'the Forms' was adequate to account for 
coming-to-be. Thus Socrates in the Phaedo first blames 
everybody else for having given no explanation; and then lays it 
down; that 'some things are Forms, others Participants in the 
Forms', and that 'while a thing is said to «be» in virtue of the 
Form, it is said to «come-to-be» qua sharing in,» to «pass-away» 
qua «losing,» the 'Form'. Hence he thinks that 'assuming the 
truth of these theses, the Forms must be causes both of coming- 



1022 



to-be and of passing-away'. On the other hand (b) there were 
others who thought 'the matter' was adequate by itself to 
account for coming-to-be, since 'the movement originates from 
the matter'. 

Neither of these theories, however, is sound. For (a) if the Forms 
are causes, why is their generating activity intermittent instead 
of perpetual and continuous - since there always are 
Participants as well as Forms? Besides, in some instances we 
see that the cause is other than the Form. For it is the doctor 
who implants health and the man of science who implants 
science, although 'Health itself and 'Science itself are as well 
as the Participants: and the same principle applies to everything 
else that is produced in accordance with an art. On the other 
hand (b) to say that 'matter generates owing to its movement' 
would be, no doubt, more scientific than to make such 
statements as are made by the thinkers we have been 
criticizing. For what 'alters' and transfigures plays a greater part 
in bringing, things into being; and we are everywhere 
accustomed, in the products of nature and of art alike, to look 
upon that which can initiate movement as the producing cause. 
Nevertheless this second theory is not right either. 

For, to begin with, it is characteristic of matter to suffer action, 
i.e. to be moved: but to move, i.e. to act, belongs to a different 
'power'. This is obvious both in the things that come-to-be by 
art and in those that come-to-be by nature. Water does not of 
itself produce out of itself an animal: and it is the art, not the 
wood, that makes a bed. Nor is this their only error. They make 
a second mistake in omitting the more controlling cause: for 
they eliminate the essential nature, i.e. the 'form'. And what is 
more, since they remove the formal cause, they invest the forces 
they assign to the 'simple' bodies - the forces which enable 
these bodies to bring things into being - with too instrumental a 
character. For 'since' (as they say) 'it is the nature of the hot to 



1023 



dissociate, of the cold to bring together, and of each remaining 
contrary either to act or to suffer action', it is out of such 
materials and by their agency (so they maintain) that everything 
else comes-to-be and passes-away. Yet (a) it is evident that even 
Fire is itself moved, i.e. suffers action. Moreover (b) their 
procedure is virtually the same as if one were to treat the saw 
(and the various instruments of carpentry) as 'the cause' of the 
things that come-to-be: for the wood must be divided if a man 
saws, must become smooth if he planes, and so on with the 
remaining tools. Hence, however true it may be that Fire is 
active, i.e. sets things moving, there is a further point they fail to 
observe - viz. that Fire is inferior to the tools or instruments in 
the manner in which it sets things moving. 



10 

As to our own theory - we have given a general account of the 
causes in an earlier work - we have now explained and 
distinguished the 'matter' and the 'form'. Further, since the 
change which is motion has been proved' to be eternal, the 
continuity of the occurrence of coming-to-be follows necessarily 
from what we have established: for the eternal motion, by 
causing 'the generator' to approach and retire, will produce 
coming-to-be uninterruptedly. At the same time it is clear that 
we were right when, in an earlier work,' we called motion (not 
coming-to-be) 'the primary form of change'. For it is far more 
reasonable that what is should cause the coming-to-be of what 
is not, than that what is not should cause the being of what is. 
Now that which is being moved is, but that which is coming-to- 
be is not: hence, also, motion is prior to coming-to-be. 



1024 



We have assumed, and have proved, that coming-to-be and 
passing-away happen to things continuously; and we assert 
that motion causes coming-to-be. That being so, it is evident 
that, if the motion be single, both processes cannot occur since 
they are contrary to one another: for it is a law of nature that 
the same cause, provided it remain in the same condition, 
always produces the same effect, so that, from a single motion, 
either coming-to-be or passing-away will always result. The 
movements must, on the contrary, be more than one, and they 
must be contrasted with one another either by the sense of 
their motion or by its irregularity: for contrary effects demand 
contraries as their causes. 

This explains why it is not the primary motion that causes 
coming-to-be and passing-away, but the motion along the 
inclined circle: for this motion not only possesses the necessary 
continuity, but includes a duality of movements as well. For if 
coming-to-be and passing-away are always to be continuous, 
there must be some body always being moved (in order that 
these changes may not fail) and moved with a duality of 
movements (in order that both changes, not one only, may 
result). Now the continuity of this movement is caused by the 
motion of the whole: but the approaching and retreating of the 
moving body are caused by the inclination. For the consequence 
of the inclination is that the body becomes alternately remote 
and near; and since its distance is thus unequal, its movement 
will be irregular. Therefore, if it generates by approaching and by 
its proximity, it - this very same body - destroys by retreating 
and becoming remote: and if it generates by many successive 
approaches, it also destroys by many successive retirements. For 
contrary effects demand contraries as their causes; and the 
natural processes of passing-away and coming-to-be occupy 
equal periods of time. Hence, too, the times - i.e. the lives - of 
the several kinds of living things have a number by which they 
are distinguished: for there is an Order controlling all things, 



1025 



and every time (i.e. every life) is measured by a period. Not all of 
them, however, are measured by the same period, but some by a 
smaller and others by a greater one: for to some of them the 
period, which is their measure, is a year, while to some it is 
longer and to others shorter. 

And there are facts of observation in manifest agreement with 
our theories. Thus we see that coming-to-be occurs as the sun 
approaches and decay as it retreats; and we see that the two 
processes occupy equal times. For the durations of the natural 
processes of passing-away and coming-to-be are equal. 
Nevertheless it Often happens that things pass-away in too 
short a time. This is due to the 'intermingling' by which the 
things that come-to-be and pass-away are implicated with one 
another. For their matter is 'irregular', i.e. is not everywhere the 
same: hence the processes by which they come-to-be must be 
'irregular' too, i.e. some too quick and others too slow. 
Consequently the phenomenon in question occurs, because the 
'irregular' coming-to-be of these things is the passing-away of 
other things. 

Coming-to-be and passing-away will, as we have said, always be 
continuous, and will never fail owing to the cause we stated. 
And this continuity has a sufficient reason on our theory. For in 
all things, as we affirm, Nature always strives after 'the better'. 
Now 'being' (we have explained elsewhere the exact variety of 
meanings we recognize in this term) is better than 'not-being': 
but not all things can possess 'being', since they are too far 
removed from the 'originative source. 'God therefore adopted 
the remaining alternative, and fulfilled the perfection of the 
universe by making coming-to-be uninterrupted: for the 
greatest possible coherence would thus be secured to existence, 
because that 'coming-to-be should itself come-to-be 
perpetually' is the closest approximation to eternal being. 



1026 



The cause of this perpetuity of coming-to-be, as we have often 
said, is circular motion: for that is the only motion which is 
continuous. That, too, is why all the other things - the things, I 
mean, which are reciprocally transformed in virtue of their 
'passions' and their 'powers of action' e.g. the 'simple' 
bodiesimitate circular motion. For when Water is transformed 
into Air, Air into Fire, and the Fire back into Water, we say the 
coming-to-be 'has completed the circle', because it reverts again 
to the beginning. Hence it is by imitating circular motion that 
rectilinear motion too is continuous. 

These considerations serve at the same time to explain what is 
to some people a baffling problem - viz. why the 'simple' bodies, 
since each them is travelling towards its own place, have not 
become dissevered from one another in the infinite lapse of 
time. The reason is their reciprocal transformation. For, had 
each of them persisted in its own place instead of being 
transformed by its neighbour, they would have got dissevered 
long ago. They are transformed, however, owing to the motion 
with its dual character: and because they are transformed, none 
of them is able to persist in any place allotted to it by the Order. 

It is clear from what has been said (i) that coming-to-be and 
passing-away actually occur, (ii) what causes them, and (iii) 
what subject undergoes them. But (a) if there is to be movement 
(as we have explained elsewhere, in an earlier work') there must 
be something which initiates it; if there is to be movement 
always, there must always be something which initiates it; if the 
movement is to be continuous, what initiates it must be single, 
unmoved, ungenerated, and incapable of 'alteration'; and if the 
circular movements are more than one, their initiating causes 
must all of them, in spite of their plurality, be in some way 
subordinated to a single 'originative source'. Further (b) since 
time is continuous, movement must be continuous, inasmuch 
as there can be no time without movement. Time, therefore, is a 



1027 



'number' of some continuous movement - a 'number', therefore, 
of the circular movement, as was established in the discussions 
at the beginning. But (c) is movement continuous because of the 
continuity of that which is moved, or because that in which the 
movement occurs (I mean, e.g. the place or the quality) is 
continuous? The answer must clearly be 'because that which is 
moved is continuous'. (For how can the quality be continuous 
except in virtue of the continuity of the thing to which it 
belongs? But if the continuity of 'that in which' contributes to 
make the movement continuous, this is true only of 'the place 
in which'; for that has 'magnitude' in a sense.) But (d) amongst 
continuous bodies which are moved, only that which is moved 
in a circle is 'continuous' in such a way that it preserves its 
continuity with itself throughout the movement. The conclusion 
therefore is that this is what produces continuous movement, 
viz. the body which is being moved in a circle; and its 
movement makes time continuous. 



11 

Wherever there is continuity in any process (coming-to-be or 
'alteration' or any kind of change whatever) we observe 
consecutiveness', i.e. this coming-to-be after that without any 
interval. Hence we must investigate whether, amongst the 
consecutive members, there is any whose future being is 
necessary; or whether, on the contrary, every one of them may 
fail to come-to-be. For that some of them may fail to occur, is 
clear, (a) We need only appeal to the distinction between the 
statements 'x will be' and 'x is about to which depends upon 
this fact. For if it be true to say of x that it 'will be', it must at 
some time be true to say of it that 'it is': whereas, though it be 
true to say of x now that 'it is about to occur', it is quite possible 



1028 



for it not to come-to-be - thus a man might not walk, though he 
is now 'about to' walk. And (b) since (to appeal to a general 
principle) amongst the things which 'are' some are capable also 
of not-being', it is clear that the same ambiguous character will 
attach to them no less when they are coming-to-be: in other 
words, their coming-to-be will not be necessary. 

Then are all the things that come-to-be of this contingent 
character? Or, on the contrary, is it absolutely necessary for 
some of them to come-to-be? Is there, in fact, a distinction in 
the field of 'coming-to-be' corresponding to the distinction, 
within the field of 'being', between things that cannot possibly 
'not-be' and things that can 'not-be'? For instance, is it 
necessary that solstices shall come-to-be, i.e. impossible that 
they should fail to be able to occur? 

Assuming that the antecedent must have come-to-be if the 
consequent is to be (e.g. that foundations must have come-to-be 
if there is to be a house: clay, if there are to be foundations), is 
the converse also true? If foundations have come-to-be, must a 
house come-to-be? The answer seems to be that the necessary 
nexus no longer holds, unless it is 'necessary' for the 
consequent (as well as for the antecedent) to come-to-be - 
'necessary' absolutely. If that be the case, however, 'a house 
must come-to-be if foundations have come-to-be', as well as 
vice versa. For the antecedent was assumed to be so related to 
the consequent that, if the latter is to be, the antecedent must 
have come-to-be before it. If, therefore, it is necessary that the 
consequent should come-to-be, the antecedent also must have 
come-to-be: and if the antecedent has come-to-be, then the 
consequent also must come-to-be - not, however, because of 
the antecedent, but because the future being of the consequent 
was assumed as necessary. Hence, in any sequence, when the 
being of the consequent is necessary, the nexus is reciprocal - 



1029 



in other words, when the antecedent has come-to-be the 
consequent must always come-to-be too. 

Now (i) if the sequence of occurrences is to proceed ad 
infinitum 'downwards', the coming-to-be of any determinate 
'this' amongst the later members of the sequence will not be 
absolutely, but only conditionally, necessary. For it will always 
be necessary that some other member shall have come-to-be 
before 'this' as the presupposed condition of the necessity that 
'this' should come-to-be: consequently, since what is 'infinite' 
has no 'originative source', neither will there be in the infinite 
sequence any 'primary' member which will make it 'necessary' 
for the remaining members to come-to-be. 

Nor again (ii) will it be possible to say with truth, even in regard 
to the members of a limited sequence, that it is 'absolutely 
necessary' for any one of them to come-to-be. We cannot truly 
say, e.g. that 'it is absolutely necessary for a house to come-to- 
be when foundations have been laid': for (unless it is always 
necessary for a house to be coming-to-be) we should be faced 
with the consequence that, when foundations have been laid, a 
thing, which need not always be, must always be. No: if its 
coming-to-be is to be 'necessary', it must be 'always' in its 
coming-to-be. For what is 'of necessity' coincides with what is 
'always', since that which 'must be' cannot possibly 'not-be'. 
Hence a thing is eternal if its 'being' is necessary: and if it is 
eternal, its 'being' is necessary. And if, therefore, the 'coming-to- 
be' of a thing is necessary, its 'coming-to-be' is eternal; and if 
eternal, necessary. 

It follows that the coming-to-be of anything, if it is absolutely 
necessary, must be cyclical - i.e. must return upon itself. For 
coming-to-be must either be limited or not limited: and if not 
limited, it must be either rectilinear or cyclical. But the first of 
these last two alternatives is impossible if coming-to-be is to be 



1030 



eternal, because there could not be any 'originative source' 
whatever in an infinite rectilinear sequence, whether its 
members be taken 'downwards' (as future events) or 'upwards' 
(as past events). Yet coming-to-be must have an 'originative 
source' (if it is to be necessary and therefore eternal), nor can it 
be eternal if it is limited. Consequently it must be cyclical. 
Hence the nexus must be reciprocal. By this I mean that the 
necessary occurrence of 'this' involves the necessary occurrence 
of its antecedent: and conversely that, given the antecedent, it 
is also necessary for the consequent to come-to-be. And this 
reciprocal nexus will hold continuously throughout the 
sequence: for it makes no difference whether the reciprocal 
nexus, of which we are speaking, is mediated by two, or by 
many, members. 

It is in circular movement, therefore, and in cyclical coming-to- 
be that the 'absolutely necessary' is to be found. In other words, 
if the coming-to-be of any things is cyclical, it is 'necessary' that 
each of them is coming-to-be and has come-to-be: and if the 
coming-to-be of any things is 'necessary', their coming-to-be is 
cyclical. 

The result we have reached is logically concordant with the 
eternity of circular motion, i.e. the eternity of the revolution of 
the heavens (a fact which approved itself on other and 
independent evidence),' since precisely those movements which 
belong to, and depend upon, this eternal revolution 'come-to-be' 
of necessity, and of necessity 'will be'. For since the revolving 
body is always setting something else in motion, the movement 
of the things it moves must also be circular. Thus, from the 
being of the 'upper revolution' it follows that the sun revolves in 
this determinate manner; and since the sun revolves thus, the 
seasons in consequence come-to-be in a cycle, i.e. return upon 
themselves; and since they come-to-be cyclically, so in their 
turn do the things whose coming-to-be the seasons initiate. 



1031 



Then why do some things manifestly come-to-be in this cyclical 
fashion (as, e.g. showers and air, so that it must rain if there is 
to be a cloud and, conversely, there must be a cloud if it is to 
rain), while men and animals do not 'return upon themselves' 
so that the same individual comes-to-be a second time (for 
though your coming-to-be presupposes your father's, his 
coming-to-be does not presuppose yours)? Why, on the contrary, 
does this coming-to-be seem to constitute a rectilinear 
sequence? 

In discussing this new problem, we must begin by inquiring 
whether all things 'return upon themselves' in a uniform 
manner; or whether, on the contrary, though in some sequences 
what recurs is numerically the same, in other sequences it is 
the same only in species. In consequence of this distinction, it is 
evident that those things, whose 'substance' - that which is 
undergoing the process - is imperishable, will be numerically, as 
well as specifically, the same in their recurrence: for the 
character of the process is determined by the character of that 
which undergoes it. Those things, on the other hand, whose 
'substance' is perish, able (not imperishable) must 'return upon 
themselves' in the sense that what recurs, though specifically 
the same, is not the same numerically. That why, when Water 
comes-to-be from Air and Air from Water, the Air is the same 
'specifically', not 'numerically': and if these too recur 
numerically the same, at any rate this does not happen with 
things whose 'substance' comes-to-be - whose 'substance' is 
such that it is essentially capable of not-being. 



1032 



Aristotle - Meteorology 
[Translated by E. W. Webster] 



Book I 



We have already discussed the first causes of nature, and all 
natural motion, also the stars ordered in the motion of the 
heavens, and the physical element - enumerating and 
specifying them and showing how they change into one 
another - and becoming and perishing in general. There 
remains for consideration a part of this inquiry which all our 
predecessors called meteorology. It is concerned with events 
that are natural, though their order is less perfect than that of 
the first of the elements of bodies. They take place in the region 
nearest to the motion of the stars. Such are the milky way, and 
comets, and the movements of meteors. It studies also all the 
affections we may call common to air and water, and the kinds 
and parts of the earth and the affections of its parts. These 
throw light on the causes of winds and earthquakes and all the 
consequences the motions of these kinds and parts involve. Of 
these things some puzzle us, while others admit of explanation 
in some degree. Further, the inquiry is concerned with the 
falling of thunderbolts and with whirlwinds and fire-winds, and 
further, the recurrent affections produced in these same bodies 
by concretion. When the inquiry into these matters is concluded 
let us consider what account we can give, in accordance with 
the method we have followed, of animals and plants, both 
generally and in detail. When that has been done we may say 



1033 



that the whole of our original undertaking will have been 
carried out. 

After this introduction let us begin by discussing our immediate 
subject. 



We have already laid down that there is one physical element 
which makes up the system of the bodies that move in a circle, 
and besides this four bodies owing their existence to the four 
principles, the motion of these latter bodies being of two kinds: 
either from the centre or to the centre. These four bodies are 
fire, air, water, earth. Fire occupies the highest place among 
them all, earth the lowest, and two elements correspond to 
these in their relation to one another, air being nearest to fire, 
water to earth. The whole world surrounding the earth, then, 
the affections of which are our subject, is made up of these 
bodies. This world necessarily has a certain continuity with the 
upper motions: consequently all its power and order is derived 
from them. (For the originating principle of all motion is the 
first cause. Besides, that clement is eternal and its motion has 
no limit in space, but is always complete; whereas all these 
other bodies have separate regions which limit one another.) So 
we must treat fire and earth and the elements like them as the 
material causes of the events in this world (meaning by material 
what is subject and is affected), but must assign causality in the 
sense of the originating principle of motion to the influence of 
the eternally moving bodies. 



1034 



Let us first recall our original principles and the distinctions 
already drawn and then explain the 'milky way' and comets and 
the other phenomena akin to these. 

Fire, air, water, earth, we assert, originate from one another, and 
each of them exists potentially in each, as all things do that can 
be resolved into a common and ultimate substrate. 

The first difficulty is raised by what is called the air. What are 
we to take its nature to be in the world surrounding the earth? 
And what is its position relatively to the other physical 
elements. (For there is no question as to the relation of the bulk 
of the earth to the size of the bodies which exist around it, since 
astronomical demonstrations have by this time proved to us 
that it is actually far smaller than some individual stars. As for 
the water, it is not observed to exist collectively and separately, 
nor can it do so apart from that volume of it which has its seat 
about the earth: the sea, that is, and rivers, which we can see, 
and any subterranean water that may be hidden from our 
observation.) The question is really about that which lies 
between the earth and the nearest stars. Are we to consider it to 
be one kind of body or more than one? And if more than one, 
how many are there and what are the bounds of their regions? 

We have already described and characterized the first element, 
and explained that the whole world of the upper motions is full 
of that body. 

This is an opinion we are not alone in holding: it appears to be 
an old assumption and one which men have held in the past, 
for the word ether has long been used to denote that element. 
Anaxagoras, it is true, seems to me to think that the word 
means the same as fire. For he thought that the upper regions 
were full of fire, and that men referred to those regions when 



1035 



they spoke of ether. In the latter point he was right, for men 
seem to have assumed that a body that was eternally in motion 
was also divine in nature; and, as such a body was different 
from any of the terrestrial elements, they determined to call it 
'ether'. 

For the um opinions appear in cycles among men not once nor 
twice, but infinitely often. 

Now there are some who maintain that not only the bodies in 
motion but that which contains them is pure fire, and the 
interval between the earth and the stars air: but if they had 
considered what is now satisfactorily established by 
mathematics, they might have given up this puerile opinion. For 
it is altogether childish to suppose that the moving bodies are 
all of them of a small size, because they so to us, looking at 
them from the earth. 

This a matter which we have already discussed in our 
treatment of the upper region, but we may return to the point 
now. 

If the intervals were full of fire and the bodies consisted of fire 
every one of the other elements would long ago have vanished. 

However, they cannot simply be said to be full of air either; for 
even if there were two elements to fill the space between the 
earth and the heavens, the air would far exceed the quantitu 
required to maintain its proper proportion to the other 
elements. For the bulk of the earth (which includes the whole 
volume of water) is infinitesimal in comparison with the whole 
world that surrounds it. Now we find that the excess in volume 
is not proportionately great where water dissolves into air or air 
into fire. Whereas the proportion between any given small 
quantity of water and the air that is generated from it ought to 
hold good between the total amount of air and the total amount 



1036 



of water. Nor does it make any difference if any one denies that 
the elements originate from one another, but asserts that they 
are equal in power. For on this view it is certain amounts of 
each that are equal in power, just as would be the case if they 
actually originated from one another. 

So it is clear that neither air nor fire alone fills the intermediate 
space. 

It remains to explain, after a preliminary discussion of 
difficulties, the relation of the two elements air and fire to the 
position of the first element, and the reason why the stars in 
the upper region impart heat to the earth and its 
neighbourhood. Let us first treat of the air, as we proposed, and 
then go on to these questions. 

Since water is generated from air, and air from water, why are 
clouds not formed in the upper air? They ought to form there 
the more, the further from the earth and the colder that region 
is. For it is neither appreciably near to the heat of the stars, nor 
to the rays relected from the earth. It is these that dissolve any 
formation by their heat and so prevent clouds from forming 
near the earth. For clouds gather at the point where the 
reflected rays disperse in the infinity of space and are lost. To 
explain this we must suppose either that it is not all air which 
water is generated, or, if it is produced from all air alike, that 
what immediately surrounds the earth is not mere air, but a 
sort of vapour, and that its vaporous nature is the reason why it 
condenses back to water again. But if the whole of that vast 
region is vapour, the amount of air and of water will be 
disproportionately great. For the spaces left by the heavenly 
bodies must be filled by some element. This cannot be fire, for 
then all the rest would have been dried up. Consequently, what 
fills it must be air and the water that surrounds the whole 
earth-vapour being water dissolved. 



1037 



After this exposition of the difficulties involved, let us go on to 
lay down the truth, with a view at once to what follows and to 
what has already been said. The upper region as far as the 
moon we affirm to consist of a body distinct both from fire and 
from air, but varying degree of purity and in kind, especially 
towards its limit on the side of the air, and of the world 
surrounding the earth. Now the circular motion of the first 
element and of the bodies it contains dissolves, and inflames by 
its motion, whatever part of the lower world is nearest to it, and 
so generates heat. From another point of view we may look at 
the motion as follows. The body that lies below the circular 
motion of the heavens is, in a sort, matter, and is potentially 
hot, cold, dry, moist, and possessed of whatever other qualities 
are derived from these. But it actually acquires or retains one of 
these in virtue of motion or rest, the cause and principle of 
which has already been explained. So at the centre and round it 
we get earth and water, the heaviest and coldest elements, by 
themselves; round them and contiguous with them, air and 
what we commonly call fire. It is not really fire, for fire is an 
excess of heat and a sort of ebullition; but in reality, of what we 
call air, the part surrounding the earth is moist and warm, 
because it contains both vapour and a dry exhalation from the 
earth. But the next part, above that, is warm and dry. For vapour 
is naturally moist and cold, but the exhalation warm and dry; 
and vapour is potentially like water, the exhalation potentially 
like fire. So we must take the reason why clouds are not formed 
in the upper region to be this: that it is filled not with mere air 
but rather with a sort of fire. 

However, it may well be that the formation of clouds in that 
upper region is also prevented by the circular motion. For the air 
round the earth is necessarily all of it in motion, except that 
which is cut off inside the circumference which makes the 
earth a complete sphere. In the case of winds it is actually 
observable that they originate in marshy districts of the earth; 



1038 



and they do not seem to blow above the level of the highest 
mountains. It is the revolution of the heaven which carries the 
air with it and causes its circular motion, fire being continuous 
with the upper element and air with fire. Thus its motion is a 
second reason why that air is not condensed into water. 

But whenever a particle of air grows heavy, the warmth in it is 
squeezed out into the upper region and it sinks, and other 
particles in turn are carried up together with the fiery 
exhalation. Thus the one region is always full of air and the 
other of fire, and each of them is perpetually in a state of 
change. 

So much to explain why clouds are not formed and why the air 
is not condensed into water, and what account must be given of 
the space between the stars and the earth, and what is the body 
that fills it. 

As for the heat derived from the sun, the right place for a 
special and scientific account of it is in the treatise about sense, 
since heat is an affection of sense, but we may now explain how 
it can be produced by the heavenly bodies which are not 
themselves hot. 

We see that motion is able to dissolve and inflame the air; 
indeed, moving bodies are often actually found to melt. Now the 
sun's motion alone is sufficient to account for the origin of 
terrestrial warmth and heat. For a motion that is to have this 
effect must be rapid and near, and that of the stars is rapid but 
distant, while that of the moon is near but slow, whereas the 
sun's motion combines both conditions in a sufficient degree. 
That most heat should be generated where the sun is present is 
easy to understand if we consider the analogy of terrestrial 
phenomena, for here, too, it is the air that is nearest to a thing 
in rapid motion which is heated most. This is just what we 



1039 



should expect, as it is the nearest air that is most dissolved by 
the motion of a solid body. 

This then is one reason why heat reaches our world. Another is 
that the fire surrounding the air is often scattered by the motion 
of the heavens and driven downwards in spite of itself. 

Shooting-stars further suffix to prove that the celestial sphere is 
not hot or fiery: for they do not occur in that upper region but 
below: yet the more and the faster a thing moves, the more apt 
it is to take fire. Besides, the sun, which most of all the stars is 
considered to be hot, is really white and not fiery in colour. 



Having determined these principles let us explain the cause of 
the appearance in the sky of burning flames and of shooting- 
stars, and of 'torches', and 'goats', as some people call them. All 
these phenomena are one and the same thing, and are due to 
the same cause, the difference between them being one of 
degree. 

The explanation of these and many other phenomena is this. 
When the sun warms the earth the evaporation which takes 
place is necessarily of two kinds, not of one only as some think. 
One kind is rather of the nature of vapour, the other of the 
nature of a windy exhalation. That which rises from the 
moisture contained in the earth and on its surface is vapour, 
while that rising from the earth itself, which is dry, is like 
smoke. Of these the windy exhalation, being warm, rises above 
the moister vapour, which is heavy and sinks below the other. 
Hence the world surrounding the earth is ordered as follows. 
First below the circular motion comes the warm and dry 



1040 



element, which we call fire, for there is no word fully adequate 
to every state of the fumid evaporation: but we must use this 
terminology since this element is the most inflammable of all 
bodies. Below this comes air. We must think of what we just 
called fire as being spread round the terrestrial sphere on the 
outside like a kind of fuel, so that a little motion often makes it 
burst into flame just as smoke does: for flame is the ebullition 
of a dry exhalation. So whenever the circular motion stirs this 
stuff up in any way, it catches fire at the point at which it is 
most inflammable. The result differs according to the 
disposition and quantity of the combustible material. If this is 
broad and long, we often see a flame burning as in a field of 
stubble: if it burns lengthwise only, we see what are called 
'torches' and 'goats' and shooting-stars. Now when the 
inflammable material is longer than it is broad sometimes it 
seems to throw off sparks as it burns. (This happens because 
matter catches fire at the sides in small portions but 
continuously with the main body.) Then it is called a 'goat'. 
When this does not happen it is a 'torch'. But if the whole 
length of the exhalation is scattered in small parts and in many 
directions and in breadth and depth alike, we get what are 
called shooting-stars. 

The cause of these shooting-stars is sometimes the motion 
which ignites the exhalation. At other times the air is 
condensed by cold and squeezes out and ejects the hot element; 
making their motion look more like that of a thing thrown than 
like a running fire. For the question might be raised whether the 
'shooting' of a 'star' is the same thing as when you put an 
exhalation below a lamp and it lights the lower lamp from the 
flame above. For here too the flame passes wonderfully quickly 
and looks like a thing thrown, and not as if one thing after 
another caught fire. Or is a 'star' when it 'shoots' a single body 
that is thrown? Apparently both cases occur: sometimes it is 
like the flame from the lamp and sometimes bodies are 



1041 



projected by being squeezed out (like fruit stones from one's 
fingers) and so are seen to fall into the sea and on the dry land, 
both by night and by day when the sky is clear. They are thrown 
downwards because the condensation which propels them 
inclines downwards. Thunderbolts fall downwards for the same 
reason: their origin is never combustion but ejection under 
pressure, since naturally all heat tends upwards. 

When the phenomenon is formed in the upper region it is due 
to the combustion of the exhalation. When it takes place at a 
lower level it is due to the ejection of the exhalation by the 
condensing and cooling of the moister evaporation: for this 
latter as it condenses and inclines downward contracts, and 
thrusts out the hot element and causes it to be thrown 
downwards. The motion is upwards or downwards or sideways 
according to the way in which the evaporation lies, and its 
disposition in respect of breadth and depth. In most cases the 
direction is sideways because two motions are involved, a 
compulsory motion downwards and a natural motion upwards, 
and under these circumstances an object always moves 
obliquely. Hence the motion of 'shooting-stars' is generally 
oblique. 

So the material cause of all these phenomena is the exhalation, 
the efficient cause sometimes the upper motion, sometimes the 
contraction and condensation of the air. Further, all these 
things happen below the moon. This is shown by their apparent 
speed, which is equal to that of things thrown by us; for it is 
because they are close to us, that these latter seem far to exceed 
in speed the stars, the sun, and the moon. 



1042 



Sometimes on a fine night we see a variety of appearances that 
form in the sky: 'chasms' for instance and 'trenches' and blood- 
red colours. These, too, have the same cause. For we have seen 
that the upper air condenses into an inflammable condition and 
that the combustion sometimes takes on the appearance of a 
burning flame, sometimes that of moving torches and stars. So 
it is not surprising that this same air when condensing should 
assume a variety of colours. For a weak light shining through a 
dense air, and the air when it acts as a mirror, will cause all 
kinds of colours to appear, but especially crimson and purple. 
For these colours generally appear when fire-colour and white 
are combined by superposition. Thus on a hot day, or through a 
smoky, medium, the stars when they rise and set look crimson. 
The light will also create colours by reflection when the mirror 
is such as to reflect colour only and not shape. 

These appearances do not persist long, because the 
condensation of the air is transient. 

'Chasms' get their appearance of depth from light breaking out 
of a dark blue or black mass of air. When the process of 
condensation goes further in such a case we often find 'torches' 
ejected. When the 'chasm' contracts it presents the appearance 
of a 'trench'. 

In general, white in contrast with black creates a variety of 
colours; like flame, for instance, through a medium of smoke. 
But by day the sun obscures them, and, with the exception of 
crimson, the colours are not seen at night because they are 
dark. 

These then must be taken to be the causes of 'shooting-stars' 
and the phenomena of combustion and also of the other 
transient appearances of this kind. 



1043 



Let us go on to explain the nature of comets and the 'milky 
way', after a preliminary discussion of the views of others. 

Anaxagoras and Democritus declare that comets are a 
conjunction of the planets approaching one another and so 
appearing to touch one another. 

Some of the Italians called Pythagoreans say that the comet is 
one of the planets, but that it appears at great intervals of time 
and only rises a little above the horizon. This is the case with 
Mercury too; because it only rises a little above the horizon it 
often fails to be seen and consequently appears at great 
intervals of time. 

A view like theirs was also expressed by Hippocrates of Chios 
and his pupil Aeschylus. Only they say that the tail does not 
belong to the comet iself, but is occasionally assumed by it on 
its course in certain situations, when our sight is reflected to 
the sun from the moisture attracted by the comet. It appears at 
greater intervals than the other stars because it is slowest to get 
clear of the sun and has been left behind by the sun to the 
extent of the whole of its circle before it reappears at the same 
point. It gets clear of the sun both towards the north and 
towards the south. In the space between the tropics it does not 
draw water to itself because that region is dried up by the sun 
on its course. When it moves towards the south it has no lack of 
the necessary moisture, but because the segment of its circle 
which is above the horizon is small, and that below it many 
times as large, it is impossible for the sun to be reflected to our 
sight, either when it approaches the southern tropic, or at the 
summer solstice. Hence in these regions it does not develop a 



1044 



tail at all. But when it is visible in the north it assumes a tail 
because the arc above the horizon is large and that below it 
small. For under these circumstances there is nothing to 
prevent our vision from being reflected to the sun. 

These views involve impossibilities, some of which are common 
to all of them, while others are peculiar to some only. 

This is the case, first, with those who say that the comet is one 
of the planets. For all the planets appear in the circle of the 
zodiac, whereas many comets have been seen outside that 
circle. Again more comets than one have often appeared 
simultaneously. Besides, if their tail is due to reflection, as 
Aeschylus and Hippocrates say, this planet ought sometimes to 
be visible without a tail since, as they it does not possess a tail 
in every place in which it appears. But, as a matter of fact, no 
planet has been observed besides the five. And all of them are 
often visible above the horizon together at the same time. 
Further, comets are often found to appear, as well when all the 
planets are visible as when some are not, but are obscured by 
the neighbourhood of the sun. Moreover the statement that a 
comet only appears in the north, with the sun at the summer 
solstice, is not true either. The great comet which appeared at 
the time of the earthquake in Achaea and the tidal wave rose 
due west; and many have been known to appear in the south. 
Again in the archonship of Euclees, son of Molon, at Athens 
there appeared a comet in the north in the month Gamelion, 
the sun being about the winter solstice. Yet they themselves 
admit that reflection over so great a space is an impossibility. 

An objection that tells equally against those who hold this 
theory and those who say that comets are a coalescence of the 
planets is, first, the fact that some of the fixed stars too get a 
tail. For this we must not only accept the authority of the 
Egyptians who assert it, but we have ourselves observed the 



1045 



fact. For a star in the thigh of the Dog had a tail, though a faint 
one. If you fixed your sight on it its light was dim, but if you just 
glanced at it, it appeared brighter. Besides, all the comets that 
have been seen in our day have vanished without setting, 
gradually fading away above the horizon; and they have not left 
behind them either one or more stars. For instance the great 
comet we mentioned before appeared to the west in winter in 
frosty weather when the sky was clear, in the archonship of 
Asteius. On the first day it set before the sun and was then not 
seen. On the next day it was seen, being ever so little behind the 
sun and immediately setting. But its light extended over a third 
part of the sky like a leap, so that people called it a 'path'. This 
comet receded as far as Orion's belt and there dissolved. 
Democritus however, insists upon the truth of his view and 
affirms that certain stars have been seen when comets dissolve. 
But on his theory this ought not to occur occasionally but 
always. Besides, the Egyptians affirm that conjunctions of the 
planets with one another, and with the fixed stars, take place, 
and we have ourselves observed Jupiter coinciding with one of 
the stars in the Twins and hiding it, and yet no comet was 
formed. Further, we can also give a rational proof of our point. It 
is true that some stars seem to be bigger than others, yet each 
one by itself looks indivisible. Consequently, just as, if they 
really had been indivisible, their conjunction could not have 
created any greater magnitude, so now that they are not in fact 
indivisible but look as if they were, their conjunction will not 
make them look any bigger. 

Enough has been said, without further argument, to show that 
the causes brought forward to explain comets are false. 



1046 



We consider a satisfactory explanation of phenomena 
inaccessible to observation to have been given when our 
account of them is free from impossibilities. The observations 
before us suggest the following account of the phenomena we 
are now considering. We know that the dry and warm 
exhalation is the outermost part of the terrestrial world which 
falls below the circular motion. It, and a great part of the air that 
is continuous with it below, is carried round the earth by the 
motion of the circular revolution. In the course of this motion it 
often ignites wherever it may happen to be of the right 
consistency, and this we maintain to be the cause of the 
'shooting' of scattered 'stars'. We may say, then, that a comet is 
formed when the upper motion introduces into a gathering of 
this kind a fiery principle not of such excessive strength as to 
burn up much of the material quickly, nor so weak as soon to be 
extinguished, but stronger and capable of burning up much 
material, and when exhalation of the right consistency rises 
from below and meets it. The kind of comet varies according to 
the shape which the exhalation happens to take. If it is diffused 
equally on every side the star is said to be fringed, if it stretches 
out in one direction it is called bearded. We have seen that 
when a fiery principle of this kind moves we seem to have a 
shooting-star: similarly when it stands still we seem to have a 
star standing still. We may compare these phenomena to a heap 
or mass of chaff into which a torch is thrust, or a spark thrown. 
That is what a shooting-star is like. The fuel is so inflammable 
that the fire runs through it quickly in a line. Now if this fire 
were to persist instead of running through the fuel and 
perishing away, its course through the fuel would stop at the 
point where the latter was densest, and then the whole might 
begin to move. Such is a comet - like a shooting-star that 
contains its beginning and end in itself. 



1047 



When the matter begins to gather in the lower region 
independently the comet appears by itself. But when the 
exhalation is constituted by one of the fixed stars or the 
planets, owing to their motion, one of them becomes a comet. 
The fringe is not close to the stars themselves. Just as haloes 
appear to follow the sun and the moon as they move, and 
encircle them, when the air is dense enough for them to form 
along under the sun's course, so too the fringe. It stands in the 
relation of a halo to the stars, except that the colour of the halo 
is due to reflection, whereas in the case of comets the colour is 
something that appears actually on them. 

Now when this matter gathers in relation to a star the comet 
necessarily appears to follow the same course as the star. But 
when the comet is formed independently it falls behind the 
motion of the universe, like the rest of the terrestrial world. It is 
this fact, that a comet often forms independently, indeed 
oftener than round one of the regular stars, that makes it 
impossible to maintain that a comet is a sort of reflection, not 
indeed, as Hippocrates and his school say, to the sun, but to the 
very star it is alleged to accompany - in fact, a kind of halo in 
the pure fuel of fire. 

As for the halo we shall explain its cause later. 

The fact that comets when frequent foreshadow wind and 
drought must be taken as an indication of their fiery 
constitution. For their origin is plainly due to the plentiful 
supply of that secretion. Hence the air is necessarily drier and 
the moist evaporation is so dissolved and dissipated by the 
quantity of the hot exhalation as not readily to condense into 
water. - But this phenomenon too shall be explained more 
clearly later when the time comes to speak of the winds. - So 
when there are many comets and they are dense, it is as we say, 
and the years are clearly dry and windy. When they are fewer 



1048 



and fainter this effect does not appear in the same degree, 
though as a rule the is found to be excessive either in duration 
or strength. For instance when the stone at Aegospotami fell out 
of the air - it had been carried up by a wind and fell down in the 
daytime - then too a comet happened to have appeared in the 
west. And at the time of the great comet the winter was dry and 
north winds prevailed, and the wave was due to an opposition 
of winds. For in the gulf a north wind blew and outside it a 
violent south wind. Again in the archonship of Nicomachus a 
comet appeared for a few days about the equinoctial circle (this 
one had not risen in the west), and simultaneously with it there 
happened the storm at Corinth. 

That there are few comets and that they appear rarely and 
outside the tropic circles more than within them is due to the 
motion of the sun and the stars. For this motion does not only 
cause the hot principle to be secreted but also dissolves it when 
it is gathering. But the chief reason is that most of this stuff 
collects in the region of the milky way. 



8 

Let us now explain the origin, cause, and nature of the milky 
way. And here too let us begin by discussing the statements of 
others on the subject. 

(1) Of the so-called Pythagoreans some say that this is the path 
of one of the stars that fell from heaven at the time of 
Phaethon's downfall. Others say that the sun used once to move 
in this circle and that this region was scorched or met with 
some other affection of this kind, because of the sun and its 
motion. 



1049 



But it is absurd not to see that if this were the reason the circle 
of the Zodiac ought to be affected in the same way, and indeed 
more so than that of the milky way, since not the sun only but 
all the planets move in it. We can see the whole of this circle 
(half of it being visible at any time of the night), but it shows no 
signs of any such affection except where a part of it touches the 
circle of the milky way. 

(2) Anaxagoras, Democritus, and their schools say that the milky 
way is the light of certain stars. For, they say, when the sun 
passes below the earth some of the stars are hidden from it. 
Now the light of those on which the sun shines is invisible, 
being obscured by the of the sun. But the milky way is the 
peculiar light of those stars which are shaded by the earth from 
the sun's rays. 

This, too, is obviously impossible. The milky way is always 
unchanged and among the same constellations (for it is clearly 
a greatest circle), whereas, since the sun does not remain in the 
same place, what is hidden from it differs at different times. 
Consequently with the change of the sun's position the milky 
way ought to change its position too: but we find that this does 
not happen. Besides, if astronomical demonstrations are correct 
and the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the 
distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than 
that of the sun (just as the sun is further from the earth than 
the moon), then the cone made by the rays of the sun would 
terminate at no great distance from the earth, and the shadow 
of the earth (what we call night) would not reach the stars. On 
the contrary, the sun shines on all the stars and the earth 
screens none of them. 

(3) There is a third theory about the milky way. Some say that it 
is a reflection of our sight to the sun, just as they say that the 
comet is. 



1050 



But this too is impossible. For if the eye and the mirror and the 
whole of the object were severally at rest, then the same part of 
the image would appear at the same point in the mirror. But if 
the mirror and the object move, keeping the same distance from 
the eye which is at rest, but at different rates of speed and so 
not always at the same interval from one another, then it is 
impossible for the same image always to appear in the same 
part of the mirror. Now the constellations included in the circle 
of the milky way move; and so does the sun, the object to which 
our sight is reflected; but we stand still. And the distance of 
those two from us is constant and uniform, but their distance 
from one another varies. For the Dolphin sometimes rises at 
midnight, sometimes in the morning. But in each case the same 
parts of the milky way are found near it. But if it were a 
reflection and not a genuine affection of these this ought not to 
be the case. 

Again, we can see the milky way reflected at night in water and 
similar mirrors. But under these circumstances it is impossible 
for our sight to be reflected to the sun. 

These considerations show that the milky way is not the path of 
one of the planets, nor the light of imperceptible stars, nor a 
reflection. And those are the chief theories handed down by 
others hitherto. 

Let us recall our fundamental principle and then explain our 
views. We have already laid down that the outermost part of 
what is called the air is potentially fire and that therefore when 
the air is dissolved by motion, there is separated off a kind of 
matter - and of this matter we assert that comets consist. We 
must suppose that what happens is the same as in the case of 
the comets when the matter does not form independently but is 
formed by one of the fixed stars or the planets. Then these stars 
appear to be fringed, because matter of this kind follows their 



1051 



course. In the same way, a certain kind of matter follows the 
sun, and we explain the halo as a reflection from it when the air 
is of the right constitution. Now we must assume that what 
happens in the case of the stars severally happens in the case of 
the whole of the heavens and all the upper motion. For it is 
natural to suppose that, if the motion of a single star excites a 
flame, that of all the stars should have a similar result, and 
especially in that region in which the stars are biggest and most 
numerous and nearest to one another. Now the circle of the 
zodiac dissolves this kind of matter because of the motion of 
the sun and the planets, and for this reason most comets are 
found outside the tropic circles. Again, no fringe appears round 
the sun or moon: for they dissolve such matter too quickly to 
admit of its formation. But this circle in which the milky way 
appears to our sight is the greatest circle, and its position is 
such that it extends far outside the tropic circles. Besides the 
region is full of the biggest and brightest constellations and also 
of what called 'scattered' stars (you have only to look to see this 
clearly). So for these reasons all this matter is continually and 
ceaselessly collecting there. A proof of the theory is this: In the 
circle itself the light is stronger in that half where the milky way 
is divided, and in it the constellations are more numerous and 
closer to one another than in the other half; which shows that 
the cause of the light is the motion of the constellations and 
nothing else. For if it is found in the circle in which there are 
most constellations and at that point in the circle at which they 
are densest and contain the biggest and the most stars, it is 
natural to suppose that they are the true cause of the affection 
in question. The circle and the constellations in it may be seen 
in the diagram. The so-called 'scattered' stars it is not possible 
to set down in the same way on the sphere because none of 
them have an evident permanent position; but if you look up to 
the sky the point is clear. For in this circle alone are the 
intervals full of these stars: in the other circles there are 



1052 



obvious gaps. Hence if we accept the cause assigned for the 
appearance of comets as plausible we must assume that the 
same kind of thing holds good of the milky way. For the fringe 
which in the former case is an affection of a single star here 
forms in the same way in relation to a whole circle. So if we are 
to define the milky way we may call it 'a fringe attaching to the 
greatest circle, and due to the matter secreted'. This, as we said 
before, explains why there are few comets and why they appear 
rarely; it is because at each revolution of the heavens this 
matter has always been and is always being separated off and 
gathered into this region. 

We have now explained the phenomena that occur in that part 
of the terrestrial world which is continuous with the motions of 
the heavens, namely, shooting-stars and the burning flame, 
comets and the milky way, these being the chief affections that 
appear in that region. 



Let us go on to treat of the region which follows next in order 
after this and which immediately surrounds the earth. It is the 
region common to water and air, and the processes attending 
the formation of water above take place in it. We must consider 
the principles and causes of all these phenomena too as before. 
The efficient and chief and first cause is the circle in which the 
sun moves. For the sun as it approaches or recedes, obviously 
causes dissipation and condensation and so gives rise to 
generation and destruction. Now the earth remains but the 
moisture surrounding it is made to evaporate by the sun's rays 
and the other heat from above, and rises. But when the heat 
which was raising it leaves it, in part dispersing to the higher 



1053 



region, in part quenched through rising so far into the upper air, 
then the vapour cools because its heat is gone and because the 
place is cold, and condenses again and turns from air into 
water. And after the water has formed it falls down again to the 
earth. 

The exhalation of water is vapour: air condensing into water is 
cloud. Mist is what is left over when a cloud condenses into 
water, and is therefore rather a sign of fine weather than of rain; 
for mist might be called a barren cloud. So we get a circular 
process that follows the course of the sun. For according as the 
sun moves to this side or that, the moisture in this process rises 
or falls. We must think of it as a river flowing up and down in a 
circle and made up partly of air, partly of water. When the sun is 
near, the stream of vapour flows upwards; when it recedes, the 
stream of water flows down: and the order of sequence, at all 
events, in this process always remains the same. So if 'Oceanus' 
had some secret meaning in early writers, perhaps they may 
have meant this river that flows in a circle about the earth. 

So the moisture is always raised by the heat and descends to 
the earth again when it gets cold. These processes and, in some 
cases, their varieties are distinguished by special names. When 
the water falls in small drops it is called a drizzle; when the 
drops are larger it is rain. 



10 

Some of the vapour that is formed by day does not rise high 
because the ratio of the fire that is raising it to the water that is 
being raised is small. When this cools and descends at night it is 
called dew and hoar-frost. When the vapour is frozen before it 
has condensed to water again it is hoar-frost; and this appears 



1054 



in winter and is commoner in cold places. It is dew when the 
vapour has condensed into water and the heat is not so great as 
to dry up the moisture that has been raised nor the cold 
sufficient (owing to the warmth of the climate or season) for the 
vapour itself to freeze. For dew is more commonly found when 
the season or the place is warm, whereas the opposite, as has 
been said, is the case with hoar-frost. For obviously vapour is 
warmer than water, having still the fire that raised it: 
consequently more cold is needed to freeze it. 

Both dew and hoar-frost are found when the sky is clear and 
there is no wind. For the vapour could not be raised unless the 
sky were clear, and if a wind were blowing it could not 
condense. 

The fact that hoar-frost is not found on mountains contributes 
to prove that these phenomena occur because the vapour does 
not rise high. One reason for this is that it rises from hollow and 
watery places, so that the heat that is raising it, bearing as it 
were too heavy a burden cannot lift it to a great height but soon 
lets it fall again. A second reason is that the motion of the air is 
more pronounced at a height, and this dissolves a gathering of 
this kind. 

Everywhere, except in Pontus, dew is found with south winds 
and not with north winds. There the opposite is the case and it 
is found with north winds and not with south. The reason is the 
same as that which explains why dew is found in warm 
weather and not in cold. For the south wind brings warm, and 
the north, wintry weather. For the north wind is cold and so 
quenches the heat of the evaporation. But in Pontus the south 
wind does not bring warmth enough to cause evaporation, 
whereas the coldness of the north wind concentrates the heat 
by a sort of recoil, so that there is more evaporation and not 
less. This is a thing which we can often observe in other places 



1055 



too. Wells, for instance, give off more vapour in a north than in a 
south wind. Only the north winds quench the heat before any 
considerable quantity of vapour has gathered, while in a south 
wind the evaporation is allowed to accumulate. 

Water, once formed, does not freeze on the surface of the earth, 
in the way that it does in the region of the clouds. 



11 

From the latter there fall three bodies condensed by cold, 
namely rain, snow, hail. Two of these correspond to the 
phenomena on the lower level and are due to the same causes, 
differing from them only in degree and quantity. 

Snow and hoar-frost are one and the same thing, and so are rain 
and dew: only there is a great deal of the former and little of the 
latter. For rain is due to the cooling of a great amount of vapour, 
for the region from which and the time during which the 
vapour is collected are considerable. But of dew there is little: 
for the vapour collects for it in a single day and from a small 
area, as its quick formation and scanty quantity show. 

The relation of hoar-frost and snow is the same: when cloud 
freezes there is snow, when vapour freezes there is hoar-frost. 
Hence snow is a sign of a cold season or country. For a great 
deal of heat is still present and unless the cold were 
overpowering it the cloud would not freeze. For there still 
survives in it a great deal of the heat which caused the moisture 
to rise as vapour from the earth. 

Hail on the other hand is found in the upper region, but the 
corresponding phenomenon in the vaporous region near the 



1056 



earth is lacking. For, as we said, to snow in the upper region 
corresponds hoar-frost in the lower, and to rain in the upper 
region, dew in the lower. But there is nothing here to correspond 
to hail in the upper region. Why this is so will be clear when we 
have explained the nature of hail. 



12 

But we must go on to collect the facts bearing on the origin of it, 
both those which raise no difficulties and those which seem 
paradoxical. 

Hail is ice, and water freezes in winter; yet hailstorms occur 
chiefly in spring and autumn and less often in the late summer, 
but rarely in winter and then only when the cold is less intense. 
And in general hailstorms occur in warmer, and snow in colder 
places. Again, there is a difficulty about water freezing in the 
upper region. It cannot have frozen before becoming water: and 
water cannot remain suspended in the air for any space of time. 
Nor can we say that the case is like that of particles of moisture 
which are carried up owing to their small size and rest on the 
iar (the water swimming on the air just as small particles of 
earth and gold often swim on water). In that case large drops 
are formed by the union of many small, and so fall down. This 
cannot take place in the case of hail, since solid bodies cannot 
coalesce like liquid ones. Clearly then drops of that size were 
suspended in the air or else they could not have been so large 
when frozen. 

Some think that the cause and origin of hail is this. The cloud is 
thrust up into the upper atmosphere, which is colder because 
the reflection of the sun's rays from the earth ceases there, and 
upon its arrival there the water freezes. They think that this 



1057 



explains why hailstorms are commoner in summer and in 
warm countries; the heat is greater and it thrusts the clouds 
further up from the earth. But the fact is that hail does not 
occur at all at a great height: yet it ought to do so, on their 
theory, just as we see that snow falls most on high mountains. 
Again clouds have often been observed moving with a great 
noise close to the earth, terrifying those who heard and saw 
them as portents of some catastrophe. Sometimes, too, when 
such clouds have been seen, without any noise, there follows a 
violent hailstorm, and the stones are of incredible size, and 
angular in shape. This shows that they have not been falling for 
long and that they were frozen near to the earth, and not as 
that theory would have it. Moreover, where the hailstones are 
large, the cause of their freezing must be present in the highest 
degree: for hail is ice as every one can see. Now those hailstones 
are large which are angular in shape. And this shows that they 
froze close to the earth, for those that fall far are worn away by 
the length of their fall and become round and smaller in size. 

It clearly follows that the congelation does not take place 
because the cloud is thrust up into the cold upper region. 

Now we see that warm and cold react upon one another by 
recoil. Hence in warm weather the lower parts of the earth are 
cold and in a frost they are warm. The same thing, we must 
suppose, happens in the air, so that in the warmer seasons the 
cold is concentrated by the surrounding heat and causes the 
cloud to go over into water suddenly. (For this reason rain-drops 
are much larger on warm days than in winter, and showers 
more violent. A shower is said to be more violent in proportion 
as the water comes down in a body, and this happens when the 
condensation takes place quickly, - though this is just the 
opposite of what Anaxagoras says. He says that this happens 
when the cloud has risen into the cold air; whereas we say that 
it happens when the cloud has descended into the warm air, 



1058 



and that the more the further the cloud has descended). But 
when the cold has been concentrated within still more by the 
outer heat, it freezes the water it has formed and there is hail. 
We get hail when the process of freezing is quicker than the 
descent of the water. For if the water falls in a certain time and 
the cold is sufficient to freeze it in less, there is no difficulty 
about its having frozen in the air, provided that the freezing 
takes place in a shorter time than its fall. The nearer to the 
earth, and the more suddenly, this process takes place, the more 
violent is the rain that results and the larger the raindrops and 
the hailstones because of the shortness of their fall. For the 
same reason large raindrops do not fall thickly. Hail is rarer in 
summer than in spring and autumn, though commoner than in 
winter, because the air is drier in summer, whereas in spring it 
is still moist, and in autumn it is beginning to grow moist. It is 
for the same reason that hailstorms sometimes occur in the late 
summer as we have said. 

The fact that the water has previously been warmed contributes 
to its freezing quickly: for so it cools sooner. Hence many 
people, when they want to cool hot water quickly, begin by 
putting it in the sun. So the inhabitants of Pontus when they 
encamp on the ice to fish (they cut a hole in the ice and then 
fish) pour warm water round their reeds that it may freeze the 
quicker, for they use the ice like lead to fix the reeds. Now it is 
in hot countries and seasons that the water which forms soon 
grows warm. 

It is for the same reason that rain falls in summer and not in 
winter in Arabia and Ethiopia too, and that in torrents and 
repeatedly on the same day. For the concentration or recoil due 
to the extreme heat of the country cools the clouds quickly. 

So much for an account of the nature and causes of rain, dew, 
snow, hoar-frost, and hail. 



1059 



13 

Let us explain the nature of winds, and all windy vapours, also 
of rivers and of the sea. But here, too, we must first discuss the 
difficulties involved: for, as in other matters, so in this no theory 
has been handed down to us that the most ordinary man could 
not have thought of. 

Some say that what is called air, when it is in motion and flows, 
is wind, and that this same air when it condenses again 
becomes cloud and water, implying that the nature of wind and 
water is the same. So they define wind as a motion of the air. 
Hence some, wishing to say a clever thing, assert that all the 
winds are one wind, because the air that moves is in fact all of it 
one and the same; they maintain that the winds appear to 
differ owing to the region from which the air may happen to 
flow on each occasion, but really do not differ at all. This is just 
like thinking that all rivers are one and the same river, and the 
ordinary unscientific view is better than a scientific theory like 
this. If all rivers flow from one source, and the same is true in 
the case of the winds, there might be some truth in this theory; 
but if it is no more true in the one case than in the other, this 
ingenious idea is plainly false. What requires investigation is 
this: the nature of wind and how it originates, its efficient cause 
and whence they derive their source; whether one ought to 
think of the wind as issuing from a sort of vessel and flowing 
until the vessel is empty, as if let out of a wineskin, or, as 
painters represent the winds, as drawing their source from 
themselves. 

We find analogous views about the origin of rivers. It is thought 
that the water is raised by the sun and descends in rain and 



1060 



gathers below the earth and so flows from a great reservoir, all 
the rivers from one, or each from a different one. No water at all 
is generated, but the volume of the rivers consists of the water 
that is gathered into such reservoirs in winter. Hence rivers are 
always fuller in winter than in summer, and some are perennial, 
others not. Rivers are perennial where the reservoir is large and 
so enough water has collected in it to last out and not be used 
up before the winter rain returns. Where the reservoirs are 
smaller there is less water in the rivers, and they are dried up 
and their vessel empty before the fresh rain comes on. 

But if any one will picture to himself a reservoir adequate to the 
water that is continuously flowing day by day, and consider the 
amount of the water, it is obvious that a receptacle that is to 
contain all the water that flows in the year would be larger than 
the earth, or, at any rate, not much smaller. 

Though it is evident that many reservoirs of this kind do exist in 
many parts of the earth, yet it is unreasonable for any one to 
refuse to admit that air becomes water in the earth for the same 
reason as it does above it. If the cold causes the vaporous air to 
condense into water above the earth we must suppose the cold 
in the earth to produce this same effect, and recognize that 
there not only exists in it and flows out of it actually formed 
water, but that water is continually forming in it too. 

Again, even in the case of the water that is not being formed 
from day to day but exists as such, we must not suppose as 
some do that rivers have their source in definite subterranean 
lakes. On the contrary, just as above the earth small drops form 
and these join others, till finally the water descends in a body as 
rain, so too we must suppose that in the earth the water at first 
trickles together little by little, and that the sources of the rivers 
drip, as it were, out of the earth and then unite. This is proved 
by facts. When men construct an aqueduct they collect the 



1061 



water in pipes and trenches, as if the earth in the higher ground 
were sweating the water out. Hence, too, the head-waters of 
rivers are found to flow from mountains, and from the greatest 
mountains there flow the most numerous and greatest rivers. 
Again, most springs are in the neighbourhood of mountains and 
of high ground, whereas if we except rivers, water rarely 
appears in the plains. For mountains and high ground, 
suspended over the country like a saturated sponge, make the 
water ooze out and trickle together in minute quantities but in 
many places. They receive a great deal of water falling as rain 
(for it makes no difference whether a spongy receptacle is 
concave and turned up or convex and turned down: in either 
case it will contain the same volume of matter) and, they also 
cool the vapour that rises and condense it back into water. 

Hence, as we said, we find that the greatest rivers flow from the 
greatest mountains. This can be seen by looking at itineraries: 
what is recorded in them consists either of things which the 
writer has seen himself or of such as he has compiled after 
inquiry from those who have seen them. 

In Asia we find that the most numerous and greatest rivers flow 
from the mountain called Parnassus, admittedly the greatest of 
all mountains towards the south-east. When you have crossed it 
you see the outer ocean, the further limit of which is unknown 
to the dwellers in our world. Besides other rivers there flow 
from it the Bactrus, the Choaspes, the Araxes: from the last a 
branch separates off and flows into lake Maeotis as the Tanais. 
From it, too, flows the Indus, the volume of whose stream is 
greatest of all rivers. From the Caucasus flows the Phasis, and 
very many other great rivers besides. Now the Caucasus is the 
greatest of the mountains that lie to the northeast, both as 
regards its extent and its height. A proof of its height is the fact 
that it can be seen from the so-called 'deeps' and from the 
entrance to the lake. Again, the sun shines on its peaks for a 



1062 



third part of the night before sunrise and again after sunset. Its 
extent is proved by the fact that thought contains many 
inhabitable regions which are occupied by many nations and in 
which there are said to be great lakes, yet they say that all these 
regions are visible up to the last peak. From Pyrene (this is a 
mountain towards the west in Celtice) there flow the Istrus and 
the Tartessus. The latter flows outside the pillars, while the 
Istrus flows through all Europe into the Euxine. Most of the 
remaining rivers flow northwards from the Hercynian 
mountains, which are the greatest in height and extent about 
that region. In the extreme north, beyond furthest Scythia, are 
the mountains called Rhipae. The stories about their size are 
altogether too fabulous: however, they say that the most and 
(after the Istrus) the greatest rivers flow from them. So, too, in 
Libya there flow from the Aethiopian mountains the Aegon and 
the Nyses; and from the so-called Silver Mountain the two 
greatest of named rivers, the river called Chremetes that flows 
into the outer ocean, and the main source of the Nile. Of the 
rivers in the Greek world, the Achelous flows from Pindus, the 
Inachus from the same mountain; the Strymon, the Nestus, and 
the Hebrus all three from Scombrus; many rivers, too, flow from 
Rhodope. 

All other rivers would be found to flow in the same way, but we 
have mentioned these as examples. Even where rivers flow 
from marshes, the marshes in almost every case are found to lie 
below mountains or gradually rising ground. 

It is clear then that we must not suppose rivers to originate 
from definite reservoirs: for the whole earth, we might almost 
say, would not be sufficient (any more than the region of the 
clouds would be) if we were to suppose that they were fed by 
actually existing water only and it were not the case that as 
some water passed out of existence some more came into 
existence, but rivers always drew their stream from an existing 



1063 



store. Secondly, the fact that rivers rise at the foot of mountains 
proves that a place transmits the water it contains by gradual 
percolation of many drops, little by little, and that this is how 
the sources of rivers originate. However, there is nothing 
impossible about the existence of such places containing a 
quantity of water like lakes: only they cannot be big enough to 
produce the supposed effect. To think that they are is just as 
absurd as if one were to suppose that rivers drew all their water 
from the sources we see (for most rivers do flow from springs). 
So it is no more reasonable to suppose those lakes to contain 
the whole volume of water than these springs. 

That there exist such chasms and cavities in the earth we are 
taught by the rivers that are swallowed up. They are found in 
many parts of the earth: in the Peloponnesus, for instance, there 
are many such rivers in Arcadia. The reason is that Arcadia is 
mountainous and there are no channels from its valleys to the 
sea. So these places get full of water, and this, having no outlet, 
under the pressure of the water that is added above, finds a way 
out for itself underground. In Greece this kind of thing happens 
on quite a small scale, but the lake at the foot of the Caucasus, 
which the inhabitants of these parts call a sea, is considerable. 
Many great rivers fall into it and it has no visible outlet but 
issues below the earth off the land of the Coraxi about the so- 
called 'deeps of Pontus'. This is a place of unfathomable depth 
in the sea: at any rate no one has yet been able to find bottom 
there by sounding. At this spot, about three hundred stadia 
from land, there comes up sweet water over a large area, not all 
of it together but in three places. And in Liguria a river equal in 
size to the Rhodanus is swallowed up and appears again 
elsewhere: the Rhodanus being a navigable river. 



1064 



14 

The same parts of the earth are not always moist or dry, but 
they change according as rivers come into existence and dry up. 
And so the relation of land to sea changes too and a place does 
not always remain land or sea throughout all time, but where 
there was dry land there comes to be sea, and where there is 
now sea, there one day comes to be dry land. But we must 
suppose these changes to follow some order and cycle. The 
principle and cause of these changes is that the interior of the 
earth grows and decays, like the bodies of plants and animals. 
Only in the case of these latter the process does not go on by 
parts, but each of them necessarily grows or decays as a whole, 
whereas it does go on by parts in the case of the earth. Here the 
causes are cold and heat, which increase and diminish on 
account of the sun and its course. It is owing to them that the 
parts of the earth come to have a different character, that some 
parts remain moist for a certain time, and then dry up and grow 
old, while other parts in their turn are filled with life and 
moisture. Now when places become drier the springs 
necessarily give out, and when this happens the rivers first 
decrease in size and then finally become dry; and when rivers 
change and disappear in one part and come into existence 
correspondingly in another, the sea must needs be affected. 

If the sea was once pushed out by rivers and encroached upon 
the land anywhere, it necessarily leaves that place dry when it 
recedes; again, if the dry land has encroached on the sea at all 
by a process of silting set up by the rivers when at their full, the 
time must come when this place will be flooded again. 

But the whole vital process of the earth takes place so gradually 
and in periods of time which are so immense compared with 
the length of our life, that these changes are not observed, and 
before their course can be recorded from beginning to end 



1065 



whole nations perish and are destroyed. Of such destructions 
the most utter and sudden are due to wars; but pestilence or 
famine cause them too. Famines, again, are either sudden and 
severe or else gradual. In the latter case the disappearance of a 
nation is not noticed because some leave the country while 
others remain; and this goes on until the land is unable to 
maintain any inhabitants at all. So a long period of time is likely 
to elapse from the first departure to the last, and no one 
remembers and the lapse of time destroys all record even before 
the last inhabitants have disappeared. In the same way a nation 
must be supposed to lose account of the time when it first 
settled in a land that was changing from a marshy and watery 
state and becoming dry. Here, too, the change is gradual and 
lasts a long time and men do not remember who came first, or 
when, or what the land was like when they came. This has been 
the case with Egypt. Here it is obvious that the land is 
continually getting drier and that the whole country is a deposit 
of the river Nile. But because the neighbouring peoples settled 
in the land gradually as the marshes dried, the lapse of time has 
hidden the beginning of the process. However, all the mouths of 
the Nile, with the single exception of that at Canopus, are 
obviously artificial and not natural. And Egypt was nothing 
more than what is called Thebes, as Homer, too, shows, modern 
though he is in relation to such changes. For Thebes is the place 
that he mentions; which implies that Memphis did not yet exist, 
or at any rate was not as important as it is now. That this should 
be so is natural, since the lower land came to be inhabited later 
than that which lay higher. For the parts that lie nearer to the 
place where the river is depositing the silt are necessarily 
marshy for a longer time since the water always lies most in the 
newly formed land. But in time this land changes its character, 
and in its turn enjoys a period of prosperity. For these places dry 
up and come to be in good condition while the places that were 
formerly well-tempered some day grow excessively dry and 



1066 



deteriorate. This happened to the land of Argos and Mycenae in 
Greece. In the time of the Trojan wars the Argive land was 
marshy and could only support a small population, whereas the 
land of Mycenae was in good condition (and for this reason 
Mycenae was the superior). But now the opposite is the case, for 
the reason we have mentioned: the land of Mycenae has 
become completely dry and barren, while the Argive land that 
was formerly barren owing to the water has now become 
fruitful. Now the same process that has taken place in this 
small district must be supposed to be going on over whole 
countries and on a large scale. 

Men whose outlook is narrow suppose the cause of such events 
to be change in the universe, in the sense of a coming to be of 
the world as a whole. Hence they say that the sea being dried up 
and is growing less, because this is observed to have happened 
in more places now than formerly. But this is only partially true. 
It is true that many places are now dry, that formerly were 
covered with water. But the opposite is true too: for if they look 
they will find that there are many places where the sea has 
invaded the land. But we must not suppose that the cause of 
this is that the world is in process of becoming. For it is absurd 
to make the universe to be in process because of small and 
trifling changes, when the bulk and size of the earth are surely 
as nothing in comparison with the whole world. Rather we 
must take the cause of all these changes to be that, just as 
winter occurs in the seasons of the year, so in determined 
periods there comes a great winter of a great year and with it 
excess of rain. But this excess does not always occur in the 
same place. The deluge in the time of Deucalion, for instance, 
took place chiefly in the Greek world and in it especially about 
ancient Hellas, the country about Dodona and the Achelous, a 
river which has often changed its course. Here the Selli dwelt 
and those who were formerly called Graeci and now Hellenes. 
When, therefore, such an excess of rain occurs we must 



1067 



suppose that it suffices for a long time. We have seen that some 
say that the size of the subterranean cavities is what makes 
some rivers perennial and others not, whereas we maintain that 
the size of the mountains is the cause, and their density and 
coldness; for great, dense, and cold mountains catch and keep 
and create most water: whereas if the mountains that overhang 
the sources of rivers are small or porous and stony and clayey, 
these rivers run dry earlier. We must recognize the same kind of 
thing in this case too. Where such abundance of rain falls in the 
great winter it tends to make the moisture of those places 
almost everlasting. But as time goes on places of the latter type 
dry up more, while those of the former, moist type, do so less: 
until at last the beginning of the same cycle returns. 

Since there is necessarily some change in the whole world, but 
not in the way of coming into existence or perishing (for the 
universe is permanent), it must be, as we say, that the same 
places are not for ever moist through the presence of sea and 
rivers, nor for ever dry. And the facts prove this. The whole land 
of the Egyptians, whom we take to be the most ancient of men, 
has evidently gradually come into existence and been produced 
by the river. This is clear from an observation of the country, 
and the facts about the Red Sea suffice to prove it too. One of 
their kings tried to make a canal to it (for it would have been of 
no little advantage to them for the whole region to have become 
navigable; Sesostris is said to have been the first of the ancient 
kings to try), but he found that the sea was higher than the 
land. So he first, and Darius afterwards, stopped making the 
canal, lest the sea should mix with the river water and spoil it. 
So it is clear that all this part was once unbroken sea. For the 
same reason Libya - the country of Ammon - is, strangely 
enough, lower and hollower than the land to the seaward of it. 
For it is clear that a barrier of silt was formed and after it lakes 
and dry land, but in course of time the water that was left 
behind in the lakes dried up and is now all gone. Again the 



1068 



silting up of the lake Maeotis by the rivers has advanced so 
much that the limit to the size of the ships which can now sail 
into it to trade is much lower than it was sixty years ago. Hence 
it is easy to infer that it, too, like most lakes, was originally 
produced by the rivers and that it must end by drying up 
entirely. 

Again, this process of silting up causes a continuous current 
through the Bosporus; and in this case we can directly observe 
the nature of the process. Whenever the current from the 
Asiatic shore threw up a sandbank, there first formed a small 
lake behind it. Later it dried up and a second sandbank formed 
in front of the first and a second lake. This process went on 
uniformly and without interruption. Now when this has been 
repeated often enough, in the course of time the strait must 
become like a river, and in the end the river itself must dry up. 

So it is clear, since there will be no end to time and the world is 
eternal, that neither the Tanais nor the Nile has always been 
flowing, but that the region whence they flow was once dry: for 
their effect may be fulfilled, but time cannot. And this will be 
equally true of all other rivers. But if rivers come into existence 
and perish and the same parts of the earth were not always 
moist, the sea must needs change correspondingly. And if the 
sea is always advancing in one place and receding in another it 
is clear that the same parts of the whole earth are not always 
either sea or land, but that all this changes in course of time. 

So we have explained that the same parts of the earth are not 
always land or sea and why that is so: and also why some rivers 
are perennial and others not. 



1069 



Book II 



Let us explain the nature of the sea and the reason why such a 
large mass of water is salt and the way in which it originally 
came to be. 

The old writers who invented theogonies say that the sea has 
springs, for they want earth and sea to have foundations and 
roots of their own. Presumably they thought that this view was 
grander and more impressive as implying that our earth was an 
important part of the universe. For they believed that the whole 
world had been built up round our earth and for its sake, and 
that the earth was the most important and primary part of it. 
Others, wiser in human knowledge, give an account of its origin. 
At first, they say, the earth was surrounded by moisture. Then 
the sun began to dry it up, part of it evaporated and is the cause 
of winds and the turnings back of the sun and the moon, while 
the remainder forms the sea. So the sea is being dried up and is 
growing less, and will end by being some day entirely dried up. 
Others say that the sea is a kind of sweat exuded by the earth 
when the sun heats it, and that this explains its saltness: for all 
sweat is salt. Others say that the saltness is due to the earth. 
Just as water strained through ashes becomes salt, so the sea 
owes its saltness to the admixture of earth with similar 
properties. 

We must now consider the facts which prove that the sea 
cannot possibly have springs. The waters we find on the earth 
either flow or are stationary. All flowing water has springs. (By a 
spring, as we have explained above, we must not understand a 
source from which waters are ladled as it were from a vessel, 



1070 



but a first point at which the water which is continually forming 
and percolating gathers.) Stationary water is either that which 
has collected and has been left standing, marshy pools, for 
instance, and lakes, which differ merely in size, or else it comes 
from springs. In this case it is always artificial, I mean as in the 
case of wells, otherwise the spring would have to be above the 
outlet. Hence the water from fountains and rivers flows of itself, 
whereas wells need to be worked artificially. All the waters that 
exist belong to one or other of these classes. 

On the basis of this division we can sec that the sea cannot 
have springs. For it falls under neither of the two classes; it does 
not flow and it is not artificial; whereas all water from springs 
must belong to one or other of them. Natural standing water 
from springs is never found on such a large scale. 

Again, there are several seas that have no communication with 
one another at all. The Red Sea, for instance, communicates but 
slightly with the ocean outside the straits, and the Hyrcanian 
and Caspian seas are distinct from this ocean and people dwell 
all round them. Hence, if these seas had had any springs 
anywhere they must have been discovered. 

It is true that in straits, where the land on either side contracts 
an open sea into a small space, the sea appears to flow. But this 
is because it is swinging to and fro. In the open sea this motion 
is not observed, but where the land narrows and contracts the 
sea the motion that was imperceptible in the open necessarily 
strikes the attention. 

The whole of the Mediterranean does actually flow. The 
direction of this flow is determined by the depth of the basins 
and by the number of rivers. Maeotis flows into Pontus and 
Pontus into the Aegean. After that the flow of the remaining 
seas is not so easy to observe. The current of Maeotis and 
Pontus is due to the number of rivers (more rivers flow into the 



1071 



Euxine and Maeotis than into the whole Mediterranean with its 
much larger basin), and to their own shallowness. For we find 
the sea getting deeper and deeper. Pontus is deeper than 
Maeotis, the Aegean than Pontus, the Sicilian sea than the 
Aegean; the Sardinian and Tyrrhenic being the deepest of all. 
(Outside the pillars of Heracles the sea is shallow owing to the 
mud, but calm, for it lies in a hollow.) We see, then, that just as 
single rivers flow from mountains, so it is with the earth as a 
whole: the greatest volume of water flows from the higher 
regions in the north. Their alluvium makes the northern seas 
shallow, while the outer seas are deeper. Some further evidence 
of the height of the northern regions of the earth is afforded by 
the view of many of the ancient meteorologists. They believed 
that the sun did not pass below the earth, but round its 
northern part, and that it was the height of this which obscured 
the sun and caused night. 

So much to prove that there cannot be sources of the sea and to 
explain its observed flow. 



We must now discuss the origin of the sea, if it has an origin, 
and the cause of its salt and bitter taste. 

What made earlier writers consider the sea to be the original 
and main body of water is this. It seems reasonable to suppose 
that to be the case on the analogy of the other elements. Each of 
them has a main bulk which by reason of its mass is the origin 
of that element, and any parts which change and mix with the 
other elements come from it. Thus the main body of fire is in 
the upper region; that of air occupies the place next inside the 
region of fire; while the mass of the earth is that round which 



1072 



the rest of the elements are seen to lie. So we must clearly look 
for something analogous in the case of water. But here we can 
find no such single mass, as in the case of the other elements, 
except the sea. River water is not a unity, nor is it stable, but is 
seen to be in a continuous process of becoming from day to day. 
It was this difficulty which made people regard the sea as the 
origin and source of moisture and of all water. And so we find it 
maintained that rivers not only flow into the sea but originate 
from it, the salt water becoming sweet by filtration. 

But this view involves another difficulty. If this body of water is 
the origin and source of all water, why is it salt and not sweet? 
The reason for this, besides answering this question, will ensure 
our having a right first conception of the nature of the sea. 

The earth is surrounded by water, just as that is by the sphere of 
air, and that again by the sphere called that of fire (which is the 
outermost both on the common view and on ours). Now the 
sun, moving as it does, sets up processes of change and 
becoming and decay, and by its agency the finest and sweetest 
water is every day carried up and is dissolved into vapour and 
rises to the upper region, where it is condensed again by the 
cold and so returns to the earth. This, as we have said before, is 
the regular course of nature. 

Hence all my predecessors who supposed that the sun was 
nourished by moisture are absurdly mistaken. Some go on to 
say that the solstices are due to this, the reason being that the 
same places cannot always supply the sun with nourishment 
and that without it he must perish. For the fire we are familiar 
with lives as long as it is fed, and the only food for fire is 
moisture. As if the moisture that is raised could reach the sun! 
or this ascent were really like that performed by flame as it 
comes into being, and to which they supposed the case of the 
sun to be analogous! Really there is no similarity. A flame is a 



1073 



process of becoming, involving a constant interchange of moist 
and dry. It cannot be said to be nourished since it scarcely 
persists as one and the same for a moment. This cannot be true 
of the sun; for if it were nourished like that, as they say it is, we 
should obviously not only have a new sun every day, as 
Heraclitus says, but a new sun every moment. Again, when the 
sun causes the moisture to rise, this is like fire heating water. 
So, as the fire is not fed by the water above it, it is absurd to 
suppose that the sun feeds on that moisture, even if its heat 
made all the water in the world evaporate. Again, it is absurd, 
considering the number and size of the stars, that these 
thinkers should consider the sun only and overlook the 
question how the rest of the heavenly bodies subsist. Again, 
they are met by the same difficulty as those who say that at 
first the earth itself was moist and the world round the earth 
was warmed by the sun, and so air was generated and the 
whole firmament grew, and the air caused winds and solstices. 
The objection is that we always plainly see the water that has 
been carried up coming down again. Even if the same amount 
does not come back in a year or in a given country, yet in a 
certain period all that has been carried up is returned. This 
implies that the celestial bodies do not feed on it, and that we 
cannot distinguish between some air which preserves its 
character once it is generated and some other which is 
generated but becomes water again and so perishes; on the 
contrary, all the moisture alike is dissolved and all of it 
condensed back into water. 

The drinkable, sweet water, then, is light and is all of it drawn 
up: the salt water is heavy and remains behind, but not in its 
natural place. For this is a question which has been sufficiently 
discussed (I mean about the natural place that water, like the 
other elements, must in reason have), and the answer is this. 
The place which we see the sea filling is not its natural place 
but that of water. It seems to belong to the sea because the 



1074 



weight of the salt water makes it remain there, while the sweet, 
drinkable water which is light is carried up. The same thing 
happens in animal bodies. Here, too, the food when it enters the 
body is sweet, yet the residuum and dregs of liquid food are 
found to be bitter and salt. This is because the sweet and 
drinkable part of it has been drawn away by the natural animal 
heat and has passed into the flesh and the other parts of the 
body according to their several natures. Now just as here it 
would be wrong for any one to refuse to call the belly the place 
of liquid food because that disappears from it soon, and to call 
it the place of the residuum because this is seen to remain, so in 
the case of our present subject. This place, we say, is the place of 
water. Hence all rivers and all the water that is generated flow 
into it: for water flows into the deepest place, and the deepest 
part of the earth is filled by the sea. Only all the light and sweet 
part of it is quickly carried off by the sun, while herest remains 
for the reason we have explained. It is quite natural that some 
people should have been puzzled by the old question why such 
a mass of water leaves no trace anywhere (for the sea does not 
increase though innumerable and vast rivers are flowing into it 
every day.) But if one considers the matter the solution is easy. 
The same amount of water does not take as long to dry up 
when it is spread out as when it is gathered in a body, and 
indeed the difference is so great that in the one case it might 
persist the whole day long while in the other it might all 
disappear in a moment - as for instance if one were to spread 
out a cup of water over a large table. This is the case with the 
rivers: all the time they are flowing their water forms a compact 
mass, but when it arrives at a vast wide place it quickly and 
imperceptibly evaporates. 

But the theory of the Phaedo about rivers and the sea is 
impossible. There it is said that the earth is pierced by 
intercommunicating channels and that the original head and 
source of all waters is what is called Tartarus - a mass of water 



1075 



about the centre, from which all waters, flowing and standing, 
are derived. This primary and original water is always surging to 
and fro, and so it causes the rivers to flow on this side of the 
earth's centre and on that; for it has no fixed seat but is always 
oscillating about the centre. Its motion up and down is what 
fills rivers. Many of these form lakes in various places (our sea is 
an instance of one of these), but all of them come round again 
in a circle to the original source of their flow, many at the same 
point, but some at a point opposite to that from which they 
issued; for instance, if they started from the other side of the 
earth's centre, they might return from this side of it. They 
descend only as far as the centre, for after that all motion is 
upwards. Water gets its tastes and colours from the kind of 
earth the rivers happened to flow through. 

But on this theory rivers do not always flow in the same sense. 
For since they flow to the centre from which they issue forth 
they will not be flowing down any more than up, but in 
whatever direction the surging of Tartarus inclines to. But at this 
rate we shall get the proverbial rivers flowing upwards, which is 
impossible. Again, where is the water that is generated and 
what goes up again as vapour to come from? For this must all of 
it simply be ignored, since the quantity of water is always the 
same and all the water that flows out from the original source 
flows back to it again. This itself is not true, since all rivers are 
seen to end in the sea except where one flows into another. Not 
one of them ends in the earth, but even when one is swallowed 
up it comes to the surface again. And those rivers are large 
which flow for a long distance through a lowying country, for by 
their situation and length they cut off the course of many 
others and swallow them up. This is why the Istrus and the Nile 
are the greatest of the rivers which flow into our sea. Indeed, so 
many rivers fall into them that there is disagreement as to the 
sources of them both. All of which is plainly impossible on the 
theory, and the more so as it derives the sea from Tartarus. 



1076 



Enough has been said to prove that this is the natural place of 
water and not of the sea, and to explain why sweet water is only 
found in rivers, while salt water is stationary, and to show that 
the sea is the end rather than the source of water, analogous to 
the residual matter of all food, and especially liquid food, in 
animal bodies. 



We must now explain why the sea is salt, and ask whether it 
eternally exists as identically the same body, or whether it did 
not exist at all once and some day will exist no longer, but will 
dry up as some people think. 

Every one admits this, that if the whole world originated the sea 
did too; for they make them come into being at the same time. 
It follows that if the universe is eternal the same must be true 
of the sea. Any one who thinks like Democritus that the sea is 
diminishing and will disappear in the end reminds us of Aesop's 
tales. His story was that Charybdis had twice sucked in the sea: 
the first time she made the mountains visible; the second time 
the islands; and when she sucks it in for the last time she will 
dry it up entirely. Such a tale is appropriate enough to Aesop in 
a rage with the ferryman, but not to serious inquirers. Whatever 
made the sea remain at first, whether it was its weight, as some 
even of those who hold these views say (for it is easy to see the 
cause here), or some other reason - clearly the same thing must 
make it persist for ever. They must either deny that the water 
raised by the sun will return at all, or, if it does, they must admit 
that the sea persists for ever or as long as this process goes on, 
and again, that for the same period of time that sweet water 
must have been carried up beforehand. So the sea will never dry 



1077 



up: for before that can happen the water that has gone up 
beforehand will return to it: for if you say that this happens 
once you must admit its recurrence. If you stop the sun's course 
there is no drying agency. If you let it go on it will draw up the 
sweet water as we have said whenever it approaches, and let it 
descend again when it recedes. This notion about the sea is 
derived from the fact that many places are found to be drier 
now than they once were. Why this is so we have explained. The 
phenomenon is due to temporary excess of rain and not to any 
process of becoming in which the universe or its parts are 
involved. Some day the opposite will take place and after that 
the earth will grow dry once again. We must recognize that this 
process always goes on thus in a cycle, for that is more 
satisfactory than to suppose a change in the whole world in 
order to explain these facts. But we have dwelt longer on this 
point than it deserves. 

To return to the saltness of the sea: those who create the sea 
once for all, or indeed generate it at all, cannot account for its 
saltness. It makes no difference whether the sea is the residue 
of all the moisture that is about the earth and has been drawn 
up by the sun, or whether all the flavour existing in the whole 
mass of sweet water is due to the admixture of a certain kind of 
earth. Since the total volume of the sea is the same once the 
water that evaporated has returned, it follows that it must 
either have been salt at first too, or, if not at first, then not now 
either. If it was salt from the very beginning, then we want to 
know why that was so; and why, if salt water was drawn up 
then, that is not the case now. 

Again, if it is maintained that an admixture of earth makes the 
sea salt (for they say that earth has many flavours and is 
washed down by the rivers and so makes the sea salt by its 
admixture), it is strange that rivers should not be salt too. How 
can the admixture of this earth have such a striking effect in a 



1078 



great quantity of water and not in each river singly? For the sea, 
differing in nothing from rivers but in being salt, is evidently 
simply the totality of river water, and the rivers are the vehicle 
in which that earth is carried to their common destination. 

It is equally absurd to suppose that anything has been 
explained by calling the sea 'the sweat of the earth', like 
Empedicles. Metaphors are poetical and so that expression of 
his may satisfy the requirements of a poem, but as a scientific 
theory it is unsatisfactory. Even in the case of the body it is a 
question how the sweet liquid drunk becomes salt sweat 
whether it is merely by the departure of some element in it 
which is sweetest, or by the admixture of something, as when 
water is strained through ashes. Actually the saltness seems to 
be due to the same cause as in the case of the residual liquid 
that gathers in the bladder. That, too, becomes bitter and salt 
though the liquid we drink and that contained in our food is 
sweet. If then the bitterness is due in these cases (as with the 
water strained through lye) to the presence of a certain sort of 
stuff that is carried along by the urine (as indeed we actually 
find a salt deposit settling in chamber-pots) and is secreted 
from the flesh in sweat (as if the departing moisture were 
washing the stuff out of the body), then no doubt the admixture 
of something earthy with the water is what makes the sea salt. 

Now in the body stuff of this kind, viz. the sediment of food, is 
due to failure to digest: but how there came to be any such 
thing in the earth requires explanation. Besides, how can the 
drying and warming of the earth cause the secretion such a 
great quantity of water; especially as that must be a mere 
fragment of what is left in the earth? Again, waiving the 
question of quantity, why does not the earth sweat now when it 
happens to be in process of drying? If it did so then, it ought to 
do so now. But it does not: on the contrary, when it is dry it 
graws moist, but when it is moist it does not secrete anything at 



1079 



all. How then was it possible for the earth at the beginning 
when it was moist to sweat as it grew dry? Indeed, the theory 
that maintains that most of the moisture departed and was 
drawn up by the sun and that what was left over is the sea is 
more reasonable; but for the earth to sweat when it is moist is 
impossible. 

Since all the attempts to account for the saltness of the sea 
seem unsuccessful let us explain it by the help of the principle 
we have used already. 

Since we recognize two kinds of evaporation, one moist, the 
other dry, it is clear that the latter must be recognized as the 
source of phenomena like those we are concerned with. 

But there is a question which we must discuss first. Does the 
sea always remain numerically one and consisting of the same 
parts, or is it, too, one in form and volume while its parts are in 
continual change, like air and sweet water and fire? All of these 
are in a constant state of change, but the form and the quantity 
of each of them are fixed, just as they are in the case of a 
flowing river or a burning flame. The answer is clear, and there 
is no doubt that the same account holds good of all these things 
alike. They differ in that some of them change more rapidly or 
more slowly than others; and they all are involved in a process 
of perishing and becoming which yet affects them all in a 
regular course. 

This being so we must go on to try to explain why the sea is 
salt. There are many facts which make it clear that this taste is 
due to the admixture of something. First, in animal bodies what 
is least digested, the residue of liquid food, is salt and bitter, as 
we said before. All animal excreta are undigested, but especially 
that which gathers in the bladder (its extreme lightness proves 
this; for everything that is digested is condensed), and also 
sweat; in these then is excreted (along with other matter) an 



1080 



identical substance to which this flavour is due. The case of 
things burnt is analogous. What heat fails to assimilate 
becomes the excrementary residue in animal bodies, and, in 
things burnt, ashes. That is why some people say that it was 
burnt earth that made the sea salt. To say that it was burnt 
earth is absurd; but to say that it was something like burnt 
earth is true. We must suppose that just as in the cases we have 
described, so in the world as a whole, everything that grows and 
is naturally generated always leaves an undigested residue, like 
that of things burnt, consisting of this sort of earth. All the 
earthy stuff in the dry exhalation is of this nature, and it is the 
dry exhalation which accounts for its great quantity. Now since, 
as we have said, the moist and the dry evaporations are mixed, 
some quantity of this stuff must always be included in the 
clouds and the water that are formed by condensation, and 
must redescend to the earth in rain. This process must always 
go on with such regularity as the sublunary world admits of. 
and it is the answer to the question how the sea comes to be 
salt. 

It also explains why rain that comes from the south, and the 
first rains of autumn, are brackish. The south is the warmest of 
winds and it blows from dry and hot regions. Hence it carries 
little moist vapour and that is why it is hot. (It makes no 
difference even if this is not its true character and it is originally 
a cold wind, for it becomes warm on its way by incorporating 
with itself a great quantity of dry evaporation from the places it 
passes over.) The north wind, on the other hand, comb ing from 
moist regions, is full of vapour and therefore cold. It is dry in 
our part of the world because it drives the clouds away before it, 
but in the south it is rainy; just as the south is a dry wind in 
Libya. So the south wind charges the rain that falls with a great 
quantity of this stuff. Autumn rain is brackish because the 
heaviest water must fall first; so that that which contains the 
greatest quantity of this kind of earth descends quickest. 



1081 



This, too, is why the sea is warm. Everything that has been 
exposed to fire contains heat potentially, as we see in the case 
of lye and ashes and the dry and liquid excreta of animals. 
Indeed those animals which are hottest in the belly have the 
hottest excreta. 

The action of this cause is continually making the sea more salt, 
but some part of its saltness is always being drawn up with the 
sweet water. This is less than the sweet water in the same ratio 
in which the salt and brackish element in rain is less than the 
sweet, and so the saltness of the sea remains constant on the 
whole. Salt water when it turns into vapour becomes sweet, and 
the vapour does not form salt water when it condenses again. 
This I know by experiment. The same thing is true in every case 
of the kind: wine and all fluids that evaporate and condense 
back into a liquid state become water. They all are water 
modified by a certain admixture, the nature of which 
determines their flavour. But this subject must be considered on 
another more suitable occasion. 

For the present let us say this. The sea is there and some of it is 
continually being drawn up and becoming sweet; this returns 
from above with the rain. But it is now different from what it 
was when it was drawn up, and its weight makes it sink below 
the sweet water. This process prevents the sea, as it does rivers, 
from drying up except from local causes (this must happen to 
sea and rivers alike). On the other hand the parts neither of the 
earth nor of the sea remain constant but only their whole bulk. 
For the same thing is true of the earth as of the sea: some of it is 
carried up and some comes down with the rain, and both that 
which remains on the surface and that which comes down 
again change their situations. 

There is more evidence to prove that saltness is due to the 
admixture of some substance, besides that which we have 



1082 



adduced. Make a vessel of wax and put it in the sea, fastening 
its mouth in such a way as to prevent any water getting in. Then 
the water that percolates through the wax sides of the vessel is 
sweet, the earthy stuff, the admixture of which makes the water 
salt, being separated off as it were by a filter. It is this stuff 
which make salt water heavy (it weighs more than fresh water) 
and thick. The difference in consistency is such that ships with 
the same cargo very nearly sink in a river when they are quite 
fit to navigate in the sea. This circumstance has before now 
caused loss to shippers freighting their ships in a river. That the 
thicker consistency is due to an admixture of something is 
proved by the fact that if you make strong brine by the 
admixture of salt, eggs, even when they are full, float in it. It 
almost becomes like mud; such a quantity of earthy matter is 
there in the sea. The same thing is done in salting fish. 

Again if, as is fabled, there is a lake in Palestine, such that if you 
bind a man or beast and throw it in it floats and does not sink, 
this would bear out what we have said. They say that this lake is 
so bitter and salt that no fish live in it and that if you soak 
clothes in it and shake them it cleans them. The following facts 
all of them support our theory that it is some earthy stuff in the 
water which makes it salt. In Chaonia there is a spring of 
brackish water that flows into a neighbouring river which is 
sweet but contains no fish. The local story is that when Heracles 
came from Erytheia driving the oxen and gave the inhabitants 
the choice, they chose salt in preference to fish. They get the 
salt from the spring. They boil off some of the water and let the 
rest stand; when it has cooled and the heat and moisture have 
evaporated together it gives them salt, not in lumps but loose 
and light like snow. It is weaker than ordinary salt and added 
freely gives a sweet taste, and it is not as white as salt generally 
is. Another instance of this is found in Umbria. There is a place 
there where reeds and rushes grow. They burn some of these, 



1083 



put the ashes into water and boil it off. When a little water is 
left and has cooled it gives a quantity of salt. 

Most salt rivers and springs must once have been hot. Then the 
original fire in them was extinguished but the earth through 
which they percolate preserves the character of lye or ashes. 
Springs and rivers with all kinds of flavours are found in many 
places. These flavours must in every case be due to the fire that 
is or was in them, for if you expose earth to different degrees of 
heat it assumes various kinds and shades of flavour. It becomes 
full of alum and lye and other things of the kind, and the fresh 
water percolates through these and changes its character. 
Sometimes it becomes acid as in Sicania, a part of Sicily. There 
they get a salt and acid water which they use as vinegar to 
season some of their dishes. In the neighbourhood of Lyncus, 
too, there is a spring of acid water, and in Scythia a bitter spring. 
The water from this makes the whole of the river into which it 
flows bitter. These differences are explained by a knowledge of 
the particular mixtures that determine different savours. But 
these have been explained in another treatise. 

We have now given an account of waters and the sea, why they 
persist, how they change, what their nature is, and have 
explained most of their natural operations and affections. 



Let us proceed to the theory of winds. Its basis is a distinction 
we have already made. We recognize two kinds of evaporation, 
one moist, the other dry. The former is called vapour: for the 
other there is no general name but we must call it a sort of 
smoke, applying to the whole of it a word that is proper to one 
of its forms. The moist cannot exist without the dry nor the dry 



1084 



without the moist: whenever we speak of either we mean that it 
predominates. Now when the sun in its circular course 
approaches, it draws up by its heat the moist evaporation: when 
it recedes the cold makes the vapour that had been raised 
condense back into water which falls and is distributed through 
the earth. (This explains why there is more rain in winter and 
more by night than by day: though the fact is not recognized 
because rain by night is more apt to escape observation than by 
day.) But there is a great quantity of fire and heat in the earth, 
and the sun not only draws up the moisture that lies on the 
surface of it, but warms and dries the earth itself. Consequently, 
since there are two kinds of evaporation, as we have said, one 
like vapour, the other like smoke, both of them are necessarily 
generated. That in which moisture predominates is the source 
of rain, as we explained before, while the dry evaporation is the 
source and substance of all winds. That things must necessarily 
take this course is clear from the resulting phenomena 
themselves, for the evaporation that is to produce them must 
necessarily differ; and the sun and the warmth in the earth not 
only can but must produce these evaporations. 

Since the two evaporations are specifically distinct, wind and 
rain obviously differ and their substance is not the same, as 
those say who maintain that one and the same air when in 
motion is wind, but when it condenses again is water. Air, as we 
have explained in an earlier book, is made up of these as 
constituents. Vapour is moist and cold (for its fluidity is due to 
its moistness, and because it derives from water it is naturally 
cold, like water that has not been warmed): whereas the smoky 
evaporation is hot and dry. Hence each contributes a part, and 
air is moist and hot. It is absurd that this air that surrounds us 
should become wind when in motion, whatever be the source of 
its motion on the contrary the case of winds is like that of 
rivers. We do not call water that flows anyhow a river, even if 
there is a great quantity of it, but only if the flow comes from a 



1085 



spring. So too with the winds; a great quantity of air might be 
moved by the fall of some large object without flowing from any 
source or spring. 

The facts bear out our theory. It is because the evaporation 
takes place uninterruptedly but differs in degree and quantity 
that clouds and winds appear in their natural proportion 
according to the season; and it is because there is now a great 
excess of the vaporous, now of the dry and smoky exhalation, 
that some years are rainy and wet, others windy and dry. 
Sometimes there is much drought or rain, and it prevails over a 
great and continuous stretch of country. At other times it is 
local; the surrounding country often getting seasonable or even 
excessive rains while there is drought in a certain part; or, 
contrariwise, all the surrounding country gets little or even no 
rain while a certain part gets rain in abundance. The reason for 
all this is that while the same affection is generally apt to 
prevail over a considerable district because adjacent places 
(unless there is something special to differentiate them) stand 
in the same relation to the sun, yet on occasion the dry 
evaporation will prevail in one part and the moist in another, or 
conversely. Again the reason for this latter is that each 
evaporation goes over to that of the neighbouring district: for 
instance, the dry evaporation circulates in its own place while 
the moist migrates to the next district or is even driven by 
winds to some distant place: or else the moist evaporation 
remains and the dry moves away. Just as in the case of the body 
when the stomach is dry the lower belly is often in the contrary 
state, and when it is dry the stomach is moist and cold, so it 
often happens that the evaporations reciprocally take one 
another's place and interchange. 

Further, after rain wind generally rises in those places where 
the rain fell, and when rain has come on the wind ceases. These 
are necessary effects of the principles we have explained. After 



1086 



rain the earth is being dried by its own heat and that from 
above and gives off the evaporation which we saw to be the 
material cause of. wind. Again, suppose this secretion is present 
and wind prevails; the heat is continually being thrown off, 
rising to the upper region, and so the wind ceases; then the fall 
in temperature makes vapour form and condense into water. 
Water also forms and cools the dry evaporation when the 
clouds are driven together and the cold concentrated in them. 
These are the causes that make wind cease on the advent of 
rain, and rain fall on the cessation of wind. 

The cause of the predominance of winds from the north and 
from the south is the same. (Most winds, as a matter of fact, are 
north winds or south winds.) These are the only regions which 
the sun does not visit: it approaches them and recedes from 
them, but its course is always over the west and the east. Hence 
clouds collect on either side, and when the sun approaches it 
provokes the moist evaporation, and when it recedes to the 
opposite side there are storms and rain. So summer and winter 
are due to the sun's motion to and from the solstices, and water 
ascends and falls again for the same reason. Now since most 
rain falls in those regions towards which and from which the 
sun turns and these are the north and the south, and since 
most evaporation must take place where there is the greatest 
rainfall, just as green wood gives most smoke, and since this 
evaporation is wind, it is natural that the most and most 
important winds should come from these quarters. (The winds 
from the north are called Boreae, those from the south Noti.) 

The course of winds is oblique: for though the evaporation rises 
straight up from the earth, they blow round it because all the 
surrounding air follows the motion of the heavens. Hence the 
question might be asked whether winds originate from above or 
from below. The motion comes from above: before we feel the 
wind blowing the air betrays its presence if there are clouds or a 



1087 



mist, for their motion shows that the wind has begun to blow 
before it has actually reached us; and this implies that the 
source of winds is above. But since wind is defined as 'a 
quantity of dry evaporation from the earth moving round the 
earth', it is clear that while the origin of the motion is from 
above, the matter and the generation of wind come from below. 
The oblique movement of the rising evaporation is caused from 
above: for the motion of the heavens determines the processes 
that are at a distance from the earth, and the motion from 
below is vertical and every cause is more active where it is 
nearest to the effect; but in its generation and origin wind 
plainly derives from the earth. 

The facts bear out the view that winds are formed by the 
gradual union of many evaporations just as rivers derive their 
sources from the water that oozes from the earth. Every wind is 
weakest in the spot from which it blows; as they proceed and 
leave their source at a distance they gather strength. Thus the 
winter in the north is windless and calm: that is, in the north 
itself; but, the breeze that blows from there so gently as to 
escape observation becomes a great wind as it passes on. 

We have explained the nature and origin of wind, the 
occurrence of drought and rains, the reason why rain stops 
wind and wind rises after rain, the prevalence of north and 
south winds and also why wind moves in the way it does. 



The sun both checks the formation of winds and stimulates it. 
When the evaporation is small in amount and faint the sun 
wastes it and dissipates by its greater heat the lesser heat 
contained in the evaporation. It also dries up the earth, the 



1088 



source of the evaporation, before the latter has appeared in 
bulk: just as, when you throw a little fuel into a great fire, it is 
often burnt up before giving off any smoke. In these ways the 
sun checks winds and prevents them from rising at all: it checks 
them by wasting the evaporation, and prevents their rising by 
drying up the earth quickly. Hence calm is very apt to prevail 
about the rising of Orion and lasts until the coming of the 
Etesiae and their 'forerunners'. 

Calm is due to two causes. Either cold quenches the 
evaporation, for instance a sharp frost: or excessive heat wastes 
it. In the intermediate periods, too, the causes are generally 
either that the evaporation has not had time to develop or that 
it has passed away and there is none as yet to replace it. 

Both the setting and the rising of Orion are considered to be 
treacherous and stormy, because they place at a change of 
season (namely of summer or winter; and because the size of 
the constellation makes its rise last over many days) and a state 
of change is always indefinite and therefore liable to 
disturbance. 

The Etesiae blow after the summer solstice and the rising of the 
dog-star: not at the time when the sun is closest nor when it is 
distant; and they blow by day and cease at night. The reason is 
that when the sun is near it dries up the earth before 
evaporation has taken place, but when it has receded a little its 
heat and the evaporation are present in the right proportion; so 
the ice melts and the earth, dried by its own heat and that of 
the sun, smokes and vapours. They abate at night because the 
cold pf the nights checks the melting of the ice. What is frozen 
gives off no evaporation, nor does that which contains no 
dryness at all: it is only where something dry contains moisture 
that it gives off evaporation under the influence of heat. 



1089 



The question is sometimes asked: why do the north winds 
which we call the Etesiae blow continuously after the summer 
solstice, when there are no corresponding south winds after the 
winter solstice? The facts are reasonable enough: for the so- 
called 'white south winds' do blow at the corresponding season, 
though they are not equally continuous and so escape 
observation and give rise to this inquiry. The reason for this is 
that the north wind I from the arctic regions which are full of 
water and snow. The sun thaws them and so the Etesiae blow: 
after rather than at the summer solstice. (For the greatest heat 
is developed not when the sun is nearest to the north, but when 
its heat has been felt for a considerable period and it has not yet 
receded far. The 'bird winds' blow in the same way after the 
winter solstice. They, too, are weak Etesiae, but they blow less 
and later than the Etesiae. They begin to blow only on the 
seventieth day because the sun is distant and therefore weaker. 
They do not blow so continuously because only things on the 
surface of the earth and offering little resistance evaporate 
then, the thoroughly frozen parts requiring greater heat to melt 
them. So they blow intermittently till the true Etesiae come on 
again at the summer solstice: for from that time onwards the 
wind tends to blow continuously.) But the south wind blows 
from the tropic of Cancer and not from the antarctic region. 

There are two inhabitable sections of the earth: one near our 
upper, or nothern pole, the other near the other or southern 
pole; and their shape is like that of a tambourine. If you draw 
lines from the centre of the earth they cut out a drum-shaped 
figure. The lines form two cones; the base of the one is the 
tropic, of the other the ever visible circle, their vertex is at the 
centre of the earth. Two other cones towards the south pole give 
corresponding segments of the earth. These sections alone are 
habitable. Beyond the tropics no one can live: for there the 
shade would not fall to the north, whereas the earth is known 
to be uninhabitable before the sun is in the zenith or the shade 



1090 



is thrown to the south: and the regions below the Bear are 
uninhabitable because of the cold. 

(The Crown, too, moves over this region: for it is in the zenith 
when it is on our meridian.) 

So we see that the way in which they now describe the 
geography of the earth is ridiculous. They depict the inhabited 
earth as round, but both ascertained facts and general 
considerations show this to be impossible. If we reflect we see 
that the inhabited region is limited in breadth, while the 
climate admits of its extending all round the earth. For we meet 
with no excessive heat or cold in the direction of its length but 
only in that of its breadth; so that there is nothing to prevent 
our travelling round the earth unless the extent of the sea 
presents an obstacle anywhere. The records of journeys by sea 
and land bear this out. They make the length far greater than 
the breadth. If we compute these voyages and journeys the 
distance from the Pillars of Heracles to India exceeds that from 
Aethiopia to Maeotis and the northernmost Scythians by a ratio 
of more than 5 to 3, as far as such matters admit of accurate 
statement. Yet we know the whole breadth of the region we 
dwell in up to the uninhabited parts: in one direction no one 
lives because of the cold, in the other because of the heat. 

But it is the sea which divides as it seems the parts beyond 
India from those beyond the Pillars of Heracles and prevents the 
earth from being inhabited all round. 

Now since there must be a region bearing the same relation to 
the southern pole as the place we live in bears to our pole, it 
will clearly correspond in the ordering of its winds as well as in 
other things. So just as we have a north wind here, they must 
have a corresponding wind from the antarctic. This wind cannot 
reach us since our own north wind is like a land breeze and 
does not even reach the limits of the region we live in. The 



1091 



prevalence of north winds here is due to our lying near the 
north. Yet even here they give out and fail to penetrate far: in 
the southern sea beyond Libya east and west winds are always 
blowing alternately, like north and south winds with us. So it is 
clear that the south wind is not the wind that blows from the 
south pole. It is neither that nor the wind from the winter 
tropic. For symmetry would require another wind blowing from 
the summer tropic, which there is not, since we know that only 
one wind blows from that quarter. So the south wind clearly 
blows from the torrid region. Now the sun is so near to that 
region that it has no water, or snow which might melt and 
cause Etesiae. But because that place is far more extensive and 
open the south wind is greater and stronger and warmer than 
the north and penetrates farther to the north than the north 
wind does to the south. 

The origin of these winds and their relation to one another has 
now been explained. 



Let us now explain the position of the winds, their oppositions, 
which can blow simultaneously with which, and which cannot, 
their names and number, and any other of their affections that 
have not been treated in the 'particular questions'. What we say 
about their position must be followed with the help of the 
figure. For clearness' sake we have drawn the circle of the 
horizon, which is round, but it represents the zone in which we 
live; for that can be divided in the same way. Let us also begin 
by laying down that those things are locally contrary which are 
locally most distant from one another, just as things specifically 
most remote from one another are specific contraries. Now 



1092 



things that face one another from opposite ends of a diameter 
are locally most distant from one another. (See diagram.) 

Let A be the point where the sun sets at the equinox and B, the 
point opposite, the place where it rises at the equinox. Let there 
be another diameter cutting this at right angles, and let the 
point H on it be the north and its diametrical opposite the 
south. Let Z be the rising of the sun at the summer solstice and 
E its setting at the summer solstice; D its rising at the winter 
solstice, and G its setting at the winter solstice. Draw a diameter 
from Z to G from D to E. Then since those things are locally 
contrary which are most distant from one another in space, and 
points diametrically opposite are most distant from one 
another, those winds must necessarily be contrary to one 
another that blow from opposite ends of a diameter. 

The names of the winds according to their position are these. 
Zephyrus is the wind that blows from A, this being the point 
where the sun sets at the equinox. Its contrary is Apeliotes 
blowing from B the point where the sun rises at the equinox. 
The wind blowing from H, the north, is the true north wind, 
called Aparctias: while Notus blowing from is its contrary; for 
this point is the south and is contrary to H, being 
diametrically opposite to it. Caecias blows from Z, where the 
sun rises at the summer solstice. Its contrary is not the wind 
blowing from E but Lips blowing from G. For Lips blows from the 
point where the sun sets at the winter solstice and is 
diametrically opposite to Caecias: so it is its contrary. Eurus 
blows from D, coming from the point where the sun rises at the 
winter solstice. It borders on Notus, and so we often find that 
people speak of 'Euro-Noti'. Its contrary is not Lips blowing from 
G but the wind that blows from E which some call Argestes, 
some Olympias, and some Sciron. This blows from the point 
where the sun sets at the summer solstice, and is the only wind 



1093 



that is diametrically opposite to Eurus. These are the winds that 
are diametrically opposite to one another and their contraries. 

There are other winds which have no contraries. The wind they 
call Thrascias, which lies between Argestes and Aparctias, blows 
from I; and the wind called Meses, which lies between Caecias 
and Aparctias, from K. (The line IK nearly coincides with the 
ever visible circle, but not quite.) These winds have no 
contraries. Meses has not, or else there would be a wind blowing 
from the point M which is diametrically opposite. Thrascias 
corresponding to the point I has not, for then there would be a 
wind blowing from N, the point which is diametrically opposite. 
(But perhaps a local wind which the inhabitants of those parts 
call Phoenicias blows from that point.) 

These are the most important and definite winds and these 
their places. 

There are more winds from the north than from the south. The 
reason for this is that the region in which we live lies nearer to 
the north. Also, much more water and snow is pushed aside 
into this quarter because the other lies under the sun and its 
course. When this thaws and soaks into the earth and is 
exposed to the heat of the sun and the earth it necessarily 
causes evaporation to rise in greater quantities and over a 
greater space. 

Of the winds we have described Aparctias is the north wind in 
the strict sense. Thrascias and Meses are north winds too. 
(Caecias is half north and half east.) South are that which blows 
from due south and Lips. East, the wind from the rising of the 
sun at the equinox and Eurus. Phoenicias is half south and half 
east. West, the wind from the true west and that called Argestes. 
More generally these winds are classified as northerly or 
southerly. The west winds are counted as northerly, for they 
blow from the place of sunset and are therefore colder; the east 



1094 



winds as southerly, for they are warmer because they blow from 
the place of sunrise. So the distinction of cold and hot or warm 
is the basis for the division of the winds into northerly and 
southerly. East winds are warmer than west winds because the 
sun shines on the east longer, whereas it leaves the west sooner 
and reaches it later. 

Since this is the distribution of the winds it is clear that 
contrary winds cannot blow simultaneously. They are 
diametrically opposite to one another and one of the two must 
be overpowered and cease. Winds that are not diametrically 
opposite to one another may blow simultaneously: for instance 
the winds from Z and from D. Hence it sometimes happens that 
both of them, though different winds and blowing from 
different quarters, are favourable to sailors making for the same 
point. 

Contrary winds commonly blow at opposite seasons. Thus 
Caecias and in general the winds north of the summer solstice 
blow about the time of the spring equinox, but about the 
autumn equinox Lips; and Zephyrus about the summer solstice, 
but about the winter solstice Eurus. 

Aparctias, Thrascias, and Argestes are the winds that fall on 
others most and stop them. Their source is so close to us that 
they are greater and stronger than other winds. They bring fair 
weather most of all winds for the same reason, for, blowing as 
they do, from close at hand, they overpower the other winds 
and stop them; they also blow away the clouds that are forming 
and leave a clear sky - unless they happen to be very cold. Then 
they do not bring fair weather, but being colder than they are 
strong they condense the clouds before driving them away. 

Caecias does not bring fair weather because it returns upon 
itself. Hence the saying: 'Bringing it on himself as Caecias does 
clouds.' 



1095 



When they cease, winds are succeeded by their neighbours in 
the direction of the movement of the sun. For an effect is most 
apt to be produced in the neighbourhood of its cause, and the 
cause of winds moves with the sun. 

Contrary winds have either the same or contrary effects. Thus 
Lips and Caecias, sometimes called Hellespontias, are both 
rainy gestes and Eurus are dry: the latter being dry at first and 
rainy afterwards. Meses and Aparctias are coldest and bring 
most snow. Aparctias, Thrascias, and Argestes bring hail. Notus, 
Zephyrus, and Eurus are hot. Caecias covers the sky with heavy 
clouds, Lips with lighter ones. Caecias does this because it 
returns upon itself and combines the qualities of Boreas and 
Eurus. By being cold it condenses and gathers the vaporous air, 
and because it is easterly it carries with it and drives before it a 
great quantity of such matter. Aparctias, Thrascias, and Argestes 
bring fair weather for the reason we have explained before. 
These winds and Meses are most commonly accompanied by 
lightning. They are cold because they blow from the north, and 
lightning is due to cold, being ejected when the clouds contract. 
Some of these same bring hail with them for the same reason; 
namely, that they cause a sudden condensation. 

Hurricanes are commonest in autumn, and next in spring: 
Aparctias, Thrascias, and Argestes give rise to them most. This is 
because hurricanes are generally formed when some winds are 
blowing and others fall on them; and these are the winds which 
are most apt to fall on others that are blowing; the reason for 
which, too, we have explained before. 

The Etesiae veer round: they begin from the north, and become 
for dwellers in the west Thrasciae, Argestae, and Zephyrus (for 
Zephyrus belongs to the north). For dwellers in the east they 
veer round as far as Apeliotes. 



1096 



So much for the winds, their origin and nature and the 
properties common to them all or peculiar to each. 



We must go on to discuss earthquakes next, for their cause is 
akin to our last subject. 

The theories that have been put forward up to the present date 
are three, and their authors three men, Anaxagoras of 
Clazomenae, and before him Anaximenes of Miletus, and later 
Democritus of Abdera. 

Anaxagoras says that the ether, which naturally moves 
upwards, is caught in hollows below the earth and so shakes it, 
for though the earth is really all of it equally porous, its surface 
is clogged up by rain. This implies that part of the whole sphere 
is 'above' and part 'below': 'above' being the part on which we 
live, 'below' the other. 

This theory is perhaps too primitive to require refutation. It is 
absurd to think of up and down otherwise than as meaning that 
heavy bodies move to the earth from every quarter, and light 
ones, such as fire, away from it; especially as we see that, as far 
as our knowledge of the earth goes, the horizon always changes 
with a change in our position, which proves that the earth is 
convex and spherical. It is absurd, too, to maintain that the 
earth rests on the air because of its size, and then to say that 
impact upwards from below shakes it right through. Besides he 
gives no account of the circumstances attendant on 
earthquakes: for not every country or every season is subject to 
them. 



1097 



Democritus says that the earth is full of water and that when a 
quantity of rain-water is added to this an earthquake is the 
result. The hollows in the earth being unable to admit the 
excess of water it forces its way in and so causes an earthquake. 
Or again, the earth as it dries draws the water from the fuller to 
the emptier parts, and the inrush of the water as it changes its 
place causes the earthquake. 

Anaximenes says that the earth breaks up when it grows wet or 
dry, and earthquakes are due to the fall of these masses as they 
break away. Hence earthquakes take place in times of drought 
and again of heavy rain, since, as we have explained, the earth 
grows dry in time of drought and breaks up, whereas the rain 
makes it sodden and destroys its cohesion. 

But if this were the case the earth ought to be found to be 
sinking in many places. Again, why do earthquakes frequently 
occur in places which are not excessively subject to drought or 
rain, as they ought to be on the theory? Besides, on this view, 
earthquakes ought always to be getting fewer, and should come 
to an end entirely some day: the notion of contraction by 
packing together implies this. So this is impossible the theory 
must be impossible too. 



8 

We have already shown that wet and dry must both give rise to 
an evaporation: earthquakes are a necessary consequence of 
this fact. The earth is essentially dry, but rain fills it with 
moisture. Then the sun and its own fire warm it and give rise to 
a quantity of wind both outside and inside it. This wind 
sometimes flows outwards in a single body, sometimes inwards, 
and sometimes it is divided. All these are necessary laws. Next 



1098 



we must find out what body has the greatest motive force. This 
will certainly be the body that naturally moves farthest and is 
most violent. Now that which has the most rapid motion is 
necessarily the most violent; for its swiftness gives its impact 
the greatest force. Again, the rarest body, that which can most 
readily pass through every other body, is that which naturally 
moves farthest. Wind satisfies these conditions in the highest 
degree (fire only becomes flame and moves rapidly when wind 
accompanies it): so that not water nor earth is the cause of 
earthquakes but wind - that is, the inrush of the external 
evaporation into the earth. 

Hence, since the evaporation generally follows in a continuous 
body in the direction in which it first started, and either all of it 
flows inwards or all outwards, most earthquakes and the 
greatest are accompanied by calm. It is true that some take 
place when a wind is blowing, but this presents no difficulty. We 
sometimes find several winds blowing simultaneously. If one of 
these enters the earth we get an earthquake attended by wind. 
Only these earthquakes are less severe because their source and 
cause is divided. 

Again, most earthquakes and the severest occur at night or, if by 
day, about noon, that being generally the calmest part of the 
day. For when the sun exerts its full power (as it does about 
noon) it shuts the evaporation into the earth. Night, too, is 
calmer than day. The absence of the sun makes the evaporation 
return into the earth like a sort of ebb tide, corresponding to the 
outward flow; especially towards dawn, for the winds, as a rule, 
begin to blow then, and if their source changes about like the 
Euripus and flows inwards the quantity of wind in the earth is 
greater and a more violent earthquake results. 

The severest earthquakes take place where the sea is full of 
currents or the earth spongy and cavernous: so they occur near 



1099 



the Hellespont and in Achaea and Sicily, and those parts of 
Euboea which correspond to our description - where the sea is 
supposed to flow in channels below the earth. The hot springs, 
too, near Aedepsus are due to a cause of this kind. It is the 
confined character of these places that makes them so liable to 
earthquakes. A great and therefore violent wind is developed, 
which would naturally blow away from the earth: but the 
onrush of the sea in a great mass thrusts it back into the earth. 
The countries that are spongy below the surface are exposed to 
earthquakes because they have room for so much wind. 

For the same reason earthquakes usually take place in spring 
and autumn and in times of wet and of drought - because these 
are the windiest seasons. Summer with its heat and winter with 
its frost cause calm: winter is too cold, summer too dry for 
winds to form. In time of drought the air is full of wind; drought 
is just the predominance of the dry over the moist evaporation. 
Again, excessive rain causes more of the evaporation to form in 
the earth. Then this secretion is shut up in a narrow compass 
and forced into a smaller space by the water that fills the 
cavities. Thus a great wind is compressed into a smaller space 
and so gets the upper hand, and then breaks out and beats 
against the earth and shakes it violently. 

We must suppose the action of the wind in the earth to be 
analogous to the tremors and throbbings caused in us by the 
force of the wind contained in our bodies. Thus some 
earthquakes are a sort of tremor, others a sort of throbbing. 
Again, we must think of an earthquake as something like the 
tremor that often runs through the body after passing water as 
the wind returns inwards from without in one volume. 

The force wind can have may be gathered not only from what 
happens in the air (where one might suppose that it owed its 
power to produce such effects to its volume), but also from what 



1100 



is observed in animal bodies. Tetanus and spasms are motions 
of wind, and their force is such that the united efforts of many 
men do not succeed in overcoming the movements of the 
patients. We must suppose, then (to compare great things with 
small), that what happens in the earth is just like that. Our 
theory has been verified by actual observation in many places. It 
has been known to happen that an earthquake has continued 
until the wind that caused it burst through the earth into the air 
and appeared visibly like a hurricane. This happened lately near 
Heracleia in Pontus and some time past at the island Hiera, one 
of the group called the Aeolian islands. Here a portion of the 
earth swelled up and a lump like a mound rose with a noise: 
finally it burst, and a great wind came out of it and threw up 
live cinders and ashes which buried the neighbouring town of 
Lipara and reached some of the towns in Italy. The spot where 
this eruption occurred is still to be seen. 

Indeed, this must be recognized as the cause of the fire that is 
generated in the earth: the air is first broken up in small 
particles and then the wind is beaten about and so catches fire. 

A phenomenon in these islands affords further evidence of the 
fact that winds move below the surface of the earth. When a 
south wind is going to blow there is a premonitory indication: a 
sound is heard in the places from which the eruptions issue. 
This is because the sea is being pushed on from a distance and 
its advance thrusts back into the earth the wind that was 
issuing from it. The reason why there is a noise and no 
earthquake is that the underground spaces are so extensive in 
proportion to the quantity of the air that is being driven on that 
the wind slips away into the void beyond. 

Again, our theory is supported by the facts that the sun appears 
hazy and is darkened in the absence of clouds, and that there is 
sometimes calm and sharp frost before earthquakes at sunrise. 



1101 



The sun is necessarily obscured and darkened when the 
evaporation which dissolves and rarefies the air begins to 
withdraw into the earth. The calm, too, and the cold towards 
sunrise and dawn follow from the theory. The calm we have 
already explained. There must as a rule be calm because the 
wind flows back into the earth: again, it must be most marked 
before the more violent earthquakes, for when the wind is not 
part outside earth, part inside, but moves in a single body, its 
strength must be greater. The cold comes because the 
evaporation which is naturally and essentially hot enters the 
earth. (Wind is not recognized to be hot, because it sets the air 
in motion, and that is full of a quantity of cold vapour. It is the 
same with the breath we blow from our mouth: close by it is 
warm, as it is when we breathe out through the mouth, but 
there is so little of it that it is scarcely noticed, whereas at a 
distance it is cold for the same reason as wind.) Well, when this 
evaporation disappears into the earth the vaporous exhalation 
concentrates and causes cold in any place in which this 
disappearance occurs. 

A sign which sometimes precedes earthquakes can be 
explained in the same way. Either by day or a little after sunset, 
in fine weather, a little, light, long-drawn cloud is seen, like a 
long very straight line. This is because the wind is leaving the 
air and dying down. Something analogous to this happens on 
the sea-shore. When the sea breaks in great waves the marks 
left on the sand are very thick and crooked, but when the sea is 
calm they are slight and straight (because the secretion is 
small). As the sea is to the shore so the wind is to the cloudy air; 
so, when the wind drops, this very straight and thin cloud is 
left, a sort of wave-mark in the air. 

An earthquake sometimes coincides with an eclipse of the 
moon for the same reason. When the earth is on the point of 
being interposed, but the light and heat of the sun has not quite 



1102 



vanished from the air but is dying away, the wind which causes 
the earthquake before the eclipse, turns off into the earth, and 
calm ensues. For there often are winds before eclipses: at 
nightfall if the eclipse is at midnight, and at midnight if the 
eclipse is at dawn. They are caused by the lessening of the 
warmth from the moon when its sphere approaches the point 
at which the eclipse is going to take place. So the influence 
which restrained and quieted the air weakens and the air 
moves again and a wind rises, and does so later, the later the 
eclipse. 

A severe earthquake does not stop at once or after a single 
shock, but first the shocks go on, often for about forty days; 
after that, for one or even two years it gives premonitory 
indications in the same place. The severity of the earthquake is 
determined by the quantity of wind and the shape of the 
passages through which it flows. Where it is beaten back and 
cannot easily find its way out the shocks are most violent, and 
there it must remain in a cramped space like water that cannot 
escape. Any throbbing in the body does not cease suddenly or 
quickly, but by degrees according as the affection passes off. So 
here the agency which created the evaporation and gave it an 
impulse to motion clearly does not at once exhaust the whole of 
the material from which it forms the wind which we call an 
earthquake. So until the rest of this is exhausted the shocks 
must continue, though more gently, and they must go on until 
there is too little of the evaporation left to have any perceptible 
effect on the earth at all. 

Subterranean noises, too, are due to the wind; sometimes they 
portend earthquakes but sometimes they have been heard 
without any earthquake following. Just as the air gives off 
various sounds when it is struck, so it does when it strikes other 
things; for striking involves being struck and so the two cases 
are the same. The sound precedes the shock because sound is 



1103 



thinner and passes through things more readily than wind. But 
when the wind is too weak by reason of thinness to cause an 
earthquake the absence of a shock is due to its filtering through 
readily, though by striking hard and hollow masses of different 
shapes it makes various noises, so that the earth sometimes 
seems to 'bellow' as the portentmongers say. 

Water has been known to burst out during an earthquake. But 
that does not make water the cause of the earthquake. The 
wind is the efficient cause whether it drives the water along the 
surface or up from below: just as winds are the causes of waves 
and not waves of winds. Else we might as well say that earth 
was the cause; for it is upset in an earthquake, just like water 
(for effusion is a form of upsetting). No, earth and water are 
material causes (being patients, not agents): the true cause is 
the wind. 

The combination of a tidal wave with an earthquake is due to 
the presence of contrary winds. It occurs when the wind which 
is shaking the earth does not entirely succeed in driving off the 
sea which another wind is bringing on, but pushes it back and 
heaps it up in a great mass in one place. Given this situation it 
follows that when this wind gives way the whole body of the 
sea, driven on by the other wind, will burst out and overwhelm 
the land. This is what happened in Achaea. There a south wind 
was blowing, but outside a north wind; then there was a calm 
and the wind entered the earth, and then the tidal wave came 
on and simultaneously there was an earthquake. This was the 
more violent as the sea allowed no exit to the wind that had 
entered the earth, but shut it in. So in their struggle with one 
another the wind caused the earthquake, and the wave by its 
settling down the inundation. 

Earthquakes are local and often affect a small district only; 
whereas winds are not local. Such phenomena are local when 



1104 



the evaporations at a given place are joined by those from the 
next and unite; this, as we explained, is what happens when 
there is drought or excessive rain locally. Now earthquakes do 
come about in this way but winds do not. For earthquakes, 
rains, and droughts have their source and origin inside the 
earth, so that the sun is not equally able to direct all the 
evaporations in one direction. But on the evaporations in the air 
the sun has more influence so that, when once they have been 
given an impulse by its motion, which is determined by its 
various positions, they flow in one direction. 

When the wind is present in sufficient quantity there is an 
earthquake. The shocks are horizontal like a tremor; except 
occasionally, in a few places, where they act vertically, upwards 
from below, like a throbbing. It is the vertical direction which 
makes this kind of earthquake so rare. The motive force does 
not easily accumulate in great quantity in the position required, 
since the surface of the earth secretes far more of the 
evaporation than its depths. Wherever an earthquake of this 
kind does occur a quantity of stones comes to the surface of the 
earth (as when you throw up things in a winnowing fan), as we 
see from Sipylus and the Phlegraean plain and the district in 
Liguria, which were devastated by this kind of earthquake. 

Islands in the middle of the sea are less exposed to earthquakes 
than those near land. First, the volume of the sea cools the 
evaporations and overpowers them by its weight and so crushes 
them. Then, currents and not shocks are produced in the sea by 
the action of the winds. Again, it is so extensive that 
evaporations do not collect in it but issue from it, and these 
draw the evaporations from the earth after them. Islands near 
the continent really form part of it: the intervening sea is not 
enough to make any difference; but those in the open sea can 
only be shaken if the whole of the sea that surrounds them is 
shaken too. 



1105 



We have now explained earthquakes, their nature and cause, 
and the most important of the circumstances attendant on 
their appearance. 



Let us go on to explain lightning and thunder, and further 
whirlwind, fire-wind, and thunderbolts: for the cause of them 
all is the same. 

As we have said, there are two kinds of exhalation, moist and 
dry, and the atmosphere contains them both potentially. It, as 
we have said before, condenses into cloud, and the density of 
the clouds is highest at their upper limit. (For they must be 
denser and colder on the side where the heat escapes to the 
upper region and leaves them. This explains why hurricanes 
and thunderbolts and all analogous phenomena move 
downwards in spite of the fact that everything hot has a natural 
tendency upwards. Just as the pips that we squeeze between 
our fingers are heavy but often jump upwards: so these things 
are necessarily squeezed out away from the densest part of the 
cloud.) Now the heat that escapes disperses to the up region. 
But if any of the dry exhalation is caught in the process as the 
air cools, it is squeezed out as the clouds contract, and collides 
in its rapid course with the neighbouring clouds, and the sound 
of this collision is what we call thunder. This collision is 
analogous, to compare small with great, to the sound we hear in 
a flame which men call the laughter or the threat of Hephaestus 
or of Hestia. This occurs when the wood dries and cracks and 
the exhalation rushes on the flame in a body. So in the clouds, 
the exhalation is projected and its impact on dense clouds 
causes thunder: the variety of the sound is due to the 



1106 



irregularity of the clouds and the hollows that intervene where 
their density is interrupted. This then, is thunder, and this its 
cause. 

It usually happens that the exhalation that is ejected is 
inflamed and burns with a thin and faint fire: this is what we 
call lightning, where we see as it were the exhalation coloured 
in the act of its ejection. It comes into existence after the 
collision and the thunder, though we see it earlier because sight 
is quicker than hearing. The rowing of triremes illustrates this: 
the oars are going back again before the sound of their striking 
the water reaches us. 

However, there are some who maintain that there is actually 
fire in the clouds. Empedocles says that it consists of some of 
the sun's rays which are intercepted: Anaxagoras that it is part 
of the upper ether (which he calls fire) which has descended 
from above. Lightning, then, is the gleam of this fire, and 
thunder the hissing noise of its extinction in the cloud. 

But this involves the view that lightning actually is prior to 
thunder and does not merely appear to be so. Again, this 
intercepting of the fire is impossible on either theory, but 
especially it is said to be drawn down from the upper ether. 
Some reason ought to be given why that which naturally 
ascends should descend, and why it should not always do so, 
but only when it is cloudy. When the sky is clear there is no 
lightning: to say that there is, is altogether wanton. 

The view that the heat of the sun's rays intercepted in the 
clouds is the cause of these phenomena is equally unattractive: 
this, too, is a most careless explanation. Thunder, lightning, and 
the rest must have a separate and determinate cause assigned 
to them on which they ensue. But this theory does nothing of 
the sort. It is like supposing that water, snow, and hail existed 
all along and were produced when the time came and not 



1107 



generated at all, as if the atmosphere brought each to hand out 
of its stock from time to time. They are concretions in the same 
way as thunder and lightning are discretions, so that if it is true 
of either that they are not generated but pre-exist, the same 
must be true of the other. Again, how can any distinction be 
made about the intercepting between this case and that of 
interception in denser substances such as water? Water, too, is 
heated by the sun and by fire: yet when it contracts again and 
grows cold and freezes no such ejection as they describe occurs, 
though it ought on their the. to take place on a proportionate 
scale. Boiling is due to the exhalation generated by fire: but it is 
impossible for it to exist in the water beforehand; and besides 
they call the noise 'hissing', not 'boiling'. But hissing is really 
boiling on a small scale: for when that which is brought into 
contact with moisture and is in process of being extinguished 
gets the better of it, then it boils and makes the noise in 
question. Some - Cleidemus is one of them - say that lightning 
is nothing objective but merely an appearance. They compare it 
to what happens when you strike the sea with a rod by night 
and the water is seen to shine. They say that the moisture in the 
cloud is beaten about in the same way, and that lightning is the 
appearance of brightness that ensues. 

This theory is due to ignorance of the theory of reflection, 
which is the real cause of that phenomenon. The water appears 
to shine when struck because our sight is reflected from it to 
some bright object: hence the phenomenon occurs mainly by 
night: the appearance is not seen by day because the daylight is 
too in, tense and obscures it. 

These are the theories of others about thunder and lightning: 
some maintaining that lightning is a reflection, the others that 
lightning is fire shining through the cloud and thunder its 
extinction, the fire not being generated in each case but existing 
beforehand. We say that the same stuff is wind on the earth, 



1108 



and earthquake under it, and in the clouds thunder. The 
essential constituent of all these phenomena is the same: 
namely, the dry exhalation. If it flows in one direction it is wind, 
in another it causes earthquakes; in the clouds, when they are 
in a process of change and contract and condense into water, it 
is ejected and causes thunder and lightning and the other 
phenomena of the same nature. 

So much for thunder and lightning. 



Book III 



Let us explain the remaining operations of this secretion in the 
same way as we have treated the rest. When this exhalation is 
secreted in small and scattered quantities and frequently, and is 
transitory, and its constitution rare, it gives rise to thunder and 
lightning. But if it is secreted in a body and is denser, that is, 
less rare, we get a hurricane. The fact that it issues in body 
explains its violence: it is due to the rapidity of the secretion. 
Now when this secretion issues in a great and continuous 
current the result corresponds to what we get when the 
opposite development takes place and rain and a quantity of 
water are produced. As far as the matter from which they are 
developed goes both sets of phenomena are the same. As soon 
as a stimulus to the development of either potentiality appears, 
that of which there is the greater quantity present in the cloud 



1109 



is at once secreted from it, and there results either rain, or, if the 
other exhalation prevails, a hurricane. 

Sometimes the exhalation in the cloud, when it is being 
secreted, collides with another under circumstances like those 
found when a wind is forced from an open into a narrow space 
in a gateway or a road. It often happens in such cases that the 
first part of the moving body is deflected because of the 
resistance due either to the narrowness or to a contrary current, 
and so the wind forms a circle and eddy. It is prevented from 
advancing in a straight line: at the same time it is pushed on 
from behind; so it is compelled to move sideways in the 
direction of least resistance. The same thing happens to the 
next part, and the next, and so on, till the series becomes one, 
that is, till a circle is formed: for if a figure is described by a 
single motion that figure must itself be one. This is how eddies 
are generated on the earth, and the case is the same in the 
clouds as far as the beginning of them goes. Only here (as in the 
case of the hurricane which shakes off the cloud without 
cessation and becomes a continuous wind) the cloud follows 
the exhalation unbroken, and the exhalation, failing to break 
away from the cloud because of its density, first moves in a 
circle for the reason given and then descends, because clouds 
are always densest on the side where the heat escapes. This 
phenomenon is called a whirlwind when it is colourless; and it 
is a sort of undigested hurricane. There is never a whirlwind 
when the weather is northerly, nor a hurricane when there is 
snow. The reason is that all these phenomena are 'wind', and 
wind is a dry and warm evaporation. Now frost and cold prevail 
over this principle and quench it at its birth: that they do prevail 
is clear or there could be no snow or northerly rain, since these 
occur when the cold does prevail. 

So the whirlwind originates in the failure of an incipient 
hurricane to escape from its cloud: it is due to the resistance 



1110 



which generates the eddy, and it consists in the spiral which 
descends to the earth and drags with it the cloud which it 
cannot shake off. It moves things by its wind in the direction in 
which it is blowing in a straight line, and whirls round by its 
circular motion and forcibly snatches up whatever it meets. 

When the cloud burns as it is drawn downwards, that is, when 
the exhalation becomes rarer, it is called a fire-wind, for its fire 
colours the neighbouring air and inflames it. 

When there is a great quantity of exhalation and it is rare and is 
squeezed out in the cloud itself we get a thunderbolt. If the 
exhalation is exceedingly rare this rareness prevents the 
thunderbolt from scorching and the poets call it 'bright': if the 
rareness is less it does scorch and they call it 'smoky'. The 
former moves rapidly because of its rareness, and because of its 
rapidity passes through an object before setting fire to it or 
dwelling on it so as to blacken it: the slower one does blacken 
the object, but passes through it before it can actually burn it. 
Further, resisting substances are affected, unresisting ones are 
not. For instance, it has happened that the bronze of a shield 
has been melted while the woodwork remained intact because 
its texture was so loose that the exhalation filtered through 
without affecting it. So it has passed through clothes, too, 
without burning them, and has merely reduced them to shreds. 

Such evidence is enough by itself to show that the exhalation is 
at work in all these cases, but we sometimes get direct evidence 
as well, as in the case of the conflagration of the temple at 
Ephesus which we lately witnessed. There independent sheets 
of flame left the main fire and were carried bodily in many 
directions. Now that smoke is exhalation and that smoke burns 
is certain, and has been stated in another place before; but 
when the flame moves bodily, then we have ocular proof that 
smoke is exhalation. On this occasion what is seen in small 



1111 



fires appeared on a much larger scale because of the quantity of 
matter that was burning. The beams which were the source of 
the exhalation split, and a quantity of it rushed in a body from 
the place from which it issued forth and went up in a blaze: so 
that the flame was actually seen moving through the air away 
and falling on the houses. For we must recognize that 
exhalation accompanies and precedes thunderbolts though it is 
colourless and so invisible. Hence, where the thunderbolt is 
going to strike, the object moves before it is struck, showing that 
the exhalation leads the way and falls on the object first. 
Thunder, too, splits things not by its noise but because the 
exhalation that strikes the object and that which makes the 
noise are ejected simultaneously. This exhalation splits the 
thing it strikes but does not scorch it at all. 

We have now explained thunder and lightning and hurricane, 
and further firewinds, whirlwinds, and thunderbolts, and 
shown that they are all of them forms of the same thing and 
wherein they all differ. 



Let us now explain the nature and cause of halo, rainbow, mock 
suns, and rods, since the same account applies to them all. 

We must first describe the phenomena and the circumstances 
in which each of them occurs. The halo often appears as a 
complete circle: it is seen round the sun and the moon and 
bright stars, by night as well as by day, and at midday or in the 
afternoon, more rarely about sunrise or sunset. 

The rainbow never forms a full circle, nor any segment greater 
than a semicircle. At sunset and sunrise the circle is smallest 



1112 



and the segment largest: as the sun rises higher the circle is 
larger and the segment smaller. After the autumn equinox in 
the shorter days it is seen at every hour of the day, in the 
summer not about midday. There are never more than two 
rainbows at one time. Each of them is three-coloured; the 
colours are the same in both and their number is the same, but 
in the outer rainbow they are fainter and their position is 
reversed. In the inner rainbow the first and largest band is red; 
in the outer rainbow the band that is nearest to this one and 
smallest is of the same colour: the other bands correspond on 
the same principle. These are almost the only colours which 
painters cannot manufacture: for there are colours which they 
create by mixing, but no mixing will give red, green, or purple. 
These are the colours of the rainbow, though between the red 
and the green an orange colour is often seen. 

Mock suns and rods are always seen by the side of the sun, not 
above or below it nor in the opposite quarter of the sky. They are 
not seen at night but always in the neighbourhood of the sun, 
either as it is rising or setting but more commonly towards 
sunset. They have scarcely ever appeared when the sun was on 
the meridian, though this once happened in Bosporus where 
two mock suns rose with the sun and followed it all through the 
day till sunset. 

These are the facts about each of these phenomena: the cause 
of them all is the same, for they are all reflections. But they are 
different varieties, and are distinguished by the surface from 
which and the way in which the reflection to the sun or some 
other bright object takes place. 

The rainbow is seen by day, and it was formerly thought that it 
never appeared by night as a moon rainbow. This opinion was 
due to the rarity of the occurrence: it was not observed, for 
though it does happen it does so rarely. The reason is that the 



1113 



colours are not so easy to see in the dark and that many other 
conditions must coincide, and all that in a single day in the 
month. For if there is to be one it must be at full moon, and then 
as the moon is either rising or setting. So we have only met with 
two instances of a moon rainbow in more than fifty years. 

We must accept from the theory of optics the fact that sight is 
reflected from air and any object with a smooth surface just as 
it is from water; also that in some mirrors the forms of things 
are reflected, in others only their colours. Of the latter kind are 
those mirrors which are so small as to be indivisible for sense. It 
is impossible that the figure of a thing should be reflected in 
them, for if it is the mirror will be sensibly divisible since 
divisibility is involved in the notion of figure. But since 
something must be reflected in them and figure cannot be, it 
remains that colour alone should be reflected. The colour of a 
bright object sometimes appears bright in the reflection, but it 
sometimes, either owing to the admixture of the colour of the 
mirror or to weakness of sight, gives rise to the appearance of 
another colour. 

However, we must accept the account we have given of these 
things in the theory of sensation, and take some things for 
granted while we explain others. 



Let us begin by explaining the shape of the halo; why it is a 
circle and why it appears round the sun or the moon or one of 
the other stars: the explanation being in all these cases the 
same. 



1114 



Sight is reflected in this way when air and vapour are 
condensed into a cloud and the condensed matter is uniform 
and consists of small parts. Hence in itself it is a sign of rain, 
but if it fades away, of fine weather, if it is broken up, of wind. 
For if it does not fade away and is not broken up but is allowed 
to attain its normal state, it is naturally a sign of rain since it 
shows that a process of condensation is proceeding which 
must, when it is carried to an end, result in rain. For the same 
reason these haloes are the darkest. It is a sign of wind when it 
is broken up because its breaking up is due to a wind which 
exists there but has not reached us. This view finds support in 
the fact that the wind blows from the quarter in which the main 
division appears in the halo. Its fading away is a sign of fine 
weather because if the air is not yet in a state to get the better 
of the heat it contains and proceed to condense into water, this 
shows that the moist vapour has not yet separated from the dry 
and firelike exhalation: and this is the cause of fine weather. 

So much for the atmospheric conditions under which the 
reflection takes place. The reflection is from the mist that forms 
round the sun or the moon, and that is why the halo is not seen 
opposite the sun like the rainbow. 

Since the reflection takes place in the same way from every 
point the result is necessarily a circle or a segment of a circle: 
for if the lines start from the same point and end at the same 
point and are equal, the points where they form an angle will 
always lie on a circle. 

Let AGB and AZB and ADB be lines each of which goes from the 
point A to the point B and forms an angle. Let the lines AG, AZ, 
AD be equal and those at B, GB, ZB, DB equal too. (See diagram.) 

Draw the line AEB. Then the triangles are equal; for their base 
AEB is equal. Draw perpendiculars to AEB from the angles; GE 
from G, ZE from Z, DE from D. Then these perpendiculars are 



1115 



equal, being in equal triangles. And they are all in one plane, 
being all at right angles to AEB and meeting at a single point E. 
So if you draw the line it will be a circle and E its centre. Now B 
is the sun, A the eye, and the circumference passing through the 
points GZD the cloud from which the line of sight is reflected to 
the sun. 

The mirrors must be thought of as contiguous: each of them is 
too small to be visible, but their contiguity makes the whole 
made up of them all to seem one. The bright band is the sun, 
which is seen as a circle, appearing successively in each of the 
mirrors as a point indivisible to sense. The band of cloud next to 
it is black, its colour being intensified by contrast with the 
brightness of the halo. The halo is formed rather near the earth 
because that is calmer: for where there is wind it is clear that 
no halo can maintain its position. 

Haloes are commoner round the moon because the greater heat 
of the sun dissolves the condensations of the air more rapidly. 

Haloes are formed round stars for the same reasons, but they 
are not prognostic in the same way because the condensation 
they imply is so insignificant as to be barren. 



We have already stated that the rainbow is a reflection: we have 
now to explain what sort of reflection it is, to describe its 
various concomitants, and to assign their causes. 

Sight is reflected from all smooth surfaces, such as are air and 
water among others. Air must be condensed if it is to act as a 
mirror, though it often gives a reflection even uncondensed 



1116 



when the sight is weak. Such was the case of a man whose sight 
was faint and indistinct. He always saw an image in front of 
him and facing him as he walked. This was because his sight 
was reflected back to him. Its morbid condition made it so weak 
and delicate that the air close by acted as a mirror, just as 
distant and condensed air normally does, and his sight could 
not push it back. So promontories in the sea 'loom' when there 
is a south-east wind, and everything seems bigger, and in a 
mist, too, things seem bigger: so, too, the sun and the stars 
seem bigger when rising and setting than on the meridian. But 
things are best reflected from water, and even in process of 
formation it is a better mirror than air, for each of the particles, 
the union of which constitutes a raindrop, is necessarily a better 
mirror than mist. Now it is obvious and has already been stated 
that a mirror of this kind renders the colour of an object only, 
but not its shape. Hence it follows that when it is on the point of 
raining and the air in the clouds is in process of forming into 
raindrops but the rain is not yet actually there, if the sun is 
opposite, or any other object bright enough to make the cloud a 
mirror and cause the sight to be reflected to the object then the 
reflection must render the colour of the object without its 
shape. Since each of the mirrors is so small as to be invisible 
and what we see is the continuous magnitude made up of them 
all, the reflection necessarily gives us a continuous magnitude 
made up of one colour; each of the mirrors contributing the 
same colour to the whole. We may deduce that since these 
conditions are realizable there will be an appearance due to 
reflection whenever the sun and the cloud are related in the 
way described and we are between them. But these are just the 
conditions under which the rainbow appears. So it is clear that 
the rainbow is a reflection of sight to the sun. 

So the rainbow always appears opposite the sun whereas the 
halo is round it. They are both reflections, but the rainbow is 
distinguished by the variety of its colours. The reflection in the 



1117 



one case is from water which is dark and from a distance; in the 
other from air which is nearer and lighter in colour. White light 
through a dark medium or on a dark surface (it makes no 
difference) looks red. We know how red the flame of green wood 
is: this is because so much smoke is mixed with the bright 
white firelight: so, too, the sun appears red through smoke and 
mist. That is why in the rainbow reflection the outer 
circumference is red (the reflection being from small particles of 
water), but not in the case of the halo. The other colours shall be 
explained later. Again, a condensation of this kind cannot 
persist in the neighbourhood of the sun: it must either turn to 
rain or be dissolved, but opposite to the sun there is an interval 
during which the water is formed. If there were not this 
distinction haloes would be coloured like the rainbow. Actually 
no complete or circular halo presents this colour, only small and 
fragmentary appearances called 'rods'. But if a haze due to 
water or any other dark substance formed there we should have 
had, as we maintain, a complete rainbow like that which we do 
find lamps. A rainbow appears round these in winter, generally 
with southerly winds. Persons whose eyes are moist see it most 
clearly because their sight is weak and easily reflected. It is due 
to the moistness of the air and the soot which the flame gives 
off and which mixes with the air and makes it a mirror, and to 
the blackness which that mirror derives from the smoky nature 
of the soot. The light of the lamp appears as a circle which is 
not white but purple. It shows the colours of the rainbow; but 
because the sight that is reflected is too weak and the mirror 
too dark, red is absent. The rainbow that is seen when oars are 
raised out of the sea involves the same relative positions as that 
in the sky, but its colour is more like that round the lamps, 
being purple rather than red. The reflection is from very small 
particles continuous with one another, and in this case the 
particles are fully formed water. We get a rainbow, too, if a man 
sprinkles fine drops in a room turned to the sun so that the sun 



1118 



is shining in part of the room and throwing a shadow in the 
rest. Then if one man sprinkles in the room, another, standing 
outside, sees a rainbow where the sun's rays cease and make 
the shadow. Its nature and colour is like that from the oars and 
its cause is the same, for the sprinkling hand corresponds to the 
oar. 

That the colours of the rainbow are those we described and how 
the other colours come to appear in it will be clear from the 
following considerations. We must recognize, as we have said, 
and lay down: first, that white colour on a black surface or seen 
through a black medium gives red; second, that sight when 
strained to a distance becomes weaker and less; third, that 
black is in a sort the negation of sight: an object is black because 
sight fails; so everything at a distance looks blacker, because 
sight does not reach it. The theory of these matters belongs to 
the account of the senses, which are the proper subjects of such 
an inquiry; we need only state about them what is necessary for 
us. At all events, that is the reason why distant objects and 
objects seen in a mirror look darker and smaller and smoother, 
why the reflection of clouds in water is darker than the clouds 
themselves. This latter is clearly the case: the reflection 
diminishes the sight that reaches them. It makes no difference 
whether the change is in the object seen or. in the sight, the 
result being in either case the same. The following fact further 
is worth noticing. When there is a cloud near the sun and we 
look at it does not look coloured at all but white, but when we 
look at the same cloud in water it shows a trace of rainbow 
colouring. Clearly, then, when sight is reflected it is weakened 
and, as it makes dark look darker, so it makes white look less 
white, changing it and bringing it nearer to black. When the 
sight is relatively strong the change is to red; the next stage is 
green, and a further degree of weakness gives violet. No further 
change is visible, but three completes the series of colours (as 
we find three does in most other things), and the change into 



1119 



the rest is imperceptible to sense. Hence also the rainbow 
appears with three colours; this is true of each of the two, but in 
a contrary way. The outer band of the primary rainbow is red: 
for the largest band reflects most sight to the sun, and the outer 
band is largest. The middle band and the third go on the same 
principle. So if the principles we laid down about the 
appearance of colours are true the rainbow necessarily has 
three colours, and these three and no others. The appearance of 
yellow is due to contrast, for the red is whitened by its 
juxtaposition with green. We can see this from the fact that the 
rainbow is purest when the cloud is blackest; and then the red 
shows most yellow. (Yellow in the rainbow comes between red 
and green.) So the whole of the red shows white by contrast 
with the blackness of the cloud around: for it is white compared 
to the cloud and the green. Again, when the rainbow is fading 
away and the red is dissolving, the white cloud is brought into 
contact with the green and becomes yellow. But the moon 
rainbow affords the best instance of this colour contrast. It 
looks quite white: this is because it appears on the dark cloud 
and at night. So, just as fire is intensified by added fire, black 
beside black makes that which is in some degree white look 
quite white. Bright dyes too show the effect of contrast. In 
woven and embroidered stuffs the appearance of colours is 
profoundly affected by their juxtaposition with one another 
(purple, for instance, appears different on white and on black 
wool), and also by differences of illumination. Thus 
embroiderers say that they often make mistakes in their colours 
when they work by lamplight, and use the wrong ones. 

We have now shown why the rainbow has three colours and 
that these are its only colours. The same cause explains the 
double rainbow and the faintness of the colours in the outer 
one and their inverted order. When sight is strained to a great 
distance the appearance of the distant object is affected in a 
certain way: and the same thing holds good here. So the 



1120 



reflection from the outer rainbow is weaker because it takes 
place from a greater distance and less of it reaches the sun, and 
so the colours seen are fainter. Their order is reversed because 
more reflection reaches the sun from the smaller, inner band. 
For that reflection is nearer to our sight which is reflected from 
the band which is nearest to the primary rainbow. Now the 
smallest band in the outer rainbow is that which is nearest, and 
so it will be red; and the second and the third will follow the 
same principle. Let B be the outer rainbow, A the inner one; let R 
stand for the red colour, G for green, V for violet; yellow appears 
at the point Y. Three rainbows or more are not found because 
even the second is fainter, so that the third reflection can have 
no strength whatever and cannot reach the sun at all. (See 
diagram.) 



The rainbow can never be a circle nor a segment of a circle 
greater than a semicircle. The consideration of the diagram will 
prove this and the other properties of the rainbow. (See 
diagram.) 

Let A be a hemisphere resting on the circle of the horizon, let its 
centre be K and let H be another point appearing on the 
horizon. Then, if the lines that fall in a cone from K have HK as 
their axis, and, K and M being joined, the lines KM are reflected 
from the hemisphere to H over the greater angle, the lines from 
K will fall on the circumference of a circle. If the reflection takes 
place when the luminous body is rising or setting the segment 
of the circle above the earth which is cut off by the horizon will 
be a semi-circle; if the luminous body is above the horizon it 
will always be less than a semicircle, and it will be smallest 



1121 



when the luminous body culminates. First let the luminous 
body be appearing on the horizon at the point H, and let KM be 
reflected to H, and let the plane in which A is, determined by 
the triangle HKM, be produced. Then the section of the sphere 
will be a great circle. Let it be A (for it makes no difference 
which of the planes passing through the line HK and 
determined by the triangle KMH is produced). Now the lines 
drawn from H and K to a point on the semicircle A are in a 
certain ratio to one another, and no lines drawn from the same 
points to another point on that semicircle can have the same 
ratio. For since both the points H and K and the line KH are 
given, the line MH will be given too; consequently the ratio of 
the line MH to the line MK will be given too. So M will touch a 
given circumference. Let this be NM. Then the intersection of 
the circumferences is given, and the same ratio cannot hold 
between lines in the same plane drawn from the same points to 
any other circumference but MN. 

Draw a line DB outside of the figure and divide it so that 
D:B=MH:MK. But MH is greater than MK since the reflection of 
the cone is over the greater angle (for it subtends the greater 
angle of the triangle KMH). Therefore D is greater than B. Then 
add to B a line Z such that B+Z:D=D:B. Then make another line 
having the same ratio to B as KH has to Z, and join MI. 

Then I is the pole of the circle on which the lines from K fall. For 
the ratio of D to IM is the same as that of Z to KH and of B to KI. 
If not, let D be in the same ratio to a line indifferently lesser or 
greater than IM, and let this line be IP. Then HK and KI and IP 
will have the same ratios to one another as Z, B, and D. But the 
ratios between Z, B, and D were such that Z+B:D=D: B. Therefore 
IH:IP=IP:IK. Now, if the points K, H be joined with the point P by 
the lines HP, KP, these lines will be to one another as IH is to IP, 
for the sides of the triangles HIP, KPI about the angle I are 
homologous. Therefore, HP too will be to KP as HI is to IP. But 



1122 



this is also the ratio of MH to MK, for the ratio both of HI to IP 
and of MH to MK is the same as that of D to B. Therefore, from 
the points H, K there will have been drawn lines with the same 
ratio to one another, not only to the circumference MN but to 
another point as well, which is impossible. Since then D cannot 
bear that ratio to any line either lesser or greater than IM (the 
proof being in either case the same), it follows that it must 
stand in that ratio to MI itself. Therefore as MI is to IK so IH will 
be to MI and finally MH to MK. 

If, then, a circle be described with I as pole at the distance MI it 
will touch all the angles which the lines from H and K make by 
their reflection. If not, it can be shown, as before, that lines 
drawn to different points in the semicircle will have the same 
ratio to one another, which was impossible. If, then, the 
semicircle A be revolved about the diameter HKI, the lines 
reflected from the points H, K at the point M will have the same 
ratio, and will make the angle KMH equal, in every plane. 
Further, the angle which HM and MI make with HI will always 
be the same. So there are a number of triangles on HI and KI 
equal to the triangles HMI and KMI. Their perpendiculars will 
fall on HI at the same point and will be equal. Let be the point 
on which they fall. Then is the centre of the circle, half of 
which, MN, is cut off by the horizon. (See diagram.) 

Next let the horizon be ABG but let H have risen above the 
horizon. Let the axis now be HI. The proof will be the same for 
the rest as before, but the pole I of the circle will be below the 
horizon AG since the point H has risen above the horizon. But 
the pole, and the centre of the circle, and the centre of that 
circle (namely HI) which now determines the position of the sun 
are on the same line. But since KH lies above the diameter AG, 
the centre will be at on the line KI below the plane of the 
circle AG determined the position of the sun before. So the 
segment YX which is above the horizon will be less than a 



1123 



semicircle. For YXM was a semicircle and it has now been cut 
off by the horizon AG. So part of it, YM, will be invisible when 
the sun has risen above the horizon, and the segment visible 
will be smallest when the sun is on the meridian; for the higher 
H is the lower the pole and the centre of the circle will be. 

In the shorter days after the autumn equinox there may be a 
rainbow at any time of the day, but in the longer days from the 
spring to the autumn equinox there cannot be a rainbow about 
midday. The reason for this is that when the sun is north of the 
equator the visible arcs of its course are all greater than a 
semicircle, and go on increasing, while the invisible arc is small, 
but when the sun is south of the equator the visible arc is small 
and the invisible arc great, and the farther the sun moves south 
of the equator the greater is the invisible arc. Consequently, in 
the days near the summer solstice, the size of the visible arc is 
such that before the point H reaches the middle of that arc, that 
is its point of culmination, the point is well below the horizon; 
the reason for this being the great size of the visible arc, and the 
consequent distance of the point of culmination from the earth. 
But in the days near the winter solstice the visible arcs are 
small, and the contrary is necessarily the case: for the sun is on 
the meridian before the point H has risen far. 



Mock suns, and rods too, are due to the causes we have 
described. A mock sun is caused by the reflection of sight to the 
sun. Rods are seen when sight reaches the sun under 
circumstances like those which we described, when there are 
clouds near the sun and sight is reflected from some liquid 
surface to the cloud. Here the clouds themselves are colourless 



1124 



when you look at them directly, but in the water they are full of 
rods. The only difference is that in this latter case the colour of 
the cloud seems to reside in the water, but in the case of rods 
on the cloud itself. Rods appear when the composition of the 
cloud is uneven, dense in part and in part rare, and more and 
less watery in different parts. Then the sight is reflected to the 
sun: the mirrors are too small for the shape of the sun to 
appear, but, the bright white light of the sun, to which the sight 
is reflected, being seen on the uneven mirror, its colour appears 
partly red, partly green or yellow. It makes no difference 
whether sight passes through or is reflected from a medium of 
that kind; the colour is the same in both cases; if it is red in the 
first case it must be the same in the other. 

Rods then are occasioned by the unevenness of the mirror - as 
regards colour, not form. The mock sun, on the contrary, 
appears when the air is very uniform, and of the same density 
throughout. This is why it is white: the uniform character of the 
mirror gives the reflection in it a single colour, while the fact 
that the sight is reflected in a body and is thrown on the sun all 
together by the mist, which is dense and watery though not yet 
quite water, causes the sun's true colour to appear just as it 
does when the reflection is from the dense, smooth surface of 
copper. So the sun's colour being white, the mock sun is white 
too. This, too, is the reason why the mock sun is a surer sign of 
rain than the rods; it indicates, more than they do, that the air is 
ripe for the production of water. Further a mock sun to the 
south is a surer sign of rain than one to the north, for the air in 
the south is readier to turn into water than that in the north. 

Mock suns and rods are found, as we stated, about sunset and 
sunrise, not above the sun nor below it, but beside it. They are 
not found very close to the sun, nor very far from it, for the sun 
dissolves the cloud if it is near, but if it is far off the reflection 
cannot take place, since sight weakens when it is reflected from 



1125 



a small mirror to a very distant object. (This is why a halo is 
never found opposite to the sun.) If the cloud is above the sun 
and close to it the sun will dissolve it; if it is above the sun but 
at a distance the sight is too weak for the reflection to take 
place, and so it will not reach the sun. But at the side of the sun, 
it is possible for the mirror to be at such an interval that the sun 
does not dissolve the cloud, and yet sight reaches it 
undiminished because it moves close to the earth and is not 
dissipated in the immensity of space. It cannot subsist below 
the sun because close to the earth the sun's rays would dissolve 
it, but if it were high up and the sun in the middle of the 
heavens, sight would be dissipated. Indeed, even by the side of 
the sun, it is not found when the sun is in the middle of the sky, 
for then the line of vision is not close to the earth, and so but 
little sight reaches the mirror and the reflection from it is 
altogether feeble. 

Some account has now been given of the effects of the secretion 
above the surface of the earth; we must go on to describe its 
operations below, when it is shut up in the parts of the earth. 

Just as its twofold nature gives rise to various effects in the 
upper region, so here it causes two varieties of bodies. We 
maintain that there are two exhalations, one vaporous the other 
smoky, and there correspond two kinds of bodies that originate 
in the earth, 'fossiles' and metals. The heat of the dry exhalation 
is the cause of all 'fossiles'. Such are the kinds of stones that 
cannot be melted, and realgar, and ochre, and ruddle, and 
sulphur, and the other things of that kind, most 'fossiles' being 
either coloured lye or, like cinnabar, a stone compounded of it. 
The vaporous exhalation is the cause of all metals, those bodies 
which are either fusible or malleable such as iron, copper, gold. 
All these originate from the imprisonment of the vaporous 
exhalation in the earth, and especially in stones. Their dryness 
compresses it, and it congeals just as dew or hoar-frost does 



1126 



when it has been separated off, though in the present case the 
metals are generated before that segregation occurs. Hence, 
they are water in a sense, and in a sense not. Their matter was 
that which might have become water, but it can no longer do so: 
nor are they, like savours, due to a qualitative change in actual 
water. Copper and gold are not formed like that, but in every 
case the evaporation congealed before water was formed. 
Hence, they all (except gold) are affected by fire, and they 
possess an admixture of earth; for they still contain the dry 
exhalation. 

This is the general theory of all these bodies, but we must take 
up each kind of them and discuss it separately. 



Book IV 



We have explained that the qualities that constitute the 
elements are four, and that their combinations determine the 
number of the elements to be four. 

Two of the qualities, the hot and the cold, are active; two, the 
dry and the moist, passive. We can satisfy ourselves of this by 
looking at instances. In every case heat and cold determine, 
conjoin, and change things of the same kind and things of 
different kinds, moistening, drying, hardening, and softening 
them. Things dry and moist, on the other hand, both in isolation 



1127 



and when present together in the same body are the subjects of 
that determination and of the other affections enumerated. The 
account we give of the qualities when we define their character 
shows this too. Hot and cold we describe as active, for 
'congregating' is essentially a species of 'being active': moist 
and dry are passive, for it is in virtue of its being acted upon in a 
certain way that a thing is said to be 'easy to determine' or 
'difficult to determine'. So it is clear that some of the qualities 
are active and some passive. 

Next we must describe the operations of the active qualities and 
the forms taken by the passive. First of all, true becoming, that 
is, natural change, is always the work of these powers and so is 
the corresponding natural destruction; and this becoming and 
this destruction are found in plants and animals and their 
parts. True natural becoming is a change introduced by these 
powers into the matter underlying a given thing when they are 
in a certain ratio to that matter, which is the passive qualities 
we have mentioned. When the hot and the cold are masters of 
the matter they generate a thing: if they are not, and the failure 
is partial, the object is imperfectly boiled or otherwise 
unconcocted. But the strictest general opposite of true 
becoming is putrefaction. All natural destruction is on the way 
to it, as are, for instance, growing old or growing dry. 
Putrescence is the end of all these things, that is of all natural 
objects, except such as are destroyed by violence: you can burn, 
for instance, flesh, bone, or anything else, but the natural course 
of their destruction ends in putrefaction. Hence things that 
putrefy begin by being moist and end by being dry. For the moist 
and the dry were their matter, and the operation of the active 
qualities caused the dry to be determined by the moist. 

Destruction supervenes when the determined gets the better of 
the determining by the help of the environment (though in a 
special sense the word putrefaction is applied to partial 



1128 



destruction, when a thing's nature is perverted). Hence 
everything, except fire, is liable to putrefy; for earth, water, and 
air putrefy, being all of them matter relatively to fire. The 
definition of putrefaction is: the destruction of the peculiar and 
natural heat in any moist subject by external heat, that is, by 
the heat of the environment. So since lack of heat is the ground 
of this affection and everything in as far as it lacks heat is cold, 
both heat and cold will be the causes of putrefaction, which will 
be due indifferently to cold in the putrefying subject or to heat 
in the environment. 

This explains why everything that putrefies grows drier and 
ends by becoming earth or dung. The subject's own heat departs 
and causes the natural moisture to evaporate with it, and then 
there is nothing left to draw in moisture, for it is a thing's 
peculiar heat that attracts moisture and draws it in. Again, 
putrefaction takes place less in cold that in hot seasons, for in 
winter the surrounding air and water contain but little heat and 
it has no power, but in summer there is more. Again, what is 
frozen does not putrefy, for its cold is greater that the heat of 
the air and so is not mastered, whereas what affects a thing 
does master it. Nor does that which is boiling or hot putrefy, for 
the heat in the air being less than that in the object does not 
prevail over it or set up any change. So too anything that is 
flowing or in motion is less apt to putrefy than a thing at rest, 
for the motion set up by the heat in the air is weaker than that 
pre-existing in the object, and so it causes no change. For the 
same reason a great quantity of a thing putrefies less readily 
than a little, for the greater quantity contains too much proper 
fire and cold for the corresponding qualities in the environment 
to get the better of. Hence, the sea putrefies quickly when 
broken up into parts, but not as a whole; and all other waters 
likewise. Animals too are generated in putrefying bodies, 
because the heat that has been secreted, being natural, 
organizes the particles secreted with it. 



1129 



So much for the nature of becoming and of destruction. 



We must now describe the next kinds of processes which the 
qualities already mentioned set up in actually existing natural 
objects as matter. 

Of these concoction is due to heat; its species are ripening, 
boiling, broiling. Inconcoction is due to cold and its species are 
rawness, imperfect boiling, imperfect broiling. (We must 
recognize that the things are not properly denoted by these 
words: the various classes of similar objects have no names 
universally applicable to them; consequently we must think of 
the species enumerated as being not what those words denote 
but something like it.) Let us say what each of them is. 
Concoction is a process in which the natural and proper heat of 
an object perfects the corresponding passive qualities, which 
are the proper matter of any given object. For when concoction 
has taken place we say that a thing has been perfected and has 
come to be itself. It is the proper heat of a thing that sets up this 
perfecting, though external influences may contribute in some 
degrees to its fulfilment. Baths, for instance, and other things of 
the kind contribute to the digestion of food, but the primary 
cause is the proper heat of the body. In some cases of 
concoction the end of the process is the nature of the thing - 
nature, that is, in the sense of the formal cause and essence. In 
other cases it leads to some presupposed state which is 
attained when the moisture has acquired certain properties or a 
certain magnitude in the process of being broiled or boiled or of 
putrefying, or however else it is being heated. This state is the 
end, for when it has been reached the thing has some use and 



1130 



we say that concoction has taken place. Must is an instance of 
this, and the matter in boils when it becomes purulent, and 
tears when they become rheum, and so with the rest. 

Concoction ensues whenever the matter, the moisture, is 
mastered. For the matter is what is determined by the heat 
connatural to the object, and as long as the ratio between them 
exists in it a thing maintains its nature. Hence things like the 
liquid and solid excreta and ejecta in general are signs of 
health, and concoction is said to have taken place in them, for 
they show that the proper heat has got the better of the 
indeterminate matter. 

Things that undergo a process of concoction necessarily 
become thicker and hotter, for the action of heat is to make 
things more compact, thicker, and drier. 

This then is the nature of concoction: but inconcoction is an 
imperfect state due to lack of proper heat, that is, to cold. That 
of which the imperfect state is, is the corresponding passive 
qualities which are the natural matter of anything. 

So much for the definition of concoction and inconcoction. 



Ripening is a sort of concoction; for we call it ripening when 
there is a concoction of the nutriment in fruit. And since 
concoction is a sort of perfecting, the process of ripening is 
perfect when the seeds in fruit are able to reproduce the fruit in 
which they are found; for in all other cases as well this is what 
we mean by 'perfect'. This is what 'ripening' means when the 
word is applied to fruit. However, many other things that have 



1131 



undergone concoction are said to be 'ripe', the general character 
of the process being the same, though the word is applied by an 
extension of meaning. The reason for this extension is, as we 
explained before, that the various modes in which natural heat 
and cold perfect the matter they determine have not special 
names appropriated to them. In the case of boils and phlegm, 
and the like, the process of ripening is the concoction of the 
moisture in them by their natural heat, for only that which gets 
the better of matter can determine it. So everything that ripens 
is condensed from a spirituous into a watery state, and from a 
watery into an earthy state, and in general from being rare 
becomes dense. In this process the nature of the thing that is 
ripening incorporates some of the matter in itself, and some it 
rejects. So much for the definition of ripening. 

Rawness is its opposite and is therefore an imperfect 
concoction of the nutriment in the fruit, namely, of the 
undetermined moisture. Consequently a raw thing is either 
spirituous or watery or contains both spirit and water. Ripening 
being a kind of perfecting, rawness will be an imperfect state, 
and this state is due to a lack of natural heat and its 
disproportion to the moisture that is undergoing the process of 
ripening. (Nothing moist ripens without the admixture of some 
dry matter: water alone of liquids does not thicken.) This 
disproportion may be due either to defect of heat or to excess of 
the matter to be determined: hence the juice of raw things is 
thin, cold rather than hot, and unfit for food or drink. Rawness, 
like ripening, is used to denote a variety of states. Thus the 
liquid and solid excreta and catarrhs are called raw for the 
same reason, for in every case the word is applied to things 
because their heat has not got the mastery in them and 
compacted them. If we go further, brick is called raw and so is 
milk and many other things too when they are such as to admit 
of being changed and compacted by heat but have remained 
unaffected. Hence, while we speak of 'boiled' water, we cannot 



1132 



speak of raw water, since it does not thicken. We have now 
defined ripening and rawness and assigned their causes. 

Boiling is, in general, a concoction by moist heat of the 
indeterminate matter contained in the moisture of the thing 
boiled, and the word is strictly applicable only to things boiled 
in the way of cooking. The indeterminate matter, as we said, 
will be either spirituous or watery. The cause of the concoction 
is the fire contained in the moisture; for what is cooked in a 
frying-pan is broiled: it is the heat outside that affects it and, as 
for the moisture in which it is contained, it dries this up and 
draws it into itself. But a thing that is being boiled behaves in 
the opposite way: the moisture contained in it is drawn out of it 
by the heat in the liquid outside. Hence boiled meats are drier 
than broiled; for, in boiling, things do not draw the moisture 
into themselves, since the external heat gets the better of the 
internal: if the internal heat had got the better it would have 
drawn the moisture to itself. Not every body admits of the 
process of boiling: if there is no moisture in it, it does not (for 
instance, stones), nor does it if there is moisture in it but the 
density of the body is too great for it to be mastered, as in the 
case of wood. But only those bodies can be boiled that contain 
moisture which can be acted on by the heat contained in the 
liquid outside. It is true that gold and wood and many other 
things are said to be 'boiled': but this is a stretch of the meaning 
of the word, though the kind of thing intended is the same, the 
reason for the usage being that the various cases have no 
names appropriated to them. Liquids too, like milk and must, 
are said to undergo a process of 'boiling' when the external fire 
that surrounds and heats them changes the savour in the liquid 
into a given form, the process being thus in a way like what we 
have called boiling. 

The end of the things that undergo boiling, or indeed any form 
of concoction, is not always the same: some are meant to be 



1133 



eaten, some drunk, and some are intended for other uses; for 
instance dyes, too, are said to be 'boiled'. 

All those things then admit of 'boiling' which can grow denser, 
smaller, or heavier; also those which do that with a part of 
themselves and with a part do the opposite, dividing in such a 
way that one portion thickens while the other grows thinner, 
like milk when it divides into whey and curd. Oil by itself is 
affected in none of these ways, and therefore cannot be said to 
admit of 'boiling'. Such then is the pfcies of concoction known 
as 'boiling', and the process is the same in an artificial and in a 
natural instrument, for the cause will be the same in every case. 

Imperfect boiling is the form of inconcoction opposed to boiling. 
Now the opposite of boiling properly so called is an 
inconcoction of the undetermined matter in a body due to lack 
of heat in the surrounding liquid. (Lack of heat implies, as we 
have pointed out, the presence of cold.) The motion which 
causes imperfect boiling is different from that which causes 
boiling, for the heat which operates the concoction is driven 
out. The lack of heat is due either to the amount of cold in the 
liquid or to the quantity of moisture in the object undergoing 
the process of boiling. Where either of these conditions is 
realized the heat in the surrounding liquid is too great to have 
no effect at all, but too small to carry out the process of 
concocting uniformly and thoroughly. Hence things are harder 
when they are imperfectly boiled than when they are boiled, 
and the moisture in them more distinct from the solid parts. So 
much for the definition and causes of boiling and imperfect 
boiling. 

Broiling is concoction by dry foreign heat. Hence if a man were 
to boil a thing but the change and concoction in it were due, not 
to the heat of the liquid but to that of the fire, the thing will 
have been broiled and not boiled when the process has been 



1134 



carried to completion: if the process has gone too far we use the 
word 'scorched' to describe it. If the process leaves the thing 
drier at the end the agent has been dry heat. Hence the outside 
is drier than the inside, the opposite being true of things boiled. 
Where the process is artificial, broiling is more difficult than 
boiling, for it is difficult to heat the inside and the outside 
uniformly, since the parts nearer to the fire are the first to get 
dry and consequently get more intensely dry. In this way the 
outer pores contract and the moisture in the thing cannot be 
secreted but is shut in by the closing of the pores. Now broiling 
and boiling are artificial processes, but the same general kind of 
thing, as we said, is found in nature too. The affections 
produced are similar though they lack a name; for art imitates 
nature. For instance, the concoction of food in the body is like 
boiling, for it takes place in a hot and moist medium and the 
agent is the heat of the body. So, too, certain forms of 
indigestion are like imperfect boiling. And it is not true that 
animals are generated in the concoction of food, as some say. 
Really they are generated in the excretion which putrefies in the 
lower belly, and they ascend afterwards. For concoction goes on 
in the upper belly but the excretion putrefies in the lower: the 
reason for this has been explained elsewhere. 

We have seen that the opposite of boiling is imperfect boiling: 
now there is something correspondingly opposed to the species 
of concoction called broiling, but it is more difficult to find a 
name for it. It would be the kind of thing that would happen if 
there were imperfect broiling instead of broiling proper through 
lack of heat due to deficiency in the external fire or to the 
quantity of water in the thing undergoing the process. For then 
we should get too much heat for no effect to be produced, but 
too little for concoction to take place. 

We have now explained concoction and inconcoction, ripening 
and rawness, boiling and broiling, and their opposites. 



1135 



We must now describe the forms taken by the passive qualities 
the moist and the dry. The elements of bodies, that is, the 
passive ones, are the moist and the dry; the bodies themselves 
are compounded of them and whichever predominates 
determines the nature of the body; thus some bodies partake 
more of the dry, others of the moist. All the forms to be 
described will exist either actually, or potentially and in their 
opposite: for instance, there is actual melting and on the other 
hand that which admits of being melted. 

Since the moist is easily determined and the dry determined 
with difficulty, their relation to one another is like that of a dish 
and its condiments. The moist is what makes the dry 
determinable, and each serves as a sort of glue to the other - as 
Empedocles said in his poem on Nature, 'glueing meal together 
by means of water.' Thus the determined body involves them 
both. Of the elements earth is especially representative of the 
dry, water of the moist, and therefore all determinate bodies in 
our world involve earth and water. Every body shows the quality 
of that element which predominates in it. It is because earth 
and water are the material elements of all bodies that animals 
live in them alone and not in air or fire. 

Of the qualities of bodies hardness and softness are those 
which must primarily belong to a determined thing, for 
anything made up of the dry and the moist is necessarily either 
hard or soft. Hard is that the surface of which does not yield 
into itself; soft that which does yield but not by interchange of 
place: water, for instance, is not soft, for its surface does not 
yield to pressure or sink in but there is an interchange of place. 



1136 



Those things are absolutely hard and soft which satisfy the 
definition absolutely, and those things relatively so which do so 
compared with another thing. Now relatively to one another 
hard and soft are indefinable, because it is a matter of degree, 
but since all the objects of sense are determined by reference to 
the faculty of sense it is clearly the relation to touch which 
determines that which is hard and soft absolutely, and touch is 
that which we use as a standard or mean. So we call that which 
exceeds it hard and that which falls short of it soft. 



A body determined by its own boundary must be either hard or 
soft; for it either yields or does not. 

It must also be concrete: or it could not be so determined. So 
since everything that is determined and solid is either hard or 
soft and these qualities are due to concretion, all composite and 
determined bodies must involve concretion. Concretion 
therefore must be discussed. 

Now there are two causes besides matter, the agent and the 
quality brought about, the agent being the efficient cause, the 
quality the formal cause. Hence concretion and disaggregation, 
drying and moistening, must have these two causes. 

But since concretion is a form of drying let us speak of the latter 
first. 

As we have explained, the agent operates by means of two 
qualities and the patient is acted on in virtue of two qualities: 
action takes place by means of heat or cold, and the quality is 
produced either by the presence or by the absence of heat or 



1137 



cold; but that which is acted upon is moist or dry or a 
compound of both. Water is the element characterized by the 
moist, earth that characterized by the dry, for these among the 
elements that admit the qualities moist and dry are passive. 
Therefore cold, too, being found in water and earth (both of 
which we recognize to be cold), must be reckoned rather as a 
passive quality. It is active only as contributing to destruction or 
incidentally in the manner described before; for cold is 
sometimes actually said to burn and to warm, but not in the 
same way as heat does, but by collecting and concentrating 
heat. 

The subjects of drying are water and the various watery fluids 
and those bodies which contain water either foreign or 
connatural. By foreign I mean like the water in wool, by 
connatural, like that in milk. The watery fluids are wine, urine, 
whey, and in general those fluids which have no sediment or 
only a little, except where this absence of sediment is due to 
viscosity. For in some cases, in oil and pitch for instance, it is 
the viscosity which prevents any sediment from appearing. 

It is always a process of heating or cooling that dries things, but 
the agent in both cases is heat, either internal or external. For 
even when things are dried by cooling, like a garment, where 
the moisture exists separately it is the internal heat that dries 
them. It carries off the moisture in the shape of vapour (if there 
is not too much of it), being itself driven out by the surrounding 
cold. So everything is dried, as we have said, by a process either 
of heating or cooling, but the agent is always heat, either 
internal or external, carrying off the moisture in vapour. By 
external heat I mean as where things are boiled: by internal 
where the heat breathes out and takes away and uses up its 
moisture. So much for drying. 



1138 



Liquefaction is, first, condensation into water; second, the 
melting of a solidified body. The first, condensation, is due to 
the cooling of vapour: what melting is will appear from the 
account of solidification. 

Whatever solidifies is either water or a mixture of earth and 
water, and the agent is either dry heat or cold. Hence those of 
the bodies solidified by heat or cold which are soluble at all are 
dissolved by their opposites. Bodies solidified by the dry-hot are 
dissolved by water, which is the moist-cold, while bodies 
solidified by cold are dissolved by fire, which is hot. Some things 
seem to be solidified by water, e.g. boiled honey, but really it is 
not the water but the cold in the water which effects the 
solidification. Aqueous bodies are not solidified by fire: for it is 
fire that dissolves them, and the same cause in the same 
relation cannot have opposite effects upon the same thing. 
Again, water solidifies owing to the departure of heat; so it will 
clearly be dissolved by the entry into it of heat: cold, therefore, 
must be the agent in solidifying it. 

Hence aqueous bodies do not thicken when they solidify; for 
thickening occurs when the moisture goes off and the dry 
matter comes together, but water is the only liquid that does 
not thicken. Those bodies that are made up of both earth and 
water are solidified both by fire and by cold and in either case 
are thickened. The operation of the two is in a way the same 
and in a way different. Heat acts by drawing off the moisture, 
and as the moisture goes off in vapour the dry matter thickens 
and collects. Cold acts by driving out the heat, which is 
accompanied by the moisture as this goes off in vapour with it. 
Bodies that are soft but not liquid do not thicken but solidify 
when the moisture leaves them, e.g. potter's clay in process of 



1139 



baking: but those mixed bodies that are liquid thicken besides 
solidifying, like milk. Those bodies which have first been 
thickened or hardened by cold often begin by becoming moist: 
thus potter's clay at first in the process of baking steams and 
grows softer, and is liable to distortion in the ovens for that 
reason. 

Now of the bodies solidified by cold which are made up both of 
earth and water but in which the earth preponderates, those 
which solidify by the departure of heat melt by heat when it 
enters into them again; this is the case with frozen mud. But 
those which solidify by refrigeration, where all the moisture has 
gone off in vapour with the heat, like iron and horn, cannot be 
dissolved except by excessive heat, but they can be softened - 
though manufactured iron does melt, to the point of becoming 
fluid and then solidifying again. This is how steel is made. The 
dross sinks to the bottom and is purged away: when this has 
been done often and the metal is pure we have steel. The 
process is not repeated often because the purification of the 
metal involves great waste and loss of weight. But the iron that 
has less dross is the better iron. The stone pyrimachus, too, 
melts and forms into drops and becomes fluid; after having 
been in a fluid state it solidifies and becomes hard again. 
Millstones, too, melt and become fluid: when the fluid mass 
begins to solidify it is black but its consistency comes to be like 
that of lime, and earth, too 

Of the bodies which are solidified by dry heat some are 
insoluble, others are dissolved by liquid. Pottery and some kinds 
of stone that are formed out of earth burnt up by fire, such as 
millstones, cannot be dissolved. Natron and salt are soluble by 
liquid, but not all liquid but only such as is cold. Hence water 
and any of its varieties melt them, but oil does not. For the 
opposite of the dry-hot is the cold-moist and what the one 



1140 



solidified the other will dissolve, and so opposites will have 
opposite effects. 



If a body contains more water than earth fire only thickens it: if 
it contains more earth fire solidifies it. Hence natron and salt 
and stone and potter's clay must contain more earth. 

The nature of oil presents the greatest problem. If water 
preponderated in it, cold ought to solidify it; if earth 
preponderated, then fire ought to do so. Actually neither 
solidifies, but both thicken it. The reason is that it is full of air 
(hence it floats on the top of water, since air tends to rise). Cold 
thickens it by turning the air in it into water, for any mixture of 
oil and water is thicker than either. Fire and the lapse of time 
thicken and whiten it. The whitening follows on the evaporation 
of any water that may have been in it; the is due to the change 
of the air into water as the heat in the oil is dissipated. The 
effect in both cases is the same and the cause is the same, but 
the manner of its operation is different. Both heat and cold 
thicken it, but neither dries it (neither the sun nor cold dries oil), 
not only because it is glutinous but because it contains air. Its 
glutinous nature prevents it from giving off vapour and so fire 
does not dry it or boil it off. 

Those bodies which are made up of earth and water may be 
classified according to the preponderance of either. There is a 
kind of wine, for instance, which both solidifies and thickens by 
boiling - I mean, must. All bodies of this kind lose their water as 
they That it is their water may be seen from the fact that the 
vapour from them condenses into water when collected. So 
wherever some sediment is left this is of the nature of earth. 



1141 



Some of these bodies, as we have said, are also thickened and 
dried by cold. For cold not only solidifies but also dries water, 
and thickens things by turning air into water. (Solidifying, as we 
have said, is a form of drying.) Now those things that are not 
thickened by cold, but solidified, belong rather to water, e.g.. 
wine, urine, vinegar, lye, whey. But those things that are 
thickened (not by evaporation due to fire) are made up either of 
earth or of water and air: honey of earth, while oil contains air. 
Milk and blood, too, are made up of both water and earth, 
though earth generally predominates in them. So, too, are the 
liquids out of which natron and salt are formed; and stones are 
also formed from some mixtures of this kind. Hence, if the whey 
has not been separated, it burns away if you boil it over a fire. 
But the earthy element in milk can also be coagulated by the 
help of fig-juice, if you boil it in a certain way as doctors do 
when they treat it with fig-juice, and this is how the whey and 
the cheese are commonly separated. Whey, once separated, 
does not thicken, as the milk did, but boils away like water. 
Sometimes, however, there is little or no cheese in milk, and 
such milk is not nutritive and is more like water. The case of 
blood is similar: cold dries and so solidifies it. Those kinds of 
blood that do not solidify, like that of the stag, belong rather to 
water and are very cold. Hence they contain no fibres: for the 
fibres are of earth and solid, and blood from which they have 
been removed does not solidify. This is because it cannot dry; 
for what remains is water, just as what remains of milk when 
cheese has been removed is water. The fact that diseased blood 
will not solidify is evidence of the same thing, for such blood is 
of the nature of serum and that is phlegm and water, the nature 
of the animal having failed to get the better of it and digest it. 

Some of these bodies are soluble, e.g. natron, some insoluble, 
e.g. pottery: of the latter, some, like horn, can be softened by 
heat, others, like pottery and stone, cannot. The reason is that 
opposite causes have opposite effects: consequently, if 



1142 



solidification is due to two causes, the cold and the dry, solution 
must be due to the hot and the moist, that is, to fire and to 
water (these being opposites): water dissolving what was 
solidified by fire alone, fire what was solidified by cold alone. 
Consequently, if any things happen to be solidified by the action 
of both, these are least apt to be soluble. Such a case we find 
where things have been heated and are then solidified by cold. 
When the heat in leaving them has caused most of the 
moisture to evaporate, the cold so compacts these bodies 
together again as to leave no entrance even for moisture. 
Therefore heat does not dissolve them (for it only dissolves 
those bodies that are solidified by cold alone), nor does water 
(for it does not dissolve what cold solidifies, but only what is 
solidified by dry heat). But iron is melted by heat and solidified 
by cold. Wood consists of earth and air and is therefore 
combustible but cannot be melted or softened by heat. (For the 
same reason it floats in water - all except ebony. This does not, 
for other kinds of wood contain a preponderance of air, but in 
black ebony the air has escaped and so earth preponderates in 
it.) Pottery consists of earth alone because it solidified gradually 
in the process of drying. Water cannot get into it, for the pores 
were only large enough to admit of vapour escaping: and seeing 
that fire solidified it, that cannot dissolve it either. 

So solidification and melting, their causes, and the kinds of 
subjects in which they occur have been described. 



8 

All this makes it clear that bodies are formed by heat and cold 
and that these agents operate by thickening and solidifying. It is 
because these qualities fashion bodies that we find heat in all of 



1143 



them, and in some cold in so far as heat is absent. These 
qualities, then, are present as active, and the moist and the dry- 
as passive, and consequently all four are found in mixed bodies. 
So water and earth are the constituents of homogeneous bodies 
both in plants and in animals and of metals such as gold, silver, 
and the rest - water and earth and their respective exhalations 
shut up in the compound bodies, as we have explained 
elsewhere. 

All these mixed bodies are distinguished from one another, 
firstly by the qualities special to the various senses, that is, by 
their capacities of action. (For a thing is white, fragrant, sonant, 
sweet, hot, cold in virtue of a power of acting on sense). 
Secondly by other more characteristic affections which express 
their aptitude to be affected: I mean, for instance, the aptitude 
to melt or solidify or bend and so forth, all these qualities, like 
moist and dry, being passive. These are the qualities that 
differentiate bone, flesh, sinew, wood, bark, stone and all other 
homogeneous natural bodies. Let us begin by enumerating 
these qualities expressing the aptitude or inaptitude of a thing 
to be affected in a certain way. They are as follows: to be apt or 
inapt to solidify, melt, be softened by heat, be softened by water, 
bend, break, be comminuted, impressed, moulded, squeezed; to 
be tractile or non-tractile, malleable or non-malleable, to be 
fissile or non-fissile, apt or inapt to be cut; to be viscous or 
friable, compressible or incompressible, combustible or 
incombustible; to be apt or inapt to give off fumes. These 
affections differentiate most bodies from one another. Let us go 
on to explain the nature of each of them. We have already given 
a general account of that which is apt or inapt to solidify or to 
melt, but let us return to them again now. Of all the bodies that 
admit of solidification and hardening, some are brought into 
this state by heat, others by cold. Heat does this by drying up 
their moisture, cold by driving out their heat. Consequently 
some bodies are affected in this way by defect of moisture, 



1144 



some by defect of heat: watery bodies by defect of heat, earthy 
bodies of moisture. Now those bodies that are so affected by 
defect of moisture are dissolved by water, unless like pottery 
they have so contracted that their pores are too small for the 
particles of water to enter. All those bodies in which this is not 
the case are dissolved by water, e.g. natron, salt, dry mud. Those 
bodies that solidified through defect of heat are melted by heat, 
e.g. ice, lead, copper. So much for the bodies that admit of 
solidification and of melting, and those that do not admit of 
melting. 

The bodies which do not admit of solidification are those which 
contain no aqueous moisture and are not watery, but in which 
heat and earth preponderate, like honey and must (for these are 
in a sort of state of effervescence), and those which do possess 
some water but have a preponderance of air, like oil and 
quicksilver, and all viscous substances such as pitch and 
birdlime. 



Those bodies admit of softening which are not (like ice) made 
up of water, but in which earth predominates. All their moisture 
must not have left them (as in the case of natron and salt), nor 
must the relation of dry to moist in them be incongruous (as in 
the case of pottery). They must be tractile (without admitting 
water) or malleable (without consisting of water), and the agent 
in softening them is fire. Such are iron and horn. 

Both of bodies that can melt and of bodies that cannot, some do 
and some do not admit of softening in water. Copper, for 
instance, which can be melted, cannot be softened in water, 
whereas wool and earth can be softened in water, for they can 



1145 



be soaked. (It is true that though copper can be melted the 
agent in its case is not water, but some of the bodies that can be 
melted by water too such as natron and salt cannot be softened 
in water: for nothing is said to be so affected unless the water 
soaks into it and makes it softer.) Some things, on the other 
hand, such as wool and grain, can be softened by water though 
they cannot be melted. Any body that is to be softened by water 
must be of earth and must have its pores larger than the 
particles of water, and the pores themselves must be able to 
resist the action of water, whereas bodies that can be 'melted' 
by water must have pores throughout. 

(Why is it that earth is both 'melted' and softened by moisture, 
while natron is 'melted' but not softened? Because natron is 
pervaded throughout by pores so that the parts are immediately 
divided by the water, but earth has also pores which do not 
connect and is therefore differently affected according as the 
water enters by one or the other set of pores.) 

Some bodies can be bent or straightened, like the reed or the 
withy, some cannot, like pottery and stone. Those bodies are apt 
to be bent and straightened which can change from being 
curved to being straight and from being straight to being 
curved, and bending and straightening consist in the change or 
motion to the straight or to a curve, for a thing is said to be in 
process of being bent whether it is being made to assume a 
convex or a concave shape. So bending is defined as motion to 
the convex or the concave without a change of length. For if we 
added 'or to the straight', we should have a thing bent and 
straight at once, and it is impossible for that which is straight to 
be bent. And if all bending is a bending back or a bending down, 
the former being a change to the convex, the latter to the 
concave, a motion that leads to the straight cannot be called 
bending, but bending and straightening are two different things. 



1146 



These, then, are the things that can, and those that cannot be 
bent, and be straightened. 

Some things can be both broken and comminuted, others admit 
only one or the other. Wood, for instance, can be broken but not 
comminuted, ice and stone can be comminuted but not broken, 
while pottery may either be comminuted or broken. The 
distinction is this: breaking is a division and separation into 
large parts, comminution into parts of any size, but there must 
be more of them than two. Now those solids that have many 
pores not communicating with one another are comminuible 
(for the limit to their subdivision is set by the pores), but those 
whose pores stretch continuously for a long way are breakable, 
while those which have pores of both kinds are both 
comminuible and breakable. 

Some things, e.g. copper and wax, are impressible, others, e.g. 
pottery and water, are not. The process of being impressed is 
the sinking of a part of the surface of a thing in response to 
pressure or a blow, in general to contact. Such bodies are either 
soft, like wax, where part of the surface is depressed while the 
rest remains, or hard, like copper. Non-impressible bodies are 
either hard, like pottery (its surface does not give way and sink 
in), or liquid, like water (for though water does give way it is not 
in a part of it, for there is a reciprocal change of place of all its 
parts). Those impressibles that retain the shape impressed on 
them and are easily moulded by the hand are called 'plastic'; 
those that are not easily moulded, such as stone or wood, or are 
easily moulded but do not retain the shape impressed, like wool 
or a sponge, are not plastic. The last group are said to be 
'squeezable'. Things are 'squeezable' when they can contract 
into themselves under pressure, their surface sinking in without 
being broken and without the parts interchanging position as 
happens in the case of water. (We speak of pressure when there 
is movement and the motor remains in contact with the thing 



1147 



moved, of impact when the movement is due to the local 
movement of the motor.) Those bodies are subject to squeezing 
which have empty pores - empty, that is, of the stuff of which 
the body itself consists - and that can sink upon the void spaces 
within them, or rather upon their pores. For sometimes the 
pores upon which a body sinks in are not empty (a wet sponge, 
for instance, has its pores full). But the pores, if full, must be full 
of something softer than the body itself which is to contract. 
Examples of things squeezable are the sponge, wax, flesh. Those 
things are not squeezable which cannot be made to contract 
upon their own pores by pressure, either because they have no 
pores or because their pores are full of something too hard. 
Thus iron, stone, water and all liquids are incapable of being 
squeezed. 

Things are tractile when their surface can be made to elongate, 
for being drawn out is a movement of the surface, remaining 
unbroken, in the direction of the mover. Some things are 
tractile, e.g. hair, thongs, sinew, dough, birdlime, and some are 
not, e.g. water, stone. Some things are both tractile and 
squeezable, e.g. wool; in other cases the two qualities do not 
coincide; phlegm, for instance, is tractile but not squeezable, 
and a sponge squeezable but not tractile. 

Some things are malleable, like copper. Some are not, like stone 
and wood. Things are malleable when their surface can be made 
to move (but only in part) both downwards and sideways with 
one and the same blow: when this is not possible a body is not 
malleable. All malleable bodies are impressible, but not all 
impressible bodies are malleable, e.g. wood, though on the 
whole the two go together. Of squeezable things some are 
malleable and some not: wax and mud are malleable, wool is 
not. Some things are fissile, e.g. wood, some are not, e.g. potter's 
clay. A thing is fissile when it is apt to divide in advance of the 
instrument dividing it, for a body is said to split when it divides 



1148 



to a further point than that to which the dividing instrument 
divides it and the act of division advances: which is not the case 
with cutting. Those bodies which cannot behave like this are 
non-fissile. Nothing soft is fissile (by soft I mean absolutely soft 
and not relatively: for iron itself may be relatively soft); nor are 
all hard things fissile, but only such as are neither liquid nor 
impressible nor comminuible. Such are the bodies that have the 
pores along which they cohere lengthwise and not crosswise. 

Those hard or soft solids are apt to be cut which do not 
necessarily either split in advance of the instrument or break 
into minute fragments when they are being divided. Those that 
necessarily do so and liquids cannot be cut. Some things can be 
both split and cut, like wood, though generally it is lengthwise 
that a thing can be split and crosswise that it can be cut. For, a 
body being divided into many parts fin so far as its unity is 
made up of many lengths it is apt to be split, in so far as it is 
made up of many breadths it is apt to be cut. 

A thing is viscous when, being moist or soft, it is tractile. Bodies 
owe this property to the interlocking of their parts when they 
are composed like chains, for then they can be drawn out to a 
great length and contracted again. Bodies that are not like this 
are friable. Bodies are compressible when they are squeezable 
and retain the shape they have been squeezed into; 
incompressible when they are either inapt to be squeezed at all 
or do not retain the shape they have been squeezed into. 

Some bodies are combustible and some are not. Wood, wool, 
bone are combustible; stone, ice are not. Bodies are combustible 
when their pores are such as to admit fire and their longitudinal 
pores contain moisture weaker than fire. If they have no 
moisture, or if, as in ice or very green wood, the moisture is 
stronger than fire, they are not combustible. 



1149 



Those bodies give off fumes which contain moisture, but in 
such a form that it does not go off separately in vapour when 
they are exposed to fire. For vapour is a moist secretion tending 
to the nature of air produced from a liquid by the agency of 
burning heat. Bodies that give off fumes give off secretions of 
the nature of air by the lapse of time: as they perish away they 
dry up or become earth. But the kind of secretion we are 
concerned with now differs from others in that it is not moist 
nor does it become wind (which is a continuous flow of air in a 
given direction). Fumes are common secretion of dry and moist 
together caused by the agency of burning heat. Hence they do 
not moisten things but rather colour them. 

The fumes of a woody body are called smoke. (I mean to include 
bones and hair and everything of this kind in the same class. 
For there is no name common to all the objects that I mean, but, 
for all that, these things are all in the same class by analogy. 
Compare what Empedocles says: They are one and the same, 
hair and leaves and the thick wings of birds and scales that 
grow on stout limbs.) The fumes of fat are a sooty smoke and 
those of oily substances a greasy steam. Oil does not boil away 
or thicken by evaporation because it does not give off vapour 
but fumes. Water on the other hand does not give off fumes, but 
vapour. Sweet wine does give off fumes, for it contains fat and 
behaves like oil. It does not solidify under the influence of cold 
and it is apt to burn. Really it is not wine at all in spite of its 
name: for it does not taste like wine and consequently does not 
inebriate as ordinary wine does. It contains but little fumigable 
stuff and consequently is inflammable. 

All bodies are combustible that dissolve into ashes, and all 
bodies do this that solidify under the influence either of heat or 
of both heat and cold; for we find that all these bodies are 
mastered by fire. Of stones the precious stone called carbuncle 
is least amenable to fire. 



1150 



Of combustible bodies some are inflammable and some are not, 
and some of the former are reduced to coals. Those are called 
'inflammable' which produce flame and those which do not are 
called 'non-inflammable'. Those fumigable bodies that are not 
liquid are inflammable, but pitch, oil, wax are inflammable in 
conjunction with other bodies rather than by themselves. Most 
inflammable are those bodies that give off smoke. Of bodies of 
this kind those that contain more earth than smoke are apt to 
be reduced to coals. Some bodies that can be melted are not 
inflammable, e.g. copper; and some bodies that cannot be 
melted are inflammable, e.g. wood; and some bodies can be 
melted and are also inflammable, e.g. frankincense. The reason 
is that wood has its moisture all together and this is continuous 
throughout and so it burns up: whereas copper has it in each 
part but not continuous, and insufficient in quantity to give rise 
to flame. In frankincense it is disposed in both of these ways. 
Fumigable bodies are inflammable when earth predominates in 
them and they are consequently such as to be unable to melt. 
These are inflammable because they are dry like fire. When this 
dry comes to be hot there is fire. This is why flame is burning 
smoke or dry exhalation. The fumes of wood are smoke, those 
of wax and frankincense and such-like, and pitch and whatever 
contains pitch or such-like are sooty smoke, while the fumes of 
oil and oily substances are a greasy steam; so are those of all 
substances which are not at all combustible by themselves 
because there is too little of the dry in them (the dry being the 
means by which the transition to fire is effected), but burn very 
readily in conjunction with something else. (For the fat is just 
the conjunction of the oily with the dry.) So those bodies that 
give off fumes, like oil and pitch, belong rather to the moist, but 
those that burn to the dry. 



1151 



10 

Homogeneous bodies differ to touch - by these affections and 
differences, as we have said. They also differ in respect of their 
smell, taste, and colour. 

By homogeneous bodies I mean, for instance, 'metals', gold, 
copper, silver, tin, iron, stone, and everything else of this kind 
and the bodies that are extracted from them; also the 
substances found in animals and plants, for instance, flesh, 
bones, sinew, skin, viscera, hair, fibres, veins (these are the 
elements of which the non-homogeneous bodies like the face, a 
hand, a foot, and everything of that kind are made up), and in 
plants, wood, bark, leaves, roots, and the rest like them. 

The homogeneous bodies, it is true, are constituted by a 
different cause, but the matter of which they are composed is 
the dry and the moist, that is, water and earth (for these bodies 
exhibit those qualities most clearly). The agents are the hot and 
the cold, for they constitute and make concrete the 
homogeneous bodies out of earth and water as matter. Let us 
consider, then, which of the homogeneous bodies are made of 
earth and which of water, and which of both. 

Of organized bodies some are liquid, some soft, some hard. The 
soft and the hard are constituted by a process of solidification, 
as we have already explained. 

Those liquids that go off in vapour are made of water, those 
that do not are either of the nature of earth, or a mixture either 
of earth and water, like milk, or of earth and air, like wood, or of 
water and air, like oil. Those liquids which are thickened by heat 
are a mixture. (Wine is a liquid which raises a difficulty: for it is 
both liable to evaporation and it also thickens; for instance new 
wine does. The reason is that the word 'wine' is ambiguous and 
different 'wines' behave in different ways. New wine is more 



1152 



earthy than old, and for this reason it is more apt to be 
thickened by heat and less apt to be congealed by cold. For it 
contains much heat and a great proportion of earth, as in 
Arcadia, where it is so dried up in its skins by the smoke that 
you scrape it to drink. If all wine has some sediment in it then it 
will belong to earth or to water according to the quantity of the 
sediment it possesses.) The liquids that are thickened by cold 
are of the nature of earth; those that are thickened either by 
heat or by cold consist of more than one element, like oil and 
honey, and 'sweet wine'. 

Of solid bodies those that have been solidified by cold are of 
water, e.g. ice, snow, hail, hoar-frost. Those solidified by heat are 
of earth, e.g. pottery, cheese, natron, salt. Some bodies are 
solidified by both heat and cold. Of this kind are those solidified 
by refrigeration, that is by the privation both of heat and of the 
moisture which departs with the heat. For salt and the bodies 
that are purely of earth solidify by the privation of moisture 
only, ice by that of heat only, these bodies by that of both. So 
both the active qualities and both kinds of matter were involved 
in the process. Of these bodies those from which all the 
moisture has gone are all of them of earth, like pottery or 
amber. (For amber, also, and the bodies called 'tears' are formed 
by refrigeration, like myrrh, frankincense, gum. Amber, too, 
appears to belong to this class of things: the animals enclosed 
in it show that it is formed by solidification. The heat is driven 
out of it by the cold of the river and causes the moisture to 
evaporate with it, as in the case of honey when it has been 
heated and is immersed in water.) Some of these bodies cannot 
be melted or softened; for instance, amber and certain stones, 
e.g. the stalactites in caves. (For these stalactites, too, are 
formed in the same way: the agent is not fire, but cold which 
drives out the heat, which, as it leaves the body, draws out the 
moisture with it: in the other class of bodies the agent is 
external fire.) In those from which the moisture has not wholly 



1153 



gone earth still preponderates, but they admit of softening by 
heat, e.g. iron and horn. 

Now since we must include among 'meltables' those bodies 
which are melted by fire, these contain some water: indeed 
some of them, like wax, are common to earth and water alike. 
But those that are melted by water are of earth. Those that are 
not melted either by fire or water are of earth, or of earth and 
water. 

Since, then, all bodies are either liquid or solid, and since the 
things that display the affections we have enumerated belong to 
these two classes and there is nothing intermediate, it follows 
that we have given a complete account of the criteria for 
distinguishing whether a body consists of earth or of water or of 
more elements than one, and whether fire was the agent in its 
formation, or cold, or both. 

Gold, then, and silver and copper and tin and lead and glass and 
many nameless stone are of water: for they are all melted by 
heat. Of water, too, are some wines and urine and vinegar and 
lye and whey and serum: for they are all congealed by cold. In 
iron, horn, nails, bones, sinews, wood, hair, leaves, bark, earth 
preponderates. So, too, in amber, myrrh, frankincense, and all 
the substances called 'tears', and stalactites, and fruits, such as 
leguminous plants and corn. For things of this kind are, to a 
greater or less degree, of earth. For of all these bodies some 
admit of softening by heat, the rest give off fumes and are 
formed by refrigeration. So again in natron, salt, and those kinds 
of stones that are not formed by refrigeration and cannot be 
melted. Blood, on the other hand, and semen, are made up of 
earth and water and air. If the blood contains fibres, earth 
preponderates in it: consequently its solidifies by refrigeration 
and is melted by liquids; if not, it is of water and therefore does 



1154 



not solidify. Semen solidifies by refrigeration, its moisture 
leaving it together with its heat. 



11 

We must investigate in the light of the results we have arrived 
at what solid or liquid bodies are hot and what cold. 

Bodies consisting of water are commonly cold, unless (like lye, 
urine, wine) they contain foreign heat. Bodies consisting of 
earth, on the other hand, are commonly hot because heat was 
active in forming them: for instance lime and ashes. 

We must recognize that cold is in a sense the matter of bodies. 
For the dry and the moist are matter (being passive) and earth 
and water are the elements that primarily embody them, and 
they are characterized by cold. Consequently cold must 
predominate in every body that consists of one or other of the 
elements simply, unless such a body contains foreign heat as 
water does when it boils or when it has been strained through 
ashes. This latter, too, has acquired heat from the ashes, for 
everything that has been burnt contains more or less heat. This 
explains the generation of animals in putrefying bodies: the 
putrefying body contains the heat which destroyed its proper 
heat. 

Bodies made up of earth and water are hot, for most of them 
derive their existence from concoction and heat, though some, 
like the waste products of the body, are products of 
putrefaction. Thus blood, semen, marrow, figjuice, and all things 
of the kinds are hot as long as they are in their natural state, but 
when they perish and fall away from that state they are so no 
longer. For what is left of them is their matter and that is earth 



1155 



and water. Hence both views are held about them, some people 
maintaining them to be cold and others to be warm; for they are 
observed to be hot when they are in their natural state, but to 
solidify when they have fallen away from it. That, then, is the 
case of mixed bodies. However, the distinction we laid down 
holds good: if its matter is predominantly water a body is cold 
(water being the complete opposite of fire), but if earth or air it 
tends to be warm. 

It sometimes happens that the coldest bodies can be raised to 
the highest temperature by foreign heat; for the most solid and 
the hardest bodies are coldest when deprived of heat and most 
burning after exposure to fire: thus water is more burning than 
smoke and stone than water. 



12 

Having explained all this we must describe the nature of flesh, 
bone, and the other homogeneous bodies severally. 

Our account of the formation of the homogeneous bodies has 
given us the elements out of which they are compounded and 
the classes into which they fall, and has made it clear to which 
class each of those bodies belongs. The homogeneous bodies 
are made up of the elements, and all the works of nature in turn 
of the homogeneous bodies as matter. All the homogeneous 
bodies consist of the elements described, as matter, but their 
essential nature is determined by their definition. This fact is 
always clearer in the case of the later products of those, in fact, 
that are instruments, as it were, and have an end: it is clearer, 
for instance, that a dead man is a man only in name. And so the 
hand of a dead man, too, will in the same way be a hand in 
name only, just as stone flutes might still be called flutes: for 



1156 



these members, too, are instruments of a kind. But in the case 
of flesh and bone the fact is not so clear to see, and in that of 
fire and water even less. For the end is least obvious there 
where matter predominates most. If you take the extremes, 
matter is pure matter and the essence is pure definition; but the 
bodies intermediate between the two are matter or definition in 
proportion as they are near to either. For each of those elements 
has an end and is not water or fire in any and every condition of 
itself, just as flesh is not flesh nor viscera viscera, and the same 
is true in a higher degree with face and hand. What a thing is 
always determined by its function: a thing really is itself when it 
can perform its function; an eye, for instance, when it can see. 
When a thing cannot do so it is that thing only in name, like a 
dead eye or one made of stone, just as a wooden saw is no more 
a saw than one in a picture. The same, then, is true of flesh, 
except that its function is less clear than that of the tongue. So, 
too, with fire; but its function is perhaps even harder to specify 
by physical inquiry than that of flesh. The parts of plants, and 
inanimate bodies like copper and silver, are in the same case. 
They all are what they are in virtue of a certain power of action 
or passion - just like flesh and sinew. But we cannot state their 
form accurately, and so it is not easy to tell when they are really 
there and when they are not unless the body is thoroughly 
corrupted and its shape only remains. So ancient corpses 
suddenly become ashes in the grave and very old fruit preserves 
its shape only but not its taste: so, too, with the solids that form 
from milk. 

Now heat and cold and the motions they set up as the bodies 
are solidified by the hot and the cold are sufficient to form all 
such parts as are the homogeneous bodies, flesh, bone, hair, 
sinew, and the rest. For they are all of them differentiated by the 
various qualities enumerated above, tension, tractility, 
comminuibility, hardness, softness, and the rest of them: all of 
which are derived from the hot and the cold and the mixture of 



1157 



their motions. But no one would go as far as to consider them 
sufficient in the case of the non-homogeneous parts (like the 
head, the hand, or the foot) which these homogeneous parts go 
to make up. Cold and heat and their motion would be admitted 
to account for the formation of copper or silver, but not for that 
of a saw, a bowl, or a box. So here, save that in the examples 
given the cause is art, but in the nonhomogeneous bodies 
nature or some other cause. 

Since, then, we know to what element each of the 
homogeneous bodies belongs, we must now find the definition 
of each of them, the answer, that is, to the question, 'what is' 
flesh, semen, and the rest? For we know the cause of a thing 
and its definition when we know the material or the formal or, 
better, both the material and the formal conditions of its 
generation and destruction, and the efficient cause of it. 

After the homogeneous bodies have been explained we must 
consider the non-homogeneous too, and lastly the bodies made 
up of these, such as man, plants, and the rest. 



1158 



Aristotle - On the Soul 
[Translated by J. A. Smith] 



Book I 



Holding as we do that, while knowledge of any kind is a thing to 
be honoured and prized, one kind of it may, either by reason of 
its greater exactness or of a higher dignity and greater 
wonderfulness in its objects, be more honourable and precious 
than another, on both accounts we should naturally be led to 
place in the front rank the study of the soul. The knowledge of 
the soul admittedly contributes greatly to the advance of truth 
in general, and, above all, to our understanding of Nature, for 
the soul is in some sense the principle of animal life. Our aim is 
to grasp and understand, first its essential nature, and secondly 
its properties; of these some are taught to be affections proper 
to the soul itself, while others are considered to attach to the 
animal owing to the presence within it of soul. 

To attain any assured knowledge about the soul is one of the 
most difficult things in the world. As the form of question 
which here presents itself, viz. the question 'What is it?', recurs 
in other fields, it might be supposed that there was some single 
method of inquiry applicable to all objects whose essential 
nature (as we are endeavouring to ascertain there is for derived 
properties the single method of demonstration); in that case 
what we should have to seek for would be this unique method. 
But if there is no such single and general method for solving the 
question of essence, our task becomes still more difficult; in the 



1159 



case of each different subject we shall have to determine the 
appropriate process of investigation. If to this there be a clear 
answer, e.g. that the process is demonstration or division, or 
some known method, difficulties and hesitations still beset us - 
with what facts shall we begin the inquiry? For the facts which 
form the starting-points in different subjects must be different, 
as e.g. in the case of numbers and surfaces. 

First, no doubt, it is necessary to determine in which of the 
summa genera soul lies, what it is; is it 'a this-somewhat, 'a 
substance, or is it a quale or a quantum, or some other of the 
remaining kinds of predicates which we have distinguished? 
Further, does soul belong to the class of potential existents, or is 
it not rather an actuality? Our answer to this question is of the 
greatest importance. 

We must consider also whether soul is divisible or is without 
parts, and whether it is everywhere homogeneous or not; and if 
not homogeneous, whether its various forms are different 
specifically or generically: up to the present time those who 
have discussed and investigated soul seem to have confined 
themselves to the human soul. We must be careful not to ignore 
the question whether soul can be defined in a single 
unambiguous formula, as is the case with animal, or whether 
we must not give a separate formula for each of it, as we do for 
horse, dog, man, god (in the latter case the 'universal' animal - 
and so too every other 'common predicate' - being treated 
either as nothing at all or as a later product). Further, if what 
exists is not a plurality of souls, but a plurality of parts of one 
soul, which ought we to investigate first, the whole soul or its 
parts? (It is also a difficult problem to decide which of these 
parts are in nature distinct from one another.) Again, which 
ought we to investigate first, these parts or their functions, 
mind or thinking, the faculty or the act of sensation, and so on? 
If the investigation of the functions precedes that of the parts, 



1160 



the further question suggests itself: ought we not before either 
to consider the correlative objects, e.g. of sense or thought? It 
seems not only useful for the discovery of the causes of the 
derived properties of substances to be acquainted with the 
essential nature of those substances (as in mathematics it is 
useful for the understanding of the property of the equality of 
the interior angles of a triangle to two right angles to know the 
essential nature of the straight and the curved or of the line and 
the plane) but also conversely, for the knowledge of the 
essential nature of a substance is largely promoted by an 
acquaintance with its properties: for, when we are able to give 
an account conformable to experience of all or most of the 
properties of a substance, we shall be in the most favourable 
position to say something worth saying about the essential 
nature of that subject; in all demonstration a definition of the 
essence is required as a starting-point, so that definitions which 
do not enable us to discover the derived properties, or which fail 
to facilitate even a conjecture about them, must obviously, one 
and all, be dialectical and futile. 

A further problem presented by the affections of soul is this: are 
they all affections of the complex of body and soul, or is there 
any one among them peculiar to the soul by itself? To determine 
this is indispensable but difficult. If we consider the majority of 
them, there seems to be no case in which the soul can act or be 
acted upon without involving the body; e.g. anger, courage, 
appetite, and sensation generally. Thinking seems the most 
probable exception; but if this too proves to be a form of 
imagination or to be impossible without imagination, it too 
requires a body as a condition of its existence. If there is any 
way of acting or being acted upon proper to soul, soul will be 
capable of separate existence; if there is none, its separate 
existence is impossible. In the latter case, it will be like what is 
straight, which has many properties arising from the 
straightness in it, e.g. that of touching a bronze sphere at a 



1161 



point, though straightness divorced from the other constituents 
of the straight thing cannot touch it in this way; it cannot be so 
divorced at all, since it is always found in a body. It therefore 
seems that all the affections of soul involve a body - passion, 
gentleness, fear, pity, courage, joy, loving, and hating; in all these 
there is a concurrent affection of the body. In support of this we 
may point to the fact that, while sometimes on the occasion of 
violent and striking occurrences there is no excitement or fear 
felt, on others faint and feeble stimulations produce these 
emotions, viz. when the body is already in a state of tension 
resembling its condition when we are angry. Here is a still 
clearer case: in the absence of any external cause of terror we 
find ourselves experiencing the feelings of a man in terror. From 
all this it is obvious that the affections of soul are enmattered 
formulable essences. 

Consequently their definitions ought to correspond, e.g. anger 
should be defined as a certain mode of movement of such and 
such a body (or part or faculty of a body) by this or that cause 
and for this or that end. That is precisely why the study of the 
soul must fall within the science of Nature, at least so far as in 
its affections it manifests this double character. Hence a 
physicist would define an affection of soul differently from a 
dialectician; the latter would define e.g. anger as the appetite 
for returning pain for pain, or something like that, while the 
former would define it as a boiling of the blood or warm 
substance surround the heart. The latter assigns the material 
conditions, the former the form or formulable essence; for what 
he states is the formulable essence of the fact, though for its 
actual existence there must be embodiment of it in a material 
such as is described by the other. Thus the essence of a house is 
assigned in such a formula as 'a shelter against destruction by 
wind, rain, and heat'; the physicist would describe it as 'stones, 
bricks, and timbers'; but there is a third possible description 
which would say that it was that form in that material with that 



1162 



purpose or end. Which, then, among these is entitled to be 
regarded as the genuine physicist? The one who confines 
himself to the material, or the one who restricts himself to the 
formulable essence alone? Is it not rather the one who 
combines both in a single formula? If this is so, how are we to 
characterize the other two? Must we not say that there is no 
type of thinker who concerns himself with those qualities or 
attributes of the material which are in fact inseparable from the 
material, and without attempting even in thought to separate 
them? The physicist is he who concerns himself with all the 
properties active and passive of bodies or materials thus or thus 
defined; attributes not considered as being of this character he 
leaves to others, in certain cases it may be to a specialist, e.g. a 
carpenter or a physician, in others (a) where they are 
inseparable in fact, but are separable from any particular kind of 
body by an effort of abstraction, to the mathematician, (b) 
where they are separate both in fact and in thought from body 
altogether, to the First Philosopher or metaphysician. But we 
must return from this digression, and repeat that the affections 
of soul are inseparable from the material substratum of animal 
life, to which we have seen that such affections, e.g. passion and 
fear, attach, and have not the same mode of being as a line or a 
plane. 



For our study of soul it is necessary, while formulating the 
problems of which in our further advance we are to find the 
solutions, to call into council the views of those of our 
predecessors who have declared any opinion on this subject, in 
order that we may profit by whatever is sound in their 
suggestions and avoid their errors. 



1163 



The starting-point of our inquiry is an exposition of those 
characteristics which have chiefly been held to belong to soul in 
its very nature. Two characteristic marks have above all others 
been recognized as distinguishing that which has soul in it from 
that which has not - movement and sensation. It may be said 
that these two are what our predecessors have fixed upon as 
characteristic of soul. 

Some say that what originates movement is both pre-eminently 
and primarily soul; believing that what is not itself moved 
cannot originate movement in another, they arrived at the view 
that soul belongs to the class of things in movement. This is 
what led Democritus to say that soul is a sort of fire or hot 
substance; his 'forms' or atoms are infinite in number; those 
which are spherical he calls fire and soul, and compares them 
to the motes in the air which we see in shafts of light coming 
through windows; the mixture of seeds of all sorts he calls the 
elements of the whole of Nature (Leucippus gives a similar 
account); the spherical atoms are identified with soul because 
atoms of that shape are most adapted to permeate everywhere, 
and to set all the others moving by being themselves in 
movement. This implies the view that soul is identical with 
what produces movement in animals. That is why, further, they 
regard respiration as the characteristic mark of life; as the 
environment compresses the bodies of animals, and tends to 
extrude those atoms which impart movement to them, because 
they themselves are never at rest, there must be a 
reinforcement of these by similar atoms coming in from 
without in the act of respiration; for they prevent the extrusion 
of those which are already within by counteracting the 
compressing and consolidating force of the environment; and 
animals continue to live only so long as they are able to 
maintain this resistance. 



1164 



The doctrine of the Pythagoreans seems to rest upon the same 
ideas; some of them declared the motes in air, others what 
moved them, to be soul. These motes were referred to because 
they are seen always in movement, even in a complete calm. 

The same tendency is shown by those who define soul as that 
which moves itself; all seem to hold the view that movement is 
what is closest to the nature of soul, and that while all else is 
moved by soul, it alone moves itself. This belief arises from their 
never seeing anything originating movement which is not first 
itself moved. 

Similarly also Anaxagoras (and whoever agrees with him in 
saying that mind set the whole in movement) declares the 
moving cause of things to be soul. His position must, however, 
be distinguished from that of Democritus. Democritus roundly 
identifies soul and mind, for he identifies what appears with 
what is true - that is why he commends Homer for the phrase 
'Hector lay with thought distraught'; he does not employ mind 
as a special faculty dealing with truth, but identifies soul and 
mind. What Anaxagoras says about them is more obscure; in 
many places he tells us that the cause of beauty and order is 
mind, elsewhere that it is soul; it is found, he says, in all 
animals, great and small, high and low, but mind (in the sense 
of intelligence) appears not to belong alike to all animals, and 
indeed not even to all human beings. 

All those, then, who had special regard to the fact that what has 
soul in it is moved, adopted the view that soul is to be identified 
with what is eminently originative of movement. All, on the 
other hand, who looked to the fact that what has soul in it 
knows or perceives what is, identify soul with the principle or 
principles of Nature, according as they admit several such 
principles or one only. Thus Empedocles declares that it is 



1165 



formed out of all his elements, each of them also being soul; his 
words are: 

For 'tis by Earth we see Earth, by Water Water, 

By Ether Ether divine, by Fire destructive Fire, 

By Love Love, and Hate by cruel Hate. 

In the same way Plato in the Timaeus fashions soul out of his 
elements; for like, he holds, is known by like, and things are 
formed out of the principles or elements, so that soul must be 
so too. Similarly also in his lectures 'On Philosophy' it was set 
forth that the Animal-itself is compounded of the Idea itself of 
the One together with the primary length, breadth, and depth, 
everything else, the objects of its perception, being similarly 
constituted. Again he puts his view in yet other terms: Mind is 
the monad, science or knowledge the dyad (because it goes 
undeviatingly from one point to another), opinion the number 
of the plane, sensation the number of the solid; the numbers 
are by him expressly identified with the Forms themselves or 
principles, and are formed out of the elements; now things are 
apprehended either by mind or science or opinion or sensation, 
and these same numbers are the Forms of things. 

Some thinkers, accepting both premisses, viz. that the soul is 
both originative of movement and cognitive, have compounded 
it of both and declared the soul to be a self-moving number. 

As to the nature and number of the first principles opinions 
differ. The difference is greatest between those who regard 
them as corporeal and those who regard them as incorporeal, 
and from both dissent those who make a blend and draw their 
principles from both sources. The number of principles is also in 
dispute; some admit one only, others assert several. There is a 
consequent diversity in their several accounts of soul; they 
assume, naturally enough, that what is in its own nature 



1166 



originative of movement must be among what is primordial. 
That has led some to regard it as fire, for fire is the subtlest of 
the elements and nearest to incorporeality; further, in the most 
primary sense, fire both is moved and originates movement in 
all the others. 

Democritus has expressed himself more ingeniously than the 
rest on the grounds for ascribing each of these two characters to 
soul; soul and mind are, he says, one and the same thing, and 
this thing must be one of the primary and indivisible bodies, 
and its power of originating movement must be due to its 
fineness of grain and the shape of its atoms; he says that of all 
the shapes the spherical is the most mobile, and that this is the 
shape of the particles of fire and mind. 

Anaxagoras, as we said above, seems to distinguish between 
soul and mind, but in practice he treats them as a single 
substance, except that it is mind that he specially posits as the 
principle of all things; at any rate what he says is that mind 
alone of all that is simple, unmixed, and pure. He assigns both 
characteristics, knowing and origination of movement, to the 
same principle, when he says that it was mind that set the 
whole in movement. 

Thales, too, to judge from what is recorded about him, seems to 
have held soul to be a motive force, since he said that the 
magnet has a soul in it because it moves the iron. 

Diogenes (and others) held the soul to be air because he 
believed air to be finest in grain and a first principle; therein lay 
the grounds of the soul's powers of knowing and originating 
movement. As the primordial principle from which all other 
things are derived, it is cognitive; as finest in grain, it has the 
power to originate movement. 



1167 



Heraclitus too says that the first principle - the 'warm 
exhalation' of which, according to him, everything else is 
composed - is soul; further, that this exhalation is most 
incorporeal and in ceaseless flux; that what is in movement 
requires that what knows it should be in movement; and that 
all that is has its being essentially in movement (herein 
agreeing with the majority). 

Alcmaeon also seems to have held a similar view about soul; he 
says that it is immortal because it resembles 'the immortals,' 
and that this immortality belongs to it in virtue of its ceaseless 
movement; for all the 'things divine,' moon, sun, the planets, 
and the whole heavens, are in perpetual movement. 

of More superficial writers, some, e.g. Hippo, have pronounced it 
to be water; they seem to have argued from the fact that the 
seed of all animals is fluid, for Hippo tries to refute those who 
say that the soul is blood, on the ground that the seed, which is 
the primordial soul, is not blood. 

Another group (Critias, for example) did hold it to be blood; they 
take perception to be the most characteristic attribute of soul, 
and hold that perceptiveness is due to the nature of blood. 

Each of the elements has thus found its partisan, except earth - 
earth has found no supporter unless we count as such those 
who have declared soul to be, or to be compounded of, all the 
elements. All, then, it may be said, characterize the soul by three 
marks, Movement, Sensation, Incorporeality, and each of these 
is traced back to the first principles. That is why (with one 
exception) all those who define the soul by its power of knowing 
make it either an element or constructed out of the elements. 
The language they all use is similar; like, they say, is known by 
like; as the soul knows everything, they construct it out of all 
the principles. Hence all those who admit but one cause or 
element, make the soul also one (e.g. fire or air), while those 



1168 



who admit a multiplicity of principles make the soul also 
multiple. The exception is Anaxagoras; he alone says that mind 
is impassible and has nothing in common with anything else. 
But, if this is so, how or in virtue of what cause can it know? 
That Anaxagoras has not explained, nor can any answer be 
inferred from his words. All who acknowledge pairs of opposites 
among their principles, construct the soul also out of these 
contraries, while those who admit as principles only one 
contrary of each pair, e.g. either hot or cold, likewise make the 
soul some one of these. That is why, also, they allow themselves 
to be guided by the names; those who identify soul with the hot 
argue that sen (to live) is derived from sein (to boil), while those 
who identify it with the cold say that soul (psuche) is so called 
from the process of respiration and (katapsuxis). Such are the 
traditional opinions concerning soul, together with the grounds 
on which they are maintained. 



We must begin our examination with movement; for doubtless, 
not only is it false that the essence of soul is correctly described 
by those who say that it is what moves (or is capable of moving) 
itself, but it is an impossibility that movement should be even 
an attribute of it. 

We have already pointed out that there is no necessity that 
what originates movement should itself be moved. There are 
two senses in which anything may be moved - either (a) 
indirectly, owing to something other than itself, or (b) directly, 
owing to itself. Things are 'indirectly moved' which are moved 
as being contained in something which is moved, e.g. sailors in 
a ship, for they are moved in a different sense from that in 



1169 



which the ship is moved; the ship is 'directly moved', they are 
'indirectly moved', because they are in a moving vessel. This is 
clear if we consider their limbs; the movement proper to the 
legs (and so to man) is walking, and in this case the sailors tare 
not walking. Recognizing the double sense of 'being moved', 
what we have to consider now is whether the soul is 'directly 
moved' and participates in such direct movement. 

There are four species of movement - locomotion, alteration, 
diminution, growth; consequently if the soul is moved, it must 
be moved with one or several or all of these species of 
movement. Now if its movement is not incidental, there must 
be a movement natural to it, and, if so, as all the species 
enumerated involve place, place must be natural to it. But if the 
essence of soul be to move itself, its being moved cannot be 
incidental to - as it is to what is white or three cubits long; they 
too can be moved, but only incidentally - what is moved is that 
of which 'white' and 'three cubits long' are the attributes, the 
body in which they inhere; hence they have no place: but if the 
soul naturally partakes in movement, it follows that it must 
have a place. 

Further, if there be a movement natural to the soul, there must 
be a counter-movement unnatural to it, and conversely. The 
same applies to rest as well as to movement; for the terminus 
ad quern of a thing's natural movement is the place of its 
natural rest, and similarly the terminus ad quern of its enforced 
movement is the place of its enforced rest. But what meaning 
can be attached to enforced movements or rests of the soul, it is 
difficult even to imagine. 

Further, if the natural movement of the soul be upward, the soul 
must be fire; if downward, it must be earth; for upward and 
downward movements are the definitory characteristics of 
these bodies. The same reasoning applies to the intermediate 



1170 



movements, termini, and bodies. Further, since the soul is 
observed to originate movement in the body, it is reasonable to 
suppose that it transmits to the body the movements by which 
it itself is moved, and so, reversing the order, we may infer from 
the movements of the body back to similar movements of the 
soul. Now the body is moved from place to place with 
movements of locomotion. Hence it would follow that the soul 
too must in accordance with the body change either its place as 
a whole or the relative places of its parts. This carries with it the 
possibility that the soul might even quit its body and re-enter it, 
and with this would be involved the possibility of a resurrection 
of animals from the dead. But, it may be contended, the soul 
can be moved indirectly by something else; for an animal can be 
pushed out of its course. Yes, but that to whose essence belongs 
the power of being moved by itself, cannot be moved by 
something else except incidentally, just as what is good by or in 
itself cannot owe its goodness to something external to it or to 
some end to which it is a means. 

If the soul is moved, the most probable view is that what moves 
it is sensible things. 

We must note also that, if the soul moves itself, it must be the 
mover itself that is moved, so that it follows that if movement is 
in every case a displacement of that which is in movement, in 
that respect in which it is said to be moved, the movement of 
the soul must be a departure from its essential nature, at least if 
its self-movement is essential to it, not incidental. 

Some go so far as to hold that the movements which the soul 
imparts to the body in which it is are the same in kind as those 
with which it itself is moved. An example of this is Democritus, 
who uses language like that of the comic dramatist Philippus, 
who accounts for the movements that Daedalus imparted to his 
wooden Aphrodite by saying that he poured quicksilver into it; 



1171 



similarly Democritus says that the spherical atoms which 
according to him constitute soul, owing to their own ceaseless 
movements draw the whole body after them and so produce its 
movements. We must urge the question whether it is these very 
same atoms which produce rest also - how they could do so, it 
is difficult and even impossible to say. And, in general, we may 
object that it is not in this way that the soul appears to originate 
movement in animals - it is through intention or process of 
thinking. 

It is in the same fashion that the Timaeus also tries to give a 
physical account of how the soul moves its body; the soul, it is 
there said, is in movement, and so owing to their mutual 
implication moves the body also. After compounding the soul- 
substance out of the elements and dividing it in accordance 
with the harmonic numbers, in order that it may possess a 
connate sensibility for 'harmony' and that the whole may move 
in movements well attuned, the Demiurge bent the straight line 
into a circle; this single circle he divided into two circles united 
at two common points; one of these he subdivided into seven 
circles. All this implies that the movements of the soul are 
identified with the local movements of the heavens. 

Now, in the first place, it is a mistake to say that the soul is a 
spatial magnitude. It is evident that Plato means the soul of the 
whole to be like the sort of soul which is called mind not like 
the sensitive or the desiderative soul, for the movements of 
neither of these are circular. Now mind is one and continuous 
in the sense in which the process of thinking is so, and thinking 
is identical with the thoughts which are its parts; these have a 
serial unity like that of number, not a unity like that of a spatial 
magnitude. Hence mind cannot have that kind of unity either; 
mind is either without parts or is continuous in some other way 
than that which characterizes a spatial magnitude. How, indeed, 
if it were a spatial magnitude, could mind possibly think? Will it 



1172 



think with any one indifferently of its parts? In this case, the 
'part' must be understood either in the sense of a spatial 
magnitude or in the sense of a point (if a point can be called a 
part of a spatial magnitude). If we accept the latter alternative, 
the points being infinite in number, obviously the mind can 
never exhaustively traverse them; if the former, the mind must 
think the same thing over and over again, indeed an infinite 
number of times (whereas it is manifestly possible to think a 
thing once only). If contact of any part whatsoever of itself with 
the object is all that is required, why need mind move in a 
circle, or indeed possess magnitude at all? On the other hand, if 
contact with the whole circle is necessary, what meaning can be 
given to the contact of the parts? Further, how could what has 
no parts think what has parts, or what has parts think what has 
none? We must identify the circle referred to with mind; for it is 
mind whose movement is thinking, and it is the circle whose 
movement is revolution, so that if thinking is a movement of 
revolution, the circle which has this characteristic movement 
must be mind. 

If the circular movement is eternal, there must be something 
which mind is always thinking - what can this be? For all 
practical processes of thinking have limits - they all go on for 
the sake of something outside the process, and all theoretical 
processes come to a close in the same way as the phrases in 
speech which express processes and results of thinking. Every 
such linguistic phrase is either definitory or demonstrative. 
Demonstration has both a starting-point and may be said to end 
in a conclusion or inferred result; even if the process never 
reaches final completion, at any rate it never returns upon itself 
again to its starting-point, it goes on assuming a fresh middle 
term or a fresh extreme, and moves straight forward, but 
circular movement returns to its starting-point. Definitions, too, 
are closed groups of terms. 



1173 



Further, if the same revolution is repeated, mind must 
repeatedly think the same object. 

Further, thinking has more resemblance to a coming to rest or 
arrest than to a movement; the same may be said of inferring. 

It might also be urged that what is difficult and enforced is 
incompatible with blessedness; if the movement of the soul is 
not of its essence, movement of the soul must be contrary to its 
nature. It must also be painful for the soul to be inextricably 
bound up with the body; nay more, if, as is frequently said and 
widely accepted, it is better for mind not to be embodied, the 
union must be for it undesirable. 

Further, the cause of the revolution of the heavens is left 
obscure. It is not the essence of soul which is the cause of this 
circular movement - that movement is only incidental to soul - 
nor is, a fortiori, the body its cause. Again, it is not even asserted 
that it is better that soul should be so moved; and yet the 
reason for which God caused the soul to move in a circle can 
only have been that movement was better for it than rest, and 
movement of this kind better than any other. But since this sort 
of consideration is more appropriate to another field of 
speculation, let us dismiss it for the present. 

The view we have just been examining, in company with most 
theories about the soul, involves the following absurdity: they 
all join the soul to a body, or place it in a body, without adding 
any specification of the reason of their union, or of the bodily 
conditions required for it. Yet such explanation can scarcely be 
omitted; for some community of nature is presupposed by the 
fact that the one acts and the other is acted upon, the one 
moves and the other is moved; interaction always implies a 
special nature in the two interagents. All, however, that these 
thinkers do is to describe the specific characteristics of the soul; 
they do not try to determine anything about the body which is 



1174 



to contain it, as if it were possible, as in the Pythagorean myths, 
that any soul could be clothed upon with any body - an absurd 
view, for each body seems to have a form and shape of its own. 
It is as absurd as to say that the art of carpentry could embody 
itself in flutes; each art must use its tools, each soul its body. 



There is yet another theory about soul, which has commended 
itself to many as no less probable than any of those we have 
hitherto mentioned, and has rendered public account of itself in 
the court of popular discussion. Its supporters say that the soul 
is a kind of harmony, for (a) harmony is a blend or composition 
of contraries, and (b) the body is compounded out of contraries. 
Harmony, however, is a certain proportion or composition of the 
constituents blended, and soul can be neither the one nor the 
other of these. Further, the power of originating movement 
cannot belong to a harmony, while almost all concur in 
regarding this as a principal attribute of soul. It is more 
appropriate to call health (or generally one of the good states of 
the body) a harmony than to predicate it of the soul. The 
absurdity becomes most apparent when we try to attribute the 
active and passive affections of the soul to a harmony; the 
necessary readjustment of their conceptions is difficult. Further, 
in using the word 'harmony' we have one or other of two cases 
in our mind; the most proper sense is in relation to spatial 
magnitudes which have motion and position, where harmony 
means the disposition and cohesion of their parts in such a 
manner as to prevent the introduction into the whole of 
anything homogeneous with it, and the secondary sense, 
derived from the former, is that in which it means the ratio 
between the constituents so blended; in neither of these senses 



1175 



is it plausible to predicate it of soul. That soul is a harmony in 
the sense of the mode of composition of the parts of the body is 
a view easily refutable; for there are many composite parts and 
those variously compounded; of what bodily part is mind or the 
sensitive or the appetitive faculty the mode of composition? 
And what is the mode of composition which constitutes each of 
them? It is equally absurd to identify the soul with the ratio of 
the mixture; for the mixture which makes flesh has a different 
ratio between the elements from that which makes bone. The 
consequence of this view will therefore be that distributed 
throughout the whole body there will be many souls, since 
every one of the bodily parts is a different mixture of the 
elements, and the ratio of mixture is in each case a harmony, i.e. 
a soul. 

From Empedocles at any rate we might demand an answer to 
the following question for he says that each of the parts of the 
body is what it is in virtue of a ratio between the elements: is 
the soul identical with this ratio, or is it not rather something 
over and above this which is formed in the parts? Is love the 
cause of any and every mixture, or only of those that are in the 
right ratio? Is love this ratio itself, or is love something over and 
above this? Such are the problems raised by this account. But, 
on the other hand, if the soul is different from the mixture, why 
does it disappear at one and the same moment with that 
relation between the elements which constitutes flesh or the 
other parts of the animal body? Further, if the soul is not 
identical with the ratio of mixture, and it is consequently not 
the case that each of the parts has a soul, what is that which 
perishes when the soul quits the body? 

That the soul cannot either be a harmony, or be moved in a 
circle, is clear from what we have said. Yet that it can be moved 
incidentally is, as we said above, possible, and even that in a 
sense it can move itself, i.e. in the sense that the vehicle in 



1176 



which it is can be moved, and moved by it; in no other sense 
can the soul be moved in space. 

More legitimate doubts might remain as to its movement in 
view of the following facts. We speak of the soul as being pained 
or pleased, being bold or fearful, being angry, perceiving, 
thinking. All these are regarded as modes of movement, and 
hence it might be inferred that the soul is moved. This, however, 
does not necessarily follow. We may admit to the full that being 
pained or pleased, or thinking, are movements (each of them a 
'being moved'), and that the movement is originated by the soul. 
For example we may regard anger or fear as such and such 
movements of the heart, and thinking as such and such another 
movement of that organ, or of some other; these modifications 
may arise either from changes of place in certain parts or from 
qualitative alterations (the special nature of the parts and the 
special modes of their changes being for our present purpose 
irrelevant). Yet to say that it is the soul which is angry is as 
inexact as it would be to say that it is the soul that weaves webs 
or builds houses. It is doubtless better to avoid saying that the 
soul pities or learns or thinks and rather to say that it is the 
man who does this with his soul. What we mean is not that the 
movement is in the soul, but that sometimes it terminates in 
the soul and sometimes starts from it, sensation e.g. coming 
from without inwards, and reminiscence starting from the soul 
and terminating with the movements, actual or residual, in the 
sense organs. 

The case of mind is different; it seems to be an independent 
substance implanted within the soul and to be incapable of 
being destroyed. If it could be destroyed at all, it would be under 
the blunting influence of old age. What really happens in 
respect of mind in old age is, however, exactly parallel to what 
happens in the case of the sense organs; if the old man could 
recover the proper kind of eye, he would see just as well as the 



1177 



young man. The incapacity of old age is due to an affection not 
of the soul but of its vehicle, as occurs in drunkenness or 
disease. Thus it is that in old age the activity of mind or 
intellectual apprehension declines only through the decay of 
some other inward part; mind itself is impassible. Thinking, 
loving, and hating are affections not of mind, but of that which 
has mind, so far as it has it. That is why, when this vehicle 
decays, memory and love cease; they were activities not of 
mind, but of the composite which has perished; mind is, no 
doubt, something more divine and impassible. That the soul 
cannot be moved is therefore clear from what we have said, and 
if it cannot be moved at all, manifestly it cannot be moved by 
itself. 

Of all the opinions we have enumerated, by far the most 
unreasonable is that which declares the soul to be a self-moving 
number; it involves in the first place all the impossibilities 
which follow from regarding the soul as moved, and in the 
second special absurdities which follow from calling it a 
number. How we to imagine a unit being moved? By what 
agency? What sort of movement can be attributed to what is 
without parts or internal differences? If the unit is both 
originative of movement and itself capable of being moved, it 
must contain difference. 

Further, since they say a moving line generates a surface and a 
moving point a line, the movements of the psychic units must 
be lines (for a point is a unit having position, and the number of 
the soul is, of course, somewhere and has position). 

Again, if from a number a number or a unit is subtracted, the 
remainder is another number; but plants and many animals 
when divided continue to live, and each segment is thought to 
retain the same kind of soul. 



1178 



It must be all the same whether we speak of units or corpuscles; 
for if the spherical atoms of Democritus became points, nothing 
being retained but their being a quantum, there must remain in 
each a moving and a moved part, just as there is in what is 
continuous; what happens has nothing to do with the size of 
the atoms, it depends solely upon their being a quantum. That 
is why there must be something to originate movement in the 
units. If in the animal what originates movement is the soul, so 
also must it be in the case of the number, so that not the mover 
and the moved together, but the mover only, will be the soul. 
But how is it possible for one of the units to fulfil this function 
of originating movement? There must be some difference 
between such a unit and all the other units, and what difference 
can there be between one placed unit and another except a 
difference of position? If then, on the other hand, these psychic 
units within the body are different from the points of the body, 
there will be two sets of units both occupying the same place; 
for each unit will occupy a point. And yet, if there can be two, 
why cannot there be an infinite number? For if things can 
occupy an indivisible lace, they must themselves be indivisible. 
If, on the other hand, the points of the body are identical with 
the units whose number is the soul, or if the number of the 
points in the body is the soul, why have not all bodies souls? For 
all bodies contain points or an infinity of points. 

Further, how is it possible for these points to be isolated or 
separated from their bodies, seeing that lines cannot be 
resolved into points? 



1179 



The result is, as we have said, that this view, while on the one 
side identical with that of those who maintain that soul is a 
subtle kind of body, is on the other entangled in the absurdity 
peculiar to Democritus' way of describing the manner in which 
movement is originated by soul. For if the soul is present 
throughout the whole percipient body, there must, if the soul be 
a kind of body, be two bodies in the same place; and for those 
who call it a number, there must be many points at one point, 
or every body must have a soul, unless the soul be a different 
sort of number - other, that is, than the sum of the points 
existing in a body. Another consequence that follows is that the 
animal must be moved by its number precisely in the way that 
Democritus explained its being moved by his spherical psychic 
atoms. What difference does it make whether we speak of small 
spheres or of large units, or, quite simply, of units in movement? 
One way or another, the movements of the animal must be due 
to their movements. Hence those who combine movement and 
number in the same subject lay themselves open to these and 
many other similar absurdities. It is impossible not only that 
these characters should give the definition of soul - it is 
impossible that they should even be attributes of it. The point is 
clear if the attempt be made to start from this as the account of 
soul and explain from it the affections and actions of the soul, 
e.g. reasoning, sensation, pleasure, pain, &c. For, to repeat what 
we have said earlier, movement and number do not facilitate 
even conjecture about the derivative properties of soul. 

Such are the three ways in which soul has traditionally been 
defined; one group of thinkers declared it to be that which is 
most originative of movement because it moves itself, another 
group to be the subtlest and most nearly incorporeal of all kinds 
of body. We have now sufficiently set forth the difficulties and 
inconsistencies to which these theories are exposed. It remains 



1180 



now to examine the doctrine that soul is composed of the 
elements. 

The reason assigned for this doctrine is that thus the soul may 
perceive or come to know everything that is, but the theory 
necessarily involves itself in many impossibilities. Its upholders 
assume that like is known only by like, and imagine that by 
declaring the soul to be composed of the elements they succeed 
in identifying the soul with all the things it is capable of 
apprehending. But the elements are not the only things it 
knows; there are many others, or, more exactly, an infinite 
number of others, formed out of the elements. Let us admit that 
the soul knows or perceives the elements out of which each of 
these composites is made up; but by what means will it know or 
perceive the composite whole, e.g. what God, man, flesh, bone 
(or any other compound) is? For each is, not merely the 
elements of which it is composed, but those elements combined 
in a determinate mode or ratio, as Empedocles himself says of 
bone, 

The kindly Earth in its broad-bosomed moulds 

Won of clear Water two parts out of eight, 

And four of Fire; and so white bones were formed. 

Nothing, therefore, will be gained by the presence of the 
elements in the soul, unless there be also present there the 
various formulae of proportion and the various compositions in 
accordance with them. Each element will indeed know its fellow 
outside, but there will be no knowledge of bone or man, unless 
they too are present in the constitution of the soul. The 
impossibility of this needs no pointing out; for who would 
suggest that stone or man could enter into the constitution of 
the soul? The same applies to 'the good' and 'the not-good', and 
so on. 



1181 



Further, the word 'is' has many meanings: it may be used of a 
'this' or substance, or of a quantum, or of a quale, or of any 
other of the kinds of predicates we have distinguished. Does the 
soul consist of all of these or not? It does not appear that all 
have common elements. Is the soul formed out of those 
elements alone which enter into substances? so how will it be 
able to know each of the other kinds of thing? Will it be said 
that each kind of thing has elements or principles of its own, 
and that the soul is formed out of the whole of these? In that 
case, the soul must be a quantum and a quale and a substance. 
But all that can be made out of the elements of a quantum is a 
quantum, not a substance. These (and others like them) are the 
consequences of the view that the soul is composed of all the 
elements. 

It is absurd, also, to say both (a) that like is not capable of being 
affected by like, and (b) that like is perceived or known by like, 
for perceiving, and also both thinking and knowing, are, on their 
own assumption, ways of being affected or moved. 

There are many puzzles and difficulties raised by saying, as 
Empedocles does, that each set of things is known by means of 
its corporeal elements and by reference to something in soul 
which is like them, and additional testimony is furnished by 
this new consideration; for all the parts of the animal body 
which consist wholly of earth such as bones, sinews, and hair 
seem to be wholly insensitive and consequently not perceptive 
even of objects earthy like themselves, as they ought to have 
been. 

Further, each of the principles will have far more ignorance 
than knowledge, for though each of them will know one thing, 
there will be many of which it will be ignorant. Empedocles at 
any rate must conclude that his God is the least intelligent of all 
beings, for of him alone is it true that there is one thing, Strife, 



1182 



which he does not know, while there is nothing which mortal 
beings do not know, for ere is nothing which does not enter into 
their composition. 

In general, we may ask, Why has not everything a soul, since 
everything either is an element, or is formed out of one or 
several or all of the elements? Each must certainly know one or 
several or all. 

The problem might also be raised, What is that which unifies 
the elements into a soul? The elements correspond, it would 
appear, to the matter; what unites them, whatever it is, is the 
supremely important factor. But it is impossible that there 
should be something superior to, and dominant over, the soul 
(and a fortiori over the mind); it is reasonable to hold that mind 
is by nature most primordial and dominant, while their 
statement that it is the elements which are first of all that is. 

All, both those who assert that the soul, because of its 
knowledge or perception of what is compounded out of the 
elements, and is those who assert that it is of all things the 
most originative of movement, fail to take into consideration all 
kinds of soul. In fact (1) not all beings that perceive can 
originate movement; there appear to be certain animals which 
stationary, and yet local movement is the only one, so it seems, 
which the soul originates in animals. And (2) the same objection 
holds against all those who construct mind and the perceptive 
faculty out of the elements; for it appears that plants live, and 
yet are not endowed with locomotion or perception, while a 
large number of animals are without discourse of reason. Even 
if these points were waived and mind admitted to be a part of 
the soul (and so too the perceptive faculty), still, even so, there 
would be kinds and parts of soul of which they had failed to 
give any account. 



1183 



The same objection lies against the view expressed in the 
'Orphic' poems: there it is said that the soul comes in from the 
whole when breathing takes place, being borne in upon the 
winds. Now this cannot take place in the case of plants, nor 
indeed in the case of certain classes of animal, for not all 
classes of animal breathe. This fact has escaped the notice of 
the holders of this view. 

If we must construct the soul out of the elements, there is no 
necessity to suppose that all the elements enter into its 
construction; one element in each pair of contraries will suffice 
to enable it to know both that element itself and its contrary. By 
means of the straight line we know both itself and the curved - 
the carpenter's rule enables us to test both - but what is curved 
does not enable us to distinguish either itself or the straight. 
Certain thinkers say that soul is intermingled in the whole 
universe, and it is perhaps for that reason that Thales came to 
the opinion that all things are full of gods. This presents some 
difficulties: Why does the soul when it resides in air or fire not 
form an animal, while it does so when it resides in mixtures of 
the elements, and that although it is held to be of higher quality 
when contained in the former? (One might add the question, 
why the soul in air is maintained to be higher and more 
immortal than that in animals.) Both possible ways of replying 
to the former question lead to absurdity or paradox; for it is 
beyond paradox to say that fire or air is an animal, and it is 
absurd to refuse the name of animal to what has soul in it. The 
opinion that the elements have soul in them seems to have 
arisen from the doctrine that a whole must be homogeneous 
with its parts. If it is true that animals become animate by 
drawing into themselves a portion of what surrounds them, the 
partisans of this view are bound to say that the soul of the 
Whole too is homogeneous with all its parts. If the air sucked in 
is homogeneous, but soul heterogeneous, clearly while some 
part of soul will exist in the inbreathed air, some other part will 



1184 



not. The soul must either be homogeneous, or such that there 
are some parts of the Whole in which it is not to be found. 

From what has been said it is now clear that knowing as an 
attribute of soul cannot be explained by soul's being composed 
of the elements, and that it is neither sound nor true to speak of 
soul as moved. But since (a) knowing, perceiving, opining, and 
further (b) desiring, wishing, and generally all other modes of 
appetition, belong to soul, and (c) the local movements of 
animals, and (d) growth, maturity, and decay are produced by 
the soul, we must ask whether each of these is an attribute of 
the soul as a whole, i.e. whether it is with the whole soul we 
think, perceive, move ourselves, act or are acted upon, or 
whether each of them requires a different part of the soul? So 
too with regard to life. Does it depend on one of the parts of 
soul? Or is it dependent on more than one? Or on all? Or has it 
some quite other cause? 

Some hold that the soul is divisible, and that one part thinks, 
another desires. If, then, its nature admits of its being divided, 
what can it be that holds the parts together? Surely not the 
body; on the contrary it seems rather to be the soul that holds 
the body together; at any rate when the soul departs the body 
disintegrates and decays. If, then, there is something else which 
makes the soul one, this unifying agency would have the best 
right to the name of soul, and we shall have to repeat for it the 
question: Is it one or multipartite? If it is one, why not at once 
admit that 'the soul' is one? If it has parts, once more the 
question must be put: What holds its parts together, and so ad 
infinitum? 

The question might also be raised about the parts of the soul: 
What is the separate role of each in relation to the body? For, if 
the whole soul holds together the whole body, we should expect 
each part of the soul to hold together a part of the body. But this 



1185 



seems an impossibility; it is difficult even to imagine what sort 
of bodily part mind will hold together, or how it will do this. 

It is a fact of observation that plants and certain insects go on 
living when divided into segments; this means that each of the 
segments has a soul in it identical in species, though not 
numerically identical in the different segments, for both of the 
segments for a time possess the power of sensation and local 
movement. That this does not last is not surprising, for they no 
longer possess the organs necessary for self-maintenance. But, 
all the same, in each of the bodily parts there are present all the 
parts of soul, and the souls so present are homogeneous with 
one another and with the whole; this means that the several 
parts of the soul are indisseverable from one another, although 
the whole soul is divisible. It seems also that the principle found 
in plants is also a kind of soul; for this is the only principle 
which is common to both animals and plants; and this exists in 
isolation from the principle of sensation, though there nothing 
which has the latter without the former. 



Book II 



Let the foregoing suffice as our account of the views concerning 
the soul which have been handed on by our predecessors; let us 
now dismiss them and make as it were a completely fresh start, 



1186 



endeavouring to give a precise answer to the question, What is 
soul? i.e. to formulate the most general possible definition of it. 

We are in the habit of recognizing, as one determinate kind of 
what is, substance, and that in several senses, (a) in the sense of 
matter or that which in itself is not 'a this', and (b) in the sense 
of form or essence, which is that precisely in virtue of which a 
thing is called 'a this', and thirdly (c) in the sense of that which 
is compounded of both (a) and (b). Now matter is potentiality, 
form actuality; of the latter there are two grades related to one 
another as e.g. knowledge to the exercise of knowledge. 

Among substances are by general consent reckoned bodies and 
especially natural bodies; for they are the principles of all other 
bodies. Of natural bodies some have life in them, others not; by 
life we mean self-nutrition and growth (with its correlative 
decay). It follows that every natural body which has life in it is a 
substance in the sense of a composite. 

But since it is also a body of such and such a kind, viz. having 
life, the body cannot be soul; the body is the subject or matter, 
not what is attributed to it. Hence the soul must be a substance 
in the sense of the form of a natural body having life potentially 
within it. But substance is actuality, and thus soul is the 
actuality of a body as above characterized. Now the word 
actuality has two senses corresponding respectively to the 
possession of knowledge and the actual exercise of knowledge. 
It is obvious that the soul is actuality in the first sense, viz. that 
of knowledge as possessed, for both sleeping and waking 
presuppose the existence of soul, and of these waking 
corresponds to actual knowing, sleeping to knowledge 
possessed but not employed, and, in the history of the 
individual, knowledge comes before its employment or exercise. 

That is why the soul is the first grade of actuality of a natural 
body having life potentially in it. The body so described is a body 



1187 



which is organized. The parts of plants in spite of their extreme 
simplicity are 'organs'; e.g. the leaf serves to shelter the 
pericarp, the pericarp to shelter the fruit, while the roots of 
plants are analogous to the mouth of animals, both serving for 
the absorption of food. If, then, we have to give a general 
formula applicable to all kinds of soul, we must describe it as 
the first grade of actuality of a natural organized body. That is 
why we can wholly dismiss as unnecessary the question 
whether the soul and the body are one: it is as meaningless as 
to ask whether the wax and the shape given to it by the stamp 
are one, or generally the matter of a thing and that of which it is 
the matter. Unity has many senses (as many as 'is' has), but the 
most proper and fundamental sense of both is the relation of an 
actuality to that of which it is the actuality. We have now given 
an answer to the question, what is soul? - an answer which 
applies to it in its full extent. It is substance in the sense which 
corresponds to the definitive formula of a thing's essence. That 
means that it is 'the essential whatness' of a body of the 
character just assigned. Suppose that what is literally an 'organ', 
like an axe, were a natural body, its 'essential whatness', would 
have been its essence, and so its soul; if this disappeared from 
it, it would have ceased to be an axe, except in name. As it is, it 
is just an axe; it wants the character which is required to make 
its whatness or formulable essence a soul; for that, it would 
have had to be a natural body of a particular kind, viz. one 
having in itself the power of setting itself in movement and 
arresting itself. Next, apply this doctrine in the case of the 
'parts' of the living body. Suppose that the eye were an animal- 
sight would have been its soul, for sight is the substance or 
essence of the eye which corresponds to the formula, the eye 
being merely the matter of seeing; when seeing is removed the 
eye is no longer an eye, except in name - it is no more a real eye 
than the eye of a statue or of a painted figure. We must now 
extend our consideration from the 'parts' to the whole living 



1188 



body; for what the departmental sense is to the bodily part 
which is its organ, that the whole faculty of sense is to the 
whole sensitive body as such. 

We must not understand by that which is 'potentially capable of 
living' what has lost the soul it had, but only what still retains 
it; but seeds and fruits are bodies which possess the 
qualification. Consequently, while waking is actuality in a sense 
corresponding to the cutting and the seeing, the soul is 
actuality in the sense corresponding to the power of sight and 
the power in the tool; the body corresponds to what exists in 
potentiality; as the pupil plus the power of sight constitutes the 
eye, so the soul plus the body constitutes the animal. 

From this it indubitably follows that the soul is inseparable from 
its body, or at any rate that certain parts of it are (if it has parts) 
for the actuality of some of them is nothing but the actualities 
of their bodily parts. Yet some may be separable because they 
are not the actualities of any body at all. Further, we have no 
light on the problem whether the soul may not be the actuality 
of its body in the sense in which the sailor is the actuality of the 
ship. 

This must suffice as our sketch or outline determination of the 
nature of soul. 



Since what is clear or logically more evident emerges from what 
in itself is confused but more observable by us, we must 
reconsider our results from this point of view. For it is not 
enough for a definitive formula to express as most now do the 
mere fact; it must include and exhibit the ground also. At 



1189 



present definitions are given in a form analogous to the 
conclusion of a syllogism; e.g. What is squaring? The 
construction of an equilateral rectangle equal to a given oblong 
rectangle. Such a definition is in form equivalent to a 
conclusion. One that tells us that squaring is the discovery of a 
line which is a mean proportional between the two unequal 
sides of the given rectangle discloses the ground of what is 
defined. 

We resume our inquiry from a fresh starting-point by calling 
attention to the fact that what has soul in it differs from what 
has not, in that the former displays life. Now this word has 
more than one sense, and provided any one alone of these is 
found in a thing we say that thing is living. Living, that is, may 
mean thinking or perception or local movement and rest, or 
movement in the sense of nutrition, decay and growth. Hence 
we think of plants also as living, for they are observed to 
possess in themselves an originative power through which they 
increase or decrease in all spatial directions; they grow up and 
down, and everything that grows increases its bulk alike in both 
directions or indeed in all, and continues to live so long as it can 
absorb nutriment. 

This power of self-nutrition can be isolated from the other 
powers mentioned, but not they from it - in mortal beings at 
least. The fact is obvious in plants; for it is the only psychic 
power they possess. 

This is the originative power the possession of which leads us to 
speak of things as living at all, but it is the possession of 
sensation that leads us for the first time to speak of living 
things as animals; for even those beings which possess no 
power of local movement but do possess the power of sensation 
we call animals and not merely living things. 



1190 



The primary form of sense is touch, which belongs to all 
animals, just as the power of self-nutrition can be isolated from 
touch and sensation generally, so touch can be isolated from all 
other forms of sense. (By the power of self-nutrition we mean 
that departmental power of the soul which is common to plants 
and animals: all animals whatsoever are observed to have the 
sense of touch.) What the explanation of these two facts is, we 
must discuss later. At present we must confine ourselves to 
saying that soul is the source of these phenomena and is 
characterized by them, viz. by the powers of self-nutrition, 
sensation, thinking, and motivity. 

Is each of these a soul or a part of a soul? And if a part, a part in 
what sense? A part merely distinguishable by definition or a 
part distinct in local situation as well? In the case of certain of 
these powers, the answers to these questions are easy, in the 
case of others we are puzzled what to say. just as in the case of 
plants which when divided are observed to continue to live 
though removed to a distance from one another (thus showing 
that in their case the soul of each individual plant before 
division was actually one, potentially many), so we notice a 
similar result in other varieties of soul, i.e. in insects which have 
been cut in two; each of the segments possesses both sensation 
and local movement; and if sensation, necessarily also 
imagination and appetition; for, where there is sensation, there 
is also pleasure and pain, and, where these, necessarily also 
desire. 

We have no evidence as yet about mind or the power to think; it 
seems to be a widely different kind of soul, differing as what is 
eternal from what is perishable; it alone is capable of existence 
in isolation from all other psychic powers. All the other parts of 
soul, it is evident from what we have said, are, in spite of certain 
statements to the contrary, incapable of separate existence 
though, of course, distinguishable by definition. If opining is 



1191 



distinct from perceiving, to be capable of opining and to be 
capable of perceiving must be distinct, and so with all the other 
forms of living above enumerated. Further, some animals 
possess all these parts of soul, some certain of them only, 
others one only (this is what enables us to classify animals); the 
cause must be considered later.' A similar arrangement is found 
also within the field of the senses; some classes of animals have 
all the senses, some only certain of them, others only one, the 
most indispensable, touch. 

Since the expression 'that whereby we live and perceive' has 
two meanings, just like the expression 'that whereby we know' 
- that may mean either (a) knowledge or (b) the soul, for we can 
speak of knowing by or with either, and similarly that whereby 
we are in health may be either (a) health or (b) the body or some 
part of the body; and since of the two terms thus contrasted 
knowledge or health is the name of a form, essence, or ratio, or 
if we so express it an actuality of a recipient matter - knowledge 
of what is capable of knowing, health of what is capable of 
being made healthy (for the operation of that which is capable 
of originating change terminates and has its seat in what is 
changed or altered); further, since it is the soul by or with which 
primarily we live, perceive, and think: - it follows that the soul 
must be a ratio or formulable essence, not a matter or subject. 
For, as we said, word substance has three meanings form, 
matter, and the complex of both and of these three what is 
called matter is potentiality, what is called form actuality. Since 
then the complex here is the living thing, the body cannot be 
the actuality of the soul; it is the soul which is the actuality of a 
certain kind of body. Hence the Tightness of the view that the 
soul cannot be without a body, while it csnnot he a body; it is 
not a body but something relative to a body. That is why it is in a 
body, and a body of a definite kind. It was a mistake, therefore, 
to do as former thinkers did, merely to fit it into a body without 
adding a definite specification of the kind or character of that 



1192 



body. Reflection confirms the observed fact; the actuality of any 
given thing can only be realized in what is already potentially 
that thing, i.e. in a matter of its own appropriate to it. From all 
this it follows that soul is an actuality or formulable essence of 
something that possesses a potentiality of being besouled. 



Of the psychic powers above enumerated some kinds of living 
things, as we have said, possess all, some less than all, others 
one only. Those we have mentioned are the nutritive, the 
appetitive, the sensory, the locomotive, and the power of 
thinking. Plants have none but the first, the nutritive, while 
another order of living things has this plus the sensory. If any 
order of living things has the sensory, it must also have the 
appetitive; for appetite is the genus of which desire, passion, 
and wish are the species; now all animals have one sense at 
least, viz. touch, and whatever has a sense has the capacity for 
pleasure and pain and therefore has pleasant and painful 
objects present to it, and wherever these are present, there is 
desire, for desire is just appetition of what is pleasant. Further, 
all animals have the sense for food (for touch is the sense for 
food); the food of all living things consists of what is dry, moist, 
hot, cold, and these are the qualities apprehended by touch; all 
other sensible qualities are apprehended by touch only 
indirectly. Sounds, colours, and odours contribute nothing to 
nutriment; flavours fall within the field of tangible qualities. 
Hunger and thirst are forms of desire, hunger a desire for what 
is dry and hot, thirst a desire for what is cold and moist; flavour 
is a sort of seasoning added to both. We must later clear up 
these points, but at present it may be enough to say that all 
animals that possess the sense of touch have also appetition. 



1193 



The case of imagination is obscure; we must examine it later. 
Certain kinds of animals possess in addition the power of 
locomotion, and still another order of animate beings, i.e. man 
and possibly another order like man or superior to him, the 
power of thinking, i.e. mind. It is now evident that a single 
definition can be given of soul only in the same sense as one 
can be given of figure. For, as in that case there is no figure 
distinguishable and apart from triangle, &c, so here there is no 
soul apart from the forms of soul just enumerated. It is true that 
a highly general definition can be given for figure which will fit 
all figures without expressing the peculiar nature of any figure. 
So here in the case of soul and its specific forms. Hence it is 
absurd in this and similar cases to demand an absolutely 
general definition which will fail to express the peculiar nature 
of anything that is, or again, omitting this, to look for separate 
definitions corresponding to each infima species. The cases of 
figure and soul are exactly parallel; for the particulars 
subsumed under the common name in both cases - figures and 
living beings - constitute a series, each successive term of 
which potentially contains its predecessor, e.g. the square the 
triangle, the sensory power the self-nutritive. Hence we must 
ask in the case of each order of living things, What is its soul, i.e. 
What is the soul of plant, animal, man? Why the terms are 
related in this serial way must form the subject of later 
examination. But the facts are that the power of perception is 
never found apart from the power of self-nutrition, while - in 
plants - the latter is found isolated from the former. Again, no 
sense is found apart from that of touch, while touch is found by 
itself; many animals have neither sight, hearing, nor smell. 
Again, among living things that possess sense some have the 
power of locomotion, some not. Lastly, certain living beings - a 
small minority - possess calculation and thought, for (among 
mortal beings) those which possess calculation have all the 
other powers above mentioned, while the converse does not 



1194 



hold - indeed some live by imagination alone, while others have 
not even imagination. The mind that knows with immediate 
intuition presents a different problem. 

It is evident that the way to give the most adequate definition of 
soul is to seek in the case of each of its forms for the most 
appropriate definition. 



It is necessary for the student of these forms of soul first to find 
a definition of each, expressive of what it is, and then to 
investigate its derivative properties, &c. But if we are to express 
what each is, viz. what the thinking power is, or the perceptive, 
or the nutritive, we must go farther back and first give an 
account of thinking or perceiving, for in the order of 
investigation the question of what an agent does precedes the 
question, what enables it to do what it does. If this is correct, we 
must on the same ground go yet another step farther back and 
have some clear view of the objects of each; thus we must start 
with these objects, e.g. with food, with what is perceptible, or 
with what is intelligible. 

It follows that first of all we must treat of nutrition and 
reproduction, for the nutritive soul is found along with all the 
others and is the most primitive and widely distributed power 
of soul, being indeed that one in virtue of which all are said to 
have life. The acts in which it manifests itself are reproduction 
and the use of food - reproduction, I say, because for any living 
thing that has reached its normal development and which is 
unmutilated, and whose mode of generation is not 
spontaneous, the most natural act is the production of another 
like itself, an animal producing an animal, a plant a plant, in 



1195 



order that, as far as its nature allows, it may partake in the 
eternal and divine. That is the goal towards which all things 
strive, that for the sake of which they do whatsoever their 
nature renders possible. The phrase 'for the sake of which' is 
ambiguous; it may mean either (a) the end to achieve which, or 
(b) the being in whose interest, the act is done. Since then no 
living thing is able to partake in what is eternal and divine by 
uninterrupted continuance (for nothing perishable can for ever 
remain one and the same), it tries to achieve that end in the 
only way possible to it, and success is possible in varying 
degrees; so it remains not indeed as the self-same individual 
but continues its existence in something like itself - not 
numerically but specifically one. 

The soul is the cause or source of the living body. The terms 
cause and source have many senses. But the soul is the cause of 
its body alike in all three senses which we explicitly recognize. 
It is (a) the source or origin of movement, it is (b) the end, it is (c) 
the essence of the whole living body. 

That it is the last, is clear; for in everything the essence is 
identical with the ground of its being, and here, in the case of 
living things, their being is to live, and of their being and their 
living the soul in them is the cause or source. Further, the 
actuality of whatever is potential is identical with its formulable 
essence. 

It is manifest that the soul is also the final cause of its body. For 
Nature, like mind, always does whatever it does for the sake of 
something, which something is its end. To that something 
corresponds in the case of animals the soul and in this it 
follows the order of nature; all natural bodies are organs of the 
soul. This is true of those that enter into the constitution of 
plants as well as of those which enter into that of animals. This 
shows that that the sake of which they are is soul. We must 



1196 



here recall the two senses of that for the sake of which', viz. (a) 
the end to achieve which, and (b) the being in whose interest, 
anything is or is done. 

We must maintain, further, that the soul is also the cause of the 
living body as the original source of local movement. The power 
of locomotion is not found, however, in all living things. But 
change of quality and change of quantity are also due to the 
soul. Sensation is held to be a qualitative alteration, and 
nothing except what has soul in it is capable of sensation. The 
same holds of the quantitative changes which constitute 
growth and decay; nothing grows or decays naturally except 
what feeds itself, and nothing feeds itself except what has a 
share of soul in it. 

Empedocles is wrong in adding that growth in plants is to be 
explained, the downward rooting by the natural tendency of 
earth to travel downwards, and the upward branching by the 
similar natural tendency of fire to travel upwards. For he 
misinterprets up and down; up and down are not for all things 
what they are for the whole Cosmos: if we are to distinguish 
and identify organs according to their functions, the roots of 
plants are analogous to the head in animals. Further, we must 
ask what is the force that holds together the earth and the fire 
which tend to travel in contrary directions; if there is no 
counteracting force, they will be torn asunder; if there is, this 
must be the soul and the cause of nutrition and growth. By 
some the element of fire is held to be the cause of nutrition and 
growth, for it alone of the primary bodies or elements is 
observed to feed and increase itself. Hence the suggestion that 
in both plants and animals it is it which is the operative force. A 
concurrent cause in a sense it certainly is, but not the principal 
cause, that is rather the soul; for while the growth of fire goes 
on without limit so long as there is a supply of fuel, in the case 
of all complex wholes formed in the course of nature there is a 



1197 



limit or ratio which determines their size and increase, and 
limit and ratio are marks of soul but not of fire, and belong to 
the side of formulable essence rather than that of matter. 

Nutrition and reproduction are due to one and the same psychic 
power. It is necessary first to give precision to our account of 
food, for it is by this function of absorbing food that this psychic 
power is distinguished from all the others. The current view is 
that what serves as food to a living thing is what is contrary to 
it - not that in every pair of contraries each is food to the other: 
to be food a contrary must not only be transformable into the 
other and vice versa, it must also in so doing increase the bulk 
of the other. Many a contrary is transformed into its other and 
vice versa, where neither is even a quantum and so cannot 
increase in bulk, e.g. an invalid into a healthy subject. It is clear 
that not even those contraries which satisfy both the conditions 
mentioned above are food to one another in precisely the same 
sense; water may be said to feed fire, but not fire water. Where 
the members of the pair are elementary bodies only one of the 
contraries, it would appear, can be said to feed the other. But 
there is a difficulty here. One set of thinkers assert that like fed, 
as well as increased in amount, by like. Another set, as we have 
said, maintain the very reverse, viz. that what feeds and what is 
fed are contrary to one another; like, they argue, is incapable of 
being affected by like; but food is changed in the process of 
digestion, and change is always to what is opposite or to what is 
intermediate. Further, food is acted upon by what is nourished 
by it, not the other way round, as timber is worked by a 
carpenter and not conversely; there is a change in the carpenter 
but it is merely a change from not-working to working. In 
answering this problem it makes all the difference whether we 
mean by 'the food' the 'finished' or the 'raw' product. If we use 
the word food of both, viz. of the completely undigested and the 
completely digested matter, we can justify both the rival 
accounts of it; taking food in the sense of undigested matter, it 



1198 



is the contrary of what is fed by it, taking it as digested it is like 
what is fed by it. Consequently it is clear that in a certain sense 
we may say that both parties are right, both wrong. 

Since nothing except what is alive can be fed, what is fed is the 
besouled body and just because it has soul in it. Hence food is 
essentially related to what has soul in it. Food has a power 
which is other than the power to increase the bulk of what is 
fed by it; so far forth as what has soul in it is a quantum, food 
may increase its quantity, but it is only so far as what has soul 
in it is a 'this-somewhat' or substance that food acts as food; in 
that case it maintains the being of what is fed, and that 
continues to be what it is so long as the process of nutrition 
continues. Further, it is the agent in generation, i.e. not the 
generation of the individual fed but the reproduction of another 
like it; the substance of the individual fed is already in 
existence; the existence of no substance is a self-generation but 
only a self-maintenance. 

Hence the psychic power which we are now studying may be 
described as that which tends to maintain whatever has this 
power in it of continuing such as it was, and food helps it to do 
its work. That is why, if deprived of food, it must cease to be. 

The process of nutrition involves three factors, (a) what is fed, 

(b) that wherewith it is fed, (c) what does the feeding; of these 

(c) is the first soul, (a) the body which has that soul in it, (b) the 
food. But since it is right to call things after the ends they 
realize, and the end of this soul is to generate another being like 
that in which it is, the first soul ought to be named the 
reproductive soul. The expression (b) 'wherewith it is fed' is 
ambiguous just as is the expression 'wherewith the ship is 
steered'; that may mean either (i) the hand or (ii) the rudder, i.e. 
either (i) what is moved and sets in movement, or (ii) what is 
merely moved. We can apply this analogy here if we recall that 



1199 



all food must be capable of being digested, and that what 
produces digestion is warmth; that is why everything that has 
soul in it possesses warmth. 

We have now given an outline account of the nature of food; 
further details must be given in the appropriate place. 



Having made these distinctions let us now speak of sensation in 
the widest sense. Sensation depends, as we have said, on a 
process of movement or affection from without, for it is held to 
be some sort of change of quality. Now some thinkers assert 
that like is affected only by like; in what sense this is possible 
and in what sense impossible, we have explained in our general 
discussion of acting and being acted upon. 

Here arises a problem: why do we not perceive the senses 
themselves as well as the external objects of sense, or why 
without the stimulation of external objects do they not produce 
sensation, seeing that they contain in themselves fire, earth, 
and all the other elements, which are the direct or indirect 
objects is so of sense? It is clear that what is sensitive is only 
potentially, not actually. The power of sense is parallel to what 
is combustible, for that never ignites itself spontaneously, but 
requires an agent which has the power of starting ignition; 
otherwise it could have set itself on fire, and would not have 
needed actual fire to set it ablaze. 

In reply we must recall that we use the word 'perceive' in two 
ways, for we say (a) that what has the power to hear or see, 
'sees' or 'hears', even though it is at the moment asleep, and 
also (b) that what is actually seeing or hearing, 'sees' or 'hears'. 



1200 



Hence 'sense' too must have two meanings, sense potential, and 
sense actual. Similarly 'to be a sentient' means either (a) to have 
a certain power or (b) to manifest a certain activity. To begin 
with, for a time, let us speak as if there were no difference 
between (i) being moved or affected, and (ii) being active, for 
movement is a kind of activity - an imperfect kind, as has 
elsewhere been explained. Everything that is acted upon or 
moved is acted upon by an agent which is actually at work. 
Hence it is that in one sense, as has already been stated, what 
acts and what is acted upon are like, in another unlike, i.e. prior 
to and during the change the two factors are unlike, after it like. 

But we must now distinguish not only between what is 
potential and what is actual but also different senses in which 
things can be said to be potential or actual; up to now we have 
been speaking as if each of these phrases had only one sense. 
We can speak of something as 'a knower' either (a) as when we 
say that man is a knower, meaning that man falls within the 
class of beings that know or have knowledge, or (b) as when we 
are speaking of a man who possesses a knowledge of grammar; 
each of these is so called as having in him a certain potentiality, 
but there is a difference between their respective potentialities, 
the one (a) being a potential knower, because his kind or matter 
is such and such, the other (b), because he can in the absence of 
any external counteracting cause realize his knowledge in 
actual knowing at will. This implies a third meaning of 'a 
knower' (c), one who is already realizing his knowledge - he is a 
knower in actuality and in the most proper sense is knowing, 
e.g. this A. Both the former are potential knowers, who realize 
their respective potentialities, the one (a) by change of quality, 
i.e. repeated transitions from one state to its opposite under 
instruction, the other (b) by the transition from the inactive 
possession of sense or grammar to their active exercise. The two 
kinds of transition are distinct. 



1201 



Also the expression 'to be acted upon' has more than one 
meaning; it may mean either (a) the extinction of one of two 
contraries by the other, or (b) the maintenance of what is 
potential by the agency of what is actual and already like what 
is acted upon, with such likeness as is compatible with one's 
being actual and the other potential. For what possesses 
knowledge becomes an actual knower by a transition which is 
either not an alteration of it at all (being in reality a 
development into its true self or actuality) or at least an 
alteration in a quite different sense from the usual meaning. 

Hence it is wrong to speak of a wise man as being 'altered' 
when he uses his wisdom, just as it would be absurd to speak of 
a builder as being altered when he is using his skill in building a 
house. 

What in the case of knowing or understanding leads from 
potentiality to actuality ought not to be called teaching but 
something else. That which starting with the power to know 
learns or acquires knowledge through the agency of one who 
actually knows and has the power of teaching either (a) ought 
not to be said 'to be acted upon' at all or (b) we must recognize 
two senses of alteration, viz. (i) the substitution of one quality 
for another, the first being the contrary of the second, or (ii) the 
development of an existent quality from potentiality in the 
direction of fixity or nature. 

In the case of what is to possess sense, the first transition is due 
to the action of the male parent and takes place before birth so 
that at birth the living thing is, in respect of sensation, at the 
stage which corresponds to the possession of knowledge. Actual 
sensation corresponds to the stage of the exercise of knowledge. 
But between the two cases compared there is a difference; the 
objects that excite the sensory powers to activity, the seen, the 
heard, &c, are outside. The ground of this difference is that 



1202 



what actual sensation apprehends is individuals, while what 
knowledge apprehends is universals, and these are in a sense 
within the soul. That is why a man can exercise his knowledge 
when he wishes, but his sensation does not depend upon 
himself a sensible object must be there. A similar statement 
must be made about our knowledge of what is sensible - on the 
same ground, viz. that the sensible objects are individual and 
external. 

A later more appropriate occasion may be found thoroughly to 
clear up all this. At present it must be enough to recognize the 
distinctions already drawn; a thing may be said to be potential 
in either of two senses, (a) in the sense in which we might say 
of a boy that he may become a general or (b) in the sense in 
which we might say the same of an adult, and there are two 
corresponding senses of the term 'a potential sentient'. There 
are no separate names for the two stages of potentiality; we 
have pointed out that they are different and how they are 
different. We cannot help using the incorrect terms 'being acted 
upon or altered' of the two transitions involved. As we have 
said, has the power of sensation is potentially like what the 
perceived object is actually; that is, while at the beginning of the 
process of its being acted upon the two interacting factors are 
dissimilar, at the end the one acted upon is assimilated to the 
other and is identical in quality with it. 



In dealing with each of the senses we shall have first to speak of 
the objects which are perceptible by each. The term 'object of 
sense' covers three kinds of objects, two kinds of which are, in 
our language, directly perceptible, while the remaining one is 



1203 



only incidentally perceptible. Of the first two kinds one (a) 
consists of what is perceptible by a single sense, the other (b) of 
what is perceptible by any and all of the senses. I call by the 
name of special object of this or that sense that which cannot 
be perceived by any other sense than that one and in respect of 
which no error is possible; in this sense colour is the special 
object of sight, sound of hearing, flavour of taste. Touch, indeed, 
discriminates more than one set of different qualities. Each 
sense has one kind of object which it discerns, and never errs in 
reporting that what is before it is colour or sound (though it 
may err as to what it is that is coloured or where that is, or what 
it is that is sounding or where that is.) Such objects are what we 
propose to call the special objects of this or that sense. 

'Common sensibles' are movement, rest, number, figure, 
magnitude; these are not peculiar to any one sense, but are 
common to all. There are at any rate certain kinds of movement 
which are perceptible both by touch and by sight. 

We speak of an incidental object of sense where e.g. the white 
object which we see is the son of Diares; here because 'being the 
son of Diares' is incidental to the directly visible white patch we 
speak of the son of Diares as being (incidentally) perceived or 
seen by us. Because this is only incidentally an object of sense, 
it in no way as such affects the senses. Of the two former kinds, 
both of which are in their own nature perceptible by sense, the 
first kind - that of special objects of the several senses - 
constitute the objects of sense in the strictest sense of the term 
and it is to them that in the nature of things the structure of 
each several sense is adapted. 



1204 



The object of sight is the visible, and what is visible is (a) colour 
and (b) a certain kind of object which can be described in words 
but which has no single name; what we mean by (b) will be 
abundantly clear as we proceed. Whatever is visible is colour 
and colour is what lies upon what is in its own nature visible; 
'in its own nature' here means not that visibility is involved in 
the definition of what thus underlies colour, but that that 
substratum contains in itself the cause of visibility. Every colour 
has in it the power to set in movement what is actually 
transparent; that power constitutes its very nature. That is why 
it is not visible except with the help of light; it is only in light 
that the colour of a thing is seen. Hence our first task is to 
explain what light is. 

Now there clearly is something which is transparent, and by 
'transparent' I mean what is visible, and yet not visible in itself, 
but rather owing its visibility to the colour of something else; of 
this character are air, water, and many solid bodies. Neither air 
nor water is transparent because it is air or water; they are 
transparent because each of them has contained in it a certain 
substance which is the same in both and is also found in the 
eternal body which constitutes the uppermost shell of the 
physical Cosmos. Of this substance light is the activity - the 
activity of what is transparent so far forth as it has in it the 
determinate power of becoming transparent; where this power 
is present, there is also the potentiality of the contrary, viz. 
darkness. Light is as it were the proper colour of what is 
transparent, and exists whenever the potentially transparent is 
excited to actuality by the influence of fire or something 
resembling 'the uppermost body'; for fire too contains 
something which is one and the same with the substance in 
question. 



1205 



We have now explained what the transparent is and what light 
is; light is neither fire nor any kind whatsoever of body nor an 
efflux from any kind of body (if it were, it would again itself be a 
kind of body) - it is the presence of fire or something resembling 
fire in what is transparent. It is certainly not a body, for two 
bodies cannot be present in the same place. The opposite of 
light is darkness; darkness is the absence from what is 
transparent of the corresponding positive state above 
characterized; clearly therefore, light is just the presence of 
that. 

Empedocles (and with him all others who used the same forms 
of expression) was wrong in speaking of light as 'travelling' or 
being at a given moment between the earth and its envelope, its 
movement being unobservable by us; that view is contrary both 
to the clear evidence of argument and to the observed facts; if 
the distance traversed were short, the movement might have 
been unobservable, but where the distance is from extreme East 
to extreme West, the draught upon our powers of belief is too 
great. 

What is capable of taking on colour is what in itself is 
colourless, as what can take on sound is what is soundless; 
what is colourless includes (a) what is transparent and (b) what 
is invisible or scarcely visible, i.e. what is 'dark'. The latter (b) is 
the same as what is transparent, when it is potentially, not of 
course when it is actually transparent; it is the same substance 
which is now darkness, now light. 

Not everything that is visible depends upon light for its 
visibility. This is only true of the 'proper' colour of things. Some 
objects of sight which in light are invisible, in darkness 
stimulate the sense; that is, things that appear fiery or shining. 
This class of objects has no simple common name, but 
instances of it are fungi, flesh, heads, scales, and eyes offish. In 



1206 



none of these is what is seen their own proper' colour. Why we 
see these at all is another question. At present what is obvious 
is that what is seen in light is always colour. That is why 
without the help of light colour remains invisible. Its being 
colour at all means precisely its having in it the power to set in 
movement what is already actually transparent, and, as we have 
seen, the actuality of what is transparent is just light. 

The following experiment makes the necessity of a medium 
clear. If what has colour is placed in immediate contact with the 
eye, it cannot be seen. Colour sets in movement not the sense 
organ but what is transparent, e.g. the air, and that, extending 
continuously from the object to the organ, sets the latter in 
movement. Democritus misrepresents the facts when he 
expresses the opinion that if the interspace were empty one 
could distinctly see an ant on the vault of the sky; that is an 
impossibility. Seeing is due to an affection or change of what 
has the perceptive faculty, and it cannot be affected by the seen 
colour itself; it remains that it must be affected by what comes 
between. Hence it is indispensable that there be something in 
between - if there were nothing, so far from seeing with greater 
distinctness, we should see nothing at all. 

We have now explained the cause why colour cannot be seen 
otherwise than in light. Fire on the other hand is seen both in 
darkness and in light; this double possibility follows necessarily 
from our theory, for it is just fire that makes what is potentially 
transparent actually transparent. 

The same account holds also of sound and smell; if the object of 
either of these senses is in immediate contact with the organ no 
sensation is produced. In both cases the object sets in 
movement only what lies between, and this in turn sets the 
organ in movement: if what sounds or smells is brought into 
immediate contact with the organ, no sensation will be 



1207 



produced. The same, in spite of all appearances, applies also to 
touch and taste; why there is this apparent difference will be 
clear later. What comes between in the case of sounds is air; the 
corresponding medium in the case of smell has no name. But, 
corresponding to what is transparent in the case of colour, there 
is a quality found both in air and water, which serves as a 
medium for what has smell - I say 'in water' because animals 
that live in water as well as those that live on land seem to 
possess the sense of smell, and 'in air' because man and all 
other land animals that breathe, perceive smells only when 
they breathe air in. The explanation of this too will be given 
later. 



8 

Now let us, to begin with, make certain distinctions about 
sound and hearing. 

Sound may mean either of two things (a) actual, and (b) 
potential, sound. There are certain things which, as we say, 
'have no sound', e.g. sponges or wool, others which have, e.g. 
bronze and in general all things which are smooth and solid - 
the latter are said to have a sound because they can make a 
sound, i.e. can generate actual sound between themselves and 
the organ of hearing. 

Actual sound requires for its occurrence (i, ii) two such bodies 
and (iii) a space between them; for it is generated by an impact. 
Hence it is impossible for one body only to generate a sound - 
there must be a body impinging and a body impinged upon; 
what sounds does so by striking against something else, and 
this is impossible without a movement from place to place. 



1208 



As we have said, not all bodies can by impact on one another 
produce sound; impact on wool makes no sound, while the 
impact on bronze or any body which is smooth and hollow 
does. Bronze gives out a sound when struck because it is 
smooth; bodies which are hollow owing to reflection repeat the 
original impact over and over again, the body originally set in 
movement being unable to escape from the concavity. 

Further, we must remark that sound is heard both in air and in 
water, though less distinctly in the latter. Yet neither air nor 
water is the principal cause of sound. What is required for the 
production of sound is an impact of two solids against one 
another and against the air. The latter condition is satisfied 
when the air impinged upon does not retreat before the blow, 
i.e. is not dissipated by it. 

That is why it must be struck with a sudden sharp blow, if it is 
to sound - the movement of the whip must outrun the 
dispersion of the air, just as one might get in a stroke at a heap 
or whirl of sand as it was traveling rapidly past. 

An echo occurs, when, a mass of air having been unified, 
bounded, and prevented from dissipation by the containing 
walls of a vessel, the air originally struck by the impinging body 
and set in movement by it rebounds from this mass of air like a 
ball from a wall. It is probable that in all generation of sound 
echo takes place, though it is frequently only indistinctly heard. 
What happens here must be analogous to what happens in the 
case of light; light is always reflected - otherwise it would not 
be diffused and outside what was directly illuminated by the 
sun there would be blank darkness; but this reflected light is 
not always strong enough, as it is when it is reflected from 
water, bronze, and other smooth bodies, to cast a shadow, which 
is the distinguishing mark by which we recognize light. 



1209 



It is rightly said that an empty space plays the chief part in the 
production of hearing, for what people mean by 'the vacuum' is 
the air, which is what causes hearing, when that air is set in 
movement as one continuous mass; but owing to its friability it 
emits no sound, being dissipated by impinging upon any 
surface which is not smooth. When the surface on which it 
impinges is quite smooth, what is produced by the original 
impact is a united mass, a result due to the smoothness of the 
surface with which the air is in contact at the other end. 

What has the power of producing sound is what has the power 
of setting in movement a single mass of air which is continuous 
from the impinging body up to the organ of hearing. The organ 
of hearing is physically united with air, and because it is in air, 
the air inside is moved concurrently with the air outside. Hence 
animals do not hear with all parts of their bodies, nor do all 
parts admit of the entrance of air; for even the part which can 
be moved and can sound has not air everywhere in it. Air in 
itself is, owing to its friability, quite soundless; only when its 
dissipation is prevented is its movement sound. The air in the 
ear is built into a chamber just to prevent this dissipating 
movement, in order that the animal may accurately apprehend 
all varieties of the movements of the air outside. That is why we 
hear also in water, viz. because the water cannot get into the air 
chamber or even, owing to the spirals, into the outer ear. If this 
does happen, hearing ceases, as it also does if the tympanic 
membrane is damaged, just as sight ceases if the membrane 
covering the pupil is damaged. It is also a test of deafness 
whether the ear does or does not reverberate like a horn; the air 
inside the ear has always a movement of its own, but the sound 
we hear is always the sounding of something else, not of the 
organ itself. That is why we say that we hear with what is 
empty and echoes, viz. because what we hear with is a chamber 
which contains a bounded mass of air. 



1210 



Which is it that 'sounds', the striking body or the struck? Is not 
the answer 'it is both, but each in a different way? Sound is a 
movement of what can rebound from a smooth surface when 
struck against it. As we have explained' not everything sounds 
when it strikes or is struck, e.g. if one needle is struck against 
another, neither emits any sound. In order, therefore, that sound 
may be generated, what is struck must be smooth, to enable the 
air to rebound and be shaken off from it in one piece. 

The distinctions between different sounding bodies show 
themselves only in actual sound; as without the help of light 
colours remain invisible, so without the help of actual sound 
the distinctions between acute and grave sounds remain 
inaudible. Acute and grave are here metaphors, transferred from 
their proper sphere, viz. that of touch, where they mean 
respectively (a) what moves the sense much in a short time, (b) 
what moves the sense little in a long time. Not that what is 
sharp really moves fast, and what is grave, slowly, but that the 
difference in the qualities of the one and the other movement is 
due to their respective speeds. There seems to be a sort of 
parallelism between what is acute or grave to hearing and what 
is sharp or blunt to touch; what is sharp as it were stabs, while 
what is blunt pushes, the one producing its effect in a short, the 
other in a long time, so that the one is quick, the other slow. 

Let the foregoing suffice as an analysis of sound. Voice is a kind 
of sound characteristic of what has soul in it; nothing that is 
without soul utters voice, it being only by a metaphor that we 
speak of the voice of the flute or the lyre or generally of what 
(being without soul) possesses the power of producing a 
succession of notes which differ in length and pitch and timbre. 
The metaphor is based on the fact that all these differences are 
found also in voice. Many animals are voiceless, e.g. all non- 
sanuineous animals and among sanguineous animals fish. This 
is just what we should expect, since voice is a certain 



1211 



movement of air. The fish, like those in the Achelous, which are 
said to have voice, really make the sounds with their gills or 
some similar organ. Voice is the sound made by an animal, and 
that with a special organ. As we saw, everything that makes a 
sound does so by the impact of something (a) against 
something else, (b) across a space, (c) filled with air; hence it is 
only to be expected that no animals utter voice except those 
which take in air. Once air is inbreathed, Nature uses it for two 
different purposes, as the tongue is used both for tasting and 
for articulating; in that case of the two functions tasting is 
necessary for the animal's existence (hence it is found more 
widely distributed), while articulate speech is a luxury 
subserving its possessor's well-being; similarly in the former 
case Nature employs the breath both as an indispensable 
means to the regulation of the inner temperature of the living 
body and also as the matter of articulate voice, in the interests 
of its possessor's well-being. Why its former use is 
indispensable must be discussed elsewhere. 

The organ of respiration is the windpipe, and the organ to 
which this is related as means to end is the lungs. The latter is 
the part of the body by which the temperature of land animals 
is raised above that of all others. But what primarily requires 
the air drawn in by respiration is not only this but the region 
surrounding the heart. That is why when animals breathe the 
air must penetrate inwards. 

Voice then is the impact of the inbreathed air against the 
'windpipe', and the agent that produces the impact is the soul 
resident in these parts of the body. Not every sound, as we said, 
made by an animal is voice (even with the tongue we may 
merely make a sound which is not voice, or without the tongue 
as in coughing); what produces the impact must have soul in it 
and must be accompanied by an act of imagination, for voice is 
a sound with a meaning, and is not merely the result of any 



1212 



impact of the breath as in coughing; in voice the breath in the 
windpipe is used as an instrument to knock with against the 
walls of the windpipe. This is confirmed by our inability to 
speak when we are breathing either out or in - we can only do 
so by holding our breath; we make the movements with the 
breath so checked. It is clear also why fish are voiceless; they 
have no windpipe. And they have no windpipe because they do 
not breathe or take in air. Why they do not is a question 
belonging to another inquiry. 



Smell and its object are much less easy to determine than what 
we have hitherto discussed; the distinguishing characteristic of 
the object of smell is less obvious than those of sound or colour. 
The ground of this is that our power of smell is less 
discriminating and in general inferior to that of many species of 
animals; men have a poor sense of smell and our apprehension 
of its proper objects is inseparably bound up with and so 
confused by pleasure and pain, which shows that in us the 
organ is inaccurate. It is probable that there is a parallel failure 
in the perception of colour by animals that have hard eyes: 
probably they discriminate differences of colour only by the 
presence or absence of what excites fear, and that it is thus that 
human beings distinguish smells. It seems that there is an 
analogy between smell and taste, and that the species of tastes 
run parallel to those of smells - the only difference being that 
our sense of taste is more discriminating than our sense of 
smell, because the former is a modification of touch, which 
reaches in man the maximum of discriminative accuracy. While 
in respect of all the other senses we fall below many species of 
animals, in respect of touch we far excel all other species in 



1213 



exactness of discrimination. That is why man is the most 
intelligent of all animals. This is confirmed by the fact that it is 
to differences in the organ of touch and to nothing else that the 
differences between man and man in respect of natural 
endowment are due; men whose flesh is hard are ill-endowed 
by nature, men whose flesh is soft, wellendowed. 

As flavours may be divided into (a) sweet, (b) bitter, so with 
smells. In some things the flavour and the smell have the same 
quality, i.e. both are sweet or both bitter, in others they diverge. 
Similarly a smell, like a flavour, may be pungent, astringent, 
acid, or succulent. But, as we said, because smells are much less 
easy to discriminate than flavours, the names of these varieties 
are applied to smells only metaphorically; for example 'sweet' is 
extended from the taste to the smell of saffron or honey, 
'pungent' to that of thyme, and so on. 

In the same sense in which hearing has for its object both the 
audible and the inaudible, sight both the visible and the 
invisible, smell has for its object both the odorous and the 
inodorous. 'Inodorous' may be either (a) what has no smell at 
all, or (b) what has a small or feeble smell. The same ambiguity 
lurks in the word 'tasteless'. 

Smelling, like the operation of the senses previously examined, 
takes place through a medium, i.e. through air or water - I add 
water, because water-animals too (both sanguineous and non- 
sanguineous) seem to smell just as much as land-animals; at 
any rate some of them make directly for their food from a 
distance if it has any scent. That is why the following facts 
constitute a problem for us. All animals smell in the same way, 
but man smells only when he inhales; if he exhales or holds his 
breath, he ceases to smell, no difference being made whether 
the odorous object is distant or near, or even placed inside the 
nose and actually on the wall of the nostril; it is a disability 



1214 



common to all the senses not to perceive what is in immediate 
contact with the organ of sense, but our failure to apprehend 
what is odorous without the help of inhalation is peculiar (the 
fact is obvious on making the experiment). Now since bloodless 
animals do not breathe, they must, it might be argued, have 
some novel sense not reckoned among the usual five. Our reply 
must be that this is impossible, since it is scent that is 
perceived; a sense that apprehends what is odorous and what 
has a good or bad odour cannot be anything but smell. Further, 
they are observed to be deleteriously effected by the same 
strong odours as man is, e.g. bitumen, sulphur, and the like. 
These animals must be able to smell without being able to 
breathe. The probable explanation is that in man the organ of 
smell has a certain superiority over that in all other animals just 
as his eyes have over those of hard-eyed animals. Man's eyes 
have in the eyelids a kind of shelter or envelope, which must be 
shifted or drawn back in order that we may see, while hardeyed 
animals have nothing of the kind, but at once see whatever 
presents itself in the transparent medium. Similarly in certain 
species of animals the organ of smell is like the eye of hard- 
eyed animals, uncurtained, while in others which take in air it 
probably has a curtain over it, which is drawn back in 
inhalation, owing to the dilating of the veins or pores. That 
explains also why such animals cannot smell under water; to 
smell they must first inhale, and that they cannot do under 
water. 

Smells come from what is dry as flavours from what is moist. 
Consequently the organ of smell is potentially dry. 



1215 



10 

What can be tasted is always something that can be touched, 
and just for that reason it cannot be perceived through an 
interposed foreign body, for touch means the absence of any 
intervening body. Further, the flavoured and tasteable body is 
suspended in a liquid matter, and this is tangible. Hence, if we 
lived in water, we should perceive a sweet object introduced 
into the water, but the water would not be the medium through 
which we perceived; our perception would be due to the 
solution of the sweet substance in what we imbibed, just as if it 
were mixed with some drink. There is no parallel here to the 
perception of colour, which is due neither to any blending of 
anything with anything, nor to any efflux of anything from 
anything. In the case of taste, there is nothing corresponding to 
the medium in the case of the senses previously discussed; but 
as the object of sight is colour, so the object of taste is flavour. 
But nothing excites a perception of flavour without the help of 
liquid; what acts upon the sense of taste must be either actually 
or potentially liquid like what is saline; it must be both (a) itself 
easily dissolved, and (b) capable of dissolving along with itself 
the tongue. Taste apprehends both (a) what has taste and (b) 
what has no taste, if we mean by (b) what has only a slight or 
feeble flavour or what tends to destroy the sense of taste. In this 
it is exactly parallel to sight, which apprehends both what is 
visible and what is invisible (for darkness is invisible and yet is 
discriminated by sight; so is, in a different way, what is over 
brilliant), and to hearing, which apprehends both sound and 
silence, of which the one is audible and the other inaudible, and 
also over-loud sound. This corresponds in the case of hearing to 
over-bright light in the case of sight. As a faint sound is 
'inaudible', so in a sense is a loud or violent sound. The word 
'invisible' and similar privative terms cover not only (a) what is 
simply without some power, but also (b) what is adapted by 
nature to have it but has not it or has it only in a very low 



1216 



degree, as when we say that a species of swallow is 'footless' or 
that a variety of fruit is 'stoneless'. So too taste has as its object 
both what can be tasted and the tasteless - the latter in the 
sense of what has little flavour or a bad flavour or one 
destructive of taste. The difference between what is tasteless 
and what is not seems to rest ultimately on that between what 
is drinkable and what is undrinkable both are tasteable, but the 
latter is bad and tends to destroy taste, while the former is the 
normal stimulus of taste. What is drinkable is the common 
object of both touch and taste. 

Since what can be tasted is liquid, the organ for its perception 
cannot be either (a) actually liquid or (b) incapable of becoming 
liquid. Tasting means a being affected by what can be tasted as 
such; hence the organ of taste must be liquefied, and so to start 
with must be non-liquid but capable of liquefaction without 
loss of its distinctive nature. This is confirmed by the fact that 
the tongue cannot taste either when it is too dry or when it is 
too moist; in the latter case what occurs is due to a contact with 
the pre-existent moisture in the tongue itself, when after a 
foretaste of some strong flavour we try to taste another flavour; 
it is in this way that sick persons find everything they taste 
bitter, viz. because, when they taste, their tongues are 
overflowing with bitter moisture. 

The species of flavour are, as in the case of colour, (a) simple, i.e. 
the two contraries, the sweet and the bitter, (b) secondary, viz. (i) 
on the side of the sweet, the succulent, (ii) on the side of the 
bitter, the saline, (iii) between these come the pungent, the 
harsh, the astringent, and the acid; these pretty well exhaust 
the varieties of flavour. It follows that what has the power of 
tasting is what is potentially of that kind, and that what is 
tasteable is what has the power of making it actually what it 
itself already is. 



1217 



11 

Whatever can be said of what is tangible, can be said of touch, 
and vice versa; if touch is not a single sense but a group of 
senses, there must be several kinds of what is tangible. It is a 
problem whether touch is a single sense or a group of senses. It 
is also a problem, what is the organ of touch; is it or is it not the 
flesh (including what in certain animals is homologous with 
flesh)? On the second view, flesh is 'the medium' of touch, the 
real organ being situated farther inward. The problem arises 
because the field of each sense is according to the accepted 
view determined as the range between a single pair of 
contraries, white and black for sight, acute and grave for 
hearing, bitter and sweet for taste; but in the field of what is 
tangible we find several such pairs, hot cold, dry moist, hard 
soft, &c. This problem finds a partial solution, when it is recalled 
that in the case of the other senses more than one pair of 
contraries are to be met with, e.g. in sound not only acute and 
grave but loud and soft, smooth and rough, &c; there are 
similar contrasts in the field of colour. Nevertheless we are 
unable clearly to detect in the case of touch what the single 
subject is which underlies the contrasted qualities and 
corresponds to sound in the case of hearing. 

To the question whether the organ of touch lies inward or not 
(i.e. whether we need look any farther than the flesh), no 
indication in favour of the second answer can be drawn from 
the fact that if the object comes into contact with the flesh it is 
at once perceived. For even under present conditions if the 
experiment is made of making a web and stretching it tight over 
the flesh, as soon as this web is touched the sensation is 
reported in the same manner as before, yet it is clear that the or 



1218 



is gan is not in this membrane. If the membrane could be grown 
on to the flesh, the report would travel still quicker. The flesh 
plays in touch very much the same part as would be played in 
the other senses by an air-envelope growing round our body; 
had we such an envelope attached to us we should have 
supposed that it was by a single organ that we perceived 
sounds, colours, and smells, and we should have taken sight, 
hearing, and smell to be a single sense. But as it is, because that 
through which the different movements are transmitted is not 
naturally attached to our bodies, the difference of the various 
sense-organs is too plain to miss. But in the case of touch the 
obscurity remains. 

There must be such a naturally attached 'medium' as flesh, for 
no living body could be constructed of air or water; it must be 
something solid. Consequently it must be composed of earth 
along with these, which is just what flesh and its analogue in 
animals which have no true flesh tend to be. Hence of necessity 
the medium through which are transmitted the manifoldly 
contrasted tactual qualities must be a body naturally attached 
to the organism. That they are manifold is clear when we 
consider touching with the tongue; we apprehend at the tongue 
all tangible qualities as well as flavour. Suppose all the rest of 
our flesh was, like the tongue, sensitive to flavour, we should 
have identified the sense of taste and the sense of touch; what 
saves us from this identification is the fact that touch and taste 
are not always found together in the same part of the body. The 
following problem might be raised. Let us assume that every 
body has depth, i.e. has three dimensions, and that if two bodies 
have a third body between them they cannot be in contact with 
one another; let us remember that what is liquid is a body and 
must be or contain water, and that if two bodies touch one 
another under water, their touching surfaces cannot be dry, but 
must have water between, viz. the water which wets their 
bounding surfaces; from all this it follows that in water two 



1219 



bodies cannot be in contact with one another. The same holds 
of two bodies in air - air being to bodies in air precisely what 
water is to bodies in water - but the facts are not so evident to 
our observation, because we live in air, just as animals that live 
in water would not notice that the things which touch one 
another in water have wet surfaces. The problem, then, is: does 
the perception of all objects of sense take place in the same 
way, or does it not, e.g. taste and touch requiring contact (as 
they are commonly thought to do), while all other senses 
perceive over a distance? The distinction is unsound; we 
perceive what is hard or soft, as well as the objects of hearing, 
sight, and smell, through a 'medium', only that the latter are 
perceived over a greater distance than the former; that is why 
the facts escape our notice. For we do perceive everything 
through a medium; but in these cases the fact escapes us. Yet, 
to repeat what we said before, if the medium for touch were a 
membrane separating us from the object without our observing 
its existence, we should be relatively to it in the same condition 
as we are now to air or water in which we are immersed; in 
their case we fancy we can touch objects, nothing coming in 
between us and them. But there remains this difference 
between what can be touched and what can be seen or can 
sound; in the latter two cases we perceive because the medium 
produces a certain effect upon us, whereas in the perception of 
objects of touch we are affected not by but along with the 
medium; it is as if a man were struck through his shield, where 
the shock is not first given to the shield and passed on to the 
man, but the concussion of both is simultaneous. 

In general, flesh and the tongue are related to the real organs of 
touch and taste, as air and water are to those of sight, hearing, 
and smell. Hence in neither the one case nor the other can 
there be any perception of an object if it is placed immediately 
upon the organ, e.g. if a white object is placed on the surface of 
the eye. This again shows that what has the power of perceiving 



1220 



the tangible is seated inside. Only so would there be a complete 
analogy with all the other senses. In their case if you place the 
object on the organ it is not perceived, here if you place it on the 
flesh it is perceived; therefore flesh is not the organ but the 
medium of touch. 

What can be touched are distinctive qualities of body as body; 
by such differences I mean those which characterize the 
elements, viz, hot cold, dry moist, of which we have spoken 
earlier in our treatise on the elements. The organ for the 
perception of these is that of touch - that part of the body in 
which primarily the sense of touch resides. This is that part 
which is potentially such as its object is actually: for all sense- 
perception is a process of being so affected; so that that which 
makes something such as it itself actually is makes the other 
such because the other is already potentially such. That is why 
when an object of touch is equally hot and cold or hard and soft 
we cannot perceive; what we perceive must have a degree of the 
sensible quality lying beyond the neutral point. This implies 
that the sense itself is a 'mean' between any two opposite 
qualities which determine the field of that sense. It is to this 
that it owes its power of discerning the objects in that field. 
What is 'in the middle' is fitted to discern; relatively to either 
extreme it can put itself in the place of the other. As what is to 
perceive both white and black must, to begin with, be actually 
neither but potentially either (and so with all the other sense- 
organs), so the organ of touch must be neither hot nor cold. 

Further, as in a sense sight had for its object both what was 
visible and what was invisible (and there was a parallel truth 
about all the other senses discussed), so touch has for its object 
both what is tangible and what is intangible. Here by 'intangible' 
is meant (a) what like air possesses some quality of tangible 
things in a very slight degree and (b) what possesses it in an 
excessive degree, as destructive things do. 



1221 



We have now given an outline account of each of the several 
senses. 



12 

The following results applying to any and every sense may now 
be formulated. 

(A) By a 'sense' is meant what has the power of receiving into 
itself the sensible forms of things without the matter. This must 
be conceived of as taking place in the way in which a piece of 
wax takes on the impress of a signet-ring without the iron or 
gold; we say that what produces the impression is a signet of 
bronze or gold, but its particular metallic constitution makes no 
difference: in a similar way the sense is affected by what is 
coloured or flavoured or sounding, but it is indifferent what in 
each case the substance is; what alone matters is what quality 
it has, i.e. in what ratio its constituents are combined. 

(B) By 'an organ of sense' is meant that in which ultimately such 
a power is seated. 

The sense and its organ are the same in fact, but their essence 
is not the same. What perceives is, of course, a spatial 
magnitude, but we must not admit that either the having the 
power to perceive or the sense itself is a magnitude; what they 
are is a certain ratio or power in a magnitude. This enables us to 
explain why objects of sense which possess one of two opposite 
sensible qualities in a degree largely in excess of the other 
opposite destroy the organs of sense; if the movement set up by 
an object is too strong for the organ, the equipoise of contrary 
qualities in the organ, which just is its sensory power, is 
disturbed; it is precisely as concord and tone are destroyed by 



1222 



too violently twanging the strings of a lyre. This explains also 
why plants cannot perceive, in spite of their having a portion of 
soul in them and obviously being affected by tangible objects 
themselves; for undoubtedly their temperature can be lowered 
or raised. The explanation is that they have no mean of contrary 
qualities, and so no principle in them capable of taking on the 
forms of sensible objects without their matter; in the case of 
plants the affection is an affection by form-and-matter together. 
The problem might be raised: Can what cannot smell be said to 
be affected by smells or what cannot see by colours, and so on? 
It might be said that a smell is just what can be smelt, and if it 
produces any effect it can only be so as to make something 
smell it, and it might be argued that what cannot smell cannot 
be affected by smells and further that what can smell can be 
affected by it only in so far as it has in it the power to smell 
(similarly with the proper objects of all the other senses). 
Indeed that this is so is made quite evident as follows. Light or 
darkness, sounds and smells leave bodies quite unaffected; 
what does affect bodies is not these but the bodies which are 
their vehicles, e.g. what splits the trunk of a tree is not the 
sound of the thunder but the air which accompanies thunder. 
Yes, but, it may be objected, bodies are affected by what is 
tangible and by flavours. If not, by what are things that are 
without soul affected, i.e. altered in quality? Must we not, then, 
admit that the objects of the other senses also may affect them? 
Is not the true account this, that all bodies are capable of being 
affected by smells and sounds, but that some on being acted 
upon, having no boundaries of their own, disintegrate, as in the 
instance of air, which does become odorous, showing that some 
effect is produced on it by what is odorous? But smelling is 
more than such an affection by what is odorous - what more? Is 
not the answer that, while the air owing to the momentary 
duration of the action upon it of what is odorous does itself 



1223 



become perceptible to the sense of smell, smelling is an 
observing of the result produced? 



Book III 



That there is no sixth sense in addition to the five enumerated - 
sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch - may be established by the 
following considerations: 

If we have actually sensation of everything of which touch can 
give us sensation (for all the qualities of the tangible qua 
tangible are perceived by us through touch); and if absence of a 
sense necessarily involves absence of a sense-organ; and if (1) 
all objects that we perceive by immediate contact with them are 
perceptible by touch, which sense we actually possess, and (2) 
all objects that we perceive through media, i.e. without 
immediate contact, are perceptible by or through the simple 
elements, e.g. air and water (and this is so arranged that (a) if 
more than one kind of sensible object is perceivable through a 
single medium, the possessor of a sense-organ homogeneous 
with that medium has the power of perceiving both kinds of 
objects; for example, if the sense-organ is made of air, and air is 
a medium both for sound and for colour; and that (b) if more 
than one medium can transmit the same kind of sensible 
objects, as e.g. water as well as air can transmit colour, both 
being transparent, then the possessor of either alone will be 



1224 



able to perceive the kind of objects transmissible through both); 
and if of the simple elements two only, air and water, go to form 
sense-organs (for the pupil is made of water, the organ of 
hearing is made of air, and the organ of smell of one or other of 
these two, while fire is found either in none or in all - warmth 
being an essential condition of all sensibility - and earth either 
in none or, if anywhere, specially mingled with the components 
of the organ of touch; wherefore it would remain that there can 
be no sense-organ formed of anything except water and air); 
and if these sense-organs are actually found in certain animals; 
- then all the possible senses are possessed by those animals 
that are not imperfect or mutilated (for even the mole is 
observed to have eyes beneath its skin); so that, if there is no 
fifth element and no property other than those which belong to 
the four elements of our world, no sense can be wanting to such 
animals. 

Further, there cannot be a special sense-organ for the common 
sensibles either, i.e. the objects which we perceive incidentally 
through this or that special sense, e.g. movement, rest, figure, 
magnitude, number, unity; for all these we perceive by 
movement, e.g. magnitude by movement, and therefore also 
figure (for figure is a species of magnitude), what is at rest by 
the absence of movement: number is perceived by the negation 
of continuity, and by the special sensibles; for each sense 
perceives one class of sensible objects. So that it is clearly 
impossible that there should be a special sense for any one of 
the common sensibles, e.g. movement; for, if that were so, our 
perception of it would be exactly parallel to our present 
perception of what is sweet by vision. That is so because we 
have a sense for each of the two qualities, in virtue of which 
when they happen to meet in one sensible object we are aware 
of both contemporaneously. If it were not like this our 
perception of the common qualities would always be incidental, 
i.e. as is the perception of Cleon's son, where we perceive him 



1225 



not as Cleon's son but as white, and the white thing which we 
really perceive happens to be Cleon's son. 

But in the case of the common sensibles there is already in us a 
general sensibility which enables us to perceive them directly; 
there is therefore no special sense required for their perception: 
if there were, our perception of them would have been exactly 
like what has been above described. 

The senses perceive each other's special objects incidentally; 
not because the percipient sense is this or that special sense, 
but because all form a unity: this incidental perception takes 
place whenever sense is directed at one and the same moment 
to two disparate qualities in one and the same object, e.g. to the 
bitterness and the yellowness of bile, the assertion of the 
identity of both cannot be the act of either of the senses; hence 
the illusion of sense, e.g. the belief that if a thing is yellow it is 
bile. 

It might be asked why we have more senses than one. Is it to 
prevent a failure to apprehend the common sensibles, e.g. 
movement, magnitude, and number, which go along with the 
special sensibles? Had we no sense but sight, and that sense no 
object but white, they would have tended to escape our notice 
and everything would have merged for us into an 
indistinguishable identity because of the concomitance of 
colour and magnitude. As it is, the fact that the common 
sensibles are given in the objects of more than one sense 
reveals their distinction from each and all of the special 
sensibles. 



1226 



Since it is through sense that we are aware that we are seeing or 
hearing, it must be either by sight that we are aware of seeing, 
or by some sense other than sight. But the sense that gives us 
this new sensation must perceive both sight and its object, viz. 
colour: so that either (1) there will be two senses both percipient 
of the same sensible object, or (2) the sense must be percipient 
of itself. Further, even if the sense which perceives sight were 
different from sight, we must either fall into an infinite regress, 
or we must somewhere assume a sense which is aware of itself. 
If so, we ought to do this in the first case. 

This presents a difficulty: if to perceive by sight is just to see, 
and what is seen is colour (or the coloured), then if we are to see 
that which sees, that which sees originally must be coloured. It 
is clear therefore that 'to perceive by sight' has more than one 
meaning; for even when we are not seeing, it is by sight that we 
discriminate darkness from light, though not in the same way 
as we distinguish one colour from another. Further, in a sense 
even that which sees is coloured; for in each case the sense- 
organ is capable of receiving the sensible object without its 
matter. That is why even when the sensible objects are gone the 
sensings and imaginings continue to exist in the sense-organs. 

The activity of the sensible object and that of the percipient 
sense is one and the same activity, and yet the distinction 
between their being remains. Take as illustration actual sound 
and actual hearing: a man may have hearing and yet not be 
hearing, and that which has a sound is not always sounding. 
But when that which can hear is actively hearing and which can 
sound is sounding, then the actual hearing and the actual 
sound are merged in one (these one might call respectively 
hearkening and sounding). 



1227 



If it is true that the movement, both the acting and the being 
acted upon, is to be found in that which is acted upon, both the 
sound and the hearing so far as it is actual must be found in 
that which has the faculty of hearing; for it is in the passive 
factor that the actuality of the active or motive factor is 
realized; that is why that which causes movement may be at 
rest. Now the actuality of that which can sound is just sound or 
sounding, and the actuality of that which can hear is hearing or 
hearkening; 'sound' and 'hearing' are both ambiguous. The 
same account applies to the other senses and their objects. For 
as the-acting-and-being-acted-upon is to be found in the 
passive, not in the active factor, so also the actuality of the 
sensible object and that of the sensitive subject are both 
realized in the latter. But while in some cases each aspect of the 
total actuality has a distinct name, e.g. sounding and 
hearkening, in some one or other is nameless, e.g. the actuality 
of sight is called seeing, but the actuality of colour has no name: 
the actuality of the faculty of taste is called tasting, but the 
actuality of flavour has no name. Since the actualities of the 
sensible object and of the sensitive faculty are one actuality in 
spite of the difference between their modes of being, actual 
hearing and actual sounding appear and disappear from 
existence at one and the same moment, and so actual savour 
and actual tasting, &c, while as potentialities one of them may 
exist without the other. The earlier students of nature were 
mistaken in their view that without sight there was no white or 
black, without taste no savour. This statement of theirs is partly 
true, partly false: 'sense' and 'the sensible object' are ambiguous 
terms, i.e. may denote either potentialities or actualities: the 
statement is true of the latter, false of the former. This 
ambiguity they wholly failed to notice. 

If voice always implies a concord, and if the voice and the 
hearing of it are in one sense one and the same, and if concord 
always implies a ratio, hearing as well as what is heard must be 



1228 



a ratio. That is why the excess of either the sharp or the flat 
destroys the hearing. (So also in the case of savours excess 
destroys the sense of taste, and in the case of colours excessive 
brightness or darkness destroys the sight, and in the case of 
smell excess of strength whether in the direction of sweetness 
or bitterness is destructive.) This shows that the sense is a ratio. 

That is also why the objects of sense are (1) pleasant when the 
sensible extremes such as acid or sweet or salt being pure and 
unmixed are brought into the proper ratio; then they are 
pleasant: and in general what is blended is more pleasant than 
the sharp or the flat alone; or, to touch, that which is capable of 
being either warmed or chilled: the sense and the ratio are 
identical: while (2) in excess the sensible extremes are painful 
or destructive. 

Each sense then is relative to its particular group of sensible 
qualities: it is found in a sense-organ as such and discriminates 
the differences which exist within that group; e.g. sight 
discriminates white and black, taste sweet and bitter, and so in 
all cases. Since we also discriminate white from sweet, and 
indeed each sensible quality from every other, with what do we 
perceive that they are different? It must be by sense; for what is 
before us is sensible objects. (Hence it is also obvious that the 
flesh cannot be the ultimate sense-organ: if it were, the 
discriminating power could not do its work without immediate 
contact with the object.) 

Therefore (1) discrimination between white and sweet cannot 
be effected by two agencies which remain separate; both the 
qualities discriminated must be present to something that is 
one and single. On any other supposition even if I perceived 
sweet and you perceived white, the difference between them 
would be apparent. What says that two things are different 
must be one; for sweet is different from white. Therefore what 



1229 



asserts this difference must be self-identical, and as what 
asserts, so also what thinks or perceives. That it is not possible 
by means of two agencies which remain separate to 
discriminate two objects which are separate, is therefore 
obvious; and that (it is not possible to do this in separate 
movements of time may be seen' if we look at it as follows. For 
as what asserts the difference between the good and the bad is 
one and the same, so also the time at which it asserts the one to 
be different and the other to be different is not accidental to the 
assertion (as it is for instance when I now assert a difference 
but do not assert that there is now a difference); it asserts thus - 
both now and that the objects are different now; the objects 
therefore must be present at one and the same moment. Both 
the discriminating power and the time of its exercise must be 
one and undivided. 

But, it may be objected, it is impossible that what is self- 
identical should be moved at me and the same time with 
contrary movements in so far as it is undivided, and in an 
undivided moment of time. For if what is sweet be the quality 
perceived, it moves the sense or thought in this determinate 
way, while what is bitter moves it in a contrary way, and what is 
white in a different way. Is it the case then that what 
discriminates, though both numerically one and indivisible, is at 
the same time divided in its being? In one sense, it is what is 
divided that perceives two separate objects at once, but in 
another sense it does so qua undivided; for it is divisible in its 
being but spatially and numerically undivided, is not this 
impossible? For while it is true that what is self-identical and 
undivided may be both contraries at once potentially, it cannot 
be self-identical in its being - it must lose its unity by being put 
into activity. It is not possible to be at once white and black, and 
therefore it must also be impossible for a thing to be affected at 
one and the same moment by the forms of both, assuming it to 



1230 



be the case that sensation and thinking are properly so 
described. 

The answer is that just as what is called a 'point' is, as being at 
once one and two, properly said to be divisible, so here, that 
which discriminates is qua undivided one, and active in a single 
moment of time, while so far forth as it is divisible it twice over 
uses the same dot at one and the same time. So far forth then 
as it takes the limit as two' it discriminates two separate objects 
with what in a sense is divided: while so far as it takes it as one, 
it does so with what is one and occupies in its activity a single 
moment of time. 

About the principle in virtue of which we say that animals are 
percipient, let this discussion suffice. 



There are two distinctive peculiarities by reference to which we 
characterize the soul (1) local movement and (2) thinking, 
discriminating, and perceiving. Thinking both speculative and 
practical is regarded as akin to a form of perceiving; for in the 
one as well as the other the soul discriminates and is cognizant 
of something which is. Indeed the ancients go so far as to 
identify thinking and perceiving; e.g. Empedocles says 'For 'tis in 
respect of what is present that man's wit is increased', and 
again 'Whence it befalls them from time to time to think 
diverse thoughts', and Homer's phrase 'For suchlike is man's 
mind' means the same. They all look upon thinking as a bodily 
process like perceiving, and hold that like is known as well as 
perceived by like, as I explained at the beginning of our 
discussion. Yet they ought at the same time to have accounted 
for error also; for it is more intimately connected with animal 



1231 



existence and the soul continues longer in the state of error 
than in that of truth. They cannot escape the dilemma: either (1) 
whatever seems is true (and there are some who accept this) or 
(2) error is contact with the unlike; for that is the opposite of the 
knowing of like by like. 

But it is a received principle that error as well as knowledge in 
respect to contraries is one and the same. 

That perceiving and practical thinking are not identical is 
therefore obvious; for the former is universal in the animal 
world, the latter is found in only a small division of it. Further, 
speculative thinking is also distinct from perceiving - I mean 
that in which we find Tightness and wrongness - rightness in 
prudence, knowledge, true opinion, wrongness in their 
opposites; for perception of the special objects of sense is 
always free from error, and is found in all animals, while it is 
possible to think falsely as well as truly, and thought is found 
only where there is discourse of reason as well as sensibility. For 
imagination is different from either perceiving or discursive 
thinking, though it is not found without sensation, or 
judgement without it. That this activity is not the same kind of 
thinking as judgement is obvious. For imagining lies within our 
own power whenever we wish (e.g. we can call up a picture, as 
in the practice of mnemonics by the use of mental images), but 
in forming opinions we are not free: we cannot escape the 
alternative of falsehood or truth. Further, when we think 
something to be fearful or threatening, emotion is immediately 
produced, and so too with what is encouraging; but when we 
merely imagine we remain as unaffected as persons who are 
looking at a painting of some dreadful or encouraging scene. 
Again within the field of judgement itself we find varieties, 
knowledge, opinion, prudence, and their opposites; of the 
differences between these I must speak elsewhere. 



1232 



Thinking is different from perceiving and is held to be in part 
imagination, in part judgement: we must therefore first mark 
off the sphere of imagination and then speak of judgement. If 
then imagination is that in virtue of which an image arises for 
us, excluding metaphorical uses of the term, is it a single faculty 
or disposition relative to images, in virtue of which we 
discriminate and are either in error or not? The faculties in 
virtue of which we do this are sense, opinion, science, 
intelligence. 

That imagination is not sense is clear from the following 
considerations: Sense is either a faculty or an activity, e.g. sight 
or seeing: imagination takes place in the absence of both, as e.g. 
in dreams. (Again, sense is always present, imagination not. If 
actual imagination and actual sensation were the same, 
imagination would be found in all the brutes: this is held not to 
be the case; e.g. it is not found in ants or bees or grubs. (Again, 
sensations are always true, imaginations are for the most part 
false. (Once more, even in ordinary speech, we do not, when 
sense functions precisely with regard to its object, say that we 
imagine it to be a man, but rather when there is some failure of 
accuracy in its exercise. And as we were saying before, visions 
appear to us even when our eyes are shut. Neither is 
imagination any of the things that are never in error: e.g. 
knowledge or intelligence; for imagination may be false. 

It remains therefore to see if it is opinion, for opinion may be 
either true or false. 

But opinion involves belief (for without belief in what we opine 
we cannot have an opinion), and in the brutes though we often 
find imagination we never find belief. Further, every opinion is 
accompanied by belief, belief by conviction, and conviction by 
discourse of reason: while there are some of the brutes in which 
we find imagination, without discourse of reason. It is clear 



1233 



then that imagination cannot, again, be (1) opinion plus 
sensation, or (2) opinion mediated by sensation, or (3) a blend of 
opinion and sensation; this is impossible both for these reasons 
and because the content of the supposed opinion cannot be 
different from that of the sensation (I mean that imagination 
must be the blending of the perception of white with the 
opinion that it is white: it could scarcely be a blend of the 
opinion that it is good with the perception that it is white): to 
imagine is therefore (on this view) identical with the thinking of 
exactly the same as what one in the strictest sense perceives. 
But what we imagine is sometimes false though our 
contemporaneous judgement about it is true; e.g. we imagine 
the sun to be a foot in diameter though we are convinced that it 
is larger than the inhabited part of the earth, and the following 
dilemma presents itself. Either (a while the fact has not 
changed and the (observer has neither forgotten nor lost belief 
in the true opinion which he had, that opinion has disappeared, 
or (b) if he retains it then his opinion is at once true and false. A 
true opinion, however, becomes false only when the fact alters 
without being noticed. 

Imagination is therefore neither any one of the states 
enumerated, nor compounded out of them. 

But since when one thing has been set in motion another thing 
may be moved by it, and imagination is held to be a movement 
and to be impossible without sensation, i.e. to occur in beings 
that are percipient and to have for its content what can be 
perceived, and since movement may be produced by actual 
sensation and that movement is necessarily similar in character 
to the sensation itself, this movement must be (1) necessarily (a) 
incapable of existing apart from sensation, (b) incapable of 
existing except when we perceive, (such that in virtue of its 
possession that in which it is found may present various 



1234 



phenomena both active and passive, and (such that it may be 
either true or false. 

The reason of the last characteristic is as follows. Perception (1) 
of the special objects of sense is never in error or admits the 
least possible amount of falsehood. (2) That of the 
concomitance of the objects concomitant with the sensible 
qualities comes next: in this case certainly we may be deceived; 
for while the perception that there is white before us cannot be 
false, the perception that what is white is this or that may be 
false. (3) Third comes the perception of the universal attributes 
which accompany the concomitant objects to which the special 
sensibles attach (I mean e.g. of movement and magnitude); it is 
in respect of these that the greatest amount of sense-illusion is 
possible. 

The motion which is due to the activity of sense in these three 
modes of its exercise will differ from the activity of sense; (1) 
the first kind of derived motion is free from error while the 
sensation is present; (2) and (3) the others may be erroneous 
whether it is present or absent, especially when the object of 
perception is far off. If then imagination presents no other 
features than those enumerated and is what we have described, 
then imagination must be a movement resulting from an actual 
exercise of a power of sense. 

As sight is the most highly developed sense, the name 
Phantasia (imagination) has been formed from Phaos (light) 
because it is not possible to see without light. 

And because imaginations remain in the organs of sense and 
resemble sensations, animals in their actions are largely guided 
by them, some (i.e. the brutes) because of the non-existence in 
them of mind, others (i.e. men) because of the temporary 
eclipse in them of mind by feeling or disease or sleep. 



1235 



About imagination, what it is and why it exists, let so much 
suffice. 



Turning now to the part of the soul with which the soul knows 
and thinks (whether this is separable from the others in 
definition only, or spatially as well) we have to inquire (1) what 
differentiates this part, and (2) how thinking can take place. 

If thinking is like perceiving, it must be either a process in 
which the soul is acted upon by what is capable of being 
thought, or a process different from but analogous to that. The 
thinking part of the soul must therefore be, while impassible, 
capable of receiving the form of an object; that is, must be 
potentially identical in character with its object without being 
the object. Mind must be related to what is thinkable, as sense 
is to what is sensible. 

Therefore, since everything is a possible object of thought, mind 
in order, as Anaxagoras says, to dominate, that is, to know, must 
be pure from all admixture; for the co-presence of what is alien 
to its nature is a hindrance and a block: it follows that it too, like 
the sensitive part, can have no nature of its own, other than 
that of having a certain capacity. Thus that in the soul which is 
called mind (by mind I mean that whereby the soul thinks and 
judges) is, before it thinks, not actually any real thing. For this 
reason it cannot reasonably be regarded as blended with the 
body: if so, it would acquire some quality, e.g. warmth or cold, or 
even have an organ like the sensitive faculty: as it is, it has 
none. It was a good idea to call the soul 'the place of forms', 
though (1) this description holds only of the intellective soul, 
and (2) even this is the forms only potentially, not actually. 



1236 



Observation of the sense-organs and their employment reveals 
a distinction between the impassibility of the sensitive and that 
of the intellective faculty. After strong stimulation of a sense we 
are less able to exercise it than before, as e.g. in the case of a 
loud sound we cannot hear easily immediately after, or in the 
case of a bright colour or a powerful odour we cannot see or 
smell, but in the case of mind thought about an object that is 
highly intelligible renders it more and not less able afterwards 
to think objects that are less intelligible: the reason is that while 
the faculty of sensation is dependent upon the body, mind is 
separable from it. 

Once the mind has become each set of its possible objects, as a 
man of science has, when this phrase is used of one who is 
actually a man of science (this happens when he is now able to 
exercise the power on his own initiative), its condition is still 
one of potentiality, but in a different sense from the potentiality 
which preceded the acquisition of knowledge by learning or 
discovery: the mind too is then able to think itself. 

Since we can distinguish between a spatial magnitude and what 
it is to be such, and between water and what it is to be water, 
and so in many other cases (though not in all; for in certain 
cases the thing and its form are identical), flesh and what it is 
to be flesh are discriminated either by different faculties, or by 
the same faculty in two different states: for flesh necessarily 
involves matter and is like what is snub-nosed, a this in a this. 
Now it is by means of the sensitive faculty that we discriminate 
the hot and the cold, i.e. the factors which combined in a 
certain ratio constitute flesh: the essential character of flesh is 
apprehended by something different either wholly separate 
from the sensitive faculty or related to it as a bent line to the 
same line when it has been straightened out. 



1237 



Again in the case of abstract objects what is straight is 
analogous to what is snub-nosed; for it necessarily implies a 
continuum as its matter: its constitutive essence is different, if 
we may distinguish between straightness and what is straight: 
let us take it to be two-ness. It must be apprehended, therefore, 
by a different power or by the same power in a different state. 
To sum up, in so far as the realities it knows are capable of 
being separated from their matter, so it is also with the powers 
of mind. 

The problem might be suggested: if thinking is a passive 
affection, then if mind is simple and impassible and has 
nothing in common with anything else, as Anaxagoras says, 
how can it come to think at all? For interaction between two 
factors is held to require a precedent community of nature 
between the factors. Again it might be asked, is mind a possible 
object of thought to itself? For if mind is thinkable per se and 
what is thinkable is in kind one and the same, then either (a) 
mind will belong to everything, or (b) mind will contain some 
element common to it with all other realities which makes 
them all thinkable. 

(1) Have not we already disposed of the difficulty about 
interaction involving a common element, when we said that 
mind is in a sense potentially whatever is thinkable, though 
actually it is nothing until it has thought? What it thinks must 
be in it just as characters may be said to be on a writingtablet 
on which as yet nothing actually stands written: this is exactly 
what happens with mind. 

(Mind is itself thinkable in exactly the same way as its objects 
are. For (a) in the case of objects which involve no matter, what 
thinks and what is thought are identical; for speculative 
knowledge and its object are identical. (Why mind is not always 
thinking we must consider later.) (b) In the case of those which 



1238 



contain matter each of the objects of thought is only potentially 
present. It follows that while they will not have mind in them 
(for mind is a potentiality of them only in so far as they are 
capable of being disengaged from matter) mind may yet be 
thinkable. 



Since in every class of things, as in nature as a whole, we find 
two factors involved, (1) a matter which is potentially all the 
particulars included in the class, (2) a cause which is productive 
in the sense that it makes them all (the latter standing to the 
former, as e.g. an art to its material), these distinct elements 
must likewise be found within the soul. 

And in fact mind as we have described it is what it is what it is 
by virtue of becoming all things, while there is another which is 
what it is by virtue of making all things: this is a sort of positive 
state like light; for in a sense light makes potential colours into 
actual colours. 

Mind in this sense of it is separable, impassible, unmixed, since 
it is in its essential nature activity (for always the active is 
superior to the passive factor, the originating force to the matter 
which it forms). 

Actual knowledge is identical with its object: in the individual, 
potential knowledge is in time prior to actual knowledge, but in 
the universe as a whole it is not prior even in time. Mind is not 
at one time knowing and at another not. When mind is set free 
from its present conditions it appears as just what it is and 
nothing more: this alone is immortal and eternal (we do not, 
however, remember its former activity because, while mind in 



1239 



this sense is impassible, mind as passive is destructible), and 
without it nothing thinks. 



The thinking then of the simple objects of thought is found in 
those cases where falsehood is impossible: where the 
alternative of true or false applies, there we always find a 
putting together of objects of thought in a quasi-unity. As 
Empedocles said that 'where heads of many a creature sprouted 
without necks' they afterwards by Love's power were combined, 
so here too objects of thought which were given separate are 
combined, e.g. 'incommensurate' and 'diagonal': if the 
combination be of objects past or future the combination of 
thought includes in its content the date. For falsehood always 
involves a synthesis; for even if you assert that what is white is 
not white you have included not white in a synthesis. It is 
possible also to call all these cases division as well as 
combination. However that may be, there is not only the true or 
false assertion that Cleon is white but also the true or false 
assertion that he was or will he white. In each and every case 
that which unifies is mind. 

Since the word 'simple' has two senses, i.e. may mean either (a) 
'not capable of being divided' or (b) 'not actually divided', there 
is nothing to prevent mind from knowing what is undivided, e.g. 
when it apprehends a length (which is actually undivided) and 
that in an undivided time; for the time is divided or undivided 
in the same manner as the line. It is not possible, then, to tell 
what part of the line it was apprehending in each half of the 
time: the object has no actual parts until it has been divided: if 
in thought you think each half separately, then by the same act 



1240 



you divide the time also, the half-lines becoming as it were new 
wholes of length. But if you think it as a whole consisting of 
these two possible parts, then also you think it in a time which 
corresponds to both parts together. (But what is not 
quantitatively but qualitatively simple is thought in a simple 
time and by a simple act of the soul.) 

But that which mind thinks and the time in which it thinks are 
in this case divisible only incidentally and not as such. For in 
them too there is something indivisible (though, it may be, not 
isolable) which gives unity to the time and the whole of length; 
and this is found equally in every continuum whether temporal 
or spatial. 

Points and similar instances of things that divide, themselves 
being indivisible, are realized in consciousness in the same 
manner as privations. 

A similar account may be given of all other cases, e.g. how evil 
or black is cognized; they are cognized, in a sense, by means of 
their contraries. That which cognizes must have an element of 
potentiality in its being, and one of the contraries must be in it. 
But if there is anything that has no contrary, then it knows itself 
and is actually and possesses independent existence. 

Assertion is the saying of something concerning something, e.g. 
affirmation, and is in every case either true or false: this is not 
always the case with mind: the thinking of the definition in the 
sense of the constitutive essence is never in error nor is it the 
assertion of something concerning something, but, just as while 
the seeing of the special object of sight can never be in error, the 
belief that the white object seen is a man may be mistaken, so 
too in the case of objects which are without matter. 



1241 



Actual knowledge is identical with its object: potential 
knowledge in the individual is in time prior to actual knowledge 
but in the universe it has no priority even in time; for all things 
that come into being arise from what actually is. In the case of 
sense clearly the sensitive faculty already was potentially what 
the object makes it to be actually; the faculty is not affected or 
altered. This must therefore be a different kind from movement; 
for movement is, as we saw, an activity of what is imperfect, 
activity in the unqualified sense, i.e. that of what has been 
perfected, is different from movement. 

To perceive then is like bare asserting or knowing; but when the 
object is pleasant or painful, the soul makes a quasi-affirmation 
or negation, and pursues or avoids the object. To feel pleasure or 
pain is to act with the sensitive mean towards what is good or 
bad as such. Both avoidance and appetite when actual are 
identical with this: the faculty of appetite and avoidance are not 
different, either from one another or from the faculty of sense- 
perception; but their being is different. 

To the thinking soul images serve as if they were contents of 
perception (and when it asserts or denies them to be good or 
bad it avoids or pursues them). That is why the soul never 
thinks without an image. The process is like that in which the 
air modifies the pupil in this or that way and the pupil 
transmits the modification to some third thing (and similarly in 
hearing), while the ultimate point of arrival is one, a single 
mean, with different manners of being. 

With what part of itself the soul discriminates sweet from hot I 
have explained before and must now describe again as follows: 
That with which it does so is a sort of unity, but in the way just 
mentioned, i.e. as a connecting term. And the two faculties it 
connects, being one by analogy and numerically, are each to 



1242 



each as the qualities discerned are to one another (for what 
difference does it make whether we raise the problem of 
discrimination between disparates or between contraries, e.g. 
white and black?). Let then C be to D as is to B: it follows 
alternando that C: A:: D: B. If then C and D belong to one subject, 
the case will be the same with them as with and B; and B form a 
single identity with different modes of being; so too will the 
former pair. The same reasoning holds if be sweet and B white. 

The faculty of thinking then thinks the forms in the images, 
and as in the former case what is to be pursued or avoided is 
marked out for it, so where there is no sensation and it is 
engaged upon the images it is moved to pursuit or avoidance. 
E.g.. perceiving by sense that the beacon is fire, it recognizes in 
virtue of the general faculty of sense that it signifies an enemy, 
because it sees it moving; but sometimes by means of the 
images or thoughts which are within the soul, just as if it were 
seeing, it calculates and deliberates what is to come by 
reference to what is present; and when it makes a 
pronouncement, as in the case of sensation it pronounces the 
object to be pleasant or painful, in this case it avoids or persues 
and so generally in cases of action. 

That too which involves no action, i.e. that which is true or 
false, is in the same province with what is good or bad: yet they 
differ in this, that the one set imply and the other do not a 
reference to a particular person. 

The so-called abstract objects the mind thinks just as, if one 
had thought of the snubnosed not as snub-nosed but as hollow, 
one would have thought of an actuality without the flesh in 
which it is embodied: it is thus that the mind when it is 
thinking the objects of Mathematics thinks as separate 
elements which do not exist separate. In every case the mind 
which is actively thinking is the objects which it thinks. 



1243 



Whether it is possible for it while not existing separate from 
spatial conditions to think anything that is separate, or not, we 
must consider later. 



8 

Let us now summarize our results about soul, and repeat that 
the soul is in a way all existing things; for existing things are 
either sensible or thinkable, and knowledge is in a way what is 
knowable, and sensation is in a way what is sensible: in what 
way we must inquire. 

Knowledge and sensation are divided to correspond with the 
realities, potential knowledge and sensation answering to 
potentialities, actual knowledge and sensation to actualities. 
Within the soul the faculties of knowledge and sensation are 
potentially these objects, the one what is knowable, the other 
what is sensible. They must be either the things themselves or 
their forms. The former alternative is of course impossible: it is 
not the stone which is present in the soul but its form. 

It follows that the soul is analogous to the hand; for as the hand 
is a tool of tools, so the mind is the form of forms and sense the 
form of sensible things. 

Since according to common agreement there is nothing outside 
and separate in existence from sensible spatial magnitudes, the 
objects of thought are in the sensible forms, viz. both the 
abstract objects and all the states and affections of sensible 
things. Hence (1) no one can learn or understand anything in 
the absence of sense, and (when the mind is actively aware of 
anything it is necessarily aware of it along with an image; for 



1244 



images are like sensuous contents except in that they contain 
no matter. 

Imagination is different from assertion and denial; for what is 
true or false involves a synthesis of concepts. In what will the 
primary concepts differ from images? Must we not say that 
neither these nor even our other concepts are images, though 
they necessarily involve them? 



The soul of animals is characterized by two faculties, (a) the 
faculty of discrimination which is the work of thought and 
sense, and (b) the faculty of originating local movement. Sense 
and mind we have now sufficiently examined. Let us next 
consider what it is in the soul which originates movement. Is it 
a single part of the soul separate either spatially or in 
definition? Or is it the soul as a whole? If it is a part, is that part 
different from those usually distinguished or already mentioned 
by us, or is it one of them? The problem at once presents itself, 
in what sense we are to speak of parts of the soul, or how many 
we should distinguish. For in a sense there is an infinity of 
parts: it is not enough to distinguish, with some thinkers, the 
calculative, the passionate, and the desiderative, or with others 
the rational and the irrational; for if we take the dividing lines 
followed by these thinkers we shall find parts far more 
distinctly separated from one another than these, namely those 
we have just mentioned: (1) the nutritive, which belongs both to 
plants and to all animals, and (2) the sensitive, which cannot 
easily be classed as either irrational or rational; further (3) the 
imaginative, which is, in its being, different from all, while it is 
very hard to say with which of the others it is the same or not 



1245 



the same, supposing we determine to posit separate parts in the 
soul; and lastly (4) the appetitive, which would seem to be 
distinct both in definition and in power from all hitherto 
enumerated. 

It is absurd to break up the last-mentioned faculty: as these 
thinkers do, for wish is found in the calculative part and desire 
and passion in the irrational; and if the soul is tripartite 
appetite will be found in all three parts. Turning our attention to 
the present object of discussion, let us ask what that is which 
originates local movement of the animal. 

The movement of growth and decay, being found in all living 
things, must be attributed to the faculty of reproduction and 
nutrition, which is common to all: inspiration and expiration, 
sleep and waking, we must consider later: these too present 
much difficulty: at present we must consider local movement, 
asking what it is that originates forward movement in the 
animal. 

That it is not the nutritive faculty is obvious; for this kind of 
movement is always for an end and is accompanied either by 
imagination or by appetite; for no animal moves except by 
compulsion unless it has an impulse towards or away from an 
object. Further, if it were the nutritive faculty, even plants would 
have been capable of originating such movement and would 
have possessed the organs necessary to carry it out. Similarly it 
cannot be the sensitive faculty either; for there are many 
animals which have sensibility but remain fast and immovable 
throughout their lives. 

If then Nature never makes anything without a purpose and 
never leaves out what is necessary (except in the case of 
mutilated or imperfect growths; and that here we have neither 
mutilation nor imperfection may be argued from the facts that 
such animals (a) can reproduce their species and (b) rise to 



1246 



completeness of nature and decay to an end), it follows that, 
had they been capable of originating forward movement, they 
would have possessed the organs necessary for that purpose. 
Further, neither can the calculative faculty or what is called 
'mind' be the cause of such movement; for mind as speculative 
never thinks what is practicable, it never says anything about an 
object to be avoided or pursued, while this movement is always 
in something which is avoiding or pursuing an object. No, not 
even when it is aware of such an object does it at once enjoin 
pursuit or avoidance of it; e.g. the mind often thinks of 
something terrifying or pleasant without enjoining the emotion 
of fear. It is the heart that is moved (or in the case of a pleasant 
object some other part). Further, even when the mind does 
command and thought bids us pursue or avoid something, 
sometimes no movement is produced; we act in accordance 
with desire, as in the case of moral weakness. And, generally, we 
observe that the possessor of medical knowledge is not 
necessarily healing, which shows that something else is 
required to produce action in accordance with knowledge; the 
knowledge alone is not the cause. Lastly, appetite too is 
incompetent to account fully for movement; for those who 
successfully resist temptation have appetite and desire and yet 
follow mind and refuse to enact that for which they have 
appetite. 



10 

These two at all events appear to be sources of movement: 
appetite and mind (if one may venture to regard imagination as 
a kind of thinking; for many men follow their imaginations 
contrary to knowledge, and in all animals other than man there 
is no thinking or calculation but only imagination). 



1247 



Both of these then are capable of originating local movement, 
mind and appetite: (1) mind, that is, which calculates means to 
an end, i.e. mind practical (it differs from mind speculative in 
the character of its end); while (2) appetite is in every form of it 
relative to an end: for that which is the object of appetite is the 
stimulant of mind practical; and that which is last in the 
process of thinking is the beginning of the action. It follows that 
there is a justification for regarding these two as the sources of 
movement, i.e. appetite and practical thought; for the object of 
appetite starts a movement and as a result of that thought gives 
rise to movement, the object of appetite being it a source of 
stimulation. So too when imagination originates movement, it 
necessarily involves appetite. 

That which moves therefore is a single faculty and the faculty 
of appetite; for if there had been two sources of movement - 
mind and appetite - they would have produced movement in 
virtue of some common character. As it is, mind is never found 
producing movement without appetite (for wish is a form of 
appetite; and when movement is produced according to 
calculation it is also according to wish), but appetite can 
originate movement contrary to calculation, for desire is a form 
of appetite. Now mind is always right, but appetite and 
imagination may be either right or wrong. That is why, though 
in any case it is the object of appetite which originates 
movement, this object may be either the real or the apparent 
good. To produce movement the object must be more than this: 
it must be good that can be brought into being by action; and 
only what can be otherwise than as it is can thus be brought 
into being. That then such a power in the soul as has been 
described, i.e. that called appetite, originates movement is clear. 
Those who distinguish parts in the soul, if they distinguish and 
divide in accordance with differences of power, find themselves 
with a very large number of parts, a nutritive, a sensitive, an 
intellective, a deliberative, and now an appetitive part; for these 



1248 



are more different from one another than the faculties of desire 
and passion. 

Since appetites run counter to one another, which happens 
when a principle of reason and a desire are contrary and is 
possible only in beings with a sense of time (for while mind bids 
us hold back because of what is future, desire is influenced by 
what is just at hand: a pleasant object which is just at hand 
presents itself as both pleasant and good, without condition in 
either case, because of want of foresight into what is farther 
away in time), it follows that while that which originates 
movement must be specifically one, viz. the faculty of appetite 
as such (or rather farthest back of all the object of that faculty; 
for it is it that itself remaining unmoved originates the 
movement by being apprehended in thought or imagination), 
the things that originate movement are numerically many. 

All movement involves three factors, (1) that which originates 
the movement, (2) that by means of which it originates it, and 
(3) that which is moved. The expression 'that which originates 
the movement' is ambiguous: it may mean either (a) something 
which itself is unmoved or (b) that which at once moves and is 
moved. Here that which moves without itself being moved is 
the realizable good, that which at once moves and is moved is 
the faculty of appetite (for that which is influenced by appetite 
so far as it is actually so influenced is set in movement, and 
appetite in the sense of actual appetite is a kind of movement), 
while that which is in motion is the animal. The instrument 
which appetite employs to produce movement is no longer 
psychical but bodily: hence the examination of it falls within 
the province of the functions common to body and soul. To state 
the matter summarily at present, that which is the instrument 
in the production of movement is to be found where a 
beginning and an end coincide as e.g. in a ball and socket joint; 
for there the convex and the concave sides are respectively an 



1249 



end and a beginning (that is why while the one remains at rest, 
the other is moved): they are separate in definition but not 
separable spatially. For everything is moved by pushing and 
pulling. Hence just as in the case of a wheel, so here there must 
be a point which remains at rest, and from that point the 
movement must originate. 

To sum up, then, and repeat what I have said, inasmuch as an 
animal is capable of appetite it is capable of self-movement; it is 
not capable of appetite without possessing imagination; and all 
imagination is either (1) calculative or (2) sensitive. In the latter 
an animals, and not only man, partake. 



11 

We must consider also in the case of imperfect animals, sc. 
those which have no sense but touch, what it is that in them 
originates movement. Can they have imagination or not? or 
desire? Clearly they have feelings of pleasure and pain, and if 
they have these they must have desire. But how can they have 
imagination? Must not we say that, as their movements are 
indefinite, they have imagination and desire, but indefinitely? 

Sensitive imagination, as we have said, is found in all animals, 
deliberative imagination only in those that are calculative: for 
whether this or that shall be enacted is already a task requiring 
calculation; and there must be a single standard to measure by, 
for that is pursued which is greater. It follows that what acts in 
this way must be able to make a unity out of several images. 

This is the reason why imagination is held not to involve 
opinion, in that it does not involve opinion based on inference, 
though opinion involves imagination. Hence appetite contains 



1250 



no deliberative element. Sometimes it overpowers wish and sets 
it in movement: at times wish acts thus upon appetite, like one 
sphere imparting its movement to another, or appetite acts thus 
upon appetite, i.e. in the condition of moral weakness (though 
by nature the higher faculty is always more authoritative and 
gives rise to movement). Thus three modes of movement are 
possible. 

The faculty of knowing is never moved but remains at rest. 
Since the one premiss or judgement is universal and the other 
deals with the particular (for the first tells us that such and 
such a kind of man should do such and such a kind of act, and 
the second that this is an act of the kind meant, and I a person 
of the type intended), it is the latter opinion that really 
originates movement, not the universal; or rather it is both, but 
the one does so while it remains in a state more like rest, while 
the other partakes in movement. 



12 

The nutritive soul then must be possessed by everything that is 
alive, and every such thing is endowed with soul from its birth 
to its death. For what has been born must grow, reach maturity, 
and decay - all of which are impossible without nutrition. 
Therefore the nutritive faculty must be found in everything that 
grows and decays. 

But sensation need not be found in all things that live. For it is 
impossible for touch to belong either (1) to those whose body is 
uncompounded or (2) to those which are incapable of taking in 
the forms without their matter. 



1251 



But animals must be endowed with sensation, since Nature 
does nothing in vain. For all things that exist by Nature are 
means to an end, or will be concomitants of means to an end. 
Every body capable of forward movement would, if unendowed 
with sensation, perish and fail to reach its end, which is the aim 
of Nature; for how could it obtain nutriment? Stationary living 
things, it is true, have as their nutriment that from which they 
have arisen; but it is not possible that a body which is not 
stationary but produced by generation should have a soul and a 
discerning mind without also having sensation. (Nor yet even if 
it were not produced by generation. Why should it not have 
sensation? Because it were better so either for the body or for 
the soul? But clearly it would not be better for either: the 
absence of sensation will not enable the one to think better or 
the other to exist better.) Therefore no body which is not 
stationary has soul without sensation. 

But if a body has sensation, it must be either simple or 
compound. And simple it cannot be; for then it could not have 
touch, which is indispensable. This is clear from what follows. 
An animal is a body with soul in it: every body is tangible, i.e. 
perceptible by touch; hence necessarily, if an animal is to 
survive, its body must have tactual sensation. All the other 
senses, e.g. smell, sight, hearing, apprehend through media; but 
where there is immediate contact the animal, if it has no 
sensation, will be unable to avoid some things and take others, 
and so will find it impossible to survive. That is why taste also is 
a sort of touch; it is relative to nutriment, which is just tangible 
body; whereas sound, colour, and odour are innutritious, and 
further neither grow nor decay. Hence it is that taste also must 
be a sort of touch, because it is the sense for what is tangible 
and nutritious. 

Both these senses, then, are indispensable to the animal, and it 
is clear that without touch it is impossible for an animal to be. 



1252 



All the other senses subserve well-being and for that very 
reason belong not to any and every kind of animal, but only to 
some, e.g. those capable of forward movement must have them; 
for, if they are to survive, they must perceive not only by 
immediate contact but also at a distance from the object. This 
will be possible if they can perceive through a medium, the 
medium being affected and moved by the perceptible object, 
and the animal by the medium, just as that which produces 
local movement causes a change extending to a certain point, 
and that which gave an impulse causes another to produce a 
new impulse so that the movement traverses a medium the 
first mover impelling without being impelled, the last moved 
being impelled without impelling, while the medium (or media, 
for there are many) is both - so is it also in the case of 
alteration, except that the agent produces produces it without 
the patient's changing its place. Thus if an object is dipped into 
wax, the movement goes on until submersion has taken place, 
and in stone it goes no distance at all, while in water the 
disturbance goes far beyond the object dipped: in air the 
disturbance is propagated farthest of all, the air acting and 
being acted upon, so long as it maintains an unbroken unity. 
That is why in the case of reflection it is better, instead of saying 
that the sight issues from the eye and is reflected, to say that 
the air, so long as it remains one, is affected by the shape and 
colour. On a smooth surface the air possesses unity; hence it is 
that it in turn sets the sight in motion, just as if the impression 
on the wax were transmitted as far as the wax extends. 



13 

It is clear that the body of an animal cannot be simple, i.e. 
consist of one element such as fire or air. For without touch it is 



1253 



impossible to have any other sense; for every body that has soul 
in it must, as we have said, be capable of touch. All the other 
elements with the exception of earth can constitute organs of 
sense, but all of them bring about perception only through 
something else, viz. through the media. Touch takes place by 
direct contact with its objects, whence also its name. All the 
other organs of sense, no doubt, perceive by contact, only the 
contact is mediate: touch alone perceives by immediate contact. 
Consequently no animal body can consist of these other 
elements. 

Nor can it consist solely of earth. For touch is as it were a mean 
between all tangible qualities, and its organ is capable of 
receiving not only all the specific qualities which characterize 
earth, but also the hot and the cold and all other tangible 
qualities whatsoever. That is why we have no sensation by 
means of bones, hair, &c, because they consist of earth. So too 
plants, because they consist of earth, have no sensation. 
Without touch there can be no other sense, and the organ of 
touch cannot consist of earth or of any other single element. 

It is evident, therefore, that the loss of this one sense alone 
must bring about the death of an animal. For as on the one 
hand nothing which is not an animal can have this sense, so on 
the other it is the only one which is indispensably necessary to 
what is an animal. This explains, further, the following 
difference between the other senses and touch. In the case of all 
the others excess of intensity in the qualities which they 
apprehend, i.e. excess of intensity in colour, sound, and smell, 
destroys not the but only the organs of the sense (except 
incidentally, as when the sound is accompanied by an impact or 
shock, or where through the objects of sight or of smell certain 
other things are set in motion, which destroy by contact); 
flavour also destroys only in so far as it is at the same time 
tangible. But excess of intensity in tangible qualities, e.g. heat, 



1254 



cold, or hardness, destroys the animal itself. As in the case of 
every sensible quality excess destroys the organ, so here what is 
tangible destroys touch, which is the essential mark of life; for it 
has been shown that without touch it is impossible for an 
animal to be. That is why excess in intensity of tangible 
qualities destroys not merely the organ, but the animal itself, 
because this is the only sense which it must have. 

All the other senses are necessary to animals, as we have said, 
not for their being, but for their well-being. Such, e.g. is sight, 
which, since it lives in air or water, or generally in what is 
pellucid, it must have in order to see, and taste because of what 
is pleasant or painful to it, in order that it may perceive these 
qualities in its nutriment and so may desire to be set in motion, 
and hearing that it may have communication made to it, and a 
tongue that it may communicate with its fellows. 



1255 



Aristotle - Parva Naturalia 
[Translated by J. I. Beare and G.R.T. Ross] 



On Sense and the Sensible 
[translated by J. I. Beare] 



Having now definitely considered the soul, by itself, and its 
several faculties, we must next make a survey of animals and all 
living things, in order to ascertain what functions are peculiar, 
and what functions are common, to them. What has been 
already determined respecting the soul [sc. by itself] must be 
assumed throughout. The remaining parts [sc. the attributes of 
soul and body conjointly] of our subject must be now dealt with, 
and we may begin with those that come first. 

The most important attributes of animals, whether common to 
all or peculiar to some, are, manifestly, attributes of soul and 
body in conjunction, e.g. sensation, memory, passion, appetite 
and desire in general, and, in addition pleasure and pain. For 
these may, in fact, be said to belong to all animals. But there are, 
besides these, certain other attributes, of which some are 
common to all living things, while others are peculiar to certain 
species of animals. The most important of these may be 
summed up in four pairs, viz. waking and sleeping, youth and 
old age, inhalation and exhalation, life and death. We must 
endeavour to arrive at a scientific conception of these, 



1256 



determining their respective natures, and the causes of their 
occurrence. 

But it behoves the Physical Philosopher to obtain also a clear 
view of the first principles of health and disease, inasmuch as 
neither health nor disease can exist in lifeless things. Indeed we 
may say of most physical inquirers, and of those physicians 
who study their art philosophically, that while the former 
complete their works with a disquisition on medicine, the latter 
usually base their medical theories on principles derived from 
Physics. 

That all the attributes above enumerated belong to soul and 
body in conjunction, is obvious; for they all either imply 
sensation as a concomitant, or have it as their medium. Some 
are either affections or states of sensation, others, means of 
defending and safe-guarding it, while others, again, involve its 
destruction or negation. Now it is clear, alike by reasoning and 
observation, that sensation is generated in the soul through the 
medium of the body. 

We have already, in our treatise On the Soul, explained the 
nature of sensation and the act of perceiving by sense, and the 
reason why this affection belongs to animals. Sensation must, 
indeed, be attributed to all animals as such, for by its presence 
or absence we distinguish essentially between what is and what 
is not an animal. 

But coming now to the special senses severally, we may say that 
touch and taste necessarily appertain to all animals, touch, for 
the reason given in On the Soul, and taste, because of nutrition. 
It is by taste that one distinguishes in food the pleasant from 
the unpleasant, so as to flee from the latter and pursue the 
former: and savour in general is an affection of nutrient matter. 



1257 



The senses which operate through external media, viz. smelling, 
hearing, seeing, are found in all animals which possess the 
faculty of locomotion. To all that possess them they are a means 
of preservation; their final cause being that such creatures may, 
guided by antecedent perception, both pursue their food, and 
shun things that are bad or destructive. But in animals which 
have also intelligence they serve for the attainment of a higher 
perfection. They bring in tidings of many distinctive qualities of 
things, from which the knowledge of truth, speculative and 
practical, is generated in the soul. 

Of the two last mentioned, seeing, regarded as a supply for the 
primary wants of life, and in its direct effects, is the superior 
sense; but for developing intelligence, and in its indirect 
consequences, hearing takes the precedence. The faculty of 
seeing, thanks to the fact that all bodies are coloured, brings 
tidings of multitudes of distinctive qualities of all sorts; whence 
it is through this sense especially that we perceive the common 
sensibles, viz. figure, magnitude, motion, number: while hearing 
announces only the distinctive qualities of sound, and, to some 
few animals, those also of voice, indirectly, however, it is 
hearing that contributes most to the growth of intelligence. For 
rational discourse is a cause of instruction in virtue of its being 
audible, which it is, not directly, but indirectly; since it is 
composed of words, and each word is a thought-symbol. 
Accordingly, of persons destitute from birth of either sense, the 
blind are more intelligent than the deaf and dumb. 



Of the distinctive potency of each of the faculties of sense 
enough has been said already. 



1258 



But as to the nature of the sensory organs, or parts of the body 
in which each of the senses is naturally implanted, inquirers 
now usually take as their guide the fundamental elements of 
bodies. Not, however, finding it easy to coordinate five senses 
with four elements, they are at a loss respecting the fifth sense. 
But they hold the organ of sight to consist of fire, being 
prompted to this view by a certain sensory affection of whose 
true cause they are ignorant. This is that, when the eye is 
pressed or moved, fire appears to flash from it. This naturally 
takes place in darkness, or when the eyelids are closed, for then, 
too, darkness is produced. 

This theory, however, solves one question only to raise another; 
for, unless on the hypothesis that a person who is in his full 
senses can see an object of vision without being aware of it, the 
eye must on this theory see itself. But then why does the above 
affection not occur also when the eye is at rest? The true 
explanation of this affection, which will contain the answer to 
our question, and account for the current notion that the eye 
consists of fire, must be determined in the following way: 
Things which are smooth have the natural property of shining 
in darkness, without, however, producing light. Now, the part of 
the eye called 'the black', i.e. its central part, is manifestly 
smooth. The phenomenon of the flash occurs only when the eye 
is moved, because only then could it possibly occur that the 
same one object should become as it were two. The rapidity of 
the movement has the effect of making that which sees and 
that which is seen seem different from one another. Hence the 
phenomenon does not occur unless the motion is rapid and 
takes place in darkness. For it is in the dark that that which is 
smooth, e.g. the heads of certain fishes, and the sepia of the 
cuttle-fish, naturally shines, and, when the movement of the 
eye is slow, it is impossible that that which sees and that which 
is seen should appear to be simultaneously two and one. But, in 



1259 



fact, the eye sees itself in the above phenomenon merely as it 
does so in ordinary optical reflexion. 

If the visual organ proper really were fire, which is the doctrine 
of Empedocles, a doctrine taught also in the Timaeus, and if 
vision were the result of light issuing from the eye as from a 
lantern, why should the eye not have had the power of seeing 
even in the dark? It is totally idle to say, as the Timaeus does, 
that the visual ray coming forth in the darkness is quenched. 
What is the meaning of this 'quenching' of light? That which, 
like a fire of coals or an ordinary flame, is hot and dry is, indeed, 
quenched by the moist or cold; but heat and dryness are 
evidently not attributes of light. Or if they are attributes of it, 
but belong to it in a degree so slight as to be imperceptible to us, 
we should have expected that in the daytime the light of the 
sun should be quenched when rain falls, and that darkness 
should prevail in frosty weather. Flame, for example, and ignited 
bodies are subject to such extinction, but experience shows that 
nothing of this sort happens to the sunlight. 

Empedocles at times seems to hold that vision is to be 
explained as above stated by light issuing forth from the eye, 
e.g. in the following passage: - 

As when one who purposes going abroad prepares a lantern, 

A gleam of fire blazing through the stormy night, 

Adjusting thereto, to screen it from all sorts of winds, 

transparent sides, 

Which scatter the breath of the winds as they blow, 

While, out through them leaping, the fire, 

i.e. all the more subtile part of this, 



1260 



Shines along his threshold old incessant beams: 

So [Divine love] embedded the round "lens", [viz.] 

the primaeval fire fenced within the membranes, 

In [its own] delicate tissues; 

And these fended off the deep surrounding flood, 

While leaping forth the fire, i.e. all its more subtile part. - 

Sometimes he accounts for vision thus, but at other times he 
explains it by emanations from the visible objects. 

Democritus, on the other hand, is right in his opinion that the 
eye is of water; not, however, when he goes on to explain seeing 
as mere mirroring. The mirroring that takes place in an eye is 
due to the fact that the eye is smooth, and it really has its seat 
not in the eye which is seen, but in that which sees. For the case 
is merely one of reflexion. But it would seem that even in his 
time there was no scientific knowledge of the general subject of 
the formation of images and the phenomena of reflexion. It is 
strange too, that it never occurred to him to ask why, if his 
theory be true, the eye alone sees, while none of the other 
things in which images are reflected do so. 

True, then, the visual organ proper is composed of water, yet 
vision appertains to it not because it is so composed, but 
because it is translucent - a property common alike to water 
and to air. But water is more easily confined and more easily 
condensed than air; wherefore it is that the pupil, i.e. the eye 
proper, consists of water. That it does so is proved by facts of 
actual experience. The substance which flows from eyes when 
decomposing is seen to be water, and this in undeveloped 
embryos is remarkably cold and glistening. In sanguineous 
animals the white of the eye is fat and oily, in order that the 



1261 



moisture of the eye may be proof against freezing. Wherefore 
the eye is of all parts of the body the least sensitive to cold: no 
one ever feels cold in the part sheltered by the eyelids. The eyes 
of bloodless animals are covered with a hard scale which gives 
them similar protection. 

It is, to state the matter generally, an irrational notion that the 
eye should see in virtue of something issuing from it; that the 
visual ray should extend itself all the way to the stars, or else go 
out merely to a certain point, and there coalesce, as some say, 
with rays which proceed from the object. It would be better to 
suppose this coalescence to take place in the fundament of the 
eye itself. But even this would be mere trifling. For what is 
meant by the 'coalescence' of light with light? Or how is it 
possible? Coalescence does not occur between any two things 
taken at random. And how could the light within the eye 
coalesce with that outside it? For the environing membrane 
comes between them. 

That without light vision is impossible has been stated 
elsewhere; but, whether the medium between the eye and its 
objects is air or light, vision is caused by a process through this 
medium. 

Accordingly, that the inner part of the eye consists of water is 
easily intelligible, water being translucent. 

Now, as vision outwardly is impossible without [extra-organic] 
light, so also it is impossible inwardly [without light within the 
organ]. There must, therefore, be some translucent medium 
within the eye, and, as this is not air, it must be water. The soul 
or its perceptive part is not situated at the external surface of 
the eye, but obviously somewhere within: whence the necessity 
of the interior of the eye being translucent, i.e. capable of 
admitting light. And that it is so is plain from actual 
occurrences. It is matter of experience that soldiers wounded in 



1262 



battle by a sword slash on the temple, so inflicted as to sever 
the passages of [i.e. inward from] the eye, feel a sudden onset of 
darkness, as if a lamp had gone out; because what is called the 
pupil, i.e. the translucent, which is a sort of inner lamp, is then 
cut off [from its connexion with the soul]. 

Hence, if the facts be at all as here stated, it is clear that - if one 
should explain the nature of the sensory organs in this way, i.e. 
by correlating each of them with one of the four elements, - we 
must conceive that the part of the eye immediately concerned 
in vision consists of water, that the part immediately concerned 
in the perception of sound consists of air, and that the sense of 
smell consists of fire. (I say the sense of smell, not the organ.) 
For the organ of smell is only potentially that which the sense 
of smell, as realized, is actually; since the object of sense is 
what causes the actualization of each sense, so that it (the 
sense) must (at the instant of actualization) be (actually) that 
which before (the moment of actualization) it was potentially. 
Now, odour is a smoke-like evaporation, and smoke-like 
evaporation arises from fire. This also helps us to understand 
why the olfactory organ has its proper seat in the environment 
of the brain, for cold matter is potentially hot. In the same way 
must the genesis of the eye be explained. Its structure is an 
offshoot from the brain, because the latter is the moistest and 
coldest of all the bodily parts. 

The organ of touch proper consists of earth, and the faculty of 
taste is a particular form of touch. This explains why the 
sensory organ of both touch and taste is closely related to the 
heart. For the heart as being the hottest of all the bodily parts, is 
the counterpoise of the brain. 

This then is the way in which the characteristics of the bodily 
organs of sense must be determined. 



1263 



Of the sensibles corresponding to each sensory organ, viz. 
colour, sound, odour, savour, touch, we have treated in On the 
Soul in general terms, having there determined what their 
function is, and what is implied in their becoming actualized in 
relation to their respective organs. We must next consider what 
account we are to give of any one of them; what, for example, 
we should say colour is, or sound, or odour, or savour; and so 
also respecting [the object of] touch. We begin with colour. 

Now, each of them may be spoken of from two points of view, 
i.e. either as actual or as potential. We have in On the Soul 
explained in what sense the colour, or sound, regarded as 
actualized [for sensation] is the same as, and in what sense it is 
different from, the correlative sensation, the actual seeing or 
hearing. The point of our present discussion is, therefore, to 
determine what each sensible object must be in itself, in order 
to be perceived as it is in actual consciousness. 

We have already in On the Soul stated of Light that it is the 
colour of the Translucent, [being so related to it] incidentally; for 
whenever a fiery element is in a translucent medium presence 
there is Light; while the privation of it is Darkness. But the 
'Translucent', as we call it, is not something peculiar to air, or 
water, or any other of the bodies usually called translucent, but 
is a common 'nature' and power, capable of no separate 
existence of its own, but residing in these, and subsisting 
likewise in all other bodies in a greater or less degree. As the 
bodies in which it subsists must have some extreme bounding 
surface, so too must this. Here, then, we may say that Light is a 
'nature' inhering in the Translucent when the latter is without 
determinate boundary. But it is manifest that, when the 
Translucent is in determinate bodies, its bounding extreme 



1264 



must be something real; and that colour is just this 'something' 
we are plainly taught by facts - colour being actually either at 
the external limit, or being itself that limit, in bodies. Hence it 
was that the Pythagoreans named the superficies of a body its 
'hue', for 'hue', indeed, lies at the limit of the body; but the limit 
of the body; is not a real thing; rather we must suppose that the 
same natural substance which, externally, is the vehicle of 
colour exists [as such a possible vehicle] also in the interior of 
the body. 

Air and water, too [i.e. as well as determinately bounded bodies] 
are seen to possess colour; for their brightness is of the nature 
of colour. But the colour which air or sea presents, since the 
body in which it resides is not determinately bounded, is not 
the same when one approaches and views it close by as it is 
when one regards it from a distance; whereas in determinate 
bodies the colour presented is definitely fixed, unless, indeed, 
when the atmospheric environment causes it to change. Hence 
it is clear that that in them which is susceptible of colour is in 
both cases the same. It is therefore the Translucent, according to 
the degree to which it subsists in bodies (and it does so in all 
more or less), that causes them to partake of colour. But since 
the colour is at the extremity of the body, it must be at the 
extremity of the Translucent in the body. Whence it follows that 
we may define colour as the limit of the Translucent in 
determinately bounded body. For whether we consider the 
special class of bodies called translucent, as water and such 
others, or determinate bodies, which appear to possess a fixed 
colour of their own, it is at the exterior bounding surface that all 
alike exhibit their colour. 

Now, that which when present in air produces light may be 
present also in the Translucent which pervades determinate 
bodies; or again, it may not be present, but there may be a 
privation of it. Accordingly, as in the case of air the one 



1265 



condition is light, the other darkness, in the same way the 
colours White and Black are generated in determinate bodies. 

We must now treat of the other colours, reviewing the several 
hypotheses invented to explain their genesis. 

(1) It is conceivable that the White and the Black should be 
juxtaposed in quantities so minute that [a particle of] either 
separately would be invisible, though the joint product [of two 
particles, a black and a white] would be visible; and that they 
should thus have the other colours for resultants. Their product 
could, at all events, appear neither white nor black; and, as it 
must have some colour, and can have neither of these, this 
colour must be of a mixed character - in fact, a species of colour 
different from either. Such, then, is a possible way of conceiving 
the existence of a plurality of colours besides the White and 
Black; and we may suppose that [of this 'plurality'] many are the 
result of a [numerical] ratio; for the blacks and whites may be 
juxtaposed in the ratio of 3 to 2 or of 3 to 4, or in ratios 
expressible by other numbers; while some may be juxtaposed 
according to no numerically expressible ratio, but according to 
some relation of excess or defect in which the blacks and 
whites involved would be incommensurable quantities; and, 
accordingly, we may regard all these colours [viz. all those based 
on numerical ratios] as analogous to the sounds that enter into 
music, and suppose that those involving simple numerical 
ratios, like the concords in music, may be those generally 
regarded as most agreeable; as, for example, purple, crimson, 
and some few such colours, their fewness being due to the 
same causes which render the concords few. The other 
compound colours may be those which are not based on 
numbers. Or it may be that, while all colours whatever [except 
black and white] are based on numbers, some are regular in this 
respect, others irregular; and that the latter [though now 
supposed to be all based on numbers], whenever they are not 



1266 



pure, owe this character to a corresponding impurity in [the 
arrangement of] their numerical ratios. This then is one 
conceivable hypothesis to explain the genesis of intermediate 
colours. 

(2) Another is that the Black and White appear the one through 
the medium of the other, giving an effect like that sometimes 
produced by painters overlaying a less vivid upon a more vivid 
colour, as when they desire to represent an object appearing 
under water or enveloped in a haze, and like that produced by 
the sun, which in itself appears white, but takes a crimson hue 
when beheld through a fog or a cloud of smoke. On this 
hypothesis, too, a variety of colours may be conceived to arise in 
the same way as that already described; for between those at 
the surface and those underneath a definite ratio might 
sometimes exist; in other cases they might stand in no 
determinate ratio. To [introduce a theory of colour which would 
set all these hypotheses aside, and] say with the ancients that 
colours are emanations, and that the visibility of objects is due 
to such a cause, is absurd. For they must, in any case, explain 
sense-perception through Touch; so that it were better to say at 
once that visual perception is due to a process set up by the 
perceived object in the medium between this object and the 
sensory organ; due, that is, to contact [with the medium 
affected,] not to emanations. 

If we accept the hypothesis of juxtaposition, we must assume 
not only invisible magnitude, but also imperceptible time, in 
order that the succession in the arrival of the stimulatory 
movements may be unperceived, and that the compound colour 
seen may appear to be one, owing to its successive parts 
seeming to present themselves at once. On the hypothesis of 
superposition, however, no such assumption is needful: the 
stimulatory process produced in the medium by the upper 
colour, when this is itself unaffected, will be different in kind 



1267 



from that produced by it when affected by the underlying 
colour. Hence it presents itself as a different colour, i.e. as one 
which is neither white nor black. So that, if it is impossible to 
suppose any magnitude to be invisible, and we must assume 
that there is some distance from which every magnitude is 
visible, this superposition theory, too [i.e. as well as No. 3 infra], 
might pass as a real theory of colour-mixture. Indeed, in the 
previous case also there is no reason why, to persons at a 
distance from the juxtaposed blacks and whites, some one 
colour should not appear to present itself as a blend of both. 
[But it would not be so on a nearer view], for it will be shown, in 
a discussion to be undertaken later on, that there is no 
magnitude absolutely invisible. 

(3) There is a mixture of bodies, however, not merely such as 
some suppose, i.e. by juxtaposition of their minimal parts, 
which, owing to [the weakness of our] sense, are imperceptible 
by us, but a mixture by which they [i.e. the 'matter' of which 
they consist] are wholly blent together by interpenetration, as 
we have described it in the treatise on Mixture, where we dealt 
with this subject generally in its most comprehensive aspect. 
For, on the supposition we are criticizing, the only totals capable 
of being mixed are those which are divisible into minimal parts, 
[e.g. genera into individuals] as men, horses, or the [various 
kinds of] seeds. For of mankind as a whole the individual man is 
such a least part; of horses [as an aggregate] the individual 
horse. Hence by the juxtaposition of these we obtain a mixed 
total, consisting [like a troop of cavalry] of both together; but we 
do not say that by such a process any individual man has been 
mixed with any individual horse. Not in this way, but by 
complete interpenetration [of their matter], must we conceive 
those things to be mixed which are not divisible into minima; 
and it is in the case of these that natural mixture exhibits itself 
in its most perfect form. We have explained already in our 
discourse 'On Mixture' how such mixture is possible. This being 



1268 



the true nature of mixture, it is plain that when bodies are 
mixed their colours also are necessarily mixed at the same 
time; and [it is no less plain] that this is the real cause 
determining the existence of a plurality of colours - not 
superposition or juxtaposition. For when bodies are thus mixed, 
their resultant colour presents itself as one and the same at all 
distances alike; not varying as it is seen nearer or farther away. 

Colours will thus, too [as well as on the former hypotheses], be 
many in number on account of the fact that the ingredients 
may be combined with one another in a multitude of ratios; 
some will be based on determinate numerical ratios, while 
others again will have as their basis a relation of quantitative 
excess or defect not expressible in integers. And all else that 
was said in reference to the colours, considered as juxtaposed 
or superposed, may be said of them likewise when regarded as 
mixed in the way just described. 

Why colours, as well as savours and sounds, consist of species 
determinate [in themselves] and not infinite [in number] is a 
question which we shall discuss hereafter. 



We have now explained what colour is, and the reason why 
there are many colours; while before, in our work On the Soul, 
we explained the nature of sound and voice. We have next to 
speak of Odour and Savour, both of which are almost the same 
physical affection, although they each have their being in 
different things. Savours, as a class, display their nature more 
clearly to us than Odours, the cause of which is that the 
olfactory sense of man is inferior in acuteness to that of the 
lower animals, and is, when compared with our other senses, 



1269 



the least perfect of Man's sense of Touch, on the contrary, excels 
that of all other animals in fineness, and Taste is a modification 
of Touch. 

Now the natural substance water per se tends to be tasteless. 
But [since without water tasting is impossible] either (a) we 
must suppose that water contains in itself [uniformly diffused 
through it] the various kinds of savour, already formed, though 
in amounts so small as to be imperceptible, which is the 
doctrine of Empedocles; or (b) the water must be a sort of 
matter, qualified, as it were, to produce germs of savours of all 
kinds, so that all kinds of savour are generated from the water, 
though different kinds from its different parts, or else (c) the 
water is in itself quite undifferentiated in respect of savour 
[whether developed or undeveloped], but some agent, such for 
example as one might conceive Heat or the Sun to be, is the 
efficient cause of savour. 

(a) Of these three hypotheses, the falsity of that held by 
Empedocles is only too evident. For we see that when pericarpal 
fruits are plucked [from the tree] and exposed in the sun, or 
subjected to the action of fire, their sapid juices are changed by 
the heat, which shows that their qualities are not due to their 
drawing anything from the water in the ground, but to a change 
which they undergo within the pericarp itself; and we see, 
moreover, that these juices, when extracted and allowed to lie, 
instead of sweet become by lapse of time harsh or bitter, or 
acquire savours of any and every sort; and that, again, by the 
process of boiling or fermentation they are made to assume 
almost all kinds of new savours. 

(b) It is likewise impossible that water should be a material 
qualified to generate all kinds of Savour germs [so that different 
savours should arise out of different parts of the water]; for we 



1270 



see different kinds of taste generated from the same water, 
having it as their nutriment. 

(C) It remains, therefore, to suppose that the water is changed 
by passively receiving some affection from an external agent. 
Now, it is manifest that water does not contract the quality of 
sapidity from the agency of Heat alone. For water is of all liquids 
the thinnest, thinner even than oil itself, though oil, owing to its 
viscosity, is more ductile than water, the latter being uncohesive 
in its particles; whence water is more difficult than oil to hold 
in the hand without spilling. But since perfectly pure water does 
not, when subjected to the action of Heat, show any tendency to 
acquire consistency, we must infer that some other agency than 
heat is the cause of sapidity. For all savours [i.e. sapid liquors] 
exhibit a comparative consistency. Heat is, however, a coagent 
in the matter. 

Now the sapid juices found in pericarpal fruits evidently exist 
also in the earth. Hence many of the old natural philosophers 
assert that water has qualities like those of the earth through 
which it flows, a fact especially manifest in the case of saline 
springs, for salt is a form of earth. Hence also when liquids are 
filtered through ashes, a bitter substance, the taste they yield is 
bitter. There are many wells, too, of which some are bitter, 
others acid, while others exhibit other tastes of all kinds. 

As was to be anticipated, therefore, it is in the vegetable 
kingdom that tastes occur in richest variety. For, like all things 
else, the Moist, by nature's law, is affected only by its contrary; 
and this contrary is the Dry. Thus we see why the Moist is 
affected by Fire, which as a natural substance, is dry. Heat is, 
however, the essential property of Fire, as Dryness is of Earth, 
according to what has been said in our treatise on the elements. 
Fire and Earth, therefore, taken absolutely as such, have no 
natural power to affect, or be affected by, one another; nor have 



1271 



any other pair of substances. Any two things can affect, or be 
affected by, one another only so far as contrariety to the other 
resides in either of them. 

As, therefore, persons washing Colours or Savours in a liquid 
cause the water in which they wash to acquire such a quality 
[as that of the colour or savour], so nature, too, by washing the 
Dry and Earthy in the Moist, and by filtering the latter, that is, 
moving it on by the agency of heat through the dry and earthy, 
imparts to it a certain quality. This affection, wrought by the 
aforesaid Dry in the Moist, capable of transforming the sense of 
Taste from potentiality to actuality, is Savour. Savour brings into 
actual exercise the perceptive faculty which pre-existed only in 
potency. The activity of sense-perception in general is 
analogous, not to the process of acquiring knowledge, but to 
that of exercising knowledge already acquired. 

That Savours, either as a quality or as the privation of a quality, 
belong not to every form of the Dry but to the Nutrient, we shall 
see by considering that neither the Dry without the Moist, nor 
the Moist without the Dry, is nutrient. For no single element, but 
only composite substance, constitutes nutriment for animals. 
Now, among the perceptible elements of the food which 
animals assimilate, the tangible are the efficient causes of 
growth and decay; it is qua hot or cold that the food assimilated 
causes these; for the heat or cold is the direct cause of growth 
or decay. It is qua gustable, however, that the assimilated food 
supplies nutrition. For all organisms are nourished by the Sweet 
[i.e. the 'gustable' proper], either by itself or in combination with 
other savours. Of this we must speak with more precise detail in 
our work on Generation: for the present we need touch upon it 
only so far as our subject here requires. Heat causes growth, and 
fits the food-stuff for alimentation; it attracts [into the organic 
system] that which is light [viz. the sweet], while the salt and 
bitter it rejects because of their heaviness. In fact, whatever 



1272 



effects external heat produces in external bodies, the same are 
produced by their internal heat in animal and vegetable 
organisms. Hence it is [i.e. by the agency of heat as described] 
that nourishment is effected by the sweet. The other savours are 
introduced into and blended in food [naturally] on a principle 
analogous to that on which the saline or the acid is used 
artificially, i.e. for seasoning. These latter are used because they 
counteract the tendency of the sweet to be too nutrient, and to 
float on the stomach. 

As the intermediate colours arise from the mixture of white and 
black, so the intermediate savours arise from the Sweet and 
Bitter; and these savours, too, severally involve either a definite 
ratio, or else an indefinite relation of degree, between their 
components, either having certain integral numbers at the basis 
of their mixture, and, consequently, of their stimulative effect, 
or else being mixed in proportions not arithmetically 
expressible. The tastes which give pleasure in their combination 
are those which have their components joined in a definite 
ratio. 

The sweet taste alone is Rich, [therefore the latter may be 
regarded as a variety of the former], while [so far as both imply 
privation of the Sweet] the Saline is fairly identical with the 
Bitter. Between the extremes of sweet and bitter come the 
Harsh, the Pungent, the Astringent, and the Acid. Savours and 
Colours, it will be observed, contain respectively about the same 
number of species. For there are seven species of each, if, as is 
reasonable, we regard Dun [or Grey] as a variety of Black (for the 
alternative is that Yellow should be classed with White, as Rich 
with Sweet); while [the irreducible colours, viz.] Crimson, Violet, 
leek-Green, and deep Blue, come between White and Black, and 
from these all others are derived by mixture. 



1273 



Again, as Black is a privation of White in the Translucent, so 
Saline or Bitter is a privation of Sweet in the Nutrient Moist. 
This explains why the ash of all burnt things is bitter; for the 
potable [sc. the sweet] moisture has been exuded from them. 

Democritus and most of the natural philosophers who treat of 
sense-perception proceed quite irrationally, for they represent 
all objects of sense as objects of Touch. Yet, if this is really so, it 
clearly follows that each of the other senses is a mode of Touch; 
but one can see at a glance that this is impossible. 

Again, they treat the percepts common to all senses as proper to 
one. For [the qualities by which they explain taste viz.] 
Magnitude and Figure, Roughness and Smoothness, and, 
moreover, the Sharpness and Bluntness found in solid bodies, 
are percepts common to all the senses, or if not to all, at least to 
Sight and Touch. This explains why it is that the senses are 
liable to err regarding them, while no such error arises 
respecting their proper sensibles; e.g. the sense of Seeing is not 
deceived as to Colour, nor is that of Hearing as to Sound. 

On the other hand, they reduce the proper to common 
sensibles, as Democritus does with White and Black; for he 
asserts that the latter is [a mode of the] rough, and the former 
[a mode of the] smooth, while he reduces Savours to the atomic 
figures. Yet surely no one sense, or, if any, the sense of Sight 
rather than any other, can discern the common sensibles. But if 
we suppose that the sense of Taste is better able to do so, then - 
since to discern the smallest objects in each kind is what marks 
the acutest sense. - Taste should have been the sense which 
best perceived the common sensibles generally, and showed the 
most perfect power of discerning figures in general. 

Again, all the sensibles involve contrariety; e.g. in Colour White 
is contrary to Black, and in Savours Bitter is contrary to Sweet; 
but no one figure is reckoned as contrary to any other figure. 



1274 



Else, to which of the possible polygonal figures [to which 
Democritus reduces Bitter] is the spherical figure [to which he 
reduces Sweet] contrary? 

Again, since figures are infinite in number, savours also should 
be infinite; [the possible rejoinder - 'that they are so, only that 
some are not perceived' - cannot be sustained] for why should 
one savour be perceived, and another not? 

This completes our discussion of the object of Taste, i.e. Savour; 
for the other affections of Savours are examined in their proper 
place in connection with the natural history of Plants. 



Our conception of the nature of Odours must be analogous to 
that of Savours; inasmuch as the Sapid Dry effects in air and 
water alike, but in a different province of sense, precisely what 
the Dry effects in the Moist of water only. We customarily 
predicate Translucency of both air and water in common; but it 
is not qua translucent that either is a vehicle of odour, but qua 
possessed of a power of washing or rinsing [and so imbibing] 
the Sapid Dryness. 

For the object of Smell exists not in air only: it also exists in 
water. This is proved by the case of fishes and testacea, which 
are seen to possess the faculty of smell, although water 
contains no air (for whenever air is generated within water it 
rises to the surface), and these creatures do not respire. Hence, 
if one were to assume that air and water are both moist, it 
would follow that Odour is the natural substance consisting of 
the Sapid Dry diffused in the Moist, and whatever is of this kind 
would be an object of Smell. 



1275 



That the property of odorousness is based upon the Sapid may 
be seen by comparing the things which possess with those 
which do not possess odour. The elements, viz. Fire, Air, Earth, 
Water, are inodorous, because both the dry and the moist 
among them are without sapidity, unless some added 
ingredient produces it. This explains why sea-water possesses 
odour, for [unlike 'elemental' water] it contains savour and 
dryness. Salt, too, is more odorous than natron, as the oil which 
exudes from the former proves, for natron is allied to 
['elemental'] earth more nearly than salt. Again, a stone is 
inodorous, just because it is tasteless, while, on the contrary, 
wood is odorous, because it is sapid. The kinds of wood, too, 
which contain more ['elemental'] water are less odorous than 
others. Moreover, to take the case of metals, gold is inodorous 
because it is without taste, but bronze and iron are odorous; and 
when the [sapid] moisture has been burnt out of them, their 
slag is, in all cases, less odorous the metals [than the metals 
themselves]. Silver and tin are more odorous than the one class 
of metals, less so than the other, inasmuch as they are water [to 
a greater degree than the former, to a less degree than the 
latter]. 

Some writers look upon Fumid exhalation, which is a 
compound of Earth and Air, as the essence of Odour. [Indeed all 
are inclined to rush to this theory of Odour.] Heraclitus implied 
his adherence to it when he declared that if all existing things 
were turned into Smoke, the nose would be the organ to discern 
them with. All writers incline to refer odour to this cause [sc. 
exhalation of some sort], but some regard it as aqueous, others 
as fumid, exhalation; while others, again, hold it to be either. 
Aqueous exhalation is merely a form of moisture, but fumid 
exhalation is, as already remarked, composed of Air and Earth. 
The former when condensed turns into water; the latter, in a 
particular species of earth. Now, it is unlikely that odour is 
either of these. For vaporous exhalation consists of mere water 



1276 



[which, being tasteless, is inodorous]; and fumid exhalation 
cannot occur in water at all, though, as has been before stated, 
aquatic creatures also have the sense of smell. 

Again, the exhalation theory of odour is analogous to the theory 
of emanations. If, therefore, the latter is untenable, so, too, is the 
former. 

It is clearly conceivable that the Moist, whether in air (for air, 
too, is essentially moist) or in water, should imbibe the 
influence of, and have effects wrought in it by, the Sapid 
Dryness. Moreover, if the Dry produces in moist media, i.e. 
water and air, an effect as of something washed out in them, it 
is manifest that odours must be something analogous to 
savours. Nay, indeed, this analogy is, in some instances, a fact 
[registered in language]; for odours as well as savours are 
spoken of as pungent, sweet, harsh, astringent rich [='savoury']; 
and one might regard fetid smells as analogous to bitter tastes; 
which explains why the former are offensive to inhalation as 
the latter are to deglutition. It is clear, therefore, that Odour is in 
both water and air what Savour is in water alone. This explains 
why coldness and freezing render Savours dull, and abolish 
odours altogether; for cooling and freezing tend to annul the 
kinetic heat which helps to fabricate sapidity. 

There are two species of the Odorous. For the statement of 
certain writers that the odorous is not divisible into species is 
false; it is so divisible. We must here define the sense in which 
these species are to be admitted or denied. 

One class of odours, then, is that which runs parallel, as has 
been observed, to savours: to odours of this class their 
pleasantness or unpleasantness belongs incidentally. For owing 
to the fact that Savours are qualities of nutrient matter, the 
odours connected with these [e.g. those of a certain food] are 
agreeable as long as animals have an appetite for the food, but 



1277 



they are not agreeable to them when sated and no longer in 
want of it; nor are they agreeable, either, to those animals that 
do not like the food itself which yields the odours. Hence, as we 
observed, these odours are pleasant or unpleasant incidentally, 
and the same reasoning explains why it is that they are 
perceptible to all animals in common. 

The other class of odours consists of those agreeable in their 
essential nature, e.g. those of flowers. For these do not in any 
degree stimulate animals to food, nor do they contribute in any 
way to appetite; their effect upon it, if any, is rather the 
opposite. For the verse of Strattis ridiculing Euripides - 

Use not perfumery to flavour soup, contains a truth. 

Those who nowadays introduce such flavours into beverages 
deforce our sense of pleasure by habituating us to them, until, 
from two distinct kinds of sensations combined, pleasure arises 
as it might from one simple kind. 

Of this species of odour man alone is sensible; the other, viz. 
that correlated with Tastes, is, as has been said before, 
perceptible also to the lower animals. And odours of the latter 
sort, since their pleasureableness depends upon taste, are 
divided into as many species as there are different tastes; but 
we cannot go on to say this of the former kind of odour, since its 
nature is agreeable or disagreeable per se. The reason why the 
perception of such odours is peculiar to man is found in the 
characteristic state of man's brain. For his brain is naturally 
cold, and the blood which it contains in its vessels is thin and 
pure but easily cooled (whence it happens that the exhalation 
arising from food, being cooled by the coldness of this region, 
produces unhealthy rheums); therefore it is that odours of such 
a species have been generated for human beings, as a safeguard 
to health. This is their sole function, and that they perform it is 
evident. For food, whether dry or moist, though sweet to taste, is 



1278 



often unwholesome; whereas the odour arising from what is 
fragrant, that odour which is pleasant in its own right, is, so to 
say, always beneficial to persons in any state of bodily health 
whatever. 

For this reason, too, the perception of odour [in general] effected 
through respiration, not in all animals, but in man and certain 
other sanguineous animals, e.g. quadrupeds, and all that 
participate freely in the natural substance air; because when 
odours, on account of the lightness of the heat in them, mount 
to the brain, the health of this region is thereby promoted. For 
odour, as a power, is naturally heat-giving. Thus Nature has 
employed respiration for two purposes: primarily for the relief 
thereby brought to the thorax, secondarily for the inhalation of 
odour. For while an animal is inhaling, - odour moves in 
through its nostrils, as it were 'from a side-entrance.' 

But the perception of the second class of odours above 
described [does not belong to all animal, but] is confined to 
human beings, because man's brain is, in proportion to his 
whole bulk, larger and moister than the brain of any other 
animal. This is the reason of the further fact that man alone, so 
to speak, among animals perceives and takes pleasure in the 
odours of flowers and such things. For the heat and stimulation 
set up by these odours are commensurate with the excess of 
moisture and coldness in his cerebral region. On all the other 
animals which have lungs, Nature has bestowed their due 
perception of one of the two kinds of odour [i.e. that connected 
with nutrition] through the act of respiration, guarding against 
the needless creation of two organs of sense; for in the fact that 
they respire the other animals have already sufficient provision 
for their perception of the one species of odour only, as human 
beings have for their perception of both. 



1279 



But that creatures which do not respire have the olfactory sense 
is evident. For fishes, and all insects as a class, have, thanks to 
the species of odour correlated with nutrition, a keen olfactory 
sense of their proper food from a distance, even when they are 
very far away from it; such is the case with bees, and also with 
the class of small ants, which some denominate knipes. Among 
marine animals, too, the murex and many other similar animals 
have an acute perception of their food by its odour. 

It is not equally certain what the organ is whereby they so 
perceive. This question, of the organ whereby they perceive 
odour, may well cause a difficulty, if we assume that smelling 
takes place in animals only while respiring (for that this is the 
fact is manifest in all the animals which do respire), whereas 
none of those just mentioned respires, and yet they have the 
sense of smell - unless, indeed, they have some other sense not 
included in the ordinary five. This supposition is, however, 
impossible. For any sense which perceives odour is a sense of 
smell, and this they do perceive, though probably not in the 
same way as creatures which respire, but when the latter are 
respiring the current of breath removes something that is laid 
like a lid upon the organ proper (which explains why they do 
not perceive odours when not respiring); while in creatures 
which do not respire this is always off: just as some animals 
have eyelids on their eyes, and when these are not raised they 
cannot see, whereas hard-eyed animals have no lids, and 
consequently do not need, besides eyes, an agency to raise the 
lids, but see straightway [without intermission] from the actual 
moment at which it is first possible for them to do so [i.e. from 
the moment when an object first comes within their field of 
vision]. 

Consistently with what has been said above, not one of the 
lower animals shows repugnance to the odour of things which 
are essentially ill-smelling, unless one of the latter is positively 



1280 



pernicious. They are destroyed, however, by these things, just as 
human beings are; i.e. as human beings get headaches from, 
and are often asphyxiated by, the fumes of charcoal, so the 
lower animals perish from the strong fumes of brimstone and 
bituminous substances; and it is owing to experience of such 
effects that they shun these. For the disagreeable odour in itself 
they care nothing whatever (though the odours of many plants 
are essentially disagreeable), unless, indeed, it has some effect 
upon the taste of their food. 

The senses making up an odd number, and an odd number 
having always a middle unit, the sense of smell occupies in 
itself as it were a middle position between the tactual senses, 
i.e. Touch and Taste, and those which perceive through a 
medium, i.e. Sight and Hearing. Hence the object of smell, too, is 
an affection of nutrient substances (which fall within the class 
of Tangibles), and is also an affection of the audible and the 
visible; whence it is that creatures have the sense of smell both 
in air and water. Accordingly, the object of smell is something 
common to both of these provinces, i.e. it appertains both to the 
tangible on the one hand, and on the other to the audible and 
translucent. Hence the propriety of the figure by which it has 
been described by us as an immersion or washing of dryness in 
the Moist and Fluid. Such then must be our account of the sense 
in which one is or is not entitled to speak of the odorous as 
having species. 

The theory held by certain of the Pythagoreans, that some 
animals are nourished by odours alone, is unsound. For, in the 
first place, we see that food must be composite, since the bodies 
nourished by it are not simple. This explains why waste matter 
is secreted from food, either within the organisms, or, as in 
plants, outside them. But since even water by itself alone, that 
is, when unmixed, will not suffice for food - for anything which 
is to form a consistency must be corporeal - , it is still much less 



1281 



conceivable that air should be so corporealized [and thus fitted 
to be food]. But, besides this, we see that all animals have a 
receptacle for food, from which, when it has entered, the body 
absorbs it. Now, the organ which perceives odour is in the head, 
and odour enters with the inhalation of the breath; so that it 
goes to the respiratory region. It is plain, therefore, that odour, 
qua odour, does not contribute to nutrition; that, however, it is 
serviceable to health is equally plain, as well by immediate 
perception as from the arguments above employed; so that 
odour is in relation to general health what savour is in the 
province of nutrition and in relation to the bodies nourished. 

This then must conclude our discussion of the several organs of 
sense-perception. 



One might ask: if every body is infinitely divisible, are its 
sensible qualities - Colour, Savour, Odour, Sound, Weight, Cold 
or Heat, [Heaviness or] Lightness, Hardness or Softness - also 
infinitely divisible? Or, is this impossible? 

[One might well ask this question], because each of them is 
productive of sense-perception, since, in fact, all derive their 
name [of 'sensible qualities'] from the very circumstance of 
their being able to stimulate this. Hence, [if this is so] both our 
perception of them should likewise be divisible to infinity, and 
every part of a body [however small] should be a perceptible 
magnitude. For it is impossible, e.g. to see a thing which is white 
but not of a certain magnitude. 

Since if it were not so, [if its sensible qualities were not divisible, 
pari passu with body], we might conceive a body existing but 



1282 



having no colour, or weight, or any such quality; accordingly not 
perceptible at all. For these qualities are the objects of sense- 
perception. On this supposition, every perceptible object should 
be regarded as composed not of perceptible [but of 
imperceptible] parts. Yet it must [be really composed of 
perceptible parts], since assuredly it does not consist of 
mathematical [and therefore purely abstract and non-sensible] 
quantities. Again, by what faculty should we discern and 
cognize these [hypothetical real things without sensible 
qualities]? Is it by Reason? But they are not objects of Reason; 
nor does reason apprehend objects in space, except when it acts 
in conjunction with sense-perception. At the same time, if this 
be the case [that there are magnitudes, physically real, but 
without sensible quality], it seems to tell in favour of the 
atomistic hypothesis; for thus, indeed, [by accepting this 
hypothesis], the question [with which this chapter begins] 
might be solved [negatively]. But it is impossible [to accept this 
hypothesis]. Our views on the subject of atoms are to be found 
in our treatise on Movement. 

The solution of these questions will bring with it also the 
answer to the question why the species of Colour, Taste, Sound, 
and other sensible qualities are limited. For in all classes of 
things lying between extremes the intermediates must be 
limited. But contraries are extremes, and every object of sense- 
perception involves contrariety: e.g. in Colour, White x Black; in 
Savour, Sweet x Bitter, and in all the other sensibles also the 
contraries are extremes. Now, that which is continuous is 
divisible into an infinite number of unequal parts, but into a 
finite number of equal parts, while that which is not per se 
continuous is divisible into species which are finite in number. 
Since then, the several sensible qualities of things are to be 
reckoned as species, while continuity always subsists in these, 
we must take account of the difference between the Potential 
and the Actual. It is owing to this difference that we do not 



1283 



[actually] see its ten-thousandth part in a grain of millet, 
although sight has embraced the whole grain within its scope; 
and it is owing to this, too, that the sound contained in a 
quarter-tone escapes notice, and yet one hears the whole strain, 
inasmuch as it is a continuum; but the interval between the 
extreme sounds [that bound the quarter-tone] escapes the ear 
[being only potentially audible, not actually]. So, in the case of 
other objects of sense, extremely small constituents are 
unnoticed; because they are only potentially not actually 
[perceptible e.g.] visible, unless when they have been parted 
from the wholes. So the footlength too exists potentially in the 
two-foot length, but actually only when it has been separated 
from the whole. But objective increments so small as those 
above might well, if separated from their totals, [instead of 
achieving 'actual' exisistence] be dissolved in their 
environments, like a drop of sapid moisture poured out into the 
sea. But even if this were not so [sc. with the objective 
magnitude], still, since the [subjective] of sense-perception is 
not perceptible in itself, nor capable of separate existence (since 
it exists only potentially in the more distinctly perceivable 
whole of sense-perception), so neither will it be possible to 
perceive [actually] its correlatively small object [sc. its quantum 
of pathema or sensible quality] when separated from the object- 
total. But yet this [small object] is to be considered as 
perceptible: for it is both potentially so already [i.e. even when 
alone], and destined to be actually so when it has become part 
of an aggregate. Thus, therefore, we have shown that some 
magnitudes and their sensible qualities escape notice, and the 
reason why they do so, as well as the manner in which they are 
still perceptible or not perceptible in such cases. Accordingly 
then when these [minutely subdivided] sensibles have once 
again become aggregated in a whole in such a manner, 
relatively to one another, as to be perceptible actually, and not 
merely because they are in the whole, but even apart from it, it 



1284 



follows necessarily [from what has been already stated] that 
their sensible qualities, whether colours or tastes or sounds, are 
limited in number. 

One might ask: - do the objects of sense-perception, or the 
movements proceeding from them ([since movements there 
are,] in whichever of the two ways [viz. by emanations or by 
stimulatory kinesis] sense-perception takes place), when these 
are actualized for perception, always arrive first at a spatial 
middle point [between the sense-organ and its object], as Odour 
evidently does, and also Sound? For he who is nearer [to the 
odorous object] perceives the Odour sooner [than who is farther 
away], and the Sound of a stroke reaches us some time after it 
has been struck. Is it thus also with an object seen, and with 
Light? Empedocles, for example, says that the Light from the 
Sun arrives first in the intervening space before it comes to the 
eye, or reaches the Earth. This might plausibly seem to be the 
case. For whatever is moved [in space], is moved from one place 
to another; hence there must be a corresponding interval of 
time also in which it is moved from the one place to the other. 
But any given time is divisible into parts; so that we should 
assume a time when the sun's ray was not as yet seen, but was 
still travelling in the middle space. 

Now, even if it be true that the acts of 'hearing' and 'having 
heard', and, generally, those of 'perceiving' and 'having 
perceived', form co-instantaneous wholes, in other words, that 
acts of sense-perception do not involve a process of becoming, 
but have their being none the less without involving such a 
process; yet, just as, [in the case of sound], though the stroke 
which causes the Sound has been already struck, the Sound is 
not yet at the ear (and that this last is a fact is further proved by 
the transformation which the letters [viz. the consonants as 
heard] undergo [in the case of words spoken from a distance], 
implying that the local movement [involved in Sound] takes 



1285 



place in the space between [us and the speaker]; for the reason 
why [persons addressed from a distance] do not succeed in 
catching the sense of what is said is evidently that the air 
[sound wave] in moving towards them has its form changed) 
[granting this, then, the question arises]: is the same also true in 
the case of Colour and Light? For certainly it is not true that the 
beholder sees, and the object is seen, in virtue of some merely 
abstract relationship between them, such as that between 
equals. For if it were so, there would be no need [as there is] that 
either [the beholder or the thing beheld] should occupy some 
particular place; since to the equalization of things their being 
near to, or far from, one another makes no difference. 

Now this [travelling through successive positions in the 
medium] may with good reason take place as regards Sound 
and Odour, for these, like [their media] Air and Water, are 
continuous, but the movement of both is divided into parts. This 
too is the ground of the fact that the object which the person 
first in order of proximity hears or smells is the same as that 
which each subsequent person perceives, while yet it is not the 
same. 

Some, indeed, raise a question also on these very points; they 
declare it impossible that one person should hear, or see, or 
smell, the same object as another, urging the impossibility of 
several persons in different places hearing or smelling [the 
same object], for the one same thing would [thus] be divided 
from itself. The answer is that, in perceiving the object which 
first set up the motion - e.g. a bell, or frankincense, or fire - all 
perceive an object numerically one and the same; while, of 
course, in the special object perceived they perceive an object 
numerically different for each, though specifically the same for 
all; and this, accordingly, explains how it is that many persons 
together see, or smell, or hear [the same object]. These things 
[the odour or sound proper] are not bodies, but an affection or 



1286 



process of some kind (otherwise this [viz. simultaneous 
perception of the one object by many] would not have been, as 
it is, a fact of experience) though, on the other hand, they each 
imply a body [as their cause]. 

But [though sound and odour may travel,] with regard to Light 
the case is different. For Light has its raison d'etre in the being 
[not becoming] of something, but it is not a movement. And in 
general, even in qualitative change the case is different from 
what it is in local movement [both being different species of 
kinesis]. Local movements, of course, arrive first at a point 
midway before reaching their goal (and Sound, it is currently 
believed, is a movement of something locally moved), but we 
cannot go on to assert this [arrival at a point midway] like 
manner of things which undergo qualitative change. For this 
kind of change may conceivably take place in a thing all at once, 
without one half of it being changed before the other; e.g. it is 
conceivable that water should be frozen simultaneously in 
every part. But still, for all that, if the body which is heated or 
frozen is extensive, each part of it successively is affected by the 
part contiguous, while the part first changed in quality is so 
changed by the cause itself which originates the change, and 
thus the change throughout the whole need not take place 
coinstantaneously and all at once. Tasting would have been as 
smelling now is, if we lived in a liquid medium, and perceived 
[the sapid object] at a distance, before touching it. 

Naturally, then, the parts of media between a sensory organ and 
its object are not all affected at once - except in the case of 
Light [illumination] for the reason above stated, and also in the 
case of seeing, for the same reason; for Light is an efficient 
cause of seeing. 



1287 



Another question respecting sense-perception is as follows: 
assuming, as is natural, that of two [simultaneous] sensory 
stimuli the stronger always tends to extrude the weaker [from 
consciousness], is it conceivable or not that one should be able 
to discern two objects coinstantaneously in the same individual 
time? The above assumption explains why persons do not 
perceive what is brought before their eyes, if they are at the 
time deep in thought, or in a fright, or listening to some loud 
noise. This assumption, then, must be made, and also the 
following: that it is easier to discern each object of sense when 
in its simple form than when an ingredient in a mixture; easier, 
for example, to discern wine when neat than when blended, 
and so also honey, and [in other provinces] a colour, or to 
discern the nete by itself alone, than [when sounded with the 
hypate] in the octave; the reason being that component 
elements tend to efface [the distinctive characteristics of] one 
another. Such is the effect [on one another] of all ingredients of 
which, when compounded, some one thing is formed. 

If, then, the greater stimulus tends to expel the less, it 
necessarily follows that, when they concur, this greater should 
itself too be less distinctly perceptible than if it were alone, 
since the less by blending with it has removed some of its 
individuality, according to our assumption that simple objects 
are in all cases more distinctly perceptible. 

Now, if the two stimuli are equal but heterogeneous, no 
perception of either will ensue; they will alike efface one 
another's characteristics. But in such a case the perception of 
either stimulus in its simple form is impossible. Hence either 
there will then be no sense-perception at all, or there will be a 
perception compounded of both and differing from either. The 
latter is what actually seems to result from ingredients blended 



1288 



together, whatever may be the compound in which they are so 
mixed. 

Since, then, from some concurrent [sensory stimuli] a resultant 
object is produced, while from others no such resultant is 
produced, and of the latter sort are those things which belong to 
different sense provinces (for only those things are capable of 
mixture whose extremes are contraries, and no one compound 
can be formed from, e.g. White and Sharp, except indirectly, i.e. 
not as a concord is formed of Sharp and Grave); there follows 
logically the impossibility of discerning such concurrent stimuli 
coinstantaneously. For we must suppose that the stimuli, when 
equal, tend alike to efface one another, since no one [form of 
stimulus] results from them; while, if they are unequal, the 
stronger alone is distinctly perceptible. 

Again, the soul would be more likely to perceive 
coinstantaneously, with one and the same sensory act, two 
things in the same sensory province, such as the Grave and the 
Sharp in sound; for the sensory stimulation in this one province 
is more likely to be unitemporal than that involving two 
different provinces, as Sight and Hearing. But it is impossible to 
perceive two objects coinstantaneously in the same sensory act 
unless they have been mixed, [when, however, they are no 
longer two], for their amalgamation involves their becoming 
one, and the sensory act related to one object is itself one, and 
such act, when one, is, of course, coinstantaneous with itself. 
Hence, when things are mixed we of necessity perceive them 
coinstantaneously: for we perceive them by a perception 
actually one. For an object numerically one means that which is 
perceived by a perception actually one, whereas an object 
specifically one means that which is perceived by a sensory act 
potentially one [i.e. by an energeia of the same sensuous 
faculty]. If then the actualized perception is one, it will declare 
its data to be one object; they must, therefore, have been mixed. 



1289 



Accordingly, when they have not been mixed, the actualized 
perceptions which perceive them will be two; but [if so, their 
perception must be successive not coinstantaneous, for] in one 
and the same faculty the perception actualized at any single 
moment is necessarily one, only one stimulation or exertion of 
a single faculty being possible at a single instant, and in the 
case supposed here the faculty is one. It follows, therefore, that 
we cannot conceive the possibility of perceiving two distinct 
objects coinstantaneously with one and the same sense. 

But if it be thus impossible to perceive coinstantaneously two 
objects in the same province of sense if they are really two, 
manifestly it is still less conceivable that we should perceive 
coinstantaneously objects in two different sensory provinces, as 
White and Sweet. For it appears that when the Soul predicates 
numerical unity it does so in virtue of nothing else than such 
coinstantaneous perception [of one object, in one instant, by 
one energeia]: while it predicates specific unity in virtue of [the 
unity of] the discriminating faculty of sense together with [the 
unity of] the mode in which this operates. What I mean, for 
example, is this; the same sense no doubt discerns White and 
Black, [which are hence generically one] though specifically 
different from one another, and so, too, a faculty of sense self- 
identical, but different from the former, discerns Sweet and 
Bitter; but while both these faculties differ from one another 
[and each from itself] in their modes of discerning either of 
their respective contraries, yet in perceiving the co-ordinates in 
each province they proceed in manners analogous to one 
another; for instance, as Taste perceives Sweet, so Sight 
perceives White; and as the latter perceives Black, so the former 
perceives Bitter. 

Again, if the stimuli of sense derived from Contraries are 
themselves Contrary, and if Contraries cannot be conceived as 
subsisting together in the same individual subject, and if 



1290 



Contraries, e.g. Sweet and Bitter, come under one and the same 
sense-faculty, we must conclude that it is impossible to discern 
them coinstantaneously. It is likewise clearly impossible so to 
discern such homogeneous sensibles as are not [indeed] 
Contrary, [but are yet of different species]. For these are, [in the 
sphere of colour, for instance], classed some with White, others 
with Black, and so it is, likewise, in the other provinces of sense; 
for example, of savours, some are classed with Sweet, and 
others with Bitter. Nor can one discern the components in 
compounds coinstantaneously (for these are ratios of 
Contraries, as e.g. the Octave or the Fifth); unless, indeed, on 
condition of perceiving them as one. For thus, and not 
otherwise, the ratios of the extreme sounds are compounded 
into one ratio: since we should have together the ratio, on the 
one hand, of Many to Few or of Odd to Even, on the other, that 
of Few to Many or of Even to Odd [and these, to be perceived 
together, must be unified]. 

If, then, the sensibles denominated co-ordinates though in 
different provinces of sense (e.g. I call Sweet and White co- 
ordinates though in different provinces) stand yet more aloof, 
and differ more, from one another than do any sensibles in the 
same province; while Sweet differs from White even more than 
Black does from White, it is still less conceivable that one 
should discern them [viz. sensibles in different sensory 
provinces whether co-ordinates or not] coinstantaneously than 
sensibles which are in the same province. Therefore, if 
coinstantaneous perception of the latter be impossible, that of 
the former is a fortiori impossible. 

Some of the writers who treat of concords assert that the 
sounds combined in these do not reach us simultaneously, but 
only appear to do so, their real successiveness being unnoticed 
whenever the time it involves is [so small as to be] 
imperceptible. Is this true or not? One might perhaps, following 



1291 



this up, go so far as to say that even the current opinion that 
one sees and hears coinstantaneously is due merely to the fact 
that the intervals of time [between the really successive 
perceptions of sight and hearing] escape observation. But this 
can scarcely be true, nor is it conceivable that any portion of 
time should be [absolutely] imperceptible, or that any should be 
absolutely unnoticeable; the truth being that it is possible to 
perceive every instant of time. [This is so]; because, if it is 
inconceivable that a person should, while perceiving himself or 
aught else in a continuous time, be at any instant unaware of 
his own existence; while, obviously, the assumption, that there 
is in the time-continuum a time so small as to be absolutely 
imperceptible, carries the implication that a person would, 
during such time, be unaware of his own existence, as well as of 
his seeing and perceiving; [this assumption must be false]. 

Again, if there is any magnitude, whether time or thing, 
absolutely imperceptible owing to its smallness, it follows that 
there would not be either a thing which one perceives, or a time 
in which one perceives it, unless in the sense that in some part 
of the given time he sees some part of the given thing. For [let 
there be a line ab, divided into two parts at g, and let this line 
represent a whole object and a corresponding whole time. Now,] 
if one sees the whole line, and perceives it during a time which 
forms one and the same continuum, only in the sense that he 
does so in some portion of this time, let us suppose the part gb, 
representing a time in which by supposition he was perceiving 
nothing, cut off from the whole. Well, then, he perceives in a 
certain part [viz. in the remainder] of the time, or perceives a 
part [viz. the remainder] of the line, after the fashion in which 
one sees the whole earth by seeing some given part of it, or 
walks in a year by walking in some given part of the year. But 
[by hypothesis] in the part bg he perceives nothing: therefore, in 
fact, he is said to perceive the whole object and during the 
whole time simply because he perceives [some part of the 



1292 



object] in some part of the time ab. But the same argument 
holds also in the case of ag [the remainder, regarded in its turn 
as a whole]; for it will be found [on this theory of vacant times 
and imperceptible magnitudes] that one always perceives only 
in some part of a given whole time, and perceives only some 
part of a whole magnitude, and that it is impossible to perceive 
any [really] whole [object in a really whole time; a conclusion 
which is absurd, as it would logically annihilate the perception 
of both Objects and Time]. 

Therefore we must conclude that all magnitudes are 
perceptible, but their actual dimensions do not present 
themselves immediately in their presentation as objects. One 
sees the sun, or a four-cubit rod at a distance, as a magnitude, 
but their exact dimensions are not given in their visual 
presentation: nay, at times an object of sight appears indivisible, 
but [vision like other special senses, is fallible respecting 
'common sensibles', e.g. magnitude, and] nothing that one sees 
is really indivisible. The reason of this has been previously 
explained. It is clear then, from the above arguments, that no 
portion of time is imperceptible. 

But we must here return to the question proposed above for 
discussion, whether it is possible or impossible to perceive 
several objects coinstantaneously; by 'coinstantaneously' I 
mean perceiving the several objects in a time one and 
indivisible relatively to one another, i.e. indivisible in a sense 
consistent with its being all a continuum. 

First, then, is it conceivable that one should perceive the 
different things coinstantaneously, but each with a different 
part of the Soul? Or [must we object] that, in the first place, to 
begin with the objects of one and the same sense, e.g. Sight, if 
we assume it [the Soul qua exercising Sight] to perceive one 
colour with one part, and another colour with a different part, it 



1293 



will have a plurality of parts the same in species, [as they must 
be,] since the objects which it thus perceives fall within the 
same genus? 

Should any one [to illustrate how the Soul might have in it two 
different parts specifically identical, each directed to a set of 
aistheta the same in genus with that to which the other is 
directed] urge that, as there are two eyes, so there may be in the 
Soul something analogous, [the reply is] that of the eyes, 
doubtless, some one organ is formed, and hence their 
actualization in perception is one; but if this is so in the Soul, 
then, in so far as what is formed of both [i.e. of any two 
specifically identical parts as assumed] is one, the true 
perceiving subject also will be one, [and the contradictory of the 
above hypothesis (of different parts of Soul remaining engaged 
in simultaneous perception with one sense) is what emerges 
from the analogy]; while if the two parts of Soul remain 
separate, the analogy of the eyes will fail, [for of these some one 
is really formed]. 

Furthermore, [on the supposition of the need of different parts 
of Soul, co-operating in each sense, to discern different objects 
coinstantaneously], the senses will be each at the same time 
one and many, as if we should say that they were each a set of 
diverse sciences; for neither will an 'activity' exist without its 
proper faculty, nor without activity will there be sensation. 

But if the Soul does not, in the way suggested [i.e. with different 
parts of itself acting simultaneously], perceive in one and the 
same individual time sensibles of the same sense, a fortiori it is 
not thus that it perceives sensibles of different senses. For it is, 
as already stated, more conceivable that it should perceive a 
plurality of the former together in this way than a plurality of 
heterogeneous objects. 



1294 



If then, as is the fact, the Soul with one part perceives Sweet, 
with another, White, either that which results from these is 
some one part, or else there is no such one resultant. But there 
must be such an one, inasmuch as the general faculty of sense- 
perception is one. What one object, then, does that one faculty 
[when perceiving an object, e.g. as both White and Sweet] 
perceive? [None]; for assuredly no one object arises by 
composition of these [heterogeneous objects, such as White and 
Sweet]. We must conclude, therefore, that there is, as has been 
stated before, some one faculty in the soul with which the latter 
perceives all its percepts, though it perceives each different 
genus of sensibles through a different organ. 

May we not, then, conceive this faculty which perceives White 
and Sweet to be one qua indivisible [sc. qua combining its 
different simultaneous objects] in its actualization, but 
different, when it has become divisible [sc. qua distinguishing 
its different simultaneous objects] in its actualization? 

Or is what occurs in the case of the perceiving Soul conceivably 
analogous to what holds true in that of the things themselves? 
For the same numerically one thing is white and sweet, and has 
many other qualities, [while its numerical oneness is not 
thereby prejudiced] if the fact is not that the qualities are really 
separable in the object from one another, but that the being of 
each quality is different [from that of every other]. In the same 
way therefore we must assume also, in the case of the Soul, that 
the faculty of perception in general is in itself numerically one 
and the same, but different [differentiated] in its being; 
different, that is to say, in genus as regards some of its objects, 
in species as regards others. Hence too, we may conclude that 
one can perceive [numerically different objects] 
coinstantaneously with a faculty which is numerically one and 
the same, but not the same in its relationship [sc. according as 
the objects to which it is directed are not the same]. 



1295 



That every sensible object is a magnitude, and that nothing 
which it is possible to perceive is indivisible, may be thus 
shown. The distance whence an object could not be seen is 
indeterminate, but that whence it is visible is determinate. We 
may say the same of the objects of Smelling and Hearing, and of 
all sensibles not discerned by actual contact. Now, there is, in 
the interval of distance, some extreme place, the last from 
which the object is invisible, and the first from which it is 
visible. This place, beyond which if the object be one cannot 
perceive it, while if the object be on the hither side one must 
perceive it, is, I presume, itself necessarily indivisible. Therefore, 
if any sensible object be indivisible, such object, if set in the said 
extreme place whence imperceptibility ends and perceptibility 
begins, will have to be both visible and invisible their objects, 
whether regarded in general or at the same time; but this is 
impossible. 

This concludes our survey of the characteristics of the organs of 
Sense-perception and their objects, whether regarded in general 
or in relation to each organ. Of the remaining subjects, we must 
first consider that of memory and remembering. 



1296 



On Memory and Reminiscence 
translated by J. I. Beare 



We have, in the next place, to treat of Memory and 
Remembering, considering its nature, its cause, and the part of 
the soul to which this experience, as well as that of Recollecting, 
belongs. For the persons who possess a retentive memory are 
not identical with those who excel in power of recollection; 
indeed, as a rule, slow people have a good memory, whereas 
those who are quick-witted and clever are better at recollecting. 

We must first form a true conception of these objects of 
memory, a point on which mistakes are often made. Now to 
remember the future is not possible, but this is an object of 
opinion or expectation (and indeed there might be actually a 
science of expectation, like that of divination, in which some 
believe); nor is there memory of the present, but only sense- 
perception. For by the latter we know not the future, nor the 
past, but the present only. But memory relates to the past. No 
one would say that he remembers the present, when it is 
present, e.g. a given white object at the moment when he sees 
it; nor would one say that he remembers an object of scientific 
contemplation at the moment when he is actually 
contemplating it, and has it full before his mind; - of the former 
he would say only that he perceives it, of the latter only that he 
knows it. But when one has scientific knowledge, or perception, 
apart from the actualizations of the faculty concerned, he thus 
'remembers' (that the angles of a triangle are together equal to 
two right angles); as to the former, that he learned it, or thought 
it out for himself, as to the latter, that he heard, or saw, it, or 



1297 



had some such sensible experience of it. For whenever one 
exercises the faculty of remembering, he must say within 
himself, 'I formerly heard (or otherwise perceived) this,' or 'I 
formerly had this thought'. 

Memory is, therefore, neither Perception nor Conception, but a 
state or affection of one of these, conditioned by lapse of time. 
As already observed, there is no such thing as memory of the 
present while present, for the present is object only of 
perception, and the future, of expectation, but the object of 
memory is the past. All memory, therefore, implies a time 
elapsed; consequently only those animals which perceive time 
remember, and the organ whereby they perceive time is also 
that whereby they remember. 

The subject of 'presentation' has been already considered in our 
work On the Soul. Without a presentation intellectual activity is 
impossible. For there is in such activity an incidental affection 
identical with one also incidental in geometrical 
demonstrations. For in the latter case, though we do not for the 
purpose of the proof make any use of the fact that the quantity 
in the triangle (for example, which we have drawn) is 
determinate, we nevertheless draw it determinate in quantity. 
So likewise when one exerts the intellect (e.g. on the subject of 
first principles), although the object may not be quantitative, 
one envisages it as quantitative, though he thinks it in 
abstraction from quantity; while, on the other hand, if the 
object of the intellect is essentially of the class of things that are 
quantitative, but indeterminate, one envisages it as if it had 
determinate quantity, though subsequently, in thinking it, he 
abstracts from its determinateness. Why we cannot exercise the 
intellect on any object absolutely apart from the continuous, or 
apply it even to non-temporal things unless in connexion with 
time, is another question. Now, one must cognize magnitude 
and motion by means of the same faculty by which one 



1298 



cognizes time (i.e. by that which is also the faculty of memory), 
and the presentation (involved in such cognition) is an affection 
of the sensus communis; whence this follows, viz. that the 
cognition of these objects (magnitude, motion time) is effected 
by the (said sensus communis, i.e. the) primary faculty of 
perception. Accordingly, memory (not merely of sensible, but) 
even of intellectual objects involves a presentation: hence we 
may conclude that it belongs to the faculty of intelligence only 
incidentally, while directly and essentially it belongs to the 
primary faculty of sense-perception. 

Hence not only human beings and the beings which possess 
opinion or intelligence, but also certain other animals, possess 
memory. If memory were a function of (pure) intellect, it would 
not have been as it is an attribute of many of the lower animals, 
but probably, in that case, no mortal beings would have had 
memory; since, even as the case stands, it is not an attribute of 
them all, just because all have not the faculty of perceiving 
time. Whenever one actually remembers having seen or heard, 
or learned, something, he includes in this act (as we have 
already observed) the consciousness of 'formerly'; and the 
distinction of 'former' and 'latter' is a distinction in time. 

Accordingly if asked, of which among the parts of the soul 
memory is a function, we reply: manifestly of that part to which 
'presentation' appertains; and all objects capable of being 
presented (viz. aistheta) are immediately and properly objects of 
memory, while those (viz. noeta) which necessarily involve (but 
only involve) presentation are objects of memory incidentally. 

One might ask how it is possible that though the affection (the 
presentation) alone is present, and the (related) fact absent, the 
latter - that which is not present - is remembered. (The 
question arises), because it is clear that we must conceive that 
which is generated through sense-perception in the sentient 



1299 



soul, and in the part of the body which is its seat - viz. that 
affection the state whereof we call memory - to be some such 
thing as a picture. The process of movement (sensory 
stimulation) involved the act of perception stamps in, as it were, 
a sort of impression of the percept, just as persons do who 
make an impression with a seal. This explains why, in those 
who are strongly moved owing to passion, or time of life, no 
mnemonic impression is formed; just as no impression would 
be formed if the movement of the seal were to impinge on 
running water; while there are others in whom, owing to the 
receiving surface being frayed, as happens to (the stucco on) old 
(chamber) walls, or owing to the hardness of the receiving 
surface, the requisite impression is not implanted at all. Hence 
both very young and very old persons are defective in memory; 
they are in a state of flux, the former because of their growth, 
the latter, owing to their decay. In like manner, also, both those 
who are too quick and those who are too slow have bad 
memories. The former are too soft, the latter too hard (in the 
texture of their receiving organs), so that in the case of the 
former the presented image (though imprinted) does not 
remain in the soul, while on the latter it is not imprinted at all. 

But then, if this truly describes what happens in the genesis of 
memory, (the question stated above arises:) when one 
remembers, is it this impressed affection that he remembers, or 
is it the objective thing from which this was derived? If the 
former, it would follow that we remember nothing which is 
absent; if the latter, how is it possible that, though perceiving 
directly only the impression, we remember that absent thing 
which we do not perceive? Granted that there is in us 
something like an impression or picture, why should the 
perception of the mere impression be memory of something 
else, instead of being related to this impression alone? For when 
one actually remembers, this impression is what he 
contemplates, and this is what he perceives. How then does he 



1300 



remember what is not present? One might as well suppose it 
possible also to see or hear that which is not present. In reply, 
we suggest that this very thing is quite conceivable, nay, 
actually occurs in experience. A picture painted on a panel is at 
once a picture and a likeness: that is, while one and the same, it 
is both of these, although the 'being' of both is not the same, 
and one may contemplate it either as a picture, or as a likeness. 
Just in the same way we have to conceive that the mnemonic 
presentation within us is something which by itself is merely an 
object of contemplation, while, in-relation to something else, it 
is also a presentation of that other thing. In so far as it is 
regarded in itself, it is only an object of contemplation, or a 
presentation; but when considered as relative to something 
else, e.g. as its likeness, it is also a mnemonic token. Hence, 
whenever the residual sensory process implied by it is 
actualized in consciousness, if the soul perceives this in so far 
as it is something absolute, it appears to occur as a mere 
thought or presentation; but if the soul perceives it qua related 
to something else, then, - just as when one contemplates the 
painting in the picture as being a likeness, and without having 
(at the moment) seen the actual Koriskos, contemplates it as a 
likeness of Koriskos, and in that case the experience involved in 
this contemplation of it (as relative) is different from what one 
has when he contemplates it simply as a painted figure - (so in 
the case of memory we have the analogous difference for), of 
the objects in the soul, the one (the unrelated object) presents 
itself simply as a thought, but the other (the related object) just 
because, as in the painting, it is a likeness, presents itself as a 
mnemonic token. 

We can now understand why it is that sometimes, when we 
have such processes, based on some former act of perception, 
occurring in the soul, we do not know whether this really 
implies our having had perceptions corresponding to them, and 
we doubt whether the case is or is not one of memory. But 



1301 



occasionally it happens that (while thus doubting) we get a 
sudden idea and recollect that we heard or saw something 
formerly. This (occurrence of the 'sudden idea') happens 
whenever, from contemplating a mental object as absolute, one 
changes his point of view, and regards it as relative to 
something else. 

The opposite (sc. to the case of those who at first do not 
recognize their phantasms as mnemonic) also occurs, as 
happened in the cases of Antipheron of Oreus and others 
suffering from mental derangement; for they were accustomed 
to speak of their mere phantasms as facts of their past 
experience, and as if remembering them. This takes place 
whenever one contemplates what is not a likeness as if it were 
a likeness. 

Mnemonic exercises aim at preserving one's memory of 
something by repeatedly reminding him of it; which implies 
nothing else (on the learner's part) than the frequent 
contemplation of something (viz. the 'mnemonic', whatever it 
may be) as a likeness, and not as out of relation. 

As regards the question, therefore, what memory or 
remembering is, it has now been shown that it is the state of a 
presentation, related as a likeness to that of which it is a 
presentation; and as to the question of which of the faculties 
within us memory is a function, (it has been shown) that it is a 
function of the primary faculty of sense-perception, i.e. of that 
faculty whereby we perceive time. 



1302 



Next comes the subject of Recollection, in dealing with which 
we must assume as fundamental the truths elicited above in 
our introductory discussions. For recollection is not the 
'recovery' or 'acquisition' of memory; since at the instant when 
one at first learns (a fact of science) or experiences (a particular 
fact of sense), he does not thereby 'recover' a memory, 
inasmuch as none has preceded, nor does he acquire one ab 
initio. It is only at the instant when the aforesaid state or 
affection (of the aisthesis or upolepsis) is implanted in the soul 
that memory exists, and therefore memory is not itself 
implanted concurrently with the continuous implantation of 
the (original) sensory experience. 

Further: at the very individual and concluding instant when 
first (the sensory experience or scientific knowledge) has been 
completely implanted, there is then already established in the 
person affected the (sensory) affection, or the scientific 
knowledge (if one ought to apply the term 'scientific knowledge' 
to the (mnemonic) state or affection; and indeed one may well 
remember, in the 'incidental' sense, some of the things (i.e. ta 
katholou) which are properly objects of scientific knowledge); 
but to remember, strictly and properly speaking, is an activity 
which will not be immanent until the original experience has 
undergone lapse of time. For one remembers now what one saw 
or otherwise experienced formerly; the moment of the original 
experience and the moment of the memory of it are never 
identical. 

Again, (even when time has elapsed, and one can be said really 
to have acquired memory, this is not necessarily recollection, for 
firstly) it is obviously possible, without any present act of 
recollection, to remember as a continued consequence of the 
original perception or other experience; whereas when (after an 



1303 



interval of obliviscence) one recovers some scientific knowledge 
which he had before, or some perception, or some other 
experience, the state of which we above declared to be memory, 
it is then, and then only, that this recovery may amount to a 
recollection of any of the things aforesaid. But, (though as 
observed above, remembering does not necessarily imply 
recollecting), recollecting always implies remembering, and 
actualized memory follows (upon the successful act of 
recollecting). 

But secondly, even the assertion that recollection is the 
reinstatement in consciousness of something which was there 
before but had disappeared requires qualification. This 
assertion may be true, but it may also be false; for the same 
person may twice learn (from some teacher), or twice discover 
(i.e. excogitate), the same fact. Accordingly, the act of 
recollecting ought (in its definition) to be distinguished from 
these acts; i.e. recollecting must imply in those who recollect 
the presence of some spring over and above that from which 
they originally learn. 

Acts of recollection, as they occur in experience, are due to the 
fact that one movement has by nature another that succeeds it 
in regular order. 

If this order be necessary, whenever a subject experiences the 
former of two movements thus connected, it will (invariably) 
experience the latter; if, however, the order be not necessary, 
but customary, only in the majority of cases will the subject 
experience the latter of the two movements. But it is a fact that 
there are some movements, by a single experience of which 
persons take the impress of custom more deeply than they do 
by experiencing others many times; hence upon seeing some 
things but once we remember them better than others which 
we may have been frequently. 



1304 



Whenever therefore, we are recollecting, we are experiencing 
certain of the antecedent movements until finally we 
experience the one after which customarily comes that which 
we seek. This explains why we hunt up the series (of kineseis) 
having started in thought either from a present intuition or 
some other, and from something either similar, or contrary, to 
what we seek, or else from that which is contiguous with it. 
Such is the empirical ground of the process of recollection; for 
the mnemonic movements involved in these starting-points are 
in some cases identical, in others, again, simultaneous, with 
those of the idea we seek, while in others they comprise a 
portion of them, so that the remnant which one experienced 
after that portion (and which still requires to be excited in 
memory) is comparatively small. 

Thus, then, it is that persons seek to recollect, and thus, too, it is 
that they recollect even without the effort of seeking to do so, 
viz. when the movement implied in recollection has supervened 
on some other which is its condition. For, as a rule, it is when 
antecedent movements of the classes here described have first 
been excited, that the particular movement implied in 
recollection follows. We need not examine a series of which the 
beginning and end lie far apart, in order to see how (by 
recollection) we remember; one in which they lie near one 
another will serve equally well. For it is clear that the method is 
in each case the same, that is, one hunts up the objective series, 
without any previous search or previous recollection. For (there 
is, besides the natural order, viz. the order of the pralmata, or 
events of the primary experience, also a customary order, and) 
by the effect of custom the mnemonic movements tend to 
succeed one another in a certain order. Accordingly, therefore, 
when one wishes to recollect, this is what he will do: he will try 
to obtain a beginning of movement whose sequel shall be the 
movement which he desires to reawaken. This explains why 
attempts at recollection succeed soonest and best when they 



1305 



start from a beginning (of some objective series). For, in order of 
succession, the mnemonic movements are to one another as 
the objective facts (from which they are derived). Accordingly, 
things arranged in a fixed order, like the successive 
demonstrations in geometry, are easy to remember (or recollect) 
while badly arranged subjects are remembered with difficulty. 

Recollecting differs also in this respect from relearning, that one 
who recollects will be able, somehow, to move, solely by his own 
effort, to the term next after the starting-point. When one 
cannot do this of himself, but only by external assistance, he no 
longer remembers (i.e. he has totally forgotten, and therefore of 
course cannot recollect). It often happens that, though a person 
cannot recollect at the moment, yet by seeking he can do so, 
and discovers what he seeks. This he succeeds in doing by 
setting up many movements, until finally he excites one of a 
kind which will have for its sequel the fact he wishes to 
recollect. For remembering (which is the condicio sine qua non 
of recollecting) is the existence, potentially, in the mind of a 
movement capable of stimulating it to the desired movement, 
and this, as has been said, in such a way that the person should 
be moved (prompted to recollection) from within himself, i.e. in 
consequence of movements wholly contained within himself. 

But one must get hold of a starting-point. This explains why it is 
that persons are supposed to recollect sometimes by starting 
from mnemonic loci. The cause is that they pass swiftly in 
thought from one point to another, e.g. from milk to white, from 
white to mist, and thence to moist, from which one remembers 
Autumn (the 'season of mists'), if this be the season he is trying 
to recollect. 

It seems true in general that the middle point also among all 
things is a good mnemonic starting-point from which to reach 
any of them. For if one does not recollect before, he will do so 



1306 



when he has come to this, or, if not, nothing can help him; as, 
e.g. if one were to have in mind the numerical series denoted by 
the symbols A, B, G, D, E, Z, I, H, 0. For, if he does not remember 
what he wants at E, then at E he remembers 0; because from E 
movement in either direction is possible, to D or to Z. But, if it is 
not for one of these that he is searching, he will remember 
(what he is searching for) when he has come to G if he is 
searching for H or I. But if (it is) not (for H or I that he is 
searching, but for one of the terms that remain), he will 
remember by going to A, and so in all cases (in which one starts 
from a middle point). The cause of one's sometimes recollecting 
and sometimes not, though starting from the same point, is, 
that from the same starting-point a movement can be made in 
several directions, as, for instance, from G to I or to D. If, then, 
the mind has not (when starting from E) moved in an old path 
(i.e. one in which it moved first having the objective experience, 
and that, therefore, in which un-'ethized' phusis would have it 
again move), it tends to move to the more customary; for (the 
mind having, by chance or otherwise, missed moving in the 'old' 
way) Custom now assumes the role of Nature. Hence the 
rapidity with which we recollect what we frequently think 
about. For as regular sequence of events is in accordance with 
nature, so, too, regular sequence is observed in the actualization 
of kinesis (in consciousness), and here frequency tends to 
produce (the regularity of) nature. And since in the realm of 
nature occurrences take place which are even contrary to 
nature, or fortuitous, the same happens a fortiori in the sphere 
swayed by custom, since in this sphere natural law is not 
similarly established. Hence it is that (from the same starting- 
point) the mind receives an impulse to move sometimes in the 
required direction, and at other times otherwise, (doing the 
latter) particularly when something else somehow deflects the 
mind from the right direction and attracts it to itself. This last 
consideration explains too how it happens that, when we want 



1307 



to remember a name, we remember one somewhat like it, 
indeed, but blunder in reference to (i.e. in pronouncing) the one 
we intended. 

Thus, then, recollection takes place. 

But the point of capital importance is that (for the purpose of 
recollection) one should cognize, determinately or 
indeterminately, the time-relation (of that which he wishes to 
recollect). There is, let it be taken as a fact, something by which 
one distinguishes a greater and a smaller time; and it is 
reasonable to think that one does this in a way analogous to 
that in which one discerns (spacial) magnitudes. For it is not by 
the mind's reaching out towards them, as some say a visual ray 
from the eye does (in seeing), that one thinks of large things at a 
distance in space (for even if they are not there, one may 
similarly think them); but one does so by a proportionate 
mental movement. For there are in the mind the like figures 
and movements (i.e. 'like' to those of objects and events). 
Therefore, when one thinks the greater objects, in what will his 
thinking those differ from his thinking the smaller? (In 
nothing,) because all the internal though smaller are as it were 
proportional to the external. Now, as we may assume within a 
person something proportional to the forms (of distant 
magnitudes), so, too, we may doubtless assume also something 
else proportional to their distances. As, therefore, if one has 
(psychically) the movement in AB, BE, he constructs in thought 
(i.e. knows objectively) GD, since AG and GD bear equal ratios 
respectively (to AB and BE), (so he who recollects also proceeds). 
Why then does he construct GD rather than ZH? Is it not 
because as AG is to AB, so is to I? These movements therefore 
(sc. in AB, BE, and in 0:1) he has simultaneously. But if he wishes 
to construct to thought ZH, he has in mind BE in like manner as 
before (when constructing GD), but now, instead of (the 



1308 



movements of the ratio) 0:1, he has in mind (those of the ratio 
K:L; for K:L::ZA:BA. (See diagram.) 

When, therefore, the 'movement' corresponding to the object 
and that corresponding to its time concur, then one actually 
remembers. If one supposes (himself to move in these different 
but concurrent ways) without really doing so, he supposes 
himself to remember. 

For one may be mistaken, and think that he remembers when 
he really does not. But it is not possible, conversely, that when 
one actually remembers he should not suppose himself to 
remember, but should remember unconsciously. For 
remembering, as we have conceived it, essentially implies 
consciousness of itself. If, however, the movement 
corresponding to the objective fact takes place without that 
corresponding to the time, or, if the latter takes place without 
the former, one does not remember. 

The movement answering to the time is of two kinds. 
Sometimes in remembering a fact one has no determinate time- 
notion of it, no such notion as that e.g. he did something or 
other on the day before yesterday; while in other cases he has a 
determinate notion of the time. Still, even though one does not 
remember with actual determination of the time, he genuinely 
remembers, none the less. Persons are wont to say that they 
remember (something), but yet do not know when (it occurred, 
as happens) whenever they do not know determinately the 
exact length of time implied in the 'when'. 

It has been already stated that those who have a good memory 
are not identical with those who are quick at recollecting. But 
the act of recollecting differs from that of remembering, not 
only chronologically, but also in this, that many also of the other 
animals (as well as man) have memory, but, of all that we are 
acquainted with, none, we venture to say, except man, shares in 



1309 



the faculty of recollection. The cause of this is that recollection 
is, as it were a mode of inference. For he who endeavours to 
recollect infers that he formerly saw, or heard, or had some such 
experience, and the process (by which he succeeds in 
recollecting) is, as it were, a sort of investigation. But to 
investigate in this way belongs naturally to those animals alone 
which are also endowed with the faculty of deliberation; (which 
proves what was said above), for deliberation is a form of 
inference. 

That the affection is corporeal, i.e. that recollection is a 
searching for an 'image' in a corporeal substrate, is proved by 
the fact that in some persons, when, despite the most 
strenuous application of thought, they have been unable to 
recollect, it (viz. the anamnesis = the effort at recollection) 
excites a feeling of discomfort, which, even though they 
abandon the effort at recollection, persists in them none the 
less; and especially in persons of melancholic temperament. For 
these are most powerfully moved by presentations. The reason 
why the effort of recollection is not under the control of their 
will is that, as those who throw a stone cannot stop it at their 
will when thrown, so he who tries to recollect and 'hunts' (after 
an idea) sets up a process in a material part, (that) in which 
resides the affection. Those who have moisture around that part 
which is the centre of sense-perception suffer most discomfort 
of this kind. For when once the moisture has been set in motion 
it is not easily brought to rest, until the idea which was sought 
for has again presented itself, and thus the movement has 
found a straight course. For a similar reason bursts of anger or 
fits of terror, when once they have excited such motions, are not 
at once allayed, even though the angry or terrified persons (by 
efforts of will) set up counter motions, but the passions 
continue to move them on, in the same direction as at first, in 
opposition to such counter motions. The affection resembles 
also that in the case of words, tunes, or sayings, whenever one 



1310 



of them has become inveterate on the lips. People give them up 
and resolve to avoid them; yet again they find themselves 
humming the forbidden air, or using the prohibited word. Those 
whose upper parts are abnormally large, as. is the case with 
dwarfs, have abnormally weak memory, as compared with their 
opposites, because of the great weight which they have resting 
upon the organ of perception, and because their mnemonic 
movements are, from the very first, not able to keep true to a 
course, but are dispersed, and because, in the effort at 
recollection, these movements do not easily find a direct 
onward path. Infants and very old persons have bad memories, 
owing to the amount of movement going on within them; for 
the latter are in process of rapid decay, the former in process of 
vigorous growth; and we may add that children, until 
considerably advanced in years, are dwarf-like in their bodily 
structure. Such then is our theory as regards memory and 
remembering their nature, and the particular organ of the soul 
by which animals remember; also as regards recollection, its 
formal definition, and the manner and causes of its 
performance. 



1311 



On Sleep And Sleeplessness 
translated by J. I. Beare 



With regard to sleep and waking, we must consider what they 
are: whether they are peculiar to soul or to body, or common to 
both; and if common, to what part of soul or body they 
appertain: further, from what cause it arises that they are 
attributes of animals, and whether all animals share in them 
both, or some partake of the one only, others of the other only, 
or some partake of neither and some of both. 

Further, in addition to these questions, we must also inquire 
what the dream is, and from what cause sleepers sometimes 
dream, and sometimes do not; or whether the truth is that 
sleepers always dream but do not always remember (their 
dream); and if this occurs, what its explanation is. 

Again, [we must inquire] whether it is possible or not to foresee 
the future (in dreams), and if it be possible, in what manner; 
further, whether, supposing it possible, it extends only to things 
to be accomplished by the agency of Man, or to those also of 
which the cause lies in supra-human agency, and which result 
from the workings of Nature, or of Spontaneity. 

First, then, this much is clear, that waking and sleep appertain 
to the same part of an animal, inasmuch as they are opposites, 
and sleep is evidently a privation of waking. For contraries, in 
natural as well as in all other matters, are seen always to 
present themselves in the same subject, and to be affections of 
the same: examples are - health and sickness, beauty and 



1312 



ugliness, strength and weakness, sight and blindness, hearing 
and deafness. This is also clear from the following 
considerations. The criterion by which we know the waking 
person to be awake is identical with that by which we know the 
sleeper to be asleep; for we assume that one who is exercising 
sense-perception is awake, and that every one who is awake 
perceives either some external movement or else some 
movement in his own consciousness. If waking, then, consists 
in nothing else than the exercise of sense-perception, the 
inference is clear, that the organ, in virtue of which animals 
perceive, is that by which they wake, when they are awake, or 
sleep, when they are awake, or sleep, when they are asleep. 

But since the exercise of sense-perception does not belong to 
soul or body exclusively, then (since the subject of actuality is in 
every case identical with that of potentiality, and what is called 
sense-perception, as actuality, is a movement of the soul 
through the body) it is clear that its affection is not an affection 
of soul exclusively, and that a soulless body has not the 
potentiality of perception. [Thus sleep and waking are not 
attributes of pure intelligence, on the one hand, or of inanimate 
bodies, on the other.] 

Now, whereas we have already elsewhere distinguished what 
are called the parts of the soul, and whereas the nutrient is, in 
all living bodies, capable of existing without the other parts, 
while none of the others can exist without the nutrient; it is 
clear that sleep and waking are not affections of such living 
things as partake only of growth and decay, e.g. not of plants, 
because these have not the faculty of sense-perception, 
whether or not this be capable of separate existence; in its 
potentiality, indeed, and in its relationships, it is separable. 

Likewise it is clear that [of those which either sleep or wake] 
there is no animal which is always awake or always asleep, but 



1313 



that both these affections belong [alternately] to the same 
animals. For if there be an animal not endued with sense- 
perception, it is impossible that this should either sleep or 
wake; since both these are affections of the activity of the 
primary faculty of sense-perception. But it is equally impossible 
also that either of these two affections should perpetually 
attach itself to the same animal, e.g. that some species of 
animal should be always asleep or always awake, without 
intermission; for all organs which have a natural function must 
lose power when they work beyond the natural time-limit of 
their working period; for instance, the eyes [must lose power] 
from [too long continued] seeing, and must give it up; and so it 
is with the hand and every other member which has a function. 
Now, if sense-perception is the function of a special organ, this 
also, if it continues perceiving beyond the appointed time-limit 
of its continuous working period, will lose its power, and will do 
its work no longer. Accordingly, if the waking period is 
determined by this fact, that in it sense-perception is free; if in 
the case of some contraries one of the two must be present, 
while in the case of others this is not necessary; if waking is the 
contrary of sleeping, and one of these two must be present to 
every animal: it must follow that the state of sleeping is 
necessary. Finally, if such affection is Sleep, and this is a state of 
powerlessness arising from excess of waking, and excess of 
waking is in its origin sometimes morbid, sometimes not, so 
that the powerlessness or dissolution of activity will be so or 
not; it is inevitable that every creature which wakes must also 
be capable of sleeping, since it is impossible that it should 
continue actualizing its powers perpetually. 

So, also, it is impossible for any animal to continue always 
sleeping. For sleep is an affection of the organ of sense- 
perception - a sort of tie or inhibition of function imposed on it, 
so that every creature that sleeps must needs have the organ of 
sense-perception. Now, that alone which is capable of sense- 



1314 



perception in actuality has the faculty of sense-perception; but 
to realize this faculty, in the proper and unqualified sense, is 
impossible while one is asleep. All sleep, therefore, must be 
susceptible of awakening. Accordingly, almost all other animals 
are clearly observed to partake in sleep, whether they are 
aquatic, aerial, or terrestrial, since fishes of all kinds, and 
molluscs, as well as all others which have eyes, have been seen 
sleeping. 'Hard-eyed' creatures and insects manifestly assume 
the posture of sleep; but the sleep of all such creatures is of 
brief duration, so that often it might well baffle one's 
observation to decide whether they sleep or not. Of testaceous 
animals, on the contrary, no direct sensible evidence is as yet 
forthcoming to determine whether they sleep, but if the above 
reasoning be convincing to any one, he who follows it will admit 
this [viz. that they do so.] 

That, therefore, all animals sleep may be gathered from these 
considerations. For an animal is defined as such by its 
possessing sense-perception; and we assert that sleep is, in a 
certain way, an inhibition of function, or, as it were, a tie, 
imposed on sense-perception, while its loosening or remission 
constitutes the being awake. But no plant can partake in either 
of these affections, for without sense-perception there is 
neither sleeping nor waking. But creatures which have sense- 
perception have likewise the feeling of pain and pleasure, while 
those which have these have appetite as well; but plants have 
none of these affections. A mark of this is that the nutrient part 
does its own work better when (the animal) is asleep than when 
it is awake. Nutrition and growth are then especially promoted, 
a fact which implies that creatures do not need sense- 
perception to assist these processes. 



1315 



We must now proceed to inquire into the cause why one sleeps 
and wakes, and into the particular nature of the sense- 
perception, or sense-perceptions, if there be several, on which 
these affections depend. Since, then, some animals possess all 
the modes of sense-perception, and some not all, not, for 
example, sight, while all possess touch and taste, except such 
animals as are imperfectly developed, a class of which we have 
already treated in our work on the soul; and since an animal 
when asleep is unable to exercise, in the simple sense any 
particular sensory faculty whatever, it follows that in the state 
called sleep the same affection must extend to all the special 
senses; because, if it attaches itself to one of them but not to 
another, then an animal while asleep may perceive with the 
latter; but this is impossible. 

Now, since every sense has something peculiar, and also 
something common; peculiar, as, e.g. seeing is to the sense of 
sight, hearing to the auditory sense, and so on with the other 
senses severally; while all are accompanied by a common 
power, in virtue whereof a person perceives that he sees or 
hears (for, assuredly, it is not by the special sense of sight that 
one sees that he sees; and it is not by mere taste, or sight, or 
both together that one discerns, and has the faculty of 
discerning, that sweet things are different from white things, 
but by a faculty connected in common with all the organs of 
sense; for there is one sensory function, and the controlling 
sensory faculty is one, though differing as a faculty of 
perception in relation to each genus of sensibles, e.g. sound or 
colour); and since this [common sensory activity] subsists in 
association chiefly with the faculty of touch (for this can exist 
apart from all the other organs of sense, but none of them can 
exist apart from it - a subject of which we have treated in our 
speculations concerning the Soul); it is therefore evident that 



1316 



waking and sleeping are an affection of this [common and 
controlling organ of sense-perception]. This explains why they 
belong to all animals, for touch [with which this common organ 
is chiefly connected], alone, [is common] to all [animals]. 

For if sleeping were caused by the special senses having each 
and all undergone some affection, it would be strange that 
these senses, for which it is neither necessary nor in a manner 
possible to realize their powers simultaneously, should 
necessarily all go idle and become motionless simultaneously. 
For the contrary experience, viz. that they should not go to rest 
altogether, would have been more reasonably anticipated. But, 
according to the explanation just given, all is quite clear 
regarding those also. For, when the sense organ which controls 
all the others, and to which all the others are tributary, has been 
in some way affected, that these others should be all affected at 
the same time is inevitable, whereas, if one of the tributaries 
becomes powerless, that the controlling organ should also 
become powerless need in no wise follow. 

It is indeed evident from many considerations that sleep does 
not consist in the mere fact that the special senses do not 
function or that one does not employ them; and that it does not 
consist merely in an inability to exercise the sense-perceptions; 
for such is what happens in cases of swooning. A swoon means 
just such impotence of perception, and certain other cases of 
unconsciousness also are of this nature. Moreover, persons who 
have the bloodvessels in the neck compressed become 
insensible. But sleep supervenes when such incapacity of 
exercise has neither arisen in some casual organ of sense, nor 
from some chance cause, but when, as has been just stated, it 
has its seat in the primary organ with which one perceives 
objects in general. For when this has become powerless all the 
other sensory organs also must lack power to perceive; but 



1317 



when one of them has become powerless, it is not necessary for 
this also to lose its power. 

We must next state the cause to which it is due, and its quality 
as an affection. Now, since there are several types of cause (for 
we assign equally the 'final', the 'efficient', the 'material', and 
the 'formal' as causes), in the first place, then, as we assert that 
Nature operates for the sake of an end, and that this end is a 
good; and that to every creature which is endowed by nature 
with the power to move, but cannot with pleasure to itself move 
always and continuously, rest is necessary and beneficial; and 
since, taught by experience, men apply to sleep this 
metaphorical term, calling it a 'rest' [from the strain of 
movement implied in sense-perception]: we conclude that its 
end is the conservation of animals. But the waking state is for 
an animal its highest end, since the exercise of sense- 
perception or of thought is the highest end for all beings to 
which either of these appertains; inasmuch as these are best, 
and the highest end is what is best: whence it follows that sleep 
belongs of necessity to each animal. I use the term 'necessity' in 
its conditional sense, meaning that if an animal is to exist and 
have its own proper nature, it must have certain endowments; 
and, if these are to belong to it, certain others likewise must 
belong to it [as their condition.] 

The next question to be discussed is that of the kind of 
movement or action, taking place within their bodies, from 
which the affection of waking or sleeping arises in animals. 
Now, we must assume that the causes of this affection in all 
other animals are identical with, or analogous to, those which 
operate in sanguineous animals; and that the causes operating 
in sanguineous animals generally are identical with those 
operating in man. Hence we must consider the entire subject in 
the light of these instances [afforded by sanguineous animals, 
especially man]. Now, it has been definitely settled already in 



1318 



another work that sense-perception in animals originates ill the 
same part of the organism in which movement originates. This 
locus of origination is one of three determinate loci, viz. that 
which lies midway between the head and the abdomen. This is 
sanguineous animals is the region of the heart; for all 
sanguineous animals have a heart; and from this it is that both 
motion and the controlling sense-perception originate. Now, as 
regards movement, it is obvious that that of breathing and of 
the cooling process generally takes its rise there; and it is with a 
view to the conservation of the [due amount of] heat in this part 
that nature has formed as she has both the animals which 
respire, and those which cool themselves by moisture. Of this 
[cooling process] per se we shall treat hereafter. In bloodless 
animals, and insects, and such as do not respire, the 'connatural 
spirit' is seen alternately puffed up and subsiding in the part 
which is in them analogous [to the region of the heart in 
sanguineous animals]. This is clearly observable in the 
holoptera [insects with undivided wings] as wasps and bees; 
also in flies and such creatures. And since to move anything, or 
do anything, is impossible without strength, and holding the 
breath produces strength - in creatures which inhale, the 
holding of that breath which comes from without, but, in 
creatures which do not respire, of that which is connatural 
(which explains why winged insects of the class holoptera, 
when they move, are perceived to make a humming noise, due 
to the friction of the connatural spirit colliding with the 
diaphragm); and since movement is, in every animal, attended 
with some sense-perception, either internal or external, in the 
primary organ of sense, [we conclude] accordingly that if 
sleeping and waking are affections of this organ, the place in 
which, or the organ in which, sleep and waking originate, is self- 
evident [being that in which movement and sense-perception 
originate, viz. the heart]. 



1319 



Some persons move in their sleep, and perform many acts like 
waking acts, but not without a phantasm or an exercise of 
sense-perception; for a dream is in a certain way a sense- 
impression. But of them we have to speak later on. Why it is 
that persons when aroused remember their dreams, but do not 
remember these acts which are like waking acts, has been 
already explained in the work 'Of Problems'. 



The point for consideration next in order to the preceding is: - 
What are the processes in which the affection of waking and 
sleeping originates, and whence do they arise? Now, since it is 
when it has sense-perception that an animal must first take 
food and receive growth, and in all cases food in its ultimate 
form is, in sanguineous animals, the natural substance blood, 
or, in bloodless animals, that which is analogous to this; and 
since the veins are the place of the blood, while the origin of 
these is the heart - an assertion which is proved by anatomy - it 
is manifest that, when the external nutriment enters the parts 
fitted for its reception, the evaporation arising from it enters 
into the veins, and there, undergoing a change, is converted into 
blood, and makes its way to their source [the heart]. We have 
treated of all this when discussing the subject of nutrition, but 
must here recapitulate what was there said, in order that we 
may obtain a scientific view of the beginnings of the process, 
and come to know what exactly happens to the primary organ 
of sense-perception to account for the occurrence of waking 
and sleep. For sleep, as has been shown, is not any given 
impotence of the perceptive faculty; for unconsciousness, a 
certain form of asphyxia, and swooning, all produce such 
impotence. Moreover it is an established fact that some persons 



1320 



in a profound trance have still had the imaginative faculty in 
play. This last point, indeed, gives rise to a difficulty; for if it is 
conceivable that one who had swooned should in this state fall 
asleep, the phantasm also which then presented itself to his 
mind might be regarded as a dream. Persons, too, who have 
fallen into a deep trance, and have come to be regarded as dead, 
say many things while in this condition. The same view, 
however, is to be taken of all these cases, [i.e. that they are not 
cases of sleeping or dreaming]. 

As we observed above, sleep is not co-extensive with any and 
every impotence of the perceptive faculty, but this affection is 
one which arises from the evaporation attendant upon the 
process of nutrition. The matter evaporated must be driven 
onwards to a certain point, then turn back, and change its 
current to and fro, like a tide-race in a narrow strait. Now, in 
every animal the hot naturally tends to move [and carry other 
things] upwards, but when it has reached the parts above 
[becoming cool], it turns back again, and moves downwards in a 
mass. This explains why fits of drowsiness are especially apt to 
come on after meals; for the matter, both the liquid and the 
corporeal, which is borne upwards in a mass, is then of 
considerable quantity. When, therefore, this comes to a stand it 
weighs a person down and causes him to nod, but when it has 
actually sunk downwards, and by its return has repulsed the 
hot, sleep comes on, and the animal so affected is presently 
asleep. A confirmation of this appears from considering the 
things which induce sleep; they all, whether potable or edible, 
for instance poppy, mandragora, wine, darnel, produce a 
heaviness in the head; and persons borne down [by sleepiness] 
and nodding [drowsily] all seem affected in this way, i.e. they 
are unable to lift up the head or the eye-lids. And it is after 
meals especially that sleep comes on like this, for the 
evaporation from the foods eaten is then copious. It also follows 
certain forms of fatigue; for fatigue operates as a solvent, and 



1321 



the dissolved matter acts, if not cold, like food prior to digestion. 
Moreover, some kinds of illness have this same effect; those 
arising from moist and hot secretions, as happens with fever- 
patients and in cases of lethargy. Extreme youth also has this 
effect; infants, for example, sleep a great deal, because of the 
food being all borne upwards - a mark whereof appears in the 
disproportionately large size of the upper parts compared with 
the lower during infancy, which is due to the fact that growth 
predominates in the direction of the former. Hence also they are 
subject to epileptic seizures; for sleep is like epilepsy, and, in a 
sense, actually is a seizure of this sort. Accordingly, the 
beginning of this malady takes place with many during sleep, 
and their subsequent habitual seizures occur in sleep, not in 
waking hours. For when the spirit [evaporation] moves upwards 
in a volume, on its return downwards it distends the veins, and 
forcibly compresses the passage through which respiration is 
effected. This explains why wines are not good for infants or for 
wet nurses (for it makes no difference, doubtless, whether the 
infants themselves, or their nurses, drink them), but such 
persons should drink them [if at all] diluted with water and in 
small quantity. For wine is spirituous, and of all wines the dark 
more so than any other. The upper parts, in infants, are so filled 
with nutriment that within five months [after birth] they do not 
even turn the neck [sc. to raise the head]; for in them, as in 
persons deeply intoxicated, there is ever a large quantity of 
moisture ascending. It is reasonable, too, to think that this 
affection is the cause of the embryo's remaining at rest in the 
womb at first. Also, as a general rule, persons whose veins are 
inconspicuous, as well as those who are dwarf-like, or have 
abnormally large heads, are addicted to sleep. For in the former 
the veins are narrow, so that it is not easy for the moisture to 
flow down through them; while in the case of dwarfs and those 
whose heads are abnormally large, the impetus of the 
evaporation upwards is excessive. Those [on the contrary] 



1322 



whose veins are large are, thanks to the easy flow through the 
veins, not addicted to sleep, unless, indeed, they labour under 
some other affection which counteracts [this easy flow]. Nor are 
the 'atrabilious' addicted to sleep, for in them the inward region 
is cooled so that the quantity of evaporation in their case is not 
great. For this reason they have large appetites, though spare 
and lean; for their bodily condition is as if they derived no 
benefit from what they eat. The dark bile, too, being itself 
naturally cold, cools also the nutrient tract, and the other parts 
wheresoever such secretion is potentially present [i.e. tends to 
be formed]. 

Hence it is plain from what has been said that sleep is a sort of 
concentration, or natural recoil, of the hot matter inwards 
[towards its centre], due to the cause above mentioned. Hence 
restless movement is a marked feature in the case of a person 
when drowsy. But where it [the heat in the upper and outer 
parts] begins to fail, he grows cool, and owing to this cooling 
process his eye-lids droop. Accordingly [in sleep] the upper and 
outward parts are cool, but the inward and lower, i.e. the parts 
at the feet and in the interior of the body, are hot. 

Yet one might found a difficulty on the facts that sleep is most 
oppressive in its onset after meals, and that wine, and other 
such things, though they possess heating properties, are 
productive of sleep, for it is not probable that sleep should be a 
process of cooling while the things that cause sleeping are 
themselves hot. Is the explanation of this, then, to be found in 
the fact that, as the stomach when empty is hot, while 
replenishment cools it by the movement it occasions, so the 
passages and tracts in the head are cooled as the 'evaporation' 
ascends thither? Or, as those who have hot water poured on 
them feel a sudden shiver of cold, just so in the case before us, 
may it be that, when the hot substance ascends, the cold 
rallying to meet it cools [the aforesaid parts] deprives their 



1323 



native heat of all its power, and compels it to retire? Moreover, 
when much food is taken, which [i.e. the nutrient evaporation 
from which] the hot substance carries upwards, this latter, like a 
fire when fresh logs are laid upon it, is itself cooled, until the 
food has been digested. 

For, as has been observed elsewhere, sleep comes on when the 
corporeal element [in the 'evaporation'] conveyed upwards by 
the hot, along the veins, to the head. But when that which has 
been thus carried up can no longer ascend, but is too great in 
quantity [to do so], it forces the hot back again and flows 
downwards. Hence it is that men sink down [as they do in sleep] 
when the heat which tends to keep them erect (man alone, 
among animals, being naturally erect) is withdrawn; and this, 
when it befalls them, causes unconsciousness, and afterwards 
phantasy. 

Or are the solutions thus proposed barely conceivable accounts 
of the refrigeration which takes place, while, as a matter of fact, 
the region of the brain is, as stated elsewhere, the main 
determinant of the matter? For the brain, or in creatures 
without a brain that which corresponds to it, is of all parts of 
the body the coolest. Therefore, as moisture turned into vapour 
by the sun's heat is, when it has ascended to the upper regions, 
cooled by the coldness of the latter, and becoming condensed, is 
carried downwards, and turned into water once more; just so 
the excrementitious evaporation, when carried up by the heat to 
the region of the brain, is condensed into a 'phlegm' (which 
explains why catarrhs are seen to proceed from the head); while 
that evaporation which is nutrient and not unwholesome, 
becoming condensed, descends and cools the hot. The tenuity 
or narrowness of the veins about the brain itself contributes to 
its being kept cool, and to its not readily admitting the 
evaporation. This, then, is a sufficient explanation of the cooling 



1324 



which takes place, despite the fact that the evaporation is 
exceedingly hot. 

A person awakes from sleep when digestion is completed: when 
the heat, which had been previously forced together in large 
quantity within a small compass from out the surrounding part, 
has once more prevailed, and when a separation has been 
effected between the more corporeal and the purer blood. The 
finest and purest blood is that contained in the head, while the 
thickest and most turbid is that in the lower parts. The source of 
all the blood is, as has been stated both here and elsewhere, the 
heart. Now of the chambers in the heart the central 
communicates with each of the two others. Each of the latter 
again acts as receiver from each, respectively, of the two vessels, 
called the 'great' and the 'aorta'. It is in the central chamber that 
the [above-mentioned] separation takes place. To go into these 
matters in detail would, however, be more properly the business 
of a different treatise from the present. Owing to the fact that 
the blood formed after the assimilation of food is especially in 
need of separation, sleep [then especially] occurs [and lasts] 
until the purest part of this blood has been separated off into 
the upper parts of the body, and the most turbid into the lower 
parts. When this has taken place animals awake from sleep, 
being released from the heaviness consequent on taking food. 
We have now stated the cause of sleeping, viz. that it consists in 
the recoil by the corporeal element, upborne by the connatural 
heat, in a mass upon the primary sense-organ; we have also 
stated what sleep is, having shown that it is a seizure of the 
primary sense-organ, rendering it unable to actualize its 
powers; arising of necessity (for it is impossible for an animal to 
exist if the conditions which render it an animal be not 
fulfilled), i.e. for the sake of its conservation; since remission of 
movement tends to the conservation of animals. 



1325 



On Dreams 
translated by J. I. Beare 



We must, in the next place, investigate the subject of the dream, 
and first inquire to which of the faculties of the soul it presents 
itself, i.e. whether the affection is one which pertains to the 
faculty of intelligence or to that of sense-perception; for these 
are the only faculties within us by which we acquire knowledge. 

If, then, the exercise of the faculty of sight is actual seeing, that 
of the auditory faculty, hearing, and, in general that of the 
faculty of sense-perception, perceiving; and if there are some 
perceptions common to the senses, such as figure, magnitude, 
motion, &c, while there are others, as colour, sound, taste, 
peculiar [each to its own sense]; and further, if all creatures, 
when the eyes are closed in sleep, are unable to see, and the 
analogous statement is true of the other senses, so that 
manifestly we perceive nothing when asleep; we may conclude 
that it is not by sense-perception we perceive a dream. 

But neither is it by opinion that we do so. For [in dreams] we not 
only assert, e.g. that some object approaching is a man or a 
horse [which would be an exercise of opinion], but that the 
object is white or beautiful, points on which opinion without 
sense-perception asserts nothing either truly or falsely. It is, 
however, a fact that the soul makes such assertions in sleep. We 
seem to see equally well that the approaching figure is a man, 



1326 



and that it is white. [In dreams], too, we think something else, 
over and above the dream presentation, just as we do in waking 
moments when we perceive something; for we often also 
reason about that which we perceive. So, too, in sleep we 
sometimes have thoughts other than the mere phantasms 
immediately before our minds. This would be manifest to any 
one who should attend and try, immediately on arising from 
sleep, to remember [his dreaming experience]. There are cases 
of persons who have seen such dreams, those, for example, who 
believe themselves to be mentally arranging a given list of 
subjects according to the mnemonic rule. They frequently find 
themselves engaged in something else besides the dream, viz. 
in setting a phantasm which they envisage into its mnemonic 
position. Hence it is plain that not every 'phantasm' in sleep is a 
mere dream-image, and that the further thinking which we 
perform then is due to an exercise of the faculty of opinion. 

So much at least is plain on all these points, viz. that the faculty 
by which, in waking hours, we are subject to illusion when 
affected by disease, is identical with that which produces 
illusory effects in sleep. So, even when persons are in excellent 
health, and know the facts of the case perfectly well, the sun, 
nevertheless, appears to them to be only a foot wide. Now, 
whether the presentative faculty of the soul be identical with, or 
different from, the faculty of sense-perception, in either case 
the illusion does not occur without our actually seeing or 
[otherwise] perceiving something. Even to see wrongly or to 
hear wrongly can happen only to one who sees or hears 
something real, though not exactly what he supposes. But we 
have assumed that in sleep one neither sees, nor hears, nor 
exercises any sense whatever. Perhaps we may regard it as true 
that the dreamer sees nothing, yet as false that his faculty of 
sense-perception is unaffected, the fact being that the sense of 
seeing and the other senses may possibly be then in a certain 
way affected, while each of these affections, as duly as when he 



1327 



is awake, gives its impulse in a certain manner to his [primary] 
faculty of sense, though not in precisely the same manner as 
when he is awake. Sometimes, too, opinion says [to dreamers] 
just as to those who are awake, that the object seen is an 
illusion; at other times it is inhibited, and becomes a mere 
follower of the phantasm. 

It is plain therefore that this affection, which we name 
'dreaming', is no mere exercise of opinion or intelligence, but 
yet is not an affection of the faculty of perception in the simple 
sense. If it were the latter it would be possible [when asleep] to 
hear and see in the simple sense. 

How then, and in what manner, it takes place, is what we have 
to examine. Let us assume, what is indeed clear enough, that 
the affection [of dreaming] pertains to sense-perception as 
surely as sleep itself does. For sleep does not pertain to one 
organ in animals and dreaming to another; both pertain to the 
same organ. 

But since we have, in our work On the Soul, treated of 
presentation, and the faculty of presentation is identical with 
that of sense-perception, though the essential notion of a 
faculty of presentation is different from that of a faculty of 
sense-perception; and since presentation is the movement set 
up by a sensory faculty when actually discharging its function, 
while a dream appears to be a presentation (for a presentation 
which occurs in sleep - whether simply or in some particular 
way - is what we call a dream): it manifestly follows that 
dreaming is an activity of the faculty of sense-perception, but 
belongs to this faculty qua presentative. 



1328 



We can best obtain a scientific view of the nature of the dream 
and the manner in which it originates by regarding it in the 
light of the circumstances attending sleep. The objects of sense- 
perception corresponding to each sensory organ produce sense- 
perception in us, and the affection due to their operation is 
present in the organs of sense not only when the perceptions 
are actualized, but even when they have departed. 

What happens in these cases may be compared with what 
happens in the case of projectiles moving in space. For in the 
case of these the movement continues even when that which 
set up the movement is no longer in contact [with the things 
that are moved]. For that which set them in motion moves a 
certain portion of air, and this, in turn, being moved excites 
motion in another portion; and so, accordingly, it is in this way 
that [the bodies], whether in air or in liquids, continue moving, 
until they come to a standstill. 

This we must likewise assume to happen in the case of 
qualitative change; for that part which [for example] has been 
heated by something hot, heats [in turn] the part next to it, and 
this propagates the affection continuously onwards until the 
process has come round to its oint of origination. This must also 
happen in the organ wherein the exercise of sense-perception 
takes place, since sense-perception, as realized in actual 
perceiving, is a mode of qualitative change. This explains why 
the affection continues in the sensory organs, both in their 
deeper and in their more superficial parts, not merely while 
they are actually engaged in perceiving, but even after they have 
ceased to do so. That they do this, indeed, is obvious in cases 
where we continue for some time engaged in a particular form 
of perception, for then, when we shift the scene of our 
perceptive activity, the previous affection remains; for instance, 



1329 



when we have turned our gaze from sunlight into darkness. For 
the result of this is that one sees nothing, owing to the excited 
by the light still subsisting in our eyes. Also, when we have 
looked steadily for a long while at one colour, e.g. at white or 
green, that to which we next transfer our gaze appears to be of 
the same colour. Again if, after having looked at the sun or 
some other brilliant object, we close the eyes, then, if we watch 
carefully, it appears in a right line with the direction of vision 
(whatever this may be), at first in its own colour; then it changes 
to crimson, next to purple, until it becomes black and 
disappears. And also when persons turn away from looking at 
objects in motion, e.g. rivers, and especially those which flow 
very rapidly, they find that the visual stimulations still present 
themselves, for the things really at rest are then seen moving: 
persons become very deaf after hearing loud noises, and after 
smelling very strong odours their power of smelling is impaired; 
and similarly in other cases. These phenomena manifestly take 
place in the way above described. 

That the sensory organs are acutely sensitive to even a slight 
qualitative difference [in their objects] is shown by what 
happens in the case of mirrors; a subject to which, even taking 
it independently, one might devote close consideration and 
inquiry. At the same time it becomes plain from them that as 
the eye [in seeing] is affected [by the object seen], so also it 
produces a certain effect upon it. If a woman chances during 
her menstrual period to look into a highly polished mirror, the 
surface of it will grow cloudy with a blood-coloured haze. It is 
very hard to remove this stain from a new mirror, but easier to 
remove from an older mirror. As we have said before, the cause 
of this lies in the fact that in the act of sight there occurs not 
only a passion in the sense organ acted on by the polished 
surface, but the organ, as an agent, also produces an action, as 
is proper to a brilliant object. For sight is the property of an 
organ possessing brilliance and colour. The eyes, therefore, have 



1330 



their proper action as have other parts of the body. Because it is 
natural to the eye to be filled with blood-vessels, a woman's 
eyes, during the period of menstrual flux and inflammation, will 
undergo a change, although her husband will not note this 
since his seed is of the same nature as that of his wife. The 
surrounding atmosphere, through which operates the action of 
sight, and which surrounds the mirror also, will undergo a 
change of the same sort that occurred shortly before in the 
woman's eyes, and hence the surface of the mirror is likewise 
affected. And as in the case of a garment, the cleaner it is the 
more quickly it is soiled, so the same holds true in the case of 
the mirror. For anything that is clean will show quite clearly a 
stain that it chances to receive, and the cleanest object shows 
up even the slightest stain. A bronze mirror, because of its 
shininess, is especially sensitive to any sort of contact (the 
movement of the surrounding air acts upon it like a rubbing or 
pressing or wiping); on that account, therefore, what is clean 
will show up clearly the slightest touch on its surface. It is hard 
to cleanse smudges off new mirrors because the stain 
penetrates deeply and is suffused to all parts; it penetrates 
deeply because the mirror is not a dense medium, and is 
suffused widely because of the smoothness of the object. On the 
other hand, in the case of old mirrors, stains do not remain 
because they do not penetrate deeply, but only smudge the 
surface. 

From this therefore it is plain that stimulatory motion is set up 
even by slight differences, and that sense-perception is quick to 
respond to it; and further that the organ which perceives colour 
is not only affected by its object, but also reacts upon it. Further 
evidence to the same point is afforded by what takes place in 
wines, and in the manufacture of unguents. For both oil, when 
prepared, and wine become rapidly infected by the odours of 
the things near them; they not only acquire the odours of the 
things thrown into or mixed with them, but also those of the 



1331 



things which are placed, or which grow, near the vessels 
containing them. 

In order to answer our original question, let us now, therefore, 
assume one proposition, which is clear from what precedes, viz. 
that even when the external object of perception has departed, 
the impressions it has made persist, and are themselves objects 
of perception: and [let us assume], besides, that we are easily 
deceived respecting the operations of sense-perception when 
we are excited by emotions, and different persons according to 
their different emotions; for example, the coward when excited 
by fear, the amorous person by amorous desire; so that, with but 
little resemblance to go upon, the former thinks he sees his foes 
approaching, the latter, that he sees the object of his desire; and 
the more deeply one is under the influence of the emotion, the 
less similarity is required to give rise to these illusory 
impressions. Thus too, both in fits of anger, and also in all states 
of appetite, all men become easily deceived, and more so the 
more their emotions are excited. This is the reason too why 
persons in the delirium of fever sometimes think they see 
animals on their chamber walls, an illusion arising from the 
faint resemblance to animals of the markings thereon when put 
together in patterns; and this sometimes corresponds with the 
emotional states of the sufferers, in such a way that, if the latter 
be not very ill, they know well enough that it is an illusion; but 
if the illness is more severe they actually move according to the 
appearances. The cause of these occurrences is that the faculty 
in virtue of which the controlling sense judges is not identical 
with that in virtue of which presentations come before the 
mind. A proof of this is, that the sun presents itself as only a 
foot in diameter, though often something else gainsays the 
presentation. Again, when the fingers are crossed, the one 
object [placed between them] is felt [by the touch] as two; but 
yet we deny that it is two; for sight is more authoritative than 
touch. Yet, if touch stood alone, we should actually have 



1332 



pronounced the one object to be two. The ground of such false 
judgements is that any appearances whatever present 
themselves, not only when its object stimulates a sense, but 
also when the sense by itself alone is stimulated, provided only 
it be stimulated in the same manner as it is by the object. For 
example, to persons sailing past the land seems to move, when 
it is really the eye that is being moved by something else [the 
moving ship.] 



From this it is manifest that the stimulatory movements based 
upon sensory impressions, whether the latter are derived from 
external objects or from causes within the body, present 
themselves not only when persons are awake, but also then, 
when this affection which is called sleep has come upon them, 
with even greater impressiveness. For by day, while the senses 
and the intellect are working together, they (i.e. such 
movements) are extruded from consciousness or obscured, just 
as a smaller is beside a larger fire, or as small beside great pains 
or pleasures, though, as soon as the latter have ceased, even 
those which are trifling emerge into notice. But by night [i.e. in 
sleep] owing to the inaction of the particular senses, and their 
powerlessness to realize themselves, which arises from the 
reflux of the hot from the exterior parts to the interior, they [i.e. 
the above 'movements'] are borne in to the head quarters of 
sense-perception, and there display themselves as the 
disturbance (of waking life) subsides. We must suppose that, 
like the little eddies which are being ever formed in rivers, so 
the sensory movements are each a continuous process, often 
remaining like what they were when first started, but often, too, 
broken into other forms by collisions with obstacles. This [last 



1333 



mentioned point], moreover, gives the reason why no dreams 
occur in sleep immediately after meals, or to sleepers who are 
extremely young, e.g. to infants. The internal movement in such 
cases is excessive, owing to the heat generated from the food. 
Hence, just as in a liquid, if one vehemently disturbs it, 
sometimes no reflected image appears, while at other times one 
appears, indeed, but utterly distorted, so as to seem quite unlike 
its original; while, when once the motion has ceased, the 
reflected images are clear and plain; in the same manner during 
sleep the phantasms, or residuary movements, which are based 
upon the sensory impressions, become sometimes quite 
obliterated by the above described motion when too violent; 
while at other times the sights are indeed seen, but confused 
and weird, and the dreams [which then appear] are unhealthy, 
like those of persons who are atrabilious, or feverish, or 
intoxicated with wine. For all such affections, being spirituous, 
cause much commotion and disturbance. In sanguineous 
animals, in proportion as the blood becomes calm, and as its 
purer are separated from its less pure elements, the fact that 
the movement, based on impressions derived from each of the 
organs of sense, is preserved in its integrity, renders the dreams 
healthy, causes a [clear] image to present itself, and makes the 
dreamer think, owing to the effects borne in from the organ of 
sight, that he actually sees, and owing to those which come 
from the organ of hearing, that he really hears; and so on with 
those also which proceed from the other sensory organs. For it 
is owing to the fact that the movement which reaches the 
primary organ of sense comes from them, that one even when 
awake believes himself to see, or hear, or otherwise perceive; 
just as it is from a belief that the organ of sight is being 
stimulated, though in reality not so stimulated, that we 
sometimes erroneously declare ourselves to see, or that, from 
the fact that touch announces two movements, we think that 
the one object is two. For, as a rule, the governing sense affirms 



1334 



the report of each particular sense, unless another particular 
sense, more authoritative, makes a contradictory report. In 
every case an appearance presents itself, but what appears does 
not in every case seem real, unless when the deciding faculty is 
inhibited, or does not move with its proper motion. Moreover, as 
we said that different men are subject to illusions, each 
according to the different emotion present in him, so it is that 
the sleeper, owing to sleep, and to the movements then going 
on in his sensory organs, as well as to the other facts of the 
sensory process, [is liable to illusion], so that the dream 
presentation, though but little like it, appears as some actual 
given thing. For when one is asleep, in proportion as most of the 
blood sinks inwards to its fountain [the heart], the internal 
[sensory] movements, some potential, others actual accompany 
it inwards. They are so related [in general] that, if anything 
move the blood, some one sensory movement will emerge from 
it, while if this perishes another will take its place; while to one 
another also they are related in the same way as the artificial 
frogs in water which severally rise [in fixed succesion] to the 
surface in the order in which the salt [which keeps them down] 
becomes dissolved. The residuary movements are like these: 
they are within the soul potentially, but actualize themselves 
only when the impediment to their doing so has been relaxed; 
and according as they are thus set free, they begin to move in 
the blood which remains in the sensory organs, and which is 
now but scanty, while they possess verisimilitude after the 
manner of cloud-shapes, which in their rapid metamorphoses 
one compares now to human beings and a moment afterwards 
to centaurs. Each of them is however, as has been said, the 
remnant of a sensory impression taken when sense was 
actualizing itself; and when this, the true impression, has 
departed, its remnant is still immanent, and it is correct to say 
of it, that though not actually Koriskos, it is like Koriskos. For 
when the person was actually perceiving, his controlling and 



1335 



judging sensory faculty did not call it Koriskos, but, prompted 
by this [impression], called the genuine person yonder Koriskos. 
Accordingly, this sensory impulse, which, when actually 
perceiving, it [the controlling faculty] describes (unless 
completely inhibited by the blood), it now [in dreams] when 
quasi-perceiving, receives from the movements persisting in the 
sense-organs, and mistakes it - an impulse that is merely like 
the true [objective] impression - for the true impression itself, 
while the effect of sleep is so great that it causes this mistake to 
pass unnoticed. Accordingly, just as if a finger be inserted 
beneath the eyeball without being observed, one object will not 
only present two visual images, but will create an opinion of its 
being two objects; while if it [the finger] be observed, the 
presentation will be the same, but the same opinion will not be 
formed of it; exactly so it is in states of sleep: if the sleeper 
perceives that he is asleep, and is conscious of the sleeping 
state during which the perception comes before his mind, it 
presents itself still, but something within him speaks to this 
effect: 'the image of Koriskos presents itself, but the real 
Koriskos is not present'; for often, when one is asleep, there is 
something in consciousness which declares that what then 
presents itself is but a dream. If, however, he is not aware of 
being asleep, there is nothing which will contradict the 
testimony of the bare presentation. 

That what we here urge is true, i.e. that there are such 
presentative movements in the sensory organs, any one may 
convince himself, if he attends to and tries to remember the 
affections we experience when sinking into slumber or when 
being awakened. He will sometimes, in the moment of 
awakening, surprise the images which present themselves to 
him in sleep, and find that they are really but movements 
lurking in the organs of sense. And indeed some very young 
persons, if it is dark, though looking with wide open eyes, see 



1336 



multitudes of phantom figures moving before them, so that 
they often cover up their heads in terror. 

From all this, then, the conclusion to be drawn is, that the 
dream is a sort of presentation, and, more particularly, one 
which occurs in sleep; since the phantoms just mentioned are 
not dreams, nor is any other a dream which presents itself 
when the sense-perceptions are in a state of freedom. Nor is 
every presentation which occurs in sleep necessarily a dream. 
For in the first place, some persons [when asleep] actually, in a 
certain way, perceive sounds, light, savour, and contact; feebly, 
however, and, as it were, remotely. For there have been cases in 
which persons while asleep, but with the eyes partly open, saw 
faintly in their sleep (as they supposed) the light of a lamp, and 
afterwards, on being awakened, straightway recognized it as the 
actual light of a real lamp; while, in other cases, persons who 
faintly heard the crowing of cocks or the barking of dogs 
identified these clearly with the real sounds as soon as they 
awoke. Some persons, too, return answers to questions put to 
them in sleep. For it is quite possible that, of waking or sleeping, 
while the one is present in the ordinary sense, the other also 
should be present in a certain way. But none of these 
occurrences should be called a dream. Nor should the true 
thoughts, as distinct from the mere presentations, which occur 
in sleep [be called dreams]. The dream proper is a presentation 
based on the movement of sense impressions, when such 
presentation occurs during sleep, taking sleep in the strict sense 
of the term. 

There are cases of persons who in their whole lives have never 
had a dream, while others dream when considerably advanced 
in years, having never dreamed before. The cause of their not 
having dreams appears somewhat like that which operates in 
the case of infants, and [that which operates] immediately after 
meals. It is intelligible enough that no dream-presentation 



1337 



should occur to persons whose natural constitution is such that 
in them copious evaporation is borne upwards, which, when 
borne back downwards, causes a large quantity of motion. But it 
is not surprising that, as age advances, a dream should at length 
appear to them. Indeed, it is inevitable that, as a change is 
wrought in them in proportion to age or emotional experience, 
this reversal [from non-dreaming to dreaming] should occur 
also. 



On Prophesying by Dreams 
translated by J. I. Beare 



As to the divination which takes place in sleep, and is said to be 
based on dreams, we cannot lightly either dismiss it with 
contempt or give it implicit confidence. The fact that all 
persons, or many, suppose dreams to possess a special 
significance, tends to inspire us with belief in it [such 
divination], as founded on the testimony of experience; and 
indeed that divination in dreams should, as regards some 
subjects, be genuine, is not incredible, for it has a show of 
reason; from which one might form a like opinion also 
respecting all other dreams. Yet the fact of our seeing no 
probable cause to account for such divination tends to inspire 
us with distrust. For, in addition to its further unreasonableness, 
it is absurd to combine the idea that the sender of such dreams 



1338 



should be God with the fact that those to whom he sends them 
are not the best and wisest, but merely commonplace persons. 
If, however, we abstract from the causality of God, none of the 
other causes assigned appears probable. For that certain 
persons should have foresight in dreams concerning things 
destined to take place at the Pillars of Hercules, or on the banks 
of the Borysthenes, seems to be something to discover the 
explanation of which surpasses the wit of man. Well then, the 
dreams in question must be regarded either as causes, or as 
tokens, of the events, or else as coincidences; either as all, or 
some, of these, or as one only. I use the word 'cause' in the 
sense in which the moon is [the cause] of an eclipse of the sun, 
or in which fatigue is [a cause] of fever; 'token' [in the sense in 
which] the entrance of a star [into the shadow] is a token of the 
eclipse, or [in which] roughness of the tongue [is a token] of 
fever; while by 'coincidence' I mean, for example, the 
occurrence of an eclipse of the sun while some one is taking a 
walk; for the walking is neither a token nor a cause of the 
eclipse, nor the eclipse [a cause or token] of the walking. For this 
reason no coincidence takes place according to a universal or 
general rule. Are we then to say that some dreams are causes, 
others tokens, e.g. of events taking place in the bodily 
organism? At all events, even scientific physicians tell us that 
one should pay diligent attention to dreams, and to hold this 
view is reasonable also for those who are not practitioners, but 
speculative philosophers. For the movements which occur in 
the daytime [within the body] are, unless very great and violent, 
lost sight of in contrast with the waking movements, which are 
more impressive. In sleep the opposite takes place, for then 
even trifling movements seem considerable. This is plain in 
what often happens during sleep; for example, dreamers fancy 
that they are affected by thunder and lightning, when in fact 
there are only faint ringings in their ears; or that they are 
enjoying honey or other sweet savours, when only a tiny drop of 



1339 



phlegm is flowing down [the oesophagus]; or that they are 
walking through fire, and feeling intense heat, when there is 
only a slight warmth affecting certain parts of the body. When 
they are awakened, these things appear to them in this their 
true character. But since the beginnings of all events are small, 
so, it is clear, are those also of the diseases or other affections 
about to occur in our bodies. In conclusion, it is manifest that 
these beginnings must be more evident in sleeping than in 
waking moments. 

Nay, indeed, it is not improbable that some of the presentations 
which come before the mind in sleep may even be causes of the 
actions cognate to each of them. For as when we are about to 
act [in waking hours], or are engaged in any course of action, or 
have already performed certain actions, we often find ourselves 
concerned with these actions, or performing them, in a vivid 
dream; the cause whereof is that the dream-movement has had 
a way paved for it from the original movements set up in the 
daytime; exactly so, but conversely, it must happen that the 
movements set up first in sleep should also prove to be starting- 
points of actions to be performed in the daytime, since the 
recurrence by day of the thought of these actions also has had 
its way paved for it in the images before the mind at night. Thus 
then it is quite conceivable that some dreams may be tokens 
and causes [of future events]. 

Most [so-called prophetic] dreams are, however, to be classed as 
mere coincidences, especially all such as are extravagant, and 
those in the fulfilment of which the dreamers have no initiative, 
such as in the case of a sea-fight, or of things taking place far 
away. As regards these it is natural that the fact should stand as 
it does whenever a person, on mentioning something, finds the 
very thing mentioned come to pass. Why, indeed, should this 
not happen also in sleep? The probability is, rather, that many 
such things should happen. As, then, one's mentioning a 



1340 



particular person is neither token nor cause of this person's 
presenting himself, so, in the parallel instance, the dream is, to 
him who has seen it, neither token nor cause of its [so-called] 
fulfilment, but a mere coincidence. Hence the fact that many 
dreams have no 'fulfilment', for coincidence do not occur 
according to any universal or general law. 



On the whole, forasmuch as certain of the lower animals also 
dream, it may be concluded that dreams are not sent by God, 
nor are they designed for this purpose [to reveal the future]. 
They have a divine aspect, however, for Nature [their cause] is 
divinely planned, though not itself divine. A special proof [of 
their not being sent by God] is this: the power of foreseeing the 
future and of having vivid dreams is found in persons of inferior 
type, which implies that God does not send their dreams; but 
merely that all those whose physical temperament is, as it were, 
garrulous and excitable, see sights of all descriptions; for, 
inasmuch as they experience many movements of every kind, 
they just chance to have visions resembling objective facts, their 
luck in these matters being merely like that of persons who play 
at even and odd. For the principle which is expressed in the 
gambler's maxim: 'If you make many throws your luck must 
change,' holds in their case also. 

That many dreams have no fulfilment is not strange, for it is so 
too with many bodily toms and weather-signs, e.g. those of train 
or wind. For if another movement occurs more influential than 
that from which, while [the event to which it pointed was] still 
future, the given token was derived, the event [to which such 
token pointed] does not take place. So, of the things which 



1341 



ought to be accomplished by human agency, many, though well- 
planned are by the operation of other principles more powerful 
[than man's agency] brought to nought. For, speaking generally, 
that which was about to happen is not in every case what now 
is happening, nor is that which shall hereafter he identical with 
that which is now going to be. Still, however, we must hold that 
the beginnings from which, as we said, no consummation 
follows, are real beginnings, and these constitute natural tokens 
of certain events, even though the events do not come to pass. 

As for [prophetic] dreams which involve not such beginnings 
[sc. of future events] as we have here described, but such as are 
extravagant in times, or places, or magnitudes; or those 
involving beginnings which are not extravagant in any of these 
respects, while yet the persons who see the dream hold not in 
their own hands the beginnings [of the event to which it points]: 
unless the foresight which such dreams give is the result of 
pure coincidence, the following would be a better explanation of 
it than that proposed by Democritus, who alleges 'images' and 
'emanations' as its cause. As, when something has caused 
motion in water or air, this [the portion of water or air], and, 
though the cause has ceased to operate, such motion 
propagates itself to a certain point, though there the prime 
movement is not present; just so it may well be that a 
movement and a consequent sense-perception should reach 
sleeping souls from the objects from which Democritus 
represents 'images' and 'emanations' coming; that such 
movements, in whatever way they arrive, should be more 
perceptible at night [than by day], because when proceeding 
thus in the daytime they are more liable to dissolution (since at 
night the air is less disturbed, there being then less wind); and 
that they shall be perceived within the body owing to sleep, 
since persons are more sensitive even to slight sensory 
movements when asleep than when awake. It is these 
movements then that cause 'presentations', as a result of which 



1342 



sleepers foresee the future even relatively to such events as 
those referred to above. These considerations also explain why 
this experience befalls commonplace persons and not the most 
intelligent. For it would have regularly occurred both in the 
daytime and to the wise had it been God who sent it; but, as we 
have explained the matter, it is quite natural that commonplace 
persons should be those who have foresight [in dreams]. For the 
mind of such persons is not given to thinking, but, as it were, 
derelict, or totally vacant, and, when once set moving, is borne 
passively on in the direction taken by that which moves it. With 
regard to the fact that some persons who are liable to 
derangement have this foresight, its explanation is that their 
normal mental movements do not impede [the alien 
movements], but are beaten off by the latter. Therefore it is that 
they have an especially keen perception of the alien 
movements. 

That certain persons in particular should have vivid dreams, e.g. 
that familiar friends should thus have foresight in a special 
degree respecting one another, is due to the fact that such 
friends are most solicitous on one another's behalf. For as 
acquaintances in particular recognize and perceive one another 
a long way off, so also they do as regards the sensory 
movements respecting one another; for sensory movements 
which refer to persons familiarly known are themselves more 
familiar. Atrabilious persons, owing to their impetuosity, are, 
when they, as it were, shoot from a distance, expert at hitting; 
while, owing to their mutability, the series of movements 
deploys quickly before their minds. For even as the insane 
recite, or con over in thought, the poems of Philaegides, e.g. the 
Aphrodite, whose parts succeed in order of similitude, just so do 
they [the 'atrabilious'] go on and on stringing sensory 
movements together. Moreover, owing to their aforesaid 
impetuosity, one movement within them is not liable to be 
knocked out of its course by some other movement. 



1343 



The most skilful interpreter of dreams is he who has the faculty 
of observing resemblances. Any one may interpret dreams 
which are vivid and plain. But, speaking of 'resemblances', I 
mean that dream presentations are analogous to the forms 
reflected in water, as indeed we have already stated. In the 
latter case, if the motion in the water be great, the reflexion has 
no resemblance to its original, nor do the forms resemble the 
real objects. Skilful, indeed, would he be in interpreting such 
reflexions who could rapidly discern, and at a glance 
comprehend, the scattered and distorted fragments of such 
forms, so as to perceive that one of them represents a man, or a 
horse, Or anything whatever. Accordingly, in the other case also, 
in a similar way, some such thing as this [blurred image] is all 
that a dream amounts to; for the internal movement effaces the 
clearness of the dream. 

The questions, therefore, which we proposed as to the nature of 
sleep and the dream, and the cause to which each of them is 
due, and also as to divination as a result of dreams, in every 
form of it, have now been discussed. 



1344 



On Longevity and Shortness of Life 
translated by G. R. T. Ross 



The reasons for some animals being long-lived and others 
short-lived, and, in a word, causes of the length and brevity of 
life call for investigation. 

The necessary beginning to our inquiry is a statement of the 
difficulties about these points. For it is not clear whether in 
animals and plants universally it is a single or diverse cause 
that makes some to be long-lived, others short-lived. Plants too 
have in some cases a long life, while in others it lasts but for a 
year. 

Further, in a natural structure are longevity and a sound 
constitution coincident, or is shortness of life independent of 
unhealthiness? Perhaps in the case of certain maladies a 
diseased state of the body and shortness of life are 
interchangeable, while in the case of others ill-health is 
perfectly compatible with long life. 

Of sleep and waking we have already treated; about life and 
death we shall speak later on, and likewise about health and 
disease, in so far as it belongs to the science of nature to do so. 
But at present we have to investigate the causes of some 
creatures being long-lived, and others short-lived. We find this 
distinction affecting not only entire genera opposed as wholes 
to one another, but applying also to contrasted sets of 
individuals within the same species. As an instance of the 
difference applying to the genus I give man and horse (for 



1345 



mankind has a longer life than the horse), while within the 
species there is the difference between man and man; for of 
men also some are long-lived, others short-lived, differing from 
each other in respect of the different regions in which they 
dwell. Races inhabiting warm countries have longer life, those 
living in a cold climate live a shorter time. Likewise there are 
similar differences among individuals occupying the same 
locality. 



In order to find premisses for our argument, we must answer 
the question, What is that which, in natural objects, makes 
them easily destroyed, or the reverse? Since fire and water, and 
whatsoever is akin thereto, do not possess identical powers they 
are reciprocal causes of generation and decay. Hence it is 
natural to infer that everything else arising from them and 
composed of them should share in the same nature, in all cases 
where things are not, like a house, a composite unity formed by 
the synthesis of many things. 

In other matters a different account must be given; for in many 
things their mode of dissolution is something peculiar to 
themselves, e.g. in knowledge and health and disease. These 
pass away even though the medium in which they are found is 
not destroyed but continues to exist; for example, take the 
termination of ignorance, which is recollection or learning, 
while knowledge passes away into forgetfulness, or error. But 
accidentally the disintegration of a natural object is 
accompanied by the destruction of the non-physical reality; for, 
when the animal dies, the health or knowledge resident in it 
passes away too. Hence from these considerations we may draw 



1346 



a conclusion about the soul too; for, if the inherence of soul in 
body is not a matter of nature but like that of knowledge in the 
soul, there would be another mode of dissolution pertaining to 
it besides that which occurs when the body is destroyed. But 
since evidently it does not admit of this dual dissolution, the 
soul must stand in a different case in respect of its union with 
the body. 



Perhaps one might reasonably raise the question whether there 
is any place where what is corruptible becomes incorruptible, as 
fire does in the upper regions where it meets with no opposite. 
Opposites destroy each other, and hence accidentally, by their 
destruction, whatsoever is attributed to them is destroyed. But 
no opposite in a real substance is accidentally destroyed, 
because real substance is not predicated of any subject. Hence a 
thing which has no opposite, or which is situated where it has 
no opposite, cannot be destroyed. For what will that be which 
can destroy it, if destruction comes only through contraries, but 
no contrary to it exists either absolutely or in the particular 
place where it is? But perhaps this is in one sense true, in 
another sense not true, for it is impossible that anything 
containing matter should not have in any sense an opposite. 
Heat and straightness can be present in every part of a thing, 
but it is impossible that the thing should be nothing but hot or 
white or straight; for, if that were so, attributes would have an 
independent existence. Hence if, in all cases, whenever the 
active and the passive exist together, the one acts and the other 
is acted on, it is impossible that no change should occur. 
Further, this is so if a waste product is an opposite, and waste 
must always be produced; for opposition is always the source of 



1347 



change, and refuse is what remains of the previous opposite. 
But, after expelling everything of a nature actually opposed, 
would an object in this case also be imperishable? No, it would 
be destroyed by the environment. 

If then that is so, what we have said sufficiently accounts for 
the change; but, if not, we must assume that something of 
actually opposite character is in the changing object, and refuse 
is produced. 

Hence accidentally a lesser flame is consumed by a greater one, 
for the nutriment, to wit the smoke, which the former takes a 
long period to expend, is used up by the big flame quickly. 

Hence [too] all things are at all times in a state of transition and 
are coming into being and passing away. The environment acts 
on them either favourably or antagonistically, and, owing to 
this, things that change their situation become more or less 
enduring than their nature warrants, but never are they eternal 
when they contain contrary qualities; for their matter is an 
immediate source of contrariety, so that if it involves locality 
they show change of situation, if quantity, increase and 
diminution, while if it involves qualitative affection we find 
alteration of character. 



We find that a superior immunity from decay attaches neither 
to the largest animals (the horse has shorter life than man) nor 
to those that are small (for most insects live but for a year). Nor 
are plants as a whole less liable to perish than animals (many 
plants are annuals), nor have sanguineous animals the pre- 
eminence (for the bee is longer-lived than certain sanguineous 



1348 



animals). Neither is it the bloodless animals that live longest 
(for molluscs live only a year, though bloodless), nor terrestrial 
organisms (there are both plants and terrestrial animals of 
which a single year is the period), nor the occupants of the sea 
(for there we find the crustaceans and the molluscs, which are 
short-lived). 

Speaking generally, the longest-lived things occur among the 
plants, e.g. the date-palm. Next in order we find them among 
the sanguineous animals rather than among the bloodless, and 
among those with feet rather than among the denizens of the 
water. Hence, taking these two characters together, the longest- 
lived animals fall among sanguineous animals which have feet, 
e.g. man and elephant. As a matter of fact also it is a general 
rule that the larger live longer than the smaller, for the other 
long-lived animals too happen to be of a large size, as are also 
those I have mentioned. 



The following considerations may enable us to understand the 
reasons for all these facts. We must remember that an animal is 
by nature humid and warm, and to live is to be of such a 
constitution, while old age is dry and cold, and so is a corpse. 
This is plain to observation. But the material constituting the 
bodies of all things consists of the following - the hot and the 
cold, the dry and the moist. Hence when they age they must 
become dry, and therefore the fluid in them requires to be not 
easily dried up. Thus we explain why fat things are not liable to 
decay. The reason is that they contain air; now air relatively to 
the other elements is fire, and fire never becomes corrupted. 



1349 



Again the humid element in animals must not be small in 
quantity, for a small quantity is easily dried up. This is why both 
plants and animals that are large are, as a general rule, longer- 
lived than the rest, as was said before; it is to be expected that 
the larger should contain more moisture. But it is not merely 
this that makes them longer lived; for the cause is twofold, to 
wit, the quality as well as the quantity of the fluid. Hence the 
moisture must be not only great in amount but also warm, in 
order to be neither easily congealed nor easily dried up. 

It is for this reason also that man lives longer than some 
animals which are larger; for animals live longer though there is 
a deficiency in the amount of their moisture, if the ratio of its 
qualitative superiority exceeds that of its quantitative 
deficiency. 

In some creatures the warm element is their fatty substance, 
which prevents at once desiccation and congelation; but in 
others it assumes a different flavour. Further, that which is 
designed to be not easily destroyed should not yield waste 
products. Anything of such a nature causes death either by 
disease or naturally, for the potency of the waste product works 
adversely and destroys now the entire constitution, now a 
particular member. 

This is why salacious animals and those abounding in seed age 
quickly; the seed is a residue, and further, by being lost, it 
produces dryness. Hence the mule lives longer than either the 
horse or the ass from which it sprang, and females live longer 
than males if the males are salacious. Accordingly cock- 
sparrows have a shorter life than the females. Again males 
subject to great toil are short-lived and age more quickly owing 
to the labour; toil produces dryness and old age is dry. But by 
natural constitution and as a general rule males live longer than 



1350 



females, and the reason is that the male is an animal with more 
warmth than the female. 

The same kind of animals are longer-lived in warm than in cold 
climates for the same reason, on account of which they are of 
larger size. The size of animals of cold constitution illustrates 
this particularly well, and hence snakes and lizards and scaly 
reptiles are of great size in warm localities, as also are testacea 
in the Red Sea: the warm humidity there is the cause equally of 
their augmented size and of their life. But in cold countries the 
humidity in animals is more of a watery nature, and hence is 
readily congealed. Consequently it happens that animals with 
little or no blood are in northerly regions either entirely absent 
(both the land animals with feet and the water creatures whose 
home is the sea) or, when they do occur, they are smaller and 
have shorter life; for the frost prevents growth. 

Both plants and animals perish if not fed, for in that case they 
consume themselves; just as a large flame consumes and burns 
up a small one by using up its nutriment, so the natural warmth 
which is the primary cause of digestion consumes the material 
in which it is located. 

Water animals have a shorter life than terrestrial creatures, not 
strictly because they are humid, but because they are watery, 
and watery moisture is easily destroyed, since it is cold and 
readily congealed. For the same reason bloodless animals perish 
readily unless protected by great size, for there is neither 
fatness nor sweetness about them. In animals fat is sweet, and 
hence bees are longer-lived than other animals of larger size. 



1351 



It is amongst the plants that we find the longest life - more 
than among the animals, for, in the first place, they are less 
watery and hence less easily frozen. Further they have an 
oiliness and a viscosity which makes them retain their moisture 
in a form not easily dried up, even though they are dry and 
earthy. 

But we must discover the reason why trees are of an enduring 
constitution, for it is peculiar to them and is not found in any 
animals except the insects. 

Plants continually renew themselves and hence last for a long 
time. New shoots continually come and the others grow old, 
and with the roots the same thing happens. But both processes 
do not occur together. Rather it happens that at one time the 
trunk and the branches alone die and new ones grow up beside 
them, and it is only when this has taken place that the fresh 
roots spring from the surviving part. Thus it continues, one part 
dying and the other growing, and hence also it lives a long time. 

There is a similarity, as has been already said, between plants 
and insects, for they live, though divided, and two or more may 
be derived from a single one. Insects, however, though 
managing to live, are not able to do so long, for they do not 
possess organs; nor can the principle resident in each of the 
separated parts create organs. In the case of a plant, however, it 
can do so; every part of a plant contains potentially both root 
and stem. Hence it is from this source that issues that 
continued growth when one part is renewed and the other 
grows old; it is practically a case of longevity. The taking of slips 
furnishes a similar instance, for we might say that, in a way, 
when we take a slip the same thing happens; the shoot cut off 
is part of the plant. Thus in taking slips this perpetuation of life 
occurs though their connexion with the plant is severed, but in 



1352 



the former case it is the continuity that is operative. The reason 
is that the life principle potentially belonging to them is present 
in every part. 

Identical phenomena are found both in plants and in animals. 
For in animals the males are, in general, the longer-lived. They 
have their upper parts larger than the lower (the male is more 
of the dwarf type of build than the female), and it is in the 
upper part that warmth resides, in the lower cold. In plants also 
those with great heads are longer-lived, and such are those that 
are not annual but of the tree-type, for the roots are the head 
and upper part of a plant, and among the annuals growth 
occurs in the direction of their lower parts and the fruit. 

These matters however will be specially investigated in the 
work On Plants. But this is our account of the reasons for the 
duration of life and for short life in animals. It remains for us to 
discuss youth and age, and life and death. To come to a definite 
understanding about these matters would complete our course 
of study on animals. 



1353 



On Youth and Old Age, On Breathing, On Life and Death 
translated by G. R. T. Ross 



We must now treat of youth and old age and life and death. We 
must probably also at the same time state the causes of 
respiration as well, since in some cases living and the reverse 
depend on this. 

We have elsewhere given a precise account of the soul, and 
while it is clear that its essential reality cannot be corporeal, yet 
manifestly it must exist in some bodily part which must be one 
of those possessing control over the members. Let us for the 
present set aside the other divisions or faculties of the soul 
(whichever of the two be the correct name). But as to being 
what is called an animal and a living thing, we find that in all 
beings endowed with both characteristics (viz. being an animal 
and being alive) there must be a single identical part in virtue of 
which they live and are called animals; for an animal qua 
animal cannot avoid being alive. But a thing need not, though 
alive, be animal, for plants live without having sensation, and it 
is by sensation that we distinguish animal from what is not 
animal. 

This organ, then, must be numerically one and the same and 
yet possess multiple and disparate aspects, for being animal 
and living are not identical. Since then the organs of special 
sensation have one common organ in which the senses when 
functioning must meet, and this must be situated midway 
between what is called before and behind (we call 'before' the 
direction from which sensation comes, 'behind' the opposite), 



1354 



further, since in all living things the body is divided into upper 
and lower (they all have upper and lower parts, so that this is 
true of plants as well), clearly the nutritive principle must be 
situated midway between these regions. That part where food 
enters we call upper, considering it by itself and not relatively to 
the surrounding universe, while downward is that part by which 
the primary excrement is discharged. 

Plants are the reverse of animals in this respect. To man in 
particular among the animals, on account of his erect stature, 
belongs the characteristic of having his upper parts pointing 
upwards in the sense in which that applies to the universe, 
while in the others these are in an intermediate position. But in 
plants, owing to their being stationary and drawing their 
sustenance from the ground, the upper part must always be 
down; for there is a correspondence between the roots in a 
plant and what is called the mouth in animals, by means of 
which they take in their food, whether the source of supply be 
the earth or each other's bodies. 



All perfectly formed animals are to be divided into three parts, 
one that by which food is taken in, one that by which excrement 
is discharged, and the third the region intermediate between 
them. In the largest animals this latter is called the chest and in 
the others something corresponding; in some also it is more 
distinctly marked off than in others. All those also that are 
capable of progression have additional members subservient to 
this purpose, by means of which they bear the whole trunk, to 
wit legs and feet and whatever parts are possessed of the same 
powers. Now it is evident both by observation and by inference 



1355 



that the source of the nutritive soul is in the midst of the three 
parts. For many animals, when either part - the head or the 
receptacle of the food - is cut off, retain life in that member to 
which the middle remains attached. This can be seen to occur 
in many insects, e.g. wasps and bees, and many animals also 
besides insects can, though divided, continue to live by means 
of the part connected with nutrition. 

While this member is indeed in actuality single, yet potentially 
it is multiple, for these animals have a constitution similar to 
that of Plants; plants when cut into sections continue to live, 
and a number of trees can be derived from one single source. A 
separate account will be given of the reason why some plants 
cannot live when divided, while others can be propagated by 
the taking of slips. In this respect, however, plants and insects 
are alike. 

It is true that the nutritive soul, in beings possessing it, while 
actually single must be potentially plural. And it is too with the 
principle of sensation, for evidently the divided segments of 
these animals have sensation. They are unable, however, to 
preserve their constitution, as plants can, not possessing the 
organs on which the continuance of life depends, for some lack 
the means for seizing, others for receiving their food; or again 
they may be destitute of other organs as well. 

Divisible animals are like a number of animals grown together, 
but animals of superior construction behave differently because 
their constitution is a unity of the highest possible kind. Hence 
some of the organs on division display slight sensitiveness 
because they retain some psychical susceptibility; the animals 
continue to move after the vitals have been abstracted: 
tortoises, for example, do so even after the heart has been 
removed. 



1356 



The same phenomenon is evident both in plants and in 
animals, and in plants we note it both in their propagation by 
seed and in grafts and cuttings. Genesis from seeds always 
starts from the middle. All seeds are bivalvular, and the place of 
junction is situated at the point of attachment (to the plant), an 
intermediate part belonging to both halves. It is from this part 
that both root and stem of growing things emerge; the starting- 
point is in a central position between them. In the case of grafts 
and cuttings this is particularly true of the buds; for the bud is 
in a way the starting-point of the branch, but at the same time 
it is in a central position. Hence it is either this that is cut off, or 
into this that the new shoot is inserted, when we wish either a 
new branch or a new root to spring from it; which proves that 
the point of origin in growth is intermediate between stem and 
root. 

Likewise in sanguineous animals the heart is the first organ 
developed; this is evident from what has been observed in those 
cases where observation of their growth is possible. Hence in 
bloodless animals also what corresponds to the heart must 
develop first. We have already asserted in our treatise on The 
Parts of Animals that it is from the heart that the veins issue, 
and that in sanguineous animals the blood is the final 
nutriment from which the members are formed. Hence it is 
clear that there is one function in nutrition which the mouth 
has the faculty of performing, and a different one appertaining 
to the stomach. But it is the heart that has supreme control, 
exercising an additional and completing function. Hence in 
sanguineous animals the source both of the sensitive and of the 
nutritive soul must be in the heart, for the functions relative to 
nutrition exercised by the other parts are ancillary to the 



1357 



activity of the heart. It is the part of the dominating organ to 
achieve the final result, as of the physician's efforts to be 
directed towards health, and not to be occupied with 
subordinate offices. 

Certainly, however, all saguineous animals have the supreme 
organ of the sensefaculties in the heart, for it is here that we 
must look for the common sensorium belonging to all the 
sense-organs. These in two cases, taste and touch, can be 
clearly seen to extend to the heart, and hence the others also 
must lead to it, for in it the other organs may possibly initiate 
changes, whereas with the upper region of the body taste and 
touch have no connexion. Apart from these considerations, if 
the life is always located in this part, evidently the principle of 
sensation must be situated there too, for it is qua animal that 
an animal is said to be a living thing, and it is called animal 
because endowed with sensation. Elsewhere in other works we 
have stated the reasons why some of the sense-organs are, as is 
evident, connected with the heart, while others are situated in 
the head. (It is this fact that causes some people to think that it 
is in virtue of the brain that the function of perception belongs 
to animals.) 



Thus if, on the one hand, we look to the observed facts, what we 
have said makes it clear that the source of the sensitive soul, 
together with that connected with growth and nutrition, is 
situated in this organ and in the central one of the three 
divisions of the body. But it follows by deduction also; for we see 
that in every case, when several results are open to her, Nature 
always brings to pass the best. Now if both principles are 



1358 



located in the midst of the substance, the two parts of the body, 
viz. that which elaborates and that which receives the 
nutriment in its final form will best perform their appropriate 
function; for the soul will then be close to each, and the central 
situation which it will, as such, occupy is the position of a 
dominating power. 

Further, that which employs an instrument and the instrument 
it employs must be distinct (and must be spatially diverse too, if 
possible, as in capacity), just as the flute and that which plays it 
- the hand - are diverse. Thus if animal is defined by the 
possession of sensitive soul, this soul must in the sanguineous 
animals be in the heart, and, in the bloodless ones, in the 
corresponding part of their body. But in animals all the 
members and the whole body possess some connate warmth of 
constitution, and hence when alive they are observed to be 
warm, but when dead and deprived of life they are the opposite. 
Indeed, the source of this warmth must be in the heart in 
sanguineous animals, and in the case of bloodless animals in 
the corresponding organ, for, though all parts of the body by 
means of their natural heat elaborate and concoct the 
nutriment, the governing organ takes the chief share in this 
process. Hence, though the other members become cold, life 
remains; but when the warmth here is quenched, death always 
ensues, because the source of heat in all the other members 
depends on this, and the soul is, as it were, set aglow with fire 
in this part, which in sanguineous animals is the heart and in 
the bloodless order the analogous member. Hence, of necessity, 
life must be coincident with the maintenance of heat, and what 
we call death is its destruction. 



1359 



However, it is to be noticed that there are two ways in which fire 
ceases to exist; it may go out either by exhaustion or by 
extinction. That which is self-caused we call exhaustion, that 
due to its opposites extinction. [The former is that due to old 
age, the latter to violence.] But either of these ways in which fire 
ceases to be may be brought about by the same cause, for, when 
there is a deficiency of nutriment and the warmth can obtain no 
maintenance, the fire fails; and the reason is that the opposite, 
checking digestion, prevents the fire from being fed. But in other 
cases the result is exhaustion, when the heat accumulates 
excessively owing to lack of respiration and of refrigeration. For 
in this case what happens is that the heat, accumulating in 
great quantity, quickly uses up its nutriment and consumes it 
all before more is sent up by evaporation. Hence not only is a 
smaller fire readily put out by a large one, but of itself the 
candle flame is consumed when inserted in a large blaze just as 
is the case with any other combustible. The reason is that the 
nutriment in the flame is seized by the larger one before fresh 
fuel can be added, for fire is ever coming into being and rushing 
just like a river, but so speedily as to elude observation. 

Clearly therefore, if the bodily heat must be conserved (as is 
necessary if life is to continue), there must be some way of 
cooling the heat resident in the source of warmth. Take as an 
illustration what occurs when coals are confined in a brazier. If 
they are kept covered up continuously by the so-called 'choker', 
they are quickly extinguished, but, if the lid is in rapid 
alternation lifted up and put on again they remain glowing for a 
long time. Banking up a fire also keeps it in, for the ashes, being 
porous, do not prevent the passage of air, and again they enable 
it to resist extinction by the surrounding air by means of the 
supply of heat which it possesses. However, we have stated in 
The Problems the reasons why these operations, namely 



1360 



banking up and covering up a fire, have the opposite effects (in 
the one case the fire goes out, in the other it continues alive for 
a considerable time). 



Everything living has soul, and it, as we have said, cannot exist 
without the presence of heat in the constitution. In plants the 
natural heat is sufficiently well kept alive by the aid which their 
nutriment and the surrounding air supply. For the food has a 
cooling effect [as it enters, just as it has in man] when first it is 
taken in, whereas abstinence from food produces heat and 
thirst. The air, if it be motionless, becomes hot, but by the entry 
of food a motion is set up which lasts until digestion is 
completed and so cools it. If the surrounding air is excessively 
cold owing to the time of year, there being severe frost, plants 
shrivel, or if, in the extreme heats of summer the moisture 
drawn from the ground cannot produce its cooling effect, the 
heat comes to an end by exhaustion. Trees suffering at such 
seasons are said to be blighted or star-stricken. Hence the 
practice of laying beneath the roots stones of certain species or 
water in pots, for the purpose of cooling the roots of the plants. 

Some animals pass their life in the water, others in the air, and 
therefore these media furnish the source and means of 
refrigeration, water in the one case, air in the other. We must 
proceed - and it will require further application on our part - to 
give an account of the way and manner in which this 
refrigeration occurs. 



1361 



A few of the previous physical philosophers have spoken of 
respiration. The reason, however, why it exists in animals they 
have either not declared or, when they have, their statements 
are not correct and show a comparative lack of acquaintance 
with the facts. Moreover they assert that all animals respire - 
which is untrue. Hence these points must first claim our 
attention, in order that we may not be thought to make 
unsubstantiated charges against authors no longer alive. 

First then, it is evident that all animals with lungs breathe, but 
in some cases breathing animals have a bloodless and spongy 
lung, and then there is less need for respiration. These animals 
can remain under water for a time, which relatively to their 
bodily strength, is considerable. All oviparous animals, e.g. the 
frog-tribe, have a spongy lung. Also hemydes and tortoises can 
remain for a long time immersed in water; for their lung, 
containing little blood, has not much heat. Hence, when once it 
is inflated, it itself, by means of its motion, produces a cooling 
effect and enables the animal to remain immersed for a long 
time. Suffocation, however, always ensues if the animal is 
forced to hold its breath for too long a time, for none of this 
class take in water in the way fishes do. On the other hand, 
animals which have the lung charged with blood have greater 
need of respiration on account of the amount of their heat, 
while none at all of the others which do not possess lungs 
breathe. 



8 

Democritus of Abdera and certain others who have treated of 
respiration, while saying nothing definite about the lungless 



1362 



animals, nevertheless seem to speak as if all breathed. But 
Anaxagoras and Diogenes both maintain that all breathe, and 
state the manner in which fishes and oysters respire. 
Anaxagoras says that when fishes discharge water through 
their gills, air is formed in the mouth, for there can be no 
vacuum, and that it is by drawing in this that they respire. 
Diogenes' statement is that, when they discharge water through 
their gills, they suck the air out of the water surrounding the 
mouth by means of the vacuum formed in the mouth, for he 
believes there is air in the water. 

But these theories are untenable. Firstly, they state only what is 
the common element in both operations and so leave out the 
half of the matter. For what goes by the name of respiration 
consists, on the one hand, of inhalation, and, on the other, of 
the exhalation of breath; but, about the latter they say nothing, 
nor do they describe how such animals emit their breath. 
Indeed, explanation is for them impossible for, when the 
creatures respire, they must discharge their breath by the same 
passage as that by which they draw it in, and this must happen 
in alternation. Hence, as a result, they must take the water into 
their mouth at the same time as they breathe out. But the air 
and the water must meet and obstruct each other. Further, 
when they discharge the water they must emit their breath by 
the mouth or the gills, and the result will be that they will 
breathe in and breathe out at the same time, for it is at that 
moment that respiration is said to occur. But it is impossible 
that they should do both at the same time. Hence, if respiring 
creatures must both exhale and inhale the air, and if none of 
these animals can breathe out, evidently none can respire at all. 



1363 



Further, the assertion that they draw in air out of the mouth or 
out of the water by means of the mouth is an impossibility, for, 
not having a lung, they have no windpipe; rather the stomach is 
closely juxtaposed to the mouth, so that they must do the 
sucking with the stomach. But in that case the other animals 
would do so also, which is not the truth; and the water-animals 
also would be seen to do it when out of the water, whereas 
quite evidently they do not. Further, in all animals that respire 
and draw breath there is to be observed a certain motion in the 
part of the body which draws in the air, but in the fishes this 
does not occur. Fishes do not appear to move any of the parts in 
the region of the stomach, except the gills alone, and these 
move both when they are in the water and when they are 
thrown on to dry land and gasp. Moreover, always when 
respiring animals are killed by being suffocated in water, 
bubbles are formed of the air which is forcibly discharged, as 
happens, e.g. when one forces a tortoise or a frog or any other 
animal of a similar class to stay beneath water. But with fishes 
this result never occurs, in whatsoever way we try to obtain it, 
since they do not contain air drawn from an external source. 
Again, the manner of respiration said to exist in them might 
occur in the case of men also when they are under water. For if 
fishes draw in air out of the surrounding water by means of 
their mouth why should not men too and other animals do so 
also; they should also, in the same way as fishes, draw in air out 
of the mouth. If in the former case it were possible, so also 
should it be in the latter. But, since in the one it is not so, 
neither does it occur in the other. Furthermore, why do fishes, if 
they respire, die in the air and gasp (as can be seen) as in 
suffocation? It is not want of food that produces this effect 
upon them, and the reason given by Diogenes is foolish, for he 
says that in air they take in too much air and hence die, but in 
the water they take in a moderate amount. But that should be a 



1364 



possible occurrence with land animals also; as facts are, 
however, no land animal seems to be suffocated by excessive 
respiration. Again, if all animals breathe, insects must do so 
also, many of them seem to live though divided not merely into 
two, but into several parts, e.g. the class called Scolopendra. But 
how can they, when thus divided, breathe, and what is the 
organ they employ? The main reason why these writers have 
not given a good account of these facts is that they have no 
acquaintance with the internal organs, and that they did not 
accept the doctrine that there is a final cause for whatever 
Nature does. If they had asked for what purpose respiration 
exists in animals, and had considered this with reference to the 
organs, e.g. the gills and the lungs, they would have discovered 
the reason more speedily. 



10 

Democritus, however, does teach that in the breathing animals 
there is a certain result produced by respiration; he asserts that 
it prevents the soul from being extruded from the body. 
Nevertheless, he by no means asserts that it is for this purpose 
that Nature so contrives it, for he, like the other physical 
philosophers, altogether fails to attain to any such explanation. 
His statement is that the soul and the hot element are identical, 
being the primary forms among the spherical particles. Hence, 
when these are being crushed together by the surrounding 
atmosphere thrusting them out, respiration, according to his 
account, comes in to succour them. For in the air there are 
many of those particles which he calls mind and soul. Hence, 
when we breathe and the air enters, these enter along with it, 
and by their action cancel the pressure, thus preventing the 
expulsion of the soul which resides in the animal. 



1365 



This explains why life and death are bound up with the taking 
in and letting out of the breath; for death occurs when the 
compression by the surrounding air gains the upper hand, and, 
the animal being unable to respire, the air from outside can no 
longer enter and counteract the compression. Death is the 
departure of those forms owing to the expulsive pressure 
exerted by the surrounding air. Death, however, occurs not by 
haphazard but, when natural, owing to old age, and, when 
unnatural, to violence. 

But the reason for this and why all must die Democritus has by 
no means made clear. And yet, since evidently death occurs at 
one time of life and not at another, he should have said whether 
the cause is external or internal. Neither does he assign the 
cause of the beginning of respiration, nor say whether it is 
internal or external. Indeed, it is not the case that the external 
mind superintends the reinforcement; rather the origin of 
breathing and of the respiratory motion must be within: it is not 
due to pressure from around. It is absurd also that what 
surrounds should compress and at the same time by entering 
dilate. This then is practically his theory, and how he puts it. 

But if we must consider that our previous account is true, and 
that respiration does not occur in every animal, we must deem 
that this explains death not universally, but only in respiring 
animals. Yet neither is it a good account of these even, as may 
clearly be seen from the facts and phenomena of which we all 
have experience. For in hot weather we grow warmer, and, 
having more need of respiration, we always breathe faster. But, 
when the air around is cold and contracts and solidifies the 
body, retardation of the breathing results. Yet this was just the 
time when the external air should enter and annul the 
expulsive movement, whereas it is the opposite that occurs. For 
when the breath is not let out and the heat accumulates too 
much then we need to respire, and to respire we must draw in 



1366 



the breath. When hot, people breathe rapidly, because they 
must do so in order to cool themselves, just when the theory of 
Democritus would make them add fire to fire. 



11 

The theory found in the Timaeus, of the passing round of the 
breath by pushing, by no means determines how, in the case of 
the animals other than land-animals, their heat is preserved, 
and whether it is due to the same or a different cause. For if 
respiration occurs only in land-animals we should be told what 
is the reason of that. Likewise, if it is found in others also, but in 
a different form, this form of respiration, if they all can breathe, 
must also be described. 

Further, the method of explaining involves a fiction. It is said 
that when the hot air issues from the mouth it pushes the 
surrounding air, which being carried on enters the very place 
whence the internal warmth issued, through the interstices of 
the porous flesh; and this reciprocal replacement is due to the 
fact that a vacuum cannot exist. But when it has become hot 
the air passes out again by the same route, and pushes back 
inwards through the mouth the air that had been discharged in 
a warm condition. It is said that it is this action which goes on 
continuously when the breath is taken in and let out. 

But according to this way of thinking it will follow that we 
breathe out before we breathe in. But the opposite is the case, as 
evidence shows, for though these two functions go on in 
alternation, yet the last act when life comes to a close is the 
letting out of the breath, and hence its admission must have 
been the beginning of the process. 



1367 



Once more, those who give this kind of explanation by no 
means state the final cause of the presence in animals of this 
function (to wit the admission and emission of the breath), but 
treat it as though it were a contingent accompaniment of life. 
Yet it evidently has control over life and death, for it results 
synchronously that when respiring animals are unable to 
breathe they perish. Again, it is absurd that the passage of the 
hot air out through the mouth and back again should be quite 
perceptible, while we were not able to detect the thoracic influx 
and the return outwards once more of the heated breath. It is 
also nonsense that respiration should consist in the entrance of 
heat, for the evidence is to the contrary effect; what is breathed 
out is hot, and what is breathed in is cold. When it is hot we 
pant in breathing, for, because what enters does not adequately 
perform its cooling function, we have as a consequence to draw 
the breath frequently. 



12 

It is certain, however, that we must not entertain the notion 
that it is for purposes of nutrition that respiration is designed, 
and believe that the internal fire is fed by the breath; 
respiration, as it were, adding fuel to the fire, while the feeding 
of the flame results in the outward passage of the breath. To 
combat this doctrine I shall repeat what I said in opposition to 
the previous theories. This, or something analogous to it, should 
occur in the other animals also (on this theory), for all possess 
vital heat. Further, how are we to describe this fictitious process 
of the generation of heat from the breath? Observation shows 
rather that it is a product of the food. A consequence also of this 
theory is that the nutriment would enter and the refuse be 



1368 



discharged by the same channel, but this does not appear to 
occur in the other instances. 



13 

Empedocles also gives an account of respiration without, 
however, making clear what its purpose is, or whether or not it 
is universal in animals. Also when dealing with respiration by 
means of the nostrils he imagines he is dealing with what is the 
primary kind of respiration. Even the breath which passes 
through the nostrils passes through the windpipe out of the 
chest as well, and without the latter the nostrils cannot act. 
Again, when animals are bereft of respiration through the 
nostrils, no detrimental result ensues, but, when prevented 
from breathing through the windpipe, they die. Nature employs 
respiration through the nostrils as a secondary function in 
certain animals in order to enable them to smell. But the reason 
why it exists in some only is that though almost all animals are 
endowed with the sense of smell, the sense-organ is not the 
same in all. 

A more precise account has been given about this elsewhere. 
Empedocles, however, explains the passage inwards and 
outwards of the breath, by the theory that there are certain 
blood-vessels, which, while containing blood, are not filled by it, 
but have passages leading to the outer air, the calibre of which 
is fine in contrast to the size of the solid particles, but large 
relatively to those in the air. Hence, since it is the nature of the 
blood to move upwards and downwards, when it moves down 
the air rushes in and inspiration occurs; when the blood rises, 
the air is forced out and the outward motion of the breath 
results. He compares this process to what occurs in a clepsydra. 



1369 



Thus all things outwards breathe and in; - their flesh has tubes 

Bloodless, that stretch towards the body's outmost edge, 

Which, at their mouths, full many frequent channels pierce, 

Cleaving the extreme nostrils through; thus, while the gore 

Lies hid, for air is cut a thoroughfare most plain. 

And thence, whenever shrinks away the tender blood, 

Enters the blustering wind with swelling billow wild. 

But when the blood leaps up, backward it breathes. As when 

With water-clock of polished bronze a maiden sporting, 

Sets on her comely hand the narrow of the tube 

And dips it in the frail-formed water's silvery sheen; 

Not then the flood the vessel enters, but the air, 

Until she frees the crowded stream. But then indeed 

Upon the escape runs in the water meet. 

So also when within the vessel's deeps the water 

Remains, the opening by the hand of flesh being closed, 

The outer air that entrance craves restrains the flood 

At the gates of the sounding narrow, 

upon the surface pressing, 

Until the maid withdraws her hand. But then in contrariwise 

Once more the air comes in and water meet flows out. 



1370 



Thus to the to the subtle blood, surging throughout the limbs, 

Whene'er it shrinks away into the far recesses 

Admits a stream of air rushing with swelling wave, 

But, when it backward leaps, in like bulk air flows out. 

This then is what he says of respiration. But, as we said, all 
animals that evidently respire do so by means of the windpipe, 
when they breathe either through the mouth or through the 
nostrils. Hence, if it is of this kind of respiration that he is 
talking, we must ask how it tallies with the explanation given. 
But the facts seem to be quite opposed. The chest is raised in 
the manner of a forge-bellows when the breath is drawn in - it 
is quite reasonable that it should be heat which raises up and 
that the blood should occupy the hot region - but it collapses 
and sinks down, like the bellows once more, when the breath is 
let out. The difference is that in a bellows it is not by the same 
channel that the air is taken in and let out, but in breathing it is. 

But, if Empedocles is accounting only for respiration through 
the nostrils, he is much in error, for that does not involve the 
nostrils alone, but passes by the channel beside the uvula where 
the extremity of the roof of the mouth is, some of the air going 
this way through the apertures of the nostrils and some 
through the mouth, both when it enters and when it passes out. 
Such then is the nature and magnitude of the difficulties 
besetting the theories of other writers concerning respiration. 



14 

We have already stated that life and the presence of soul 
involve a certain heat. Not even the digesting process to which 



1371 



is due the nutrition of animals occurs apart from soul and 
warmth, for it is to fire that in all cases elaboration is due. It is 
for this reason, precisely, that the primary nutritive soul also 
must be located in that part of the body and in that division of 
this region which is the immediate vehicle of this principle. The 
region in question is intermediate between that where food 
enters and that where excrement is discharged. In bloodless 
animals it has no name, but in the sanguineous class this organ 
is called the heart. The blood constitutes the nutriment from 
which the organs of the animal are directly formed. Likewise 
the bloodvessels must have the same originating source, since 
the one exists for the other's behoof - as a vessel or receptacle 
for it. In sanguineous animals the heart is the starting-point of 
the veins; they do not traverse it, but are found to stretch out 
from it, as dissections enable us to see. 

Now the other psychical faculties cannot exist apart from the 
power of nutrition (the reason has already been stated in the 
treatise On the Soul), and this depends on the natural fire, by 
the union with which Nature has set it aglow. But fire, as we 
have already stated, is destroyed in two ways, either by 
extinction or by exhaustion. It suffers extinction from its 
opposites. Hence it can be extinguished by the surrounding cold 
both when in mass and (though more speedily) when scattered. 
Now this way of perishing is due to violence equally in living 
and in lifeless objects, for the division of an animal by 
instruments and consequent congelation by excess of cold 
cause death. But exhaustion is due to excess of heat; if there is 
too much heat close at hand and the thing burning does not 
have a fresh supply of fuel added to it, it goes out by exhaustion, 
not by the action of cold. Hence, if it is going to continue it must 
be cooled, for cold is a preventive against this form of 
extinction. 



1372 



15 

Some animals occupy the water, others live on land, and, that 
being so, in the case of those which are very small and 
bloodless the refrigeration due to the surrounding water or air is 
sufficient to prevent destruction from this cause. Having little 
heat, they require little cold to combat it. Hence too such 
animals are almost all short-lived, for, being small, they have 
less scope for deflection towards either extreme. But some 
insects are longer-lived though bloodless, like all the others), 
and these have a deep indentation beneath the waist, in order 
to secure cooling through the membrane, which there is 
thinner. They are warmer animals and hence require more 
refrigeration, and such are bees (some of which live as long as 
seven years) and all that make a humming noise, like wasps, 
cockchafers, and crickets. They make a sound as if of panting by 
means of air, for, in the middle section itself, the air which 
exists internally and is involved in their construction, causing a 
rising and falling movement, produces friction against the 
membrane. The way in which they move this region is like the 
motion due to the lungs in animals that breathe the outer air, or 
to the gills in fishes. What occurs is comparable to the 
suffocation of a respiring animal by holding its mouth, for then 
the lung causes a heaving motion of this kind. In the case of 
these animals this internal motion is not sufficient for 
refrigeration, but in insects it is. It is by friction against the 
membrane that they produce the humming sound, as we said, 
in the way that children do by blowing through the holes of a 
reed covered by a fine membrane. It is thus that the singing 
crickets too produce their song; they possess greater warmth 
and are indented at the waist, but the songless variety have no 
fissure there. 



1373 



Animals also which are sanguineous and possess a lung, though 
that contains little blood and is spongy, can in some cases, 
owing to the latter fact, live a long time without breathing; for 
the lung, containing little blood or fluid, can rise a long way: its 
own motion can for a long time produce sufficient refrigeration. 
But at last it ceases to suffice, and the animal dies of suffocation 
if it does not respire - as we have already said. For of exhaustion 
that kind which is destruction due to lack of refrigeration is 
called suffocation, and whatsoever is thus destroyed is said to 
be suffocated. 

We have already stated that among animals insects do not 
respire, and the fact is open to observation in the case of even 
small creatures like flies and bees, for they can swim about in a 
fluid for a long time if it is not too hot or too cold. Yet animals 
with little strength tend to breathe more frequently. These, 
however, die of what is called suffocation when the stomach 
becomes filled and the heat in the central segment is destroyed. 
This explains also why they revive after being among ashes for 
a time. 

Again among water-animals those that are bloodless remain 
alive longer in air than those that have blood and admit the sea- 
water, as, for example, fishes. Since it is a small quantity of heat 
they possess, the air is for a long time adequate for the 
purposes of refrigeration in such animals as the Crustacea and 
the polyps. It does not however suffice, owing to their want of 
heat, to keep them finally in life, for most fishes also live though 
among earth, yet in a motionless state, and are to be found by 
digging. For all animals that have no lung at all or have a 
bloodless one require less refrigeration. 



1374 



16 

Concerning the bloodless animals we have declared that in 
some cases it is the surrounding air, in others fluid, that aids 
the maintenance of life. But in the case of animals possessing 
blood and heart, all which have a lung admit the air and 
produce the cooling effect by breathing in and out. All animals 
have a lung that are viviparous and are so internally, not 
externally merely (the Selachia are viviparous, but not 
internally), and of the oviparous class those that have wings, 
e.g. birds, and those with scales, e.g. tortoises, lizards, and 
snakes. The former class have a lung charged with blood, but in 
the most part of the latter it is spongy. Hence they employ 
respiration more sparingly as already said. The function is 
found also in all that frequent and pass their life in the water, 
e.g. the class of water-snakes and frogs and crocodiles and 
hemydes, both sea - and land-tortoises, and seals. 

All these and similar animals both bring forth on land and sleep 
on shore or, when they do so in the water, keep the head above 
the surface in order to respire. But all with gills produce 
refrigeration by taking in water; the Selachia and all other 
footless animals have gills. Fish are footless, and the limbs they 
have get their name (pterugion) from their similarity to wings 
(pterux). But of those with feet one only, so far as observed, has 
gills. It is called the tadpole. 

No animal yet has been seen to possess both lungs and gills, 
and the reason for this is that the lung is designed for the 
purpose of refrigeration by means of the air (it seems to have 
derived its name (pneumon) from its function as a receptacle of 
the breath (pneuma)), while gills are relevant to refrigeration by 
water. Now for one purpose one organ is adapted and one single 
means of refrigeration is sufficient in every case. Hence, since 
we see that Nature does nothing in vain, and if there were two 



1375 



organs one would be purposeless, this is the reason why some 
animals have gills, others lungs, but none possess both. 



17 

Every animal in order to exist requires nutriment, in order to 
prevent itself from dying, refrigeration; and so Nature employs 
the same organ for both purposes. For, as in some cases the 
tongue serves both for discerning tastes and for speech, so in 
animals with lungs the mouth is employed both in working up 
the food and in the passage of the breath outwards and 
inwards. In lungless and non-respiring animals it is employed in 
working up the food, while in those of them that require 
refrigeration it is the gills that are created for this purpose. 

We shall state further on how it is that these organs have the 
faculty of producing refrigeration. But to prevent their food from 
impeding these operations there is a similar contrivance in the 
respiring animals and in those that admit water. At the moment 
of respiration they do not take in food, for otherwise suffocation 
results owing to the food, whether liquid or dry, slipping in 
through the windpipe and lying on the lung. The windpipe is 
situated before the oesophagus, through which food passes into 
what is called the stomach, but in quadrupeds which are 
sanguineous there is, as it were, a lid over the windpipe - the 
epiglottis. In birds and oviparous quadrupeds this covering is 
absent, but its office is discharged by a contraction of the 
windpipe. The latter class contract the windpipe when 
swallowing their food; the former close down the epiglottis. 
When the food has passed, the epiglottis is in the one case 
raised, and in the other the windpipe is expanded, and the air 
enters to effect refrigeration. In animals with gills the water is 



1376 



first discharged through them and then the food passes in 
through the mouth; they have no windpipe and hence can take 
no harm from liquid lodging in this organ, only from its 
entering the stomach. For these reasons the expulsion of water 
and the seizing of their food is rapid, and their teeth are sharp 
and in almost all cases arranged in a saw-like fashion, for they 
are debarred from chewing their food. 



18 

Among water-animals the cetaceans may give rise to some 
perplexity, though they too can be rationally explained. 

Examples of such animals are dolphins and whales, and all 
others that have a blowhole. They have no feet, yet possess a 
lung though admitting the sea-water. The reason for possessing 
a lung is that which we have now stated [refrigeration]; the 
admission of water is not for the purpose of refrigeration. That 
is effected by respiration, for they have a lung. Hence they sleep 
with their head out of the water, and dolphins, at any rate, 
snore. Further, if they are entangled in nets they soon die of 
suffocation owing to lack of respiration, and hence they can be 
seen to come to the surface owing to the necessity of breathing. 
But, since they have to feed in the water, they must admit it, 
and it is in order to discharge this that they all have a blow- 
hole; after admitting the water they expel it through the blow- 
hole as the fishes do through the gills. The position of the blow- 
hole is an indication of this, for it leads to none of the organs 
which are charged with blood; but it lies before the brain and 
thence discharges water. 

It is for the very same reason that molluscs and crustaceans 
admit water - I mean such animals as Carabi and Carcini. For 



1377 



none of these is refrigeration a necessity, for in every case they 
have little heat and are bloodless, and hence are sufficiently 
cooled by the surrounding water. But in feeding they admit 
water, and hence must expel it in order to prevent its being 
swallowed simultaneously with the food. Thus crustaceans, like 
the Carcini and Carabi, discharge water through the folds beside 
their shaggy parts, while cuttlefish and the polyps employ for 
this purpose the hollow above the head. There is, however, a 
more precise account of these in the History of Animals. 

Thus it has been explained that the cause of the admission of 
the water is refrigeration, and the fact that animals constituted 
for a life in water must feed in it. 



19 

An account must next be given of refrigeration and the manner 
in which it occurs in respiring animals and those possessed of 
gills. We have already said that all animals with lungs respire. 
The reason why some creatures have this organ, and why those 
having it need respiration, is that the higher animals have a 
greater proportion of heat, for at the same time they must have 
been assigned a higher soul and they have a higher nature than 
plants. Hence too those with most blood and most warmth in 
the lung are of greater size, and animal in which the blood in 
the lung is purest and most plentiful is the most erect, namely 
man; and the reason why he alone has his upper part directed 
to the upper part of the universe is that he possesses such a 
lung. Hence this organ as much as any other must be assigned 
to the essence of the animal both in man and in other cases. 

This then is the purpose of refrigeration. As for the constraining 
and efficient cause, we must believe that it created animals like 



1378 



this, just as it created many others also not of this constitution. 
For some have a greater proportion of earth in their 
composition, like plants, and others, e.g. aquatic animals, 
contain a larger amount of water; while winged and terrestrial 
animals have an excess of air and fire respectively. It is always 
in the region proper to the element preponderating in the 
scheme of their constitution that things exist. 



20 

Empedocles is then in error when he says that those animals 
which have the most warmth and fire live in the water to 
counterbalance the excess of heat in their constitution, in order 
that, since they are deficient in cold and fluid, they may be kept 
in life by the contrary character of the region they occupy; for 
water has less heat than air. But it is wholly absurd that the 
water-animals should in every case originate on dry land, and 
afterwards change their place of abode to the water; for they are 
almost all footless. He, however, when describing their original 
structure says that, though originating on dry land, they have 
abandoned it and migrated to the water. But again it is evident 
that they are not warmer than land-animals, for in some cases 
they have no blood at all, in others little. 

The question, however, as to what sorts of animals should be 
called warm and what cold, has in each special case received 
consideration. Though in one respect there is reason in the 
explanation which Empedocles aims at establishing, yet his 
account is not correct. Excess in a bodily state is cured by a 
situation or season of opposite character, but the constitution is 
best maintained by an environment akin to it. There is a 
difference between the material of which any animal is 



1379 



constituted and the states and dispositions of that material. For 
example, if nature were to constitute a thing of wax or of ice, 
she would not preserve it by putting it in a hot place, for the 
opposing quality would quickly destroy it, seeing that heat 
dissolves that which cold congeals. Again, a thing composed of 
salt or nitre would not be taken and placed in water, for fluid 
dissolves that of which the consistency is due to the hot and 
the dry. 

Hence if the fluid and the dry supply the material for all bodies, 
it is reasonable that things the composition of which is due to 
the fluid and the cold should have liquid for their medium [and, 
if they are cold, they will exist in the cold], while that which is 
due to the dry will be found in the dry. Thus trees grow not in 
water but on dry land. But the same theory would relegate them 
to the water, on account of their excess of dryness, just as it 
does the things that are excessively fiery. They would migrate 
thither not on account of its cold but owing to its fluidity. 

Thus the natural character of the material of objects is of the 
same nature as the region in which they exist; the liquid is 
found in liquid, the dry on land, the warm in air. With regard, 
however, to states of body, a cold situation has, on the other 
hand, a beneficial effect on excess of heat, and a warm 
environment on excess of cold, for the region reduces to a mean 
the excess in the bodily condition. The regions appropriate to 
each material and the revolutions of the seasons which all 
experience supply the means which must be sought in order to 
correct such excesses; but, while states of the body can be 
opposed in character to the environment, the material of which 
it is composed can never be so. This, then, is a sufficient 
explanation of why it is not owing to the heat in their 
constitution that some animals are aquatic, others terrestrial, as 
Empedocles maintains, and of why some possess lungs and 
others do not. 



1380 



21 

The explanation of the admission of air and respiration in those 
animals in which a lung is found, and especially in those in 
which it is full of blood, is to be found in the fact that it is of a 
spongy nature and full of tubes, and that it is the most fully 
charged with blood of all the visceral organs. All animals with a 
full-blooded lung require rapid refrigeration because there is 
little scope for deviation from the normal amount of their vital 
fire; the air also must penetrate all through it on account of the 
large quantity of blood and heat it contains. But both these 
operations can be easily performed by air, for, being of a subtle 
nature, it penetrates everywhere and that rapidly, and so 
performs its cooling function; but water has the opposite 
characteristics. 

The reason why animals with a full-blooded lung respire most 
is hence manifest; the more heat there is, the greater is the 
need for refrigeration, and at the same time breath can easily 
pass to the source of heat in the heart. 



22 

In order to understand the way in which the heart is connected 
with the lung by means of passages, we must consult both 
dissections and the account in the History of Animals. The 
universal cause of the need which the animal has for 
refrigeration, is the union of the soul with fire that takes place 
in the heart. Respiration is the means of effecting refrigeration, 



1381 



of which those animals make use that possess a lung as well as 
a heart. But when they, as for example the fishes, which on 
account of their aquatic nature have no lung, possess the latter 
organ without the former, the cooling is effected through the 
gills by means of water. For ocular evidence as to how the heart 
is situated relatively to the gills we must employ dissections, 
and for precise details we must refer to Natural History. As a 
summarizing statement, however, and for present purposes, the 
following is the account of the matter. 

It might appear that the heart has not the same position in 
terrestrial animals and fishes, but the position really is 
identical, for the apex of the heart is in the direction in which 
they incline their heads. But it is towards the mouth in fishes 
that the apex of the heart points, seeing that they do not incline 
their heads in the same direction as land-animals do. Now from 
the extremity of the heart a tube of a sinewy, arterial character 
runs to the centre where the gills all join. This then is the 
largest of those ducts, but on either side of the heart others also 
issue and run to the extremity of each gill, and by means of the 
ceaseless flow of water through the gills, effect the cooling 
which passes to the heart. 

In similar fashion as the fish move their gills, respiring animals 
with rapid action raise and let fall the chest according as the 
breath is admitted or expelled. If air is limited in amount and 
unchanged they are suffocated, for either medium, owing to 
contact with the blood, rapidly becomes hot. The heat of the 
blood counteracts the refrigeration and, when respiring animals 
can no longer move the lung aquatic animals their gills, 
whether owing to disease or old age, their death ensues. 



1382 



23 

To be born and to die are common to all animals, but there are 
specifically diverse ways in which these phenomena occur; of 
destruction there are different types, though yet something is 
common to them all. There is violent death and again natural 
death, and the former occurs when the cause of death is 
external, the latter when it is internal, and involved from the 
beginning in the constitution of the organ, and not an affection 
derived from a foreign source. In the case of plants the name 
given to this is withering, in animals senility. Death and decay 
pertain to all things that are not imperfectly developed; to the 
imperfect also they may be ascribed in nearly the same but not 
an identical sense. Under the imperfect I class eggs and seeds of 
plants as they are before the root appears. 

It is always to some lack of heat that death is due, and in perfect 
creatures the cause is its failure in the organ containing the 
source of the creature's essential nature. This member is situate, 
as has been said, at the junction of the upper and lower parts; 
in plants it is intermediate between the root and the stem, in 
sanguineous animals it is the heart, and in those that are 
bloodless the corresponding part of their body. But some of 
these animals have potentially many sources of life, though in 
actuality they possess only one. This is why some insects live 
when divided, and why, even among sanguineous animals, all 
whose vitality is not intense live for a long time after the heart 
has been removed. Tortoises, for example, do so and make 
movements with their feet, so long as the shell is left, a fact to 
be explained by the natural inferiority of their constitution, as it 
is in insects also. 

The source of life is lost to its possessors when the heat with 
which it is bound up is no longer tempered by cooling, for, as I 
have often remarked, it is consumed by itself. Hence when, 



1383 



owing to lapse of time, the lung in the one class and the gills in 
the other get dried up, these organs become hard and earthy 
and incapable of movement, and cannot be expanded or 
contracted. Finally things come to a climax, and the fire goes 
out from exhaustion. 

Hence a small disturbance will speedily cause death in old age. 
Little heat remains, for the most of it has been breathed away in 
the long period of life preceding, and hence any increase of 
strain on the organ quickly causes extinction. It is just as 
though the heart contained a tiny feeble flame which the 
slightest movement puts out. Hence in old age death is painless, 
for no violent disturbance is required to cause death, and there 
is an entire absence of feeling when the soul's connexion is 
severed. All diseases which harden the lung by forming tumours 
or waste residues, or by excess of morbid heat, as happens in 
fevers, accelerate the breathing owing to the inability of the 
lung to move far either upwards or downwards. Finally, when 
motion is no longer possible, the breath is given out and death 
ensues. 



24 

Generation is the initial participation, mediated by warm 
substance, in the nutritive soul, and life is the maintenance of 
this participation. Youth is the period of the growth of the 
primary organ of refrigeration, old age of its decay, while the 
intervening time is the prime of life. 

A violent death or dissolution consists in the extinction or 
exhaustion of the vital heat (for either of these may cause 
dissolution), while natural death is the exhaustion of the heat 
owing to lapse of time, and occurring at the end of life. In plants 



1384 



this is to wither, in animals to die. Death, in old age, is the 
exhaustion due to inability on the part of the organ, owing to 
old age, to produce refrigeration. This then is our account of 
generation and life and death, and the reason for their 
occurrence in animals. 



25 

It is hence also clear why respiring animals are suffocated in 
water and fishes in air. For it is by water in the latter class, by 
air in the former that refrigeration is effected, and either of 
these means of performing the function is removed by a change 
of environment. 

There is also to be explained in either case the cause of the 
cause of the motion of the gills and of the lungs, the rise and 
fall of which effects the admission and expulsion of the breath 
or of water. The following, moreover, is the manner of the 
constitution of the organ. 



26 

In connexion with the heart there are three phenomena, which, 
though apparently of the same nature, are really not so, namely 
palpitation, pulsation, and respiration. 

Palpitation is the rushing together of the hot substance in the 
heart owing to the chilling influence of residual or waste 
products. It occurs, for example, in the ailment known as 
'spasms' and in other diseases. It occurs also in fear, for when 



1385 



one is afraid the upper parts become cold, and the hot 
substance, fleeing away, by its concentration in the heart 
produces palpitation. It is crushed into so small a space that 
sometimes life is extinguished, and the animals die of the fright 
and morbid disturbance. 

The beating of the heart, which, as can be seen, goes on 
continuously, is similar to the throbbing of an abscess. That, 
however, is accompanied by pain, because the change produced 
in the blood is unnatural, and it goes on until the matter formed 
by concoction is discharged. There is a similarity between this 
phenomenon and that of boiling; for boiling is due to the 
volatilization of fluid by heat and the expansion consequent on 
increase of bulk. But in an abscess, if there is no evaporation 
through the walls, the process terminates in suppuration due to 
the thickening of the liquid, while in boiling it ends in the 
escape of the fluid out of the containing vessel. 

In the heart the beating is produced by the heat expanding the 
fluid, of which the food furnishes a constant supply. It occurs 
when the fluid rises to the outer wall of the heart, and it goes on 
continuously; for there is a constant flow of the fluid that goes 
to constitute the blood, it being in the heart that the blood 
receives its primary elaboration. That this is so we can perceive 
in the initial stages of generation, for the heart can be seen to 
contain blood before the veins become distinct. This explains 
why pulsation in youth exceeds that in older people, for in the 
young the formation of vapour is more abundant. 

All the veins pulse, and do so simultaneously with each other, 
owing to their connexion with the heart. The heart always 
beats, and hence they also beat continuously and 
simultaneously with each other and with it. 



1386 



Palpitation, then, is the recoil of the heart against the 
compression due to cold; and pulsation is the volatilization of 
the heated fluid. 



27 

Respiration takes place when the hot substance which is the 
seat of the nutritive principle increases. For it, like the rest of 
the body, requires nutrition, and more so than the members, for 
it is through it that they are nourished. But when it increases it 
necessarily causes the organ to rise. This organ we must to be 
constructed like the bellows in a smithy, for both heart and 
lungs conform pretty well to this shape. Such a structure must 
be double, for the nutritive principle must be situated in the 
centre of the natural force. 

Thus on increase of bulk expansion results, which necessarily 
causes the surrounding parts to rise. Now this can be seen to 
occur when people respire; they raise their chest because the 
motive principle of the organ described resident within the 
chest causes an identical expansion of this organ. When it 
dilates the outer air must rush in as into a bellows, and, being 
cold, by its chilling influence reduces by extinction the excess of 
the fire. But, as the increase of bulk causes the organ to dilate, 
so diminution causes contraction, and when it collapses the air 
which entered must pass out again. When it enters the air is 
cold, but on issuing it is warm owing to its contact with the heat 
resident in this organ, and this is specially the case in those 
animals that possess a full-blooded lung. The numerous canal- 
like ducts in the lung, into which it passes, have each a blood- 
vessel lying alongside, so that the whole lung is thought to be 
full of blood. The inward passage of the air is called respiration, 



1387 



the outward expiration, and this double movement goes on 
continuously just so long as the animal lives and keeps this 
organ in continuous motion; it is for this reason that life is 
bound up with the passage of the breath outwards and inwards. 

It is in the same way that the motion of the gills in fishes takes 
place. When the hot substance in the blood throughout the 
members rises, the gills rise too, and let the water pass through, 
but when it is chilled and retreats through its channels to the 
heart, they contract and eject the water. Continually as the heat 
in the heart rises, continually on being chilled it returns thither 
again. Hence, as in respiring animals life and death are bound 
up with respiration, so in the other animals class they depend 
on the admission of water. 

Our discussion of life and death and kindred topics is now 
practically complete. But health and disease also claim the 
attention of the scientist, and not merely of the physician, in so 
far as an account of their causes is concerned. The extent to 
which these two differ and investigate diverse provinces must 
not escape us, since facts show that their inquiries are, to a 
certain extent, at least conterminous. For physicians of culture 
and refinement make some mention of natural science, and 
claim to derive their principles from it, while the most 
accomplished investigators into nature generally push their 
studies so far as to conclude with an account of medical 
principles. 



1388 



Aristotle - History of Animals 
[Translated by D'Arcy Wentworth Thompson] 



Book I 



Of the parts of animals some are simple: to wit, all such as 
divide into parts uniform with themselves, as flesh into flesh; 
others are composite, such as divide into parts not uniform with 
themselves, as, for instance, the hand does not divide into 
hands nor the face into faces. 

And of such as these, some are called not parts merely, but 
limbs or members. Such are those parts that, while entire in 
themselves, have within themselves other diverse parts: as for 
instance, the head, foot, hand, the arm as a whole, the chest; for 
these are all in themselves entire parts, and there are other 
diverse parts belonging to them. 

All those parts that do not subdivide into parts uniform with 
themselves are composed of parts that do so subdivide, for 
instance, hand is composed of flesh, sinews, and bones. Of 
animals, some resemble one another in all their parts, while 
others have parts wherein they differ. Sometimes the parts are 
identical in form or species, as, for instance, one man's nose or 
eye resembles another man's nose or eye, flesh flesh, and bone 
bone; and in like manner with a horse, and with all other 
animals which we reckon to be of one and the same species: for 
as the whole is to the whole, so each to each are the parts 



1389 



severally. In other cases the parts are identical, save only for a 
difference in the way of excess or defect, as is the case in such 
animals as are of one and the same genus. By 'genus' I mean, 
for instance, Bird or Fish, for each of these is subject to 
difference in respect of its genus, and there are many species of 
fishes and of birds. 

Within the limits of genera, most of the parts as a rule exhibit 
differences through contrast of the property or accident, such as 
colour and shape, to which they are subject: in that some are 
more and some in a less degree the subject of the same 
property or accident; and also in the way of multitude or 
fewness, magnitude or parvitude, in short in the way of excess 
or defect. Thus in some the texture of the flesh is soft, in others 
firm; some have a long bill, others a short one; some have 
abundance of feathers, others have only a small quantity. It 
happens further that some have parts that others have not: for 
instance, some have spurs and others not, some have crests and 
others not; but as a general rule, most parts and those that go to 
make up the bulk of the body are either identical with one 
another, or differ from one another in the way of contrast and of 
excess and defect. For 'the more' and 'the less' may be 
represented as 'excess' or 'defect'. 

Once again, we may have to do with animals whose parts are 
neither identical in form nor yet identical save for differences in 
the way of excess or defect: but they are the same only in the 
way of analogy, as, for instance, bone is only analogous to fish- 
bone, nail to hoof, hand to claw, and scale to feather; for what 
the feather is in a bird, the scale is in a fish. 

The parts, then, which animals severally possess are diverse 
from, or identical with, one another in the fashion above 
described. And they are so furthermore in the way of local 
disposition: for many animals have identical organs that differ 



1390 



in position; for instance, some have teats in the breast, others 
close to the thighs. 

Of the substances that are composed of parts uniform (or 
homogeneous) with themselves, some are soft and moist, 
others are dry and solid. The soft and moist are such either 
absolutely or so long as they are in their natural conditions, as, 
for instance, blood, serum, lard, suet, marrow, sperm, gall, milk 
in such as have it flesh and the like; and also, in a different way, 
the superfluities, as phlegm and the excretions of the belly and 
the bladder. The dry and solid are such as sinew, skin, vein, hair, 
bone, gristle, nail, horn (a term which as applied to the part 
involves an ambiguity, since the whole also by virtue of its form 
is designated horn), and such parts as present an analogy to 
these. 

Animals differ from one another in their modes of subsistence, 
in their actions, in their habits, and in their parts. Concerning 
these differences we shall first speak in broad and general 
terms, and subsequently we shall treat of the same with close 
reference to each particular genus. 

Differences are manifested in modes of subsistence, in habits, 
in actions performed. For instance, some animals live in water 
and others on land. And of those that live in water some do so 
in one way, and some in another: that is to say, some live and 
feed in the water, take in and emit water, and cannot live if 
deprived of water, as is the case with the great majority of 
fishes; others get their food and spend their days in the water, 
but do not take in water but air, nor do they bring forth in the 
water. Many of these creatures are furnished with feet, as the 
otter, the beaver, and the crocodile; some are furnished with 
wings, as the diver and the grebe; some are destitute of feet, as 
the water-snake. Some creatures get their living in the water 
and cannot exist outside it: but for all that do not take in either 



1391 



air or water, as, for instance, the sea-nettle and the oyster. And 
of creatures that live in the water some live in the sea, some in 
rivers, some in lakes, and some in marshes, as the frog and the 
newt. 

Of animals that live on dry land some take in air and emit it, 
which phenomena are termed 'inhalation' and 'exhalation'; as, 
for instance, man and all such land animals as are furnished 
with lungs. Others, again, do not inhale air, yet live and find 
their sustenance on dry land; as, for instance, the wasp, the bee, 
and all other insects. And by 'insects' I mean such creatures as 
have nicks or notches on their bodies, either on their bellies or 
on both backs and bellies. 

And of land animals many, as has been said, derive their 
subsistence from the water; but of creatures that live in and 
inhale water not a single one derives its subsistence from dry 
land. 

Some animals at first live in water, and by and by change their 
shape and live out of water, as is the case with river worms, for 
out of these the gadfly develops. 

Furthermore, some animals are stationary, and some are erratic. 
Stationary animals are found in water, but no such creature is 
found on dry land. In the water are many creatures that live in 
close adhesion to an external object, as is the case with several 
kinds of oyster. And, by the way, the sponge appears to be 
endowed with a certain sensibility: as a proof of which it is 
alleged that the difficulty in detaching it from its moorings is 
increased if the movement to detach it be not covertly applied. 

Other creatures adhere at one time to an object and detach 
themselves from it at other times, as is the case with a species 
of the so-called sea-nettle; for some of these creatures seek 
their food in the night-time loose and unattached. 



1392 



Many creatures are unattached but motionless, as is the case 
with oysters and the so-called holothuria. Some can swim, as, 
for instance, fishes, molluscs, and crustaceans, such as the 
crawfish. But some of these last move by walking, as the crab, 
for it is the nature of the creature, though it lives in water, to 
move by walking. 

Of land animals some are furnished with wings, such as birds 
and bees, and these are so furnished in different ways one from 
another; others are furnished with feet. Of the animals that are 
furnished with feet some walk, some creep, and some wriggle. 
But no creature is able only to move by flying, as the fish is able 
only to swim, for the animals with leathern wings can walk; the 
bat has feet and the seal has imperfect feet. 

Some birds have feet of little power, and are therefore called 
Apodes. This little bird is powerful on the wing; and, as a rule, 
birds that resemble it are weak-footed and strong winged, such 
as the swallow and the drepanis or (?) Alpine swift; for all these 
birds resemble one another in their habits and in their plumage, 
and may easily be mistaken one for another. (The apus is to be 
seen at all seasons, but the drepanis only after rainy weather in 
summer; for this is the time when it is seen and captured, 
though, as a general rule, it is a rare bird.) 

Again, some animals move by walking on the ground as well as 
by swimming in water. 

Furthermore, the following differences are manifest in their 
modes of living and in their actions. Some are gregarious, some 
are solitary, whether they be furnished with feet or wings or be 
fitted for a life in the water; and some partake of both 
characters, the solitary and the gregarious. And of the 
gregarious, some are disposed to combine for social purposes, 
others to live each for its own self. 



1393 



Gregarious creatures are, among birds, such as the pigeon, the 
crane, and the swan; and, by the way, no bird furnished with 
crooked talons is gregarious. Of creatures that live in water 
many kinds of fishes are gregarious, such as the so-called 
migrants, the tunny, the pelamys, and the bonito. 

Man, by the way, presents a mixture of the two characters, the 
gregarious and the solitary. 

Social creatures are such as have some one common object in 
view; and this property is not common to all creatures that are 
gregarious. Such social creatures are man, the bee, the wasp, the 
ant, and the crane. 

Again, of these social creatures some submit to a ruler, others 
are subject to no governance: as, for instance, the crane and the 
several sorts of bee submit to a ruler, whereas ants and 
numerous other creatures are every one his own master. 

And again, both of gregarious and of solitary animals, some are 
attached to a fixed home and others are erratic or nomad. 

Also, some are carnivorous, some graminivorous, some 
omnivorous: whilst some feed on a peculiar diet, as for instance 
the bees and the spiders, for the bee lives on honey and certain 
other sweets, and the spider lives by catching flies; and some 
creatures live on fish. Again, some creatures catch their food, 
others treasure it up; whereas others do not so. 

Some creatures provide themselves with a dwelling, others go 
without one: of the former kind are the mole, the mouse, the 
ant, the bee; of the latter kind are many insects and 
quadrupeds. Further, in respect to locality of dwelling place, 
some creatures dwell under ground, as the lizard and the snake; 
others live on the surface of the ground, as the horse and the 
dog. make to themselves holes, others do not 



1394 



Some are nocturnal, as the owl and the bat; others live in the 
daylight. 

Moreover, some creatures are tame and some are wild: some are 
at all times tame, as man and the mule; others are at all times 
savage, as the leopard and the wolf; and some creatures can be 
rapidly tamed, as the elephant. 

Again, we may regard animals in another light. For, whenever a 
race of animals is found domesticated, the same is always to be 
found in a wild condition; as we find to be the case with horses, 
kine, swine, (men), sheep, goats, and dogs. 

Further, some animals emit sound while others are mute, and 
some are endowed with voice: of these latter some have 
articulate speech, while others are inarticulate; some are given 
to continual chirping and twittering some are prone to silence; 
some are musical, and some unmusical; but all animals without 
exception exercise their power of singing or chattering chiefly in 
connexion with the intercourse of the sexes. 

Again, some creatures live in the fields, as the cushat; some on 
the mountains, as the hoopoe; some frequent the abodes of 
men, as the pigeon. 

Some, again, are peculiarly salacious, as the partridge, the barn- 
door cock and their congeners; others are inclined to chastity, as 
the whole tribe of crows, for birds of this kind indulge but rarely 
in sexual intercourse. 

Of marine animals, again, some live in the open seas, some near 
the shore, some on rocks. 

Furthermore, some are combative under offence; others are 
provident for defence. Of the former kind are such as act as 
aggressors upon others or retaliate when subjected to ill usage, 



1395 



and of the latter kind are such as merely have some means of 
guarding themselves against attack. 

Animals also differ from one another in regard to character in 
the following respects. Some are good-tempered, sluggish, and 
little prone to ferocity, as the ox; others are quick tempered, 
ferocious and unteachable, as the wild boar; some are 
intelligent and timid, as the stag and the hare; others are mean 
and treacherous, as the snake; others are noble and courageous 
and high-bred, as the lion; others are thorough-bred and wild 
and treacherous, as the wolf: for, by the way, an animal is 
highbred if it come from a noble stock, and an animal is 
thorough-bred if it does not deflect from its racial 
characteristics. 

Further, some are crafty and mischievous, as the fox; some are 
spirited and affectionate and fawning, as the dog; others are 
easy-tempered and easily domesticated, as the elephant; others 
are cautious and watchful, as the goose; others are jealous and 
self-conceited, as the peacock. But of all animals man alone is 
capable of deliberation. 

Many animals have memory, and are capable of instruction; but 
no other creature except man can recall the past at will. 

With regard to the several genera of animals, particulars as to 
their habits of life and modes of existence will be discussed 
more fully by and by. 



Common to all animals are the organs whereby they take food 
and the organs where into they take it; and these are either 



1396 



identical with one another, or are diverse in the ways above 
specified: to wit, either identical in form, or varying in respect of 
excess or defect, or resembling one another analogically, or 
differing in position. 

Furthermore, the great majority of animals have other organs 
besides these in common, whereby they discharge the residuum 
of their food: I say, the great majority, for this statement does 
not apply to all. And, by the way, the organ whereby food is 
taken in is called the mouth, and the organ whereinto it is 
taken, the belly; the remainder of the alimentary system has a 
great variety of names. 

Now the residuum of food is twofold in kind, wet and dry, and 
such creatures as have organs receptive of wet residuum are 
invariably found with organs receptive of dry residuum; but 
such as have organs receptive of dry residuum need not possess 
organs receptive of wet residuum. In other words, an animal has 
a bowel or intestine if it have a bladder; but an animal may have 
a bowel and be without a bladder. And, by the way, I may here 
remark that the organ receptive of wet residuum is termed 
'bladder', and the organ receptive of dry residuum 'intestine or 
'bowel'. 



Of animals otherwise, a great many have, besides the organs 
above-mentioned, an organ for excretion of the sperm: and of 
animals capable of generation one secretes into another, and 
the other into itself. The latter is termed 'female', and the 
former 'male'; but some animals have neither male nor female. 
Consequently, the organs connected with this function differ in 



1397 



form, for some animals have a womb and others an organ 
analogous thereto. 

The above-mentioned organs, then, are the most indispensable 
parts of animals; and with some of them all animals without 
exception, and with others animals for the most part, must 
needs be provided. 

One sense, and one alone, is common to all animals - the sense 
of touch. Consequently, there is no special name for the organ 
in which it has its seat; for in some groups of animals the organ 
is identical, in others it is only analogous. 



Every animal is supplied with moisture, and, if the animal be 
deprived of the same by natural causes or artificial means, 
death ensues: further, every animal has another part in which 
the moisture is contained. These parts are blood and vein, and 
in other animals there is something to correspond; but in these 
latter the parts are imperfect, being merely fibre and serum or 
lymph. 

Touch has its seat in a part uniform and homogeneous, as in 
the flesh or something of the kind, and generally, with animals 
supplied with blood, in the parts charged with blood. In other 
animals it has its seat in parts analogous to the parts charged 
with blood; but in all cases it is seated in parts that in their 
texture are homogeneous. 

The active faculties, on the contrary, are seated in the parts that 
are heterogeneous: as, for instance, the business of preparing 



1398 



the food is seated in the mouth, and the office of locomotion in 
the feet, the wings, or in organs to correspond. 

Again, some animals are supplied with blood, as man, the horse, 
and all such animals as are, when full-grown, either destitute of 
feet, or two-footed, or four-footed; other animals are bloodless, 
such as the bee and the wasp, and, of marine animals, the 
cuttle-fish, the crawfish, and all such animals as have more 
than four feet. 



Again, some animals are viviparous, others oviparous, others 
vermiparous or 'grub-bearing'. Some are viviparous, such as 
man, the horse, the seal, and all other animals that are hair- 
coated, and, of marine animals, the cetaceans, as the dolphin, 
and the so-called Selachia. (Of these latter animals, some have a 
tubular air-passage and no gills, as the dolphin and the whale: 
the dolphin with the air-passage going through its back, the 
whale with the air-passage in its forehead; others have 
uncovered gills, as the Selachia, the sharks and rays.) 

What we term an egg is a certain completed result of 
conception out of which the animal that is to be develops, and 
in such a way that in respect to its primitive germ it comes from 
part only of the egg, while the rest serves for food as the germ 
develops. A 'grub' on the other hand is a thing out of which in 
its entirety the animal in its entirety develops, by differentiation 
and growth of the embryo. 

Of viviparous animals, some hatch eggs in their own interior, as 
creatures of the shark kind; others engender in their interior a 
live foetus, as man and the horse. When the result of 



1399 



conception is perfected, with some animals a living creature is 
brought forth, with others an egg is brought to light, with others 
a grub. Of the eggs, some have egg-shells and are of two 
different colours within, such as birds' eggs; others are soft- 
skinned and of uniform colour, as the eggs of animals of the 
shark kind. Of the grubs, some are from the first capable of 
movement, others are motionless. However, with regard to 
these phenomena we shall speak precisely hereafter when we 
come to treat of Generation. 

Furthermore, some animals have feet and some are destitute 
thereof. Of such as have feet some animals have two, as is the 
case with men and birds, and with men and birds only; some 
have four, as the lizard and the dog; some have more, as the 
centipede and the bee; but allsoever that have feet have an even 
number of them. 

Of swimming creatures that are destitute of feet, some have 
winglets or fins, as fishes: and of these some have four fins, two 
above on the back, two below on the belly, as the gilthead and 
the basse; some have two only, to wit, such as are exceedingly 
long and smooth, as the eel and the conger; some have none at 
all, as the muraena, but use the sea just as snakes use dry 
ground - and by the way, snakes swim in water in just the same 
way. Of the shark-kind some have no fins, such as those that are 
flat and long-tailed, as the ray and the sting-ray, but these fishes 
swim actually by the undulatory motion of their flat bodies; the 
fishing frog, however, has fins, and so likewise have all such 
fishes as have not their flat surfaces thinned off to a sharp edge. 

Of those swimming creatures that appear to have feet, as is the 
case with the molluscs, these creatures swim by the aid of their 
feet and their fins as well, and they swim most rapidly 
backwards in the direction of the trunk, as is the case with the 



1400 



cuttle-fish or sepia and the calamary; and, by the way, neither of 
these latter can walk as the poulpe or octopus can. 

The hard-skinned or crustaceous animals, like the crawfish, 
swim by the instrumentality of their tail-parts; and they swim 
most rapidly tail foremost, by the aid of the fins developed upon 
that member. The newt swims by means of its feet and tail; and 
its tail resembles that of the sheatfish, to compare little with 
great. 

Of animals that can fly some are furnished with feathered 
wings, as the eagle and the hawk; some are furnished with 
membranous wings, as the bee and the cockchafer; others are 
furnished with leathern wings, as the flying fox and the bat. All 
flying creatures possessed of blood have feathered wings or 
leathern wings; the bloodless creatures have membranous 
wings, as insects. The creatures that have feathered wings or 
leathern wings have either two feet or no feet at all: for there 
are said to be certain flying serpents in Ethiopia that are 
destitute of feet. 

Creatures that have feathered wings are classed as a genus 
under the name of 'bird'; the other two genera, the leathern- 
winged and membrane-winged, are as yet without a generic 
title. 

Of creatures that can fly and are bloodless some are 
coleopterous or sheath-winged, for they have their wings in a 
sheath or shard, like the cockchafer and the dung-beetle; others 
are sheathless, and of these latter some are dipterous and some 
tetrapterous: tetrapterous, such as are comparatively large or 
have their stings in the tail, dipterous, such as are 
comparatively small or have their stings in front. The coleoptera 
are, without exception, devoid of stings; the diptera have the 
sting in front, as the fly, the horsefly, the gadfly, and the gnat. 



1401 



Bloodless animals as a general rule are inferior in point of size 
to blooded animals; though, by the way, there are found in the 
sea some few bloodless creatures of abnormal size, as in the 
case of certain molluscs. And of these bloodless genera, those 
are the largest that dwell in milder climates, and those that 
inhabit the sea are larger than those living on dry land or in 
fresh water. 

All creatures that are capable of motion move with four or more 
points of motion; the blooded animals with four only: as, for 
instance, man with two hands and two feet, birds with two 
wings and two feet, quadrupeds and fishes severally with four 
feet and four fins. Creatures that have two winglets or fins, or 
that have none at all like serpents, move all the same with not 
less than four points of motion; for there are four bends in their 
bodies as they move, or two bends together with their fins. 
Bloodless and many footed animals, whether furnished with 
wings or feet, move with more than four points of motion; as, 
for instance, the dayfly moves with four feet and four wings: 
and, I may observe in passing, this creature is exceptional not 
only in regard to the duration of its existence, whence it 
receives its name, but also because though a quadruped it has 
wings also. 

All animals move alike, four-footed and many-footed; in other 
words, they all move cross-corner-wise. And animals in general 
have two feet in advance; the crab alone has four. 



Very extensive genera of animals, into which other subdivisions 
fall, are the following: one, of birds; one, of fishes; and another, 
of cetaceans. Now all these creatures are blooded. 



1402 



There is another genus of the hard-shell kind, which is called 
oyster; another of the soft-shell kind, not as yet designated by a 
single term, such as the spiny crawfish and the various kinds of 
crabs and lobsters; and another of molluscs, as the two kinds of 
calamary and the cuttle-fish; that of insects is different. All 
these latter creatures are bloodless, and such of them as have 
feet have a goodly number of them; and of the insects some 
have wings as well as feet. 

Of the other animals the genera are not extensive. For in them 
one species does not comprehend many species; but in one 
case, as man, the species is simple, admitting of no 
differentiation, while other cases admit of differentiation, but 
the forms lack particular designations. 

So, for instance, creatures that are qudapedal and unprovided 
with wings are blooded without exception, but some of them 
are viviparous, and some oviparous. Such as are viviparous are 
hair-coated, and such as are oviparous are covered with a kind 
of tessellated hard substance; and the tessellated bits of this 
substance are, as it were, similar in regard to position to a scale. 

An animal that is blooded and capable of movement on dry 
land, but is naturally unprovided with feet, belongs to the 
serpent genus; and animals of this genus are coated with the 
tessellated horny substance. Serpents in general are oviparous; 
the adder, an exceptional case, is viviparous: for not all 
viviparous animals are hair-coated, and some fishes also are 
viviparous. 

All animals, however, that are hair-coated are viviparous. For, by 
the way, one must regard as a kind of hair such prickly hairs as 
hedgehogs and porcupines carry; for these spines perform the 
office of hair, and not of feet as is the case with similar parts of 
sea-urchins. 



1403 



In the genus that combines all viviparous quadrupeds are many 
species, but under no common appellation. They are only 
named as it were one by one, as we say man, lion, stag, horse, 
dog, and so on; though, by the way, there is a sort of genus that 
embraces all creatures that have bushy manes and bushy tails, 
such as the horse, the ass, the mule, the jennet, and the animals 
that are called Hemioni in Syria, from their externally 
resembling mules, though they are not strictly of the same 
species. And that they are not so is proved by the fact that they 
mate with and breed from one another. For all these reasons, we 
must take animals species by species, and discuss their 
peculiarities severally. 

These preceding statements, then, have been put forward thus 
in a general way, as a kind of foretaste of the number of subjects 
and of the properties that we have to consider in order that we 
may first get a clear notion of distinctive character and common 
properties. By and by we shall discuss these matters with 
greater minuteness. 

After this we shall pass on to the discussion of causes. For to do 
this when the investigation of the details is complete is the 
proper and natural method, and that whereby the subjects and 
the premisses of our argument will afterwards be rendered 
plain. 

In the first place we must look to the constituent parts of 
animals. For it is in a way relative to these parts, first and 
foremost, that animals in their entirety differ from one another: 
either in the fact that some have this or that, while they have 
not that or this; or by peculiarities of position or of 
arrangement; or by the differences that have been previously 
mentioned, depending upon diversity of form, or excess or 
defect in this or that particular, on analogy, or on contrasts of 
the accidental qualities. 



1404 



To begin with, we must take into consideration the parts of 
Man. For, just as each nation is wont to reckon by that monetary 
standard with which it is most familiar, so must we do in other 
matters. And, of course, man is the animal with which we are 
all of us the most familiar. 

Now the parts are obvious enough to physical perception. 
However, with the view of observing due order and sequence 
and of combining rational notions with physical perception, we 
shall proceed to enumerate the parts: firstly, the organic, and 
afterwards the simple or non-composite. 



The chief parts into which the body as a whole is subdivided, 
are the head, the neck, the trunk (extending from the neck to 
the privy parts), which is called the thorax, two arms and two 
legs. 

Of the parts of which the head is composed the hair-covered 
portion is called the 'skull'. The front portion of it is termed 
'bregma' or 'sinciput', developed after birth - for it is the last of 
all the bones in the body to acquire solidity, - the hinder part is 
termed the 'occiput', and the part intervening between the 
sinciput and the occiput is the 'crown'. The brain lies 
underneath the sinciput; the occiput is hollow. The skull 
consists entirely of thin bone, rounded in shape, and contained 
within a wrapper of fleshless skin. 

The skull has sutures: one, of circular form, in the case of 
women; in the case of men, as a general rule, three meeting at a 
point. Instances have been known of a man's skull devoid of 
suture altogether. In the skull the middle line, where the hair 



1405 



parts, is called the crown or vertex. In some cases the parting is 
double; that is to say, some men are double crowned, not in 
regard to the bony skull, but in consequence of the double fall 
or set of the hair. 



8 

The part that lies under the skull is called the 'face': but in the 
case of man only, for the term is not applied to a fish or to an 
ox. In the face the part below the sinciput and between the eyes 
is termed the forehead. When men have large foreheads, they 
are slow to move; when they have small ones, they are fickle; 
when they have broad ones, they are apt to be distraught; when 
they have foreheads rounded or bulging out, they are quick- 
tempered. 



Underneath the forehead are two eyebrows. Straight eyebrows 
are a sign of softness of disposition; such as curve in towards 
the nose, of harshness; such as curve out towards the temples, 
of humour and dissimulation; such as are drawn in towards one 
another, of jealousy. 

Under the eyebrows come the eyes. These are naturally two in 
number. Each of them has an upper and a lower eyelid, and the 
hairs on the edges of these are termed 'eyelashes'. The central 
part of the eye includes the moist part whereby vision is 
effected, termed the 'pupil', and the part surrounding it called 
the 'black'; the part outside this is the 'white'. A part common to 



1406 



the upper and lower eyelid is a pair of nicks or corners, one in 
the direction of the nose, and the other in the direction of the 
temples. When these are long they are a sign of bad disposition; 
if the side toward the nostril be fleshy and comb-like, they are a 
sign of dishonesty. 

All animals, as a general rule, are provided with eyes, excepting 
the ostracoderms and other imperfect creatures; at all events, 
all viviparous animals have eyes, with the exception of the 
mole. And yet one might assert that, though the mole has not 
eyes in the full sense, yet it has eyes in a kind of a way. For in 
point of absolute fact it cannot see, and has no eyes visible 
externally; but when the outer skin is removed, it is found to 
have the place where eyes are usually situated, and the black 
parts of the eyes rightly situated, and all the place that is 
usually devoted on the outside to eyes: showing that the parts 
are stunted in development, and the skin allowed to grow over. 



10 

Of the eye the white is pretty much the same in all creatures; 
but what is called the black differs in various animals. Some 
have the rim black, some distinctly blue, some greyish-blue, 
some greenish; and this last colour is the sign of an excellent 
disposition, and is particularly well adapted for sharpness of 
vision. Man is the only, or nearly the only, creature, that has 
eyes of diverse colours. Animals, as a rule, have eyes of one 
colour only. Some horses have blue eyes. 

Of eyes, some are large, some small, some medium-sized; of 
these, the medium-sized are the best. Moreover, eyes 
sometimes protrude, sometimes recede, sometimes are neither 
protruding nor receding. Of these, the receding eye is in all 



1407 



animals the most acute; but the last kind are the sign of the 
best disposition. Again, eyes are sometimes inclined to wink 
under observation, sometimes to remain open and staring, and 
sometimes are disposed neither to wink nor stare. The last kind 
are the sign of the best nature, and of the others, the latter kind 
indicates impudence, and the former indecision. 



11 

Furthermore, there is a portion of the head, whereby an animal 
hears, a part incapable of breathing, the 'ear'. I say 'incapable of 
breathing', for Alcmaeon is mistaken when he says that goats 
inspire through their ears. Of the ear one part is unnamed, the 
other part is called the 'lobe'; and it is entirely composed of 
gristle and flesh. The ear is constructed internally like the 
trumpet-shell, and the innermost bone is like the ear itself, and 
into it at the end the sound makes its way, as into the bottom of 
a jar. This receptacle does not communicate by any passage 
with the brain, but does so with the palate, and a vein extends 
from the brain towards it. The eyes also are connected with the 
brain, and each of them lies at the end of a little vein. Of 
animals possessed of ears man is the only one that cannot 
move this organ. Of creatures possessed of hearing, some have 
ears, whilst others have none, but merely have the passages for 
ears visible, as, for example, feathered animals or animals 
coated with horny tessellates. 

Viviparous animals, with the exception of the seal, the dolphin, 
and those others which after a similar fashion to these are 
cetaceans, are all provided with ears; for, by the way, the shark- 
kind are also viviparous. Now, the seal has the passages visible 
whereby it hears; but the dolphin can hear, but has no ears, nor 



1408 



yet any passages visible. But man alone is unable to move his 
ears, and all other animals can move them. And the ears lie, 
with man, in the same horizontal plane with the eyes, and not 
in a plane above them as is the case with some quadrupeds. Of 
ears, some are fine, some are coarse, and some are of medium 
texture; the last kind are best for hearing, but they serve in no 
way to indicate character. Some ears are large, some small, 
some medium-sized; again, some stand out far, some lie in 
close and tight, and some take up a medium position; of these 
such as are of medium size and of medium position are 
indications of the best disposition, while the large and 
outstanding ones indicate a tendency to irrelevant talk or 
chattering. The part intercepted between the eye, the ear, and 
the crown is termed the 'temple'. Again, there is a part of the 
countenance that serves as a passage for the breath, the 'nose'. 
For a man inhales and exhales by this organ, and sneezing is 
effected by its means: which last is an outward rush of collected 
breath, and is the only mode of breath used as an omen and 
regarded as supernatural. Both inhalation and exhalation go 
right on from the nose towards the chest; and with the nostrils 
alone and separately it is impossible to inhale or exhale, owing 
to the fact that the inspiration and respiration take place from 
the chest along the windpipe, and not by any portion connected 
with the head; and indeed it is possible for a creature to live 
without using this process of nasal respiration. 

Again, smelling takes place by means of the nose, - smelling, or 
the sensible discrimination of odour. And the nostril admits of 
easy motion, and is not, like the ear, intrinsically immovable. A 
part of it, composed of gristle, constitutes, a septum or partition, 
and part is an open passage; for the nostril consists of two 
separate channels. The nostril (or nose) of the elephant is long 
and strong, and the animal uses it like a hand; for by means of 
this organ it draws objects towards it, and takes hold of them, 



1409 



and introduces its food into its mouth, whether liquid or dry 
food, and it is the only living creature that does so. 

Furthermore, there are two jaws; the front part of them 
constitutes the chin, and the hinder part the cheek. All animals 
move the lower jaw, with the exception of the river crocodile; 
this creature moves the upper jaw only. 

Next after the nose come two lips, composed of flesh, and facile 
of motion. The mouth lies inside the jaws and lips. Parts of the 
mouth are the roof or palate and the pharynx. 

The part that is sensible of taste is the tongue. The sensation 
has its seat at the tip of the tongue; if the object to be tasted be 
placed on the flat surface of the organ, the taste is less sensibly 
experienced. The tongue is sensitive in all other ways wherein 
flesh in general is so: that is, it can appreciate hardness, or 
warmth and cold, in any part of it, just as it can appreciate taste. 
The tongue is sometimes broad, sometimes narrow, and 
sometimes of medium width; the last kind is the best and the 
clearest in its discrimination of taste. Moreover, the tongue is 
sometimes loosely hung, and sometimes fastened: as in the 
case of those who mumble and who lisp. 

The tongue consists of flesh, soft and spongy, and the so-called 
'epiglottis' is a part of this organ. 

That part of the mouth that splits into two bits is called the 
'tonsils'; that part that splits into many bits, the 'gums'. Both 
the tonsils and the gums are composed of flesh. In the gums are 
teeth, composed of bone. 

Inside the mouth is another part, shaped like a bunch of grapes, 
a pillar streaked with veins. If this pillar gets relaxed and 
inflamed it is called 'uvula' or 'bunch of grapes', and it then has 
a tendency to bring about suffocation. 



1410 



12 

The neck is the part between the face and the trunk. Of this the 
front part is the larynx land the back part the ur The front part, 
composed of gristle, through which respiration and speech is 
effected, is termed the 'windpipe'; the part that is fleshy is the 
oesophagus, inside just in front of the chine. The part to the 
back of the neck is the epomis, or 'shoulder-point'. 

These then are the parts to be met with before you come to the 
thorax. 

To the trunk there is a front part and a back part. Next after the 
neck in the front part is the chest, with a pair of breasts. To each 
of the breasts is attached a teat or nipple, through which in the 
case of females the milk percolates; and the breast is of a 
spongy texture. Milk, by the way, is found at times in the male; 
but with the male the flesh of the breast is tough, with the 
female it is soft and porous. 



13 

Next after the thorax and in front comes the 'belly', and its root 
the 'navel'. Underneath this root the bilateral part is the 'flank': 
the undivided part below the navel, the 'abdomen', the 
extremity of which is the region of the 'pubes'; above the navel 
the 'hypochondrium'; the cavity common to the hypochondrium 
and the flank is the gut-cavity. 



1411 



Serving as a brace girdle to the hinder parts is the pelvis, and 
hence it gets its name (osphus), for it is symmetrical (isophues) 
in appearance; of the fundament the part for resting on is 
termed the 'rump', and the part whereon the thigh pivots is 
termed the 'socket' (or acetabulum). 

The 'womb' is a part peculiar to the female; and the 'penis' is 
peculiar to the male. This latter organ is external and situated at 
the extremity of the trunk; it is composed of two separate parts: 
of which the extreme part is fleshy, does not alter in size, and is 
called the glans; and round about it is a skin devoid of any 
specific title, which integument if it be cut asunder never grows 
together again, any more than does the jaw or the eyelid. And 
the connexion between the latter and the glans is called the 
frenum. The remaining part of the penis is composed of gristle; 
it is easily susceptible of enlargement; and it protrudes and 
recedes in the reverse directions to what is observable in the 
identical organ in cats. Underneath the penis are two 'testicles', 
and the integument of these is a skin that is termed the 
'scrotum'. 

Testicles are not identical with flesh, and are not altogether 
diverse from it. But by and by we shall treat in an exhaustive 
way regarding all such parts. 



14 

The privy part of the female is in character opposite to that of 
the male. In other words, the part under the pubes is hollow or 
receding, and not, like the male organ, protruding. Further, there 
is an 'urethra' outside the womb; which organ serves as a 
passage for the sperm of the male, and as an outlet for liquid 
excretion to both sexes). 



1412 



The part common to the neck and chest is the 'throat'; the 
'armpit' is common to side, arm, and shoulder; and the 'groin' is 
common to thigh and abdomen. The part inside the thigh and 
buttocks is the 'perineum', and the part outside the thigh and 
buttocks is the 'hypoglutis'. 

The front parts of the trunk have now been enumerated. 

The part behind the chest is termed the 'back'. 



15 

Parts of the back are a pair of 'shoulderblades', the 'back-bone', 
and, underneath on a level with the belly in the trunk, the 
'loins'. Common to the upper and lower part of the trunk are 
the 'ribs', eight on either side, for as to the so-called seven- 
ribbed Ligyans we have not received any trustworthy evidence. 

Man, then, has an upper and a lower part, a front and a back 
part, a right and a left side. Now the right and the left side are 
pretty well alike in their parts and identical throughout, except 
that the left side is the weaker of the two; but the back parts do 
not resemble the front ones, neither do the lower ones the 
upper: only that these upper and lower parts may be said to 
resemble one another thus far, that, if the face be plump or 
meagre, the abdomen is plump or meagre to correspond; and 
that the legs correspond to the arms, and where the upper arm 
is short the thigh is usually short also, and where the feet are 
small the hands are small correspondingly. 

Of the limbs, one set, forming a pair, is 'arms'. To the arm belong 
the 'shoulder', 'upper-arm', 'elbow', 'fore-arm', and 'hand'. To the 
hand belong the 'palm', and the five 'fingers'. The part of the 



1413 



finger that bends is termed 'knuckle', the part that is inflexible 
is termed the 'phalanx'. The big finger or thumb is single- 
jointed, the other fingers are double jointed. The bending both 
of the arm and of the finger takes place from without inwards 
in all cases; and the arm bends at the elbow. The inner part of 
the hand is termed the palm', and is fleshy and divided by joints 
or lines: in the case of long-lived people by one or two 
extending right across, in the case of the short-lived by two, not 
so extending. The joint between hand and arm is termed the 
'wrist'. The outside or back of the hand is sinewy, and has no 
specific designation. 

There is another duplicate limb, the 'leg'. Of this limb the 
double-knobbed part is termed the 'thigh-bone', the sliding part 
of the 'kneecap', the double-boned part the 'leg'; the front part 
of this latter is termed the 'shin', and the part behind it the 
'calf, wherein the flesh is sinewy and venous, in some cases 
drawn upwards towards the hollow behind the knee, as in the 
case of people with large hips, and in other cases drawn 
downwards. The lower extremity of the shin is the 'ankle', 
duplicate in either leg. The part of the limb that contains a 
multiplicity of bones is the 'foot'. The hinder part of the foot is 
the 'heel'; at the front of it the divided part consists of 'toes', 
five in number; the fleshy part underneath is the 'ball'; the 
upper part or back of the foot is sinewy and has no particular 
appellation; of the toe, one portion is the 'nail' and another the 
'joint', and the nail is in all cases at the extremity; and toes are 
without exception single jointed. Men that have the inside or 
sole of the foot clumsy and not arched, that is, that walk resting 
on the entire under-surface of their feet, are prone to roguery. 
The joint common to thigh and shin is the 'knee'. 

These, then, are the parts common to the male and the female 
sex. The relative position of the parts as to up and down, or to 
front and back, or to right and left, all this as regards externals 



1414 



might safely be left to mere ordinary perception. But for all that, 
we must treat of them for the same reason as the one 
previously brought forward; that is to say, we must refer to them 
in order that a due and regular sequence may be observed in 
our exposition, and in order that by the enumeration of these 
obvious facts due attention may be subsequently given to those 
parts in men and other animals that are diverse in any way 
from one another. 

In man, above all other animals, the terms 'upper' and 'lower' 
are used in harmony with their natural positions; for in him, 
upper and lower have the same meaning as when they are 
applied to the universe as a whole. In like manner the terms, 'in 
front', 'behind', 'right' and 'left', are used in accordance with 
their natural sense. But in regard to other animals, in some 
cases these distinctions do not exist, and in others they do so, 
but in a vague way. For instance, the head with all animals is up 
and above in respect to their bodies; but man alone, as has been 
said, has, in maturity, this part uppermost in respect to the 
material universe. 

Next after the head comes the neck, and then the chest and the 
back: the one in front and the other behind. Next after these 
come the belly, the loins, the sexual parts, and the haunches; 
then the thigh and shin; and, lastly, the feet. 

The legs bend frontwards, in the direction of actual progression, 
and frontwards also lies that part of the foot which is the most 
effective of motion, and the flexure of that part; but the heel lies 
at the back, and the anklebones lie laterally, earwise. The arms 
are situated to right and left, and bend inwards: so that the 
convexities formed by bent arms and legs are practically face to 
face with one another in the case of man. 

As for the senses and for the organs of sensation, the eyes, the 
nostrils, and the tongue, all alike are situated frontwards; the 



1415 



sense of hearing, and the organ of hearing, the ear, is situated 
sideways, on the same horizontal plane with the eyes. The eyes 
in man are, in proportion to his size, nearer to one another than 
in any other animal. 

Of the senses man has the sense of touch more refined than 
any animal, and so also, but in less degree, the sense of taste; in 
the development of the other senses he is surpassed by a great 
number of animals. 



16 

The parts, then, that are externally visible are arranged in the 
way above stated, and as a rule have their special designations, 
and from use and wont are known familiarly to all; but this is 
not the case with the inner parts. For the fact is that the inner 
parts of man are to a very great extent unknown, and the 
consequence is that we must have recourse to an examination 
of the inner parts of other animals whose nature in any way 
resembles that of man. 

In the first place then, the brain lies in the front part of the 
head. And this holds alike with all animals possessed of a brain; 
and all blooded animals are possessed thereof, and, by the way, 
molluscs as well. But, taking size for size of animal, the largest 
brain, and the moistest, is that of man. Two membranes enclose 
it: the stronger one near the bone of the skull; the inner one, 
round the brain itself, is finer. The brain in all cases is bilateral. 
Behind this, right at the back, comes what is termed the 
'cerebellum', differing in form from the brain as we may both 
feel and see. 



1416 



The back of the head is with all animals empty and hollow, 
whatever be its size in the different animals. For some creatures 
have big heads while the face below is small in proportion, as is 
the case with round-faced animals; some have little heads and 
long jaws, as is the case, without exception, among animals of 
the mane-and-tail species. 

The brain in all animals is bloodless, devoid of veins, and 
naturally cold to the touch; in the great majority of animals it 
has a small hollow in its centre. The brain-caul around it is 
reticulated with veins; and this brain-caul is that skin-like 
membrane which closely surrounds the brain. Above the brain 
is the thinnest and weakest bone of the head, which is termed 
or 'sinciput'. 

From the eye there go three ducts to the brain: the largest and 
the medium-sized to the cerebellum, the least to the brain 
itself; and the least is the one situated nearest to the nostril. 
The two largest ones, then, run side by side and do not meet; 
the medium-sized ones meet - and this is particularly visible in 
fishes, - for they lie nearer than the large ones to the brain; the 
smallest pair are the most widely separate from one another, 
and do not meet. 

Inside the neck is what is termed the oesophagus (whose other 
name is derived oesophagus from its length and narrowness), 
and the windpipe. The windpipe is situated in front of the 
oesophagus in all animals that have a windpipe, and all animals 
have one that are furnished with lungs. The windpipe is made 
up of gristle, is sparingly supplied with blood, and is streaked all 
round with numerous minute veins; it is situated, in its upper 
part, near the mouth, below the aperture formed by the nostrils 
into the mouth - an aperture through which, when men, in 
drinking, inhale any of the liquid, this liquid finds its way out 
through the nostrils. In betwixt the two openings comes the so- 



1417 



called epiglottis, an organ capable of being drawn over and 
covering the orifice of the windpipe communicating with the 
mouth; the end of the tongue is attached to the epiglottis. In the 
other direction the windpipe extends to the interval between 
the lungs, and hereupon bifurcates into each of the two 
divisions of the lung; for the lung in all animals possessed of 
the organ has a tendency to be double. In viviparous animals, 
however, the duplication is not so plainly discernible as in other 
species, and the duplication is least discernible in man. And in 
man the organ is not split into many parts, as is the case with 
some vivipara, neither is it smooth, but its surface is uneven. 

In the case of the ovipara, such as birds and oviparous 
quadrupeds, the two parts of the organ are separated to a 
distance from one another, so that the creatures appear to be 
furnished with a pair of lungs; and from the windpipe, itself 
single, there branch off two separate parts extending to each of 
the two divisions of the lung. It is attached also to the great vein 
and to what is designated the 'aorta'. When the windpipe is 
charged with air, the air passes on to the hollow parts of the 
lung. These parts have divisions, composed of gristle, which 
meet at an acute angle; from the divisions run passages through 
the entire lung, giving off smaller and smaller ramifications. 
The heart also is attached to the windpipe, by connexions of fat, 
gristle, and sinew; and at the point of juncture there is a hollow. 
When the windpipe is charged with air, the entrance of the air 
into the heart, though imperceptible in some animals, is 
perceptible enough in the larger ones. Such are the properties of 
the windpipe, and it takes in and throws out air only, and takes 
in nothing else either dry or liquid, or else it causes you pain 
until you shall have coughed up whatever may have gone down. 

The oesophagus communicates at the top with the mouth, close 
to the windpipe, and is attached to the backbone and the 
windpipe by membranous ligaments, and at last finds its way 



1418 



through the midriff into the belly. It is composed of flesh-like 
substance, and is elastic both lengthways and breadthways. 

The stomach of man resembles that of a dog; for it is not much 
bigger than the bowel, but is somewhat like a bowel of more 
than usual width; then comes the bowel, single, convoluted, 
moderately wide. The lower part of the gut is like that of a pig; 
for it is broad, and the part from it to the buttocks is thick and 
short. The caul, or great omentum, is attached to the middle of 
the stomach, and consists of a fatty membrane, as is the case 
with all other animals whose stomachs are single and which 
have teeth in both jaws. 

The mesentery is over the bowels; this also is membranous and 
broad, and turns to fat. It is attached to the great vein and the 
aorta, and there run through it a number of veins closely packed 
together, extending towards the region of the bowels, beginning 
above and ending below. 

So much for the properties of the oesophagus, the windpipe, 
and the stomach. 



17 

The heart has three cavities, and is situated above the lung at 
the division of the windpipe, and is provided with a fatty and 
thick membrane where it fastens on to the great vein and the 
aorta. It lies with its tapering portion upon the aorta, and this 
portion is similarly situated in relation to the chest in all 
animals that have a chest. In all animals alike, in those that 
have a chest and in those that have none, the apex of the heart 
points forwards, although this fact might possibly escape notice 
by a change of position under dissection. The rounded end of 



1419 



the heart is at the top. The apex is to a great extent fleshy and 
close in texture, and in the cavities of the heart are sinews. As a 
rule the heart is situated in the middle of the chest in animals 
that have a chest, and in man it is situated a little to the left- 
hand side, leaning a little way from the division of the breasts 
towards the left breast in the upper part of the chest. 

The heart is not large, and in its general shape it is not 
elongated; in fact, it is somewhat round in form: only, be it 
remembered, it is sharp-pointed at the bottom. It has three 
cavities, as has been said: the right-hand one the largest of the 
three, the left-hand one the least, and the middle one 
intermediate in size. All these cavities, even the two small ones, 
are connected by passages with the lung, and this fact is 
rendered quite plain in one of the cavities. And below, at the 
point of attachment, in the largest cavity there is a connexion 
with the great vein (near which the mesentery lies); and in the 
middle one there is a connexion with the aorta. 

Canals lead from the heart into the lung, and branch off just as 
the windpipe does, running all over the lung parallel with the 
passages from the windpipe. The canals from the heart are 
uppermost; and there is no common passage, but the passages 
through their having a common wall receive the breath and 
pass it on to the heart; and one of the passages conveys it to the 
right cavity, and the other to the left. 

With regard to the great vein and the aorta we shall, by and by, 
treat of them together in a discussion devoted to them and to 
them alone. In all animals that are furnished with a lung, and 
that are both internally and externally viviparous, the lung is of 
all organs the most richly supplied with blood; for the lung is 
throughout spongy in texture, and along by every single pore in 
it go branches from the great vein. Those who imagine it to be 
empty are altogether mistaken; and they are led into their error 



1420 



by their observation of lungs removed from animals under 
dissection, out of which organs the blood had all escaped 
immediately after death. 

Of the other internal organs the heart alone contains blood. And 
the lung has blood not in itself but in its veins, but the heart has 
blood in itself; for in each of its three cavities it has blood, but 
the thinnest blood is what it has in its central cavity. 

Under the lung comes the thoracic diaphragm or midriff, 
attached to the ribs, the hypochondria and the backbone, with a 
thin membrane in the middle of it. It has veins running through 
it; and the diaphragm in the case of man is thicker in 
proportion to the size of his frame than in other animals. 

Under the diaphragm on the right-hand side lies the 'liver', and 
on the left-hand side the 'spleen', alike in all animals that are 
provided with these organs in an ordinary and not preternatural 
way; for, be it observed, in some quadrupeds these organs have 
been found in a transposed position. These organs are 
connected with the stomach by the caul. 

To outward view the spleen of man is narrow and long, 
resembling the self-same organ in the pig. The liver in the great 
majority of animals is not provided with a 'gall-bladder'; but the 
latter is present in some. The liver of a man is round-shaped, 
and resembles the same organ in the ox. And, by the way, the 
absence above referred to of a gall-bladder is at times met with 
in the practice of augury. For instance, in a certain district of the 
Chalcidic settlement in Euboea the sheep are devoid of gall- 
bladders; and in Naxos nearly all the quadrupeds have one so 
large that foreigners when they offer sacrifice with such victims 
are bewildered with fright, under the impression that the 
phenomenon is not due to natural causes, but bodes some 
mischief to the individual offerers of the sacrifice. 



1421 



Again, the liver is attached to the great vein, but it has no 
communication with the aorta; for the vein that goes off from 
the great vein goes right through the liver, at a point where are 
the so-called 'portals' of the liver. The spleen also is connected 
only with the great vein, for a vein extends to the spleen off 
from it. 

After these organs come the 'kidneys', and these are placed 
close to the backbone, and resemble in character the same 
organ in kine. In all animals that are provided with this organ, 
the right kidney is situated higher up than the other. It has also 
less fatty substance than the left-hand one and is less moist. 
And this phenomenon also is observable in all the other 
animals alike. 

Furthermore, passages or ducts lead into the kidneys both from 
the great vein and from the aorta, only not into the cavity. For, 
by the way, there is a cavity in the middle of the kidney, bigger 
in some creatures and less in others; but there is none in the 
case of the seal. This latter animal has kidneys resembling in 
shape the identical organ in kine, but in its case the organs are 
more solid than in any other known creature. The ducts that 
lead into the kidneys lose themselves in the substance of the 
kidneys themselves; and the proof that they extend no farther 
rests on the fact that they contain no blood, nor is any clot 
found therein. The kidneys, however, have, as has been said, a 
small cavity. From this cavity in the kidney there lead two 
considerable ducts or ureters into the bladder; and others spring 
from the aorta, strong and continuous. And to the middle of 
each of the two kidneys is attached a hollow sinewy vein, 
stretching right along the spine through the narrows; by and by 
these veins are lost in either loin, and again become visible 
extending to the flank. And these off-branchings of the veins 
terminate in the bladder. For the bladder lies at the extremity, 
and is held in position by the ducts stretching from the kidneys, 



1422 



along the stalk that extends to the urethra; and pretty well all 
round it is fastened by fine sinewy membranes, that resemble to 
some extent the thoracic diaphragm. The bladder in man is, 
proportionately to his size, tolerably large. 

To the stalk of the bladder the private part is attached, the 
external orifices coalescing; but a little lower down, one of the 
openings communicates with the testicles and the other with 
the bladder. The penis is gristly and sinewy in its texture. With it 
are connected the testicles in male animals, and the properties 
of these organs we shall discuss in our general account of the 
said organ. 

All these organs are similar in the female; for there is no 
difference in regard to the internal organs, except in respect to 
the womb, and with reference to the appearance of this organ I 
must refer the reader to diagrams in my 'Anatomy'. The womb, 
however, is situated over the bowel, and the bladder lies over 
the womb. But we must treat by and by in our pages of the 
womb of all female animals viewed generally. For the wombs of 
all female animals are not identical, neither do their local 
dispositions coincide. 

These are the organs, internal and external, of man, and such is 
their nature and such their local disposition. 



1423 



Book II 



With regard to animals in general, some parts or organs are 
common to all, as has been said, and some are common only to 
particular genera; the parts, moreover, are identical with or 
different from one another on the lines already repeatedly laid 
down. For as a general rule all animals that are generically 
distinct have the majority of their parts or organs different in 
form or species; and some of them they have only analogically 
similar and diverse in kind or genus, while they have others 
that are alike in kind but specifically diverse; and many parts or 
organs exist in some animals, but not in others. 

For instance, viviparous quadrupeds have all a head and a neck, 
and all the parts or organs of the head, but they differ each from 
other in the shapes of the parts. The lion has its neck composed 
of one single bone instead of vertebrae; but, when dissected, the 
animal is found in all internal characters to resemble the dog. 

The quadrupedal vivipara instead of arms have forelegs. This is 
true of all quadrupeds, but such of them as have toes have, 
practically speaking, organs analogous to hands; at all events, 
they use these fore-limbs for many purposes as hands. And they 
have the limbs on the left-hand side less distinct from those on 
the right than man. 

The fore-limbs then serve more or less the purpose of hands in 
quadrupeds, with the exception of the elephant. This latter 
animal has its toes somewhat indistinctly defined, and its front 
legs are much bigger than its hinder ones; it is five-toed, and 
has short ankles to its hind feet. But it has a nose such in 



1424 



properties and such in size as to allow of its using the same for 
a hand. For it eats and drinks by lifting up its food with the aid 
of this organ into its mouth, and with the same organ it lifts up 
articles to the driver on its back; with this organ it can pluck up 
trees by the roots, and when walking through water it spouts 
the water up by means of it; and this organ is capable of being 
crooked or coiled at the tip, but not of flexing like a joint, for it is 
composed of gristle. 

Of all animals man alone can learn to make equal use of both 
hands. 

All animals have a part analogous to the chest in man, but not 
similar to his; for the chest in man is broad, but that of all other 
animals is narrow. Moreover, no other animal but man has 
breasts in front; the elephant, certainly, has two breasts, not 
however in the chest, but near it. 

Moreover, also, animals have the flexions of their fore and hind 
limbs in directions opposite to one another, and in directions 
the reverse of those observed in the arms and legs of man; with 
the exception of the elephant. In other words, with the 
viviparous quadrupeds the front legs bend forwards and the 
hind ones backwards, and the concavities of the two pairs of 
limbs thus face one another. 

The elephant does not sleep standing, as some were wont to 
assert, but it bends its legs and settles down; only that in 
consequence of its weight it cannot bend its leg on both sides 
simultaneously, but falls into a recumbent position on one side 
or the other, and in this position it goes to sleep. And it bends 
its hind legs just as a man bends his legs. 

In the case of the ovipara, as the crocodile and the lizard and 
the like, both pairs of legs, fore and hind, bend forwards, with a 
slight swerve on one side. The flexion is similar in the case of 



1425 



the multipeds; only that the legs in between the extreme ends 
always move in a manner intermediate between that of those in 
front and those behind, and accordingly bend sideways rather 
than backwards or forwards. But man bends his arms and his 
legs towards the same point, and therefore in opposite ways: 
that is to say, he bends his arms backwards, with just a slight 
inclination inwards, and his legs frontwards. No animal bends 
both its fore-limbs and hind-limbs backwards; but in the case of 
all animals the flexion of the shoulders is in the opposite 
direction to that of the elbows or the joints of the forelegs, and 
the flexure in the hips to that of the knees of the hind-legs: so 
that since man differs from other animals in flexion, those 
animals that possess such parts as these move them 
contrariwise to man. 

Birds have the flexions of their limbs like those of the 
quadrupeds; for, although bipeds, they bend their legs 
backwards, and instead of arms or front legs have wings which 
bend frontwards. 

The seal is a kind of imperfect or crippled quadruped; for just 
behind the shoulder-blade its front feet are placed, resembling 
hands, like the front paws of the bear; for they are furnished 
with five toes, and each of the toes has three flexions and a nail 
of inconsiderable size. The hind feet are also furnished with five 
toes; in their flexions and nails they resemble the front feet, and 
in shape they resemble a fish's tail. 

The movements of animals, quadruped and multiped, are 
crosswise, or in diagonals, and their equilibrium in standing 
posture is maintained crosswise; and it is always the limb on 
the right-hand side that is the first to move. The lion, however, 
and the two species of camels, both the Bactrian and the 
Arabian, progress by an amble; and the action so called is when 



1426 



the animal never overpasses the right with the left, but always 
follows close upon it. 

Whatever parts men have in front, these parts quadrupeds have 
below, in or on the belly; and whatever parts men have behind, 
these parts quadrupeds have above on their backs. Most 
quadrupeds have a tail; for even the seal has a tiny one 
resembling that of the stag. Regarding the tails of the pithecoids 
we must give their distinctive properties by and by animal 

All viviparous quadrupeds are hair-coated, whereas man has 
only a few short hairs excepting on the head, but, so far as the 
head is concerned, he is hairier than any other animal. Further, 
of hair-coated animals, the back is hairier than the belly, which 
latter is either comparatively void of hair or smooth and void of 
hair altogether. With man the reverse is the case. 

Man also has upper and lower eyelashes, and hair under the 
armpits and on the pubes. No other animal has hair in either of 
these localities, or has an under eyelash; though in the case of 
some animals a few straggling hairs grow under the eyelid. 

Of hair-coated quadrupeds some are hairy all over the body, as 
the pig, the bear, and the dog; others are especially hairy on the 
neck and all round about it, as is the case with animals that 
have a shaggy mane, such as the lion; others again are 
especially hairy on the upper surface of the neck from the head 
as far as the withers, namely, such as have a crested mane, as in 
the case with the horse, the mule, and, among the 
undomesticated horned animals, the bison. 

The so-called hippelaphus also has a mane on its withers, and 
the animal called pardion, in either case a thin mane extending 
from the head to the withers; the hippelaphus has, 
exceptionally, a beard by the larynx. Both these animals have 
horns and are cloven-footed; the female, however, of the 



1427 



hippelaphus has no horns. This latter animal resembles the stag 
in size; it is found in the territory of the Arachotae, where the 
wild cattle also are found. Wild cattle differ from their 
domesticated congeners just as the wild boar differs from the 
domesticated one. That is to say they are black, strong looking, 
with a hook-nosed muzzle, and with horns lying more over the 
back. The horns of the hippelaphus resemble those of the 
gazelle. 

The elephant, by the way, is the least hairy of all quadrupeds. 
With animals, as a general rule, the tail corresponds with the 
body as regards thickness or thinness of hair-coating; that is, 
with animals that have long tails, for some creatures have tails 
of altogether insignificant size. 

Camels have an exceptional organ wherein they differ from all 
other animals, and that is the so-called 'hump' on their back. 
The Bactrian camel differs from the Arabian; for the former has 
two humps and the latter only one, though it has, by the way, a 
kind of a hump below like the one above, on which, when it 
kneels, the weight of the whole body rests. The camel has four 
teats like the cow, a tail like that of an ass, and the privy parts of 
the male are directed backwards. It has one knee in each leg, 
and the flexures of the limb are not manifold, as some say, 
although they appear to be so from the constricted shape of the 
region of the belly. It has a huckle-bone like that of kine, but 
meagre and small in proportion to its bulk. It is cloven-footed, 
and has not got teeth in both jaws; and it is cloven footed in the 
following way: at the back there is a slight cleft extending as far 
up as the second joint of the toes; and in front there are small 
hooves on the tip of the first joint of the toes; and a sort of web 
passes across the cleft, as in geese. The foot is fleshy 
underneath, like that of the bear; so that, when the animal goes 
to war, they protect its feet, when they get sore, with sandals. 



1428 



The legs of all quadrupeds are bony, sinewy, and fleshless; and 
in point of fact such is the case with all animals that are 
furnished with feet, with the exception of man. They are also 
unfurnished with buttocks; and this last point is plain in an 
especial degree in birds. It is the reverse with man; for there is 
scarcely any part of the body in which man is so fleshy as in the 
buttock, the thigh, and the calf; for the part of the leg called 
gastroenemia or is fleshy. 

Of blooded and viviparous quadrupeds some have the foot 
cloven into many parts, as is the case with the hands and feet of 
man (for some animals, by the way, are many-toed, as the lion, 
the dog, and the pard); others have feet cloven in twain, and 
instead of nails have hooves, as the sheep, the goat, the deer, 
and the hippopotamus; others are uncloven of foot, such for 
instance as the solid-hooved animals, the horse and the mule. 
Swine are either cloven-footed or uncloven-footed; for there are 
in Illyria and in Paeonia and elsewhere solid-hooved swine. The 
cloven-footed animals have two clefts behind; in the solid- 
hooved this part is continuous and undivided. 

Furthermore, of animals some are horned, and some are not so. 
The great majority of the horned animals are cloven-footed, as 
the ox, the stag, the goat; and a solid-hooved animal with a pair 
of horns has never yet been met with. But a few animals are 
known to be singled-horned and single-hooved, as the Indian 
ass; and one, to wit the oryx, is single horned and cloven- 
hooved. 

Of all solid-hooved animals the Indian ass alone has an 
astragalus or huckle-bone; for the pig, as was said above, is 
either solid-hooved or cloven-footed, and consequently has no 
well-formed huckle-bone. Of the cloven footed many are 
provided with a huckle-bone. Of the many-fingered or many- 
toed, no single one has been observed to have a huckle-bone, 



1429 



none of the others any more than man. The lynx, however, has 
something like a hemiastragal, and the lion something 
resembling the sculptor's 'labyrinth'. All the animals that have a 
huckle-bone have it in the hinder legs. They have also the bone 
placed straight up in the joint; the upper part, outside; the lower 
part, inside; the sides called Coa turned towards one another, 
the sides called Chia outside, and the keraiae or 'horns' on the 
top. This, then, is the position of the hucklebone in the case of 
all animals provided with the part. 

Some animals are, at one and the same time, furnished with a 
mane and furnished also with a pair of horns bent in towards 
one another, as is the bison (or aurochs), which is found in 
Paeonia and Maedica. But all animals that are horned are 
quadrupedal, except in cases where a creature is said 
metaphorically, or by a figure of speech, to have horns; just as 
the Egyptians describe the serpents found in the neighbourhood 
of Thebes, while in point of fact the creatures have merely 
protuberances on the head sufficiently large to suggest such an 
epithet. 

Of horned animals the deer alone has a horn, or antler, hard 
and solid throughout. The horns of other animals are hollow for 
a certain distance, and solid towards the extremity. The hollow 
part is derived from the skin, but the core round which this is 
wrapped - the hard part - is derived from the bones; as is the 
case with the horns of oxen. The deer is the only animal that 
sheds its horns, and it does so annually, after reaching the age 
of two years, and again renews them. All other animals retain 
their horns permanently, unless the horns be damaged by 
accident. 

Again, with regard to the breasts and the generative organs, 
animals differ widely from one another and from man. For 
instance, the breasts of some animals are situated in front, 



1430 



either in the chest or near to it, and there are in such cases two 
breasts and two teats, as is the case with man and the elephant, 
as previously stated. For the elephant has two breasts in the 
region of the axillae; and the female elephant has two breasts 
insignificant in size and in no way proportionate to the bulk of 
the entire frame, in fact, so insignificant as to be invisible in a 
sideways view; the males also have breasts, like the females, 
exceedingly small. The she-bear has four breasts. Some animals 
have two breasts, but situated near the thighs, and teats, 
likewise two in number, as the sheep; others have four teats, as 
the cow. Some have breasts neither in the chest nor at the 
thighs, but in the belly, as the dog and pig; and they have a 
considerable number of breasts or dugs, but not all of equal size. 
Thus the shepard has four dugs in the belly, the lioness two, and 
others more. The she-camel, also, has two dugs and four teats, 
like the cow. Of solid-hooved animals the males have no dugs, 
excepting in the case of males that take after the mother, which 
phenomenon is observable in horses. 

Of male animals the genitals of some are external, as is the case 
with man, the horse, and most other creatures; some are 
internal, as with the dolphin. With those that have the organ 
externally placed, the organ in some cases is situated in front, 
as in the cases already mentioned, and of these some have the 
organ detached, both penis and testicles, as man; others have 
penis and testicles closely attached to the belly, some more 
closely, some less; for this organ is not detached in the wild 
boar nor in the horse. 

The penis of the elephant resembles that of the horse; 
compared with the size of the animal it is disproportionately 
small; the testicles are not visible, but are concealed inside in 
the vicinity of the kidneys; and for this reason the male speedily 
gives over in the act of intercourse. The genitals of the female 
are situated where the udder is in sheep; when she is in heat, 



1431 



she draws the organ back and exposes it externally, to facilitate 
the act of intercourse for the male; and the organ opens out to a 
considerable extent. 

With most animals the genitals have the position above 
assigned; but some animals discharge their urine backwards, as 
the lynx, the lion, the camel, and the hare. Male animals differ 
from one another, as has been said, in this particular, but all 
female animals are retromingent: even the female elephant like 
other animals, though she has the privy part below the thighs. 

In the male organ itself there is a great diversity. For in some 
cases the organ is composed of flesh and gristle, as in man; in 
such cases, the fleshy part does not become inflated, but the 
gristly part is subject to enlargement. In other cases, the organ 
is composed of fibrous tissue, as with the camel and the deer; in 
other cases it is bony, as with the fox, the wolf, the marten, and 
the weasel; for this organ in the weasel has a bone. 

When man has arrived at maturity, his upper part is smaller 
than the lower one, but with all other blooded animals the 
reverse holds good. By the 'upper' part we mean all extending 
from the head down to the parts used for excretion of residuum, 
and by the 'lower' part else. With animals that have feet the 
hind legs are to be rated as the lower part in our comparison of 
magnitudes, and with animals devoid of feet, the tail, and the 
like. 

When animals arrive at maturity, their properties are as above 
stated; but they differ greatly from one another in their growth 
towards maturity. For instance, man, when young, has his upper 
part larger than the lower, but in course of growth he comes to 
reverse this condition; and it is owing to this circumstance that 
- an exceptional instance, by the way - he does not progress in 
early life as he does at maturity, but in infancy creeps on all 
fours; but some animals, in growth, retain the relative 



1432 



proportion of the parts, as the dog. Some animals at first have 
the upper part smaller and the lower part larger, and in course 
of growth the upper part gets to be the larger, as is the case with 
the bushy-tailed animals such as the horse; for in their case 
there is never, subsequently to birth, any increase in the part 
extending from the hoof to the haunch. 

Again, in respect to the teeth, animals differ greatly both from 
one another and from man. All animals that are quadrupedal, 
blooded and viviparous, are furnished with teeth; but, to begin 
with, some are double-toothed (or fully furnished with teeth in 
both jaws), and some are not. For instance, horned quadrupeds 
are not double-toothed; for they have not got the front teeth in 
the upper jaw; and some hornless animals, also, are not double 
toothed, as the camel. Some animals have tusks, like the boar, 
and some have not. Further, some animals are saw-toothed, 
such as the lion, the pard, and the dog; and some have teeth 
that do not interlock but have flat opposing crowns, as the 
horse and the ox; and by 'saw-toothed' we mean such animals 
as interlock the sharp-pointed teeth in one jaw between the 
sharp-pointed ones in the other. No animal is there that 
possesses both tusks and horns, nor yet do either of these 
structures exist in any animal possessed of 'saw-teeth'. The 
front teeth are usually sharp, and the back ones blunt. The seal 
is saw-toothed throughout, inasmuch as he is a sort of link with 
the class of fishes; for fishes are almost all saw-toothed. 

No animal of these genera is provided with double rows of 
teeth. There is, however, an animal of the sort, if we are to 
believe Ctesias. He assures us that the Indian wild beast called 
the 'martichoras' has a triple row of teeth in both upper and 
lower jaw; that it is as big as a lion and equally hairy, and that 
its feet resemble those of the lion; that it resembles man in its 
face and ears; that its eyes are blue, and its colour vermilion; 
that its tail is like that of the land-scorpion; that it has a sting in 



1433 



the tail, and has the faculty of shooting off arrow-wise the 
spines that are attached to the tail; that the sound of its voice is 
a something between the sound of a pan-pipe and that of a 
trumpet; that it can run as swiftly as deer, and that it is savage 
and a man-eater. 

Man sheds his teeth, and so do other animals, as the horse, the 
mule, and the ass. And man sheds his front teeth; but there is 
no instance of an animal that sheds its molars. The pig sheds 
none of its teeth at all. 



With regard to dogs some doubts are entertained, as some 
contend that they shed no teeth whatever, and others that they 
shed the canines, but those alone; the fact being, that they do 
shed their teeth like man, but that the circumstance escapes 
observation, owing to the fact that they never shed them until 
equivalent teeth have grown within the gums to take the place 
of the shed ones. We shall be justified in supposing that the 
case is similar with wild beasts in general; for they are said to 
shed their canines only. Dogs can be distinguished from one 
another, the young from the old, by their teeth; for the teeth in 
young dogs are white and sharp-pointed; in old dogs, black and 
blunt. 



1434 



In this particular, the horse differs entirely from animals in 
general: for, generally speaking, as animals grow older their 
teeth get blacker, but the horse's teeth grow whiter with age. 

The so-called 'canines' come in between the sharp teeth and 
the broad or blunt ones, partaking of the form of both kinds; for 
they are broad at the base and sharp at the tip. 

Males have more teeth than females in the case of men, sheep, 
goats, and swine; in the case of other animals observations have 
not yet been made: but the more teeth they have the more long- 
lived are they, as a rule, while those are short-lived in 
proportion that have teeth fewer in number and thinly set. 



The last teeth to come in man are molars called 'wisdom-teeth', 
which come at the age of twenty years, in the case of both 
sexes. Cases have been known in women upwards, of eighty 
years old where at the very close of life the wisdom-teeth have 
come up, causing great pain in their coming; and cases have 
been known of the like phenomenon in men too. This happens, 
when it does happen, in the case of people where the wisdom- 
teeth have not come up in early years. 



1435 



The elephant has four teeth on either side, by which it munches 
its food, grinding it like so much barley-meal, and, quite apart 
from these, it has its great teeth, or tusks, two in number. In the 
male these tusks are comparatively large and curved upwards; 
in the female, they are comparatively small and point in the 
opposite direction; that is, they look downwards towards the 
ground. The elephant is furnished with teeth at birth, but the 
tusks are not then visible. 



The tongue of the elephant is exceedingly small, and situated 
far back in the mouth, so that it is difficult to get a sight of it. 



Furthermore, animals differ from one another in the relative 
size of their mouths. In some animals the mouth opens wide, as 
is the case with the dog, the lion, and with all the saw-toothed 
animals; other animals have small mouths, as man; and others 
have mouths of medium capacity, as the pig and his congeners. 

(The Egyptian hippopotamus has a mane like a horse, is cloven- 
footed like an ox, and is snub-nosed. It has a huckle-bone like 
cloven-footed animals, and tusks just visible; it has the tail of a 
pig, the neigh of a horse, and the dimensions of an ass. The hide 
is so thick that spears are made out of it. In its internal organs it 
resembles the horse and the ass.) 



1436 



8 

Some animals share the properties of man and the quadrupeds, 
as the ape, the monkey, and the baboon. The monkey is a tailed 
ape. The baboon resembles the ape in form, only that it is bigger 
and stronger, more like a dog in face, and is more savage in its 
habits, and its teeth are more dog-like and more powerful. 

Apes are hairy on the back in keeping with their quadrupedal 
nature, and hairy on the belly in keeping with their human form 
- for, as was said above, this characteristic is reversed in man 
and the quadruped - only that the hair is coarse, so that the ape 
is thickly coated both on the belly and on the back. Its face 
resembles that of man in many respects; in other words, it has 
similar nostrils and ears, and teeth like those of man, both front 
teeth and molars. Further, whereas quadrupeds in general are 
not furnished with lashes on one of the two eyelids, this 
creature has them on both, only very thinly set, especially the 
under ones; in fact they are very insignificant indeed. And we 
must bear in mind that all other quadrupeds have no under 
eyelash at all. 

The ape has also in its chest two teats upon poorly developed 
breasts. It has also arms like man, only covered with hair, and it 
bends these legs like man, with the convexities of both limbs 
facing one another. In addition, it has hands and fingers and 
nails like man, only that all these parts are somewhat more 
beast-like in appearance. Its feet are exceptional in kind. That is, 
they are like large hands, and the toes are like fingers, with the 
middle one the longest of all, and the under part of the foot is 
like a hand except for its length, and stretches out towards the 
extremities like the palm of the hand; and this palm at the after 



1437 



end is unusually hard, and in a clumsy obscure kind of way 
resembles a heel. The creature uses its feet either as hands or 
feet, and doubles them up as one doubles a fist. Its upper-arm 
and thigh are short in proportion to the forearm and the shin. It 
has no projecting navel, but only a hardness in the ordinary 
locality of the navel. Its upper part is much larger than its lower 
part, as is the case with quadrupeds; in fact, the proportion of 
the former to the latter is about as five to three. Owing to this 
circumstance and to the fact that its feet resemble hands and 
are composed in a manner of hand and of foot: of foot in the 
heel extremity, of the hand in all else - for even the toes have 
what is called a 'palm': - for these reasons the animal is oftener 
to be found on all fours than upright. It has neither hips, 
inasmuch as it is a quadruped, nor yet a tail, inasmuch as it is a 
biped, except nor yet a tal by the way that it has a tail as small 
as small can be, just a sort of indication of a tail. The genitals of 
the female resemble those of the female in the human species; 
those of the male are more like those of a dog than are those of 
a man. 



The monkey, as has been observed, is furnished with a tail. In 
all such creatures the internal organs are found under 
dissection to correspond to those of man. 

So much then for the properties of the organs of such animals 
as bring forth their young into the world alive. 



1438 



10 

Oviparous and blooded quadrupeds - and, by the way, no 
terrestrial blooded animal is oviparous unless it is quadrupedal 
or is devoid of feet altogether - are furnished with a head, a 
neck, a back, upper and under parts, the front legs and hind 
legs, and the part analogous to the chest, all as in the case of 
viviparous quadrupeds, and with a tail, usually large, in 
exceptional cases small. And all these creatures are many-toed, 
and the several toes are cloven apart. Furthermore, they all have 
the ordinary organs of sensation, including a tongue, with the 
exception of the Egyptian crocodile. 

This latter animal, by the way, resembles certain fishes. For, as a 
general rule, fishes have a prickly tongue, not free in its 
movements; though there are some fishes that present a 
smooth undifferentiated surface where the tongue should be, 
until you open their mouths wide and make a close inspection. 

Again, oviparous blooded quadrupeds are unprovided with ears, 
but possess only the passage for hearing; neither have they 
breasts, nor a copulatory organ, nor external testicles, but 
internal ones only; neither are they hair coated, but are in all 
cases covered with scaly plates. Moreover, they are without 
exception saw-toothed. 

River crocodiles have pigs' eyes, large teeth and tusks, and 
strong nails, and an impenetrable skin composed of scaly 
plates. They see but poorly under water, but above the surface of 
it with remarkable acuteness. As a rule, they pass the day-time 
on land and the nighttime in the water; for the temperature of 
the water is at night-time more genial than that of the open air. 



1439 



11 

The chameleon resembles the lizard in the general 
configuration of its body, but the ribs stretch downwards and 
meet together under the belly as is the case with fishes, and the 
spine sticks up as with the fish. Its face resembles that of the 
baboon. Its tail is exceedingly long, terminates in a sharp point, 
and is for the most part coiled up, like a strap of leather. It 
stands higher off the ground than the lizard, but the flexure of 
the legs is the same in both creatures. Each of its feet is divided 
into two parts, which bear the same relation to one another that 
the thumb and the rest of the hand bear to one another in man. 
Each of these parts is for a short distance divided after a fashion 
into toes; on the front feet the inside part is divided into three 
and the outside into two, on the hind feet the inside part into 
two and the outside into three; it has claws also on these parts 
resembling those of birds of prey. Its body is rough all over, like 
that of the crocodile. Its eyes are situated in a hollow recess, and 
are very large and round, and are enveloped in a skin 
resembling that which covers the entire body; and in the middle 
a slight aperture is left for vision, through which the animal 
sees, for it never covers up this aperture with the cutaneous 
envelope. It keeps twisting its eyes round and shifting its line of 
vision in every direction, and thus contrives to get a sight of any 
object that it wants to see. The change in its colour takes place 
when it is inflated with air; it is then black, not unlike the 
crocodile, or green like the lizard but black-spotted like the pard. 
This change of colour takes place over the whole body alike, for 
the eyes and the tail come alike under its influence. In its 
movements it is very sluggish, like the tortoise. It assumes a 
greenish hue in dying, and retains this hue after death. It 
resembles the lizard in the position of the oesophagus and the 
windpipe. It has no flesh anywhere except a few scraps of flesh 
on the head and on the jaws and near to the root of the tail. It 
has blood only round about the heart, the eyes, the region above 



1440 



the heart, and in all the veins extending from these parts; and 
in all these there is but little blood after all. The brain is situated 
a little above the eyes, but connected with them. When the 
outer skin is drawn aside from off the eye, a something is found 
surrounding the eye, that gleams through like a thin ring of 
copper. Membranes extend well nigh over its entire frame, 
numerous and strong, and surpassing in respect of number and 
relative strength those found in any other animal. After being 
cut open along its entire length it continues to breathe for a 
considerable time; a very slight motion goes on in the region of 
the heart, and, while contraction is especially manifested in the 
neighbourhood of the ribs, a similar motion is more or less 
discernible over the whole body. It has no spleen visible. It 
hibernates, like the lizard. 



12 

Birds also in some parts resemble the above mentioned 
animals; that is to say, they have in all cases a head, a neck, a 
back, a belly, and what is analogous to the chest. The bird is 
remarkable among animals as having two feet, like man; only, 
by the way, it bends them backwards as quadrupeds bend their 
hind legs, as was noticed previously. It has neither hands nor 
front feet, but wings - an exceptional structure as compared 
with other animals. Its haunch-bone is long, like a thigh, and is 
attached to the body as far as the middle of the belly; so like to 
a thigh is it that when viewed separately it looks like a real one, 
while the real thigh is a separate structure betwixt it and the 
shin. Of all birds those that have crooked talons have the 
biggest thighs and the strongest breasts. All birds are furnished 
with many claws, and all have the toes separated more or less 
asunder; that is to say, in the greater part the toes are clearly 



1441 



distinct from one another, for even the swimming birds, 
although they are web-footed, have still their claws fully 
articulated and distinctly differentiated from one another. Birds 
that fly high in air are in all cases four-toed: that is, the greater 
part have three toes in front and one behind in place of a heel; 
some few have two in front and two behind, as the wryneck. 

This latter bird is somewhat bigger than the chaffinch, and is 
mottled in appearance. It is peculiar in the arrangement of its 
toes, and resembles the snake in the structure of its tongue; for 
the creature can protrude its tongue to the extent of four finger- 
breadths, and then draw it back again. Moreover, it can twist its 
head backwards while keeping all the rest of its body still, like 
the serpent. It has big claws, somewhat resembling those of the 
woodpecker. Its note is a shrill chirp. 

Birds are furnished with a mouth, but with an exceptional one, 
for they have neither lips nor teeth, but a beak. Neither have 
they ears nor a nose, but only passages for the sensations 
connected with these organs: that for the nostrils in the beak, 
and that for hearing in the head. Like all other animals they all 
have two eyes, and these are devoid of lashes. The heavy-bodied 
(or gallinaceous) birds close the eye by means of the lower lid, 
and all birds blink by means of a skin extending over the eye 
from the inner corner; the owl and its congeners also close the 
eye by means of the upper lid. The same phenomenon is 
observable in the animals that are protected by horny scutes, as 
in the lizard and its congeners; for they all without exception 
close the eye with the lower lid, but they do not blink like birds. 
Further, birds have neither scutes nor hair, but feathers; and the 
feathers are invariably furnished with quills. They have no tail, 
but a rump with tail-feathers, short in such as are long-legged 
and web-footed, large in others. These latter kinds of birds fly 
with their feet tucked up close to the belly; but the small 
rumped or short-tailed birds fly with their legs stretched out at 



1442 



full length. All are furnished with a tongue, but the organ is 
variable, being long in some birds and broad in others. Certain 
species of birds above all other animals, and next after man, 
possess the faculty of uttering articulate sounds; and this 
faculty is chiefly developed in broad-tongued birds. No 
oviparous creature has an epiglottis over the windpipe, but 
these animals so manage the opening and shutting of the 
windpipe as not to allow any solid substance to get down into 
the lung. 

Some species of birds are furnished additionally with spurs, but 
no bird with crooked talons is found so provided. The birds with 
talons are among those that fly well, but those that have spurs 
are among the heavy-bodied. 

Again, some birds have a crest. As a general rule the crest sticks 
up, and is composed of feathers only; but the crest of the barn- 
door cock is exceptional in kind, for, whereas it is not just 
exactly flesh, at the same time it is not easy to say what else it 
is. 



13 

Of water animals the genus of fishes constitutes a single group 
apart from the rest, and including many diverse forms. 

In the first place, the fish has a head, a back, a belly, in the 
neighbourhood of which last are placed the stomach and 
viscera; and behind it has a tail of continuous, undivided shape, 
but not, by the way, in all cases alike. No fish has a neck, or any 
limb, or testicles at all, within or without, or breasts. But, by the 
way this absence of breasts may predicated of all non- 
viviparous animals; and in point of fact viviparous animals are 



1443 



not in all cases provided with the organ, excepting such as are 
directly viviparous without being first oviparous. Thus the 
dolphin is directly viviparous, and accordingly we find it 
furnished with two breasts, not situated high up, but in the 
neighbourhood of the genitals. And this creature is not 
provided, like quadrupeds, with visible teats, but has two vents, 
one on each flank, from which the milk flows; and its young 
have to follow after it to get suckled, and this phenomenon has 
been actually witnessed. 

Fishes, then, as has been observed, have no breasts and no 
passage for the genitals visible externally. But they have an 
exceptional organ in the gills, whereby, after taking the water in 
the mouth, they discharge it again; and in the fins, of which the 
greater part have four, and the lanky ones two, as, for instance, 
the eel, and these two situated near to the gills. In like manner 
the grey mullet - as, for instance, the mullet found in the lake at 
Siphae - have only two fins; and the same is the case with the 
fish called Ribbon-fish. Some of the lanky fishes have no fins at 
all, such as the muraena, nor gills articulated like those of other 
fish. 

And of those fish that are provided with gills, some have 
coverings for this organ, whereas all the selachians have the 
organ unprotected by a cover. And those fishes that have 
coverings or opercula for the gills have in all cases their gills 
placed sideways; whereas, among selachians, the broad ones 
have the gills down below on the belly, as the torpedo and the 
ray, while the lanky ones have the organ placed sideways, as is 
the case in all the dog-fish. 

The fishing-frog has gills placed sideways, and covered not with 
a spiny operculum, as in all but the selachian fishes, but with 
one of skin. 



1444 



Morever, with fishes furnished with gills, the gills in some cases 
are simple in others duplicate; and the last gill in the direction 
of the body is always simple. And, again, some fishes have few 
gills, and others have a great number; but all alike have the 
same number on both sides. Those that have the least number 
have one gill on either side, and this one duplicate, like the 
boar-fish; others have two on either side, one simple and the 
other duplicate, like the conger and the scarus; others have four 
on either side, simple, as the elops, the synagris, the muraena, 
and the eel; others have four, all, with the exception of the 
hindmost one, in double rows, as the wrasse, the perch, the 
sheat-fish, and the carp. The dog-fish have all their gills double, 
five on a side; and the sword-fish has eight double gills. So 
much for the number of gills as found in fishes. 

Again, fishes differ from other animals in more ways than as 
regards the gills. For they are not covered with hairs as are 
viviparous land animals, nor, as is the case with certain 
oviparous quadrupeds, with tessellated scutes, nor, like birds, 
with feathers; but for the most part they are covered with 
scales. Some few are rough-skinned, while the smooth-skinned 
are very few indeed. Of the Selachia some are rough-skinned 
and some smooth-skinned; and among the smooth-skinned 
fishes are included the conger, the eel, and the tunny. 

All fishes are saw-toothed excepting the scarus; and the teeth 
in all cases are sharp and set in many rows, and in some cases 
are placed on the tongue. The tongue is hard and spiny, and so 
firmly attached that fishes in many instances seem to be devoid 
of the organ altogether. The mouth in some cases is wide- 
stretched, as it is with some viviparous quadrupeds.... 

With regard to organs of sense, all save eyes, fishes possess 
none of them, neither the organs nor their passages, neither 
ears nor nostrils; but all fishes are furnished with eyes, and the 



1445 



eyes devoid of lids, though the eyes are not hard; with regard to 
the organs connected with the other senses, hearing and smell, 
they are devoid alike of the organs themselves and of passages 
indicative of them. 

Fishes without exception are supplied with blood. Some of them 
are oviparous, and some viviparous; scaly fish are invariably 
oviparous, but cartilaginous fishes are all viviparous, with the 
single exception of the fishing- frog. 



14 

Of blooded animals there now remains the serpent genus. This 
genus is common to both elements, for, while most species 
comprehended therein are land animals, a small minority, to 
wit the aquatic species, pass their lives in fresh water. There are 
also sea-serpents, in shape to a great extent resembling their 
congeners of the land, with this exception that the head in their 
case is somewhat like the head of the conger; and there are 
several kinds of sea-serpent, and the different kinds differ in 
colour; these animals are not found in very deep water. 
Serpents, like fish, are devoid of feet. 

There are also sea-scolopendras, resembling in shape their land 
congeners, but somewhat less in regard to magnitude. These 
creatures are found in the neighbourhood of rocks; as compared 
with their land congeners they are redder in colour, are 
furnished with feet in greater numbers and with legs of more 
delicate structure. And the same remark applies to them as to 
the sea-serpents, that they are not found in very deep water. 

Of fishes whose habitat is in the vicinity of rocks there is a tiny 
one, which some call the Echeneis, or 'ship-holder', and which 



1446 



is by some people used as a charm to bring luck in affairs of law 
and love. The creature is unfit for eating. Some people assert 
that it has feet, but this is not the case: it appears, however, to 
be furnished with feet from the fact that its fins resemble those 
organs. 

So much, then, for the external parts of blooded animals, as 
regards their numbers, their properties, and their relative 
diversities. 



15 

As for the properties of the internal organs, these we must first 
discuss in the case of the animals that are supplied with blood. 
For the principal genera differ from the rest of animals, in that 
the former are supplied with blood and the latter are not; and 
the former include man, viviparous and oviparous quadrupeds, 
birds, fishes, cetaceans, and all the others that come under no 
general designation by reason of their not forming genera, but 
groups of which simply the specific name is predicable, as when 
we say 'the serpent,' the 'crocodile'. 

All viviparous quadrupeds, then, are furnished with an 
oesophagus and a windpipe, situated as in man; the same 
statement is applicable to oviparous quadrupeds and to birds, 
only that the latter present diversities in the shapes of these 
organs. As a general rule, all animals that take up air and 
breathe it in and out are furnished with a lung, a windpipe, and 
an oesophagus, with the windpipe and oesophagus not 
admitting of diversity in situation but admitting of diversity in 
properties, and with the lung admitting of diversity in both 
these respects. Further, all blooded animals have a heart and a 
diaphragm or midriff; but in small animals the existence of the 



1447 



latter organ is not so obvious owing to its delicacy and minute 
size. 

In regard to the heart there is an exceptional phenomenon 
observable in oxen. In other words, there is one species of ox 
where, though not in all cases, a bone is found inside the heart. 
And, by the way, the horse's heart also has a bone inside it. 

The genera referred to above are not in all cases furnished with 
a lung: for instance, the fish is devoid of the organ, as is also 
every animal furnished with gills. All blooded animals are 
furnished with a liver. As a general rule blooded animals are 
furnished with a spleen; but with the great majority of non- 
viviparous but oviparous animals the spleen is so small as all 
but to escape observation; and this is the case with almost all 
birds, as with the pigeon, the kite, the falcon, the owl: in point of 
fact, the aegocephalus is devoid of the organ altogether. With 
oviparous quadrupeds the case is much the same as with the 
viviparous; that is to say, they also have the spleen exceedingly 
minute, as the tortoise, the freshwater tortoise, the toad, the 
lizard, the crocodile, and the frog. 

Some animals have a gall-bladder close to the liver, and others 
have not. Of viviparous quadrupeds the deer is without the 
organ, as also the roe, the horse, the mule, the ass, the seal, and 
some kinds of pigs. Of deer those that are called Achainae 
appear to have gall in their tail, but what is so called does 
resemble gall in colour, though it is not so completely fluid, and 
the organ internally resembles a spleen. 

However, without any exception, stags are found to have 
maggots living inside the head, and the habitat of these 
creatures is in the hollow underneath the root of the tongue 
and in the neighbourhood of the vertebra to which the head is 
attached. These creatures are as large as the largest grubs; they 



1448 



grow all together in a cluster, and they are usually about twenty 
in number. 

Deer then, as has been observed, are without a gall-bladder; 
their gut, however, is so bitter that even hounds refuse to eat it 
unless the animal is exceptionally fat. With the elephant also 
the liver is unfurnished with a gall-bladder, but when the 
animal is cut in the region where the organ is found in animals 
furnished with it, there oozes out a fluid resembling gall, in 
greater or less quantities. Of animals that take in sea-water and 
are furnished with a lung, the dolphin is unprovided with a gall- 
bladder. Birds and fishes all have the organ, as also oviparous 
quadrupeds, all to a greater or a lesser extent. But of fishes 
some have the organ close to the liver, as the dogfishes, the 
sheat-fish, the rhine or angel-fish, the smooth skate, the 
torpedo, and, of the lanky fishes, the eel, the pipe-fish, and the 
hammer-headed shark. The callionymus, also, has the gall- 
bladder close to the liver, and in no other fish does the organ 
attain so great a relative size. Other fishes have the organ close 
to the gut, attached to the liver by certain extremely fine ducts. 
The bonito has the gall-bladder stretched alongside the gut and 
equalling it in length, and often a double fold of it. others have 
the organ in the region of the gut; in some cases far off, in 
others near; as the fishing-frog, the elops, the synagris, the 
muraena, and the sword-fish. Often animals of the same species 
show this diversity of position; as, for instance, some congers 
are found with the organ attached close to the liver, and others 
with it detached from and below it. The case is much the same 
with birds: that is, some have the gall-bladder close to the 
stomach, and others close to the gut, as the pigeon, the raven, 
the quail, the swallow, and the sparrow; some have it near at 
once to the liver and to the stomach as the aegocephalus; 
others have it near at once to the liver and the gut, as the falcon 
and the kite. 



1449 



16 

Again, all viviparous quadrupeds are furnished with kidneys 
and a bladder. Of the ovipara that are not quadrupedal there is 
no instance known of an animal, whether fish or bird, provided 
with these organs. Of the ovipara that are quadrupedal, the 
turtle alone is provided with these organs of a magnitude to 
correspond with the other organs of the animal. In the turtle 
the kidney resembles the same organ in the ox; that is to say, it 
looks one single organ composed of a number of small ones. 
(The bison also resembles the ox in all its internal parts). 



17 

With all animals that are furnished with these parts, the parts 
are similarly situated, and with the exception of man, the heart 
is in the middle; in man, however, as has been observed, the 
heart is placed a little to the left-hand side. In all animals the 
pointed end of the heart turns frontwards; only in fish it would 
at first sight seem otherwise, for the pointed end is turned not 
towards the breast, but towards the head and the mouth. And 
(in fish) the apex is attached to a tube just where the right and 
left gills meet together. There are other ducts extending from 
the heart to each of the gills, greater in the greater fish, lesser in 
the lesser; but in the large fishes the duct at the pointed end of 
the heart is a tube, white-coloured and exceedingly thick. Fishes 
in some few cases have an oesophagus, as the conger and the 
eel; and in these the organ is small. 



1450 



In fishes that are furnished with an undivided liver, the organ 
lies entirely on the right side; where the liver is cloven from the 
root, the larger half of the organ is on the right side: for in some 
fishes the two parts are detached from one another, without 
any coalescence at the root, as is the case with the dogfish. And 
there is also a species of hare in what is named the Fig district, 
near Lake Bolbe, and elsewhere, which animal might be taken to 
have two livers owing to the length of the connecting ducts, 
similar to the structure in the lung of birds. 

The spleen in all cases, when normally placed, is on the left- 
hand side, and the kidneys also lie in the same position in all 
creatures that possess them. There have been known instances 
of quadrupeds under dissection, where the spleen was on the 
right hand and the liver on the left; but all such cases are 
regarded as supernatural. 

In all animals the wind-pipe extends to the lung, and the 
manner how, we shall discuss hereafter; and the oesophagus, in 
all that have the organ, extends through the midriff into the 
stomach. For, by the way, as has been observed, most fishes 
have no oesophagus, but the stomach is united directly with the 
mouth, so that in some cases when big fish are pursuing little 
ones, the stomach tumbles forward into the mouth. 

All the afore-mentioned animals have a stomach, and one 
similarly situated, that is to say, situated directly under the 
midriff; and they have a gut connected therewith and closing at 
the outlet of the residuum and at what is termed the 'rectum'. 
However, animals present diversities in the structure of their 
stomachs. In the first place, of the viviparous quadrupeds, such 
of the horned animals as are not equally furnished with teeth in 
both jaws are furnished with four such chambers. These 
animals, by the way, are those that are said to chew the cud. In 
these animals the oesophagus extends from the mouth 



1451 



downwards along the lung, from the midriff to the big stomach 
(or paunch); and this stomach is rough inside and semi- 
partitioned. And connected with it near to the entry of the 
oesophagus is what from its appearance is termed the 
'reticulum' (or honeycomb bag); for outside it is like the 
stomach, but inside it resembles a netted cap; and the 
reticulum is a great deal smaller than the stomach. Connected 
with this is the 'echinus' (or many-plies), rough inside and 
laminated, and of about the same size as the reticulum. Next 
after this comes what is called the 'enystrum' (or abomasum), 
larger an longer than the echinus, furnished inside with 
numerous folds or ridges, large and smooth. After all this comes 
the gut. 

Such is the stomach of those quadrupeds that are horned and 
have an unsymmetrical dentition; and these animals differ one 
from another in the shape and size of the parts, and in the fact 
of the oesophagus reaching the stomach centralwise in some 
cases and sideways in others. Animals that are furnished 
equally with teeth in both jaws have one stomach; as man, the 
pig, the dog, the bear, the lion, the wolf. (The Thos, by the by, has 
all its internal organs similar to the wolf's.) 

All these, then have a single stomach, and after that the gut; but 
the stomach in some is comparatively large, as in the pig and 
bear, and the stomach of the pig has a few smooth folds or 
ridges; others have a much smaller stomach, not much bigger 
than the gut, as the lion, the dog, and man. In the other animals 
the shape of the stomach varies in the direction of one or other 
of those already mentioned; that is, the stomach in some 
animals resembles that of the pig; in others that of the dog, 
alike with the larger animals and the smaller ones. In all these 
animals diversities occur in regard to the size, the shape, the 
thickness or the thinness of the stomach, and also in regard to 
the place where the oesophagus opens into it. 



1452 



There is also a difference in structure in the gut of the two 
groups of animals above mentioned (those with unsymmetrical 
and those with symmetrical dentition) in size, in thickness, and 
in foldings. 

The intestines in those animals whose jaws are unequally 
furnished with teeth are in all cases the larger, for the animals 
themselves are larger than those in the other category; for very 
few of them are small, and no single one of the horned animals 
is very small. And some possess appendages (or caeca) to the 
gut, but no animal that has not incisors in both jaws has a 
straight gut. 

The elephant has a gut constricted into chambers, so 
constructed that the animal appears to have four stomachs; in 
it the food is found, but there is no distinct and separate 
receptacle. Its viscera resemble those of the pig, only that the 
liver is four times the size of that of the ox, and the other 
viscera in like proportion, while the spleen is comparatively 
small. 

Much the same may be predicated of the properties of the 
stomach and the gut in oviparous quadrupeds, as in the land 
tortoise, the turtle, the lizard, both crocodiles, and, in fact, in all 
animals of the like kind; that is to say, their stomach is one and 
simple, resembling in some cases that of the pig, and in other 
cases that of the dog. 

The serpent genus is similar and in almost all respects 
furnished similarly to the saurians among land animals, if one 
could only imagine these saurians to be increased in length and 
to be devoid of legs. That is to say, the serpent is coated with 
tessellated scutes, and resembles the saurian in its back and 
belly; only, by the way, it has no testicles, but, like fishes, has 
two ducts converging into one, and an ovary long and bifurcate. 
The rest of its internal organs are identical with those of the 



1453 



saurians, except that, owing to the narrowness and length of 
the animal, the viscera are correspondingly narrow and 
elongated, so that they are apt to escape recognition from the 
similarities in shape. Thus, the windpipe of the creature is 
exceptionally long, and the oesophagus is longer still, and the 
windpipe commences so close to the mouth that the tongue 
appears to be underneath it; and the windpipe seems to project 
over the tongue, owing to the fact that the tongue draws back 
into a sheath and does not remain in its place as in other 
animals. The tongue, moreover, is thin and long and black, and 
can be protruded to a great distance. And both serpents and 
saurians have this altogether exceptional property in the 
tongue, that it is forked at the outer extremity, and this property 
is the more marked in the serpent, for the tips of his tongue are 
as thin as hairs. The seal, also, by the way, has a split tongue. 

The stomach of the serpent is like a more spacious gut, 
resembling the stomach of the dog; then comes the gut, long, 
narrow, and single to the end. The heart is situated close to the 
pharynx, small and kidney-shaped; and for this reason the 
organ might in some cases appear not to have the pointed end 
turned towards the breast. Then comes the lung, single, and 
articulated with a membranous passage, very long, and quite 
detached from the heart. The liver is long and simple; the 
spleen is short and round: as is the case in both respects with 
the saurians. Its gall resembles that of the fish; the water- 
snakes have it beside the liver, and the other snakes have it 
usually beside the gut. These creatures are all saw-toothed. 
Their ribs are as numerous as the days of the month; in other 
words, they are thirty in number. 

Some affirm that the same phenomenon is observable with 
serpents as with swallow chicks; in other words, they say that if 
you prick out a serpent's eyes they will grow again. And further, 



1454 



the tails of saurians and of serpents, if they be cut off, will grow 
again. 

With fishes the properties of the gut and stomach are similar; 
that is, they have a stomach single and simple, but variable in 
shape according to species. For in some cases the stomach is 
gut-shaped, as with the scarus, or parrot-fish; which fish, by the 
way, appears to be the only fish that chews the cud. And the 
whole length of the gut is simple, and if it have a reduplication 
or kink it loosens out again into a simple form. 

An exceptional property in fishes and in birds for the most part 
is the being furnished with gut-appendages or caeca. Birds have 
them low down and few in number. Fishes have them high up 
about the stomach, and sometimes numerous, as in the goby, 
the galeos, the perch, the scorpaena, the citharus, the red 
mullet, and the sparus; the cestreus or grey mullet has several 
of them on one side of the belly, and on the other side only one. 
Some fish possess these appendages but only in small numbers, 
as the hepatus and the glaucus; and, by the way, they are few 
also in the dorado. These fishes differ also from one another 
within the same species, for in the dorado one individual has 
many and another few. Some fishes are entirely without the 
part, as the majority of the selachians. As for all the rest, some 
of them have a few and some a great many. And in all cases 
where the gut-appendages are found in fish, they are found 
close up to the stomach. 

In regard to their internal parts birds differ from other animals 
and from one another. Some birds, for instance, have a crop in 
front of the stomach, as the barn-door cock, the cushat, the 
pigeon, and the partridge; and the crop consists of a large 
hollow skin, into which the food first enters and where it lies 
ingested. Just where the crop leaves the oesophagus it is 
somewhat narrow; by and by it broadens out, but where it 



1455 



communicates with the stomach it narrows down again. The 
stomach (or gizzard) in most birds is fleshy and hard, and inside 
is a strong skin which comes away from the fleshy part. Other 
birds have no crop, but instead of it an oesophagus wide and 
roomy, either all the way or in the part leading to the stomach, 
as with the daw, the raven, and the carrion-crow. The quail also 
has the oesophagus widened out at the lower extremity, and in 
the aegocephalus and the owl the organ is slightly broader at 
the bottom than at the top. The duck, the goose, the gull, the 
catarrhactes, and the great bustard have the oesophagus wide 
and roomy from one end to the other, and the same applies to a 
great many other birds. In some birds there is a portion of the 
stomach that resembles a crop, as in the kestrel. In the case of 
small birds like the swallow and the sparrow neither the 
oesophagus nor the crop is wide, but the stomach is long. Some 
few have neither a crop nor a dilated oesophagus, but the latter 
is exceedingly long, as in long necked birds, such as the 
porphyrio, and, by the way, in the case of all these birds the 
excrement is unusually moist. The quail is exceptional in regard 
to these organs, as compared with other birds; in other words, it 
has a crop, and at the same time its oesophagus is wide and 
spacious in front of the stomach, and the crop is at some 
distance, relatively to its size, from the oesophagus at that part. 

Further, in most birds, the gut is thin, and simple when 
loosened out. The gut-appendages or caeca in birds, as has been 
observed, are few in number, and are not situated high up, as in 
fishes, but low down towards the extremity of the gut. Birds, 
then, have caeca - not all, but the greater part of them, such as 
the barn-door cock, the partridge, the duck, the night-raven, (the 
localus,) the ascalaphus, the goose, the swan, the great bustard, 
and the owl. Some of the little birds also have these 
appendages; but the caeca in their case are exceedingly minute, 
as in the sparrow. 



1456 



Book III 



Now that we have stated the magnitudes, the properties, and 
the relative differences of the other internal organs, it remains 
for us to treat of the organs that contribute to generation. These 
organs in the female are in all cases internal; in the male they 
present numerous diversities. 

In the blooded animals some males are altogether devoid of 
testicles, and some have the organ but situated internally; and 
of those males that have the organ internally situated, some 
have it close to the loin in the neighbourhood of the kidney and 
others close to the belly. Other males have the organ situated 
externally. In the case of these last, the penis is in some cases 
attached to the belly, whilst in others it is loosely suspended, as 
is the case also with the testicles; and, in the cases where the 
penis is attached to the belly, the attachment varies accordingly 
as the animal is emprosthuretic or opisthuretic. 

No fish is furnished with testicles, nor any other creature that 
has gills, nor any serpent whatever: nor, in short, any animal 
devoid of feet, save such only as are viviparous within 
themselves. Birds are furnished with testicles, but these are 
internally situated, close to the loin. The case is similar with 
oviparous quadrupeds, such as the lizard, the tortoise and the 
crocodile; and among the viviparous animals this peculiarity is 



1457 



found in the hedgehog. Others among those creatures that have 
the organ internally situated have it close to the belly, as is the 
case with the dolphin amongst animals devoid of feet, and with 
the elephant among viviparous quadrupeds. In other cases 
these organs are externally conspicuous. 

We have already alluded to the diversities observed in the 
attachment of these organs to the belly and the adjacent region; 
in other words, we have stated that in some cases the testicles 
are tightly fastened back, as in the pig and its allies, and that in 
others they are freely suspended, as in man. 

Fishes, then, are devoid of testicles, as has been stated, and 
serpents also. They are furnished, however, with two ducts 
connected with the midriff and running on to either side of the 
backbone, coalescing into a single duct above the outlet of the 
residuum, and by 'above' the outlet I mean the region near to 
the spine. These ducts in the rutting season get filled with the 
genital fluid, and, if the ducts be squeezed, the sperm oozes out 
white in colour. As to the differences observed in male fishes of 
diverse species, the reader should consult my treatise on 
Anatomy, and the subject will be hereafter more fully discussed 
when we describe the specific character in each case. 

The males of oviparous animals, whether biped or quadruped, 
are in all cases furnished with testicles close to the loin 
underneath the midriff. With some animals the organ is 
whitish, in others somewhat of a sallow hue; in all cases it is 
entirely enveloped with minute and delicate veins. From each of 
the two testicles extends a duct, and, as in the case of fishes, 
the two ducts coalesce into one above the outlet of the 
residuum. This constitutes the penis, which organ in the case of 
small ovipara is inconspicuous; but in the case of the larger 
ovipara, as in the goose and the like, the organ becomes quite 
visible just after copulation. 



1458 



The ducts in the case of fishes and in biped and quadruped 
ovipara are attached to the loin under the stomach and the gut, 
in betwixt them and the great vein, from which ducts or blood- 
vessels extend, one to each of the two testicles. And just as with 
fishes the male sperm is found in the seminal ducts, and the 
ducts become plainly visible at the rutting season and in some 
instances become invisible after the season is passed, so also is 
it with the testicles of birds; before the breeding season the 
organ is small in some birds and quite invisible in others, but 
during the season the organ in all cases is greatly enlarged. This 
phenomenon is remarkably illustrated in the ring-dove and the 
partridge, so much so that some people are actually of opinion 
that these birds are devoid of the organ in the winter-time. 

Of male animals that have their testicles placed frontwards, 
some have them inside, close to the belly, as the dolphin; some 
have them outside, exposed to view, close to the lower 
extremity of the belly. These animals resemble one another thus 
far in respect to this organ; but they differ from one another in 
this fact, that some of them have their testicles situated 
separately by themselves, while others, which have the organ 
situated externally, have them enveloped in what is termed the 
scrotum. 

Again, in all viviparous animals furnished with feet the 
following properties are observed in the testicles themselves. 
From the aorta there extend vein-like ducts to the head of each 
of the testicles, and another two from the kidneys; these two 
from the kidneys are supplied with blood, while the two from 
the aorta are devoid of it. From the head of the testicle 
alongside of the testicle itself is a duct, thicker and more sinewy 
than the other just alluded to - a duct that bends back again at 
the end of the testicle to its head; and from the head of each of 
the two testicles the two ducts extend until they coalesce in 
front at the penis. The duct that bends back again and that 



1459 



which is in contact with the testicle are enveloped in one and 
the same membrane, so that, until you draw aside the 
membrane, they present all the appearance of being a single 
undifferentiated duct. Further, the duct in contact with the 
testicle has its moist content qualified by blood, but to a 
comparatively less extent than in the case of the ducts higher 
up which are connected with the aorta; in the ducts that bend 
back towards the tube of the penis, the liquid is white-coloured. 
There also runs a duct from the bladder, opening into the upper 
part of the canal, around which lies, sheathwise, what is called 
the 'penis'. 

All these descriptive particulars may be regarded by the light of 
the accompanying diagram; wherein the letter A marks the 
starting-point of the ducts that extend from the aorta; the 
letters KK mark the heads of the testicles and the ducts 
descending thereunto; the ducts extending from these along the 
testicles are marked MM; the ducts turning back, in which is the 
white fluid, are marked BB; the penis D; the bladder E; and the 
testicles XX. 

(By the way, when the testicles are cut off or removed, the ducts 
draw upwards by contraction. Moreover, when male animals are 
young, their owner sometimes destroys the organ in them by 
attrition; sometimes they castrate them at a later period. And I 
may here add, that a bull has been known to serve a cow 
immediately after castration, and actually to impregnate her.) 

So much then for the properties of testicles in male animals. 

In female animals furnished with a womb, the womb is not in 
all cases the same in form or endowed with the same 
properties, but both in the vivipara and the ovipara great 
diversities present themselves. In all creatures that have the 
womb close to the genitals, the womb is two-horned, and one 
horn lies to the right-hand side and the other to the left; its 



1460 



commencement, however, is single, and so is the orifice, 
resembling in the case of the most numerous and largest 
animals a tube composed of much flesh and gristle. Of these 
parts one is termed the hystera or delphys, whence is derived 
the word adelphos, and the other part, the tube or orifice, is 
termed metra. In all biped or quadruped vivipara the womb is in 
all cases below the midriff, as in man, the dog, the pig, the 
horse, and the ox; the same is the case also in all horned 
animals. At the extremity of the so-called ceratia, or horns, the 
wombs of most animals have a twist or convolution. 

In the case of those ovipara that lay eggs externally, the wombs 
are not in all cases similarly situated. Thus the wombs of birds 
are close to the midriff, and the wombs of fishes down below, 
just like the wombs of biped and quadruped vivipara, only that, 
in the case of the fish, the wombs are delicately formed, 
membranous, and elongated; so much so that in extremely 
small fish, each of the two bifurcated parts looks like a single 
egg, and those fishes whose egg is described as crumbling 
would appear to have inside them a pair of eggs, whereas in 
reality each of the two sides consists not of one but of many 
eggs, and this accounts for their breaking up into so many 
particles. 

The womb of birds has the lower and tubular portion fleshy and 
firm, and the part close to the midriff membranous and 
exceedingly thin and fine: so thin and fine that the eggs might 
seem to be outside the womb altogether. In the larger birds the 
membrane is more distinctly visible, and, if inflated through the 
tube, lifts and swells out; in the smaller birds all these parts are 
more indistinct. 

The properties of the womb are similar in oviparous 
quadrupeds, as the tortoise, the lizard, the frog and the like; for 
the tube below is single and fleshy, and the cleft portion with 



1461 



the eggs is at the top close to the midriff. With animals devoid 
of feet that are internally oviparous and viviparous externally, 
as is the case with the dogfish and the other so-called 
Selachians (and by this title we designate such creatures 
destitute of feet and furnished with gills as are viviparous), with 
these animals the womb is bifurcate, and beginning down below 
it extends as far as the midriff, as in the case of birds. There is 
also a narrow part between the two horns running up as far as 
the midriff, and the eggs are engendered here and above at the 
origin of the midriff; afterwards they pass into the wider space 
and turn from eggs into young animals. However, the 
differences in respect to the wombs of these fishes as compared 
with others of their own species or with fishes in general, would 
be more satisfactorily studied in their various forms in 
specimens under dissection. 

The members of the serpent genus also present divergencies 
either when compared with the above-mentioned creatures or 
with one another. Serpents as a rule are oviparous, the viper 
being the only viviparous member of the genus. The viper is, 
previously to external parturition, oviparous internally; and 
owing to this perculiarity the properties of the womb in the 
viper are similar to those of the womb in the selachians. The 
womb of the serpent is long, in keeping with the body, and 
starting below from a single duct extends continuously on both 
sides of the spine, so as to give the impression of thus being a 
separate duct on each side of the spine, until it reaches the 
midriff, where the eggs are engendered in a row; and these eggs 
are laid not one by one, but all strung together. (And all animals 
that are viviparous both internally and externally have the 
womb situated above the stomach, and all the ovipara 
underneath, near to the loin. Animals that are viviparous 
externally and internally oviparous present an intermediate 
arrangement; for the underneath portion of the womb, in which 



1462 



the eggs are, is placed near to the loin, but the part about the 
orifice is above the gut.) 

Further, there is the following diversity observable in wombs as 
compared with one another: namely that the females of horned 
nonambidental animals are furnished with cotyledons in the 
womb when they are pregnant, and such is the case, among 
ambidentals, with the hare, the mouse, and the bat; whereas all 
other animals that are ambidental, viviparous, and furnished 
with feet, have the womb quite smooth, and in their case the 
attachment of the embryo is to the womb itself and not to any 
cotyledon inside it. 

The parts, then, in animals that are not homogeneous with 
themselves and uniform in their texture, both parts external 
and parts internal, have the properties above assigned to them. 



In sanguineous animals the homogeneous or uniform part most 
universally found is the blood, and its habitat the vein; next in 
degree of universality, their analogues, lymph and fibre, and, 
that which chiefly constitutes the frame of animals, flesh and 
whatsoever in the several parts is analogous to flesh; then bone, 
and parts that are analogous to bone, as fish-bone and gristle; 
and then, again, skin, membrane, sinew, hair, nails, and 
whatever corresponds to these; and, furthermore, fat, suet, and 
the excretions: and the excretions are dung, phlegm, yellow bile, 
and black bile. 

Now, as the nature of blood and the nature of the veins have all 
the appearance of being primitive, we must discuss their 
properties first of all, and all the more as some previous writers 



1463 



have treated them very unsatisfactorily. And the cause of the 
ignorance thus manifested is the extreme difficulty experienced 
in the way of observation. For in the dead bodies of animals the 
nature of the chief veins is undiscoverable, owing to the fact 
that they collapse at once when the blood leaves them; for the 
blood pours out of them in a stream, like liquid out of a vessel, 
since there is no blood separately situated by itself, except a 
little in the heart, but it is all lodged in the veins. In living 
animals it is impossible to inspect these parts, for of their very 
nature they are situated inside the body and out of sight. For 
this reason anatomists who have carried on their investigations 
on dead bodies in the dissecting room have failed to discover 
the chief roots of the veins, while those who have narrowly 
inspected bodies of living men reduced to extreme attenuation 
have arrived at conclusions regarding the origin of the veins 
from the manifestations visible externally. Of these 
investigators, Syennesis, the physician of Cyprus, writes as 
follows: 

'The big veins run thus:-from the navel across the loins, along 
the back, past the lung, in under the breasts; one from right to 
left, and the other from left to right; that from the left, through 
the liver to the kidney and the testicle, that from the right, to 
the spleen and kidney and testicle, and from thence to the 
penis.' Diogenes of Apollonia writes thus: 

'The veins in man are as follows: There are two veins pre- 
eminent in magnitude. These extend through the belly along 
the backbone, one to right, one to left; either one to the leg on 
its own side, and upwards to the head, past the collar bones, 
through the throat. From these, veins extend all over the body, 
from that on the right hand to the right side and from that on 
the left hand to the left side; the most important ones, two in 
number, to the heart in the region of the backbone; other two a 
little higher up through the chest in underneath the armpit, 



1464 



each to the hand on its side: of these two, one being termed the 
vein splenitis, and the other the vein hepatitis. Each of the pair 
splits at its extremity; the one branches in the direction of the 
thumb and the other in the direction of the palm; and from 
these run off a number of minute veins branching off to the 
fingers and to all parts of the hand. Other veins, more minute, 
extend from the main veins; from that on the right towards the 
liver, from that on the left towards the spleen and the kidneys. 
The veins that run to the legs split at the juncture of the legs 
with the trunk and extend right down the thigh. The largest of 
these goes down the thigh at the back of it, and can be 
discerned and traced as a big one; the second one runs inside 
the thigh, not quite as big as the one just mentioned. After this 
they pass on along the knee to the shin and the foot (as the 
upper veins were described as passing towards the hands), and 
arrive at the sole of the foot, and from thence continue to the 
toes. Moreover, many delicate veins separate off from the great 
veins towards the stomach and towards the ribs. 

'The veins that run through the throat to the head can be 
discerned and traced in the neck as large ones; and from each 
one of the two, where it terminates, there branch off a number 
of veins to the head; some from the right side towards the left, 
and some from the left side towards the right; and the two veins 
terminate near to each of the two ears. There is another pair of 
veins in the neck running along the big vein on either side, 
slightly less in size than the pair just spoken of, and with these 
the greater part of the veins in the head are connected. This 
other pair runs through the throat inside; and from either one 
of the two there extend veins in underneath the shoulder blade 
and towards the hands; and these appear alongside the veins 
splenitis and hepatitis as another pair of veins smaller in size. 
When there is a pain near the surface of the body, the physician 
lances these two latter veins; but when the pain is within and in 
the region of the stomach he lances the veins splenitis and 



1465 



hepatitis. And from these, other veins depart to run below the 
breasts. 

'There is also another pair running on each side through the 
spinal marrow to the testicles, thin and delicate. There is, 
further, a pair running a little underneath the cuticle through 
the flesh to the kidneys, and these with men terminate at the 
testicle, and with women at the womb. These veins are termed 
the spermatic veins. The veins that leave the stomach are 
comparatively broad just as they leave; but they become 
gradually thinner, until they change over from right to left and 
from left to right. 

'Blood is thickest when it is imbibed by the fleshy parts; when it 
is transmitted to the organs above-mentioned, it becomes thin, 
warm, and frothy.' 



Such are the accounts given by Syennesis and Diogenes. Polybus 
writes to the following effect: 

'There are four pairs of veins. The first extends from the back of 
the head, through the neck on the outside, past the backbone on 
either side, until it reaches the loins and passes on to the legs, 
after which it goes on through the shins to the outer side of the 
ankles and on to the feet. And it is on this account that 
surgeons, for pains in the back and loin, bleed in the ham and in 
the outer side of the ankle. Another pair of veins runs from the 
head, past ears, through the neck; which veins are termed the 
jugular veins. This pair goes on inside along the backbone, past 
the muscles of the loins, on to the testicles, and onwards to the 
thighs, and through the inside of the hams and through the 



1466 



shins down to the inside of the ankles and to the feet; and for 
this reason, surgeons, for pains in the muscles of the loins and 
in the testicles, bleed on the hams and the inner side of the 
ankles. The third pair extends from the temples, through the 
neck, in underneath the shoulder-blades, into the lung; those 
from right to left going in underneath the breast and on to the 
spleen and the kidney; those from left to right running from the 
lung in underneath the breast and into the liver and the kidney; 
and both terminate in the fundament. The fourth pair extend 
from the front part of the head and the eyes in underneath the 
neck and the collar-bones; from thence they stretch on through 
the upper part of the upper arms to the elbows and then 
through the fore-arms on to the wrists and the jointings of the 
fingers, and also through the lower part of the upper-arms to 
the armpits, and so on, keeping above the ribs, until one of the 
pair reaches the spleen and the other reaches the liver; and 
after this they both pass over the stomach and terminate at the 
penis.' 

The above quotations sum up pretty well the statements of all 
previous writers. Furthermore, there are some writers on 
Natural History who have not ventured to lay down the law in 
such precise terms as regards the veins, but who all alike agree 
in assigning the head and the brain as the starting-point of the 
veins. And in this opinion they are mistaken. 

The investigation of such a subject, as has been remarked, is 
one fraught with difficulties; but, if any one be keenly interested 
in the matter, his best plan will be to allow his animals to starve 
to emaciation, then to strangle them on a sudden, and 
thereupon to prosecute his investigations. 

We now proceed to give particulars regarding the properties and 
functions of the veins. There are two blood-vessels in the thorax 
by the backbone, and lying to its inner side; and of these two 



1467 



the larger one is situated to the front, and the lesser one is to 
the rear of it; and the larger is situated rather to the right hand 
side of the body, and the lesser one to the left; and by some this 
vein is termed the 'aorta', from the fact that even in dead bodies 
part of it is observed to be full of air. These blood-vessels have 
their origins in the heart, for they traverse the other viscera, in 
whatever direction they happen to run, without in any way 
losing their distinctive characteristic as blood-vessels, whereas 
the heart is as it were a part of them (and that too more in 
respect to the frontward and larger one of the two), owing to the 
fact that these two veins are above and below, with the heart 
lying midway. 

The heart in all animals has cavities inside it. In the case of the 
smaller animals even the largest of the chambers is scarcely 
discernible; the second larger is scarcely discernible in animals 
of medium size; but in the largest animals all three chambers 
are distinctly seen. In the heart then (with its pointed end 
directed frontwards, as has been observed) the largest of the 
three chambers is on the right-hand side and highest up; the 
least one is on the left-hand side; and the medium-sized one 
lies in betwixt the other two; and the largest one of the three 
chambers is a great deal larger than either of the two others. All 
three, however, are connected with passages leading in the 
direction of the lung, but all these communications are 
indistinctly discernible by reason of their minuteness, except 
one. 

The great blood-vessel, then, is attached to the biggest of the 
three chambers, the one that lies uppermost and on the right- 
hand side; it then extends right through the chamber, coming 
out as blood-vessel again; just as though the cavity of the heart 
were a part of the vessel, in which the blood broadens its 
channel as a river that widens out in a lake. The aorta is 



1468 



attached to the middle chamber; only, by the way, it is 
connected with it by much narrower pipe. 

The great blood-vessel then passes through the heart (and runs 
from the heart into the aorta). The great vessel looks as though 
made of membrane or skin, while the aorta is narrower than it, 
and is very sinewy; and as it stretches away to the head and to 
the lower parts it becomes exceedingly narrow and sinewy. 

First of all, then, upwards from the heart there stretches a part 
of the great blood-vessel towards the lung and the attachment 
of the aorta, a part consisting of a large undivided vessel. But 
there split off from it two parts; one towards the lung and the 
other towards the backbone and the last vertebra of the neck. 

The vessel, then, that extends to the lung, as the lung itself is 
duplicate, divides at first into two; and then extends along by 
every pipe and every perforation, greater along the greater ones, 
lesser along the less, so continuously that it is impossible to 
discern a single part wherein there is not perforation and vein; 
for the extremities are indistinguishable from their minuteness, 
and in point of fact the whole lung appears to be filled with 
blood. 

The branches of the blood-vessels lie above the tubes that 
extend from the windpipe. And that vessel which extends to the 
vertebra of the neck and the backbone, stretches back again 
along the backbone; as Homer represents in the lines: 

(Antilochus, asThoon turned him round), 

Transpierc'd his back with a dishonest wound; 

The hollow vein that to the neck extends, 

Along the chine, the eager javelin rends. 



1469 



From this vessel there extend small blood-vessels at each rib 
and each vertebra; and at the vertebra above the kidneys the 
vessel bifurcates. And in the above way the parts branch off 
from the great blood-vessel. 

But up above all these, from that part which is connected with 
the heart, the entire vein branches off in two directions. For its 
branches extend to the sides and to the collarbones, and then 
pass on, in men through the armpits to the arms, in quadrupeds 
to the forelegs, in birds to the wings, and in fishes to the upper 
or pectoral fins. (See diagram.) The trunks of these veins, where 
they first branch off, are called the 'jugular' veins; and, where 
they branch off to the neck the great vein run alongside the 
windpipe; and, occasionally, if these veins are pressed 
externally, men, though not actually choked, become insensible, 
shut their eyes, and fall flat on the ground. Extending in the way 
described and keeping the windpipe in betwixt them, they pass 
on until they reach the ears at the junction of the lower jaw 
with the skull. Hence again they branch off into four veins, of 
which one bends back and descends through the neck and the 
shoulder, and meets the previous branching off of the vein at 
the bend of the arm, while the rest of it terminates at the hand 
and fingers. (See diagram.) 

Each vein of the other pair stretches from the region of the ear 
to the brain, and branches off in a number of fine and delicate 
veins into the so-called meninx, or membrane, which surrounds 
the brain. The brain itself in all animals is destitute of blood, 
and no vein, great or small, holds its course therein. But of the 
remaining veins that branch off from the last mentioned vein 
some envelop the head, others close their courses in the organs 
of sense and at the roots of the teeth in veins exceedingly fine 
and minute. 



1470 



And in like manner the parts of the lesser one of the two chief 
blood-vessels, designated the aorta, branch off, accompanying 
the branches from the big vein; only that, in regard to the aorta, 
the passages are less in size, and the branches very considerably 
less than are those of the great vein. So much for the veins as 
observed in the regions above the heart. 

The part of the great vein that lies underneath the heart 
extends, freely suspended, right through the midriff, and is 
united both to the aorta and the backbone by slack 
membranous communications. From it one vein, short and 
wide, extends through the liver, and from it a number of minute 
veins branch off into the liver and disappear. From the vein that 
passes through the liver two branches separate off, of which 
one terminates in the diaphragm or so-called midriff, and the 
other runs up again through the armpit into the right arm and 
unites with the other veins at the inside of the bend of the arm; 
and it is in consequence of this local connexion that, when the 
surgeon opens this vein in the forearm, the patient is relieved of 
certain pains in the liver; and from the left-hand side of it there 
extends a short but thick vein to the spleen and the little veins 
branching off it disappear in that organ. Another part branches 
off from the left-hand side of the great vein, and ascends, by a 
course similar to the course recently described, into the left 
arm; only that the ascending vein in the one case is the vein 
that traverses the liver, while in this case it is distinct from the 
vein that runs into the spleen. Again, other veins branch off 
from the big vein; one to the omentum, and another to the 
pancreas, from which vein run a number of veins through the 
mesentery. All these veins coalesce in a single large vein, along 



1471 



the entire gut and stomach to the oesophagus; about these 
parts there is a great ramification of branch veins. 

As far as the kidneys, each of the two remaining undivided, the 
aorta and the big vein extend; and here they get more closely 
attached to the backbone, and branch off, each of the two, into a 
A shape, and the big vein gets to the rear of the aorta. But the 
chief attachment of the aorta to the backbone takes place in the 
region of the heart; and the attachment is effected by means of 
minute and sinewy vessels. The aorta, just as it draws off from 
the heart, is a tube of considerable volume, but, as it advances 
in its course, it gets narrower and more sinewy. And from the 
aorta there extend veins to the mesentery just like the veins 
that extend thither from the big vein, only that the branches in 
the case of the aorta are considerably less in magnitude; they 
are, indeed, narrow and fibrillar, and they end in delicate hollow 
fibre-like veinlets. 

There is no vessel that runs from the aorta into the liver or the 
spleen. 

From each of the two great blood-vessels there extend branches 
to each of the two flanks, and both branches fasten on to the 
bone. Vessels also extend to the kidneys from the big vein and 
the aorta; only that they do not open into the cavity of the 
organ, but their ramifications penetrate into its substance. From 
the aorta run two other ducts to the bladder, firm and 
continuous; and there are other ducts from the hollow of the 
kidneys, in no way communicating with the big vein. From the 
centre of each of the two kidneys springs a hollow sinewy vein, 
running along the backbone right through the loins; by and by 
each of the two veins first disappears in its own flank, and soon 
afterwards reappears stretching in the direction of the flank. 
The extremities of these attach to the bladder, and also in the 
male to the penis and in the female to the womb. From the big 



1472 



vein no vein extends to the womb, but the organ is connected 
with the aorta by veins numerous and closely packed. 

Furthermore, from the aorta and the great vein at the points of 
divarication there branch off other veins. Some of these run to 
the groins - large hollow veins - and then pass on down 
through the legs and terminate in the feet and toes. And, again, 
another set run through the groins and the thighs cross-garter 
fashion, from right to left and from left to right, and unite in the 
hams with the other veins. 

In the above description we have thrown light upon the course 
of the veins and their points of departure. 

In all sanguineous animals the case stands as here set forth in 
regard to the points of departure and the courses of the chief 
veins. But the description does not hold equally good for the 
entire vein-system in all these animals. For, in point of fact, the 
organs are not identically situated in them all; and, what is 
more, some animals are furnished with organs of which other 
animals are destitute. At the same time, while the description 
so far holds good, the proof of its accuracy is not equally easy in 
all cases, but is easiest in the case of animals of considerable 
magnitude and supplied abundantly with blood. For in little 
animals and those scantily supplied with blood, either from 
natural and inherent causes or from a prevalence of fat in the 
body, thorough accuracy in investigation is not equally 
attainable; for in the latter of these creatures the passages get 
clogged, like water-channels choked with slush; and the others 
have a few minute fibres to serve instead of veins. But in all 
cases the big vein is plainly discernible, even in creatures of 
insignificant size. 



1473 



The sinews of animals have the following properties. For these 
also the point of origin is the heart; for the heart has sinews 
within itself in the largest of its three chambers, and the aorta is 
a sinew-like vein; in fact, at its extremity it is actually a sinew, 
for it is there no longer hollow, and is stretched like the sinews 
where they terminate at the jointings of the bones. Be it 
remembered, however, that the sinews do not proceed in 
unbroken sequence from one point of origin, as do the blood- 
vessels. 

For the veins have the shape of the entire body, like a sketch of 
a mannikin; in such a way that the whole frame seems to be 
filled up with little veins in attenuated subjects - for the space 
occupied by flesh in fat individuals is filled with little veins in 
thin ones - whereas the sinews are distributed about the joints 
and the flexures of the bones. Now, if the sinews were derived in 
unbroken sequence from a common point of departure, this 
continuity would be discernible in attenuated specimens. 

In the ham, or the part of the frame brought into full play in the 
effort of leaping, is an important system of sinews; and another 
sinew, a double one, is that called 'the tendon', and others are 
those brought into play when a great effort of physical strength 
is required; that is to say, the epitonos or back-stay and the 
shoulder-sinews. Other sinews, devoid of specific designation, 
are situated in the region of the flexures of the bones; for all the 
bones that are attached to one another are bound together by 
sinews, and a great quantity of sinews are placed in the 
neighbourhood of all the bones. Only, by the way, in the head 
there is no sinew; but the head is held together by the sutures 
of the bones. 

Sinew is fissile lengthwise, but crosswise it is not easily broken, 
but admits of a considerable amount of hard tension. In 



1474 



connexion with sinews a liquid mucus is developed, white and 
glutinous, and the organ, in fact, is sustained by it and appears 
to be substantially composed of it. Now, vein may be submitted 
to the actual cautery, but sinew, when submitted to such action, 
shrivels up altogether; and, if sinews be cut asunder, the 
severed parts will not again cohere. A feeling of numbness is 
incidental only to parts of the frame where sinew is situated. 

There is a very extensive system of sinews connected severally 
with the feet, the hands, the ribs, the shoulder-blades, the neck, 
and the arms. 

All animals supplied with blood are furnished with sinews; but 
in the case of animals that have no flexures to their limbs, but 
are, in fact, destitute of either feet or hands, the sinews are fine 
and inconspicuous; and so, as might have been anticipated, the 
sinews in the fish are chiefly discernible in connexion with the 
fin. 



The ines (or fibrous connective tissue) are a something 
intermediate between sinew and vein. Some of them are 
supplied with fluid, the lymph; and they pass from sinew to 
vein and from vein to sinew. There is another kind of ines or 
fibre that is found in blood, but not in the blood of all animals 
alike. If this fibre be left in the blood, the blood will coagulate; if 
it be removed or extracted, the blood is found to be incapable of 
coagulation. While, however, this fibrous matter is found in the 
blood of the great majority of animals, it is not found in all. For 
instance, we fail to find it in the blood of the deer, the roe, the 
antelope, and some other animals; and, owing to this deficiency 
of the fibrous tissue, the blood of these animals does not 



1475 



coagulate to the extent observed in the blood of other animals. 
The blood of the deer coagulates to about the same extent as 
that of the hare: that is to the blood in either case coagulates, 
but not into a stiff or jelly-like substance, like the blood of 
ordinary animals, but only into a flaccid consistency like that of 
milk which is not subjected to the action of rennet. The blood of 
the antelope admits of a firmer consistency in coagulation; for 
in this respect it resembles, or only comes a little short of, the 
blood of sheep. Such are the properties of vein, sinew, and 
fibrous tissue. 



The bones in animals are all connected with one single bone, 
and are interconnected, like the veins, in one unbroken 
sequence; and there is no instance of a bone standing apart by 
itself. In all animals furnished with bones, the spine or 
backbone is the point of origin for the entire osseous system. 
The spine is composed of vertebrae, and it extends from the 
head down to the loins. The vertebrae are all perforated, and, 
above, the bony portion of the head is connected with the 
topmost vertebrae, and is designated the 'skull'. And the 
serrated lines on the skull are termed 'sutures'. 

The skull is not formed alike in all animals. In some animals the 
skull consists of one single undivided bone, as in the case of the 
dog; in others it is composite in structure, as in man; and in the 
human species the suture is circular in the female, while in the 
male it is made up of three separate sutures, uniting above in 
three-corner fashion; and instances have been known of a 
man's skull being devoid of suture altogether. The skull is 
composed not of four bones, but of six; two of these are in the 



1476 



region of the ears, small in comparison with the other four. 
From the skull extend the jaws, constituted of bone. (Animals in 
general move the lower jaw; the river crocodile is the only 
animal that moves the upper one.) In the jaws is the tooth- 
system; and the teeth are constituted of bone, and are half-way 
perforated; and the bone in question is the only kind of bone 
which it is found impossible to grave with a graving tool. 

On the upper part of the course of the backbone are the collar- 
bones and the ribs. The chest rests on ribs; and these ribs meet 
together, whereas the others do not; for no animal has bone in 
the region of the stomach. Then come the shoulder-bones, or 
blade-bones, and the arm-bones connected with these, and the 
bones in the hands connected with the bones of the arms. With 
animals that have forelegs, the osseous system of the foreleg 
resembles that of the arm in man. 

Below the level of the backbone, after the haunch-bone, comes 
the hip-socket; then the leg-bones, those in the thighs and 
those in the shins, which are termed colenes or limb-bones, a 
part of which is the ankle, while a part of the same is the so- 
called 'plectrum' in those creatures that have an ankle; and 
connected with these bones are the bones in the feet. 

Now, with all animals that are supplied with blood and 
furnished with feet, and are at the same time viviparous, the 
bones do not differ greatly one from another, but only in the 
way of relative hardness, softness, or magnitude. A further 
difference, by the way, is that in one and the same animal 
certain bones are supplied with marrow, while others are 
destitute of it. Some animals might on casual observation 
appear to have no marrow whatsoever in their bones: as is the 
case with the lion, owing to his having marrow only in small 
amount, poor and thin, and in very few bones; for marrow is 
found in his thigh and armbones. The bones of the lion are 



1477 



exceptionally hard; so hard, in fact, that if they are rubbed hard 
against one another they emit sparks like flint-stones. The 
dolphin has bones, and not fish-spine. 

Of the other animals supplied with blood, some differ but little, 
as is the case with birds; others have systems analogous, as 
fishes; for viviparous fishes, such as the cartilaginous species, 
are gristle-spined, while the ovipara have a spine which 
corresponds to the backbone in quadrupeds. This exceptional 
property has been observed in fishes, that in some of them 
there are found delicate spines scattered here and there 
throughout the fleshy parts. The serpent is similarly 
constructed to the fish; in other words, his backbone is spinous. 
With oviparous quadrupeds, the skeleton of the larger ones is 
more or less osseous; of the smaller ones, more or less spinous. 
But all sanguineous animals have a backbone of either one kind 
or other: that is, composed either of bone or of spine. 

The other portions of the skeleton are found in some animals 
and not found in others, but the presence or the absence of this 
and that part carries with it, as a matter of course, the presence 
or the absence of the bones or the spines corresponding to this 
or that part. For animals that are destitute of arms and legs 
cannot be furnished with limb-bones: and in like manner with 
animals that have the same parts, but yet have them unlike in 
form; for in these animals the corresponding bones differ from 
one another in the way of relative excess or relative defect, or in 
the way of analogy taking the place of identity. So much for the 
osseous or spinous systems in animals. 



1478 



8 

Gristle is of the same nature as bone, but differs from it in the 
way of relative excess or relative defect. And just like bone, 
cartilage also, if cut, does not grow again. In terrestrial 
viviparous sanguinea the gristle formations are unperforated, 
and there is no marrow in them as there is in bones; in the 
selachia, however - for, be it observed, they are gristle-spined - 
there is found in the case of the flat space in the region of the 
backbone, a gristle-like substance analogous to bone, and in this 
gristle-like substance there is a liquid resembling marrow. In 
viviparous animals furnished with feet, gristle formations are 
found in the region of the ears, in the nostrils, and around 
certain extremities of the bones. 



Furthermore, there are parts of other kinds, neither identical 
with, nor altogether diverse from, the parts above enumerated: 
such as nails, hooves, claws, and horns; and also, by the way, 
beaks, such as birds are furnished with - all in the several 
animals that are furnished therewithal. All these parts are 
flexible and fissile; but bone is neither flexible nor fissile, but 
frangible. 

And the colours of horns and nails and claw and hoof follow the 
colour of the skin and the hair. For according as the skin of an 
animal is black, or white, or of medium hue, so are the horns, 
the claws, or the hooves, as the case may be, of hue to match. 
And it is the same with nails. The teeth, however, follow after 
the bones. Thus in black men, such as the Aethiopians and the 
like, the teeth and bones are white, but the nails are black, like 
the whole of the skin. 



1479 



Horns in general are hollow at their point of attachment to the 
bone which juts out from the head inside the horn, but they 
have a solid portion at the tip, and they are simple and 
undivided in structure. In the case of the stag alone of all 
animals the horns are solid throughout, and ramify into 
branches (or antlers). And, whereas no other animal is known to 
shed its horns, the deer sheds its horns annually, unless it has 
been castrated; and with regard to the effects of castration in 
animals we shall have much to say hereafter. Horns attach 
rather to the skin than to the bone; which will account for the 
fact that there are found in Phrygia and elsewhere cattle that 
can move their horns as freely as their ears. 

Of animals furnished with nails - and, by the way, all animals 
have nails that have toes, and toes that have feet, except the 
elephant; and the elephant has toes undivided and slightly 
articulated, but has no nails whatsoever - of animals furnished 
with nails, some are straight-nailed, like man; others are 
crooked nailed, as the lion among animals that walk, and the 
eagle among animals that fly. 



10 

The following are the properties of hair and of parts analogous 
to hair, and of skin or hide. All viviparous animals furnished 
with feet have hair; all oviparous animals furnished with feet 
have horn-like tessellates; fishes, and fishes only, have scales - 
that is, such oviparous fishes as have the crumbling egg or roe. 
For of the lanky fishes, the conger has no such egg, nor the 
muraena, and the eel has no egg at all. 

The hair differs in the way of thickness and fineness, and of 
length, according to the locality of the part in which it is found, 



1480 



and according to the quality of skin or hide on which it grows. 
For, as a general rule, the thicker the hide, the harder and the 
thicker is the hair; and the hair is inclined to grow in abundance 
and to a great length in localities of the bodies hollow and 
moist, if the localities be fitted for the growth of hair at all. The 
facts are similar in the case of animals whether coated with 
scales or with tessellates. With soft-haired animals the hair gets 
harder with good feeding, and with hard-haired or bristly 
animals it gets softer and scantier from the same cause. Hair 
differs in quality also according to the relative heat or warmth 
of the locality: just as the hair in man is hard in warm places 
and soft in cold ones. Again, straight hair is inclined to be soft, 
and curly hair to be bristly. 



11 

Hair is naturally fissile, and in this respect it differs in degree in 
diverse animals. In some animals the hair goes on gradually 
hardening into bristle until it no longer resembles hair but 
spine, as in the case of the hedgehog. And in like manner with 
the nails; for in some animals the nail differs as regards solidity 
in no way from bone. 

Of all animals man has the most delicate skin: that is, if we take 
into consideration his relative size. In the skin or hide of all 
animals there is a mucous liquid, scanty in some animals and 
plentiful in others, as, for instance, in the hide of the ox; for 
men manufacture glue out of it. (And, by the way, in some cases 
glue is manufactured from fishes also.) The skin, when cut, is in 
itself devoid of sensation; and this is especially the case with 
the skin on the head, owing to there being no flesh between it 
and the skull. And wherever the skin is quite by itself, if it be cut 



1481 



asunder, it does not grow together again, as is seen in the thin 
part of the jaw, in the prepuce, and the eyelid. In all animals the 
skin is one of the parts that extends continuous and unbroken, 
and it comes to a stop only where the natural ducts pour out 
their contents, and at the mouth and nails. 

All sanguineous animals, then, have skin; but not all such 
animals have hair, save only under the circumstances described 
above. The hair changes its colour as animals grow old, and in 
man it turns white or grey. With animals, in general, the change 
takes place, but not very obviously, or not so obviously as in the 
case of the horse. Hair turns grey from the point backwards to 
the roots. But, in the majority of cases, grey hairs are white from 
the beginning; and this is a proof that greyness of hair does not, 
as some believe to be the case, imply withering or decrepitude, 
for no part is brought into existence in a withered or decrepit 
condition. 

In the eruptive malady called the white-sickness all the hairs 
get grey; and instances have been known where the hair 
became grey while the patients were ill of the malady, whereas 
the grey hairs shed off and black ones replaced them on their 
recovery. (Hair is more apt to turn grey when it is kept covered 
than when exposed to the action of the outer air.) In men, the 
hair over the temples is the first to turn grey, and the hair in the 
front grows grey sooner than the hair at the back; and the hair 
on the pubes is the last to change colour. 

Some hairs are congenital, others grow after the maturity of the 
animal; but this occurs in man only. The congenital hairs are on 
the head, the eyelids, and the eyebrows; of the later growths the 
hairs on the pubes are the first to come, then those under the 
armpits, and, thirdly, those on the chin; for, singularly enough, 
the regions where congenital growths and the subsequent 
growths are found are equal in number. The hair on the head 



1482 



grows scanty and sheds out to a greater extent and sooner than 
all the rest. But this remark applies only to hair in front; for no 
man ever gets bald at the back of his head. Smoothness on the 
top of the head is termed 'baldness', but smoothness on the 
eyebrows is denoted by a special term which means 'forehead- 
baldness'; and neither of these conditions of baldness 
supervenes in a man until he shall have come under the 
influence of sexual passion. For no boy ever gets bald, no 
woman, and no castrated man. In fact, if a man be castrated 
before reaching puberty, the later growths of hair never come at 
all; and, if the operation take place subsequently, the 
aftergrowths, and these only, shed off; or, rather, two of the 
growths shed off, but not that on the pubes. 

Women do not grow hairs on the chin; except that a scanty 
beard grows on some women after the monthly courses have 
stopped; and similar phenomenon is observed at times in 
priestesses in Caria, but these cases are looked upon as 
portentous with regard to coming events. The other after- 
growths are found in women, but more scanty and sparse. Men 
and women are at times born constitutionally and congenitally 
incapable of the after- growths; and individuals that are 
destitute even of the growth upon the pubes are 
constitutionally impotent. 

Hair as a rule grows more or less in length as the wearer grows 
in age; chiefly the hair on the head, then that in the beard, and 
fine hair grows longest of all. With some people as they grow 
old the eyebrows grow thicker, to such an extent that they have 
to be cut off; and this growth is owing to the fact that the 
eyebrows are situated at a conjuncture of bones, and these 
bones, as age comes on, draw apart and exude a gradual 
increase of moisture or rheum. The eyelashes do not grow in 
size, but they shed when the wearer comes first under the 
influence of sexual feelings, and shed all the quicker as this 



1483 



influence is the more powerful; and these are the last hairs to 
grow grey. 

Hairs if plucked out before maturity grow again; but they do not 
grow again if plucked out afterwards. Every hair is supplied with 
a mucous moisture at its root, and immediately after being 
plucked out it can lift light articles if it touch them with this 
mucus. 

Animals that admit of diversity of colour in the hair admit of a 
similar diversity to start with in the skin and in the cuticle of 
the tongue. 

In some cases among men the upper lip and the chin is thickly 
covered with hair, and in other cases these parts are smooth 
and the cheeks are hairy; and, by the way, smooth-chinned men 
are less inclined than bearded men to baldness. 

The hair is inclined to grow in certain diseases, especially in 
consumption, and in old age, and after death; and under these 
circumstances the hair hardens concomitantly with its growth, 
and the same duplicate phenomenon is observable in respect of 
the nails. 

In the case of men of strong sexual passions the congenital 
hairs shed the sooner, while the hairs of the after-growths are 
the quicker to come. When men are afflicted with varicose veins 
they are less inclined to take on baldness; and if they be bald 
when they become thus afflicted, they have a tendency to get 
their hair again. 

If a hair be cut, it does not grow at the point of section; but it 
gets longer by growing upward from below. In fishes the scales 
grow harder and thicker with age, and when the amimal gets 
emaciated or is growing old the scales grow harder. In 
quadrupeds as they grow old the hair in some and the wool in 
others gets deeper but scantier in amount: and the hooves or 



1484 



claws get larger in size; and the same is the case with the beaks 
of birds. The claws also increase in size, as do also the nails. 



12 

With regard to winged animals, such as birds, no creature is 
liable to change of colour by reason of age, excepting the crane. 
The wings of this bird are ash-coloured at first, but as it grows 
old the wings get black. Again, owing to special climatic 
influences, as when unusual frost prevails, a change is 
sometimes observed to take place in birds whose plumage is of 
one uniform colour; thus, birds that have dusky or downright 
black plumage turn white or grey, as the raven, the sparrow, and 
the swallow; but no case has ever yet been known of a change 
of colour from white to black. (Further, most birds change the 
colour of their plumage at different seasons of the year, so 
much so that a man ignorant of their habits might be mistaken 
as to their identity.) Some animals change the colour of their 
hair with a change in their drinking-water, for in some 
countries the same species of animal is found white in one 
district and black in another. And in regard to the commerce of 
the sexes, water in many places is of such peculiar quality that 
rams, if they have intercourse with the female after drinking it, 
beget black lambs, as is the case with the water of the Psychrus 
(so-called from its coldness), a river in the district of Assyritis in 
the Chalcidic Peninsula, on the coast of Thrace; and in 
Antandria there are two rivers of which one makes the lambs 
white and the other black. The river Scamander also has the 
reputation of making lambs yellow, and that is the reason, they 
say, why Homer designates it the 'Yellow River.' Animals as a 
general rule have no hair on their internal surfaces, and, in 



1485 



regard to their extremities, they have hair on the upper, but not 
on the lower side. 

The hare, or dasypod, is the only animal known to have hair 
inside its mouth and underneath its feet. Further, the so-called 
mousewhale instead of teeth has hairs in its mouth resembling 
pigs' bristles. 

Hairs after being cut grow at the bottom but not at the top; if 
feathers be cut off, they grow neither at top nor bottom, but 
shed and fall out. Further, the bee's wing will not grow again 
after being plucked off, nor will the wing of any creature that 
has undivided wings. Neither will the sting grow again if the bee 
lose it, but the creature will die of the loss. 



13 

In all sanguineous animals membranes are found. And 
membrane resembles a thin close-textured skin, but its 
qualities are different, as it admits neither of cleavage nor of 
extension. Membrane envelops each one of the bones and each 
one of the viscera, both in the larger and the smaller animals; 
though in the smaller animals the membranes are indiscernible 
from their extreme tenuity and minuteness. The largest of all 
the membranes are the two that surround the brain, and of 
these two the one that lines the bony skull is stronger and 
thicker than the one that envelops the brain; next in order of 
magnitude comes the membrane that encloses the heart. If 
membrane be bared and cut asunder it will not grow together 
again, and the bone thus stripped of its membrane mortifies. 



I486 



14 

The omentum or caul, by the way, is membrane. All 
sanguineous animals are furnished with this organ; but in some 
animals the organ is supplied with fat, and in others it is devoid 
of it. The omentum has both its starting-point and its 
attachment, with ambidental vivipara, in the centre of the 
stomach, where the stomach has a kind of suture; in non- 
ambidental vivipara it has its starting-point and attachment in 
the chief of the ruminating stomachs. 



15 

The bladder also is of the nature of membrane, but of 
membrane peculiar in kind, for it is extensile. The organ is not 
common to all animals, but, while it is found in all the vivipara, 
the tortoise is the only oviparous animal that is furnished 
therewithal. The bladder, like ordinary membrane, if cut 
asunder will not grow together again, unless the section be just 
at the commencement of the urethra: except indeed in very rare 
cases, for instances of healing have been known to occur. After 
death, the organ passes no liquid excretion; but in life, in 
addition to the normal liquid excretion, it passes at times dry 
excretion also, which turns into stones in the case of sufferers 
from that malady. Indeed, instances have been known of 
concretions in the bladder so shaped as closely to resemble 
cockleshells. 

Such are the properties, then, of vein, sinew and skin, of fibre 
and membrane, of hair, nail, claw and hoof, of horns, of teeth, of 



1487 



beak, of gristle, of bones, and of parts that are analogous to any 
of the parts here enumerated. 



16 

Flesh, and that which is by nature akin to it in sanguineous 
animals, is in all cases situated in between the skin and the 
bone, or the substance analogous to bone; for just as spine is a 
counterpart of bone, so is the flesh-like substance of animals 
that are constructed a spinous system the counterpart of the 
flesh of animals constructed on an osseous one. 

Flesh can be divided asunder in any direction, not lengthwise 
only as is the case with sinew and vein. When animals are 
subjected to emaciation the flesh disappears, and the creatures 
become a mass of veins and fibres; when they are over fed, fat 
takes the place of flesh. Where the flesh is abundant in an 
animal, its veins are somewhat small and the blood abnormally 
red; the viscera also and the stomach are diminutive; whereas 
with animals whose veins are large the blood is somewhat 
black, the viscera and the stomach are large, and the flesh is 
somewhat scanty. And animals with small stomachs are 
disposed to take on flesh. 



17 

Again, fat and suet differ from one another. Suet is frangible in 
all directions and congeals if subjected to extreme cold, 
whereas fat can melt but cannot freeze or congeal; and soups 
made of the flesh of animals supplied with fat do not congeal or 



1488 



coagulate, as is found with horse-flesh and pork; but soups 
made from the flesh of animals supplied with suet do coagulate, 
as is seen with mutton and goat's flesh. Further, fat and suet 
differ as to their localities: for fat is found between the skin and 
flesh, but suet is found only at the limit of the fleshy parts. Also, 
in animals supplied with fat the omentum or caul is supplied 
with fat, and it is supplied with suet in animals supplied with 
suet. Moreover, ambidental animals are supplied with fat, and 
non-ambidentals with suet. 

Of the viscera the liver in some animals becomes fatty, as, 
among fishes, is the case with the selachia, by the melting of 
whose livers an oil is manufactured. These cartilaginous fish 
themselves have no free fat at all in connexion with the flesh or 
with the stomach. The suet in fish is fatty, and does not solidify 
or congeal. All animals are furnished with fat, either 
intermingled with their flesh, or apart. Such as have no free or 
separate fat are less fat than others in stomach and omentum, 
as the eel; for it has only a scanty supply of suet about the 
omentum. Most animals take on fat in the belly, especially such 
animals as are little in motion. 

The brains of animals supplied with fat are oily, as in the pig; of 
animals supplied with suet, parched and dry. But it is about the 
kidneys more than any other viscera that animals are inclined 
to take on fat; and the right kidney is always less supplied with 
fat than the left kidney, and, be the two kidneys ever so fat, 
there is always a space devoid of fat in between the two. 
Animals supplied with suet are specially apt to have it about the 
kidneys, and especially the sheep; for this animal is apt to die 
from its kidneys being entirely enveloped. Fat or suet about the 
kidney is superinduced by overfeeding, as is found at Leontini in 
Sicily; and consequently in this district they defer driving out 
sheep to pasture until the day is well on, with the view of 
limiting their food by curtailment of the hours of pasture. 



1489 



18 

The part around the pupil of the eye is fatty in all animals, and 
this part resembles suet in all animals that possess such a part 
and that are not furnished with hard eyes. 

Fat animals, whether male or female, are more or less unfitted 
for breeding purposes. Animals are disposed to take on fat more 
when old than when young, and especially when they have 
attained their full breadth and their full length and are 
beginning to grow depthways. 



19 

And now to proceed to the consideration of the blood. In 
sanguineous animals blood is the most universal and the most 
indispensable part; and it is not an acquired or adventitious 
part, but it is a consubstantial part of all animals that are not 
corrupt or moribund. All blood is contained in a vascular 
system, to wit, the veins, and is found nowhere else, excepting 
in the heart. Blood is not sensitive to touch in any animal, any 
more than the excretions of the stomach; and the case is 
similar with the brain and the marrow. When flesh is lacerated, 
blood exudes, if the animal be alive and unless the flesh be 
gangrened. Blood in a healthy condition is naturally sweet to 
the taste, and red in colour, blood that deteriorates from natural 
decay or from disease more or less black. Blood at its best, 
before it undergoes deterioration from either natural decay or 
from disease, is neither very thick nor very thin. In the living 



1490 



animal it is always liquid and warm, but, on issuing from the 
body, it coagulates in all cases except in the case of the deer, the 
roe, and the like animals; for, as a general rule, blood coagulates 
unless the fibres be extracted. Bull's blood is the quickest to 
coagulate. 

Animals that are internally and externally viviparous are more 
abundantly supplied with blood than the sanguineous ovipara. 
Animals that are in good condition, either from natural causes 
or from their health having been attended to, have the blood 
neither too abundant - as creatures just after drinking have the 
liquid inside them in abundance - nor again very scanty, as is 
the case with animals when exceedingly fat. For animals in this 
condition have pure blood, but very little of it, and the fatter an 
animal gets the less becomes its supply of blood; for whatsoever 
is fat is destitute of blood. 

A fat substance is incorruptible, but blood and all things 
containing it corrupt rapidly, and this property characterizes 
especially all parts connected with the bones. Blood is finest 
and purest in man; and thickest and blackest in the bull and the 
ass, of all vivipara. In the lower and the higher parts of the body 
blood is thicker and blacker than in the central parts. 

Blood beats or palpitates in the veins of all animals alike all over 
their bodies, and blood is the only liquid that permeates the 
entire frames of living animals, without exception and at all 
times, as long as life lasts. Blood is developed first of all in the 
heart of animals before the body is differentiated as a whole. If 
blood be removed or if it escape in any considerable quantity, 
animals fall into a faint or swoon; if it be removed or if it escape 
in an exceedingly large quantity they die. If the blood get 
exceedingly liquid, animals fall sick; for the blood then turns 
into something like ichor, or a liquid so thin that it at times has 
been known to exude through the pores like sweat. In some 



1491 



cases blood, when issuing from the veins, does not coagulate at 
all, or only here and there. Whilst animals are sleeping the 
blood is less abundantly supplied near the exterior surfaces, so 
that, if the sleeping creature be pricked with a pin, the blood 
does not issue as copiously as it would if the creature were 
awake. Blood is developed out of ichor by coction, and fat in like 
manner out of blood. If the blood get diseased, haemorrhoids 
may ensue in the nostril or at the anus, or the veins may 
become varicose. Blood, if it corrupt in the body, has a tendency 
to turn into pus, and pus may turn into a solid concretion. 

Blood in the female differs from that in the male, for, supposing 
the male and female to be on a par as regards age and general 
health, the blood in the female is thicker and blacker than in 
the male; and with the female there is a comparative 
superabundance of it in the interior. Of all female animals the 
female in man is the most richly supplied with blood, and of all 
female animals the menstruous discharges are the most 
copious in woman. The blood of these discharges under disease 
turns into flux. Apart from the menstrual discharges, the female 
in the human species is less subject to diseases of the blood 
than the male. 

Women are seldom afflicted with varicose veins, with 
haemorrhoids, or with bleeding at the nose, and, if any of these 
maladies supervene, the menses are imperfectly discharged. 

Blood differs in quantity and appearance according to age; in 
very young animals it resembles ichor and is abundant, in the 
old it is thick and black and scarce, and in middle-aged animals 
its qualities are intermediate. In old animals the blood 
coagulates rapidly, even blood at the surface of the body; but 
this is not the case with young animals. Ichor is, in fact, nothing 
else but unconcocted blood: either blood that has not yet been 
concocted, or that has become fluid again. 



1492 



20 

We now proceed to discuss the properties of marrow; for this is 
one of the liquids found in certain sanguineous animals. All the 
natural liquids of the body are contained in vessels: as blood in 
veins, marrow in bones other moistures in membranous 
structures of the skin 

In young animals the marrow is exceedingly sanguineous, but, 
as animals grow old, it becomes fatty in animals supplied with 
fat, and suet-like in animals with suet. All bones, however, are 
not supplied with marrow, but only the hollow ones, and not all 
of these. For of the bones in the lion some contain no marrow at 
all, and some are only scantily supplied therewith; and that 
accounts, as was previously observed, for the statement made 
by certain writers that the lion is marrowless. In the bones of 
pigs it is found in small quantities; and in the bones of certain 
animals of this species it is not found at all. 

These liquids, then, are nearly always congenital in animals, but 
milk and sperm come at a later time. Of these latter, that which, 
whensoever it is present, is secreted in all cases ready-made, is 
the milk; sperm, on the other hand, is not secreted out in all 
cases, but in some only, as in the case of what are designated 
thori in fishes. 

Whatever animals have milk, have it in their breasts. All 
animals have breasts that are internally and externally 
viviparous, as for instance all animals that have hair, as man 
and the horse; and the cetaceans, as the dolphin, the porpoise, 
and the whale - for these animals have breasts and are supplied 
with milk. Animals that are oviparous or only externally 



1493 



viviparous have neither breasts nor milk, as the fish and the 
bird. 

All milk is composed of a watery serum called 'whey', and a 
consistent substance called curd (or cheese); and the thicker the 
milk, the more abundant the curd. The milk, then, of non- 
ambidentals coagulates, and that is why cheese is made of the 
milk of such animals under domestication; but the milk of 
ambidentals does not coagulate, nor their fat either, and the 
milk is thin and sweet. Now the camel's milk is the thinnest, 
and that of the human species next after it, and that of the ass 
next again, but cow's milk is the thickest. Milk does not 
coagulate under the influence of cold, but rather runs to whey; 
but under the influence of heat it coagulates and thickens. As a 
general rule milk only comes to animals in pregnancy. When 
the animal is pregnant milk is found, but for a while it is unfit 
for use, and then after an interval of usefulness it becomes unfit 
for use again. In the case of female animals not pregnant a 
small quantity of milk has been procured by the employment of 
special food, and cases have been actually known where women 
advanced in years on being submitted to the process of milking 
have produced milk, and in some cases have produced it in 
sufficient quantities to enable them to suckle an infant. 

The people that live on and about Mount Oeta take such she- 
goats as decline the male and rub their udders hard with nettles 
to cause an irritation amounting to pain; hereupon they milk 
the animals, procuring at first a liquid resembling blood, then a 
liquid mixed with purulent matter, and eventually milk, as 
freely as from females submitting to the male. 

As a general rule, milk is not found in the male of man or of any 
other animal, though from time to time it has been found in a 
male; for instance, once in Lemnos a he-goat was milked by its 
dugs (for it has, by the way, two dugs close to the penis), and 



1494 



was milked to such effect that cheese was made of the produce, 
and the same phenomenon was repeated in a male of its own 
begetting. Such occurrences, however, are regarded as 
supernatural and fraught with omen as to futurity, and in point 
of fact when the Lemnian owner of the animal inquired of the 
oracle, the god informed him that the portent foreshadowed the 
acquisition of a fortune. With some men, after puberty, milk can 
be produced by squeezing the breasts; cases have been known 
where on their being subjected to a prolonged milking process a 
considerable quantity of milk has been educed. 

In milk there is a fatty element, which in clotted milk gets to 
resemble oil. Goat's milk is mixed with sheep's milk in Sicily, 
and wherever sheep's milk is abundant. The best milk for 
clotting is not only that where the cheese is most abundant, but 
that also where the cheese is driest. 

Now some animals produce not only enough milk to rear their 
young, but a superfluous amount for general use, for cheese- 
making and for storage. This is especially the case with the 
sheep and the goat, and next in degree with the cow. Mare's 
milk, by the way, and milk of the she-ass are mixed in with 
Phrygian cheese. And there is more cheese in cow's milk than in 
goat's milk; for graziers tell us that from nine gallons of goat's 
milk they can get nineteen cheeses at an obol apiece, and from 
the same amount of cow's milk, thirty. Other animals give only 
enough of milk to rear their young withal, and no superfluous 
amount and none fitted for cheese-making, as is the case with 
all animals that have more than two breasts or dugs; for with 
none of such animals is milk produced in superabundance or 
used for the manufacture of cheese. 

The juice of the fig and rennet are employed to curdle milk. The 
fig-juice is first squeezed out into wool; the wool is then washed 
and rinsed, and the rinsing put into a little milk, and if this be 



1495 



mixed with other milk it curdles Rennet is a kind of milk, for it 
is found in the stomach of the animal while it is yet suckling. 



21 

Rennet then consists of milk with an admixture of fire, which 
comes from the natural heat of the animal, as the milk is 
concocted. All ruminating animals produce rennet, and, of 
ambidentals, the hare. Rennet improves in quality the longer it 
is kept; and cow's rennet, after being kept a good while, and also 
hare's rennet, is good for diarrhoea, and the best of all rennet is 
that of the young deer. 

In milk-producing animals the comparative amount of the yield 
varies with the size of the animal and the diversities of 
pasturage. For instance, there are in Phasis small cattle that in 
all cases give a copious supply of milk, and the large cows in 
Epirus yield each one daily some nine gallons of milk, and half 
of this from each pair of teats, and the milker has to stand erect, 
stooping forward a little, as otherwise, if he were seated, he 
would be unable to reach up to the teats. But, with the 
exception of the ass, all the quadrupeds in Epirus are of large 
size, and relatively, the cattle and the dogs are the largest. Now 
large animals require abundant pasture, and this country 
supplies just such pasturage, and also supplies diverse pasture 
grounds to suit the diverse seasons of the year. The cattle are 
particularly large, and likewise the sheep of the so-called 
Pyrrhic breed, the name being given in honour of King Pyrrhus. 

Some pasture quenches milk, as Median grass or lucerne, and 
that especially in ruminants; other feeding renders it copious, 
as cytisus and vetch; only, by the way, cytisus in flower is not 
recommended, as it has burning properties, and vetch is not 



1496 



good for pregnant kine, as it causes increased difficulty in 
parturition. However, beasts that have access to good feeding, as 
they are benefited thereby in regard to pregnancy, so also being 
well nourished produce milk in plenty. Some of the leguminous 
plants bring milk in abundance, as for instance, a large feed of 
beans with the ewe, the common she-goat, the cow, and the 
small she-goat; for this feeding makes them drop their udders. 
And, by the way, the pointing of the udder to the ground before 
parturition is a sign of there being plenty of milk coming. 

Milk remains for a long time in the female, if she be kept from 
the male and be properly fed, and, of quadrupeds, this is 
especially true of the ewe; for the ewe can be milked for eight 
months. As a general rule, ruminating animals give milk in 
abundance, and milk fitted for cheese manufacture. In the 
neighbourhood of Torone cows run dry for a few days before 
calving, and have milk all the rest of the time. In women, milk 
of a livid colour is better than white for nursing purposes; and 
swarthy women give healthier milk than fair ones. Milk that is 
richest in cheese is the most nutritious, but milk with a scanty 
supply of cheese is the more wholesome for children. 



22 

All sanguineous animals eject sperm. As to what, and how, it 
contributes to generation, these questions will be discussed in 
another treatise. Taking the size of his body into account, man 
emits more sperm than any other animal. In hairy-coated 
animals the sperm is sticky, but in other animals it is not so. It 
is white in all cases, and Herodotus is under a misapprehension 
when he states that the Aethiopians eject black sperm. 



1497 



Sperm issues from the body white and consistent, if it be 
healthy, and after quitting the body becomes thin and black. In 
frosty weather it does not coagulate, but gets exceedingly thin 
and watery both in colour and consistency; but it coagulates 
and thickens under the influence of heat. If it be long in the 
womb before issuing out, it comes more than usually thick; and 
sometimes it comes out dry and compact. Sperm capable of 
impregnating or of fructification sinks in water; sperm 
incapable Of producing that result dissolves away. But there is 
no truth in what Ctesias has written about the sperm of the 
elephant. 



Book IV 



We have now treated, in regard to blooded animals of the parts 
they have in common and of the parts peculiar to this genus or 
that, and of the parts both composite and simple, whether 
without or within. We now proceed to treat of animals devoid of 
blood. These animals are divided into several genera. 

One genus consists of so-called 'molluscs'; and by the term 
'mollusc' we mean an animal that, being devoid of blood, has its 
flesh-like substance outside, and any hard structure it may 
happen to have, inside - in this respect resembling the red - 
blooded animals, such as the genus of the cuttle-fish. 



1498 



Another genus is that of the malacostraca. These are animals 
that have their hard structure outside, and their soft or fleshlike 
substance inside, and the hard substance belonging to them has 
to be crushed rather than shattered; and to this genus belongs 
the crawfish and the crab. 

A third genus is that of the ostracoderms or 'testaceans'. These 
are animals that have their hard substance outside and their 
flesh-like substance within, and their hard substance can be 
shattered but not crushed; and to this genus belong the snail 
and the oyster. 

The fourth genus is that of insects; and this genus 
comprehends numerous and dissimilar species. Insects are 
creatures that, as the name implies, have nicks either on the 
belly or on the back, or on both belly and back, and have no one 
part distinctly osseous and no one part distinctly fleshy, but are 
throughout a something intermediate between bone and flesh; 
that is to say, their body is hard all through, inside and outside. 
Some insects are wingless, such as the iulus and the centipede; 
some are winged, as the bee, the cockchafer, and the wasp; and 
the same kind is in some cases both winged and wingless, as 
the ant and the glow-worm. 

In molluscs the external parts are as follows: in the first place, 
the so-called feet; secondly, and attached to these, the head; 
thirdly, the mantle-sac, containing the internal parts, and 
incorrectly designated by some writers the head; and, fourthly, 
fins round about the sac. (See diagram.) In all molluscs the head 
is found to be between the feet and the belly. All molluscs are 
furnished with eight feet, and in all cases these feet are 
severally furnished with a double row of suckers, with the 
exception of one single species of poulpe or octopus. The sepia, 
the small calamary and the large calamary have an exceptional 
organ in a pair of long arms or tentacles, having at their 



1499 



extremities a portion rendered rough by the presence of two 
rows of suckers; and with these arms or tentacles they 
apprehend their food and draw it into their mouths, and in 
stormy weather they cling by them to a rock and sway about in 
the rough water like ships lying at anchor. They swim by the aid 
of the fins that they have about the sac. In all cases their feet 
are furnished with suckers. 

The octopus, by the way, uses his feelers either as feet or hands; 
with the two which stand over his mouth he draws in food, and 
the last of his feelers he employs in the act of copulation; and 
this last one, by the way, is extremely sharp, is exceptional as 
being of a whitish colour, and at its extremity is bifurcate; that 
is to say, it has an additional something on the rachis, and by 
rachis is meant the smooth surface or edge of the arm on the 
far side from the suckers. (See diagram.) 

In front of the sac and over the feelers they have a hollow tube, 
by means of which they discharge any sea-water that they may 
have taken into the sac of the body in the act of receiving food 
by the mouth. They can shift the tube from side to side, and by 
means of it they discharge the black liquid peculiar to the 
animal. 

Stretching out its feet, it swims obliquely in the direction of the 
so-called head, and by this mode of swimming it can see in 
front, for its eyes are at the top, and in this attitude it has its 
mouth at the rear. The 'head', while the creature is alive, is hard, 
and looks as though it were inflated. It apprehends and retains 
objects by means of the under-surface of its arms, and the 
membrane in between its feet is kept at full tension; if the 
animal get on to the sand it can no longer retain its hold. 

There is a difference between the octopus and the other 
molluscs above mentioned: the body of the octopus is small, 
and his feet are long, whereas in the others the body is large 



1500 



and the feet short; so short, in fact, that they cannot walk on 
them. Compared with one another, the teuthis, or calamary, is 
long-shaped, and the sepia flat-shaped; and of the calamaries 
the so-called teuthus is much bigger than the teuthis; for teuthi 
have been found as much as five ells long. Some sepiae attain a 
length of two ells, and the feelers of the octopus are sometimes 
as long, or even longer. The species teuthus is not a numerous 
one; the teuthus differs from the teuthis in shape; that is, the 
sharp extremity of the teuthus is broader than that of the other, 
and, further, the encircling fin goes all round the trunk, whereas 
it is in part lacking in the teuthis; both animals are pelagic. 

In all cases the head comes after the feet, in the middle of the 
feet that are called arms or feelers. There is here situated a 
mouth, and two teeth in the mouth; and above these two large 
eyes, and betwixt the eyes a small cartilage enclosing a small 
brain; and within the mouth it has a minute organ of a fleshy 
nature, and this it uses as a tongue, for no other tongue does it 
possess. Next after this, on the outside, is what looks like a sac; 
the flesh of which it is made is divisible, not in long straight 
strips, but in annular flakes; and all molluscs have a cuticle 
around this flesh. Next after or at the back of the mouth comes 
a long and narrow oesophagus, and close after that a crop or 
craw, large and spherical, like that of a bird; then comes the 
stomach, like the fourth stomach in ruminants; and the shape 
of it resembles the spiral convolution in the trumpet-shell; from 
the stomach there goes back again, in the direction of the 
mouth, thin gut, and the gut is thicker than the oesophagus. 
(See diagram.) 

Molluscs have no viscera, but they have what is called a mytis, 
and on it a vessel containing a thick black juice; in the sepia or 
cuttle-fish this vessel is the largest, and this juice is most 
abundant. All molluscs, when frightened, discharge such a juice, 
but the discharge is most copious in the cuttle-fish. The mytis, 



1501 



then, is situated under the mouth, and the oesophagus runs 
through it; and down below at the point to which the gut 
extends is the vesicle of the black juice, and the animal has the 
vesicle and the gut enveloped in one and the same membrane, 
and by the same membrane, same orifice discharges both the 
black juice and the residuum. The animals have also certain 
hair-like or furry growths in their bodies. 

In the sepia, the teuthis, and the teuthus the hard parts are 
within, towards the back of the body; those parts are called in 
one the sepium, and in the other the 'sword'. They differ from 
one another, for the sepium in the cuttle-fish and teuthus is 
hard and flat, being a substance intermediate between bone and 
fishbone, with (in part) a crumbling, spongy texture, but in the 
teuthis the part is thin and somewhat gristly. These parts differ 
from one another in shape, as do also the bodies of the animals. 
The octopus has nothing hard of this kind in its interior, but it 
has a gristly substance round the head, which, if the animal 
grows old, becomes hard. 

The females differ from the males. The males have a duct in 
under the oesophagus, extending from the mantle-cavity to the 
lower portion of the sac, and there is an organ to which it 
attaches, resembling a breast; (see diagram) in the female there 
are two of these organs, situated higher up; (see diagram) with 
both sexes there are underneath these organs certain red 
formations. The egg of the octopus is single, uneven on its 
surface, and of large size; the fluid substance within is all 
uniform in colour, smooth, and in colour white; the size of the 
egg is so great as to fill a vessel larger than the creature's head. 
The sepia has two sacs, and inside them a number of eggs, like 
in appearance to white hailstones. For the disposition of these 
parts I must refer to my anatomical diagrams. 



1502 



The males of all these animals differ from the females, and the 
difference between the sexes is most marked in the sepia; for 
the back of the trunk, which is blacker than the belly, is rougher 
in the male than in the female, and in the male the back is 
striped, and the rump is more sharply pointed. 

There are several species of the octopus. One keeps close to the 
surface, and is the largest of them all, and near the shore the 
size is larger than in deep water; and there are others, small, 
variegated in colour, which are not articles of food. There are 
two others, one called the heledone, which differs from its 
congeners in the length of its legs and in having one row of 
suckers - all the rest of the molluscs having two, - the other 
nicknamed variously the bolitaina or the 'onion,' and the ozolis 
or the 'stinkard'. 

There are two others found in shells resembling those of the 
testaceans. One of them is nicknamed by some persons the 
nautilus or the pontilus, or by others the 'polypus' egg'; and the 
shell of this creature is something like a separate valve of a 
deep scallop-shell. This polypus lives very often near to the 
shore, and is apt to be thrown up high and dry on the beach; 
under these circumstances it is found with its shell detached, 
and dies by and by on dry land. These polypods are small, and 
are shaped, as regards the form of their bodies, like the bolbidia. 
There is another polypus that is placed within a shell like a 
snail; it never comes out of the shell, but lives inside the shell 
like the snail, and from time to time protrudes its feelers. 

So much for molluscs. 



1503 



With regard to the Malacostraca or crustaceans, one species is 
that of the crawfish, and a second, resembling the first, is that 
of the lobster; the lobster differing from the crawfish in having 
claws, and in a few other respects as well. Another species is 
that of the carid, and another is that of the crab, and there are 
many kinds both of carid and of crab. 

Of carids there are the so-called cyphae, or 'hunch-backs', the 
crangons, or squillae, and the little kind, or shrimps, and the 
little kind do not develop into a larger kind. 

Of the crab, the varieties are indefinite and incalculable. The 
largest of all crabs is one nicknamed Maia, a second variety is 
the pagarus and the crab of Heracleotis, and a third variety is 
the fresh-water crab; the other varieties are smaller in size and 
destitute of special designations. In the neighbourhood of 
Phoenice there are found on the beach certain crabs that are 
nicknamed the 'horsemen', from their running with such speed 
that it is difficult to overtake them; these crabs, when opened, 
are usually found empty, and this emptiness may be put down 
to insufficiency of nutriment. (There is another variety, small 
like the crab, but resembling in shape the lobster.) All these 
animals, as has been stated, have their hard and shelly part 
outside, where the skin is in other animals, and the fleshy part 
inside; and the belly is more or less provided with lamellae, or 
little flaps, and the female here deposits her spawn. 

The crawfishes have five feet on either side, including the claws 
at the end; and in like manner the crabs have ten feet in all, 
including the claws. Of the carids, the hunch-backed, or prawns, 
have five feet on either side, which are sharp-pointed - those 
towards the head; and five others on either side in the region of 
the belly, with their extremities flat; they are devoid of flaps on 
the under side such as the crawfish has, but on the back they 



1504 



resemble the crawfish. (See diagram.)It is very different with the 
crangon, or squilla; it has four front legs on either side, then 
three thin ones close behind on either side, and the rest of the 
body is for the most part devoid of feet. (See diagram.) Of all 
these animals the feet bend out obliquely, as is the case with 
insects; and the claws, where claws are found, turn inwards. 
The crawfish has a tail, and five fins on it; and the round- 
backed carid has a tail and four fins; the squilla also has fins at 
the tail on either side. In the case of both the hump-backed 
carid and the squilla the middle art of the tail is spinous: only 
that in the squilla the part is flattened and in the carid it is 
sharp-pointed. Of all animals of this genus the crab is the only 
one devoid of a rump; and, while the body of the carid and the 
crawfish is elongated, that of the crab is rotund. 

In the crawfish the male differs from the female: in the female 
the first foot is bifurcate, in the male it is undivided; the belly- 
fins in the female are large and overlapping on the neck, while 
in the male they are smaller and do not overlap; and, further, on 
the last feet of the male there are spur-like projections, large 
and sharp, which projections in the female are small and 
smooth. Both male and female have two antennae in front of 
the eyes, large and rough, and other antennae underneath, 
small and smooth. The eyes of all these creatures are hard and 
beady, and can move either to the inner or to the outer side. The 
eyes of most crabs have a similar facility of movement, or 
rather, in the crab this facility is developed in a higher degree. 
(See diagram.) 

The lobster is all over grey-coloured, with a mottling of black. Its 
under or hinder feet, up to the big feet or claws, are eight in 
number; then come the big feet, far larger and flatter at the tips 
than the same organs in the crawfish; and these big feet or 
claws are exceptional in their structure, for the right claw has 
the extreme flat surface long and thin, while the left claw has 



1505 



the corresponding surface thick and round. Each of the two 
claws, divided at the end like a pair of jaws, has both below and 
above a set of teeth: only that in the right claw they are all small 
and saw-shaped, while in the left claw those at the apex are 
saw-shaped and those within are molar-shaped, these latter 
being, in the under part of the cleft claw, four teeth close 
together, and in the upper part three teeth, not close together. 
Both right and left claws have the upper part mobile, and bring 
it to bear against the lower one, and both are curved like bandy- 
legs, being thereby adapted for apprehension and constriction. 
Above the two large claws come two others, covered with hair, a 
little underneath the mouth; and underneath these the gill-like 
formations in the region of the mouth, hairy and numerous. 
These organs the animal keeps in perpetual motion; and the 
two hairy feet it bends and draws in towards its mouth. The feet 
near the mouth are furnished also with delicate outgrowing 
appendages. Like the crawfish, the lobster has two teeth, or 
mandibles, and above these teeth are its antennae, long, but 
shorter and finer by far than those of the crawfish, and then 
four other antennae similar in shape, but shorter and finer than 
the others. Over these antennae come the eyes, small and short, 
not large like the eyes of the crawfish. Over the eyes is a peaky 
rough projection like a forehead, larger than the same part in 
the crawfish; in fact, the frontal part is more pointed and the 
thorax is much broader in the lobster than in the crawfish, and 
the body in general is smoother and more full of flesh. Of the 
eight feet, four are bifurcate at the extremities, and four are 
undivided. The region of the so-called neck is outwardly divided 
into five divisions, and sixthly comes the flattened portion at 
the end, and this portion has five flaps, or tail-fins; and the 
inner or under parts, into which the female drops her spawn, 
are four in number and hairy, and on each of the aforesaid parts 
is a spine turned outwards, short and straight. The body in 
general and the region of the thorax in particular are smooth, 



1506 



not rough as in the crawfish; but on the large claws the outer 
portion has larger spines. There is no apparent difference 
between the male and female, for they both have one claw, 
whichever it may be, larger than the other, and neither male nor 
female is ever found with both claws of the same size. 

All crustaceans take in water close by the mouth. The crab 
discharges it, closing up, as it does so, a small portion of the 
same, and the crawfish discharges it by way of the gills; and, by 
the way, the gill-shaped organs in the crawfish are very 
numerous. 

The following properties are common to all crustaceans: they 
have in all cases two teeth, or mandibles (for the front teeth in 
the crawfish are two in number), and in all cases there is in the 
mouth a small fleshy structure serving for a tongue; and the 
stomach is close to the mouth, only that the crawfish has a little 
oesophagus in front of the stomach, and there is a straight gut 
attached to it. This gut, in the crawfish and its congeners, and in 
the carids, extends in a straight line to the tail, and terminates 
where the animal discharges the residuum, and where the 
female deposits her spawn; in the crab it terminates where the 
flap is situated, and in the centre of the flap. (And by the way, in 
all these animals the spawn is deposited outside.) Further, the 
female has the place for the spawn running along the gut. And, 
again, all these animals have, more or less, an organ termed the 
'mytis', or 'poppyjuice'. 

We must now proceed to review their several differentiae. 

The crawfish then, as has been said, has two teeth, large and 
hollow, in which is contained a juice resembling the mytis, and 
in between the teeth is a fleshy substance, shaped like a tongue. 
After the mouth comes a short oesophagus, and then a 
membranous stomach attached to the oesophagus, and at the 
orifice Of the stomach are three teeth, two facing one another 



1507 



and a third standing by itself underneath. Coming off at a bend 
from the stomach is a gut, simple and of equal thickness 
throughout the entire length of the body until it reaches the 
anal vent. 

These are all common properties of the crawfish, the carid, and 
the crab; for the crab, be it remembered, has two teeth. 

Again, the crawfish has a duct attached all the way from the 
chest to the anal vent; and this duct is connected with the ovary 
in the female, and with the seminal ducts in the male. This 
passage is attached to the concave surface of the flesh in such a 
way that the flesh is in betwixt the duct and the gut; for the gut 
is related to the convexity and this duct to the concavity, pretty 
much as is observed in quadrupeds. And the duct is identical in 
both the sexes; that is to say, the duct in both is thin and white, 
and charged with a sallow-coloured moisture, and is attached to 
the chest. 

(The following are the properties of the egg and of the 
convolutes in the carid.) 

The male, by the way, differs from the female in regard to its 
flesh, in having in connexion with the chest two separate and 
distinct white substances, resembling in colour and 
conformation the tentacles of the cuttle-fish, and they are 
convoluted like the 'poppy' or quasi-liver of the trumpet-shell. 
These organs have their starting-point in 'cotyledons' or 
papillae, which are situated under the hindmost feet; and 
hereabouts the flesh is red and blood-coloured, but is slippery to 
the touch and in so far unlike flesh. Off from the convolute 
organ at the chest branches off another coil about as thick as 
ordinary twine; and underneath there are two granular seminal 
bodies in juxta-position with the gut. These are the organs of 
the male. The female has red-coloured eggs, which are adjacent 



1508 



to the stomach and to each side of the gut all along to the fleshy 
parts, being enveloped in a thin membrane. 

Such are the parts, internal and external, of the carid. 



The inner organs of sanguineous animals happen to have 
specific designations; for these animals have in all cases the 
inner viscera, but this is not the case with the bloodless 
animals, but what they have in common with red-blooded 
animals is the stomach, the oesophagus, and the gut. 

With regard to the crab, it has already been stated that it has 
claws and feet, and their position has been set forth; 
furthermore, for the most part they have the right claw bigger 
and stronger than the left. It has also been stated' that in 
general the eyes of the crab look sideways. Further, the trunk of 
the crab's body is single and undivided, including its head and 
any other part it may possess. Some crabs have eyes placed 
sideways on the upper part, immediately under the back, and 
standing a long way apart, and some have their eyes in the 
centre and close together, like the crabs of Heracleotis and the 
so-called 'grannies'. The mouth lies underneath the eyes, and 
inside it there are two teeth, as is the case with the crawfish, 
only that in the crab the teeth are not rounded but long; and 
over the teeth are two lids, and in betwixt them are structures 
such as the crawfish has besides its teeth. The crab takes in 
water near by the mouth, using the lids as a check to the inflow, 
and discharges the water by two passages above the mouth, 
closing by means of the lids the way by which it entered; and 
the two passage-ways are underneath the eyes. When it has 
taken in water it closes its mouth by means of both lids, and 



1509 



ejects the water in the way above described. Next after the teeth 
comes the oesophagus, very short, so short in fact that the 
stomach seems to come straightway after the mouth. Next after 
the oesophagus comes the stomach, two-horned, to the centre 
of which is attached a simple and delicate gut; and the gut 
terminates outwards, at the operculum, as has been previously 
stated. (The crab has the parts in between the lids in the 
neighbourhood of the teeth similar to the same parts in the 
crawfish.) Inside the trunk is a sallow juice and some few little 
bodies, long and white, and others spotted red. The male differs 
from the female in size and breadth, and in respect of the 
ventral flap; for this is larger in the female than in the male, and 
stands out further from the trunk, and is more hairy (as is the 
case also with the female in the crawfish). 

So much, then, for the organs of the malacostraca or Crustacea. 



With the ostracoderma, or testaceans, such as the land-snails 
and the sea-snails, and all the 'oysters' so-called, and also with 
the sea-urchin genus, the fleshy part, in such as have flesh, is 
similarly situated to the fleshy part in the crustaceans; in other 
words, it is inside the animal, and the shell is outside, and there 
is no hard substance in the interior. As compared with one 
another the testaceans present many diversities both in regard 
to their shells and to the flesh within. Some of them have no 
flesh at all, as the sea-urchin; others have flesh, but it is inside 
and wholly hidden, except the head, as in the land-snails, and 
the so-called cocalia, and, among pelagic animals, in the purple 
murex, the ceryx or trumpet-shell, the sea-snail, and the spiral- 
shaped testaceans in general. Of the rest, some are bivalved and 



1510 



some univalved; and by 'bivalves' I mean such as are enclosed 
within two shells, and by 'univalved' such as are enclosed 
within a single shell, and in these last the fleshy part is 
exposed, as in the case of the limpet. Of the bivalves, some can 
open out, like the scallop and the mussel; for all such shells are 
grown together on one side and are separate on the other, so as 
to open and shut. Other bivalves are closed on both sides alike, 
like the solen or razor-fish. Some testaceans there are, that are 
entirely enveloped in shell and expose no portion of their flesh 
outside, as the tethya or ascidians. 

Again, in regard to the shells themselves, the testaceans present 
differences when compared with one another. Some are 
smooth-shelled, like the solen, the mussel, and some clams, viz. 
those that are nicknamed 'milkshells', while others are rough- 
shelled, such as the pool-oyster or edible oyster, the pinna, and 
certain species of cockles, and the trumpet shells; and of these 
some are ribbed, such as the scallop and a certain kind of clam 
or cockle, and some are devoid of ribs, as the pinna and another 
species of clam. Testaceans also differ from one another in 
regard to the thickness or thinness of their shell, both as 
regards the shell in its entirety and as regards specific parts of 
the shell, for instance, the lips; for some have thin-lipped shells, 
like the mussel, and others have thick-lipped shells, like the 
oyster. A property common to the above mentioned, and, in fact, 
to all testaceans, is the smoothness of their shells inside. Some 
also are capable of motion, like the scallop, and indeed some 
aver that scallops can actually fly, owing to the circumstance 
that they often jump right out of the apparatus by means of 
which they are caught; others are incapable of motion and are 
attached fast to some external object, as is the case with the 
pinna. All the spiral-shaped testaceans can move and creep, and 
even the limpet relaxes its hold to go in quest of food. In the 
case of the univalves and the bivalves, the fleshy substance 
adheres to the shell so tenaciously that it can only be removed 



1511 



by an effort; in the case of the stromboids, it is more loosely 
attached. And a peculiarity of all the stromboids is the spiral 
twist of the shell in the part farthest away from the head; they 
are also furnished from birth with an operculum. And, further, 
all stromboid testaceans have their shells on the right hand 
side, and move not in the direction of the spire, but the opposite 
way. Such are the diversities observed in the external parts of 
these animals. 

The internal structure is almost the same in all these creatures, 
and in the stromboids especially; for it is in size that these 
latter differ from one another, and in accidents of the nature of 
excess or defect. And there is not much difference between 
most of the univalves and bivalves; but, while those that open 
and shut differ from one another but slightly, they differ 
considerably from such as are incapable of motion. And this will 
be illustrated more satisfactorily hereafter. 

The spiral-shaped testaceans are all similarly constructed, but 
differ from one another, as has been said, in the way of excess 
or defect (for the larger species have larger and more 
conspicuous organs, and the smaller have smaller and less 
conspicuous), and, furthermore, in relative hardness or softness, 
and in other such accidents or properties. All the stromboids, 
for instance, have the flesh that extrudes from the mouth of the 
shell, hard and stiff; some more, and some less. From the 
middle of this protrudes the head and two horns, and these 
horns are large in the large species, but exceedingly minute in 
the smaller ones. The head protrudes from them all in the same 
way; and, if the animal be alarmed, the head draws in again. 
Some of these creatures have a mouth and teeth, as the snail; 
teeth sharp, and small, and delicate. They have also a proboscis 
just like that of the fly; and the proboscis is tongue-shaped. The 
ceryx and the purple murex have this organ firm and solid; and 
just as the myops, or horse-fly, and the oestrus, or gadfly, can 



1512 



pierce the skin of a quadruped, so is that proboscis 
proportionately stronger in these testaceans; for they bore right 
through the shells of other shell-fish on which they prey. The 
stomach follows close upon the mouth, and, by the way, this 
organ in the snail resembles a bird's crop. Underneath come two 
white firm formations, mastoid or papillary in form; and similar 
formations are found in the cuttle-fish also, only that they are 
of a firmer consistency in the cuttle-fish. After the stomach 
comes an oesophagus, simple and long, extending to the poppy 
or quasi-liver, which is in the innermost recess of the shell. All 
these statements may be verified in the case of the purple 
murex and the ceryx by observation within the whorl of the 
shell. What comes next to the oesophagus is the gut; in fact, the 
gut is continuous with the oesophagus, and runs its whole 
length uncomplicated to the outlet of the residuum. The gut has 
its point of origin in the region of the coil of the mecon, or so- 
called 'poppy', and is wider hereabouts (for remember, the 
mecon is for the most part a sort of excretion in all testaceans); 
it then takes a bend and runs up again towards the fleshy part, 
and terminates by the side of the head, where the animal 
discharges its residuum; and this holds good in the case of all 
stromboid testaceans, whether terrestrial or marine. From the 
stomach there is drawn in a parallel direction with the 
oesophagus, in the larger snails, a long white duct enveloped in 
a membrane, resembling in colour the mastoid formations 
higher up; and in it are nicks or interruptions, as in the egg- 
mass of the crawfish, only, by the way, the duct of which we are 
treating is white and the egg-mass of the crawfish is red. This 
formation has no outlet nor duct, but is enveloped in a thin 
membrane with a narrow cavity in its interior. And from the gut 
downward extend black and rough formations, in close 
connexion, something like the formations in the tortoise, only 
not so black. Marine snails, also, have these formations, and the 



1513 



white ones, only that the formations are smaller in the smaller 
species. 

The non-spiral univalves and bivalves are in some respect 
similar in construction, and in some respects dissimilar, to the 
spiral testaceans. They all have a head and horns, and a mouth, 
and the organ resembling a tongue; but these organs, in the 
smaller species, are indiscernible owing to the minuteness of 
these animals, and some are indiscernible even in the larger 
species when dead, or when at rest and motionless. They all 
have the mecon, or poppy, but not all in the same place, nor of 
equal size, nor similarly open to observation; thus, the limpets 
have this organ deep down in the bottom of the shell, and the 
bivalves at the hinge connecting the two valves. They also have 
in all cases the hairy growths or beards, in a circular form, as in 
the scallops. And, with regard to the so-called 'egg', in those 
that have it, when they have it, it is situated in one of the semi- 
circles of the periphery, as is the case with the white formation 
in the snail; for this white formation in the snail corresponds to 
the so-called egg of which we are speaking. But all these organs, 
as has been stated, are distinctly traceable in the larger species, 
while in the small ones they are in some cases almost, and in 
others altogether, indiscernible. Hence they are most plainly 
visible in the large scallops; and these are the bivalves that have 
one valve flat-shaped, like the lid of a pot. The outlet of the 
excretion is in all these animals (save for the exception to be 
afterwards related) on one side; for there is a passage whereby 
the excretion passes out. (And, remember, the mecon or poppy, 
as has been stated, is an excretion in all these animals - an 
excretion enveloped in a membrane.) The so-called egg has no 
outlet in any of these creatures, but is merely an excrescence in 
the fleshy mass; and it is not situated in the same region with 
the gut, but the 'egg' is situated on the right-hand side and the 
gut on the left. Such are the relations of the anal vent in most of 
these animals; but in the case of the wild limpet (called by some 



1514 



the 'sea-ear'), the residuum issues beneath the shell, for the 
shell is perforated to give an outlet. In this particular limpet the 
stomach is seen coming after the mouth, and the egg-shaped 
formations are discernible. But for the relative positions of these 
parts you are referred to my Treatise on Anatomy. 

The so-called carcinium or hermit crab is in a way intermediate 
between the crustaceans and the testaceans. In its nature it 
resembles the crawfish kind, and it is born simple of itself, but 
by its habit of introducing itself into a shell and living there it 
resembles the testaceans, and so appears to partake of the 
characters of both kinds. In shape, to give a simple illustration, 
it resembles a spider, only that the part below the head and 
thorax is larger in this creature than in the spider. It has two 
thin red horns, and underneath these horns two long eyes, not 
retreating inwards, nor turning sideways like the eyes of the 
crab, but protruding straight out; and underneath these eyes the 
mouth, and round about the mouth several hair-like growths, 
and next after these two bifurcate legs or claws, whereby it 
draws in objects towards itself, and two other legs on either 
side, and a third small one. All below the thorax is soft, and 
when opened in dissection is found to be sallow-coloured 
within. From the mouth there runs a single passage right on to 
the stomach, but the passage for the excretions is not 
discernible. The legs and the thorax are hard, but not so hard as 
the legs and the thorax of the crab. It does not adhere to its 
shell like the purple murex and the ceryx, but can easily slip out 
of it. It is longer when found in the shell of the stromboids than 
when found in the shell of the neritae. 

And, by the way, the animal found in the shell of the neritae is a 
separate species, like to the other in most respects; but of its 
bifurcate feet or claws, the right-hand one is small and the left- 
hand one is large, and it progresses chiefly by the aid of this 
latter and larger one. (In the shells of these animals, and in 



1515 



certain others, there is found a parasite whose mode of 
attachment is similar. The particular one which we have just 
described is named the cyllarus.) 

The nerites has a smooth large round shell, and resembles the 
ceryx in shape, only the poppy-juice is, in its case, not black but 
red. It clings with great force near the middle. In calm weather, 
then, they go free afield, but when the wind blows the carcinia 
take shelter against the rocks: the neritae themselves cling fast 
like limpets; and the same is the case with the haemorrhoid or 
aporrhaid and all others of the like kind. And, by the way, they 
cling to the rock, when they turn back their operculum, for this 
operculum seems like a lid; in fact this structure represents the 
one part, in the stromboids, of that which in the bivalves is a 
duplicate shell. The interior of the animal is fleshy, and the 
mouth is inside. And it is the same with the haemorrhoid, the 
purple murex, and all suchlike animals. 

Such of the little crabs as have the left foot or claw the bigger of 
the two are found in the neritae, but not in the stromboids. are 
some snail-shells which have inside them creatures resembling 
those little crayfish that are also found in fresh water. These 
creatures, however, differ in having the part inside the shells 
But as to the characters, you are referred to my Treatise on 
Anatomy. 



The urchins are devoid of flesh, and this is a character peculiar 
to them; and while they are in all cases empty and devoid of 
any flesh within, they are in all cases furnished with the black 
formations. There are several species of the urchin, and one of 
these is that which is made use of for food; this is the kind in 



1516 



which are found the so-called eggs, large and edible, in the 
larger and smaller specimens alike; for even when as yet very 
small they are provided with them. There are two other species, 
the spatangus, and the so-called bryssus, these animals are 
pelagic and scarce. Further, there are the echinometrae, or 
'mother-urchins', the largest in size of all the species. In 
addition to these there is another species, small in size, but 
furnished with large hard spines; it lives in the sea at a depth of 
several fathoms; and is used by some people as a specific for 
cases of strangury. In the neighbourhood of Torone there are 
sea-urchins of a white colour, shells, spines, eggs and all, and 
that are longer than the ordinary sea-urchin. The spine in this 
species is not large nor strong, but rather limp; and the black 
formations in connexion with the mouth are more than usually 
numerous, and communicate with the external duct, but not 
with one another; in point of fact, the animal is in a manner 
divided up by them. The edible urchin moves with greatest 
freedom and most often; and this is indicated by the fact that 
these urchins have always something or other on their spines. 

All urchins are supplied with eggs, but in some of the species 
the eggs are exceedingly small and unfit for food. Singularly 
enough, the urchin has what we may call its head and mouth 
down below, and a place for the issue of the residuum up above; 
(and this same property is common to all stromboids and to 
limpets). For the food on which the creature lives lies down 
below; consequently the mouth has a position well adapted for 
getting at the food, and the excretion is above, near to the back 
of the shell. The urchin has, also, five hollow teeth inside, and in 
the middle of these teeth a fleshy substance serving the office 
of a tongue. Next to this comes the oesophagus, and then the 
stomach, divided into five parts, and filled with excretion, all 
the five parts uniting at the anal vent, where the shell is 
perforated for an outlet. Underneath the stomach, in another 
membrane, are the so-called eggs, identical in number in all 



1517 



cases, and that number is always an odd number, to wit five. Up 
above, the black formations are attached to the starting-point of 
the teeth, and they are bitter to the taste, and unfit for food. A 
similar or at least an analogous formation is found in many 
animals; as, for instance, in the tortoise, the toad, the frog, the 
stromboids, and, generally, in the molluscs; but the formation 
varies here and there in colour, and in all cases is altogether 
uneatable, or more or less unpalatable. In reality the mouth- 
apparatus of the urchin is continuous from one end to the other, 
but to outward appearance it is not so, but looks like a horn 
lantern with the panes of horn left out. The urchin uses its 
spines as feet; for it rests its weight on these, and then moving 
shifts from place to place. 



The so-called tethyum or ascidian has of all these animals the 
most remarkable characteristics. It is the only mollusc that has 
its entire body concealed within its shell, and the shell is a 
substance intermediate between hide and shell, so that it cuts 
like a piece of hard leather. It is attached to rocks by its shell, 
and is provided with two passages placed at a distance from 
one another, very minute and hard to see, whereby it admits 
and discharges the sea-water; for it has no visible excretion 
(whereas of shell fish in general some resemble the urchin in 
this matter of excretion, and others are provided with the so- 
called mecon, or poppy-juice). If the animal be opened, it is 
found to have, in the first place, a tendinous membrane running 
round inside the shell-like substance, and within this 
membrane is the flesh-like substance of the ascidian, not 
resembling that in other molluscs; but this flesh, to which I now 
allude, is the same in all ascidia. And this substance is attached 



1518 



in two places to the membrane and the skin, obliquely; and at 
the point of attachment the space is narrowed from side to side, 
where the fleshy substance stretches towards the passages that 
lead outwards through the shell; and here it discharges and 
admits food and liquid matter, just as it would if one of the 
passages were a mouth and the other an anal vent; and one of 
the passages is somewhat wider than the other Inside it has a 
pair of cavities, one on either side, a small partition separating 
them; and one of these two cavities contains the liquid. The 
creature has no other organ whether motor or sensory, nor, as 
was said in the case of the others, is it furnished with any organ 
connected with excretion, as other shell-fish are. The colour of 
the ascidian is in some cases sallow, and in other cases red. 

There is, furthermore, the genus of the sea-nettles, peculiar in 
its way. The sea-nettle, or sea-anemone, clings to rocks like 
certain of the testaceans, but at times relaxes its hold. It has no 
shell, but its entire body is fleshy. It is sensitive to touch, and, if 
you put your hand to it, it will seize and cling to it, as the 
cuttlefish would do with its feelers, and in such a way as to 
make the flesh of your hand swell up. Its mouth is in the centre 
of its body, and it lives adhering to the rock as an oyster to its 
shell. If any little fish come up against it it it clings to it; in fact, 
just as I described it above as doing to your hand, so it does to 
anything edible that comes in its way; and it feeds upon sea- 
urchins and scallops. Another species of the sea-nettle roams 
freely abroad. The sea-nettle appears to be devoid altogether of 
excretion, and in this respect it resembles a plant. 

Of sea-nettles there are two species, the lesser and more edible, 
and the large hard ones, such as are found in the 
neighbourhood of Chalcis. In winter time their flesh is firm, and 
accordingly they are sought after as articles of food, but in 
summer weather they are worthless, for they become thin and 
watery, and if you catch at them they break at once into bits, 



1519 



and cannot be taken off the rocks entire; and being oppressed 
by the heat they tend to slip back into the crevices of the rocks. 

So much for the external and the internal organs of molluscs, 
crustaceans, and testaceans. 



We now proceed to treat of insects in like manner. This genus 
comprises many species, and, though several kinds are clearly 
related to one another, these are not classified under one 
common designation, as in the case of the bee, the drone, the 
wasp, and all such insects, and again as in the case of those that 
have their wings in a sheath or shard, like the cockchafer, the 
carabus or stag-beetle, the cantharis or blister-beetle, and the 
like. 

Insects have three parts common to them all; the head, the 
trunk containing the stomach, and a third part in betwixt these 
two, corresponding to what in other creatures embraces chest 
and back. In the majority of insects this intermediate part is 
single; but in the long and multipedal insects it has practically 
the same number of segments as of nicks. 

All insects when cut in two continue to live, excepting such as 
are naturally cold by nature, or such as from their minute size 
chill rapidly; though, by the way, wasps notwithstanding their 
small size continue living after severance. In conjunction with 
the middle portion either the head or the stomach can live, but 
the head cannot live by itself. Insects that are long in shape and 
many-footed can live for a long while after being cut in twain, 
and the severed portions can move in either direction, 
backwards or forwards; thus, the hinder portion, if cut off, can 



1520 



crawl either in the direction of the section or in the direction of 
the tail, as is observed in the scolopendra. 

All insects have eyes, but no other organ of sense discernible, 
except that some insects have a kind of a tongue corresponding 
to a similar organ common to all testaceans; and by this organ 
such insects taste and imbibe their food. In some insects this 
organ is soft; in other insects it is firm; as it is, by the way, in the 
purple-fish, among testaceans. In the horsefly and the gadfly 
this organ is hard, and indeed it is hard in most insects. In point 
of fact, such insects as have no sting in the rear use this organ 
as a weapon, (and, by the way, such insects as are provided with 
this organ are unprovided with teeth, with the exception of a 
few insects); the fly by a touch can draw blood with this organ, 
and the gnat can prick or sting with it. 

Certain insects are furnished with prickers or stings. Some 
insects have the sting inside, as the bee and the wasp, others 
outside, as the scorpion; and, by the way, this is the only insect 
furnished with a long tail. And, further, the scorpion is 
furnished with claws, as is also the creature resembling a 
scorpion found within the pages of books. 

In addition to their other organs, flying insects are furnished 
with wings. Some insects are dipterous or double-winged, as 
the fly; others are tetrapterous or furnished with four wings, as 
the bee; and, by the way, no insect with only two wings has a 
sting in the rear. Again, some winged insects have a sheath or 
shard for their wings, as the cockchafer; whereas in others the 
wings are unsheathed, as in the bee. But in the case of all alike, 
flight is in no way modified by tail-steerage, and the wing is 
devoid of quill-structure or division of any kind. 

Again, some insects have antennae in front of their eyes, as the 
butterfly and the horned beetle. Such of them as have the power 
of jumping have the hinder legs the longer; and these long 



1521 



hind-legs whereby they jump bend backwards like the hind-legs 
of quadrupeds. All insects have the belly different from the 
back; as, in fact, is the case with all animals. The flesh of an 
insect's body is neither shell-like nor is it like the internal 
substance of shell-covered animals, nor is it like flesh in the 
ordinary sense of the term; but it is a something intermediate in 
quality. Wherefore they have nor spine, nor bone, nor sepia- 
bone, nor enveloping shell; but their body by its hardness is its 
own protection and requires no extraneous support. However, 
insects have a skin; but the skin is exceedingly thin. These and 
such-like are the external organs of insects. 

Internally, next after the mouth, comes a gut, in the majority of 
cases straight and simple down to the outlet of the residuum: 
but in a few cases the gut is coiled. No insect is provided with 
any viscera, or is supplied with fat; and these statements apply 
to all animals devoid of blood. Some have a stomach also, and 
attached to this the rest of the gut, either simple or convoluted 
as in the case of the acris or grasshopper. 

The tettix or cicada, alone of such creatures (and, in fact, alone 
of all creatures), is unprovided with a mouth, but it is provided 
with the tongue-like formation found in insects furnished with 
frontward stings; and this formation in the cicada is long, 
continuous, and devoid of any split; and by the aid of this the 
creature feeds on dew, and on dew only, and in its stomach no 
excretion is ever found. Of the cicada there are several kinds, 
and they differ from one another in relative magnitude, and in 
this respect that the achetes or chirper is provided with a cleft 
or aperture under the hypozoma and has in it a membrane 
quite discernible, whilst the membrane is indiscernible in the 
tettigonia. 

Furthermore, there are some strange creatures to be found in 
the sea, which from their rarity we are unable to classify. 



1522 



Experienced fishermen affirm, some that they have at times 
seen in the sea animals like sticks, black, rounded, and of the 
same thickness throughout; others that they have seen 
creatures resembling shields, red in colour, and furnished with 
fins packed close together; and others that they have seen 
creatures resembling the male organ in shape and size, with a 
pair of fins in the place of the testicles, and they aver that on 
one occasion a creature of this description was brought up on 
the end of a nightline. 

So much then for the parts, external and internal, exceptional 
and common, of all animals. 



8 

We now proceed to treat of the senses; for there are diversities 
in animals with regard to the senses, seeing that some animals 
have the use of all the senses, and others the use of a limited 
number of them. The total number of the senses (for we have no 
experience of any special sense not here included), is five: sight, 
hearing, smell, taste, and touch. 

Man, then, and all vivipara that have feet, and, further, all red- 
blooded ovipara, appear to have the use of all the five senses, 
except where some isolated species has been subjected to 
mutilation, as in the case of the mole. For this animal is 
deprived of sight; it has no eyes visible, but if the skin - a thick 
one, by the way - be stripped off the head, about the place in the 
exterior where eyes usually are, the eyes are found inside in a 
stunted condition, furnished with all the parts found in 
ordinary eyes; that is to say, we find there the black rim, and the 
fatty part surrounding it; but all these parts are smaller than 
the same parts in ordinary visible eyes. There is no external sign 



1523 



of the existence of these organs in the mole, owing to the 
thickness of the skin drawn over them, so that it would seem 
that the natural course of development were congenitally 
arrested; (for extending from the brain at its junction with the 
marrow are two strong sinewy ducts running past the sockets of 
the eyes, and terminating at the upper eye-teeth). All the other 
animals of the kinds above mentioned have a perception of 
colour and of sound, and the senses of smell and taste; the fifth 
sense, that, namely, of touch, is common to all animals 
whatsoever. 

In some animals the organs of sense are plainly discernible; and 
this is especially the case with the eyes. For animals have a 
special locality for the eyes, and also a special locality for 
hearing: that is to say, some animals have ears, while others 
have the passage for sound discernible. It is the same with the 
sense of smell; that is to say, some animals have nostrils, and 
others have only the passages for smell, such as birds. It is the 
same also with the organ of taste, the tongue. Of aquatic red- 
blooded animals, fishes possess the organ of taste, namely the 
tongue, but it is in an imperfect and amorphous form, in other 
words it is osseous and undetached. In some fish the palate is 
fleshy, as in the fresh-water carp, so that by an inattentive 
observer it might be mistaken for a tongue. 

There is no doubt but that fishes have the sense of taste, for a 
great number of them delight in special flavours; and fishes 
freely take the hook if it be baited with a piece of flesh from a 
tunny or from any fat fish, obviously enjoying the taste and the 
eating of food of this kind. Fishes have no visible organs for 
hearing or for smell; for what might appear to indicate an organ 
for smell in the region of the nostril has no communication 
with the brain. These indications, in fact, in some cases lead 
nowhere, like blind alleys, and in other cases lead only to the 
gills; but for all this fishes undoubtedly hear and smell. For they 



1524 



are observed to run away from any loud noise, such as would be 
made by the rowing of a galley, so as to become easy of capture 
in their holes; for, by the way, though a sound be very slight in 
the open air, it has a loud and alarming resonance to creatures 
that hear under water. And this is shown in the capture of the 
dolphin; for when the hunters have enclosed a shoal of these 
fishes with a ring of their canoes, they set up from inside the 
canoes a loud splashing in the water, and by so doing induce 
the creatures to run in a shoal high and dry up on the beach, 
and so capture them while stupefied with the noise. And yet, for 
all this, the dolphin has no organ of hearing discernible. 
Furthermore, when engaged in their craft, fishermen are 
particularly careful to make no noise with oar or net; and after 
they have spied a shoal, they let down their nets at a spot so far 
off that they count upon no noise being likely to reach the 
shoal, occasioned either by oar or by the surging of their boats 
through the water; and the crews are strictly enjoined to 
preserve silence until the shoal has been surrounded. And, at 
times, when they want the fish to crowd together, they adopt 
the stratagem of the dolphin-hunter; in other words they clatter 
stones together, that the fish may, in their fright, gather close 
into one spot, and so they envelop them within their nets. 
(Before surrounding them, then, they preserve silence, as was 
said; but, after hemming the shoal in, they call on every man to 
shout out aloud and make any kind of noise; for on hearing the 
noise and hubbub the fish are sure to tumble into the nets from 
sheer fright.) Further, when fishermen see a shoal of fish 
feeding at a distance, disporting themselves in calm bright 
weather on the surface of the water, if they are anxious to 
descry the size of the fish and to learn what kind of a fish it is, 
they may succeed in coming upon the shoal whilst yet basking 
at the surface if they sail up without the slightest noise, but if 
any man make a noise previously, the shoal will be seen to 
scurry away in alarm. Again, there is a small river-fish called the 



1525 



cottus or bullhead; this creature burrows under a rock, and 
fishers catch it by clattering stones against the rock, and the 
fish, bewildered at the noise, darts out of its hiding-place. From 
these facts it is quite obvious that fishes can hear; and indeed 
some people, from living near the sea and frequently witnessing 
such phenomena, affirm that of all living creatures the fish is 
the quickest of hearing. And, by the way, of all fishes the 
quickest of hearing are the cestreus or mullet, the chremps, the 
labrax or basse, the salpe or saupe, the chromis or sciaena, and 
such like. Other fishes are less quick of hearing, and, as might 
be expected, are more apt to be found living at the bottom of 
the sea. 

The case is similar in regard to the sense of smell. Thus, as a 
rule, fishes will not touch a bait that is not fresh, neither are 
they all caught by one and the same bait, but they are severally 
caught by baits suited to their several likings, and these baits 
they distinguish by their sense of smell; and, by the way, some 
fishes are attracted by malodorous baits, as the saupe, for 
instance, is attracted by excrement. Again, a number of fishes 
live in caves; and accordingly fishermen, when they want to 
entice them out, smear the mouth of a cave with strong- 
smelling pickles, and the fish are Soon attracted to the smell. 
And the eel is caught in a similar way; for the fisherman lays 
down an earthen pot that has held pickles, after inserting a 
'weel' in the neck thereof. As a general rule, fishes are especially 
attracted by savoury smells. For this reason, fishermen roast the 
fleshy parts of the cuttle-fish and use it as bait on account of its 
smell, for fish are peculiarly attracted by it; they also bake the 
octopus and bait their fish-baskets or weels with it, entirely, as 
they say, on account of its smell. Furthermore, gregarious fishes, 
if fish washings or bilge-water be thrown overboard, are 
observed to scud off to a distance, from apparent dislike of the 
smell. And it is asserted that they can at once detect by smell 
the presence of their own blood; and this faculty is manifested 



1526 



by their hurrying off to a great distance whenever fish-blood is 
spilt in the sea. And, as a general rule, if you bait your weel with 
a stinking bait, the fish refuse to enter the weel or even to draw 
near; but if you bait the weel with a fresh and savoury bait, they 
come at once from long distances and swim into it. And all this 
is particularly manifest in the dolphin; for, as was stated, it has 
no visible organ of hearing, and yet it is captured when 
stupefied with noise; and so, while it has no visible organ for 
smell, it has the sense of smell remarkably keen. It is manifest, 
then, that the animals above mentioned are in possession of all 
the five senses. 

All other animals may, with very few exceptions, be 
comprehended within four genera: to wit, molluscs, 
crustaceans, testaceans, and insects. Of these four genera, the 
mollusc, the crustacean, and the insect have all the senses: at 
all events, they have sight, smell, and taste. As for insects, both 
winged and wingless, they can detect the presence of scented 
objects afar off, as for instance bees and snipes detect the 
presence of honey at a distance; and do so recognizing it by 
smell. Many insects are killed by the smell of brimstone; ants, if 
the apertures to their dwellings be smeared with powdered 
origanum and brimstone, quit their nests; and most insects may 
be banished with burnt hart's horn, or better still by the burning 
of the gum styrax. The cuttle-fish, the octopus, and the crawfish 
may be caught by bait. The octopus, in fact, clings so tightly to 
the rocks that it cannot be pulled off, but remains attached even 
when the knife is employed to sever it; and yet, if you apply 
fleabane to the creature, it drops off at the very smell of it. The 
facts are similar in regard to taste. For the food that insects go 
in quest of is of diverse kinds, and they do not all delight in the 
same flavours: for instance, the bee never settles on a withered 
or wilted flower, but on fresh and sweet ones; and the conops or 
gnat settles only on acrid substances and not on sweet. The 
sense of touch, by the way, as has been remarked, is common to 



1527 



all animals. Testaceans have the senses of smell and taste. With 
regard to their possession of the sense of smell, that is proved 
by the use of baits, e.g. in the case of the purple-fish; for this 
creature is enticed by baits of rancid meat, which it perceives 
and is attracted to from a great distance. The proof that it 
possesses a sense of taste hangs by the proof of its sense of 
smell; for whenever an animal is attracted to a thing by 
perceiving its smell, it is sure to like the taste of it. Further, all 
animals furnished with a mouth derive pleasure or pain from 
the touch of sapid juices. 

With regard to sight and hearing, we cannot make statements 
with thorough confidence or on irrefutable evidence. However, 
the solen or razor-fish, if you make a noise, appears to burrow 
in the sand, and to hide himself deeper when he hears the 
approach of the iron rod (for the animal, be it observed, juts a 
little out of its hole, while the greater part of the body remains 
within), - and scallops, if you present your finger near their 
open valves, close them tight again as though they could see 
what you were doing. Furthermore, when fishermen are laying 
bait for neritae, they always get to leeward of them, and never 
speak a word while so engaged, under the firm impression that 
the animal can smell and hear; and they assure us that, if any 
one speaks aloud, the creature makes efforts to escape. With 
regard to testaceans, of the walking or creeping species the 
urchin appears to have the least developed sense of smell; and, 
of the stationary species, the ascidian and the barnacle. 

So much for the organs of sense in the general run of animals. 
We now proceed to treat of voice. 



1528 



Voice and sound are different from one another; and language 
differs from voice and sound. The fact is that no animal can give 
utterance to voice except by the action of the pharynx, and 
consequently such animals as are devoid of lung have no voice; 
and language is the articulation of vocal sounds by the 
instrumentality of the tongue. Thus, the voice and larynx can 
emit vocal or vowel sounds; non-vocal or consonantal sounds 
are made by the tongue and the lips; and out of these vocal and 
non-vocal sounds language is composed. Consequently, animals 
that have no tongue at all or that have a tongue not freely 
detached, have neither voice nor language; although, by the 
way, they may be enabled to make noises or sounds by other 
organs than the tongue. 

Insects, for instance, have no voice and no language, but they 
can emit sound by internal air or wind, though not by the 
emission of air or wind; for no insects are capable of respiration. 
But some of them make a humming noise, like the bee and the 
other winged insects; and others are said to sing, as the cicada. 
And all these latter insects make their special noises by means 
of the membrane that is underneath the 'hypozoma' - those 
insects, that is to say, whose body is thus divided; as for 
instance, one species of cicada, which makes the sound by 
means of the friction of the air. Flies and bees, and the like, 
produce their special noise by opening and shutting their wings 
in the act of flying; for the noise made is by the friction of air 
between the wings when in motion. The noise made by 
grasshoppers is produced by rubbing or reverberating with their 
long hind-legs. 

No mollusc or crustacean can produce any natural voice or 
sound. Fishes can produce no voice, for they have no lungs, nor 
windpipe and pharynx; but they emit certain inarticulate 



1529 



sounds and squeaks, which is what is called their 'voice', as the 
lyra or gurnard, and the sciaena (for these fishes make a 
grunting kind of noise) and the caprus or boar-fish in the river 
Achelous, and the chalcis and the cuckoo-fish; for the chalcis 
makes a sort piping sound, and the cuckoo-fish makes a sound 
greatly like the cry of the cuckoo, and is nicknamed from the 
circumstance. The apparent voice in all these fishes is a sound 
caused in some cases by a rubbing motion of their gills, which 
by the way are prickly, or in other cases by internal parts about 
their bellies; for they all have air or wind inside them, by 
rubbing and moving which they produce the sounds. Some 
cartilaginous fish seem to squeak. 

But in these cases the term 'voice' is inappropriate; the more 
correct expression would be 'sound'. For the scallop, when it 
goes along supporting itself on the water, which is technically 
called 'flying', makes a whizzing sound; and so does the sea- 
swallow or flying-fish: for this fish flies in the air, clean out of 
the water, being furnished with fins broad and long. Just then as 
in the flight of birds the sound made by their wings is obviously 
not voice, so is it in the case of all these other creatures. 

The dolphin, when taken out of the water, gives a squeak and 
moans in the air, but these noises do not resemble those above 
mentioned. For this creature has a voice (and can therefore 
utter vocal or vowel sounds), for it is furnished with a lung and 
a windpipe; but its tongue is not loose, nor has it lips, so as to 
give utterance to an articulate sound (or a sound of vowel and 
consonant in combination.) 

Of animals which are furnished with tongue and lung, the 
oviparous quadrupeds produce a voice, but a feeble one; in 
some cases, a shrill piping sound, like the serpent; in others, a 
thin faint cry; in others, a low hiss, like the tortoise. The 
formation of the tongue in the frog is exceptional. The front part 



1530 



of the tongue, which in other animals is detached, is tightly 
fixed in the frog as it is in all fishes; but the part towards the 
pharynx is freely detached, and may, so to speak, be spat 
outwards, and it is with this that it makes its peculiar croak. The 
croaking that goes on in the marsh is the call of the males to 
the females at rutting time; and, by the way, all animals have a 
special cry for the like end at the like season, as is observed in 
the case of goats, swine, and sheep. (The bull-frog makes its 
croaking noise by putting its under jaw on a level with the 
surface of the water and extending its upper jaw to its utmost 
capacity. The tension is so great that the upper jaw becomes 
transparent, and the animal's eyes shine through the jaw like 
lamps; for, by the way, the commerce of the sexes takes place 
usually in the night time.) Birds can utter vocal sounds; and 
such of them can articulate best as have the tongue moderately 
flat, and also such as have thin delicate tongues. In some cases, 
the male and the female utter the same note; in other cases, 
different notes. The smaller birds are more vocal and given to 
chirping than the larger ones; but in the pairing season every 
species of bird becomes particularly vocal. Some of them call 
when fighting, as the quail, others cry or crow when challenging 
to combat, as the partridge, or when victorious, as the barn-door 
cock. In some cases cock-birds and hens sing alike, as is 
observed in the nightingale, only that the hen stops singing 
when brooding or rearing her young; in other birds, the cocks 
sing more than the hens; in fact, with barn-door fowls and 
quails, the cock sings and the hen does not. 

Viviparous quadrupeds utter vocal sounds of different kinds, 
but they have no power of converse. In fact, this power, or 
language, is peculiar to man. For while the capability of talking 
implies the capability of uttering vocal sounds, the converse 
does not hold good. Men that are born deaf are in all cases also 
dumb; that is, they can make vocal sounds, but they cannot 
speak. Children, just as they have no control over other parts, so 



1531 



have no control, at first, over the tongue; but it is so far 
imperfect, and only frees and detaches itself by degrees, so that 
in the interval children for the most part lisp and stutter. 

Vocal sounds and modes of language differ according to locality. 
Vocal sounds are characterized chiefly by their pitch, whether 
high or low, and the kinds of sound capable of being produced 
are identical within the limits of one and the same species; but 
articulate sound, that one might reasonably designate 
'language', differs both in various animals, and also in the same 
species according to diversity of locality; as for instance, some 
partridges cackle, and some make a shrill twittering noise. Of 
little birds, some sing a different note from the parent birds, if 
they have been removed from the nest and have heard other 
birds singing; and a mother-nightingale has been observed to 
give lessons in singing to a young bird, from which spectacle we 
might obviously infer that the song of the bird was not equally 
congenital with mere voice, but was something capable of 
modification and of improvement. Men have the same voice or 
vocal sounds, but they differ from one another in speech or 
language. 

The elephant makes a vocal sound of a windlike sort by the 
mouth alone, unaided by the trunk, just like the sound of a man 
panting or sighing; but, if it employ the trunk as well, the sound 
produced is like that of a hoarse trumpet. 



10 

With regard to the sleeping and waking of animals, all creatures 
that are red-blooded and provided with legs give sensible proof 
that they go to sleep and that they waken up from sleep; for, as 
a matter of fact, all animals that are furnished with eyelids shut 



1532 



them up when they go to sleep. Furthermore, it would appear 
that not only do men dream, but horses also, and dogs, and 
oxen; aye, and sheep, and goats, and all viviparous quadrupeds; 
and dogs show their dreaming by barking in their sleep. With 
regard to oviparous animals we cannot be sure that they dream, 
but most undoubtedly they sleep. And the same may be said of 
water animals, such as fishes, molluscs, crustaceans, to wit 
crawfish and the like. These animals sleep without doubt, 
although their sleep is of very short duration. The proof of their 
sleeping cannot be got from the condition of their eyes - for 
none of these creatures are furnished with eyelids - but can be 
obtained only from their motionless repose. 

Apart from the irritation caused by lice and what are 
nicknamed fleas, fish are met with in a state so motionless that 
one might easily catch them by hand; and, as a matter of fact, 
these little creatures, if the fish remain long in one position, will 
attack them in myriads and devour them. For these parasites 
are found in the depths of the sea, and are so numerous that 
they devour any bait made of fish's flesh if it be left long on the 
ground at the bottom; and fishermen often draw up a cluster of 
them, all clinging on to the bait. 

But it is from the following facts that we may more reasonably 
infer that fishes sleep. Very often it is possible to take a fish off 
its guard so far as to catch hold of it or to give it a blow 
unawares; and all the while that you are preparing to catch or 
strike it, the fish is quite still but for a slight motion of the tail. 
And it is quite obvious that the animal is sleeping, from its 
movements if any disturbance be made during its repose; for it 
moves just as you would expect in a creature suddenly 
awakened. Further, owing to their being asleep, fish may be 
captured by torchlight. The watchmen in the tunny-fishery 
often take advantage of the fish being asleep to envelop them in 
a circle of nets; and it is quite obvious that they were thus 



1533 



sleeping by their lying still and allowing the glistening under- 
pays of their bodies to become visible, while the capture is 
taking Place. They sleep in the night-time more than during the 
day; and so soundly at night that you may cast the net without 
making them stir. Fish, as a general rule, sleep close to the 
ground, or to the sand or to a stone at the bottom, or after 
concealing themselves under a rock or the ground. Flat fish go 
to sleep in the sand; and they can be distinguished by the 
outlines of their shapes in the sand, and are caught in this 
position by being speared with pronged instruments. The basse, 
the chrysophrys or gilt-head, the mullet, and fish of the like sort 
are often caught in the daytime by the prong owing to their 
having been surprised when sleeping; for it is scarcely probable 
that fish could be pronged while awake. Cartilaginous fish sleep 
at times so soundly that they may be caught by hand. The 
dolphin and the whale, and all such as are furnished with a 
blow-hole, sleep with the blow-hole over the surface of the 
water, and breathe through the blow-hole while they keep up a 
quiet flapping of their fins; indeed, some mariners assure us 
that they have actually heard the dolphin snoring. 

Molluscs sleep like fishes, and crustaceans also. It is plain also 
that insects sleep; for there can be no mistaking their condition 
of motionless repose. In the bee the fact of its being asleep is 
very obvious; for at night-time bees are at rest and cease to 
hum. But the fact that insects sleep may be very well seen in 
the case of common every-day creatures; for not only do they 
rest at night-time from dimness of vision (and, by the way, all 
hard-eyed creatures see but indistinctly), but even if a lighted 
candle be presented they continue sleeping quite as soundly. 

Of all animals man is most given to dreaming. Children and 
infants do not dream, but in most cases dreaming comes on at 
the age of four or five years. Instances have been known of full- 
grown men and women that have never dreamed at all; in 



1534 



exceptional cases of this kind, it has been observed that when a 
dream occurs in advanced life it prognosticates either actual 
dissolution or a general break-up of the system. 

So much then for sensation and for the phenomena of sleeping 
and of awakening. 



11 

With regard to sex, some animals are divided into male and 
female, but others are not so divided but can only be said in a 
comparative way to bring forth young and to be pregnant. In 
animals that live confined to one spot there is no duality of sex; 
nor is there such, in fact, in any testaceans. In molluscs and in 
crustaceans we find male and female: and, indeed, in all 
animals furnished with feet, biped or quadruped; in short, in all 
such as by copulation engender either live young or egg or grub. 
In the several genera, with however certain exceptions, there 
either absolutely is or absolutely is not a duality of sex. Thus, in 
quadrupeds the duality is universal, while the absence of such 
duality is universal in testaceans, and of these creatures, as 
with plants, some individuals are fruitful and some are not their 
lying still 

But among insects and fishes, some cases are found wholly 
devoid of this duality of sex. For instance, the eel is neither male 
nor female, and can engender nothing. In fact, those who assert 
that eels are at times found with hair-like or worm-like progeny 
attached, make only random assertions from not having 
carefully noticed the locality of such attachments. For no eel 
nor animal of this kind is ever viviparous unless previously 
oviparous; and no eel was ever yet seen with an egg. And 
animals that are viviparous have their young in the womb and 



1535 



closely attached, and not in the belly; for, if the embryo were 
kept in the belly, it would be subjected to the process of 
digestion like ordinary food. When people rest duality of sex in 
the eel on the assertion that the head of the male is bigger and 
longer, and the head of the female smaller and more snubbed, 
they are taking diversity of species for diversity of sex. 

There are certain fish that are nicknamed the epitragiae, or 
capon-fish, and, by the way, fish of this description are found in 
fresh water, as the carp and the balagrus. This sort of fish never 
has either roe or milt; but they are hard and fat all over, and are 
furnished with a small gut; and these fish are regarded as of 
super-excellent quality. 

Again, just as in testaceans and in plants there is what bears 
and engenders, but not what impregnates, so is it, among fishes, 
with the psetta, the erythrinus, and the channe; for these fish 
are in all cases found furnished with eggs. 

As a general rule, in red-blooded animals furnished with feet 
and not oviparous, the male is larger and longer-lived than the 
female (except with the mule, where the female is longer-lived 
and bigger than the male); whereas in oviparous and 
vermiparous creatures, as in fishes and in insects, the female is 
larger than the male; as, for instance, with the serpent, the 
phalangium or venom-spider, the gecko, and the frog. The same 
difference in size of the sexes is found in fishes, as, for instance, 
in the smaller cartilaginous fishes, in the greater part of the 
gregarious species, and in all that live in and about rocks. The 
fact that the female is longer-lived than the male is inferred 
from the fact that female fishes are caught older than males. 
Furthermore, in all animals the upper and front parts are better, 
stronger, and more thoroughly equipped in the male than in the 
female, whereas in the female those parts are the better that 
may be termed hinder-parts or underparts. And this statement 



1536 



is applicable to man and to all vivipara that have feet. Again, the 
female is less muscular and less compactly jointed, and more 
thin and delicate in the hair - that is, where hair is found; and, 
where there is no hair, less strongly furnished in some 
analogous substance. And the female is more flaccid in texture 
of flesh, and more knock-kneed, and the shin-bones are 
thinner; and the feet are more arched and hollow in such 
animals as are furnished with feet. And with regard to voice, the 
female in all animals that are vocal has a thinner and sharper 
voice than the male; except, by the way, with kine, for the 
lowing and bellowing of the cow has a deeper note than that of 
the bull. With regard to organs of defence and offence, such as 
teeth, tusks, horns, spurs, and the like, these in some species 
the male possesses and the female does not; as, for instance, 
the hind has no horns, and where the cock-bird has a spur the 
hen is entirely destitute of the organ; and in like manner the 
sow is devoid of tusks. In other species such organs are found in 
both sexes, but are more perfectly developed in the male; as, for 
instance, the horn of the bull is more powerful than the horn of 
the cow. 



BookV 



As to the parts internal and external that all animals are 
furnished withal, and further as to the senses, to voice, and 



1537 



sleep, and the duality sex, all these topics have now been 
touched upon. It now remains for us to discuss, duly and in 
order, their several modes of propagation. 

These modes are many and diverse, and in some respects are 
like, and in other respects are unlike to one another. As we 
carried on our previous discussion genus by genus, so we must 
attempt to follow the same divisions in our present argument; 
only that whereas in the former case we started with a 
consideration of the parts of man, in the present case it behoves 
us to treat of man last of all because he involves most 
discussion. We shall commence, then, with testaceans, and then 
proceed to crustaceans, and then to the other genera in due 
order; and these other genera are, severally, molluscs, and 
insects, then fishes viviparous and fishes oviparous, and next 
birds; and afterwards we shall treat of animals provided with 
feet, both such as are oviparous and such as are viviparous, and 
we may observe that some quadrupeds are viviparous, but that 
the only viviparous biped is man. 

Now there is one property that animals are found to have in 
common with plants. For some plants are generated from the 
seed of plants, whilst other plants are self-generated through 
the formation of some elemental principle similar to a seed; 
and of these latter plants some derive their nutriment from the 
ground, whilst others grow inside other plants, as is mentioned, 
by the way, in my treatise on Botany. So with animals, some 
spring from parent animals according to their kind, whilst 
others grow spontaneously and not from kindred stock; and of 
these instances of spontaneous generation some come from 
putrefying earth or vegetable matter, as is the case with a 
number of insects, while others are spontaneously generated in 
the inside of animals out of the secretions of their several 
organs. 



1538 



In animals where generation goes by heredity, wherever there is 
duality of sex generation is due to copulation. In the group of 
fishes, however, there are some that are neither male nor 
female, and these, while they are identical generically with 
other fish, differ from them specifically; but there are others 
that stand altogether isolated and apart by themselves. Other 
fishes there are that are always female and never male, and 
from them are conceived what correspond to the wind-eggs in 
birds. Such eggs, by the way, in birds are all unfruitful; but it is 
their nature to be independently capable of generation up to the 
egg-stage, unless indeed there be some other mode than the 
one familiar to us of intercourse with the male; but concerning 
these topics we shall treat more precisely later on. In the case of 
certain fishes, however, after they have spontaneously 
generated eggs, these eggs develop into living animals; only that 
in certain of these cases development is spontaneous, and in 
others is not independent of the male; and the method of 
proceeding in regard to these matters will set forth by and by, 
for the method is somewhat like to the method followed in the 
case of birds. But whensoever creatures are spontaneously 
generated, either in other animals, in the soil, or on plants, or in 
the parts of these, and when such are generated male and 
female, then from the copulation of such spontaneously 
generated males and females there is generated a something- a 
something never identical in shape with the parents, but a 
something imperfect. For instance, the issue of copulation in 
lice is nits; in flies, grubs; in fleas, grubs egg-like in shape; and 
from these issues the parent-species is never reproduced, nor is 
any animal produced at all, but the like nondescripts only. 

First, then, we must proceed to treat of 'covering' in regard to 
such animals as cover and are covered; and then after this to 
treat in due order of other matters, both the exceptional and 
those of general occurrence. 



1539 



Those animals, then, cover and are covered in which there is a 
duality of sex, and the modes of covering in such animals are 
not in all cases similar nor analogous. For the red-blooded 
animals that are viviparous and furnished with feet have in all 
cases organs adapted for procreation, but the sexes do not in all 
cases come together in like manner. Thus, opisthuretic animals 
copulate with a rearward presentment, as is the case with the 
lion, the hare, and the lynx; though, by the way, in the case of 
the hare, the female is often observed to cover the male. 

The case is similar in most other such animals; that is to say, 
the majority of quadrupeds copulate as best they can, the male 
mounting the female; and this is the only method of copulating 
adopted by birds, though there are certain diversities of method 
observed even in birds. For in some cases the female squats on 
the ground and the male mounts on top of her, as is the case 
with the cock and hen bustard, and the barn-door cock and hen; 
in other cases, the male mounts without the female squatting, 
as with the male and female crane; for, with these birds, the 
male mounts on to the back of the female and covers her, and 
like the cock-sparrow consumes but very little time in the 
operation. Of quadrupeds, bears perform the operation lying 
prone on one another, in the same way as other quadrupeds do 
while standing up; that is to say, with the belly of the male 
pressed to the back of the female. Hedgehogs copulate erect, 
belly to belly. 

With regard to large-sized vivipara, the hind only very rarely 
sustains the mounting of the stag to the full conclusion of the 
operation, and the same is the case with the cow as regards the 



1540 



bull, owing to the rigidity of the penis of the bull. In point of 
fact, the females of these animals elicit the sperm of the male 
in the act of withdrawing from underneath him; and, by the 
way, this phenomenon has been observed in the case of the stag 
and hind, domesticated, of course. Covering with the wolf is the 
same as with the dog. Cats do not copulate with a rearward 
presentment on the part of the female, but the male stands 
erect and the female puts herself underneath him; and, by the 
way, the female cat is peculiarly lecherous, and wheedles the 
male on to sexual commerce, and caterwauls during the 
operation. Camels copulate with the female in a sitting posture, 
and the male straddles over and covers her, not with the hinder 
presentment on the female's part but like the other quadrupeds 
mentioned above, and they pass the whole day long in the 
operation; when thus engaged they retire to lonely spots, and 
none but their keeper dare approach them. And, be it observed, 
the penis of the camel is so sinewy that bow-strings are 
manufactured out of it. Elephants, also, copulate in lonely 
places, and especially by river-sides in their usual haunts; the 
female squats down, and straddles with her legs, and the male 
mounts and covers her. The seal covers like all opisthuretic 
animals, and in this species the copulation extends over a 
lengthened time, as is the case with the dog and bitch; and the 
penis in the male seal is exceptionally large. 



Oviparous quadrupeds cover one another in the same way. That 
is to say, in some cases the male mounts the female precisely as 
in the viviparous animals, as is observed in both the land and 
the sea tortoise.... And these creatures have an organ in which 
the ducts converge, and with which they perform the act of 



1541 



copulation, as is also observed in the toad, the frog, and all 
other animals of the same group. 



Long animals devoid of feet, like serpents and muraenae, 
intertwine in coition, belly to belly. And, in fact, serpents coil 
round one another so tightly as to present the appearance of a 
single serpent with a pair of heads. The same mode is followed 
by the saurians; that is to say, they coil round one another in the 
act of coition. 



All fishes, with the exception of the flat selachians, lie down 
side by side, and copulate belly to belly. Fishes, however, that are 
flat and furnished with tails - as the ray, the trygon, and the like 
- copulate not only in this way, but also, where the tail from its 
thinness is no impediment, by mounting of the male upon the 
female, belly to back. But the rhina or angel-fish, and other like 
fishes where the tail is large, copulate only by rubbing against 
one another sideways, belly to belly. Some men assure us that 
they have seen some of the selachia copulating hindways, dog 
and bitch. In the cartilaginous species the female is larger than 
the male; and the same is the case with other fishes for the 
most part. And among cartilaginous fishes are included, besides 
those already named, the bos, the lamia, the aetos, the narce or 
torpedo, the fishing-frog, and all the galeodes or sharks and 
dogfish. Cartilaginous fishes, then, of all kinds, have in many 



1542 



instances been observed copulating in the way above 
mentioned; for, by the way, in viviparous animals the process of 
copulation is of longer duration than in the ovipara. 

It is the same with the dolphin and with all cetaceans; that is to 
say, they come side by side, male and female, and copulate, and 
the act extends over a time which is neither short nor very long. 

Again, in cartilaginous fishes the male, in some species, differs 
from the female in the fact that he is furnished with two 
appendages hanging down from about the exit of the residuum, 
and that the female is not so furnished; and this distinction 
between the sexes is observed in all the species of the sharks 
and dog-fish. 

Now neither fishes nor any animals devoid of feet are furnished 
with testicles, but male serpents and male fishes have a pair of 
ducts which fill with milt or sperm at the rutting season, and 
discharge, in all cases, a milk-like juice. These ducts unite, as in 
birds; for birds, by the way, have their testicles in their interior, 
and so have all ovipara that are furnished with feet. And this 
union of the ducts is so far continued and of such extension as 
to enter the receptive organ in the female. 

In viviparous animals furnished with feet there is outwardly 
one and the same duct for the sperm and the liquid residuum; 
but there are separate ducts internally, as has been observed in 
the differentiation of the organs. And with such animals as are 
not viviparous the same passage serves for the discharge also of 
the solid residuum; although, internally, there are two passages, 
separate but near to one another. And these remarks apply to 
both male and female; for these animals are unprovided with a 
bladder except in the case of the tortoise; and the she-tortoise, 
though furnished with a bladder, has only one passage; and 
tortoises, by the way, belong to the ovipara. 



1543 



In the case of oviparous fishes the process of coition is less 
open to observation. In point of fact, some are led by the want 
of actual observation to surmise that the female becomes 
impregnated by swallowing the seminal fluid of the male. And 
there can be no doubt that this proceeding on the part of the 
female is often witnessed; for at the rutting season the females 
follow the males and perform this operation, and strike the 
males with their mouths under the belly, and the males are 
thereby induced to part with the sperm sooner and more 
plentifully. And, further, at the spawning season the males go in 
pursuit of the females, and, as the female spawns, the males 
swallow the eggs; and the species is continued in existence by 
the spawn that survives this process. On the coast of Phoenicia 
they take advantage of these instinctive propensities of the two 
sexes to catch both one and the other: that is to say, by using 
the male of the grey mullet as a decoy they collect and net the 
female, and by using the female, the male. 

The repeated observation of this phenomenon has led to the 
notion that the process was equivalent to coition, but the fact is 
that a similar phenomenon is observable in quadrupeds. For at 
the rutting seasons both the males and the females take to 
running at their genitals, and the two sexes take to smelling 
each other at those parts. (With partridges, by the way, if the 
female gets to leeward of the male, she becomes thereby 
impregnated. And often when they happen to be in heat she is 
affected in this wise by the voice of the male, or by his 
breathing down on her as he flies overhead; and, by the way, 
both the male and the female partridge keep the mouth wide 
open and protrude the tongue in the process of coition.) 

The actual process of copulation on the part of oviparous fishes 
is seldom accurately observed, owing to the fact that they very 
soon fall aside and slip asunder. But, for all that, the process has 
been observed to take place in the manner above described. 



1544 



Molluscs, such as the octopus, the sepia, and the calamary, have 
sexual intercourse all in the same way; that is to say, they unite 
at the mouth, by an interlacing of their tentacles. When, then, 
the octopus rests its so-called head against the ground and 
spreads abroad its tentacles, the other sex fits into the 
outspreading of these tentacles, and the two sexes then bring 
their suckers into mutual connexion. 

Some assert that the male has a kind of penis in one of his 
tentacles, the one in which are the largest suckers; and they 
further assert that the organ is tendinous in character, growing 
attached right up to the middle of the tentacle, and that the 
latter enables it to enter the nostril or funnel of the female. 

Now cuttle-fish and calamaries swim about closely intertwined, 
with mouths and tentacles facing one another and fitting 
closely together, and swim thus in opposite directions; and they 
fit their so-called nostrils into one another, and the one sex 
swims backwards and the other frontwards during the 
operation. And the female lays its spawn by the so-called 'blow- 
hole'; and, by the way, some declare that it is at this organ that 
the coition really takes place. 



Crustaceans copulate, as the crawfish, the lobster, the carid and 
the like, just like the opisthuretic quadrupeds, when the one 
animal turns up its tail and the other puts his tail on the other's 



1545 



tail. Copulation takes place in the early spring, near to the 
shore; and, in fact, the process has often been observed in the 
case of all these animals. Sometimes it takes place about the 
time when the figs begin to ripen. Lobsters and carids copulate 
in like manner. 

Crabs copulate at the front parts of one another, belly to belly, 
throwing their overlapping opercula to meet one another: first 
the smaller crab mounts the larger at the rear; after he has 
mounted, the larger one turns on one side. Now, the female 
differs in no respect from the male except in the circumstance 
that its operculum is larger, more elevated, and more hairy, and 
into this operculum it spawns its eggs and in the same 
neighbourhood is the outlet of the residuum. In the copulative 
process of these animals there is no protrusion of a member 
from one animal into the other. 



8 

Insects copulate at the hinder end, and the smaller individuals 
mount the larger; and the smaller individual is the male. The 
female pushes from underneath her sexual organ into the body 
of the male above, this being the reverse of the operation 
observed in other creatures; and this organ in the case of some 
insects appears to be disproportionately large when compared 
to the size of the body, and that too in very minute creatures; in 
some insects the disproportion is not so striking. This 
phenomenon may be witnessed if any one will pull asunder 
flies that are copulating; and, by the way, these creatures are, 
under the circumstances, averse to separation; for the 
intercourse of the sexes in their case is of long duration, as may 
be observed with common everyday insects, such as the fly and 



1546 



the cantharis. They all copulate in the manner above described, 
the fly, the cantharis, the sphondyle, (the phalangium spider) 
any others of the kind that copulate at all. The phalangia - that 
is to say, such of the species as spin webs - perform the 
operation in the following way: the female takes hold of the 
suspended web at the middle and gives a pull, and the male 
gives a counter pull; this operation they repeat until they are 
drawn in together and interlaced at the hinder ends; for, by the 
way, this mode of copulation suits them in consequence of the 
rotundity of their stomachs. 

So much for the modes of sexual intercourse in all animals; but, 
with regard to the same phenomenon, there are definite laws 
followed as regards the season of the year and the age of the 
animal. 

Animals in general seem naturally disposed to this intercourse 
at about the same period of the year, and that is when winter is 
changing into summer. And this is the season of spring, in 
which almost all things that fly or walk or swim take to pairing. 
Some animals pair and breed in autumn also and in winter, as 
is the case with certain aquatic animals and certain birds. Man 
pairs and breeds at all seasons, as is the case also with 
domesticated animals, owing to the shelter and good feeding 
they enjoy: that is to say, with those whose period of gestation 
is also comparatively brief, as the sow and the bitch, and with 
those birds that breed frequently. Many animals time the 
season of intercourse with a view to the right nurture 
subsequently of their young. In the human species, the male is 
more under sexual excitement in winter, and the female in 
summer. 

With birds the far greater part, as has been said, pair and breed 
during the spring and early summer, with the exception of the 
halcyon. 



1547 



The halcyon breeds at the season of the winter solstice. 
Accordingly, when this season is marked with calm weather, the 
name of 'halcyon days' is given to the seven days preceding, and 
to as many following, the solstice; as Simonides the poet says: 

God lulls for fourteen days the winds to sleep 

In winter; and this temperate interlude 

Men call the Holy Season, when the deep 

Cradles the mother Halcyon and her brood. 

And these days are calm, when southerly winds prevail at the 
solstice, northerly ones having been the accompaniment of the 
Pleiads. The halcyon is said to take seven days for building her 
nest, and the other seven for laying and hatching her eggs. In 
our country there are not always halcyon days about the time of 
the winter solstice, but in the Sicilian seas this season of calm is 
almost periodical. The bird lays about five eggs. 



(The aithyia, or diver, and the larus, or gull, lay their eggs on 
rocks bordering on the sea, two or three at a time; but the gull 
lays in the summer, and the diver at the beginning of spring, 
just after the winter solstice, and it broods over its eggs as birds 
do in general. And neither of these birds resorts to a hiding- 
place.) 

The halcyon is the most rarely seen of all birds. It is seen only 
about the time of the setting of the Pleiads and the winter 
solstice. When ships are lying at anchor in the roads, it will 
hover about a vessel and then disappear in a moment, and 



1548 



Stesichorus in one of his poems alludes to this peculiarity. The 
nightingale also breeds at the beginning of summer, and lays 
five or six eggs; from autumn until spring it retires to a hiding- 
place. 

Insects copulate and breed in winter also, that is when the 
weather is fine and south winds prevail; such, I mean, as do not 
hibernate, as the fly and the ant. The greater part of wild 
animals bring forth once and once only in the year, except in 
the case of animals like the hare, where the female can become 
superfoetally impregnated. 

In like manner the great majority of fishes breed only once a 
year, like the shoal-fishes (or, in other words, such as are caught 
in nets), the tunny, the pelamys, the grey mullet, the chalcis, the 
mackerel, the sciaena, the psetta and the like, with the 
exception of the labrax or basse; for this fish (alone amongst 
those mentioned) breeds twice a year, and the second brood is 
the weaker of the two. The trichias and the rock-fishes breed 
twice a year; the red mullet breeds thrice a year, and is 
exceptional in this respect. This conclusion in regard to the red 
mullet is inferred from the spawn; for the spawn of the fish may 
be seen in certain places at three different times of the year. The 
scorpaena breeds twice a year. The sargue breeds twice, in the 
spring and in the autumn. The saupe breeds once a year only, in 
the autumn. The female tunny breeds only once a year, but 
owing to the fact that the fish in some cases spawn early and in 
others late, it looks as though the fish bred twice over. The first 
spawning takes place in December before the solstice, and the 
latter spawning in the spring. The male tunny differs from the 
female in being unprovided with the fin beneath the belly 
which is called aphareus. 



1549 



10 

Of cartilaginous fishes, the rhina or angelfish is the only one 
that breeds twice; for it breeds at the beginning of autumn, and 
at the setting of the Pleiads: and, of the two seasons, it is in 
better condition in the autumn. It engenders at a birth seven or 
eight young. Certain of the dog-fishes, for example the spotted 
dog, seem to breed twice a month, and this results from the 
circumstance that the eggs do not all reach maturity at the 
same time. 

Some fishes breed at all seasons, as the muraena. This animal 
lays a great number of eggs at a time; and the young when 
hatched are very small but grow with great rapidity, like the 
young of the hippurus, for these fishes from being diminutive at 
the outset grow with exceptional rapidity to an exceptional size. 
(Be it observed that the muraena breeds at all seasons, but the 
hippurus only in the spring. The smyrus differs from the 
smyraena; for the muraena is mottled and weakly, whereas the 
smyrus is strong and of one uniform colour, and the colour 
resembles that of the pine-tree, and the animal has teeth inside 
and out. They say that in this case, as in other similar ones, the 
one is the male, and the other the female, of a single species. 
They come out on to the land, and are frequently caught.) 
Fishes, then, as a general rule, attain their full growth with great 
rapidity, but this is especially the case, among small fishes, with 
the coracine or crow-fish: it spawns, by the way, near the shore, 
in weedy and tangled spots. The orphus also, or sea-perch, is 
small at first, and rapidly attains a great size. The pelamys and 
the tunny breed in the Euxine, and nowhere else. The cestreus 
or mullet, the chrysophrys or gilt-head, and the labrax or basse, 
breed best where rivers run into the sea. The orcys or large- 
sized tunny, the scorpis, and many other species spawn in the 
open sea. 



1550 



11 

Fish for the most part breed some time or other during the 
three months between the middle of March and the middle of 
June. Some few breed in autumn: as, for instance, the saupe and 
the sargus, and such others of this sort as breed shortly before 
the autumn equinox; likewise the electric ray and the angel- 
fish. Other fishes breed both in winter and in summer, as was 
previously observed: as, for instance, in winter-time the basse, 
the grey mullet, and the belone or pipe-fish; and in summer- 
time, from the middle of June to the middle of July, the female 
tunny, about the time of the summer solstice; and the tunny 
lays a sac-like enclosure in which are contained a number of 
small eggs. The ryades or shoal-fishes breed in summer. 

Of the grey mullets, the chelon begins to be in roe between the 
middle of November and the middle of December; as also the 
sargue, and the smyxon or myxon, and the cephalus; and their 
period of gestation is thirty days. And, by the way, some of the 
grey mullet species are not produced from copulation, but grow 
spontaneously from mud and sand. 

As a general rule, then, fishes are in roe in the spring-time; 
while some, as has been said, are so in summer, in autumn, or 
in winter. But whereas the impregnation in the spring-time 
follows a general law, impregnation in the other seasons does 
not follow the same rule either throughout or within the limits 
of one genus; and, further, conception in these variant seasons 
is not so prolific. And, indeed, we must bear this in mind, that 
just as with plants and quadrupeds diversity of locality has 
much to do not only with general physical health but also with 
the comparative frequency of sexual intercourse and 



1551 



generation, so also with regard to fishes locality of itself has 
much to do not only in regard to the size and vigour of the 
creature, but also in regard to its parturition and its copulations, 
causing the same species to breed oftener in one place and 
seldomer in another. 



12 

The molluscs also breed in spring. Of the marine molluscs one 
of the first to breed is the sepia. It spawns at all times of the day 
and its period of gestation is fifteen days. After the female has 
laid her eggs, the male comes and discharges the milt over the 
eggs, and the eggs thereupon harden. And the two sexes of this 
animal go about in pairs, side by side; and the male is more 
mottled and more black on the back than the female. 

The octopus pairs in winter and breeds in spring, lying hidden 
for about two months. Its spawn is shaped like a vine-tendril, 
and resembles the fruit of the white poplar; the creature is 
extraordinarily prolific, for the number of individuals that come 
from the spawn is something incalculable. The male differs 
from the female in the fact that its head is longer, and that the 
organ called by the fishermen its penis, in the tentacle, is white. 
The female, after laying her eggs, broods over them, and in 
consequence gets out of condition, by reason of not going in 
quest of food during the hatching period. 

The purple murex breeds about springtime, and the ceryx at the 
close of the winter. And, as a general rule, the testaceans are 
found to be furnished with their so-called eggs in spring-time 
and in autumn, with the exception of the edible urchin; for this 
animal has the so-called eggs in most abundance in these 
seasons, but at no season is unfurnished with them; and it is 



1552 



furnished with them in especial abundance in warm weather or 
when a full moon is in the sky. Only, by the way, these remarks 
do not apply to the sea-urchin found in the Pyrrhaean Straits, 
for this urchin is at its best for table purposes in the winter; and 
these urchins are small but full of eggs. 

Snails are found by observations to become in all cases 
impregnated about the same season. 



13 

(Of birds the wild species, as has been stated, as a general rule 
pair and breed only once a year. The swallow, however, and the 
blackbird breed twice. With regard to the blackbird, however, its 
first brood is killed by inclemency of weather (for it is the 
earliest of all birds to breed), but the second brood it usually 
succeeds in rearing. 

Birds that are domesticated or that are capable of domestication 
breed frequently, just as the common pigeon breeds all through 
the summer, and as is seen in the barn-door hen; for the barn- 
door cock and hen have intercourse, and the hen breeds, at all 
seasons alike: excepting by the way, during the days about the 
winter solstice. 

Of the pigeon family there are many diversities; for the peristera 
or common pigeon is not identical with the peleias or rock- 
pigeon. In other words, the rock-pigeon is smaller than the 
common pigeon, and is less easily domesticated; it is also black, 
and small, red-footed and rough-footed; and in consequence of 
these peculiarities it is neglected by the pigeon-fancier. The 
largest of all the pigeon species is the phatta or ring-dove; and 
the next in size is the oenas or stock-dove; and the stock-dove is 



1553 



a little larger than the common pigeon. The smallest of all the 
species is the turtle-dove. Pigeons breed and hatch at all 
seasons, if they are furnished with a sunny place and all 
requisites; unless they are so furnished, they breed only in the 
summer. The spring brood is the best, or the autumn brood. At 
all events, without doubt, the produce of the hot season, the 
summer brood, is the poorest of the three.) 



14 

Further, animals differ from one another in regard to the time of 
life that is best adapted for sexual intercourse. 

To begin with, in most animals the secretion of the seminal 
fluid and its generative capacity are not phenomena 
simultaneously manifested, but manifested successively. Thus, 
in all animals, the earliest secretion of sperm is unfruitful, or if 
it be fruitful the issue is comparatively poor and small. And this 
phenomenon is especially observable in man, in viviparous 
quadrupeds, and in birds; for in the case of man and the 
quadruped the offspring is smaller, and in the case of the bird, 
the egg. 

For animals that copulate, of one and the same species, the age 
for maturity is in most species tolerably uniform, unless it 
occurs prematurely by reason of abnormality, or is postponed by 
physical injury. 

In man, then, maturity is indicated by a change of the tone of 
voice, by an increase in size and an alteration in appearance of 
the sexual organs, as also in an increase of size and alteration in 
appearance of the breasts; and above all, in the hair-growth at 
the pubes. Man begins to possess seminal fluid about the age of 



1554 



fourteen, and becomes generatively capable at about the age of 
twenty-one years. 

In other animals there is no hair-growth at the pubes (for some 
animals have no hair at all, and others have none on the belly, 
or less on the belly than on the back), but still, in some animals 
the change of voice is quite obvious; and in some animals other 
organs give indication of the commencing secretion of the 
sperm and the onset of generative capacity. As a general rule 
the female is sharper-toned in voice than the male, and the 
young animal than the elder; for, by the way, the stag has a 
much deeper-toned bay than the hind. Moreover, the male cries 
chiefly at rutting time, and the female under terror and alarm; 
and the cry of the female is short, and that of the male 
prolonged. With dogs also, as they grow old, the tone of the bark 
gets deeper. 

There is a difference observable also in the neighings of horses. 
That is to say, the female foal has a thin small neigh, and the 
male foal a small neigh, yet bigger and deeper-toned than that 
of the female, and a louder one as time goes on. And when the 
young male and female are two years old and take to breeding, 
the neighing of the stallion becomes loud and deep, and that of 
the mare louder and shriller than heretofore; and this change 
goes on until they reach the age of about twenty years; and after 
this time the neighing in both sexes becomes weaker and 
weaker. 

As a rule, then, as was stated, the voice of the male differs from 
the voice of the female, in animals where the voice admits of a 
continuous and prolonged sound, in the fact that the note in 
the male voice is more deep and bass; not, however, in all 
animals, for the contrary holds good in the case of some, as for 
instance in kine: for here the cow has a deeper note than the 
bull, and the calves a deeper note than the cattle. And we can 



1555 



thus understand the change of voice in animals that undergo 
gelding; for male animals that undergo this process assume the 
characters of the female. 

The following are the ages at which various animals become 
capacitated for sexual commerce. The ewe and the she-goat are 
sexually mature when one year old, and this statement is made 
more confidently in respect to the she-goat than to the ewe; the 
ram and the he-goat are sexually mature at the same age. The 
progeny of very young individuals among these animals differs 
from that of other males: for the males improve in the course of 
the second year, when they become fully mature. The boar and 
the sow are capable of intercourse when eight months old, and 
the female brings forth when one year old, the difference 
corresponding to her period of gestation. The boar is capable of 
generation when eight months old, but, with a sire under a year 
in age, the litter is apt to be a poor one. The ages, however, are 
not invariable; now and then the boar and the sow are capable 
of intercourse when four months old, and are capable of 
producing a litter which can be reared when six months old; but 
at times the boar begins to be capable of intercourse when ten 
months. He continues sexually mature until he is three years 
old. The dog and the bitch are, as a rule, sexually capable and 
sexually receptive when a year old, and sometimes when eight 
months old; but the priority in date is more common with the 
dog than with the bitch. The period of gestation with the bitch is 
sixty days, or sixty-one, or sixty-two, or sixty-three at the 
utmost; the period is never under sixty days, or, if it is, the litter 
comes to no good. The bitch, after delivering a litter, submits to 
the male in six months, but not before. The horse and the mare 
are, at the earliest, sexually capable and sexually mature when 
two years old; the issue, however, of parents of this age is small 
and poor. As a general rule these animals are sexually capable 
when three years old, and they grow better for breeding 
purposes until they reach twenty years. The stallion is sexually 



1556 



capable up to the age of thirty-three years, and the mare up to 
forty, so that, in point of fact, the animals are sexually capable 
all their lives long; for the stallion, as a rule, lives for about 
thirty-five years, and the mare for a little over forty; although, 
by the way, a horse has known to live to the age of seventy-five. 
The ass and the she-ass are sexually capable when thirty 
months old; but, as a rule, they are not generatively mature 
until they are three years old, or three years and a half. An 
instance has been known of a she-ass bearing and bringing 
forth a foal when only a year old. A cow has been known to 
calve when only a year old, and the calf grew as big as might be 
expected, but no more. So much for the dates in time at which 
these animals attain to generative capacity. 

In the human species, the male is generative, at the longest, up 
to seventy years, and the female up to fifty; but such extended 
periods are rare. As a rule, the male is generative up to the age 
of sixty-five, and to the age of forty-five the female is capable of 
conception. 

The ewe bears up to eight years, and, if she be carefully tended, 
up to eleven years; in fact, the ram and the ewe are sexually 
capable pretty well all their lives long. He-goats, if they be fat, 
are more or less unserviceable for breeding; and this, by the 
way, is the reason why country folk say of a vine when it stops 
bearing that it is 'running the goat'. However, if an over-fat he- 
goat be thinned down, he becomes sexually capable and 
generative. 

Rams single out the oldest ewes for copulation, and show no 
regard for the young ones. And, as has been stated, the issue of 
the younger ewes is poorer than that of the older ones. 

The boar is good for breeding purposes until he is three years of 
age; but after that age his issue deteriorates, for after that age 
his vigour is on the decline. The boar is most capable after a 



1557 



good feed, and with the first sow it mounts; if poorly fed or put 
to many females, the copulation is abbreviated, and the litter is 
comparatively poor. The first litter of the sow is the fewest in 
number; at the second litter she is at her prime. The animal, as 
it grows old, continues to breed, but the sexual desire abates. 
When they reach fifteen years, they become unproductive, and 
are getting old. If a sow be highly fed, it is all the more eager for 
sexual commerce, whether old or young; but, if it be over- 
fattened in pregnancy, it gives the less milk after parturition. 
With regard to the age of the parents, the litter is the best when 
they are in their prime; but with regard to the seasons of the 
year, the litter is the best that comes at the beginning of winter; 
and the summer litter the poorest, consisting as it usually does 
of animals small and thin and flaccid. The boar, if it be well fed, 
is sexually capable at all hours, night and day; but otherwise is 
peculiarly salacious early in the morning. As it grows old the 
sexual passion dies away, as we have already remarked. Very 
often a boar, when more or less impotent from age or debility, 
finding itself unable to accomplish the sexual commerce with 
due speed, and growing fatigued with the standing posture, will 
roll the sow over on the ground, and the pair will conclude the 
operation side by side of one another. The sow is sure of 
conception if it drops its lugs in rutting time; if the ears do not 
thus drop, it may have to rut a second time before impregnation 
takes place. 

Bitches do not submit to the male throughout their lives, but 
only until they reach a certain maturity of years. As a general 
rule, they are sexually receptive and conceptive until they are 
twelve years old; although, by the way, cases have been known 
where dogs and bitches have been respectively procreative and 
conceptive to the ages of eighteen and even of twenty years. 
But, as a rule, age diminishes the capability of generation and of 
conception with these animals as with all others. 



1558 



The female of the camel is opisthuretic, and submits to the 
male in the way above described; and the season for copulation 
in Arabia is about the month of October. Its period of gestation 
is twelve months; and it is never delivered of more than one 
foal at a time. The female becomes sexually receptive and the 
male sexually capable at the age of three years. After 
parturition, an interval of a year elapses before the female is 
again receptive to the male. 

The female elephant becomes sexually receptive when ten 
years old at the youngest, and when fifteen at the oldest; and 
the male is sexually capable when five years old, or six. The 
season for intercourse is spring. The male allows an interval of 
three years to elapse after commerce with a female: and, after it 
has once impregnated a female, it has no intercourse with her 
again. The period of gestation with the female is two years; and 
only one young animal is produced at a time, in other words it 
is uniparous. And the embryo is the size of a calf two or three 
months old. 



15 

So much for the copulations of such animals as copulate. 

We now proceed to treat of generation both with respect to 
copulating and non-copulating animals, and we shall 
commence with discussing the subject of generation in the case 
of the testaceans. 

The testacean is almost the only genus that throughout all its 
species is non-copulative. 



1559 



The porphyrae, or purple murices, gather together to some one 
place in the spring-time, and deposit the so-called 'honeycomb'. 
This substance resembles the comb, only that it is not so neat 
and delicate; and looks as though a number of husks of white 
chick-peas were all stuck together. But none of these structures 
has any open passage, and the porphyra does not grow out of 
them, but these and all other testaceans grow out of mud and 
decaying matter. The substance, is, in fact, an excretion of the 
porphyra and the ceryx; for it is deposited by the ceryx as well. 
Such, then, of the testaceans as deposit the honeycomb are 
generated spontaneously like all other testaceans, but they 
certainly come in greater abundance in places where their 
congeners have been living previously. At the commencement 
of the process of depositing the honeycomb, they throw off a 
slippery mucus, and of this the husklike formations are 
composed. These formations, then, all melt and deposit their 
contents on the ground, and at this spot there are found on the 
ground a number of minute porphyrae, and porphyrae are 
caught at times with these animalculae upon them, some of 
which are too small to be differentiated in form. If the 
porphyrae are caught before producing this honey-comb, they 
sometimes go through the process in fishing-creels, not here 
and there in the baskets, but gathering to some one spot all 
together, just as they do in the sea; and owing to the 
narrowness of their new quarters they cluster together like a 
bunch of grapes. 

There are many species of the purple murex; and some are 
large, as those found off Sigeum and Lectum; others are small, 
as those found in the Euripus, and on the coast of Caria. And 
those that are found in bays are large and rough; in most of 
them the peculiar bloom from which their name is derived is 
dark to blackness, in others it is reddish and small in size; some 
of the large ones weigh upwards of a mina apiece. But the 
specimens that are found along the coast and on the rocks are 



1560 



small-sized, and the bloom in their case is of a reddish hue. 
Further, as a general rule, in northern waters the bloom is 
blackish, and in southern waters of a reddish hue. The murex is 
caught in the spring-time when engaged in the construction of 
the honeycomb; but it is not caught at any time about the rising 
of the dog-star, for at that period it does not feed, but conceals 
itself and burrows. The bloom of the animal is situated between 
the mecon (or quasi-liver) and the neck, and the co-attachment 
of these is an intimate one. In colour it looks like a white 
membrane, and this is what people extract; and if it be removed 
and squeezed it stains your hand with the colour of the bloom. 
There is a kind of vein that runs through it, and this quasi-vein 
would appear to be in itself the bloom. And the qualities, by the 
way, of this organ are astringent. It is after the murex has 
constructed the honeycomb that the bloom is at its worst. Small 
specimens they break in pieces, shells and all, for it is no easy 
matter to extract the organ; but in dealing with the larger ones 
they first strip off the shell and then abstract the bloom. For this 
purpose the neck and mecon are separated, for the bloom lies in 
between them, above the so-called stomach; hence the 
necessity of separating them in abstracting the bloom. 
Fishermen are anxious always to break the animal in pieces 
while it is yet alive, for, if it die before the process is completed, 
it vomits out the bloom; and for this reason the fishermen keep 
the animals in creels, until they have collected a sufficient 
number and can attend to them at their leisure. Fishermen in 
past times used not to lower creels or attach them to the bait, so 
that very often the animal got dropped off in the pulling up; at 
present, however, they always attach a basket, so that if the 
animal fall off it is not lost. The animal is more inclined to slip 
off the bait if it be full inside; if it be empty it is difficult to 
shake it off. Such are the phenomena connected with the 
porphyra or murex. 



1561 



The same phenomena are manifested by the ceryx or trumpet- 
shell; and the seasons are the same in which the phenomena 
are observable. Both animals, also, the murex and the ceryx, 
have their opercula similarly situated - and, in fact, all the 
stromboids, and this is congenital with them all; and they feed 
by protruding the so-called tongue underneath the operculum. 
The tongue of the murex is bigger than one's finger, and by 
means of it, it feeds, and perforates conchylia and the shells of 
its own kind. Both the murex and the ceryx are long lived. The 
murex lives for about six years; and the yearly increase is 
indicated by a distinct interval in the spiral convolution of the 
shell. 

The mussel also constructs a honeycomb. 

With regard to the limnostreae, or lagoon oysters, wherever you 
have slimy mud there you are sure to find them beginning to 
grow. Cockles and clams and razor-fishes and scallops row 
spontaneously in sandy places. The pinna grows straight up 
from its tuft of anchoring fibres in sandy and slimy places; 
these creatures have inside them a parasite nicknamed the 
pinna-guard, in some cases a small carid and in other cases a 
little crab; if the pinna be deprived of this pinna-guard it soon 
dies. 

As a general rule, then, all testaceans grow by spontaneous 
generation in mud, differing from one another according to the 
differences of the material; oysters growing in slime, and 
cockles and the other testaceans above mentioned on sandy 
bottoms; and in the hollows of the rocks the ascidian and the 
barnacle, and common sorts, such as the limpet and the nerites. 
All these animals grow with great rapidity, especially the murex 
and the scallop; for the murex and the scallop attain their full 
growth in a year. In some of the testaceans white crabs are 
found, very diminutive in size; they are most numerous in the 



1562 



trough shaped mussel. In the pinna also is found the so-called 
pinna-guard. They are found also in the scallop and in the 
oyster; these parasites never appear to grow in size. Fishermen 
declare that the parasite is congenital with the larger animal. 
(Scallops burrow for a time in the sand, like the murex.) 

(Shell-fish, then, grow in the way above mentioned; and some of 
them grow in shallow water, some on the sea-shore, some in 
rocky places, some on hard and stony ground, and some in 
sandy places.) Some shift about from place to place, others 
remain permanent on one spot. Of those that keep to one spot 
the pinnae are rooted to the ground; the razor-fish and the clam 
keep to the same locality, but are not so rooted; but still, if 
forcibly removed they die. 

(The star-fish is naturally so warm that whatever it lays hold of 
is found, when suddenly taken away from the animal, to have 
undergone a process like boiling. Fishermen say that the star- 
fish is a great pest in the Strait of Pyrrha. In shape it resembles 
a star as seen in an ordinary drawing. The so-called 'lungs' are 
generated spontaneously. The shells that painters use are a 
good deal thicker, and the bloom is outside the shell on the 
surface. These creatures are mostly found on the coast of Caria.) 

The hermit-crab grows spontaneously out of soil and slime, and 
finds its way into untenanted shells. As it grows it shifts to a 
larger shell, as for instance into the shell of the nerites, or of the 
strombus or the like, and very often into the shell of the small 
ceryx. After entering new shell, it carries it about, and begins 
again to feed, and, by and by, as it grows, it shifts again into 
another larger one. 



1563 



16 

Moreover, the animals that are unfurnished with shells grow 
spontaneously, like the testaceans, as, for instance, the sea- 
nettles and the sponges in rocky caves. 

Of the sea-nettle, or sea-anemone, there are two species; and of 
these one species lives in hollows and never loosens its hold 
upon the rocks, and the other lives on smooth flat reefs, free 
and detached, and shifts its position from time to time. 
(Limpets also detach themselves, and shift from place to place.) 

In the chambered cavities of sponges pinna-guards or parasites 
are found. And over the chambers there is a kind of spider's 
web, by the opening and closing of which they catch mute 
fishes; that is to say, they open the web to let the fish get in, and 
close it again to entrap them. 

Of sponges there are three species; the first is of loose porous 
texture, the second is close textured, the third, which is 
nicknamed 'the sponge of Achilles', is exceptionally fine and 
close-textured and strong. This sponge is used as a lining to 
helmets and greaves, for the purpose of deadening the sound of 
the blow; and this is a very scarce species. Of the close textured 
sponges such as are particularly hard and rough are nicknamed 
'goats'. 

Sponges grow spontaneously either attached to a rock or on 
sea-beaches, and they get their nutriment in slime: a proof of 
this statement is the fact that when they are first secured they 
are found to be full of slime. This is characteristic of all living 
creatures that get their nutriment by close local attachment. 
And, by the way, the close-textured sponges are weaker than 
the more openly porous ones because their attachment extends 
over a smaller area. 



1564 



It is said that the sponge is sensitive; and as a proof of this 
statement they say that if the sponge is made aware of an 
attempt being made to pluck it from its place of attachment it 
draws itself together, and it becomes a difficult task to detach it. 
It makes a similar contractile movement in windy and 
boisterous weather, obviously with the object of tightening its 
hold. Some persons express doubts as to the truth of this 
assertion; as, for instance, the people of Torone. 

The sponge breeds parasites, worms, and other creatures, on 
which, if they be detached, the rock-fishes prey, as they prey 
also on the remaining stumps of the sponge; but, if the sponge 
be broken off, it grows again from the remaining stump and the 
place is soon as well covered as before. 

The largest of all sponges are the loose-textured ones, and these 
are peculiarly abundant on the coast of Lycia. The softest are 
the close-textured sponges; for, by the way, the so-called 
sponges of Achilles are harder than these. As a general rule, 
sponges that are found in deep calm waters are the softest; for 
usually windy and stormy weather has a tendency to harden 
them (as it has to harden all similar growing things), and to 
arrest their growth. And this accounts for the fact that the 
sponges found in the Hellespont are rough and close-textured; 
and, as a general rule, sponges found beyond or inside Cape 
Malea are, respectively, comparatively soft or comparatively 
hard. But, by the way, the habitat of the sponge should not be 
too sheltered and warm, for it has a tendency to decay, like all 
similar vegetable-like growths. And this accounts for the fact 
that the sponge is at its best when found in deep water close to 
shore; for owing to the depth of the water they enjoy shelter 
alike from stormy winds and from excessive heat. 

Whilst they are still alive and before they are washed and 
cleaned, they are blackish in colour. Their attachment is not 



1565 



made at one particular spot, nor is it made all over their bodies; 
for vacant pore-spaces intervene. There is a kind of membrane 
stretched over the under parts; and in the under parts the 
points of attachment are the more numerous. On the top most 
of the pores are closed, but four or five are open and visible; and 
we are told by some that it is through these pores that the 
animal takes its food. 

There is a particular species that is named the 'aplysia' or the 
'unwashable', from the circumstance that it cannot be cleaned. 
This species has the large open and visible pores, but all the rest 
of the body is close-textured; and, if it be dissected, it is found 
to be closer and more glutinous than the ordinary sponge, and, 
in a word, something lung like in consistency. And, on all hands, 
it is allowed that this species is sensitive and long-lived. They 
are distinguished in the sea from ordinary sponges from the 
circumstance that the ordinary sponges are white while the 
slime is in them, but that these sponges are under any 
circumstances black. 

And so much with regard to sponges and to generation in the 
testaceans. 



17 

Of crustaceans, the female crawfish after copulation conceives 
and retains its eggs for about three months, from about the 
middle of May to about the middle of August; they then lay the 
eggs into the folds underneath the belly, and their eggs grow 
like grubs. This same phenomenon is observable in molluscs 
also, and in such fishes as are oviparous; for in all these cases 
the egg continues to grow. 



1566 



The spawn of the crawfish is of a loose or granular consistency, 
and is divided into eight parts; for corresponding to each of the 
flaps on the side there is a gristly formation to which the spawn 
is attached, and the entire structure resembles a cluster of 
grapes; for each gristly formation is split into several parts. This 
is obvious enough if you draw the parts asunder; but at first 
sight the whole appears to be one and indivisible. And the 
largest are not those nearest to the outlet but those in the 
middle, and the farthest off are the smallest. The size of the 
small eggs is that of a small seed in a fig; and they are not quite 
close to the outlet, but placed middleways; for at both ends, 
tailwards and trunkwards, there are two intervals devoid of 
eggs; for it is thus that the flaps also grow. The side flaps, then, 
cannot close, but by placing the end flap on them the animal 
can close up all, and this end-flap serves them for a lid. And in 
the act of laying its eggs it seems to bring them towards the 
gristly formations by curving the flap of its tail, and then, 
squeezing the eggs towards the said gristly formations and 
maintaining a bent posture, it performs the act of laying. The 
gristly formations at these seasons increase in size and become 
receptive of the eggs; for the animal lays its eggs into these 
formations, just as the sepia lays its eggs among twigs and 
driftwood. 

It lays its eggs, then, in this manner, and after hatching them for 
about twenty days it rids itself of them all in one solid lump, as 
is quite plain from outside. And out of these eggs crawfish form 
in about fifteen days, and these crawfish are caught at times 
less then a finger's breadth, or seven-tenths of an inch, in 
length. The animal, then, lays its eggs before the middle of 
September, and after the middle of that month throws off its 
eggs in a lump. With the humped carids or prawns the time for 
gestation is four months or thereabouts. 



1567 



Crawfish are found in rough and rocky places, lobsters in 
smooth places, and neither crawfish nor lobsters are found in 
muddy ones; and this accounts for the fact that lobsters are 
found in the Hellespont and on the coast of Thasos, and 
crawfish in the neighbourhood of Sigeum and Mount Athos. 
Fishermen, accordingly, when they want to catch these various 
creatures out at sea, take bearings on the beach and elsewhere 
that tell them where the ground at the bottom is stony and 
where soft with slime. In winter and spring these animals keep 
in near to land, in summer they keep in deep water; thus at 
various times seeking respectively for warmth or coolness. 

The so-called arctus or bear-crab lays its eggs at about the same 
time as the crawfish; and consequently in winter and in the 
spring-time, before laying their eggs, they are at their best, and 
after laying at their worst. 

They cast their shell in the spring-time (just as serpents shed 
their so-called 'old-age' or slough), both directly after birth and 
in later life; this is true both of crabs and crawfish. And, by the 
way, all crawfish are long lived. 



18 

Molluscs, after pairing and copulation, lay a white spawn; and 
this spawn, as in the case of the testacean, gets granular in 
time. The octopus discharges into its hole, or into a potsherd or 
into any similar cavity, a structure resembling the tendrils of a 
young vine or the fruit of the white poplar, as has been 
previously observed. The eggs, when the female has laid them, 
are clustered round the sides of the hole. They are so numerous 
that, if they be removed they suffice to fill a vessel much larger 
than the animal's body in which they were contained. Some 



1568 



fifty days later, the eggs burst and the little polypuses creep out, 
like little spiders, in great numbers; the characteristic form of 
their limbs is not yet to be discerned in detail, but their general 
outline is clear enough. And, by the way, they are so small and 
helpless that the greater number perish; it is a fact that they 
have been seen so extremely minute as to be absolutely without 
organization, but nevertheless when touched they moved. The 
eggs of the sepia look like big black myrtle-berries, and they are 
linked all together like a bunch of grapes, clustered round a 
centre, and are not easily sundered from one another: for the 
male exudes over them some moist glairy stuff, which 
constitutes the sticky gum. These eggs increase in size; and they 
are white at the outset, but black and larger after the sprinkling 
of the male seminal fluid. 

When it has come into being the young sepia is first distinctly 
formed inside out of the white substance, and when the egg 
bursts it comes out. The inner part is formed as soon as the 
female lays the egg, something like a hail-stone; and out of this 
substance the young sepia grows by a head-attachment, just as 
young birds grow by a belly-attachment. What is the exact 
nature of the navel-attachment has not yet been observed, 
except that as the young sepia grows the white substance grows 
less and less in size, and at length, as happens with the yolk in 
the case of birds, the white substance in the case of the young 
sepia disappears. In the case of the young sepia, as in the case 
of the young of most animals, the eyes at first seem very large. 
To illustrate this by way of a figure, let A represent the ovum, B 
and C the eyes, and D the sepidium, or body of the little sepia. 
(See diagram.) 

The female sepia goes pregnant in the spring-time, and lays its 
eggs after fifteen days of gestation; after the eggs are laid there 
comes in another fifteen days something like a bunch of grapes, 
and at the bursting of these the young sepiae issue forth. But if, 



1569 



when the young ones are fully formed, you sever the outer 
covering a moment too soon, the young creatures eject 
excrement, and their colour changes from white to red in their 
alarm. 

Crustaceans, then, hatch their eggs by brooding over them as 
they carry them about beneath their bodies; but the octopus, 
the sepia, and the like hatch their eggs without stirring from the 
spot where they may have laid them, and this statement is 
particularly applicable to the sepia; in fact, the nest of the 
female sepia is often seen exposed to view close in to shore. The 
female octopus at times sits brooding over her eggs, and at 
other times squats in front of her hole, stretching out her 
tentacles on guard. 

The sepia lays her spawn near to land in the neighbourhood of 
sea-weed or reeds or any off-sweepings such as brushwood, 
twigs, or stones; and fishermen place heaps of faggots here and 
there on purpose, and on to such heaps the female deposits a 
long continuous roe in shape like a vine tendril. It lays or spirts 
out the spawn with an effort, as though there were difficulty in 
the process. The female calamary spawns at sea; and it emits 
the spawn, as does the sepia, in the mass. 

The calamary and the cuttle-fish are short-lived, as, with few 
exceptions, they never see the year out; and the same 
statement is applicable to the octopus. 

From one single egg comes one single sepia; and this is likewise 
true of the young calamary. 

The male calamary differs from the female; for if its gill-region 
be dilated and examined there are found two red formations 
resembling breasts, with which the male is unprovided. In the 
sepia, apart from this distinction in the sexes, the male, as has 
been stated, is more mottled than the female. 



1570 



19 

With regard to insects, that the male is less than the female and 
that he mounts upon her back, and how he performs the act of 
copulation and the circumstance that he gives over reluctantly, 
all this has already been set forth, most cases of insect 
copulation this process is speedily followed up by parturition. 

All insects engender grubs, with the exception of a species of 
butterfly; and the female of this species lays a hard egg, 
resembling the seed of the cnecus, with a juice inside it. But 
from the grub, the young animal does not grow out of a mere 
portion of it, as a young animal grows from a portion only of an 
egg, but the grub entire grows and the animal becomes 
differentiated out of it. 

And of insects some are derived from insect congeners, as the 
venom-spider and the common-spider from the venom-spider 
and the common-spider, and so with the attelabus or locust, the 
acris or grasshopper, and the tettix or cicada. Other insects are 
not derived from living parentage, but are generated 
spontaneously: some out of dew falling on leaves, ordinarily in 
spring-time, but not seldom in winter when there has been a 
stretch of fair weather and southerly winds; others grow in 
decaying mud or dung; others in timber, green or dry; some in 
the hair of animals; some in the flesh of animals; some in 
excrements: and some from excrement after it has been voided, 
and some from excrement yet within the living animal, like the 
helminthes or intestinal worms. And of these intestinal worms 
there are three species: one named the flat-worm, another the 
round worm, and the third the ascarid. These intestinal worms 
do not in any case propagate their kind. The flat-worm, 



1571 



however, in an exceptional way, clings fast to the gut, and lays a 
thing like a melon-seed, by observing which indication the 
physician concludes that his patient is troubled with the worm. 

The so-called psyche or butterfly is generated from caterpillars 
which grow on green leaves, chiefly leaves of the raphanus, 
which some call crambe or cabbage. At first it is less than a 
grain of millet; it then grows into a small grub; and in three 
days it is a tiny caterpillar. After this it grows on and on, and 
becomes quiescent and changes its shape, and is now called a 
chrysalis. The outer shell is hard, and the chrysalis moves if you 
touch it. It attaches itself by cobweb-like filaments, and is 
unfurnished with mouth or any other apparent organ. After a 
little while the outer covering bursts asunder, and out flies the 
winged creature that we call the psyche or butterfly. At first, 
when it is a caterpillar, it feeds and ejects excrement; but when 
it turns into the chrysalis it neither feeds nor ejects excrement. 

The same remarks are applicable to all such insects as are 
developed out of the grub, both such grubs as are derived from 
the copulation of living animals and such as are generated 
without copulation on the part of parents. For the grub of the 
bee, the anthrena, and the wasp, whilst it is young, takes food 
and voids excrement; but when it has passed from the grub 
shape to its defined form and become what is termed a 
'nympha', it ceases to take food and to void excrement, and 
remains tightly wrapped up and motionless until it has reached 
its full size, when it breaks the formation with which the cell is 
closed, and issues forth. The insects named the hypera and the 
penia are derived from similar caterpillars, which move in an 
undulatory way, progressing with one part and then pulling up 
the hinder parts by a bend of the body. The developed insect in 
each case takes its peculiar colour from the parent caterpillar. 



1572 



From one particular large grub, which has as it were horns, and 
in other respects differs from grubs in general, there comes, by 
a metamorphosis of the grub, first a caterpillar, then the cocoon, 
then the necydalus; and the creature passes through all these 
transformations within six months. A class of women unwind 
and reel off the cocoons of these creatures, and afterwards 
weave a fabric with the threads thus unwound; a Coan woman 
of the name of Pamphila, daughter of Plateus, being credited 
with the first invention of the fabric. After the same fashion the 
carabus or stag-beetle comes from grubs that live in dry wood: 
at first the grub is motionless, but after a while the shell bursts 
and the stag-beetle issues forth. 

From the cabbage is engendered the cabbageworm, and from 
the leek the prasocuris or leekbane; this creature is also winged. 
From the flat animalcule that skims over the surface of rivers 
comes the oestrus or gadfly; and this accounts for the fact that 
gadflies most abound in the neighbourhood of waters on whose 
surface these animalcules are observed. From a certain small, 
black and hairy caterpillar comes first a wingless glow-worm; 
and this creature again suffers a metamorphosis, and 
transforms into a winged insect named the bostrychus (or hair- 
curl). 

Gnats grow from ascarids; and ascarids are engendered in the 
slime of wells, or in places where there is a deposit left by the 
draining off of water. This slime decays, and first turns white, 
then black, and finally blood-red; and at this stage there 
originate in it, as it were, little tiny bits of red weed, which at 
first wriggle about all clinging together, and finally break loose 
and swim in the water, and are hereupon known as ascarids. 
After a few days they stand straight up on the water motionless 
and hard, and by and by the husk breaks off and the gnats are 
seen sitting upon it, until the sun's heat or a puff of wind sets 
them in motion, when they fly away. 



1573 



With all grubs and all animals that break out from the grub 
state, generation is due primarily to the heat of the sun or to 
wind. 

Ascarids are more likely to be found, and grow with unusual 
rapidity, in places where there is a deposit of a mixed and 
heterogeneous kind, as in kitchens and in ploughed fields, for 
the contents of such places are disposed to rapid putrefaction. 
In autumn, also, owing to the drying up of moisture, they grow 
in unusual numbers. 

The tick is generated from couch-grass. The cockchafer comes 
from a grub that is generated in the dung of the cow or the ass. 
The cantharus or scarabeus rolls a piece of dung into a ball, lies 
hidden within it during the winter, and gives birth therein to 
small grubs, from which grubs come new canthari. Certain 
winged insects also come from the grubs that are found in 
pulse, in the same fashion as in the cases described. 

Flies grow from grubs in the dung that farmers have gathered 
up into heaps: for those who are engaged in this work 
assiduously gather up the compost, and this they technically 
term 'working-up' the manure. The grub is exceedingly minute 
to begin with; first even at this stage - it assumes a reddish 
colour, and then from a quiescent state it takes on the power of 
motion, as though born to it; it then becomes a small 
motionless grub; it then moves again, and again relapses into 
immobility; it then comes out a perfect fly, and moves away 
under the influence of the sun's heat or of a puff of air. The 
myops or horse-fly is engendered in timber. The orsodacna or 
budbane is a transformed grub; and this grub is engendered in 
cabbage-stalks. The cantharis comes from the caterpillars that 
are found on fig-trees or pear-trees or fir-trees - for on all these 
grubs are engendered - and also from caterpillars found on the 
dog-rose; and the cantharis takes eagerly to ill-scented 



1574 



substances, from the fact of its having been engendered in ill- 
scented woods. The conops comes from a grub that is 
engendered in the slime of vinegar. 

And, by the way, living animals are found in substances that are 
usually supposed to be incapable of putrefaction; for instance, 
worms are found in long-lying snow; and snow of this 
description gets reddish in colour, and the grub that is 
engendered in it is red, as might have been expected, and it is 
also hairy. The grubs found in the snows of Media are large and 
white; and all such grubs are little disposed to motion. In 
Cyprus, in places where copper-ore is smelted, with heaps of 
the ore piled on day after day, an animal is engendered in the 
fire, somewhat larger than a blue bottle fly, furnished with 
wings, which can hop or crawl through the fire. And the grubs 
and these latter animals perish when you keep the one away 
from the fire and the other from the snow. Now the salamander 
is a clear case in point, to show us that animals do actually exist 
that fire cannot destroy; for this creature, so the story goes, not 
only walks through the fire but puts it out in doing so. 

On the river Hypanis in the Cimmerian Bosphorus, about the 
time of the summer solstice, there are brought down towards 
the sea by the stream what look like little sacks rather bigger 
than grapes, out of which at their bursting issues a winged 
quadruped. The insect lives and flies about until the evening, 
but as the sun goes down it pines away, and dies at sunset 
having lived just one day, from which circumstance it is called 
the ephemeron. 

As a rule, insects that come from caterpillars and grubs are held 
at first by filaments resembling the threads of a spider's web. 

Such is the mode of generation of the insects above 
enumerated, but if the latter impregnation takes placeduring 
the change of the yellow 



1575 



20 

The wasps that are nicknamed 'the ichneumons' (or hunters), 
less in size, by the way, than the ordinary wasp, kill spiders and 
carry off the dead bodies to a wall or some such place with a 
hole in it; this hole they smear over with mud and lay their 
grubs inside it, and from the grubs come the hunter-wasps. 
Some of the coleoptera and of the small and nameless insects 
make small holes or cells of mud on a wall or on a grave-stone, 
and there deposit their grubs. 

With insects, as a general rule, the time of generation from its 
commencement to its completion comprises three or four 
weeks. With grubs and grub-like creatures the time is usually 
three weeks, and in the oviparous insects as a rule four. But, in 
the case of oviparous insects, the egg-formation comes at the 
close of seven days from copulation, and during the remaining 
three weeks the parent broods over and hatches its young; i.e. 
where this is the result of copulation, as in the case of the 
spider and its congeners. As a rule, the transformations take 
place in intervals of three or four days, corresponding to the 
lengths of interval at which the crises recur in intermittent 
fevers. 

So much for the generation of insects. Their death is due to the 
shrivelling of their organs, just as the larger animals die of old 
age. 

Winged insects die in autumn from the shrinking of their wings. 
The myops dies from dropsy in the eyes. 



1576 



21 

With regard to the generation of bees different hypotheses are 
in vogue. Some affirm that bees neither copulate nor give birth 
to young, but that they fetch their young. And some say that 
they fetch their young from the flower of the callyntrum; others 
assert that they bring them from the flower of the reed, others, 
from the flower of the olive. And in respect to the olive theory, it 
is stated as a proof that, when the olive harvest is most 
abundant, the swarms are most numerous. Others declare that 
they fetch the brood of the drones from such things as above 
mentioned, but that the working bees are engendered by the 
rulers of the hive. 

Now of these rulers there are two kinds: the better kind is red in 
colour, the inferior kind is black and variegated; the ruler is 
double the size of the working bee. These rulers have the 
abdomen or part below the waist half as large again, and they 
are called by some the 'mothers', from an idea that they bear or 
generate the bees; and, as a proof of this theory of their 
motherhood, they declare that the brood of the drones appears 
even when there is no ruler-bee in the hive, but that the bees do 
not appear in his absence. Others, again, assert that these 
insects copulate, and that the drones are male and the bees 
female. 

The ordinary bee is generated in the cells of the comb, but the 
ruler-bees in cells down below attached to the comb, suspended 
from it, apart from the rest, six or seven in number, and growing 
in a way quite different from the mode of growth of the 
ordinary brood. 

Bees are provided with a sting, but the drones are not so 
provided. The rulers are provided with stings, but they never use 



1577 



them; and this latter circumstance will account for the belief of 
some people that they have no stings at all. 



22 

Of bees there are various species. The best kind is a little round 
mottled insect; another is long, and resembles the anthrena; a 
third is a black and flat-bellied, and is nick-named the 'robber'; 
a fourth kind is the drone, the largest of all, but stingless and 
inactive. And this proportionate size of the drone explains why 
some bee-masters place a net-work in front of the hives; for the 
network is put to keep the big drones out while it lets the little 
bees go in. 

Of the king bees there are, as has been stated, two kinds. In 
every hive there are more kings than one; and a hive goes to 
ruin if there be too few kings, not because of anarchy thereby 
ensuing, but, as we are told, because these creatures contribute 
in some way to the generation of the common bees. A hive will 
go also to ruin if there be too large a number of kings in it; for 
the members of the hives are thereby subdivided into too many 
separate factions. 

Whenever the spring-time is late a-coming, and when there is 
drought and mildew, then the progeny of the hive is small in 
number. But when the weather is dry they attend to the honey, 
and in rainy weather their attention is concentrated on the 
brood; and this will account for the coincidence of rich olive- 
harvests and abundant swarms. 

The bees first work at the honeycomb, and then put the pupae 
in it: by the mouth, say those who hold the theory of their 
bringing them from elsewhere. After putting in the pupae they 



1578 



put in the honey for subsistence, and this they do in the 
summer and autumn; and, by the way, the autumn honey is the 
better of the two. 

The honeycomb is made from flowers, and the materials for the 
wax they gather from the resinous gum of trees, while honey is 
distilled from dew, and is deposited chiefly at the risings of the 
constellations or when a rainbow is in the sky: and as a general 
rule there is no honey before the rising of the Pleiads. (The bee, 
then, makes the wax from flowers. The honey, however, it does 
not make, but merely gathers what is deposited out of the 
atmosphere; and as a proof of this statement we have the 
known fact that occasionally bee-keepers find the hives filled 
with honey within the space of two or three days. Furthermore, 
in autumn flowers are found, but honey, if it be withdrawn, is 
not replaced; now, after the withdrawal of the original honey, 
when no food or very little is in the hives, there would be a 
fresh stock of honey, if the bees made it from flowers.) Honey, if 
allowed to ripen and mature, gathers consistency; for at first it 
is like water and remains liquid for several days. If it be drawn 
off during these days it has no consistency; but it attains 
consistency in about twenty days. The taste of thyme-honey is 
discernible at once, from its peculiar sweetness and consistency. 

The bee gathers from every flower that is furnished with a calyx 
or cup, and from all other flowers that are sweet-tasted, without 
doing injury to any fruit; and the juices of the flowers it takes 
up with the organ that resembles a tongue and carries off to the 
hive. 

Swarms are robbed of their honey on the appearance of the wild 
fig. They produce the best larvae at the time the honey is a- 
making. The bee carries wax and bees' bread round its legs, but 
vomits the honey into the cell. After depositing its young, it 
broods over it like a bird. The grub when it is small lies 



1579 



slantwise in the comb, but by and by rises up straight by an 
effort of its own and takes food, and holds on so tightly to the 
honeycomb as actually to cling to it. 

The young of bees and of drones is white, and from the young 
come the grubs; and the grubs grow into bees and drones. The 
egg of the king bee is reddish in colour, and its substance is 
about as consistent as thick honey; and from the first it is about 
as big as the bee that is produced from it. From the young of the 
king bee there is no intermediate stage, it is said, of the grub, 
but the bee comes at once. 

Whenever the bee lays an egg in the comb there is always a 
drop of honey set against it. The larva of the bee gets feet and 
wings as soon as the cell has been stopped up with wax, and 
when it arrives at its completed form it breaks its membrane 
and flies away. It ejects excrement in the grub state, but not 
afterwards; that is, not until it has got out of the encasing 
membrane, as we have already described. If you remove the 
heads from off the larvae before the coming of the wings, the 
bees will eat them up; and if you nip off the wings from a drone 
and let it go, the bees will spontaneously bite off the wings from 
off all the remaining drones. 

The bee lives for six years as a rule, as an exception for seven 
years. If a swarm lasts for nine years, or ten, great credit is 
considered due to its management. 

In Pontus are found bees exceedingly white in colour, and these 
bees produce their honey twice a month. (The bees in 
Themiscyra, on the banks of the river Thermodon, build 
honeycombs in the ground and in hives, and these honeycombs 
are furnished with very little wax but with honey of great 
consistency; and the honeycomb, by the way, is smooth and 
level.) But this is not always the case with these bees, but only 
in the winter season; for in Pontus the ivy is abundant, and it 



1580 



flowers at this time of the year, and it is from the ivy-flower that 
they derive their honey. A white and very consistent honey is 
brought down from the upper country to Amisus, which is 
deposited by bees on trees without the employment of 
honeycombs: and this kind of honey is produced in other 
districts in Pontus. 

There are bees also that construct triple honeycombs in the 
ground; and these honeycombs supply honey but never contain 
grubs. But the honeycombs in these places are not all of this 
sort, nor do all the bees construct them. 



23 

Anthrenae and wasps construct combs for their young. When 
they have no king, but are wandering about in search of one, the 
anthrene constructs its comb on some high place, and the wasp 
inside a hole. When the anthrene and the wasp have a king, 
they construct their combs underground. Their combs are in all 
cases hexagonal like the comb of the bee. They are composed, 
however, not of wax, but of a bark-like filamented fibre, and the 
comb of the anthrene is much neater than the comb of the 
wasp. Like the bee, they put their young just like a drop of liquid 
on to the side of the cell, and the egg clings to the wall of the 
cell. But the eggs are not deposited in the cells simultaneously; 
on the contrary, in some cells are creatures big enough to fly, in 
others are nymphae, and in others are mere grubs. As in the 
case of bees, excrement is observed only in the cells where the 
grubs are found. As long as the creatures are in the nymph 
condition they are motionless, and the cell is cemented over. In 
the comb of the anthrene there is found in the cell of the young 
a drop of honey in front of it. The larvae of the anthrene and the 



1581 



wasp make their appearance not in the spring but in the 
autumn; and their growth is especially discernible in times of 
full moon. And, by the way, the eggs and the grubs never rest at 
the bottom of the cells, but always cling on to the side wall. 



24 

There is a kind of humble-bee that builds a cone-shaped nest of 
clay against a stone or in some similar situation, besmearing 
the clay with something like spittle. And this nest or hive is 
exceedingly thick and hard; in point of fact, one can hardly 
break it open with a spike. Here the insects lay their eggs, and 
white grubs are produced wrapped in a black membrane. Apart 
from the membrane there is found some wax in the 
honeycomb; and this a wax is much sallower in hue than the 
wax in the honeycomb of the bee. 



25 

Ants copulate and engender grubs; and these grubs attach 
themselves to nothing in particular, but grow on and on from 
small and rounded shapes until they become elongated and 
defined in shape: and they are engendered in spring-time. 



1582 



26 

The land-scorpion also lays a number of egg shaped grubs, and 
broods over them. When the hatching is completed, the parent 
animal, as happens with the parent spider, is ejected and put to 
death by the young ones; for very often the young ones are 
about eleven in number. 



27 

Spiders in all cases copulate in the way above mentioned, and 
generate at first small grubs. And these grubs metamorphose in 
their entirety, and not partially, into spiders; for, by the way, the 
grubs are round-shaped at the outset. And the spider, when it 
lays its eggs, broods over them, and in three days the eggs or 
grubs take definite shape. 

All spiders lay their eggs in a web; but some spiders lay in a 
small and fine web, and others in a thick one; and some, as a 
rule, lay in a round-shaped case or capsule, and some are only 
partially enveloped in the web. The young grubs are not all 
developed at one and the same time into young spiders; but the 
moment the development takes place, the young spider makes 
a leap and begins to spin his web. The juice of the grub, if you 
squeeze it, is the same as the juice found in the spider when 
young; that is to say, it is thick and white. 

The meadow spider lays its eggs into a web, one half of which is 
attached to itself and the other half is free; and on this the 
parent broods until the eggs are hatched. The phalangia lay 
their eggs in a sort of strong basket which they have woven, and 
brood over it until the eggs are hatched. The smooth spider is 
much less prolific than the phalangium or hairy spider. These 



1583 



phalangia, when they grow to full size, very often envelop the 
mother phalangium and eject and kill her; and not seldom they 
kill the father-phalangium as well, if they catch him: for, by the 
way, he has the habit of co-operating with the mother in the 
hatching. The brood of a single phalangium is sometimes three 
hundred in number. The spider attains its full growth in about 
four weeks. 



28 

Grasshoppers (or locusts) copulate in the same way as other 
insects; that is to say, with the lesser covering the larger, for the 
male is smaller than the female. The females first insert the 
hollow tube, which they have at their tails, in the ground, and 
then lay their eggs: and the male, by the way, is not furnished 
with this tube. The females lay their eggs all in a lump together, 
and in one spot, so that the entire lump of eggs resembles a 
honeycomb. After they have laid their eggs, the eggs assume the 
shape of oval grubs that are enveloped by a sort of thin clay, like 
a membrane; in this membrane-like formation they grow on to 
maturity. The larva is so soft that it collapses at a touch. The 
larva is not placed on the surface of the ground, but a little 
beneath the surface; and, when it reaches maturity, it comes out 
of its clayey investiture in the shape of a little black 
grasshopper; by and by, the skin integument strips off, and it 
grows larger and larger. 

The grasshopper lays its eggs at the close of summer, and dies 
after laying them. The fact is that, at the time of laying the eggs, 
grubs are engendered in the region of the mother grasshopper's 
neck; and the male grasshoppers die about the same time. In 
spring-time they come out of the ground; and, by the way, no 



1584 



grasshoppers are found in mountainous land or in poor land, 
but only in flat and loamy land, for the fact is they lay their eggs 
in cracks of the soil. During the winter their eggs remain in the 
ground; and with the coming of summer the last year's larva 
develops into the perfect grasshopper. 



29 

The attelabi or locusts lay their eggs and die in like manner 
after laying them. Their eggs are subject to destruction by the 
autumn rains, when the rains are unusually heavy; but in 
seasons of drought the locusts are exceedingly numerous, from 
the absence of any destructive cause, since their destruction 
seems then to be a matter of accident and to depend on luck. 



30 

Of the cicada there are two kinds; one, small in size, the first to 
come and the last to disappear; the other, large, the singing one 
that comes last and first disappears. Both in the small and the 
large species some are divided at the waist, to wit, the singing 
ones, and some are undivided; and these latter have no song. 
The large and singing cicada is by some designated the 'chirper', 
and the small cicada the 'tettigonium' or cicadelle. And, by the 
way, such of the tettigonia as are divided at the waist can sing 
just a little. 

The cicada is not found where there are no trees; and this 
accounts for the fact that in the district surrounding the city of 
Cyrene it is not found at all in the plain country, but is found in 



1585 



great numbers in the neighbourhood of the city, and especially 
where olive-trees are growing: for an olive grove is not thickly 
shaded. And the cicada is not found in cold places, and 
consequently is not found in any grove that keeps out the 
sunlight. 

The large and the small cicada copulate alike, belly to belly. The 
male discharges sperm into the female, as is the case with 
insects in general, and the female cicada has a cleft generative 
organ; and it is the female into which the male discharges the 
sperm. 

They lay their eggs in fallow lands, boring a hole with the 
pointed organ they carry in the rear, as do the locusts likewise; 
for the locust lays its eggs in unfilled lands, and this fact may 
account for their numbers in the territory adjacent to the city of 
Cyrene. The cicadae also lay their eggs in the canes on which 
husbandmen prop vines, perforating the canes; and also in the 
stalks of the squill. This brood runs into the ground. And they 
are most numerous in rainy weather. The grub, on attaining full 
size in the ground, becomes a tettigometra (or nymph), and the 
creature is sweetest to the taste at this stage before the husk is 
broken. When the summer solstice comes, the creature issues 
from the husk at night-time, and in a moment, as the husk 
breaks, the larva becomes the perfect cicada, creature, also, at 
once turns black in colour and harder and larger, and takes to 
singing. In both species, the larger and the smaller, it is the 
male that sings, and the female that is unvocal. At first, the 
males are the sweeter eating; but, after copulation, the females, 
as they are full then of white eggs. 

If you make a sudden noise as they are flying overhead they let 
drop something like water. Country people, in regard to this, say 
that they are voiding urine, ie. that they have an excrement, and 
that they feed upon dew. 



1586 



If you present your finger to a cicada and bend back the tip of it 
and then extend it again, it will endure the presentation more 
quietly than if you were to keep your finger outstretched 
altogether; and it will set to climbing your finger: for the 
creature is so weak-sighted that it will take to climbing your 
finger as though that were a moving leaf. 



31 

Of insects that are not carnivorous but that live on the juices of 
living flesh, such as lice and fleas and bugs, all, without 
exception, generate what are called 'nits', and these nits 
generate nothing. 

Of these insects the flea is generated out of the slightest 
amount of putrefying matter; for wherever there is any dry 
excrement, a flea is sure to be found. Bugs are generated from 
the moisture of living animals, as it dries up outside their 
bodies. Lice are generated out of the flesh of animals. 

When lice are coming there is a kind of small eruption visible, 
unaccompanied by any discharge of purulent matter; and, if you 
prick an animal when in this condition at the spot of eruption, 
the lice jump out. In some men the appearance of lice is a 
disease, in cases where the body is surcharged with moisture; 
and, indeed, men have been known to succumb to this louse- 
disease, as Alcmeon the poet and the Syrian Pherecydes are said 
to have done. Moreover, in certain diseases lice appear in great 
abundance. 

There is also a species of louse called the 'wild louse', and this is 
harder than the ordinary louse, and there is exceptional 
difficulty in getting the skin rid of it. Boys' heads are apt to be 



1587 



lousy, but men's in less degree; and women are more subject to 
lice than men. But, whenever people are troubled with lousy 
heads, they are less than ordinarily troubled with headache. 
And lice are generated in other animals than man. For birds are 
infested with them; and pheasants, unless they clean 
themselves in the dust, are actually destroyed by them. All 
other winged animals that are furnished with feathers are 
similarly infested, and all hair-coated creatures also, with the 
single exception of the ass, which is infested neither with lice 
nor with ticks. 

Cattle suffer both from lice and from ticks. Sheep and goats 
breed ticks, but do not breed lice. Pigs breed lice large and hard. 
In dogs are found the flea peculiar to the animal, the 
Cynoroestes. In all animals that are subject to lice, the latter 
originate from the animals themselves. Moreover, in animals 
that bathe at all, lice are more than usually abundant when 
they change the water in which they bathe. 

In the sea, lice are found on fishes, but they are generated not 
out of the fish but out of slime; and they resemble multipedal 
wood-lice, only that their tail is flat. Sea-lice are uniform in 
shape and universal in locality, and are particularly numerous 
on the body of the red mullet. And all these insects are 
multipedal and devoid of blood. 

The parasite that feeds on the tunny is found in the region of 
the fins; it resembles a scorpion, and is about the size of a 
spider. In the seas between Cyrene and Egypt there is a fish that 
attends on the dolphin, which is called the 'dolphin's louse'. 
This fish gets exceedingly fat from enjoying an abundance of 
food while the dolphin is out in pursuit of its prey. 



1588 



32 

Other animalcules besides these are generated, as we have 
already remarked, some in wool or in articles made of wool, as 
the ses or clothes-moth. And these animalcules come in greater 
numbers if the woollen substances are dusty; and they come in 
especially large numbers if a spider be shut up in the cloth or 
wool, for the creature drinks up any moisture that may be there, 
and dries up the woollen substance. This grub is found also in 
men's clothes. 

A creature is also found in wax long laid by, just as in wood, and 
it is the smallest of animalcules and is white in colour, and is 
designated the acari or mite. In books also other animalcules 
are found, some resembling the grubs found in garments, and 
some resembling tailless scorpions, but very small. As a general 
rule we may state that such animalcules are found in practically 
anything, both in dry things that are becoming moist and in 
moist things that are drying, provided they contain the 
conditions of life. 

There is a grub entitled the 'faggot-bearer', as strange a creature 
as is known. Its head projects outside its shell, mottled in 
colour, and its feet are near the end or apex, as is the case with 
grubs in general; but the rest of its body is cased in a tunic as it 
were of spider's web, and there are little dry twigs about it, that 
look as though they had stuck by accident to the creature as it 
went walking about. But these twig-like formations are 
naturally connected with the tunic, for just as the shell is with 
the body of the snail so is the whole superstructure with our 
grub; and they do not drop off, but can only be torn off, as 
though they were all of a piece with him, and the removal of the 
tunic is as fatal to this grub as the removal of the shell would be 
to the snail. In course of time this grub becomes a chrysalis, as 
is the case with the silkworm, and lives in a motionless 



1589 



condition. But as yet it is not known into what winged condition 
it is transformed. 

The fruit of the wild fig contains the psen, or fig-wasp. This 
creature is a grub at first; but in due time the husk peels off and 
the psen leaves the husk behind it and flies away, and enters 
into the fruit of the fig-tree through its orifice, and causes the 
fruit not to drop off; and with a view to this phenomenon, 
country folk are in the habit of tying wild figs on to fig-trees, 
and of planting wild fig-trees near domesticated ones. 



33 

In the case of animals that are quadrupeds and red-blooded and 
oviparous, generation takes place in the spring, but copulation 
does not take place in an uniform season. In some cases it takes 
place in the spring, in others in summer time, and in others in 
the autumn, according as the subsequent season may be 
favourable for the young. 

The tortoise lays eggs with a hard shell and of two colours 
within, like birds' eggs, and after laying them buries them in the 
ground and treads the ground hard over them; it then broods 
over the eggs on the surface of the ground, and hatches the eggs 
the next year. The hemys, or fresh-water tortoise, leaves the 
water and lays its eggs. It digs a hole of a casklike shape, and 
deposits therein the eggs; after rather less than thirty days it 
digs the eggs up again and hatches them with great rapidity, 
and leads its young at once off to the water. The sea-turtle lays 
on the ground eggs just like the eggs of domesticated birds, 
buries the eggs in the ground, and broods over them in the 
night-time. It lays a very great number of eggs, amounting at 
times to one hundred. 



1590 



Lizards and crocodiles, terrestrial and fluvial, lay eggs on land. 
The eggs of lizards hatch spontaneously on land, for the lizard 
does not live on into the next year; in fact, the life of the animal 
is said not to exceed six months. The river-crocodile lays a 
number of eggs, sixty at the most, white in colour, and broods 
over them for sixty days: for, by the way, the creature is very 
long-lived. And the disproportion is more marked in this animal 
than in any other between the smallness of the original egg and 
the huge size of the full-grown animal. For the egg is not larger 
than that of the goose, and the young crocodile is small, 
answering to the egg in size, but the full-grown animal attains 
the length of twenty-six feet; in fact, it is actually stated that 
the animal goes on growing to the end of its days. 



34 

With regard to serpents or snakes, the viper is externally 
viviparous, having been previously oviparous internally. The egg, 
as with the egg of fishes, is uniform in colour and soft-skinned. 
The young serpent grows on the surface of the egg, and, like the 
young of fishes, has no shell-like envelopment. The young of the 
viper is born inside a membrane that bursts from off the young 
creature in three days; and at times the young viper eats its way 
out from the inside of the egg. The mother viper brings forth all 
its young in one day, twenty in number, and one at a time. The 
other serpents are externally oviparous, and their eggs are 
strung on to one another like a lady's necklace; after the dam 
has laid her eggs in the ground she broods over them, and 
hatches the eggs in the following year. 



1591 



Book VI 



So much for the generative processes in snakes and insects, and 
also in oviparous quadrupeds. Birds without exception lay eggs, 
but the pairing season and the times of parturition are not alike 
for all. Some birds couple and lay at almost any time in the year, 
as for instance the barn-door hen and the pigeon: the former of 
these coupling and laying during the entire year, with the 
exception of the month before and the month after the winter 
solstice. Some hens, even in the high breeds, lay a large quantity 
of eggs before brooding, amounting to as many as sixty; and, by 
the way, the higher breeds are less prolific than the inferior 
ones. The Adrian hens are small-sized, but they lay every day; 
they are cross-tempered, and often kill their chickens; they are 
of all colours. Some domesticated hens lay twice a day; indeed, 
instances have been known where hens, after exhibiting 
extreme fecundity, have died suddenly. Hens, then, lay eggs, as 
has been stated, at all times indiscriminately; the pigeon, the 
ring-dove, the turtle-dove, and the stock-dove lay twice a year, 
and the pigeon actually lays ten times a year. The great majority 
of birds lay during the spring-time. Some birds are prolific, and 
prolific in either of two ways - either by laying often, as the 
pigeon, or by laying many eggs at a sitting, as the barn-door 
hen. All birds of prey, or birds with crooked talons, are 
unprolific, except the kestrel: this bird is the most prolific of 
birds of prey; as many as four eggs have been observed in the 
nest, and occasionally it lays even more. 



1592 



Birds in general lay their eggs in nests, but such as are 
disqualified for flight, as the partridge and the quail, do not lay 
them in nests but on the ground, and cover them over with 
loose material. The same is the case with the lark and the tetrix. 
These birds hatch in sheltered places; but the bird called 
merops in Boeotia, alone of all birds, burrows into holes in the 
ground and hatches there. 

Thrushes, like swallows, build nests of clay, on high trees, and 
build them in rows all close together, so that from their 
continuity the structure resembles a necklace of nests. Of all 
birds that hatch for themselves the hoopoe is the only one that 
builds no nest whatever; it gets into the hollow of the trunk of a 
tree, and lays its eggs there without making any sort of nest. 
The circus builds either under a dwelling-roof or on cliffs. The 
tetrix, called ourax in Athens, builds neither on the ground nor 
on trees, but on low-lying shrubs. 



The egg in the case of all birds alike is hard-shelled, if it be the 
produce of copulation and be laid by a healthy hen - for some 
hens lay soft eggs. The interior of the egg is of two colours, and 
the white part is outside and the yellow part within. 

The eggs of birds that frequent rivers and marshes differ from 
those of birds that live on dry land; that is to say, the eggs of 
waterbirds have comparatively more of the yellow or yolk and 
less of the white. Eggs vary in colour according to their kind. 
Some eggs are white, as those of the pigeon and of the 
partridge; others are yellowish, as the eggs of marsh birds; in 
some cases the eggs are mottled, as the eggs of the guinea-fowl 



1593 



and the pheasant; while the eggs of the kestrel are red, like 
vermilion. 

Eggs are not symmetrically shaped at both ends: in other words, 
one end is comparatively sharp, and the other end is 
comparatively blunt; and it is the latter end that protrudes first 
at the time of laying. Long and pointed eggs are female; those 
that are round, or more rounded at the narrow end, are male. 
Eggs are hatched by the incubation of the mother-bird. In some 
cases, as in Egypt, they are hatched spontaneously in the 
ground, by being buried in dung heaps. A story is told of a toper 
in Syracuse, how he used to put eggs into the ground under his 
rush-mat and to keep on drinking until he hatched them. 
Instances have occurred of eggs being deposited in warm 
vessels and getting hatched spontaneously. 

The sperm of birds, as of animals in general, is white. After the 
female has submitted to the male, she draws up the sperm to 
underneath her midriff. At first it is little in size and white in 
colour; by and by it is red, the colour of blood; as it grows, it 
becomes pale and yellow all over. When at length it is getting 
ripe for hatching, it is subject to differentiation of substance, 
and the yolk gathers together within and the white settles 
round it on the outside. When the full time is come, the egg 
detaches itself and protrudes, changing from soft to hard with 
such temporal exactitude that, whereas it is not hard during the 
process of protrusion, it hardens immediately after the process 
is completed: that is if there be no concomitant pathological 
circumstances. Cases have occurred where substances 
resembling the egg at a critical point of its growth - that is, 
when it is yellow all over, as the yolk is subsequently - have 
been found in the cock when cut open, underneath his midriff, 
just where the hen has her eggs; and these are entirely yellow 
in appearance and of the same size as ordinary eggs. Such 
phenomena are regarded as unnatural and portentous. 



1594 



Such as affirm that wind-eggs are the residua of eggs previously 
begotten from copulation are mistaken in this assertion, for we 
have cases well authenticated where chickens of the common 
hen and goose have laid wind-eggs without ever having been 
subjected to copulation. Wind-eggs are smaller, less palatable, 
and more liquid than true eggs, and are produced in greater 
numbers. When they are put under the mother bird, the liquid 
contents never coagulate, but both the yellow and the white 
remain as they were. Wind-eggs are laid by a number of birds: as 
for instance by the common hen, the hen partridge, the hen 
pigeon, the peahen, the goose, and the vulpanser. Eggs are 
hatched under brooding hens more rapidly in summer than in 
winter; that is to say, hens hatch in eighteen days in summer, 
but occasionally in winter take as many as twenty-five. And by 
the way for brooding purposes some birds make better mothers 
than others. If it thunders while a hen-bird is brooding, the eggs 
get addled. Wind-eggs that are called by some cynosura and uria 
are produced chiefly in summer. Wind-eggs are called by some 
zephyr-eggs, because at spring-time hen-birds are observed to 
inhale the breezes; they do the same if they be stroked in a 
peculiar way by hand. Wind-eggs can turn into fertile eggs, and 
eggs due to previous copulation can change breed, if before the 
change of the yellow to the white the hen that contains wind- 
eggs, or eggs begotten of copulation be trodden by another cock- 
bird. Under these circumstances the wind-eggs turn into fertile 
eggs, and the previously impregnated eggs follow the breed of 
the impregnator; but if the latter impregnation takes place 
during the change of the yellow to the white, then no change in 
the egg takes place: the wind-egg does not become a true egg, 
and the true egg does not take on the breed of the latter 
impregnator. If when the egg-substance is small copulation be 
intermitted, the previously existing egg-substance exhibits no 
increase; but if the hen be again submitted to the male the 
increase in size proceeds with rapidity. 



1595 



The yolk and the white are diverse not only in colour but also in 
properties. Thus, the yolk congeals under the influence of cold, 
whereas the white instead of congealing is inclined rather to 
liquefy. Again, the white stiffens under the influence of fire, 
whereas the yolk does not stiffen; but, unless it be burnt 
through and through, it remains soft, and in point of fact is 
inclined to set or to harden more from the boiling than from the 
roasting of the egg. The yolk and the white are separated by a 
membrane from one another. The so-called 'hail-stones', or 
treadles, that are found at the extremity of the yellow in no way 
contribute towards generation, as some erroneously suppose: 
they are two in number, one below and the other above. If you 
take out of the shells a number of yolks and a number of whites 
and pour them into a sauce pan and boil them slowly over a low 
fire, the yolks will gather into the centre and the whites will set 
all around them. 

Young hens are the first to lay, and they do so at the beginning 
of spring and lay more eggs than the older hens, but the eggs of 
the younger hens are comparatively small. As a general rule, if 
hens get no brooding they pine and sicken. After copulation 
hens shiver and shake themselves, and often kick rubbish about 
all round them - and this, by the way, they do sometimes after 
laying - whereas pigeons trail their rumps on the ground, and 
geese dive under the water. Conception of the true egg and 
conformation of the wind-egg take place rapidly with most 
birds; as for instance with the hen-partridge when in heat. The 
fact is that, when she stands to windward and within scent of 
the male, she conceives, and becomes useless for decoy 
purposes: for, by the way, the partridge appears to have a very 
acute sense of smell. 

The generation of the egg after copulation and the generation of 
the chick from the subsequent hatching of the egg are not 
brought about within equal periods for all birds, but differ as to 



1596 



time according to the size of the parent-birds. The egg of the 
common hen after copulation sets and matures in ten days a 
general rule; the egg of the pigeon in a somewhat lesser period. 
Pigeons have the faculty of holding back the egg at the very 
moment of parturition; if a hen pigeon be put about by any one, 
for instance if it be disturbed on its nest, or have a feather 
plucked out, or sustain any other annoyance or disturbance, 
then even though she had made up her mind to lay she can 
keep the egg back in abeyance. A singular phenomenon is 
observed in pigeons with regard to pairing: that is, they kiss one 
another just when the male is on the point of mounting the 
female, and without this preliminary the male would decline to 
perform his function. With the older males the preliminary kiss 
is only given to begin with, and subsequently sequently he 
mounts without previously kissing; with younger males the 
preliminary is never omitted. Another singularity in these birds 
is that the hens tread one another when a cock is not 
forthcoming, after kissing one another just as takes place in the 
normal pairing. Though they do not impregnate one another 
they lay more eggs under these than under ordinary 
circumstances; no chicks, however, result therefrom, but all 
such eggs are wind-eggs. 



Generation from the egg proceeds in an identical manner with 
all birds, but the full periods from conception to birth differ, as 
has been said. With the common hen after three days and three 
nights there is the first indication of the embryo; with larger 
birds the interval being longer, with smaller birds shorter. 
Meanwhile the yolk comes into being, rising towards the sharp 
end, where the primal element of the egg is situated, and where 



1597 



the egg gets hatched; and the heart appears, like a speck of 
blood, in the white of the egg. This point beats and moves as 
though endowed with life, and from it two vein-ducts with 
blood in them trend in a convoluted course (as the egg 
substance goes on growing, towards each of the two 
circumjacent integuments); and a membrane carrying bloody 
fibres now envelops the yolk, leading off from the vein-ducts. A 
little afterwards the body is differentiated, at first very small 
and white. The head is clearly distinguished, and in it the eyes, 
swollen out to a great extent. This condition of the eyes lat on 
for a good while, as it is only by degrees that they diminish in 
size and collapse. At the outset the under portion of the body 
appears insignificant in comparison with the upper portion. Of 
the two ducts that lead from the heart, the one proceeds 
towards the circumjacent integument, and the other, like a 
navel-string, towards the yolk. The life-element of the chick is in 
the white of the egg, and the nutriment comes through the 
navel-string out of the yolk. 

When the egg is now ten days old the chick and all its parts are 
distinctly visible. The head is still larger than the rest of its body, 
and the eyes larger than the head, but still devoid of vision. The 
eyes, if removed about this time, are found to be larger than 
beans, and black; if the cuticle be peeled off them there is a 
white and cold liquid inside, quite glittering in the sunlight, but 
there is no hard substance whatsoever. Such is the condition of 
the head and eyes. At this time also the larger internal organs 
are visible, as also the stomach and the arrangement of the 
viscera; and veins that seem to proceed from the heart are now 
close to the navel. From the navel there stretch a pair of veins; 
one towards the membrane that envelops the yolk (and, by the 
way, the yolk is now liquid, or more so than is normal), and the 
other towards that membrane which envelops collectively the 
membrane wherein the chick lies, the membrane of the yolk, 
and the intervening liquid. (For, as the chick grows, little by little 



1598 



one part of the yolk goes upward, and another part downward, 
and the white liquid is between them; and the white of the egg 
is underneath the lower part of the yolk, as it was at the outset.) 
On the tenth day the white is at the extreme outer surface, 
reduced in amount, glutinous, firm in substance, and sallow in 
colour. 

The disposition of the several constituent parts is as follows. 
First and outermost comes the membrane of the egg, not that of 
the shell, but underneath it. Inside this membrane is a white 
liquid; then comes the chick, and a membrane round about it, 
separating it off so as to keep the chick free from the liquid; 
next after the chick comes the yolk, into which one of the two 
veins was described as leading, the other one leading into the 
enveloping white substance. (A membrane with a liquid 
resembling serum envelops the entire structure. Then comes 
another membrane right round the embryo, as has been 
described, separating it off against the liquid. Underneath this 
comes the yolk, enveloped in another membrane (into which 
yolk proceeds the navel-string that leads from the heart and the 
big vein), so as to keep the embryo free of both liquids.) 

About the twentieth day, if you open the egg and touch the 
chick, it moves inside and chirps; and it is already coming to be 
covered with down, when, after the twentieth day is ast, the 
chick begins to break the shell. The head is situated over the 
right leg close to the flank, and the wing is placed over the head; 
and about this time is plain to be seen the membrane 
resembling an after-birth that comes next after the outermost 
membrane of the shell, into which membrane the one of the 
navel-strings was described as leading (and, by the way, the 
chick in its entirety is now within it), and so also is the other 
membrane resembling an after-birth, namely that surrounding 
the yolk, into which the second navel-string was described as 
leading; and both of them were described as being connected 



1599 



with the heart and the big vein. At this conjuncture the navel- 
string that leads to the outer afterbirth collapses and becomes 
detached from the chick, and the membrane that leads into the 
yolk is fastened on to the thin gut of the creature, and by this 
time a considerable amount of the yolk is inside the chick and a 
yellow sediment is in its stomach. About this time it discharges 
residuum in the direction of the outer after-birth, and has 
residuum inside its stomach; and the outer residuum is white 
(and there comes a white substance inside). By and by the yolk, 
diminishing gradually in size, at length becomes entirely used 
up and comprehended within the chick (so that, ten days after 
hatching, if you cut open the chick, a small remnant of the yolk 
is still left in connexion with the gut), but it is detached from 
the navel, and there is nothing in the interval between, but it 
has been used up entirely. During the period above referred to 
the chick sleeps, wakes up, makes a move and looks up and 
Chirps; and the heart and the navel together palpitate as 
though the creature were respiring. So much as to generation 
from the egg in the case of birds. 

Birds lay some eggs that are unfruitful, even eggs that are the 
result of copulation, and no life comes from such eggs by 
incubation; and this phenomenon is observed especially with 
pigeons. 

Twin eggs have two yolks. In some twin eggs a thin partition of 
white intervenes to prevent the yolks mixing with each other, 
but some twin eggs are unprovided with such partition, and the 
yokes run into one another. There are some hens that lay 
nothing but twin eggs, and in their case the phenomenon 
regarding the yolks has been observed. For instance, a hen has 
been known to lay eighteen eggs, and to hatch twins out of 
them all, except those that were wind-eggs; the rest were fertile 
(though, by the way, one of the twins is always bigger than the 
other), but the eighteenth was abnormal or monstrous. 



1600 



Birds of the pigeon kind, such as the ringdove and the turtle- 
dove, lay two eggs at a time; that is to say, they do so as a 
general rule, and they never lay more than three. The pigeon, as 
has been said, lays at all seasons; the ring-dove and the turtle- 
dove lay in the springtime, and they never lay more than twice 
in the same season. The hen-bird lays the second pair of eggs 
when the first pair happens to have been destroyed, for many of 
the hen-pigeons destroy the first brood. The hen-pigeon, as has 
been said, occasionally lays three eggs, but it never rears more 
than two chicks, and sometimes rears only one; and the odd 
one is always a wind-egg. 

Very few birds propagate within their first year. All birds, after 
once they have begun laying, keep on having eggs, though in the 
case of some birds it is difficult to detect the fact from the 
minute size of the creature. 

The pigeon, as a rule, lays a male and a female egg, and 
generally lays the male egg first; after laying it allows a day's 
interval to ensue and then lays the second egg. The male takes 
its turn of sitting during the daytime; the female sits during the 
night. The first-laid egg is hatched and brought to birth within 
twenty days; and the mother bird pecks a hole in the egg the 
day before she hatches it out. The two parent birds brood for 
some time over the chicks in the way in which they brooded 
previously over the eggs. In all connected with the rearing of the 
young the female parent is more cross-tempered than the male, 
as is the case with most animals after parturition. The hens lay 
as many as ten times in the year; occasional instances have 
been known of their laying eleven times, and in Egypt they 



1601 



actually lay twelve times. The pigeon, male and female, couples 
within the year; in fact, it couples when only six months old. 
Some assert that ringdoves and turtle-doves pair and procreate 
when only three months old, and instance their superabundant 
numbers by way of proof of the assertion. The hen-pigeon 
carries her eggs fourteen days; for as many more days the 
parent birds hatch the eggs; by the end of another fourteen days 
the chicks are so far capable of flight as to be overtaken with 
difficulty. (The ring-dove, according to all accounts, lives up to 
forty years. The partridge lives over sixteen.) (After one brood 
the pigeon is ready for another within thirty days.) 



The vulture builds its nest on inaccessible cliffs; for which 
reason its nest and young are rarely seen. And therefore 
Herodorus, father of Bryson the Sophist, declares that vultures 
belong to some foreign country unknown to us, stating as a 
proof of the assertion that no one has ever seen a vulture's nest, 
and also that vultures in great numbers make a sudden 
appearance in the rear of armies. However, difficult as it is to 
get a sight of it, a vulture's nest has been seen. The vulture lays 
two eggs. 

(Carnivorous birds in general are observed to lay but once a 
year. The swallow is the only carnivorous bird that builds a nest 
twice. If you prick out the eyes of swallow chicks while they are 
yet young, the birds will get well again and will see by and by.) 



1602 



The eagle lays three eggs and hatches two of them, as it is said 
in the verses ascribed to Musaeus: 

That lays three, hatches two, and cares for one. 

This is the case in most instances, though occasionally a brood 
of three has been observed. As the young ones grow, the mother 
becomes wearied with feeding them and extrudes one of the 
pair from the nest. At the same time the bird is said to abstain 
from food, to avoid harrying the young of wild animals. That is 
to say, its wings blanch, and for some days its talons get turned 
awry. It is in consequence about this time cross-tempered to its 
own young. The phene is said to rear the young one that has 
been expelled the nest. The eagle broods for about thirty days. 

The hatching period is about the same for the larger birds, such 
as the goose and the great bustard; for the middle-sized birds it 
extends over about twenty days, as in the case of the kite and 
the hawk. The kite in general lays two eggs, but occasionally 
rears three young ones. The so-called aegolius at times rears 
four. It is not true that, as some aver, the raven lays only two 
eggs; it lays a larger number. It broods for about twenty days 
and then extrudes its young. Other birds perform the same 
operation; at all events mother birds that lay several eggs often 
extrude one of their young. 

Birds of the eagle species are not alike in the treatment of their 
young. The white-tailed eagle is cross, the black eagle is 
affectionate in the feeding of the young; though, by the way, all 
birds of prey, when their brood is rather forward in being able to 
fly, beat and extrude them from the nest. The majority of birds 
other than birds of prey, as has been said, also act in this 
manner, and after feeding their young take no further care of 
them; but the crow is an exception. This bird for a considerable 



1603 



time takes charge of her young; for, even when her young can 
fly, she flies alongside of them and supplies them with food. 



The cuckoo is said by some to be a hawk transformed, because 
at the time of the cuckoo's coming, the hawk, which it 
resembles, is never seen; and indeed it is only for a few days 
that you will see hawks about when the cuckoo's note sounds 
early in the season. The cuckoo appears only for a short time in 
summer, and in winter disappears. The hawk has crooked 
talons, which the cuckoo has not; neither with regard to the 
head does the cuckoo resemble the hawk. In point of fact, both 
as regards the head and the claws it more resembles the pigeon. 
However, in colour and in colour alone it does resemble the 
hawk, only that the markings of the hawk are striped, and of the 
cuckoo mottled. And, by the way, in size and flight it resembles 
the smallest of the hawk tribe, which bird disappears as a rule 
about the time of the appearance of the cuckoo, though the two 
have been seen simultaneously. The cuckoo has been seen to be 
preyed on by the hawk; and this never happens between birds 
of the same species. They say no one has ever seen the young of 
the cuckoo. The bird eggs, but does not build a nest. Sometimes 
it lays its eggs in the nest of a smaller bird after first devouring 
the eggs of this bird; it lays by preference in the nest of the 
ringdove, after first devouring the eggs of the pigeon. (It 
occasionally lays two, but usually one.) It lays also in the nest of 
the hypolais, and the hypolais hatches and rears the brood. It is 
about this time that the bird becomes fat and palatable. (The 
young of hawks also get palatable and fat. One species builds a 
nest in the wilderness and on sheer and inaccessible cliffs.) 



1604 



8 

With most birds, as has been said of the pigeon, the hatching is 
carried on by the male and the female in turns: with some birds, 
however, the male only sits long enough to allow the female to 
provide herself with food. In the goose tribe the female alone 
incubates, and after once sitting on the eggs she continues 
brooding until they are hatched. 

The nests of all marsh-birds are built in districts fenny and well 
supplied with grass; consequently, the mother-bird while sitting 
quiet on her eggs can provide herself with food without having 
to submit to absolute fasting. 

With the crow also the female alone broods, and broods 
throughout the whole period; the male bird supports the 
female, bringing her food and feeding her. The female of the 
ring-dove begins to brood in the afternoon and broods through 
the entire night until breakfast-time of the following day; the 
male broods during the rest of the time. Partridges build a nest 
in two compartments; the male broods on the one and the 
female on the other. After hatching, each of the parent birds 
rears its brood. But the male, when he first takes his young out 
of the nest, treads them. 



Peafowl live for about twenty-five years, breed about the third 
year, and at the same time take on their spangled plumage. 
They hatch their eggs within thirty days or rather more. The 



1605 



peahen lays but once a year, and lays twelve eggs, or may be a 
slightly lesser number: she does not lay all the eggs there and 
then one after the other, but at intervals of two or three days. 
Such as lay for the first time lay about eight eggs. The peahen 
lays wind-eggs. They pair in the spring; and laying begins 
immediately after pairing. The bird moults when the earliest 
trees are shedding their leaves, and recovers its plumage when 
the same trees are recovering their foliage. People that rear 
peafowl put the eggs under the barn-door hen, owing to the fact 
that when the peahen is brooding over them the peacock 
attacks her and tries to trample on them; owing to this 
circumstance some birds of wild varieties run away from the 
males and lay their eggs and brood in solitude. Only two eggs 
are put under a barn-door hen, for she could not brood over and 
hatch a large number. They take every precaution, by supplying 
her with food, to prevent her going off the eggs and 
discontinuing the brooding. 

With male birds about pairing time the testicles are obviously 
larger than at other times, and this is conspicuously the case 
with the more salacious birds, such as the barn-door cock and 
the cock partridge; the peculiarity is less conspicuous in such 
birds as are intermittent in regard to pairing. 



10 

So much for the conception and generation of birds. 

It has been previously stated that fishes are not all oviparous. 
Fishes of the cartilaginous genus are viviparous; the rest are 
oviparous. And cartilaginous fishes are first oviparous internally 
and subsequently viviparous; they rear the embryos internally, 
the batrachus or fishing- frog being an exception. 



1606 



Fishes also, as was above stated, are provided with wombs, and 
wombs of diverse kinds. The oviparous genera have wombs 
bifurcate in shape and low down in position; the cartilaginous 
genus have wombs shaped like those of birds. The womb, 
however, in the cartilaginous fishes differs in this respect from 
the womb of birds, that with some cartilaginous fishes the eggs 
do not settle close to the diaphragm but middle-ways along the 
backbone, and as they grow they shift their position. 

The egg with all fishes is not of two colours within but is of 
even hue; and the colour is nearer to white than to yellow, and 
that both when the young is inside it and previously as well. 

Development from the egg in fishes differs from that in birds in 
this respect, that it does not exhibit that one of the two navel- 
strings that leads off to the membrane that lies close under the 
shell, while it does exhibit that one of the two that in the case 
of birds leads off to the yolk. In a general way the rest of the 
development from the egg onwards is identical in birds and 
fishes. That is to say, development takes place at the upper part 
of the egg, and the veins extend in like manner, at first from the 
heart; and at first the head, the eyes, and the upper parts are 
largest; and as the creature grows the egg-substance decreases 
and eventually disappears, and becomes absorbed within the 
embryo, just as takes place with the yolk in birds. 

The navel-string is attached a little way below the aperture of 
the belly. When the creatures are young the navel-string is long, 
but as they grow it diminishes in size; at length it gets small 
and becomes incorporated, as was described in the case of 
birds. The embryo and the egg are enveloped by a common 
membrane, and just under this is another membrane that 
envelops the embryo by itself; and in between the two 
membranes is a liquid. The food inside the stomach of the little 



1607 



fishes resembles that inside the stomach of young chicks, and is 
partly white and partly yellow. 

As regards the shape of the womb, the reader is referred to my 
treatise on Anatomy. The womb, however, is diverse in diverse 
fishes, as for instance in the sharks as compared one with 
another or as compared with the skate. That is to say, in some 
sharks the eggs adhere in the middle of the womb round about 
the backbone, as has been stated, and this is the case with the 
dog-fish; as the eggs grow they shift their place; and since the 
womb is bifurcate and adheres to the midriff, as in the rest of 
similar creatures, the eggs pass into one or other of the two 
compartments. This womb and the womb of the other sharks 
exhibit, as you go a little way off from the midriff, something 
resembling white breasts, which never make their appearance 
unless there be conception. 

Dog-fish and skate have a kind of egg-shell, in the which is 
found an egg-like liquid. The shape of the egg-shell resembles 
the tongue of a bagpipe, and hair-like ducts are attached to the 
shell. With the dog-fish which is called by some the 'dappled 
shark', the young are born when the shell-formation breaks in 
pieces and falls out; with the ray, after it has laid the egg the 
shell-formation breaks up and the young move out. The spiny 
dog-fish has its close to the midriff above the breast like 
formations; when the egg descends, as soon as it gets detached 
the young is born. The mode of generation is the same in the 
case of the fox-shark. 

The so-called smooth shark has its eggs in betwixt the wombs 
like the dog-fish; these eggs shift into each of the two horns of 
the womb and descend, and the young develop with the navel- 
string attached to the womb, so that, as the egg-substance gets 
used up, the embryo is sustained to all appearance just as in the 
case of quadrupeds. The navel-string is long and adheres to the 



1608 



under part of the womb (each navel-string being attached as it 
were by a sucker), and also to the centre of the embryo in the 
place where the liver is situated. If the embryo be cut open, even 
though it has the egg-substance no longer, the food inside is 
egg-like in appearance. Each embryo, as in the case of 
quadrupeds, is provided with a chorion and separate 
membranes. When young the embryo has its head upwards, but 
downwards when it gets strong and is completed in form. Males 
are generated on the left-hand side of the womb, and females 
on the right-hand side, and males and females on the same side 
together. If the embryo be cut open, then, as with quadrupeds, 
such internal organs as it is furnished with, as for instance the 
liver, are found to be large and supplied with blood. 

All cartilaginous fishes have at one and the same time eggs 
above close to the midriff (some larger, some smaller), in 
considerable numbers, and also embryos lower down. And this 
circumstance leads many to suppose that fishes of this species 
pair and bear young every month, inasmuch as they do not 
produce all their young at once, but now and again and over a 
lengthened period. But such eggs as have come down below 
within the womb are simultaneously ripened and completed in 
growth. 

Dog-fish in general can extrude and take in again their young, 
as can also the angel-fish and the electric ray - and, by the way, 
a large electric ray has been seen with about eighty embryos 
inside it - but the spiny dogfish is an exception to the rule, 
being prevented by the spine of the young fish from so doing. Of 
the flat cartilaginous fish, the trygon and the ray cannot extrude 
and take in again in consequence of the roughness of the tails 
of the young. The batrachus or fishing- frog also is unable to take 
in its young owing to the size of the head and the prickles; and, 
by the way, as was previously remarked, it is the only one of 
these fishes that is not viviparous. 



1609 



So much for the varieties of the cartilaginous species and for 
their modes of generation from the egg. 



11 

At the breeding season the sperm-ducts of the male are filled 
with sperm, so much so that if they be squeezed the sperm 
flows out spontaneously as a white fluid; the ducts are 
bifurcate, and start from the midriff and the great vein. About 
this period the sperm-ducts of the male are quite distinct (from 
the womb of the female) but at any other than the actual 
breeding time their distinctness is not obvious to a non-expert. 
The fact is that in certain fishes at certain times these organs 
are imperceptible, as was stated regarding the testicles of birds. 

Among other distinctions observed between the thoric ducts 
and the womb-ducts is the circumstance that the thoric ducts 
are attached to the loins, while the womb-ducts move about 
freely and are attached by a thin membrane. The particulars 
regarding the thoric ducts may be studied by a reference to the 
diagrams in my treatise on Anatomy. 

Cartilaginous fishes are capable of superfoetation, and their 
period of gestation is six months at the longest. The so-called 
starry dogfish bears young the most frequently; in other words 
it bears twice a month. The breeding season is in the month of 
Maemacterion. The dog-fish as a general rule bear twice in the 
year, with the exception of the little dog-fish, which bears only 
once a year. Some of them bring forth in the springtime. The 
rhine, or angel-fish, bears its first brood in the springtime, and 
its second in the autumn, about the winter setting of the 
Pleiads; the second brood is the stronger of the two. The electric 
ray brings forth in the late autumn. 



1610 



Cartilaginous fishes come out from the main seas and deep 
waters towards the shore and there bring forth their young, and 
they do so for the sake of warmth and by way of protection for 
their young. 

Observations would lead to the general rule that no one variety 
of fish pairs with another variety. The angel-fish, however, and 
the batus or skate appear to pair with one another; for there is a 
fish called the rhinobatus, with the head and front parts of the 
skate and the after parts of the rhine or angel-fish, just as 
though it were made up of both fishes together. 

Sharks then and their congeners, as the fox-shark and the dog- 
fish, and the flat fishes, such as the electric ray, the ray, the 
smooth skate, and the trygon, are first oviparous and then 
viviparous in the way above mentioned, (as are also the saw- 
fish and the ox-ray.) 



12 

The dolphin, the whale, and all the rest of the Cetacea, all, that 
is to say, that are provided with a blow-hole instead of gills, are 
viviparous. That is to say, no one of all these fishes is ever seen 
to be supplied with eggs, but directly with an embryo from 
whose differentiation comes the fish, just as in the case of 
mankind and the viviparous quadrupeds. 

The dolphin bears one at a time generally, but occasionally two. 
The whale bears one or at the most two, generally two. The 
porpoise in this respect resembles the dolphin, and, by the way, 
it is in form like a little dolphin, and is found in the Euxine; it 
differs, however, from the dolphin as being less in size and 



1611 



broader in the back; its colour is leaden-black. Many people are 
of opinion that the porpoise is a variety of the dolphin. 

All creatures that have a blow-hole respire and inspire, for they 
are provided with lungs. The dolphin has been seen asleep with 
his nose above water, and when asleep he snores. 

The dolphin and the porpoise are provided with milk, and 
suckle their young. They also take their young, when small, 
inside them. The young of the dolphin grow rapidly, being full 
grown at ten years of age. Its period of gestation is ten months. 
It brings forth its young summer, and never at any other season; 
(and, singularly enough, under the Dogstar it disappears for 
about thirty days). Its young accompany it for a considerable 
period; and, in fact, the creature is remarkable for the strength 
of its parental affection. It lives for many years; some are known 
to have lived for more than twenty-five, and some for thirty 
years; the fact is fishermen nick their tails sometimes and set 
them adrift again, and by this expedient their ages are 
ascertained. 

The seal is an amphibious animal: that is to say, it cannot take 
in water, but breathes and sleeps and brings forth on dry land - 
only close to the shore - as being an animal furnished with feet; 
it spends, however, the greater part of its time in the sea and 
derives its food from it, so that it must be classed in the 
category of marine animals. It is viviparous by immediate 
conception and brings forth its young alive, and exhibits an 
after-birth and all else just like a ewe. It bears one or two at a 
time, and three at the most. It has two teats, and suckles its 
young like a quadruped. Like the human species it brings forth 
at all seasons of the year, but especially at the time when the 
earliest kids are forthcoming. It conducts its young ones, when 
they are about twelve days old, over and over again during the 
day down to the sea, accustoming them by slow degrees to the 



1612 



water. It slips down steep places instead of walking, from the 
fact that it cannot steady itself by its feet. It can contract and 
draw itself in, for it is fleshy and soft and its bones are gristly. 
Owing to the flabbiness of its body it is difficult to kill a seal by a 
blow, unless you strike it on the temple. It looks like a cow. The 
female in regard to its genital organs resembles the female of 
the ray; in all other respects it resembles the female of the 
human species. 

So much for the phenomena of generation and of parturition in 
animals that live in water and are viviparous either internally or 
externally. 



13 

Oviparous fishes have their womb bifurcate and placed low 
down, as was said previously - and, by the way, all scaly fish are 
oviparous, as the basse, the mullet, the grey mullet, and the 
etelis, and all the so-called white-fish, and all the smooth or 
slippery fish except the eel - and their roe is of a crumbling or 
granular substance. This appearance is due to the fact that the 
whole womb of such fishes is full of eggs, so that in little fishes 
there seem to be only a couple of eggs there; for in small fishes 
the womb is indistinguishable, from its diminutive size and thin 
contexture. The pairing of fishes has been discussed previously. 

Fishes for the most part are divided into males and females, but 
one is puzzled to account for the erythrinus and the channa, for 
specimens of these species are never caught except in a 
condition of pregnancy. 

With such fish as pair, eggs are the result of copulation, but 
such fish have them also without copulation; and this is shown 



1613 



in the case of some river-fish, for the minnow has eggs when 
quite small, - almost, one may say, as soon as it is born. These 
fishes shed their eggs little by little, and, as is stated, the males 
swallow the greater part of them, and some portion of them 
goes to waste in the water; but such of the eggs as the female 
deposits on the spawning beds are saved. If all the eggs were 
preserved, each species would be infinite in number. The greater 
number of these eggs so deposited are not productive, but only 
those over which the male sheds the milt or sperm; for when 
the female has laid her eggs, the male follows and sheds its 
sperm over them, and from all the eggs so besprinkled young 
fishes proceed, while the rest are left to their fate. 

The same phenomenon is observed in the case of molluscs also; 
for in the case of the cuttlefish or sepia, after the female has 
deposited her eggs, the male besprinkles them. It is highly 
probable that a similar phenomenon takes place in regard to 
molluscs in general, though up to the present time the 
phenomenon has been observed only in the case of the 
cuttlefish. 

Fishes deposit their eggs close in to shore, the goby close to 
stones; and, by the way, the spawn of the goby is flat and 
crumbly. Fish in general so deposit their eggs; for the water 
close in to shore is warm and is better supplied with food than 
the outer sea, and serves as a protection to the spawn against 
the voracity of the larger fish. And it is for this reason that in 
the Euxine most fishes spawn near the mouth of the river 
Thermodon, because the locality is sheltered, genial, and 
supplied with fresh water. 

Oviparous fish as a rule spawn only once a year. The little 
phycis or black goby is an exception, as it spawns twice; the 
male of the black goby differs from the female as being blacker 
and having larger scales. 



1614 



Fishes then in general produce their young by copulation, and 
lay their eggs; but the pipefish, as some call it, when the time of 
parturition arrives, bursts in two, and the eggs escape out. For 
the fish has a diaphysis or cloven growth under the belly and 
abdomen (like the blind snakes), and, after it has spawned by 
the splitting of this diaphysis, the sides of the split grow 
together again. 

Development from the egg takes place similarly with fishes that 
are oviparous internally and with fishes that are oviparous 
externally; that is to say, the embryo comes at the upper end of 
the egg and is enveloped in a membrane, and the eyes, large 
and spherical, are the first organs visible. From this 
circumstance it is plain that the assertion is untenable which is 
made by some writers, to wit, that the young of oviparous fishes 
are generated like the grubs of worms; for the opposite 
phenomena are observed in the case of these grubs, in that 
their lower extremities are the larger at the outset, and that the 
eyes and the head appear later on. After the egg has been used 
up, the young fishes are like tadpoles in shape, and at first, 
without taking any nutriment, they grow by sustenance derived 
from the juice oozing from the egg; by and by, they are 
nourished up to full growth by the river-waters. 

When the Euxine is 'purged' a substance called phycus is 
carried into the Hellespont, and this substance is of a pale 
yellow colour. Some writers aver that it is the flower of the 
phycus, from which rouge is made; it comes at the beginning of 
summer. Oysters and the small fish of these localities feed on 
this substance, and some of the inhabitants of these maritime 
districts say that the purple murex derives its peculiar colour 
from it. 



1615 



14 

Marsh-fishes and river-fishes conceive at the age of five months 
as a general rule, and deposit their spawn towards the close of 
the year without exception. And with these fishes, like as with 
the marine fishes, the female does not void all her eggs at one 
time, nor the male his sperm; but they are at all times more or 
less provided, the female with eggs, and the male with sperm. 
The carp spawns as the seasons come round, five or six times, 
and follows in spawning the rising of the greater constellations. 
The chalcis spawns three times, and the other fishes once only 
in the year. They all spawn in pools left by the overflowing of 
rivers, and near to reedy places in marshes; as for instance the 
phoxinus or minnow and the perch. 

The glanis or sheat-fish and the perch deposit their spawn in 
one continuous string, like the frog; so continuous, in fact, is the 
convoluted spawn of the perch that, by reason of its 
smoothness, the fishermen in the marshes can unwind it off 
the reeds like threads off a reel. The larger individuals of the 
sheat-fish spawn in deep waters, some in water of a fathom's 
depth, the smaller in shallower water, generally close to the 
roots of the willow or of some other tree, or close to reeds or to 
moss. At times these fishes intertwine with one another, a big 
with a little one, and bring into juxtaposition the ducts - which 
some writers designate as navels - at the point where they emit 
the generative products and discharge the egg in the case of the 
female and the milt in the case of the male. Such eggs as are 
besprinkled with the milt grow, in a day or thereabouts, whiter 
and larger, and in a little while afterwards the fish's eyes 
become visible for these organs in all fishes, as for that matter 
in all other animals, are early conspicuous and seem 
disproportionately big. But such eggs as the milt fails to touch 
remain, as with marine fishes, useless and infertile. From the 
fertile eggs, as the little fish grow, a kind of sheath detaches 



1616 



itself; this is a membrane that envelops the egg and the young 
fish. When the milt has mingled with the eggs, the resulting 
product becomes very sticky or viscous, and adheres to the 
roots of trees or wherever it may have been laid. The male keeps 
on guard at the principal spawning-place, and the female after 
spawning goes away. 

In the case of the sheat-fish the growth from the egg is 
exceptionally slow, and, in consequence, the male has to keep 
watch for forty or fifty days to prevent the spawn being 
devoured by such little fishes as chance to come by. Next in 
point of slowness is the generation of the carp. As with fishes in 
general, so even with these, the spawn thus protected 
disappears and gets lost rapidly. 

In the case of some of the smaller fishes when they are only 
three days old young fishes are generated. Eggs touched by the 
male sperm take on increase both the same day and also later. 
The egg of the sheat-fish is as big as a vetch-seed; the egg of the 
carp and of the carp-species as big as a millet-seed. 

These fishes then spawn and generate in the way here 
described. The chalcis, however, spawns in deep water in dense 
shoals of fish; and the so-called tilon spawns near to beaches in 
sheltered spots in shoals likewise. The carp, the baleros, and 
fishes in general push eagerly into the shallows for the purpose 
of spawning, and very often thirteen or fourteen males are seen 
following a single female. When the female deposits her spawn 
and departs, the males follow on and shed the milt. The greater 
portion of the spawn gets wasted; because, owing to the fact 
that the female moves about while spawning, the spawn 
scatters, or so much of it as is caught in the stream and does 
not get entangled with some rubbish. For, with the exception of 
the sheatfish, no fish keeps on guard; unless, by the way, it be 



1617 



the carp, which is said to remain on guard, if it so happen that 
its spawn lies in a solid mass. 

All male fishes are supplied with milt, excepting the eel: with 
the eel, the male is devoid of milt, and the female of spawn. The 
mullet goes up from the sea to marshes and rivers; the eels, on 
the contrary, make their way down from the marshes and rivers 
to the sea. 



15 

The great majority of fish, then, as has been stated, proceed 
from eggs. However, there are some fish that proceed from mud 
and sand, even of those kinds that proceed also from pairing 
and the egg. This occurs in ponds here and there, and especially 
in a pond in the neighbourhood of Cnidos. This pond, it is said, 
at one time ran dry about the rising of the Dogstar, and the mud 
had all dried up; at the first fall of the rains there was a show of 
water in the pond, and on the first appearance of the water 
shoals of tiny fish were found in the pond. The fish in question 
was a kind of mullet, one which does not proceed from normal 
pairing, about the size of a small sprat, and not one of these 
fishes was provided with either spawn or milt. There are found 
also in Asia Minor, in rivers not communicating with the sea, 
little fishes like whitebait, differing from the small fry found 
near Cnidos but found under similar circumstances. Some 
writers actually aver that mullet all grow spontaneously. In this 
assertion they are mistaken, for the female of the fish is found 
provided with spawn, and the male with milt. However, there is 
a species of mullet that grows spontaneously out of mud and 
sand. 



1618 



From the facts above enumerated it is quite proved that certain 
fishes come spontaneously into existence, not being derived 
from eggs or from copulation. Such fish as are neither oviparous 
nor viviparous arise all from one of two sources, from mud, or 
from sand and from decayed matter that rises thence as a 
scum; for instance, the so-called froth of the small fry comes 
out of sandy ground. This fry is incapable of growth and of 
propagating its kind; after living for a while it dies away and 
another creature takes its place, and so, with short intervals 
excepted, it may be said to last the whole year through. At all 
events, it lasts from the autumn rising of Arcturus up to the 
spring-time. As a proof that these fish occasionally come out of 
the ground we have the fact that in cold weather they are not 
caught, and that they are caught in warm weather, obviously 
coming up out of the ground to catch the heat; also, when the 
fishermen use dredges and the ground is scraped up fairly 
often, the fishes appear in larger numbers and of superior 
quality. All other small fry are inferior in quality owing to 
rapidity of growth. The fry are found in sheltered and marshy 
districts, when after a spell of fine weather the ground is getting 
warmer, as, for instance, in the neighbourhood of Athens, at 
Salamis and near the tomb of Themistocles and at Marathon; 
for in these districts the froth is found. It appears, then, in such 
districts and during such weather, and occasionally appears 
after a heavy fall of rain in the froth that is thrown up by the 
falling rain, from which circumstance the substance derives its 
specific name. Foam is occasionally brought in on the surface of 
the sea in fair weather. (And in this, where it has formed on the 
surface, the so-called froth collects, as grubs swarm in manure; 
for which reason this fry is often brought in from the open sea. 
The fish is at its best in quality and quantity in moist warm 
weather.) 

The ordinary fry is the normal issue of parent fishes: the so- 
called gudgeon-fry of small insignificant gudgeon-like fish that 



1619 



burrow under the ground. From the Phaleric fry comes the 
membras, from the membras the trichis, from the trichis the 
trichias, and from one particular sort of fry, to wit from that 
found in the harbour of Athens, comes what is called the 
encrasicholus, or anchovy. There is another fry, derived from the 
maenis and the mullet. 

The unfertile fry is watery and keeps only a short time, as has 
been stated, for at last only head and eyes are left. However, the 
fishermen of late have hit upon a method of transporting it to a 
distance, as when salted it keeps for a considerable time. 



16 

Eels are not the issue of pairing, neither are they oviparous; nor 
was an eel ever found supplied with either milt or spawn, nor 
are they when cut open found to have within them passages for 
spawn or for eggs. In point of fact, this entire species of blooded 
animals proceeds neither from pair nor from the egg. 

There can be no doubt that the case is so. For in some standing 
pools, after the water has been drained off and the mud has 
been dredged away, the eels appear again after a fall of rain. In 
time of drought they do not appear even in stagnant ponds, for 
the simple reason that their existence and sustenance is 
derived from rain-water. 

There is no doubt, then, that they proceed neither from pairing 
nor from an egg. Some writers, however, are of opinion that they 
generate their kind, because in some eels little worms are 
found, from which they suppose that eels are derived. But this 
opinion is not founded on fact. Eels are derived from the so- 
called 'earth's guts' that grow spontaneously in mud and in 



1620 



humid ground; in fact, eels have at times been seen to emerge 
out of such earthworms, and on other occasions have been 
rendered visible when the earthworms were laid open by either 
scraping or cutting. Such earthworms are found both in the sea 
and in rivers, especially where there is decayed matter: in the 
sea in places where sea-weed abounds, and in rivers and 
marshes near to the edge; for it is near to the water's edge that 
sun-heat has its chief power and produces putrefaction. So 
much for the generation of the eel. 



17 

Fish do not all bring forth their young at the same season nor all 
in like manner, neither is the period of gestation for all of the 
same duration. 

Before pairing the males and females gather together in shoals; 
at the time for copulation and parturition they pair off. With 
some fishes the time of gestation is not longer than thirty days, 
with others it is a lesser period; but with all it extends over a 
number of days divisible by seven. The longest period of 
gestation is that of the species which some call a marinus. 

The sargue conceives during the month of Poseideon (or 
December), and carries its spawn for thirty days; and the 
species of mullet named by some the chelon, and the myxon, go 
with spawn at the same period and over the same length of 
time. 

All fish suffer greatly during the period of gestation, and are in 
consequence very apt to be thrown up on shore at this time. In 
some cases they are driven frantic with pain and throw 
themselves on land. At all events they are throughout this time 



1621 



continually in motion until parturition is over (this being 
especially true of the mullet), and after parturition they are in 
repose. With many fish the time for parturition terminates on 
the appearance of grubs within the belly; for small living grubs 
get generated there and eat up the spawn. 

With shoal fishes parturition takes place in the spring, and 
indeed, with most fishes, about the time of the spring equinox; 
with others it is at different times, in summer with some, and 
with others about the autumn equinox. 

The first of shoal fishes to spawn is the atherine, and it spawns 
close to land; the last is the cephalus: and this is inferred from 
the fact that the brood of the atherine appears first of all and 
the brood of the cephalus last. The mullet also spawns early. 
The saupe spawns usually at the beginning of summer, but 
occasionally in the autumn. The aulopias, which some call the 
anthias, spawns in the summer. Next in order of spawning 
comes the chrysophrys or gilthead, the basse, the mormyrus, 
and in general such fish as are nicknamed 'runners'. Latest in 
order of the shoal fish come the red mullet and the coracine; 
these spawn in autumn. The red mullet spawns on mud, and 
consequently, as the mud continues cold for a long while, 
spawns late in the year. The coracine carries its spawn for a long 
time; but, as it lives usually on rocky ground, it goes to a 
distance and spawns in places abounding in seaweed, at a 
period later than the red mullet. The maenis spawns about the 
winter solstice. Of the others, such as are pelagic spawn for the 
most part in summer; which fact is proved by their not being 
caught by fishermen during this period. 

Of ordinary fishes the most prolific is the sprat; of cartilaginous 
fishes, the fishing-frog. Specimens, however, of the fishing-frog 
are rare from the facility with which the young are destroyed, as 
the female lays her spawn all in a lump close in to shore. As a 



1622 



rule, cartilaginous fish are less prolific than other fish owing to 
their being viviparous; and their young by reason of their size 
have a better chance of escaping destruction. 

The so-called needle-fish (or pipe-fish) is late in spawning, and 
the greater portion of them are burst asunder by the eggs before 
spawning; and the eggs are not so many in number as large in 
size. The young fish cluster round the parent like so many 
young spiders, for the fish spawns on to herself; and, if any one 
touch the young, they swim away. The atherine spawns by 
rubbing its belly against the sand. 

Tunny fish also burst asunder by reason of their fat. They live 
for two years; and the fishermen infer this age from the 
circumstance that once when there was a failure of the young 
tunny fish for a year there was a failure of the full-grown tunny 
the next summer. They are of opinion that the tunny is a fish a 
year older than the pelamyd. The tunny and the mackerel pair 
about the close of the month of Elaphebolion, and spawn about 
the commencement of the month of Hecatombaeon; they 
deposit their spawn in a sort of bag. The growth of the young 
tunny is rapid. After the females have spawned in the Euxine, 
there comes from the egg what some call scordylae, but what 
the Byzantines nickname the 'auxids' or 'growers', from their 
growing to a considerable size in a few days; these fish go out of 
the Pontus in autumn along with the young tunnies, and enter 
Pontus in the spring as pelamyds. Fishes as a rule take on 
growth with rapidity, but this is peculiarly the case with all 
species of fish found in the Pontus; the growth, for instance, of 
the amia-tunny is quite visible from day to day. 

To resume, we must bear in mind that the same fish in the 
same localities have not the same season for pairing, for 
conception, for parturition, or for favouring weather. The 
coracine, for instance, in some places spawns about wheat- 



1623 



harvest. The statements here given pretend only to give the 
results of general observation. 

The conger also spawns, but the fact is not equally obvious in 
all localities, nor is the spawn plainly visible owing to the fat of 
the fish; for the spawn is lanky in shape as it is with serpents. 
However, if it be put on the fire it shows its nature; for the fat 
evaporates and melts, while the eggs dance about and explode 
with a crack. Further, if you touch the substances and rub them 
with your fingers, the fat feels smooth and the egg rough. Some 
congers are provided with fat but not with any spawn, others 
are unprovided with fat but have egg-spawn as here described. 



18 

We have, then, treated pretty fully of the animals that fly in the 
air or swim in the water, and of such of those that walk on dry 
land as are oviparous, to wit of their pairing, conception, and 
the like phenomena; it now remains to treat of the same 
phenomena in connexion with viviparous land animals and 
with man. 

The statements made in regard to the pairing of the sexes apply 
partly to the particular kinds of animal and partly to all in 
general. It is common to all animals to be most excited by the 
desire of one sex for the other and by the pleasure derived from 
copulation. The female is most cross-tempered just after 
parturition, the male during the time of pairing; for instance, 
stallions at this period bite one another, throw their riders, and 
chase them. Wild boars, though usually enfeebled at this time 
as the result of copulation, are now unusually fierce, and fight 
with one another in an extraordinary way, clothing themselves 
with defensive armour, or in other words deliberately 



1624 



thickening their hide by rubbing against trees or by coating 
themselves repeatedly all over with mud and then drying 
themselves in the sun. They drive one another away from the 
swine pastures, and fight with such fury that very often both 
combatants succumb. The case is similar with bulls, rams, and 
he-goats; for, though at ordinary times they herd together, at 
breeding time they hold aloof from and quarrel with one 
another. The male camel also is cross-tempered at pairing time 
if either a man or a camel comes near him; as for a horse, a 
camel is ready to fight him at any time. It is the same with wild 
animals. The bear, the wolf, and the lion are all at this time 
ferocious towards such as come in their way, but the males of 
these animals are less given to fight with one another from the 
fact that they are at no time gregarious. The she-bear is fierce 
after cubbing, and the bitch after pupping. 

Male elephants get savage about pairing time, and for this 
reason it is stated that men who have charge of elephants in 
India never allow the males to have intercourse with the 
females; on the ground that the males go wild at this time and 
turn topsy-turvy the dwellings of their keepers, lightly 
constructed as they are, and commit all kinds of havoc. They 
also state that abundancy of food has a tendency to tame the 
males. They further introduce other elephants amongst the wild 
ones, and punish and break them in by setting on the new- 
comers to chastise the others. 

Animals that pair frequently and not at a single specific season, 
as for instance animals domesticated by man, such as swine 
and dogs, are found to indulge in such freaks to a lesser degree 
owing to the frequency of their sexual intercourse. 

Of female animals the mare is the most sexually wanton, and 
next in order comes the cow. In fact, the mare is said to go a- 
horsing; and the term derived from the habits of this one 



1625 



animal serves as a term of abuse applicable to such females of 
the human species as are unbridled in the way of sexual 
appetite. This is the common phenomenon as observed in the 
sow when she is said to go a-boaring. The mare is said also 
about this time to get wind-impregnated if not impregnated by 
the stallion, and for this reason in Crete they never remove the 
stallion from the mares; for when the mare gets into this 
condition she runs away from all other horses. The mares under 
these circumstances fly invariably either northwards or 
southwards, and never towards either east or west. When this 
complaint is on them they allow no one to approach, until 
either they are exhausted with fatigue or have reached the sea. 
Under either of these circumstances they discharge a certain 
substance 'hippomanes', the title given to a growth on a new- 
born foal; this resembles the sow-virus, and is in great request 
amongst women who deal in drugs and potions. About horsing 
time the mares huddle closer together, are continually 
switching their tails, their neigh is abnormal in sound, and from 
the sexual organ there flows a liquid resembling genital sperm, 
but much thinner than the sperm of the male. It is this 
substance that some call hippomanes, instead of the growth 
found on the foal; they say it is extremely difficult to get as it 
oozes out only in small drops at a time. Mares also, when in 
heat, discharge urine frequently, and frisk with one another. 
Such are the phenomena connected with the horse. 

Cows go a-bulling; and so completely are they under the 
influence of the sexual excitement that the herdsmen have no 
control over them and cannot catch hold of them in the fields. 
Mares and kine alike, when in heat, indicate the fact by the 
upraising of their genital organs, and by continually voiding 
urine. Further, kine mount the bulls, follow them about; and 
keep standing beside them. The younger females both with 
horses and oxen are the first to get in heat; and their sexual 
appetites are all the keener if the weather warm and their 



1626 



bodily condition be healthy. Mares, when dipt of their coat, 
have the sexual feeling checked, and assume a downcast 
drooping appearance. The stallion recognizes by the scent the 
mares that form his company, even though they have been 
together only a few days before breeding time: if they get mixed 
up with other mares, the stallion bites and drives away the 
interlopers. He feeds apart, accompanied by his own troop of 
mares. Each stallion has assigned to him about thirty mares or 
even somewhat more; when a strange stallion approaches, he 
huddles his mares into a close ring, runs round them, then 
advances to the encounter of the newcomer; if one of the mares 
make a movement, he bites her and drives her back. The bull in 
breeding time begins to graze with the cows, and fights with 
other bulls (having hitherto grazed with them), which is termed 
by graziers 'herd-spurning'. Often in Epirus a bull disappears for 
three months together. In a general way one may state that of 
male animals either none or few herd with their respective 
females before breeding time; but they keep separate after 
reaching maturity, and the two sexes feed apart. Sows, when 
they are moved by sexual desire, or are, as it is called, a-boaring, 
will attack even human beings. 

With bitches the same sexual condition is termed 'getting into 
heat'. The sexual organ rises at this time, and there is a 
moisture about the parts. Mares drip with a white liquid at this 
season. 

Female animals are subject to menstrual discharges, but never 
in such-abundance as is the female of the human species. With 
ewes and she-goats there are signs of menstruation in breeding 
time, just before the for submitting to the male; after copulation 
also the signs are manifest, and then cease for an interval until 
the period of parturition arrives; the process then supervenes, 
and it is by this supervention that the shepherd knows that 
such and such an ewe is about to bring forth. After parturition 



1627 



comes copious menstruation, not at first much tinged with 
blood, but deeply dyed with it by and by. With the cow, the she 
ass, and the mare, the discharge is more copious actually, owing 
to their greater bulk, but proportionally to the greater bulk it is 
far less copious. The cow, for instance, when in heat, exhibits a 
small discharge to the extent of a quarter of a pint of liquid or a 
little less; and the time when this discharge takes place is the 
best time for her to be covered by the bull. Of all quadrupeds the 
mare is the most easily delivered of its young, exhibits the least 
amount of discharge after parturition, and emits the least 
amount of blood; that is to say, of all animals in proportion to 
size. With kine and mares menstruation usually manifests itself 
at intervals of two, four, and six months; but, unless one be 
constantly attending to and thoroughly acquainted with such 
animals, it is difficult to verify the circumstance, and the result 
is that many people are under the belief that the process never 
takes place with these animals at all. 

With mules menstruation never takes place, but the urine of the 
female is thicker than the urine of the male. As a general rule 
the discharge from the bladder in the case of quadrupeds is 
thicker than it is in the human species, and this discharge with 
ewes and she-goats is thicker than with rams and he-goats; but 
the urine of the jackass is thicker than the urine of the she-ass, 
and the urine of the bull is more pungent than the urine of the 
cow. After parturition the urine of all quadrupeds becomes 
thicker, especially with such animals as exhibit comparatively 
slight discharges. At breeding time the milk become purulent, 
but after parturition it becomes wholesome. During pregnancy 
ewes and she-goats get fatter and eat more; as is also the case 
with cows, and, indeed, with the females of all quadrupeds. 

In general the sexual appetites of animals are keenest in spring- 
time; the time of pairing, however, is not the same for all, but is 



1628 



adapted so as to ensure the rearing of the young at a convenient 
season. 

Domesticated swine carry their young for four months, and 
bring forth a litter of twenty at the utmost; and, by the way, if 
the litter be exceedingly numerous they cannot rear all the 
young. As the sow grows old she continues to bear, but grows 
indifferent to the boar; she conceives after a single copulation, 
but they have to put the boar to her repeatedly owing to her 
dropping after intercourse what is called the sow-virus. This 
incident befalls all sows, but some of them discharge the genital 
sperm as well. During conception any one of the litter that gets 
injured or dwarfed is called an afterpig or scut: such injury may 
occur at any part of the womb. After littering the mother offers 
the foremost teat to the first-born. When the sow is in heat, she 
must not at once be put to the boar, but only after she lets her 
lugs drop, for otherwise she is apt to get into heat again; if she 
be put to the boar when in full condition of heat, one 
copulation, as has been said, is sufficient. It is as well to supply 
the boar at the period of copulation with barley, and the sow at 
the time of parturition with boiled barley. Some swine give fine 
litters only at the beginning, with others the litters improve as 
the mothers grow in age and size. It is said that a sow, if she 
have one of her eyes knocked out, is almost sure to die soon 
afterwards. Swine for the most part live for fifteen years, but 
some fall little short of the twenty. 



19 

Ewes conceive after three or four copulations with the ram. If 
rain falls after intercourse, the ram impregnates the ewe again; 
and it is the same with the she-goat. The ewe bears usually two 



1629 



lambs, sometimes three or four. Both ewe and she-goat carry 
their young for five months; consequently wherever a district is 
sunny and the animals are used to comfort and well fed, they 
bear twice in the year. The goat lives for eight years and the 
sheep for ten, but in most cases not so long; the bell-wether, 
however, lives to fifteen years. In every flock they train one of 
the rams for bell-wether. When he is called on by name by the 
shepherd, he takes the lead of the flock: and to this duty the 
creature is trained from its earliest years. Sheep in Ethiopia live 
for twelve or thirteen years, goats for ten or eleven. In the case 
of the sheep and the goat the two sexes have intercourse all 
their lives long. 

Twins with sheep and goats may be due to richness of 
pasturage, or to the fact that either the ram or the he-goat is a 
twin-begetter or that the ewe or the she-goat is a twin-bearer. 
Of these animals some give birth to males and others to 
females; and the difference in this respect depends on the 
waters they drink and also on the sires. And if they submit to 
the male when north winds are blowing, they are apt to bear 
males; if when south winds are blowing, females. Such as bear 
females may get to bear males, due regard being paid to their 
looking northwards when put to the male. Ewes accustomed to 
be put to the ram early will refuse him if he attempt to mount 
them late. Lambs are born white and black according as white 
or black veins are under the ram's tongue; the lambs are white 
if the veins are white, and black if the veins are black, and white 
and black if the veins are white and black; and red if the veins 
are red. The females that drink salted waters are the first to take 
the male; the water should be salted before and after 
parturition, and again in the springtime. With goats the 
shepherds appoint no bell-wether, as the animal is not capable 
of repose but frisky and apt to ramble. If at the appointed 
season the elders of the flock are eager for intercourse, the 



1630 



shepherds say that it bodes well for the flock; if the younger 
ones, that the flock is going to be bad. 



20 

Of dogs there are several breeds. Of these the Laconian hound of 
either sex is fit for breeding purposes when eight months old: at 
about the same age some dogs lift the leg when voiding urine. 
The bitch conceives with one lining; this is clearly seen in the 
case where a dog contrives to line a bitch by stealth, as they 
impregnate after mounting only once. The Laconian bitch 
carries her young the sixth part of a year or sixty days: or more 
by one, two, or three, or less by one; the pups are blind for 
twelve days after birth. After pupping, the bitch gets in heat 
again in six months, but not before. Some bitches carry their 
young for the fifth part of the year or for seventy-two days; and 
their pups are blind for fourteen days. Other bitches carry their 
young for a quarter of a year or for three whole months; and the 
whelps of these are blind for seventeen days. The bitch appears 
go in heat for the same length of time. Menstruation continues 
for seven days, and a swelling of the genital organ occurs 
simultaneously; it is not during this period that the bitch is 
disposed to submit to the dog, but in the seven days that follow. 
The bitch as a rule goes in heat for fourteen days, but 
occasionally for sixteen. The birth-discharge occurs 
simultaneously with the delivery of the whelps, and the 
substance of it is thick and mucous. (The falling-off in bulk on 
the part of the mother is not so great as might have been 
inferred from the size of her frame.) The bitch is usually 
supplied with milk five days before parturition; some seven 
days previously, some four; and the milk is serviceable 
immediately after birth. The Laconian bitch is supplied with 



1631 



milk thirty days after lining. The milk at first is thickish, but 
gets thinner by degrees; with the bitch the milk is thicker than 
with the female of any other animal excepting the sow and the 
hare. When the bitch arrives at full growth an indication is given 
of her capacity for the male; that is to say, just as occurs in the 
female of the human species, a swelling takes place in the teats 
of the breasts, and the breasts take on gristle. This incident, 
however, it is difficult for any but an expert to detect, as the part 
that gives the indication is inconsiderable. The preceding 
statements relate to the female, and not one of them to the 
male. The male as a rule lifts his leg to void urine when six 
months old; some at a later period, when eight months old, 
some before they reach six months. In a general way one may 
put it that they do so when they are out of puppyhood. The 
bitch squats down when she voids urine; it is a rare exception 
that she lifts the leg to do so. The bitch bears twelve pups at the 
most, but usually five or six; occasionally a bitch will bear one 
only. The bitch of the Laconian breed generally bears eight. The 
two sexes have intercourse with each other at all periods of life. 
A very remarkable phenomenon is observed in the case of the 
Laconian hound: in other words, he is found to be more 
vigorous in commerce with the female after being hard-worked 
than when allowed to live idle. 

The dog of the Laconian breed lives ten years, and the bitch 
twelve. The bitch of other breeds usually lives for fourteen or 
fifteen years, but some live to twenty; and for this reason 
certain critics consider that Homer did well in representing the 
dog of Ulysses as having died in his twentieth year. With the 
Laconian hound, owing to the hardships to which the male is 
put, he is less long-lived than the female; with other breeds the 
distinction as to longevity is not very apparent, though as a 
general rule the male is the longer-lived. 



1632 



The dog sheds no teeth except the so-called 'canines'; these a 
dog of either sex sheds when four months old. As they shed 
these only, many people are in doubt as to the fact, and some 
people, owing to their shedding but two and its being hard to hit 
upon the time when they do so, fancy that the animal sheds no 
teeth at all; others, after observing the shedding of two, come to 
the conclusion that the creature sheds the rest in due turn. Men 
discern the age of a dog by inspection of its teeth; with young 
dogs the teeth are white and sharp pointed, with old dogs black 
and blunted. 



21 

The bull impregnates the cow at a single mount, and mounts 
with such vigour as to weigh down the cow; if his effort be 
unsuccessful, the cow must be allowed an interval of twenty 
days before being again submitted. Bulls of mature age decline 
to mount the same cow several times on one day, except, by the 
way, at considerable intervals. Young bulls by reason of their 
vigour are enabled to mount the same cow several times in one 
day, and a good many cows besides. The bull is the least 
salacious of male animals.... The victor among the bulls is the 
one that mounts the females; when he gets exhausted by his 
amorous efforts, his beaten antagonist sets on him and very 
often gets the better of the conflict. The bull and the cow are 
about a year old when it is possible for them to have commerce 
with chance of offspring: as a rule, however, they are about 
twenty months old, but it is universally allowed that they are 
capable in this respect at the age of two years. The cow goes 
with calf for nine months, and she calves in the tenth month; 
some maintain that they go in calf for ten months, to the very 
day. A calf delivered before the times here specified is an 



1633 



abortion and never lives, however little premature its birth may 
have been, as its hooves are weak and imperfect. The cow as a 
rule bears but one calf, very seldom two; she submits to the bull 
and bears as long as she lives. 

Cows live for about fifteen years, and the bulls too, if they have 
been castrated; but some live for twenty years or even more, if 
their bodily constitutions be sound. The herdsmen tame the 
castrated bulls, and give them an office in the herd analogous to 
the office of the bell-wether in a flock; and these bulls live to an 
exceptionally advanced age, owing to their exemption from 
hardship and to their browsing on pasture of good quality. The 
bull is in fullest vigour when five years old, which leads the 
critics to commend Homer for applying to the bull the epithets 
of 'five-year-old', or 'of nine seasons', which epithets are alike in 
meaning. The ox sheds his teeth at the age of two years, not all 
together but just as the horse sheds his. When the animal 
suffers from podagra it does not shed the hoof, but is subject to 
a painful swelling in the feet. The milk of the cow is serviceable 
after parturition, and before parturition there is no milk at all. 
The milk that first presents itself becomes as hard as stone 
when it clots; this result ensues unless it be previously diluted 
with water. Oxen younger than a year old do not copulate 
unless under circumstances of an unnatural and portentous 
kind: instances have been recorded of copulation in both sexes 
at the age of four months. Kine in general begin to submit to the 
male about the month of Thargelion or of Scirophorion; some, 
however, are capable of conception right on to the autumn. 
When kine in large numbers receive the bull and conceive, it is 
looked upon as prognostic of rain and stormy weather. Kine 
herd together like mares, but in lesser degree. 



1634 



22 

In the case of horses, the stallion and the mare are first fitted 
for breeding purposes when two years old. Instances, however, 
of such early maturity are rare, and their young are 
exceptionally small and weak; the ordinary age for sexual 
maturity is three years, and from that age to twenty the two 
sexes go on improving in the quality of their offspring. The mare 
carries her foal for eleven months, and casts it in the twelfth. It 
is not a fixed number of days that the stallion takes to 
impregnate the mare; it may be one, two, three, or more. An ass 
in covering will impregnate more expeditiously than a stallion. 
The act of intercourse with horses is not laborious as it is with 
oxen. In both sexes the horse is the most salacious of animals 
next after the human species. The breeding faculties of the 
younger horses may be stimulated beyond their years if they be 
supplied with good feeding in abundance. The mare as a rule 
bears only one foal; occasionally she has two, but never more. A 
mare has been known to cast two mules; but such a 
circumstance was regarded as unnatural and portentous. 

The horse then is first fitted for breeding purposes at the age of 
two and a half years, but achieves full sexual maturity when it 
has ceased to shed teeth, except it be naturally infertile; it must 
be added, however, that some horses have been known to 
impregnate the mare while the teeth were in process of 
shedding. 

The horse has forty teeth. It sheds its first set of four, two from 
the upper jaw and two from the lower, when two and a half 
years old. After a year's interval, it sheds another set of four in 
like manner, and another set of four after yet another year's 
interval; after arriving at the age of four years and six months it 
sheds no more. An instance has occurred where a horse shed all 
his teeth at once, and another instance of a horse shedding all 



1635 



his teeth with his last set of four; but such instances are very 
rare. It consequently happens that a horse when four and a half 
years old is in excellent condition for breeding purposes. 

The older horses, whether of the male or female, are the more 
generatively productive. Horses will cover mares from which 
they have been foaled and mares which they have begotten; 
and, indeed, a troop of horses is only considered perfect when 
such promiscuity of intercourse occurs. Scythians use pregnant 
mares for riding when the embryo has turned rather soon in the 
womb, and they assert that thereby the mothers have all the 
easier delivery. Quadrupeds as a rule lie down for parturition, 
and in consequence the young of them all come out of the 
womb sideways. The mare, however, when the time for 
parturition arrives, stands erect and in that posture casts its 
foal. 

The horse in general lives for eighteen or twenty years; some 
horses live for twenty-five or even thirty, and if a horse be 
treated with extreme care, it may last on to the age of fifty 
years; a horse, however, when it reaches thirty years is regarded 
as exceptionally old. The mare lives usually for twenty-five 
years, though instances have occurred of their attaining the age 
of forty. The male is less long-lived than the female by reason of 
the sexual service he is called on to render; and horses that are 
reared in a private stable live longer than such as are reared in 
troops. The mare attains her full length and height at five years 
old, the stallion at six; in another six years the animal reaches 
its full bulk, and goes on improving until it is twenty years old. 
The female, then, reaches maturity more rapidly than the male, 
but in the womb the case is reversed, just as is observed in 
regard to the sexes of the human species; and the same 
phenomenon is observed in the case of all animals that bear 
several young. 



1636 



The mare is said to suckle a mule-foal for six months, but not to 
allow its approach for any longer on account of the pain it is put 
to by the hard tugging of the young; an ordinary foal it allows to 
suck for a longer period. 

Horse and mule are at their best after the shedding of the teeth. 
After they have shed them all, it is not easy to distinguish their 
age; hence they are said to carry their mark before the 
shedding, but not after. However, even after the shedding their 
age is pretty well recognized by the aid of the canines; for in the 
case of horses much ridden these teeth are worn away by 
attrition caused by the insertion of the bit; in the case of horses 
not ridden the teeth are large and detached, and in young 
horses they are sharp and small. 

The male of the horse will breed at all seasons and during its 
whole life; the mare can take the horse all its life long, but is not 
thus ready to pair at all seasons unless it be held in check by a 
halter or some other compulsion be brought to bear. There is no 
fixed time at which intercourse of the two sexes cannot take 
place; and accordingly intercourse may chance to take place at 
a time that may render difficult the rearing of the future 
progeny. In a stable in Opus there was a stallion that used to 
serve mares when forty years old: his fore legs had to be lifted 
up for the operation. 

Mares first take the horse in the spring-time. After a mare has 
foaled she does not get impregnated at once again, but only 
after a considerable interval; in fact, the foals will be all the 
better if the interval extend over four or five years. It is, at all 
events, absolutely necessary to allow an interval of one year, 
and for that period to let her lie fallow. A mare, then, breeds at 
intervals; a she-ass breeds on and on without intermission. Of 
mares some are absolutely sterile, others are capable of 
conception but incapable of bringing the foal to full term; it is 



1637 



said to be an indication of this condition in a mare, that her foal 
if dissected is found to have other kidney-shaped substances 
round about its kidneys, presenting the appearance of having 
four kidneys. 

After parturition the mare at once swallows the after-birth, and 
bites off the growth, called the 'hippomanes', that is found on 
the forehead of the foal. This growth is somewhat smaller than 
a dried fig; and in shape is broad and round, and in colour black. 
If any bystander gets possession of it before the mare, and the 
mare gets a smell of it, she goes wild and frantic at the smell. 
And it is for this reason that venders of drugs and simples hold 
the substance in high request and include it among their stores. 

If an ass cover a mare after the mare has been covered by a 
horse, the ass will destroy the previously formed embryo. 

(Horse-trainers do not appoint a horse as leader to a troop, as 
herdsmen appoint a bull as leader to a herd, and for this reason 
that the horse is not steady but quick-tempered and skittish.) 



23 

The ass of both sexes is capable of breeding, and sheds its first 
teeth at the age of two and a half years; it sheds its second teeth 
within six months, its third within another six months, and the 
fourth after the like interval. These fourth teeth are termed the 
gnomons or age-indicators. 

A she-ass has been known to conceive when a year old, and the 
foal to be reared. After intercourse with the male it will 
discharge the genital sperm unless it be hindered, and for this 
reason it is usually beaten after such intercourse and chased 



1638 



about. It casts its young in the twelfth month. It usually bears 
but one foal, and that is its natural number, occasionally 
however it bears twins. The ass if it cover a mare destroys, as 
has been said, the embryo previously begotten by the horse; but, 
after the mare has been covered by the ass, the horse 
supervening will not spoil the embryo. The she-ass has milk in 
the tenth month of pregnancy. Seven days after casting a foal 
the she-ass submits to the male, and is almost sure to conceive 
if put to the male on this particular day; the same result, 
however, is quite possible later on. The she-ass will refuse to 
cast her foal with any one looking on or in the daylight and just 
before foaling she has to be led away into a dark place. If the 
she-ass has had young before the shedding of the index-teeth, 
she will bear all her life through; but if not, then she will neither 
conceive nor bear for the rest of her days. The ass lives for more 
than thirty years, and the she-ass lives longer than the male. 

When there is a cross between a horse and a she-ass or a 
jackass and a mare, there is much greater chance of a 
miscarriage than where the commerce is normal. The period for 
gestation in the case of a cross depends on the male, and is just 
what it would have been if the male had had commerce with a 
female of his own kind. In regard to size, looks, and vigour, the 
foal is more apt to resemble the mother than the sire. If such 
hybrid connexions be continued without intermittence, the 
female will soon go sterile; and for this reason trainers always 
allow of intervals between breeding times. A mare will not take 
the ass, nor a she ass the horse, unless the ass or she-ass shall 
have been suckled by a mare; and for this reason trainers put 
foals of the she-ass under mares, which foals are technically 
spoken of as 'mare-suckled'. These asses, thus reared, mount 
the mares in the open pastures, mastering them by force as the 
stallions do. 



1639 



24 

A mule is fitted for commerce with the female after the first 
shedding of its teeth, and at the age of seven will impregnate 
effectually; and where connexion has taken place with a mare, 
a 'hinny' has been known to be produced. After the seventh year 
it has no further intercourse with the female. A female mule 
has been known to be impregnated, but without the 
impregnation being followed up by parturition. In Syrophoenicia 
she-mules submit to the mule and bear young; but the breed, 
though it resembles the ordinary one, is different and specific. 
The hinny or stunted mule is foaled by a mare when she has 
gone sick during gestation, and corresponds to the dwarf in the 
human species and to the after-pig or scut in swine; and as is 
the case with dwarfs, the sexual organ of the hinny is 
abnormally large. 

The mule lives for a number of years. There are on record cases 
of mules living to the age of eighty, as did one in Athens at the 
time of the building of the temple; this mule on account of its 
age was let go free, but continued to assist in dragging burdens, 
and would go side by side with the other draught-beasts and 
stimulate them to their work; and in consequence a public 
decree was passed forbidding any baker driving the creature 
away from his bread-tray. The she-mule grows old more slowly 
than the mule. Some assert that the she-mule menstruates by 
the act of voiding her urine, and that the mule owes the 
prematurity of his decay to his habit of smelling at the urine. So 
much for the modes of generation in connexion with these 
animals. 



1640 



25 

Breeders and trainers can distinguish between young and old 
quadrupeds. If, when drawn back from the jaw, the skin at once 
goes back to its place, the animal is young; if it remains long 
wrinkled up, the animal is old. 



26 

The camel carries its young for ten months, and bears but one 
at a time and never more; the young camel is removed from the 
mother when a year old. The animal lives for a long period, 
more than fifty years. It bears in spring-time, and gives milk 
until the time of the next conception. Its flesh and milk are 
exceptionally palatable. The milk is drunk mixed with water in 
the proportion of either two to one or three to one. 



27 

The elephant of either sex is fitted for breeding before reaching 
the age of twenty. The female carries her young, according to 
some accounts, for two and a half years; according to others, for 
three years; and the discrepancy in the assigned periods is due 
to the fact that there are never human eyewitnesses to the 
commerce between the sexes. The female settles down on its 
rear to cast its young, and obviously suffers greatly during the 
process. The young one, immediately after birth, sucks the 
mother, not with its trunk but with the mouth; and can walk 
about and see distinctly the moment it is born. 



1641 



28 

The wild sow submits to the boar at the beginning of winter, 
and in the spring-time retreats for parturition to a lair in some 
district inaccessible to intrusion, hemmed in with sheer cliffs 
and chasms and overshadowed by trees. The boar usually 
remains by the sow for thirty days. The number of the litter and 
the period gestation is the same as in the case of the 
domesticated congener. The sound of the grunt also is similar; 
only that the sow grunts continually, and the boar but seldom. 
Of the wild boars such as are castrated grow to the largest size 
and become fiercest: to which circumstance Homer alludes 
when he says: 

'He reared against him a wild castrated boar: it was not like a 
food-devouring brute, but like a forest-clad promontory.' 

Wild boars become castrated owing to an itch befalling them in 
early life in the region of the testicles, and the castration is 
superinduced by their rubbing themselves against the trunks of 
trees. 



29 

The hind, as has been stated, submits to the stag as a rule only 
under compulsion, as she is unable to endure the male often 
owing to the rigidity of the penis. However, they do occasionally 
submit to the stag as the ewe submits ram; and when they are 
in heat the hinds avoid one another. The stag is not constant to 
one particular hind, but after a while quits one and mates with 



1642 



others. The breeding time is after the rising of Arcturus, during 
the months of Boedromion and Maimacterion. The period of 
gestation lasts for eight months. Conception comes on a few 
days after intercourse; and a number of hinds can be 
impregnated by a single male. The hind, as a rule, bears but one 
fawn, although instances have been known of her casting two. 
Out of dread of wild beasts she casts her young by the side of 
the high-road. The young fawn grows with rapidity. 
Menstruation occurs at no other time with the hind; it takes 
place only after parturition, and the substance is phlegm-like. 

The hind leads the fawn to her lair; this is her place of refuge, a 
cave with a single inlet, inside which she shelters herself 
against attack. 

Fabulous stories are told concerning the longevity of the animal, 
but the stories have never been verified, and the brevity of the 
period of gestation and the rapidity of growth in the fawn would 
not lead one to attribute extreme longevity to this creature. 

In the mountain called Elaphoeis or Deer Mountain, which is in 
Arginussa in Asia Minor - the place, by the way, where 
Alcibiades was assassinated - all the hinds have the ear split, so 
that, if they stray to a distance, they can be recognized by this 
mark; and the embryo actually has the mark while yet in the 
womb of the mother. 

The hind has four teats like the cow. After the hinds have 
become pregnant, the males all segregate one by one, and in 
consequence of the violence of their sexual passions they keep 
each one to himself, dig a hole in the ground, and bellow from 
time to time; in all these particulars they resemble the goat, and 
their foreheads from getting wetted become black, as is also the 
case with the goat. In this way they pass the time until the rain 
falls, after which time they turn to pasture. The animal acts in 
this way owing to its sexual wantonness and also to its obesity; 



1643 



for in summer-time it becomes so exceptionally fat as to be 
unable to run: in fact at this period they can be overtaken by the 
hunters that pursue them on foot in the second or third run; 
and, by the way, in consequence of the heat of the weather and 
their getting out of breath they always make for water in their 
runs. In the rutting season, the flesh of the deer is unsavoury 
and rank, like the flesh of the he-goat. In winter-time the deer 
becomes thin and weak, but towards the approach of the spring 
he is at his best for running. When on the run the deer keeps 
pausing from time to time, and waits until his pursuer draws 
upon him, whereupon he starts off again. This habit appears 
due to some internal pain: at all events, the gut is so slender 
and weak that, if you strike the animal ever so softly, it is apt to 
break asunder, though the hide of the animal remains sound 
and uninjured. 



30 

Bears, as has been previously stated, do not copulate with the 
male mounting the back of the female, but with the female 
lying down under the male. The she-bear goes with young for 
thirty days. She brings forth sometimes one cub, sometimes two 
cubs, and at most five. Of all animals the newly born cub of the 
she bear is the smallest in proportion to the size of the mother; 
that is to say, it is larger than a mouse but smaller than a 
weasel. It is also smooth and blind, and its legs and most of its 
organs are as yet inarticulate. Pairing takes Place in the month 
of Elaphebolion, and parturition about the time for retiring into 
winter quarters; about this time the bear and the she-bear are 
at the fattest. After the she-bear has reared her young, she 
comes out of her winter lair in the third month, when it is 
already spring. The female porcupine, by the way, hibernates 



1644 



and goes with young the same number of days as the she-bear, 
and in all respects as to parturition resembles this animal. 
When a she-bear is with young, it is a very hard task to catch 
her. 



31 

It has already been stated that the lion and lioness copulate 
rearwards, and that these animals are opisthuretic. They do not 
copulate nor bring forth at all seasons indiscriminately, but 
once in the year only. The lioness brings forth in the spring, 
generally two cubs at a time, and six at the very most; but 
sometimes only one. The story about the lioness discharging her 
womb in the act of parturition is a pure fable, and was merely 
invented to account for the scarcity of the animal; for the 
animal is, as is well known, a rare animal, and is not found in 
many countries. In fact, in the whole of Europe it is only found 
in the strip between the rivers Achelous and Nessus. The cubs of 
the lioness when newly born are exceedingly small, and can 
scarcely walk when two months old. The Syrian lion bears cubs 
five times: five cubs at the first litter, then four, then three, then 
two, and lastly one; after this the lioness ceases to bear for the 
rest of her days. The lioness has no mane, but this appendage is 
peculiar to the lion. The lion sheds only the four so-called 
canines, two in the upper jaw and two in the lower; and it sheds 
them when it is six months old. 



1645 



32 

The hyena in colour resembles the wolf, but is more shaggy, and 
is furnished with a mane running all along the spine. What is 
recounted concerning its genital organs, to the effect that every 
hyena is furnished with the organ both of the male and the 
female, is untrue. The fact is that the sexual organ of the male 
hyena resembles the same organ in the wolf and in the dog; the 
part resembling the female genital organ lies underneath the 
tail, and does to some extent resemble the female organ, but it 
is unprovided with duct or passage, and the passage for the 
residuum comes underneath it. The female hyena has the part 
that resembles the organ of the male, and, as in the case of the 
male, has it underneath her tail, unprovided with duct or 
passage; and after it the passage for the residuum, and 
underneath this the true female genital organ. The female 
hyena has a womb, like all other female animals of the same 
kind. It is an exceedingly rare circumstance to meet with a 
female hyena. At least a hunter said that out of eleven hyenas 
he had caught, only one was a female. 



33 

Hares copulate in a rearward posture, as has been stated, for the 
animal is opisthuretic. They breed and bear at all seasons, 
superfoetate during pregnancy, and bear young every month. 
They do not give birth to their young ones all together at one 
time, but bring them forth at intervals over as many days as the 
circumstances of each case may require. The female is supplied 
with milk before parturition; and after bearing submits 
immediately to the male, and is capable of conception while 
suckling her young. The milk in consistency resembles sow's 



1646 



milk. The young are born blind, as is the case with the greater 
part Of the fissipeds or toed animals. 



34 

The fox mounts the vixen in copulation, and the vixen bears 
young like the she-bear; in fact, her young ones are even more 
inarticulately formed. Before parturition she retires to 
sequestered places, so that it is a great rarity for a vixen to be 
caught while pregnant. After parturition she warms her young 
and gets them into shape by licking them. She bears four at 
most at a birth. 



35 

The wolf resembles the dog in regard to the time of conception 
and parturition, the number of the litter, and the blindness of 
the newborn young. The sexes couple at one special period, and 
the female brings forth at the beginning of the summer. There is 
an account given of the parturition of the she-wolf that borders 
on the fabulous, to the effect that she confines her lying-in to 
within twelve particular days of the year. And they give the 
reason for this in the form of a myth, viz. that when they 
transported Leto in so many days from the land of the 
Hyperboreans to the island of Delos, she assumed the form of a 
she-wolf to escape the anger of Here. Whether the account be 
correct or not has not yet been verified; I give it merely as it is 
currently told. There is no more of truth in the current 



1647 



statement that the she-wolf bears once and only once in her 
lifetime. 

The cat and the ichneumon bear as many young as the dog, and 
live on the same food; they live about six years. The cubs of the 
panther are born blind like those of the wolf, and the female 
bears four at the most at one birth. The particulars of 
conception are the same for the thos, or civet, as for the dog; the 
cubs of the animal are born blind, and the female bears two, or 
three, or four at a birth. It is long in the body and low in stature; 
but not withstanding the shortness of its legs it is exceptionally 
fleet of foot, owing to the suppleness of its frame and its 
capacity for leaping. 



36 

There is found in Syria a so-called mule. It is not the same as 
the cross between the horse and ass, but resembles it just as a 
wild ass resembles the domesticated congener, and derives its 
name from the resemblance. Like the wild ass, this wild mule is 
remarkable for its speed. The animals of this species interbreed 
with one another; and a proof of this statement may be 
gathered from the fact that a certain number of them were 
brought into Phrygia in the time of Pharnaces, the father of 
Pharnabazus, and the animal is there still. The number 
originally introduced was nine, and there are three there at the 
present day. 



1648 



37 

The phenomena of generation in regard to the mouse are the 
most astonishing both for the number of the young and for the 
rapidity of recurrence in the births. On one occasion a she- 
mouse in a state of pregnancy was shut up by accident in a jar 
containing millet-seed, and after a little while the lid of the jar 
was removed and upwards of one hundred and twenty mice 
were found inside it. 

The rate of propagation of field mice in country places, and the 
destruction that they cause, are beyond all telling. In many 
places their number is so incalculable that but very little of the 
corn-crop is left to the farmer; and so rapid is their mode of 
proceeding that sometimes a small farmer will one day observe 
that it is time for reaping, and on the following morning, when 
he takes his reapers afield, he finds his entire crop devoured. 
Their disappearance is unaccountable: in a few days not a 
mouse will there be to be seen. And yet in the time before these 
few days men fail to keep down their numbers by fumigating 
and unearthing them, or by regularly hunting them and turning 
in swine upon them; for pigs, by the way, turn up the mouse- 
holes by rooting with their snouts. Foxes also hunt them, and 
the wild ferrets in particular destroy them, but they make no 
way against the prolific qualities of the animal and the rapidity 
of its breeding. When they are super-abundant, nothing 
succeeds in thinning them down except the rain; but after 
heavy rains they disappear rapidly. 

In a certain district of Persia when a female mouse is dissected 
the female embryos appear to be pregnant. Some people assert, 
and positively assert, that a female mouse by licking salt can 
become pregnant without the intervention of the male. 

Mice in Egypt are covered with bristles like the hedgehog. There 
is also a different breed of mice that walk on their two hind- 



1649 



legs; their front legs are small and their hind-legs long; the 
breed is exceedingly numerous. There are many other breeds of 
mice than are here referred to. 



Book VII 



As to Man's growth, first within his mother's womb and 
afterward to old age, the course of nature, in so far as man is 
specially concerned, is after the following manner. And, by the 
way, the difference of male and female and of their respective 
organs has been dealt with heretofore. When twice seven years 
old, in the most of cases, the male begins to engender seed; and 
at the same time hair appears upon the pubes, in like manner, 
so Alcmaeon of Croton remarks, as plants first blossom and 
then seed. About the same time, the voice begins to alter, 
getting harsher and more uneven, neither shrill as formerly nor 
deep as afterward, nor yet of any even tone, but like an 
instrument whose strings are frayed and out of tune; and it is 
called, by way of by-word, the bleat of the billy-goat. Now this 
breaking of the voice is the more apparent in those who are 
making trial of their sexual powers; for in those who are prone 
to lustfulness the voice turns into the voice of a man, but not so 
in the continent. For if a lad strive diligently to hinder his voice 
from breaking, as some do of those who devote themselves to 
music, the voice lasts a long while unbroken and may even 



1650 



persist with little change. And the breasts swell and likewise the 
private parts, altering in size and shape. (And by the way, at this 
time of life those who try by friction to provoke emission of 
seed are apt to experience pain as well as voluptuous 
sensations.) At the same age in the female, the breasts swell 
and the so-called catamenia commence to flow; and this fluid 
resembles fresh blood. There is another discharge, a white one, 
by the way, which occurs in girls even at a very early age, more 
especially if their diet be largely of a fluid nature; and this 
malady causes arrest of growth and loss of flesh. In the majority 
of cases the catamenia are noticed by the time the breasts have 
grown to the height of two fingers' breadth. In girls, too, about 
this time the voice changes to a deeper note; for while in 
general the woman's voice is higher than the man's, so also the 
voices of girls are pitched in a higher key than the elder 
women's, just as the boy's are higher than the men's; and the 
girls' voices are shriller than the boys', and a maid's flute is 
tuned sharper than a lad's. 

Girls of this age have much need of surveillance. For then in 
particular they feel a natural impulse to make usage of the 
sexual faculties that are developing in them; so that unless they 
guard against any further impulse beyond that inevitable one 
which their bodily development of itself supplies, even in the 
case of those who abstain altogether from passionate 
indulgence, they contract habits which are apt to continue into 
later life. For girls who give way to wantonness grow more and 
more wanton; and the same is true of boys, unless they be 
safeguarded from one temptation and another; for the passages 
become dilated and set up a local flux or running, and besides 
this the recollection of pleasure associated with former 
indulgence creates a longing for its repetition. 

Some men are congenitally impotent owing to structural defect; 
and in like manner women also may suffer from congenital 



1651 



incapacity. Both men and women are liable to constitutional 
change, growing healthier or more sickly, or altering in the way 
of leanness, stoutness, and vigour; thus, after puberty some lads 
who were thin before grow stout and healthy, and the converse 
also happens; and the same is equally true of girls. For when in 
boy or girl the body is loaded with superfluous matter, then, 
when such superfluities are got rid of in the spermatic or 
catamenial discharge, their bodies improve in health and 
condition owing to the removal of what had acted as an 
impediment to health and proper nutrition; but in such as are of 
opposite habit their bodies become emaciated and out of 
health, for then the spermatic discharge in the one case and the 
catamenial flow in the other take place at the cost of natural 
healthy conditions. 

Furthermore, in the case of maidens the condition of the 
breasts is diverse in different individuals, for they are 
sometimes quite big and sometimes little; and as a general rule 
their size depends on whether or not the body was burthened in 
childhood with superfluous material. For when the signs of 
womanhood are nigh but not come, the more there be of 
moisture the more will it cause the breasts to swell, even to the 
bursting point; and the result is that the breasts remain during 
after-life of the bulk that they then acquired. And among men, 
the breasts grow more conspicuous and more like to those of 
women, both in young men and old, when the individual 
temperament is moist and sleek and the reverse of sinewy, and 
all the more among the dark-complexioned than the fair. 

At the outset and till the age of one and twenty the spermatic 
discharge is devoid of fecundity; afterwards it becomes fertile, 
but young men and women produce undersized and imperfect 
progeny, as is the case also with the common run of animals. 
Young women conceive readily, but, having conceived, their 
labour in childbed is apt to be difficult. 



1652 



The frame fails of reaching its full development and ages 
quickly in men of intemperate lusts and in women who become 
mothers of many children; for it appears to be the case that 
growth ceases when the woman has given birth to three 
children. Women of a lascivious disposition grow more sedate 
and virtuous after they have borne several children. 

After the age of twenty-one women are fully ripe for child- 
bearing, but men go on increasing in vigour. When the 
spermatic fluid is of a thin consistency it is infertile; when 
granular it is fertile and likely to produce male children, but 
when thin and unclotted it is apt to produce female offspring. 
And it is about this time of life that in men the beard makes its 
appearance. 



The onset of the catamenia in women takes place towards the 
end of the month; and on this account the wiseacres assert that 
the moon is feminine, because the discharge in women and the 
waning of the moon happen at one and the same time, and 
after the wane and the discharge both one and the other grow 
whole again. (In some women the catamenia occur regularly but 
sparsely every month, and more abundantly every third month.) 
With those in whom the ailment lasts but a little while, two 
days or three, recovery is easy; but where the duration is longer, 
the ailment is more troublesome. For women are ailing during 
these days; and sometimes the discharge is sudden and 
sometimes gradual, but in all cases alike there is bodily distress 
until the attack be over. In many cases at the commencement of 
the attack, when the discharge is about to appear, there occur 



1653 



spasms and rumbling noises within the womb until such time 
as the discharge manifests itself. 

Under natural conditions it is after recovery from these 
symptoms that conception takes place in women, and women 
in whom the signs do not manifest themselves for the most 
part remain childless. But the rule is not without exception, for 
some conceive in spite of the absence of these symptoms; and 
these are cases in which a secretion accumulates, not in such a 
way as actually to issue forth, but in amount equal to the 
residuum left in the case of child-bearing women after the 
normal discharge has taken place. And some conceive while the 
signs are on but not afterwards, those namely in whom the 
womb closes up immediately after the discharge. In some cases 
the menses persist during pregnancy up to the very last; but the 
result in these cases is that the offspring are poor, and either 
fail to survive or grow up weakly. 

In many cases, owing to excessive desire, arising either from 
youthful impetuosity or from lengthened abstinence, prolapsion 
of the womb takes place and the catamenia appear repeatedly, 
thrice in the month, until conception occurs; and then the 
womb withdraws upwards again to its proper place... 

As we have remarked above, the discharge is wont to be more 
abundant in women than in the females of any other animals. 
In creatures that do not bring forth their young alive nothing of 
the sort manifests itself, this particular superfluity being 
converted into bodily substance; and by the way, in such 
animals the females are sometimes larger than the males; and 
moreover, the material is used up sometimes for scutes and 
sometimes for scales, and sometimes for the abundant covering 
of feathers, whereas in the vivipara possessed of limbs it is 
turned into hair and into bodily substance (for man alone 
among them is smooth-skinned), and into urine, for this 



1654 



excretion is in the majority of such animals thick and copious. 
Only in the case of women is the superfluity turned into a 
discharge instead of being utilized in these other ways. 

There is something similar to be remarked of men: for in 
proportion to his size man emits more seminal fluid than any 
other animal (for which reason man is the smoothest of 
animals), especially such men as are of a moist habit and not 
over corpulent, and fair men in greater degree than dark. It is 
likewise with women; for in the stout, great part of the 
excretion goes to nourish the body. In the act of intercourse, 
women of a fair complexion discharge a more plentiful 
secretion than the dark; and furthermore, a watery and pungent 
diet conduces to this phenomenon. 



It is a sign of conception in women when the place is dry 
immediately after intercourse. If the lips of the orifice be 
smooth conception is difficult, for the matter slips off; and if 
they be thick it is also difficult. But if on digital examination the 
lips feel somewhat rough and adherent, and if they be likewise 
thin, then the chances are in favour of conception. Accordingly, 
if conception be desired, we must bring the parts into such a 
condition as we have just described; but if on the contrary we 
want to avoid conception then we must bring about a contrary 
disposition. Wherefore, since if the parts be smooth conception 
is prevented, some anoint that part of the womb on which the 
seed falls with oil of cedar, or with ointment of lead or with 
frankincense, commingled with olive oil. If the seed remain 
within for seven days then it is certain that conception has 



1655 



taken place; for it is during that period that what is known as 
effluxion takes place. 

In most cases the menstrual discharge recurs for some time 
after conception has taken place, its duration being mostly 
thirty days in the case of a female and about forty days in the 
case of a male child. After parturition also it is common for the 
discharge to be withheld for an equal number of days, but not in 
all cases with equal exactitude. After conception, and when the 
above-mentioned days are past, the discharge no longer takes 
its natural course but finds its way to the breasts and turns to 
milk. The first appearance of milk in the breasts is scant in 
quantity and so to speak cobwebby or interspersed with little 
threads. And when conception has taken place, there is apt to 
be a sort of feeling in the region of the flanks, which in some 
cases quickly swell up a little, especially in thin persons, and 
also in the groin. 

In the case of male children the first movement usually occurs 
on the right-hand side of the womb and about the fortieth day, 
but if the child be a female then on the left-hand side and about 
the ninetieth day. However, we must by no means assume this 
to be an accurate statement of fact, for there are many 
exceptions, in which the movement is manifested on the right- 
hand side though a female child be coming, and on the left- 
hand side though the infant be a male. And in short, these and 
all suchlike phenomena are usually subject to differences that 
may be summed up as differences of degree. 

About this period the embryo begins to resolve into distinct 
parts, it having hitherto consisted of a fleshlike substance 
without distinction of parts. 

What is called effluxion is a destruction of the embryo within 
the first week, while abortion occurs up to the fortieth day; and 



1656 



the greater number of such embryos as perish do so within the 
space of these forty days. 

In the case of a male embryo aborted at the fortieth day, if it be 
placed in cold water it holds together in a sort of membrane, 
but if it be placed in any other fluid it dissolves and disappears. 
If the membrane be pulled to bits the embryo is revealed, as big 
as one of the large kind of ants; and all the limbs are plain to 
see, including the penis, and the eyes also, which as in other 
animals are of great size. But the female embryo, if it suffer 
abortion during the first three months, is as a rule found to be 
undifferentiated; if however it reach the fourth month it comes 
to be subdivided and quickly attains further differentiation. In 
short, while within the womb, the female infant accomplishes 
the whole development of its parts more slowly than the male, 
and more frequently than the man-child takes ten months to 
come to perfection. But after birth, the females pass more 
quickly than the males through youth and maturity and age; 
and this is especially true of those that bear many children, as 
indeed I have already said. 



When the womb has conceived the seed, straightway in the 
majority of cases it closes up until seven months are fulfilled; 
but in the eighth month it opens, and the embryo, if it be fertile, 
descends in the eighth month. But such embryos as are not 
fertile but are devoid of breath at eight months old, their 
mothers do not bring into the world by parturition at eight 
months, neither does the embryo descend within the womb at 
that period nor does the womb open. And it is a sign that the 



1657 



embryo is not capable of life if it be formed without the above- 
named circumstances taking place. 

After conception women are prone to a feeling of heaviness in 
all parts of their bodies, and for instance they experience a 
sensation of darkness in front of the eyes and suffer also from 
headache. These symptoms appear sooner or later, sometimes 
as early as the tenth day, according as the patient be more or 
less burthened with superfluous humours. Nausea also and 
sickness affect the most of women, and especially such as those 
that we have just now mentioned, after the menstrual discharge 
has ceased and before it is yet turned in the direction of the 
breasts. 

Moreover, some women suffer most at the beginning of their 
pregnancy and some at a later period when the embryo has had 
time to grow; and in some women it is a common occurrence to 
suffer from strangury towards the end of their time. As a 
general rule women who are pregnant of a male child escape 
comparatively easily and retain a comparatively healthy look, 
but it is otherwise with those whose infant is a female; for these 
latter look as a rule paler and suffer more pain, and in many 
cases they are subject to swellings of the legs and eruptions on 
the body. Nevertheless the rule is subject to exceptions. 

Women in pregnancy are a prey to all sorts of longings and to 
rapid changes of mood, and some folks call this the 'ivy- 
sickness'; and with the mothers of female infants the longings 
are more acute, and they are less contented when they have got 
what they desired. 

In a certain few cases the patient feels unusually well during 
pregnancy. The worst time of all is just when the child's hair is 
beginning to grow. 



1658 



In pregnant women their own natural hair is inclined to grow 
thin and fall out, but on the other hand hair tends to grow on 
parts of the body where it was not wont to be. As a general rule, 
a man-child is more prone to movement within its mother's 
womb than a female child, and it is usually born sooner. And 
labour in the case of female children is apt to be protracted and 
sluggish, while in the case of male children it is acute and by a 
long way more difficult. Women who have connexion with their 
husbands shortly before childbirth are delivered all the more 
quickly. Occasionally women seem to be in the pains of labour 
though labour has not in fact commenced, what seemed like 
the commencement of labour being really the result of the 
foetus turning its head. 

Now all other animals bring the time of pregnancy to an end in 
a uniform way; in other words, one single term of pregnancy is 
defined for each of them. But in the case of mankind alone of all 
animals the times are diverse; for pregnancy may be of seven 
months' duration, or of eight months or of nine, and still more 
commonly of ten months, while some few women go even into 
the eleventh month. 

Children that come into the world before seven months can 
under no circumstances survive. The seven-months' children 
are the earliest that are capable of life, and most of them are 
weakly - for which reason, by the way, it is customary to 
swaddle them in wool, - and many of them are born with some 
of the orifices of the body imperforate, for instance the ears or 
the nostrils. But as they get bigger they become more perfectly 
developed, and many of them grow up. 

In Egypt, and in some other places where the women are 
fruitful and are wont to bear and bring forth many children 
without difficulty, and where the children when born are 
capable of living even if they be born subject to deformity, in 



1659 



these places the eight-months' children live and are brought up, 
but in Greece it is only a few of them that survive while most 
perish. And this being the general experience, when such a child 
does happen to survive the mother is apt to think that it was 
not an eight months' child after all, but that she had conceived 
at an earlier period without being aware of it. 

Women suffer most pain about the fourth and the eighth 
months, and if the foetus perishes in the fourth or in the eighth 
month the mother also succumbs as a general rule; so that not 
only do the eight-months' children not live, but when they die 
their mothers are in great danger of their own lives. In like 
manner children that are apparently born at a later term than 
eleven months are held to be in doubtful case; inasmuch as 
with them also the beginning of conception may have escaped 
the notice of the mother. What I mean to say is that often the 
womb gets filled with wind, and then when at a later period 
connexion and conception take place, they think that the 
former circumstance was the beginning of conception from the 
similarity of the symptoms that they experienced. 

Such then are the differences between mankind and other 
animals in regard to the many various modes of completion of 
the term of pregnancy. Furthermore, some animals produce one 
and some produce many at a birth, but the human species does 
sometimes the one and sometimes the other. As a general rule 
and among most nations the women bear one child a birth; but 
frequently and in many lands they bear twins, as for instance in 
Egypt especially. Sometimes women bring forth three and even 
four children, and especially in certain parts of the world, as has 
already been stated. The largest number ever brought forth is 
five, and such an occurrence has been witnessed on several 
occasions. There was once upon a time a certain women who 
had twenty children at four births; each time she had five, and 
most of them grew up. 



1660 



Now among other animals, if a pair of twins happen to be male 
and female they have as good a chance of surviving as though 
both had been males or both females; but among mankind very 
few twins survive if one happen to be a boy and the other a girl. 

Of all animals the woman and the mare are most inclined to 
receive the commerce of the male during pregnancy; while all 
other animals when they are pregnant avoid the male, save 
those in which the phenomenon of superfoetation occurs, such 
as the hare. Unlike that animal, the mare after once conceiving 
cannot be rendered pregnant again, but brings forth one foal 
only, at least as a general rule; in the human species cases of 
superfoetation are rare, but they do happen now and then. 

An embryo conceived some considerable time after a previous 
conception does not come to perfection, but gives rise to pain 
and causes the destruction of the earlier embryo; and, by the 
way, a case has been known to occur where owing to this 
destructive influence no less than twelve embryos conceived by 
superfoetation have been discharged. But if the second 
conception take place at a short interval, then the mother bears 
that which was later conceived, and brings forth the two 
children like actual twins, as happened, according to the legend, 
in the case of Iphicles and Hercules. The following also is a 
striking example: a certain woman, having committed adultery, 
brought forth the one child resembling her husband and the 
other resembling the adulterous lover. 

The case has also occurred where a woman, being pregnant of 
twins, has subsequently conceived a third child; and in course 
of time she brought forth the twins perfect and at full term, but 
the third a five-months' child; and this last died there and then. 
And in another case it happened that the woman was first 
delivered of a seven-months' child, and then of two which were 



1661 



of full term; and of these the first died and the other two 
survived. 

Some also have been known to conceive while about to 
miscarry, and they have lost the one child and been delivered of 
the other. 

If women while going with child cohabit after the eighth month 
the child is in most cases born covered over with a slimy fluid. 
Often also the child is found to be replete with food of which 
the mother had partaken. 



When women have partaken of salt in overabundance their 
children are apt to be born destitute of nails. 

Milk that is produced earlier than the seventh month is unfit for 
use; but as soon as the child is fit to live the milk is fit to use. 
The first of the milk is saltish, as it is likewise with sheep. Most 
women are sensibly affected by wine during pregnancy, for if 
they partake of it they grow relaxed and debilitated. 

The beginning of child-bearing in women and of the capacity to 
procreate in men, and the cessation of these functions in both 
cases, coincide in the one case with the emission of seed and in 
the other with the discharge of the catamenia: with this 
qualification that there is a lack of fertility at the 
commencement of these symptoms, and again towards their 
close when the emissions become scanty and weak. The age at 
which the sexual powers begin has been related already. As for 
their end, the menstrual discharges ceases in most women 
about their fortieth year; but with those in whom it goes on 



1662 



longer it lasts even to the fiftieth year, and women of that age 
have been known to bear children. But beyond that age there is 
no case on record. 



Men in most cases continue to be sexually competent until they 
are sixty years old, and if that limit be overpassed then until 
seventy years; and men have been actually known to procreate 
children at seventy years of age. With many men and many 
women it so happens that they are unable to produce children 
to one another, while they are able to do so in union with other 
individuals. The same thing happens with regard to the 
production of male and female offspring; for sometimes men 
and women in union with one another produce male children 
or female, as the case may be, but children of the opposite sex 
when otherwise mated. And they are apt to change in this 
respect with advancing age: for sometimes a husband and wife 
while they are young produce female children and in later life 
male children; and in other cases the very contrary occurs. And 
just the same thing is true in regard to the generative faculty: 
for some while young are childless, but have children when 
they grow older; and some have children to begin with, and 
later on no more. 

There are certain women who conceive with difficulty, but if 
they do conceive, bring the child to maturity; while others again 
conceive readily, but are unable to bring the child to birth. 
Furthermore, some men and some women produce female 
offspring and some male, as for instance in the story of 
Hercules, who among all his two and seventy children is said to 
have begotten but one girl. Those women who are unable to 



1663 



conceive, save with the help of medical treatment or some other 
adventitious circumstance, are as a general rule apt to bear 
female children rather than male. 

It is a common thing with men to be at first sexually competent 
and afterwards impotent, and then again to revert to their 
former powers. 

From deformed parents come deformed children, lame from 
lame and blind from blind, and, speaking generally, children 
often inherit anything that is peculiar in their parents and are 
born with similar marks, such as pimples or scars. Such things 
have been known to be handed down through three 
generations; for instance, a certain man had a mark on his arm 
which his son did not possess, but his grandson had it in the 
same spot though not very distinct. 

Such cases, however, are few; for the children of cripples are 
mostly sound, and there is no hard and fast rule regarding 
them. While children mostly resemble their parents or their 
ancestors, it sometimes happens that no such resemblance is to 
be traced. But parents may pass on resemblance after several 
generations, as in the case of the woman in Elis, who 
committed adultery with a negro; in this case it was not the 
woman's own daughter but the daughter's child that was a 
blackamoor. 

As a rule the daughters have a tendency to take after the 
mother, and the boys after the father; but sometimes it is the 
other way, the boys taking after the mother and the girls after 
the father. And they may resemble both parents in particular 
features. 

There have been known cases of twins that had no resemblance 
to one another, but they are alike as a general rule. There was 
once upon a time a woman who had intercourse with her 



1664 



husband a week after giving birth to a child and she conceived 
and bore a second child as like the first as any twin. Some 
women have a tendency to produce children that take after 
themselves, and others children that take after the husband; 
and this latter case is like that of the celebrated mare in 
Pharsalus, that got the name of the Honest Wife. 



In the emission of sperm there is a preliminary discharge of air, 
and the outflow is manifestly caused by a blast of air; for 
nothing is cast to a distance save by pneumatic pressure. After 
the seed reaches the womb and remains there for a while, a 
membrane forms around it; for when it happens to escape 
before it is distinctly formed, it looks like an egg enveloped in its 
membrane after removal of the eggshell; and the membrane is 
full of veins. 

All animals whatsoever, whether they fly or swim or walk upon 
dry land, whether they bring forth their young alive or in the 
egg, develop in the same way: save only that some have the 
navel attached to the womb, namely the viviparous animals, 
and some have it attached to the egg, and some to both parts 
alike, as in a certain sort of fishes. And in some cases 
membranous envelopes surround the egg, and in other cases 
the chorion surrounds it. And first of all the animal develops 
within the innermost envelope, and then another membrane 
appears around the former one, which latter is for the most part 
attached to the womb, but is in part separated from it and 
contains fluid. In between is a watery or sanguineous fluid, 
which the women folk call the forewaters. 



1665 



8 

All animals, or all such as have a navel, grow by the navel. And 
the navel is attached to the cotyledon in all such as possess 
cotyledons, and to the womb itself by a vein in all such as have 
the womb smooth. And as regards their shape within the womb, 
the four-footed animals all lie stretched out, and the footless 
animals lie on their sides, as for instance fishes; but two-legged 
animals lie in a bent position, as for instance birds; and human 
embryos lie bent, with nose between the knees and eyes upon 
the knees, and the ears free at the sides. 

All animals alike have the head upwards to begin with; but as 
they grow and approach the term of egress from the womb they 
turn downwards, and birth in the natural course of things takes 
place in all animals head foremost; but in abnormal cases it 
may take place in a bent position, or feet foremost. 

The young of quadrupeds when they are near their full time 
contain excrements, both liquid and in the form of solid lumps, 
the latter in the lower part of the bowel and the urine in the 
bladder. 

In those animals that have cotyledons in the womb the 
cotyledons grow less as the embryo grows bigger, and at length 
they disappear altogether. The navel-string is a sheath wrapped 
about blood-vessels which have their origin in the womb, from 
the cotyledons in those animals which possess them and from 
a blood-vessel in those which do not. In the larger animals, such 
as the embryos of oxen, the vessels are four in number, and in 
smaller animals two; in the very little ones, such as fowls, one 
vessel only. 

Of the four vessels that run into the embryo, two pass through 
the liver where the so-called gates or 'portae' are, running in the 



1666 



direction of the great vein, and the other two run in the 
direction of the aorta towards the point where it divides and 
becomes two vessels instead of one. Around each pair of blood- 
vessels are membranes, and surrounding these membranes is 
the navel-string itself, after the manner of a sheath. And as the 
embryo grows, the veins themselves tend more and more to 
dwindle in size. And also as the embryo matures it comes down 
into the hollow of the womb and is observed to move here, and 
sometimes rolls over in the vicinity of the groin. 



When women are in labour, their pains determine towards 
many divers parts of the body, and in most cases to one or other 
of the thighs. Those are the quickest to be delivered who 
experience severe pains in the region of the belly; and 
parturition is difficult in those who begin by suffering pain in 
the loins, and speedy when the pain is abdominal. If the child 
about to be born be a male, the preliminary flood is watery and 
pale in colour, but if a girl it is tinged with blood, though still 
watery. In some cases of labour these latter phenomena do not 
occur, either one way or the other. 

In other animals parturition is unaccompanied by pain, and the 
dam is plainly seen to suffer but moderate inconvenience. In 
women, however, the pains are more severe, and this is 
especially the case in persons of sedentary habits, and in those 
who are weak-chested and short of breath. Labour is apt to be 
especially difficult if during the process the woman while 
exerting force with her breath fails to hold it in. 

First of all, when the embryo starts to move and the membranes 
burst, there issues forth the watery flood; then afterwards 



1667 



comes the embryo, while the womb everts and the afterbirth 
comes out from within. 



10 

The cutting of the navel-string, which is the nurse's duty, is a 
matter calling for no little care and skill. For not only in cases of 
difficult labour must she be able to render assistance with 
skilful hand, but she must also have her wits about her in all 
contingencies, and especially in the operation of tying the cord. 
For if the afterbirth have come away, the navel is ligatured off 
from the afterbirth with a woollen thread and is then cut above 
the ligature; and at the place where it has been tied it heals up, 
and the remaining portion drops off. (If the ligature come loose 
the child dies from loss of blood.) But if the afterbirth has not 
yet come away, but remains after the child itself is extruded, it 
is cut away within after the ligaturing of the cord. 

It often happens that the child appears to have been born dead 
when it is merely weak, and when before the umbilical cord has 
been ligatured, the blood has run out into the cord and its 
surroundings. But experienced midwives have been known to 
squeeze back the blood into the child's body from the cord, and 
immediately the child that a moment before was bloodless 
came back to life again. 

It is the natural rule, as we have mentioned above, for all 
animals to come into the world head foremost, and children, 
moreover, have their hands stretched out by their sides. And the 
child gives a cry and puts its hands up to its mouth as soon as it 
issues forth. 



1668 



Moreover the child voids excrement sometimes at once, 
sometimes a little later, but in all cases during the first day; and 
this excrement is unduly copious in comparison with the size of 
the child; it is what the midwives call the meconium or 'poppy- 
juice'. In colour it resembles blood, extremely dark and pitch- 
like, but later on it becomes milky, for the child takes at once to 
the breast. Before birth the child makes no sound, even though 
in difficult labour it put forth its head while the rest of the body 
remains within. 

In cases where flooding takes place rather before its time, it is 
apt to be followed by difficult parturition. But if discharge take 
place after birth in small quantity, and in cases where it only 
takes place at the beginning and does not continue till the 
fortieth day, then in such cases women make a better recovery 
and are the sooner ready to conceive again. 

Until the child is forty days old it neither laughs nor weeps 
during waking hours, but of nights it sometimes does both; and 
for the most part it does not even notice being tickled, but 
passes most of its time in sleep. As it keeps on growing, it gets 
more and more wakeful; and moreover it shows signs of 
dreaming, though it is long afterwards before it remembers 
what it dreams. 

In other animals there is no contrasting difference between one 
bone and another, but all are properly formed; but in children 
the front part of the head is soft and late of ossifying. And by 
the way, some animals are born with teeth, but children begin 
to cut their teeth in the seventh month; and the front teeth are 
the first to come through, sometimes the upper and sometimes 
the lower ones. And the warmer the nurses' milk so much the 
quicker are the children's teeth to come. 



1669 



11 

After parturition and the cleasing flood the milk comes in 
plenty, and in some women it flows not only from the nipples 
but at divers parts of the breasts, and in some cases even from 
the armpits. And for some time afterwards there continue to be 
certain indurated parts of the breast called strangalides, or 
'knots', which occur when it so happens that the moisture is 
not concocted, or when it finds no outlet but accumulates 
within. For the whole breast is so spongy that if a woman in 
drinking happen to swallow a hair, she gets a pain in her breast, 
which ailment is called 'trichia'; and the pain lasts till the hair 
either find its own way out or be sucked out with the milk. 
Women continue to have milk until their next conception; and 
then the milk stops coming and goes dry, alike in the human 
species and in the quadrupedal vivipara. So long as there is a 
flow of milk the menstrual purgations do not take place, at least 
as a general rule, though the discharge has been known to occur 
during the period of suckling. For, speaking generally, a 
determination of moisture does not take place at one and the 
same time in several directions; as for instance the menstrual 
purgations tend to be scanty in persons suffering from 
haemorrhoids. And in some women the like happens owing to 
their suffering from varices, when the fluids issue from the 
pelvic region before entering into the womb. And patients who 
during suppression of the menses happen to vomit blood are no 
whit the worse. 



1670 



12 

Children are very commonly subject to convulsions, more 
especially such of them as are more than ordinarily well- 
nourished on rich or unusually plentiful milk from a stout 
nurse. Wine is bad for infants, in that it tends to excite this 
malady, and red wine is worse than white, especially when 
taken undiluted; and most things that tend to induce flatulency 
are also bad, and constipation too is prejudicial. The majority of 
deaths in infancy occur before the child is a week old, hence it 
is customary to name the child at that age, from a belief that it 
has now a better chance of survival. This malady is worst at the 
full of the moon; and by the way, it is a dangerous symptom 
when the spasms begin in the child's back. 



Book VIII 



We have now discussed the physical characteristics of animals 
and their methods of generation. Their habits and their modes 
of living vary according to their character and their food. 

In the great majority of animals there are traces of psychical 
qualities or attitudes, which qualities are more markedly 
differentiated in the case of human beings. For just as we 
pointed out resemblances in the physical organs, so in a 
number of animals we observe gentleness or fierceness, 



1671 



mildness or cross temper, courage, or timidity, fear or 
confidence, high spirit or low cunning, and, with regard to 
intelligence, something equivalent to sagacity. Some of these 
qualities in man, as compared with the corresponding qualities 
in animals, differ only quantitatively: that is to say, a man has 
more or less of this quality, and an animal has more or less of 
some other; other qualities in man are represented by 
analogous and not identical qualities: for instance, just as in 
man we find knowledge, wisdom, and sagacity, so in certain 
animals there exists some other natural potentiality akin to 
these. The truth of this statement will be the more clearly 
apprehended if we have regard to the phenomena of childhood: 
for in children may be observed the traces and seeds of what 
will one day be settled psychological habits, though 
psychologically a child hardly differs for the time being from an 
animal; so that one is quite justified in saying that, as regards 
man and animals, certain psychical qualities are identical with 
one another, whilst others resemble, and others are analogous 
to, each other. 

Nature proceeds little by little from things lifeless to animal life 
in such a way that it is impossible to determine the exact line of 
demarcation, nor on which side thereof an intermediate form 
should lie. Thus, next after lifeless things in the upward scale 
comes the plant, and of plants one will differ from another as to 
its amount of apparent vitality; and, in a word, the whole genus 
of plants, whilst it is devoid of life as compared with an animal, 
is endowed with life as compared with other corporeal entities. 
Indeed, as we just remarked, there is observed in plants a 
continuous scale of ascent towards the animal. So, in the sea, 
there are certain objects concerning which one would be at a 
loss to determine whether they be animal or vegetable. For 
instance, certain of these objects are fairly rooted, and in several 
cases perish if detached; thus the pinna is rooted to a particular 
spot, and the solen (or razor-shell) cannot survive withdrawal 



1672 



from its burrow. Indeed, broadly speaking, the entire genus of 
testaceans have a resemblance to vegetables, if they be 
contrasted with such animals as are capable of progression. 

In regard to sensibility, some animals give no indication 
whatsoever of it, whilst others indicate it but indistinctly. 
Further, the substance of some of these intermediate creatures 
is fleshlike, as is the case with the so-called tethya (or ascidians) 
and the acalephae (or sea-anemones); but the sponge is in every 
respect like a vegetable. And so throughout the entire animal 
scale there is a graduated differentiation in amount of vitality 
and in capacity for motion. 

A similar statement holds good with regard to habits of life. 
Thus of plants that spring from seed the one function seems to 
be the reproduction of their own particular species, and the 
sphere of action with certain animals is similarly limited. The 
faculty of reproduction, then, is common to all alike. If 
sensibility be superadded, then their lives will differ from one 
another in respect to sexual intercourse through the varying 
amount of pleasure derived therefrom, and also in regard to 
modes of parturition and ways of rearing their young. Some 
animals, like plants, simply procreate their own species at 
definite seasons; other animals busy themselves also in 
procuring food for their young, and after they are reared quit 
them and have no further dealings with them; other animals 
are more intelligent and endowed with memory, and they live 
with their offspring for a longer period and on a more social 
footing. 

The life of animals, then, may be divided into two acts - 
procreation and feeding; for on these two acts all their interests 
and life concentrate. Their food depends chiefly on the 
substance of which they are severally constituted; for the source 
of their growth in all cases will be this substance. And 



1673 



whatsoever is in conformity with nature is pleasant, and all 
animals pursue pleasure in keeping with their nature. 



Animals are also differentiated locally: that is to say, some live 
upon dry land, while others live in the water. And this 
differentiation may be interpreted in two different ways. Thus, 
some animals are termed terrestrial as inhaling air, and others 
aquatic as taking in water; and there are others which do not 
actually take in these elements, but nevertheless are 
constitutionally adapted to the cooling influence, so far as is 
needful to them, of one element or the other, and hence are 
called terrestrial or aquatic though they neither breathe air nor 
take in water. Again, other animals are so called from their 
finding their food and fixing their habitat on land or in water: 
for many animals, although they inhale air and breed on land, 
yet derive their food from the water, and live in water for the 
greater part of their lives; and these are the only animals to 
which as living in and on two elements the term 'amphibious' is 
applicable. There is no animal taking in water that is terrestrial 
or aerial or that derives its food from the land, whereas of the 
great number of land animals inhaling air many get their food 
from the water; moreover some are so peculiarly organized that 
if they be shut off altogether from the water they cannot 
possibly live, as for instance, the so-called sea-turtle, the 
crocodile, the hippopotamus, the seal, and some of the smaller 
creatures, such as the fresh-water tortoise and the frog: now all 
these animals choke or drown if they do not from time to time 
breathe atmospheric air: they breed and rear their young on dry 
land, or near the land, but they pass their lives in water. 



1674 



But the dolphin is equipped in the most remarkable way of all 
animals: the dolphin and other similar aquatic animals, 
including the other cetaceans which resemble it; that is to say, 
the whale, and all the other creatures that are furnished with a 
blow-hole. One can hardly allow that such an animal is 
terrestrial and terrestrial only, or aquatic and aquatic only, if by 
terrestrial we mean an animal that inhales air, and if by aquatic 
we mean an animal that takes in water. For the fact is the 
dolphin performs both these processes: he takes in water and 
discharges it by his blow-hole, and he also inhales air into his 
lungs; for, by the way, the creature is furnished with this organ 
and respires thereby, and accordingly, when caught in the nets, 
he is quickly suffocated for lack of air. He can also live for a 
considerable while out of the water, but all this while he keeps 
up a dull moaning sound corresponding to the noise made by 
air-breathing animals in general; furthermore, when sleeping, 
the animal keeps his nose above water, and he does so that he 
may breathe the air. Now it would be unreasonable to assign 
one and the same class of animals to both categories, terrestrial 
and aquatic, seeing that these categories are more or less 
exclusive of one another; we must accordingly supplement our 
definition of the term 'aquatic' or 'marine'. For the fact is, some 
aquatic animals take in water and discharge it again, for the 
same reason that leads air-breathing animals to inhale air: in 
other words, with the object of cooling the blood. Others take in 
water as incidental to their mode of feeding; for as they get 
their food in the water they cannot but take in water along with 
their food, and if they take in water they must be provided with 
some organ for discharging it. Those blooded animals, then, that 
use water for a purpose analogous to respiration are provided 
with gills; and such as take in water when catching their prey, 
with the blow-hole. Similar remarks are applicable to molluscs 
and crustaceans; for again it is by way of procuring food that 
these creatures take in water. 



1675 



Aquatic in different ways, the differences depending on bodily 
relation to external temperature and on habit of life, are such 
animals on the one hand as take in air but live in water, and 
such on the other hand as take in water and are furnished with 
gills but go upon dry land and get their living there. At present 
only one animal of the latter kind is known, the so-called 
cordylus or water-newt; this creature is furnished not with 
lungs but with gills, but for all that it is a quadruped and fitted 
for walking on dry land. 

In the case of all these animals their nature appears in some 
kind of a way to have got warped, just as some male animals 
get to resemble the female, and some female animals the male. 
The fact is that animals, if they be subjected to a modification 
in minute organs, are liable to immense modifications in their 
general configuration. This phenomenon may be observed in 
the case of gelded animals: only a minute organ of the animal is 
mutilated, and the creature passes from the male to the female 
form. We may infer, then, that if in the primary conformation of 
the embryo an infinitesimally minute but absolutely essential 
organ sustain a change of magnitude one way or the other, the 
animal will in one case turn to male and in the other to female; 
and also that, if the said organ be obliterated altogether, the 
animal will be of neither one sex nor the other. And so by the 
occurrence of modification in minute organs it comes to pass 
that one animal is terrestrial and another aquatic, in both 
senses of these terms. And, again, some animals are 
amphibious whilst other animals are not amphibious, owing to 
the circumstance that in their conformation while in the 
embryonic condition there got intermixed into them some 
portion of the matter of which their subsequent food is 
constituted; for, as was said above, what is in conformity with 
nature is to every single animal pleasant and agreeable. 



1676 



Animals then have been categorized into terrestrial and aquatic 
in three ways, according to their assumption of air or of water, 
the temperament of their bodies, or the character of their food; 
and the mode of life of an animal corresponds to the category in 
which it is found. That is to say, in some cases the animal 
depends for its terrestrial or aquatic nature on temperament 
and diet combined, as well as upon its method of respiration; 
and sometimes on temperament and habits alone. 

Of testaceans, some, that are incapable of motion, subsist on 
fresh water, for, as the sea water dissolves into its constituents, 
the fresh water from its greater thinness percolates through the 
grosser parts; in fact, they live on fresh water just as they were 
originally engendered from the same. Now that fresh water is 
contained in the sea and can be strained off from it can be 
proved in a thoroughly practical way. Take a thin vessel of 
moulded wax, attach a cord to it, and let it down quite empty 
into the sea: in twenty-four hours it will be found to contain a 
quantity of water, and the water will be fresh and drinkable. 

Sea-anemones feed on such small fishes as come in their way. 
The mouth of this creature is in the middle of its body; and this 
fact may be clearly observed in the case of the larger varieties. 
Like the oyster it has a duct for the outlet of the residuum; and 
this duct is at the top of the animal. In other words, the sea- 
anemone corresponds to the inner fleshy part of the oyster, and 
the stone to which the one creature clings corresponds to the 
shell which encases the other. 

The limpet detaches itself from the rock and goes about in 
quest of food. Of shell-fish that are mobile, some are 
carnivorous and live on little fishes, as for instance, the purple 
murex - and there can be no doubt that the purple murex is 
carnivorous, as it is caught by a bait of fish; others are 
carnivorous, but feed also on marine vegetation. 



1677 



The sea-turtles feed on shell-fish - for, by the way, their mouths 
are extraordinarily hard; whatever object it seizes, stone or 
other, it crunches into bits, but when it leaves the water for dry 
land it browses on grass). These creatures suffer greatly, and 
oftentimes die when they lie on the surface of the water 
exposed to a scorching sun; for, when once they have risen to 
the surface, they find a difficulty in sinking again. 

Crustaceans feed in like manner. They are omnivorous; that is 
to say, they live on stones, slime, sea-weed, and excrement - as 
for instance the rock-crab - and are also carnivorous. The 
crawfish or spiny-lobster can get the better of fishes even of the 
larger species, though in some of them it occasionally finds 
more than its match. Thus, this animal is so overmastered and 
cowed by the octopus that it dies of terror if it become aware of 
an octopus in the same net with itself. The crawfish can master 
the conger-eel, for owing to the rough spines of the crawfish the 
eel cannot slip away and elude its hold. The conger-eel, 
however, devours the octopus, for owing to the slipperiness of 
its antagonist the octopus can make nothing of it. The crawfish 
feeds on little fish, capturing them beside its hole or dwelling 
place; for, by the way, it is found out at sea on rough and stony 
bottoms, and in such places it makes its den. Whatever it 
catches, it puts into its mouth with its pincer-like claws, like the 
common crab. Its nature is to walk straight forward when it has 
nothing to fear, with its feelers hanging sideways; if it be 
frightened, it makes its escape backwards, darting off to a great 
distance. These animals fight one another with their claws, just 
as rams fight with their horns, raising them and striking their 
opponents; they are often also seen crowded together in herds. 
So much for the mode of life of the crustacean. 

Molluscs are all carnivorous; and of molluscs the calamary and 
the sepia are more than a match for fishes even of the large 
species. The octopus for the most part gathers shellfish, extracts 



1678 



the flesh, and feeds on that; in fact, fishermen recognize their 
holes by the number of shells lying about. Some say that the 
octopus devours its own species, but this statement is incorrect; 
it is doubtless founded on the fact that the creature is often 
found with its tentacles removed, which tentacles have really 
been eaten off by the conger. 

Fishes, all without exception, feed on spawn in the spawning 
season; but in other respects the food varies with the varying 
species. Some fishes are exclusively carnivorous, as the 
cartilaginous genus, the conger, the channa or Serranus, the 
tunny, the bass, the synodon or Dentex, the amia, the sea-perch, 
and the muraena. The red mullet is carnivorous, but feeds also 
on sea-weed, on shell-fish, and on mud. The grey mullet feeds 
on mud, the dascyllus on mud and offal, the scarus or parrot- 
fish and the melanurus on sea-weed, the saupe on offal and 
sea-weed; the saupe feeds also on zostera, and is the only fish 
that is captured with a gourd. All fishes devour their own 
species, with the single exception of the cestreus or mullet; and 
the conger is especially ravenous in this respect. The cephalus 
and the mullet in general are the only fish that eat no flesh; this 
may be inferred from the facts that when caught they are never 
found with flesh in their intestines, and that the bait used to 
catch them is not flesh but barley-cake. Every fish of the mullet- 
kind lives on sea-weed and sand. The cephalus, called by some 
the 'chelon', keeps near in to the shore, the peraeas keeps out at 
a distance from it, and feeds on a mucous substance exuding 
from itself, and consequently is always in a starved condition. 
The cephalus lives in mud, and is in consequence heavy and 
slimy; it never feeds on any other fish. As it lives in mud, it has 
every now and then to make a leap upwards out of the mud so 
as to wash the slime from off its body. There is no creature 
known to prey upon the spawn of the cephalus, so that the 
species is exceedingly numerous; when, however, the is full- 
grown it is preyed upon by a number of fishes, and especially by 



1679 



the acharnas or bass. Of all fishes the mullet is the most 
voracious and insatiable, and in consequence its belly is kept at 
full stretch; whenever it is not starving, it may be considered as 
out of condition. When it is frightened, it hides its head in mud, 
under the notion that it is hiding its whole body. The synodon is 
carnivorous and feeds on molluscs. Very often the synodon and 
the channa cast up their stomachs while chasing smaller fishes; 
for, be it remembered, fishes have their stomachs close to the 
mouth, and are not furnished with a gullet. 

Some fishes then, as has been stated, are carnivorous, and 
carnivorous only, as the dolphin, the synodon, the gilt-head, the 
selachians, and the molluscs. Other fishes feed habitually on 
mud or sea-weed or sea-moss or the so-called stalk-weed or 
growing plants; as for instance, the phycis, the goby, and the 
rock-fish; and, by the way, the only meat that the phycis will 
touch is that of prawns. Very often, however, as has been stated, 
they devour one another, and especially do the larger ones 
devour the smaller. The proof of their being carnivorous is the 
fact that they can be caught with flesh for a bait. The mackerel, 
the tunny, and the bass are for the most part carnivorous, but 
they do occasionally feed on sea-weed. The sargue feeds on the 
leavings of the trigle or red mullet. The red mullet burrows in 
the mud, when it sets the mud in motion and quits its haunt, 
the sargue settles down into the place and feeds on what is left 
behind, and prevents any smaller fish from settling in the 
immediate vicinity. 

Of all fishes the so-called scarus, or parrot, wrasse, is the only 
one known to chew the cud like a quadruped. 

As a general rule the larger fishes catch the smaller ones in 
their mouths whilst swimming straight after them in the 
ordinary position; but the selachians, the dolphin, and all the 
cetacea must first turn over on their backs, as their mouths are 



1680 



placed down below; this allows a fair chance of escape to the 
smaller fishes, and, indeed, if it were not so, there would be very 
few of the little fishes left, for the speed and voracity of the 
dolphin is something marvellous. 

Of eels a few here and there feed on mud and on chance 
morsels of food thrown to them; the greater part of them 
subsist on fresh water. Eel-breeders are particularly careful to 
have the water kept perfectly clear, by its perpetually flowing on 
to flat slabs of stone and then flowing off again; sometimes they 
coat the eel-tanks with plaster. The fact is that the eel will soon 
choke if the water is not clear as his gills are peculiarly small. 
On this account, when fishing for eels, they disturb the water. In 
the river Strymon eel-fishing takes place at the rising of the 
Pleiads, because at this period the water is troubled and the 
mud raised up by contrary winds; unless the water be in this 
condition, it is as well to leave the eels alone. When dead the 
eel, unlike the majority of fishes, neither floats on nor rises to 
the surface; and this is owing to the smallness of the stomach. 
A few eels are supplied with fat, but the greater part have no fat 
whatsoever. When removed from the water they can live for five 
or six days; for a longer period if north winds prevail, for a 
shorter if south winds. If they are removed in summer from the 
pools to the tanks they will die; but not so if removed in the 
winter. They are not capable of holding out against any abrupt 
change; consequently they often die in large numbers when 
men engaged in transporting them from one place to another 
dip them into water particularly cold. They will also die of 
suffocation if they be kept in a scanty supply of water. This 
same remark will hold good for fishes in general; for they are 
suffocated if they be long confined in a short supply of water, 
with the water kept unchanged - just as animals that respire 
are suffocated if they be shut up with a scanty supply of air. The 
eel in some cases lives for seven or eight years. The river-eel 
feeds on his own species, on grass, or on roots, or on any chance 



1681 



food found in the mud. Their usual feeding-time is at night, and 
during the day-time they retreat into deep water. And so much 
for the food of fishes. 



Of birds, such as have crooked talons are carnivorous without 
exception, and cannot swallow corn or bread-food even if it be 
put into their bills in tit-bits; as for instance, the eagle of every 
variety, the kite, the two species of hawks, to wit, the dove-hawk 
and the sparrow-hawk - and, by the way, these two hawks differ 
greatly in size from one another - and the buzzard. The buzzard 
is of the same size as the kite, and is visible at all seasons of the 
year. There is also the phene (or lammergeier) and the vulture. 
The phene is larger than the common eagle and is ashen in 
colour. Of the vulture there are two varieties: one small and 
whitish, the other comparatively large and rather more ashen- 
coloured than white. Further, of birds that fly by night, some 
have crooked talons, such as the night-raven, the owl, and the 
eagle-owl. The eagle-owl resembles the common owl in shape, 
but it is quite as large as the eagle. Again, there is the eleus, the 
Aegolian owl, and the little horned owl. Of these birds, the eleus 
is somewhat larger than the barn-door cock, and the Aegolian 
owl is of about the same size as the eleus, and both these birds 
hunt the jay; the little horned owl is smaller than the common 
owl. All these three birds are alike in appearance, and all three 
are carnivorous. 

Again, of birds that have not crooked talons some are 
carnivorous, such as the swallow. Others feed on grubs, such as 
the chaffinch, the sparrow, the 'batis', the green linnet, and the 
titmouse. Of the titmouse there are three varieties. The largest 



1682 



is the finch-titmouse - for it is about the size of a finch; the 
second has a long tail, and from its habitat is called the hill- 
titmouse; the third resembles the other two in appearance, but 
is less in size than either of them. Then come the becca-fico, the 
black-cap, the bull-finch, the robin, the epilais, the midget-bird, 
and the golden-crested wren. This wren is little larger than a 
locust, has a crest of bright red gold, and is in every way a 
beautiful and graceful little bird. Then the anthus, a bird about 
the size of a finch; and the mountain-finch, which resembles a 
finch and is of much the same size, but its neck is blue, and it is 
named from its habitat; and lastly the wren and the rook. The 
above-enumerated birds and the like of them feed either wholly 
or for the most part on grubs, but the following and the like feed 
on thistles; to wit, the linnet, the thraupis, and the goldfinch. All 
these birds feed on thistles, but never on grubs or any living 
thing whatever; they live and roost also on the plants from 
which they derive their food. 

There are other birds whose favourite food consists of insects 
found beneath the bark of trees; as for instance, the great and 
the small pie, which are nicknamed the woodpeckers. These 
two birds resemble one another in plumage and in note, only 
that the note of the larger bird is the louder of the two; they 
both frequent the trunks of trees in quest of food. There is also 
the greenpie, a bird about the size of a turtle-dove, green- 
coloured all over, that pecks at the bark of trees with 
extraordinary vigour, lives generally on the branch of a tree, has 
a loud note, and is mostly found in the Peloponnese. There is 
another bird called the 'grub-picker' (or tree-creeper), about as 
small as the penduline titmouse, with speckled plumage of an 
ashen colour, and with a poor note; it is a variety of the 
woodpecker. 

There are other birds that live on fruit and herbage, such as the 
wild pigeon or ringdove, the common pigeon, the rock-dove, and 



1683 



the turtle-dove. The ring-dove and the common pigeon are 
visible at all seasons; the turtledove only in the summer, for in 
winter it lurks in some hole or other and is never seen. The 
rock-dove is chiefly visible in the autumn, and is caught at that 
season; it is larger than the common pigeon but smaller than 
the wild one; it is generally caught while drinking. These 
pigeons bring their young ones with them when they visit this 
country. All our other birds come to us in the early summer and 
build their nests here, and the greater part of them rear their 
young on animal food, with the sole exception of the pigeon 
and its varieties. 

The whole genus of birds may be pretty well divided into such 
as procure their food on dry land, such as frequent rivers and 
lakes, and such as live on or by the sea. 

Of water-birds such as are web-footed live actually on the water, 
while such as are split-footed live by the edge of it - and, by the 
way, water-birds that are not carnivorous live on water-plants, 
(but most of them live on fish), like the heron and the spoonbill 
that frequent the banks of lakes and rivers; and the spoonbill, 
by the way, is less than the common heron, and has a long flat 
bill. There are furthermore the stork and the seamew; and the 
seamew, by the way, is ashen-coloured. There is also the 
schoenilus, the cinclus, and the white-rump. Of these smaller 
birds the last mentioned is the largest, being about the size of 
the common thrush; all three may be described as 'wag-tails'. 
Then there is the scalidris, with plumage ashen-grey, but 
speckled. Moreover, the family of the halcyons or kingfishers 
live by the waterside. Of kingfishers there are two varieties; one 
that sits on reeds and sings; the other, the larger of the two, is 
without a note. Both these varieties are blue on the back. There 
is also the trochilus (or sandpiper). The halcyon also, including a 
variety termed the cerylus, is found near the seaside. The crow 
also feeds on such animal life as is cast up on the beach, for the 



1684 



bird is omnivorous. There are also the white gull, the cepphus, 
the aethyia, and the charadrius. 

Of web-footed birds, the larger species live on the banks of 
rivers and lakes; as the swan, the duck, the coot, the grebe, and 
the teal - a bird resembling the duck but less in size - and the 
water-raven or cormorant. This bird is the size of a stork, only 
that its legs are shorter; it is web-footed and is a good swimmer; 
its plumage is black. It roosts on trees, and is the only one of all 
such birds as these that is found to build its nest in a tree. 
Further there is the large goose, the little gregarious goose, the 
vulpanser, the horned grebe, and the penelops. The sea-eagle 
lives in the neighbourhood of the sea and seeks its quarry in 
lagoons. 

A great number of birds are omnivorous. Birds of prey feed on 
any animal or bird, other than a bird of prey, that they may 
catch. These birds never touch one of their own genus, whereas 
fishes often devour members actually of their own species. 

Birds, as a rule, are very spare drinkers. In fact birds of prey 
never drink at all, excepting a very few, and these drink very 
rarely; and this last observation is peculiarly applicable to the 
kestrel. The kite has been seen to drink, but he certainly drinks 
very seldom. 



Animals that are coated with tessellates - such as the lizard and 
the other quadrupeds, and the serpents - are omnivorous: at all 
events they are carnivorous and graminivorous; and serpents, 
by the way, are of all animals the greatest gluttons. 



1685 



Tessellated animals are spare drinkers, as are also all such 
animals as have a spongy lung, and such a lung, scantily 
supplied with blood, is found in all oviparous animals. Serpents, 
by the by, have an insatiate appetite for wine; consequently, at 
times men hunt for snakes by pouring wine into saucers and 
putting them into the interstices of walls, and the creatures are 
caught when inebriated. Serpents are carnivorous, and 
whenever they catch an animal they extract all its juices and 
eject the creature whole. And, by the way, this is done by all 
other creatures of similar habits, as for instance the spider; only 
that the spider sucks out the juices of its prey outside, and the 
serpent does so in its belly. The serpent takes any food 
presented to him, eats birds and animals, and swallows eggs 
entire. But after taking his prey he stretches himself until he 
stands straight out to the very tip, and then he contracts and 
squeezes himself into little compass, so that the swallowed 
mass may pass down his outstretched body; and this action on 
his part is due to the tenuity and length of his gullet. Spiders 
and snakes can both go without food for a long time; and this 
remark may be verified by observation of specimens kept alive 
in the shops of the apothecaries. 



Of viviparous quadrupeds such as are fierce and jag-toothed are 
without exception carnivorous; though, by the way, it is stated 
of the wolf, but of no other animal, that in extremity of hunger 
it will eat a certain kind of earth. These carnivorous animals 
never eat grass except when they are sick, just as dogs bring on 
a vomit by eating grass and thereby purge themselves. 



1686 



The solitary wolf is more apt to attack man than the wolf that 
goes with a pack. 

The animal called 'glanus' by some and 'hyaena' by others is as 
large as a wolf, with a mane like a horse, only that the hair is 
stiffer and longer and extends over the entire length of the 
chine. It will lie in wait for a man and chase him, and will 
inveigle a dog within its reach by making a noise that resembles 
the retching noise of a man vomiting. It is exceedingly fond of 
putrefied flesh, and will burrow in a graveyard to gratify this 
propensity. 

The bear is omnivorous. It eats fruit, and is enabled by the 
suppleness of its body to climb a tree; it also eats vegetables, 
and it will break up a hive to get at the honey; it eats crabs and 
ants also, and is in a general way carnivorous. It is so powerful 
that it will attack not only the deer but the wild boar, if it can 
take it unawares, and also the bull. After coming to close 
quarters with the bull it falls on its back in front of the animal, 
and, when the bull proceeds to butt, the bear seizes hold of the 
bull's horns with its front paws, fastens its teeth into his 
shoulder, and drags him down to the ground. For a short time 
together it can walk erect on its hind legs. All the flesh it eats it 
first allows to become carrion. 

The lion, like all other savage and jag-toothed animals, is 
carnivorous. It devours its food greedily and fiercely, and often 
swallows its prey entire without rending it at all; it will then go 
fasting for two or three days together, being rendered capable of 
this abstinence by its previous surfeit. It is a spare drinker. It 
discharges the solid residuum in small quantities, about every 
other day or at irregular intervals, and the substance of it is 
hard and dry like the excrement of a dog. The wind discharged 
from off its stomach is pungent, and its urine emits a strong 
odour, a phenomenon which, in the case of dogs, accounts for 



1687 



their habit of sniffing at trees; for, by the way, the lion, like the 
dog, lifts its leg to void its urine. It infects the food it eats with a 
strong smell by breathing on it, and when the animal is cut 
open an overpowering vapour exhales from its inside. 

Some wild quadrupeds feed in lakes and rivers; the seal is the 
only one that gets its living on the sea. To the former class of 
animals belong the so-called castor, the satyrium, the otter, and 
the so-called latax, or beaver. The beaver is flatter than the otter 
and has strong teeth; it often at night-time emerges from the 
water and goes nibbling at the bark of the aspens that fringe the 
riversides. The otter will bite a man, and it is said that whenever 
it bites it will never let go until it hears a bone crack. The hair of 
the beaver is rough, intermediate in appearance between the 
hair of the seal and the hair of the deer. 



Jag-toothed animals drink by lapping, as do also some animals 
with teeth differently formed, as the mouse. Animals whose 
upper and lower teeth meet evenly drink by suction, as the 
horse and the ox; the bear neither laps nor sucks, but gulps 
down his drink. Birds, a rule, drink by suction, but the long 
necked birds stop and elevate their heads at intervals; the 
purple coot is the only one (of the long-necked birds) that 
swallows water by gulps. 

Horned animals, domesticated or wild, and all such as are not 
jag-toothed, are all frugivorous and graminivorous, save under 
great stress of hunger. The pig is an exception, it cares little for 
grass or fruit, but of all animals it is the fondest of roots, owing 
to the fact that its snout is peculiarly adapted for digging them 
out of the ground; it is also of all animals the most easily 



1688 



pleased in the matter of food. It takes on fat more rapidly in 
proportion to its size than any other animal; in fact, a pig can be 
fattened for the market in sixty days. Pig-dealers can tell the 
amount of flesh taken on, by having first weighed the animal 
while it was being starved. Before the fattening process begins, 
the creature must be starved for three days; and, by the way, 
animals in general will take on fat if subjected previously to a 
course of starvation; after the three days of starvation, pig- 
breeders feed the animal lavishly. Breeders in Thrace, when 
fattening pigs, give them a drink on the first day; then they miss 
one, and then two days, then three and four, until the interval 
extends over seven days. The pigs' meat used for fattening is 
composed of barley, millet, figs, acorns, wild pears, and 
cucumbers. These animals - and other animals that have warm 
bellies - are fattened by repose. (Pigs also fatten the better by 
being allowed to wallow in mud. They like to feed in batches of 
the same age. A pig will give battle even to a wolf.) If a pig be 
weighed when living, you may calculate that after death its 
flesh will weigh five-sixths of that weight, and the hair, the 
blood, and the rest will weigh the other sixth. When suckling 
their young, swine - like all other animals - get attenuated. So 
much for these animals. 



Cattle feed on corn and grass, and fatten on vegetables that 
tend to cause flatulency, such as bitter vetch or bruised beans or 
bean-stalks. The older ones also will fatten if they be fed up 
after an incision has been made into their hide, and air blown 
thereinto. Cattle will fatten also on barley in its natural state or 
on barley finely winnowed, or on sweet food, such as figs, or 
pulp from the wine-press, or on elm-leaves. But nothing is so 



1689 



fattening as the heat of the sun and wallowing in warm waters. 
If the horns of young cattle be smeared with hot wax, you may 
mold them to any shape you please, and cattle are less subject 
to disease of the hoof if you smear the horny parts with wax, 
pitch, or olive oil. Herded cattle suffer more when they are 
forced to change their pasture ground by frost than when snow 
is the cause of change. Cattle grow all the more in size when 
they are kept from sexual commerce over a number of years; 
and it is with a view to growth in size that in Epirus the so- 
called Pyrrhic kine are not allowed intercourse with the bull 
until they are nine years old; from which circumstance they are 
nicknamed the 'unbulled' kine. Of these Pyrrhic cattle, by the 
way, they say that there are only about four hundred in the 
world, that they are the private property of the Epirote royal 
family, that they cannot thrive out of Epirus, and that people 
elsewhere have tried to rear them, but without success. 



8 

Horses, mules, and asses feed on corn and grass, but are 
fattened chiefly by drink. Just in proportion as beasts of burden 
drink water, so will they more or less enjoy their food, and a 
place will give good or bad feeding according as the water is 
good or bad. Green corn, while ripening, will give a smooth coat; 
but such corn is injurious if the spikes are too stiff and sharp. 
The first crop of clover is unwholesome, and so is clover over 
which ill-scented water runs; for the clover is sure to get the 
taint of the water. Cattle like clear water for drinking; but the 
horse in this respect resembles the camel, for the camel likes 
turbid and thick water, and will never drink from a stream until 
he has trampled it into a turbid condition. And, by the way, the 



1690 



camel can go without water for as much as four days, but after 
that when he drinks, he drinks in immense quantities. 



The elephant at the most can eat nine Macedonian medimni of 
fodder at one meal; but so large an amount is unwholesome. As 
a general rule it can take six or seven medimni of fodder, five 
medimni of wheat, and five mareis of wine - six cotylae going to 
the maris. An elephant has been known to drink right off 
fourteen Macedonian metretae of water, and another metretae 
later in the day. 

Camels live for about thirty years; in some exceptional cases 
they live much longer, and instances have been known of their 
living to the age of a hundred. The elephant is said by some to 
live for about two hundred years; by others, for three hundred. 



10 

Sheep and goats are graminivorous, but sheep browse 
assiduously and steadily, whereas goats shift their ground 
rapidly, and browse only on the tips of the herbage. Sheep are 
much improved in condition by drinking, and accordingly they 
give the flocks salt every five days in summer, to the extent of 
one medimnus to the hundred sheep, and this is found to 
render a flock healthier and fatter. In fact they mix salt with the 
greater part of their food; a large amount of salt is mixed into 
their bran (for the reason that they drink more when thirsty), 
and in autumn they get cucumbers with a sprinkling of salt on 



1691 



them; this admixture of salt in their food tends also to increase 
the quantity of milk in the ewes. If sheep be kept on the move 
at midday they will drink more copiously towards evening; and 
if the ewes be fed with salted food as the lambing season draws 
near they will get larger udders. Sheep are fattened by twigs of 
the olive or of the oleaster, by vetch, and bran of every kind; and 
these articles of food fatten all the more if they be first 
sprinkled with brine. Sheep will take on flesh all the better if 
they be first put for three days through a process of starving. In 
autumn, water from the north is more wholesome for sheep 
than water from the south. Pasture grounds are all the better if 
they have a westerly aspect. 

Sheep will lose flesh if they be kept overmuch on the move or 
be subjected to any hardship. In winter time shepherds can 
easily distinguish the vigorous sheep from the weakly, from the 
fact that the vigorous sheep are covered with hoar-frost while 
the weakly ones are quite free of it; the fact being that the 
weakly ones feeling oppressed with the burden shake 
themselves and so get rid of it. The flesh of all quadrupeds 
deteriorates in marshy pastures, and is the better on high 
grounds. Sheep that have flat tails can stand the winter better 
than long-tailed sheep, and short-fleeced sheep than the 
shaggy-fleeced; and sheep with crisp wool stand the rigour of 
winter very poorly. Sheep are healthier than goats, but goats are 
stronger than sheep. (The fleeces and the wool of sheep that 
have been killed by wolves, as also the clothes made from them, 
are exceptionally infested with lice.) 



1692 



11 

Of insects, such as have teeth are omnivorous; such as have a 
tongue feed on liquids only, extracting with that organ juices 
from all quarters. And of these latter some may be called 
omnivorous, inasmuch as they feed on every kind of juice, as for 
instance, the common fly; others are blood-suckers, such as the 
gadfly and the horse-fly, others again live on the juices of fruits 
and plants. The bee is the only insect that invariably eschews 
whatever is rotten; it will touch no article of food unless it have 
a sweet-tasting juice, and it is particularly fond of drinking 
water if it be found bubbling up clear from a spring 
underground. 

So much for the food of animals of the leading genera. 



12 

The habits of animals are all connected with either breeding 
and the rearing of young, or with the procuring a due supply of 
food; and these habits are modified so as to suit cold and heat 
and the variations of the seasons. For all animals have an 
instinctive perception of the changes of temperature, and, just 
as men seek shelter in houses in winter, or as men of great 
possessions spend their summer in cool places and their winter 
in sunny ones, so also all animals that can do so shift their 
habitat at various seasons. 

Some creatures can make provision against change without 
stirring from their ordinary haunts; others migrate, quitting 
Pontus and the cold countries after the autumnal equinox to 
avoid the approaching winter, and after the spring equinox 
migrating from warm lands to cool lands to avoid the coming 



1693 



heat. In some cases they migrate from places near at hand, in 
others they may be said to come from the ends of the world, as 
in the case of the crane; for these birds migrate from the 
steppes of Scythia to the marshlands south of Egypt where the 
Nile has its source. And it is here, by the way, that they are said 
to fight with the pygmies; and the story is not fabulous, but 
there is in reality a race of dwarfish men, and the horses are 
little in proportion, and the men live in caves underground. 
Pelicans also migrate, and fly from the Strymon to the Ister, and 
breed on the banks of this river. They depart in flocks, and the 
birds in front wait for those in the rear, owing to the fact that 
when the flock is passing over the intervening mountain range, 
the birds in the rear lose sight of their companions in the van. 

Fishes also in a similar manner shift their habitat now out of 
the Euxine and now into it. In winter they move from the outer 
sea in towards land in quest of heat; in summer they shift from 
shallow waters to the deep sea to escape the heat. 

Weakly birds in winter and in frosty weather come down to the 
plains for warmth, and in summer migrate to the hills for 
coolness. The more weakly an animal is the greater hurry will it 
be in to migrate on account of extremes of temperature, either 
hot or cold; thus the mackerel migrates in advance of the 
tunnies, and the quail in advance of the cranes. The former 
migrates in the month of Boedromion, and the latter in the 
month of Maemacterion. All creatures are fatter in migrating 
from cold to heat than in migrating from heat to cold; thus the 
quail is fatter when he emigrates in autumn than when he 
arrives in spring. The migration from cold countries is 
contemporaneous with the close of the hot season. Animals are 
in better trim for breeding purposes in spring-time, when they 
change from hot to cool lands. 



1694 



Of birds, the crane, as has been said, migrates from one end of 
the world to the other; they fly against the wind. The story told 
about the stone is untrue: to wit, that the bird, so the story goes, 
carries in its inside a stone by way of ballast, and that the stone 
when vomited up is a touchstone for gold. 

The cushat and the rock-dove migrate, and never winter in our 
country, as is the case also with the turtle-dove; the common 
pigeon, however, stays behind. The quail also migrates; only, by 
the way, a few quails and turtle-doves may stay behind here and 
there in sunny districts. Cushats and turtle-doves flock together, 
both when they arrive and when the season for migration 
comes round again. When quails come to land, if it be fair 
weather or if a north wind is blowing, they will pair off and 
manage pretty comfortably; but if a southerly wind prevail they 
are greatly distressed owing to the difficulties in the way of 
flight, for a southerly wind is wet and violent. For this reason 
bird-catchers are never on the alert for these birds during fine 
weather, but only during the prevalence of southerly winds, 
when the bird from the violence of the wind is unable to fly. 
And, by the way, it is owing to the distress occasioned by the 
bulkiness of its body that the bird always screams while flying: 
for the labour is severe. When the quails come from abroad they 
have no leaders, but when they migrate hence, the glottis flits 
along with them, as does also the landrail, and the eared owl, 
and the corncrake. The corncrake calls them in the night, and 
when the birdcatchers hear the croak of the bird in the 
nighttime they know that the quails are on the move. The 
landrail is like a marsh bird, and the glottis has a tongue that 
can project far out of its beak. The eared owl is like an ordinary 
owl, only that it has feathers about its ears; by some it is called 
the night-raven. It is a great rogue of a bird, and is a capital 
mimic; a bird-catcher will dance before it and, while the bird is 
mimicking his gestures, the accomplice comes behind and 
catches it. The common owl is caught by a similar trick. 



1695 



As a general rule all birds with crooked talons are short-necked, 
flat-tongued, and disposed to mimicry. The Indian bird, the 
parrot, which is said to have a man's tongue, answers to this 
description; and, by the way, after drinking wine, the parrot 
becomes more saucy than ever. 

Of birds, the following are migratory - the crane, the swan, the 
pelican, and the lesser goose. 



13 

Of fishes, some, as has been observed, migrate from the outer 
seas in towards shore, and from the shore towards the outer 
seas, to avoid the extremes of cold and heat. 

Fish living near to the shore are better eating than deep-sea 
fish. The fact is they have more abundant and better feeding, for 
wherever the sun's heat can reach vegetation is more abundant, 
better in quality, and more delicate, as is seen in any ordinary 
garden. Further, the black shore-weed grows near to shore; the 
other shore-weed is like wild weed. Besides, the parts of the sea 
near to shore are subjected to a more equable temperature; and 
consequently the flesh of shallow-water fishes is firm and 
consistent, whereas the flesh of deep-water fishes is flaccid and 
watery. 

The following fishes are found near into the shore - the 
synodon, the black bream, the merou, the gilthead, the mullet, 
the red mullet, the wrasse, the weaver, the callionymus, the 
goby, and rock-fishes of all kinds. The following are deep-sea 
fishes - the trygon, the cartilaginous fishes, the white conger, 
the serranus, the erythrinus, and the glaucus. The braize, the 
sea-scorpion, the black conger, the muraena, and the piper or 



1696 



sea-cuckoo are found alike in shallow and deep waters. These 
fishes, however, vary for various localities; for instance, the goby 
and all rock-fish are fat off the coast of Crete. Again, the tunny 
is out of season in summer, when it is being preyed on by its 
own peculiar louse-parasite, but after the rising of Arcturus, 
when the parasite has left it, it comes into season again. A 
number of fish also are found in sea-estuaries; such as the 
saupe, the gilthead, the red mullet, and, in point of fact, the 
greater part of the gregarious fishes. The bonito also is found in 
such waters, as, for instance, off the coast of Alopeconnesus; 
and most species of fishes are found in Lake Bistonis. The coly- 
mackerel as a rule does not enter the Euxine, but passes the 
summer in the Propontis, where it spawns, and winters in the 
Aegean. The tunny proper, the pelamys, and the bonito 
penetrate into the Euxine in summer and pass the summer 
there; as do also the greater part of such fish as swim in shoals 
with the currents, or congregate in shoals together. And most 
fish congregate in shoals, and shoal-fishes in all cases have 
leaders. 

Fish penetrate into the Euxine for two reasons, and firstly for 
food. For the feeding is more abundant and better in quality 
owing to the amount of fresh river-water that discharges into 
the sea, and moreover, the large fishes of this inland sea are 
smaller than the large fishes of the outer sea. In point of fact, 
there is no large fish in the Euxine excepting the dolphin and 
the porpoise, and the dolphin is a small variety; but as soon as 
you get into the outer sea the big fishes are on the big scale. 
Furthermore, fish penetrate into this sea for the purpose of 
breeding; for there are recesses there favourable for spawning, 
and the fresh and exceptionally sweet water has an invigorating 
effect upon the spawn. After spawning, when the young fishes 
have attained some size, the parent fish swim out of the Euxine 
immediately after the rising of the Pleiads. If winter comes in 
with a southerly wind, they swim out with more or less of 



1697 



deliberation; but, if a north wind be blowing, they swim out with 
greater rapidity, from the fact that the breeze is favourable to 
their own course. And, by the way, the young fish are caught 
about this time in the neighbourhood of Byzantium very small 
in size, as might have been expected from the shortness of their 
sojourn in the Euxine. The shoals in general are visible both as 
they quit and enter the Euxine. The trichiae, however, only can 
be caught during their entry, but are never visible during their 
exit; in point of fact, when a trichia is caught running outwards 
in the neighbourhood of Byzantium, the fishermen are 
particularly careful to cleanse their nets, as the circumstance is 
so singular and exceptional. The way of accounting for this 
phenomenon is that this fish, and this one only, swims 
northwards into the Danube, and then at the point of its 
bifurcation swims down southwards into the Adriatic. And, as a 
proof that this theory is correct, the very opposite phenomenon 
presents itself in the Adriatic; that is to say, they are not caught 
in that sea during their entry, but are caught during their exit. 

Tunny-fish swim into the Euxine keeping the shore on their 
right, and swim out of it with the shore upon their left. It is 
stated that they do so as being naturally weak-sighted, and 
seeing better with the right eye. 

During the daytime shoal-fish continue on their way, but during 
the night they rest and feed. But if there be moonlight, they 
continue their journey without resting at all. Some people 
accustomed to sea-life assert that shoal-fish at the period of the 
winter solstice never move at all, but keep perfectly still 
wherever they may happen to have been overtaken by the 
solstice, and this lasts until the equinox. 

The coly-mackerel is caught more frequently on entering than 
on quitting the Euxine. And in the Propontis the fish is at its 
best before the spawning season. Shoal-fish, as a rule, are 



1698 



caught in greater quantities as they leave the Euxine, and at 
that season they are in the best condition. At the time of their 
entrance they are caught in very plump condition close to 
shore, but those are in comparatively poor condition that are 
caught farther out to sea. Very often, when the coly-mackerel 
and the mackerel are met by a south wind in their exit, there 
are better catches to the southward than in the neighbourhood 
of Byzantium. So much then for the phenomenon of migration 
of fishes. 

Now the same phenomenon is observed in fishes as in 
terrestrial animals in regard to hibernation: in other words, 
during winter fishes take to concealing themselves in out of the 
way places, and quit their places of concealment in the warmer 
season. But, by the way, animals go into concealment by way of 
refuge against extreme heat, as well as against extreme cold. 
Sometimes an entire genus will thus seek concealment; in other 
cases some species will do so and others will not. For instance, 
the shell-fish seek concealment without exception, as is seen in 
the case of those dwelling in the sea, the purple murex, the 
ceryx, and all such like; but though in the case of the detached 
species the phenomenon is obvious - for they hide themselves, 
as is seen in the scallop, or they are provided with an 
operculum on the free surface, as in the case of land snails - in 
the case of the non-detached the concealment is not so clearly 
observed. They do not go into hiding at one and the same 
season; but the snails go in winter, the purple murex and the 
ceryx for about thirty days at the rising of the Dog-star, and the 
scallop at about the same period. But for the most part they go 
into concealment when the weather is either extremely cold or 
extremely hot. 



1699 



14 

Insects almost all go into hiding, with the exception of such of 
them as live in human habitations or perish before the 
completion of the year. They hide in the winter; some of them 
for several days, others for only the coldest days, as the bee. For 
the bee also goes into hiding: and the proof that it does so is 
that during a certain period bees never touch the food set before 
them, and if a bee creeps out of the hive, it is quite transparent, 
with nothing whatsoever in its stomach; and the period of its 
rest and hiding lasts from the setting of the Pleiads until 
springtime. 

Animals take their winter-sleep or summer-sleep by concealing 
themselves in warm places, or in places where they have been 
used to lie concealed. 



15 

Several blooded animals take this sleep, such as the pholidotes 
or tessellates, namely, the serpent, the lizard, the gecko, and the 
river, crocodile, all of which go into hiding for four months in 
the depth of winter, and during that time eat nothing. Serpents 
in general burrow under ground for this purpose; the viper 
conceals itself under a stone. 

A great number of fishes also take this sleep, and notably, the 
hippurus and coracinus in winter time; for, whereas fish in 
general may be caught at all periods of the year more or less, 
there is this singularity observed in these fishes, that they are 
caught within a certain fixed period of the year, and never by 
any chance out of it. The muraena also hides, and the orphus or 
sea-perch, and the conger. Rock-fish pair off, male and female, 



1700 



for hiding (just as for breeding); as is observed in the case of the 
species of wrasse called the thrush and the owzel, and in the 
perch. 

The tunny also takes a sleep in winter in deep waters, and gets 
exceedingly fat after the sleep. The fishing season for the tunny 
begins at the rising of the Pleiads and lasts, at the longest, down 
to the setting of Arcturus; during the rest of the year they are 
hid and enjoying immunity. About the time of hibernation a few 
tunnies or other hibernating fishes are caught while swimming 
about, in particularly warm localities and in exceptionally fine 
weather, or on nights of full moon; for the fishes are induced (by 
the warmth or the light) to emerge for a while from their lair in 
quest of food. 

Most fishes are at their best for the table during the summer or 
winter sleep. 

The primas-tunny conceals itself in the mud; this may be 
inferred from the fact that during a particular period the fish is 
never caught, and that, when it is caught after that period, it is 
covered with mud and has its fins damaged. In the spring these 
tunnies get in motion and proceed towards the coast, coupling 
and breeding, and the females are now caught full of spawn. At 
this time they are considered as in season, but in autumn and 
in winter as of inferior quality; at this time also the males are 
full of milt. When the spawn is small, the fish is hard to catch, 
but it is easily caught when the spawn gets large, as the fish is 
then infested by its parasite. Some fish burrow for sleep in the 
sand and some in mud, just keeping their mouths outside. 

Most fishes hide, then, during the winter only, but crustaceans, 
the rock-fish, the ray, and the cartilaginous species hide only 
during extremely severe weather, and this may be inferred from 
the fact that these fishes are never by any chance caught when 
the weather is extremely cold. Some fishes, however, hide 



1701 



during the summer, as the glaucus or grey-back; this fish hides 
in summer for about sixty days. The hake also and the gilthead 
hide; and we infer that the hake hides over a lengthened period 
from the fact that it is only caught at long intervals. We are led 
also to infer that fishes hide in summer from the circumstance 
that the takes of certain fish are made between the rise and 
setting of certain constellations: of the Dog-star in particular, 
the sea at this period being upturned from the lower depths. 
This phenomenon may be observed to best advantage in the 
Bosporus; for the mud is there brought up to the surface and 
the fish are brought up along with it. They say also that very 
often, when the sea-bottom is dredged, more fish will be caught 
by the second haul than by the first one. Furthermore, after very 
heavy rains numerous specimens become visible of creatures 
that at other times are never seen at all or seen only at 
intervals. 



16 

A great number of birds also go into hiding; they do not all 
migrate, as is generally supposed, to warmer countries. Thus, 
certain birds (as the kite and the swallow) when they are not far 
off from places of this kind, in which they have their permanent 
abode, betake themselves thither; others, that are at a distance 
from such places, decline the trouble of migration and simply 
hide themselves where they are. Swallows, for instance, have 
been often found in holes, quite denuded of their feathers, and 
the kite on its first emergence from torpidity has been seen to 
fly from out some such hiding-place. And with regard to this 
phenomenon of periodic torpor there is no distinction observed, 
whether the talons of a bird be crooked or straight; for instance, 
the stork, the owzel, the turtle-dove, and the lark, all go into 



1702 



hiding. The case of the turtledove is the most notorious of all, 
for we would defy any one to assert that he had anywhere seen 
a turtle-dove in winter-time; at the beginning of the hiding time 
it is exceedingly plump, and during this period it moults, but 
retains its plumpness. Some cushats hide; others, instead of 
hiding, migrate at the same time as the swallow. The thrush and 
the starling hide; and of birds with crooked talons the kite and 
the owl hide for a few days. 



17 

Of viviparous quadrupeds the porcupine and the bear retire into 
concealment. The fact that the bear hides is well established, 
but there are doubts as to its motive for so doing, whether it be 
by reason of the cold or from some other cause. About this 
period the male and the female become so fat as to be hardly 
capable of motion. The female brings forth her young at this 
time, and remains in concealment until it is time to bring the 
cubs out; and she brings them out in spring, about three 
months after the winter solstice. The bear hides for at least 
forty days; during fourteen of these days it is said not to move 
at all, but during most of the subsequent days it moves, and 
from time to time wakes up. A she-bear in pregnancy has either 
never been caught at all or has been caught very seldom. There 
can be no doubt but that during this period they eat nothing; for 
in the first place they never emerge from their hiding-place, and 
further, when they are caught, their belly and intestines are 
found to be quite empty. It is also said that from no food being 
taken the gut almost closes up, and that in consequence the 
animal on first emerging takes to eating arum with the view of 
opening up and distending the gut. 



1703 



The dormouse actually hides in a tree, and gets very fat at that 
period; as does also the white mouse of Pontus. 

(Of animals that hide or go torpid some slough off what is called 
their 'old-age'. This name is applied to the outermost skin, and 
to the casing that envelops the developing organism.) 

In discussing the case of terrestrial vivipara we stated that the 
reason for the bear's seeking concealment is an open question. 
We now proceed to treat of the tessellates. The tessellates for 
the most part go into hiding, and if their skin is soft they slough 
off their 'old-age', but not if the skin is shell-like, as is the shell 
of the tortoise - for, by the way, the tortoise and the fresh water 
tortoise belong to the tessellates. Thus, the old-age is sloughed 
off by the gecko, the lizard, and above all, by serpents; and they 
slough off the skin in springtime when emerging from their 
torpor, and again in the autumn. Vipers also slough off their 
skin both in spring and in autumn, and it is not the case, as 
some aver, that this species of the serpent family is exceptional 
in not sloughing. When the serpent begins to slough, the skin 
peels off at first from the eyes, so that any one ignorant of the 
phenomenon would suppose the animal were going blind; after 
that it peels off the head, and so on, until the creature presents 
to view only a white surface all over. The sloughing goes on for a 
day and a night, beginning with the head and ending with the 
tail. During the sloughing of the skin an inner layer comes to 
the surface, for the creature emerges just as the embryo from its 
afterbirth. 

All insects that slough at all slough in the same way; as the 
silphe, and the empis or midge, and all the coleoptera, as for 
instance the cantharus-beetle. They all slough after the period 
of development; for just as the afterbirth breaks from off the 
young of the vivipara so the outer husk breaks off from around 
the young of the vermipara, in the same way both with the bee 



1704 



and the grasshopper. The cicada the moment after issuing from 
the husk goes and sits upon an olive tree or a reed; after the 
breaking up of the husk the creature issues out, leaving a little 
moisture behind, and after a short interval flies up into the air 
and sets a. chirping. 

Of marine animals the crawfish and the lobster slough 
sometimes in the spring, and sometimes in autumn after 
parturition. Lobsters have been caught occasionally with the 
parts about the thorax soft, from the shell having there peeled 
off, and the lower parts hard, from the shell having not yet 
peeled off there; for, by the way, they do not slough in the same 
manner as the serpent. The crawfish hides for about five 
months. Crabs also slough off their old-age; this is generally 
allowed with regard to the soft-shelled crabs, and it is said to be 
the case with the testaceous kind, as for instance with the large 
'granny' crab. When these animals slough their shell becomes 
soft all over, and as for the crab, it can scarcely crawl. These 
animals also do not cast their skins once and for all, but over 
and over again. 

So much for the animals that go into hiding or torpidity, for the 
times at which, and the ways in which, they go; and so much 
also for the animals that slough off their old-age, and for the 
times at which they undergo the process. 



18 

Animals do not all thrive at the same seasons, nor do they 
thrive alike during all extremes of weather. Further animals of 
diverse species are in a diverse way healthy or sickly at certain 
seasons; and, in point of fact, some animals have ailments that 
are unknown to others. Birds thrive in times of drought, both in 



1705 



their general health and in regard to parturition, and this is 
especially the case with the cushat; fishes, however, with a few 
exceptions, thrive best in rainy weather; on the contrary rainy 
seasons are bad for birds - and so by the way is much drinking - 
and drought is bad for fishes. Birds of prey, as has been already 
stated, may in a general way be said never to drink at all, 
though Hesiod appears to have been ignorant of the fact, for in 
his story about the siege of Ninus he represents the eagle that 
presided over the auguries as in the act of drinking; all other 
birds drink, but drink sparingly, as is the case also with all other 
spongy-lunged oviparous animals. Sickness in birds may be 
diagnosed from their plumage, which is ruffled when they are 
sickly instead of lying smooth as when they are well. 



19 

The majority of fishes, as has been stated, thrive best in rainy 
seasons. Not only have they food in greater abundance at this 
time, but in a general way rain is wholesome for them just as it 
is for vegetation - for, by the way, kitchen vegetables, though 
artificially watered, derive benefit from rain; and the same 
remark applies even to reeds that grow in marshes, as they 
hardly grow at all without a rainfall. That rain is good for fishes 
may be inferred from the fact that most fishes migrate to the 
Euxine for the summer; for owing to the number of the rivers 
that discharge into this sea its water is exceptionally fresh, and 
the rivers bring down a large supply of food. Besides, a great 
number of fishes, such as the bonito and the mullet, swim up 
the rivers and thrive in the rivers and marshes. The sea- 
gudgeon also fattens in the rivers, and, as a rule, countries 
abounding in lagoons furnish unusually excellent fish. While 
most fishes, then, are benefited by rain, they are chiefly 



1706 



benefited by summer rain; or we may state the case thus, that 
rain is good for fishes in spring, summer, and autumn, and fine 
dry weather in winter. As a general rule what is good for men is 
good for fishes also. 

Fishes do not thrive in cold places, and those fishes suffer most 
in severe winters that have a stone in their head, as the 
chromis, the basse, the sciaena, and the braize; for owing to the 
stone they get frozen with the cold, and are thrown up on shore. 

Whilst rain is wholesome for most fishes, it is, on the contrary, 
unwholesome for the mullet, the cephalus, and the so-called 
marinus, for rain superinduces blindness in most of these 
fishes, and all the more rapidly if the rainfall be superabundant. 
The cephalus is peculiarly subject to this malady in severe 
winters; their eyes grow white, and when caught they are in 
poor condition, and eventually the disease kills them. It would 
appear that this disease is due to extreme cold even more than 
to an excessive rainfall; for instance, in many places and more 
especially in shallows off the coast of Nauplia, in the Argolid, a 
number of fishes have been known to be caught out at sea in 
seasons of severe cold. The gilthead also suffers in winter; the 
acharnas suffers in summer, and loses condition. The coracine 
is exceptional among fishes in deriving benefit from drought, 
and this is due to the fact that heat and drought are apt to come 
together. 

Particular places suit particular fishes; some are naturally fishes 
of the shore, and some of the deep sea, and some are at home 
in one or the other of these regions, and others are common to 
the two and are at home in both. Some fishes will thrive in one 
particular spot, and in that spot only. As a general rule it may be 
said that places abounding in weeds are wholesome; at all 
events, fishes caught in such places are exceptionally fat: that 
is, such fishes a a habit all sorts of localities as well. The fact is 



1707 



that weed-eating fishes find abundance of their special food in 
such localities, and carnivorous fish find an unusually large 
number of smaller fish. It matters also whether the wind be 
from the north or south: the longer fish thrive better when a 
north wind prevails, and in summer at one and the same spot 
more long fish will be caught than flat fish with a north wind 
blowing. 

The tunny and the sword-fish are infested with a parasite about 
the rising of the Dog-star; that is to say, about this time both 
these fishes have a grub beside their fins that is nicknamed the 
'gadfly'. It resembles the scorpion in shape, and is about the size 
of the spider. So acute is the pain it inflicts that the sword-fish 
will often leap as high out of the water as a dolphin; in fact, it 
sometimes leaps over the bulwarks of a vessel and falls back on 
the deck. The tunny delights more than any other fish in the 
heat of the sun. It will burrow for warmth in the sand in shallow 
waters near to shore, or will, because it is warm, disport itself 
on the surface of the sea. 

The fry of little fishes escape by being overlooked, for it is only 
the larger ones of the small species that fishes of the large 
species will pursue. The greater part of the spawn and the fry of 
fishes is destroyed by the heat of the sun, for whatever of them 
the sun reaches it spoils. 

Fishes are caught in greatest abundance before sunrise and 
after sunset, or, speaking generally, just about sunset and 
sunrise. Fishermen haul up their nets at these times, and speak 
of the hauls then made as the 'nick-of-time' hauls. The fact is, 
that at these times fishes are particularly weak-sighted; at night 
they are at rest, and as the light grows stronger they see 
comparatively well. 

We know of no pestilential malady attacking fishes, such as 
those which attack man, and horses and oxen among the 



1708 



quadrupedal vivipara, and certain species of other genera, 
domesticated and wild; but fishes do seem to suffer from 
sickness; and fishermen infer this from the fact that at times 
fishes in poor condition, and looking as though they were sick, 
and of altered colour, are caught in a large haul of well- 
conditioned fish of their own species. So much for sea-fishes. 



20 

River-fish and lake-fish also are exempt from diseases of a 
pestilential character, but certain species are subject to special 
and peculiar maladies. For instance, the sheat-fish just before 
the rising of the Dog-star, owing to its swimming near the 
surface of the water, is liable to sunstroke, and is paralysed by a 
loud peal of thunder. The carp is subject to the same 
eventualities but in a lesser degree. The sheatfish is destroyed in 
great quantities in shallow waters by the serpent called the 
dragon. In the balerus and tilon a worm is engendered about the 
rising of the Dog-star, that sickens these fish and causes them 
to rise towards the surface, where they are killed by the 
excessive heat. The chalcis is subject to a very violent malady; 
lice are engendered underneath their gills in great numbers, 
and cause destruction among them; but no other species of fish 
is subject to any such malady. 

If mullein be introduced into water it will kill fish in its vicinity. 
It is used extensively for catching fish in rivers and ponds; by 
the Phoenicians it is made use of also in the sea. 

There are two other methods employed for catch-fish. It is a 
known fact that in winter fishes emerge from the deep parts of 
rivers and, by the way, at all seasons fresh water is tolerably 
cold. A trench accordingly is dug leading into a river, and 



1709 



wattled at the river end with reeds and stones, an aperture 
being left in the wattling through which the river water flows 
into the trench; when the frost comes on the fish can be taken 
out of the trench in weels. Another method is adopted in 
summer and winter alike. They run across a stream a dam 
composed of brushwood and stones leaving a small open space, 
and in this space they insert a weel; they then coop the fish in 
towards this place, and draw them up in the weel as they swim 
through the open space. 

Shell-fish, as a rule, are benefited by rainy weather. The purple 
murex is an exception; if it be placed on a shore near to where a 
river discharges, it will die within a day after tasting the fresh 
water. The murex lives for about fifty days after capture; during 
this period they feed off one another, as there grows on the 
shell a kind of sea-weed or sea-moss; if any food is thrown to 
them during this period, it is said to be done not to keep them 
alive, but to make them weigh more. 

To shell-fish in general drought is unwholesome. During dry 
weather they decrease in size and degenerate in quality; and it 
is during such weather that the red scallop is found in more 
than usual abundance. In the Pyrrhaean Strait the clam was 
exterminated, partly by the dredging-machine used in their 
capture, and partly by long-continued droughts. Rainy weather 
is wholesome to the generality of shellfish owing to the fact 
that the sea-water then becomes exceptionally sweet. In the 
Euxine, owing to the coldness of the climate, shellfish are not 
found: nor yet in rivers, excepting a few bivalves here and there. 
Univalves, by the way, are very apt to freeze to death in 
extremely cold weather. So much for animals that live in water. 



1710 



21 

To turn to quadrupeds, the pig suffers from three diseases, one 
of which is called branchos, a disease attended with swellings 
about the windpipe and the jaws. It may break out in any part of 
the body; very often it attacks the foot, and occasionally the ear; 
the neighbouring parts also soon rot, and the decay goes on 
until it reaches the lungs, when the animal succumbs. The 
disease develops with great rapidity, and the moment it sets in 
the animal gives up eating. The swineherds know but one way 
to cure it, namely, by complete excision, when they detect the 
first signs of the disease. There are two other diseases, which 
are both alike termed craurus. The one is attended with pain 
and heaviness in the head, and this is the commoner of the two, 
the other with diarrhoea. The latter is incurable, the former is 
treated by applying wine fomentations to the snout and rinsing 
the nostrils with wine. Even this disease is very hard to cure; it 
has been known to kill within three or four days. The animal is 
chiefly subject to branchos when it gets extremely fat, and 
when the heat has brought a good supply of figs. The treatment 
is to feed on mashed mulberries, to give repeated warm baths, 
and to lance the under part of the tongue. 

Pigs with flabby flesh are subject to measles about the legs, 
neck, and shoulders, for the pimples develop chiefly in these 
parts. If the pimples are few in number the flesh is 
comparatively sweet, but if they be numerous it gets watery and 
flaccid. The symptoms of measles are obvious, for the pimples 
show chiefly on the under side of the tongue, and if you pluck 
the bristles off the chine the skin will appear suffused with 
blood, and further the animal will be unable to keep its hind- 
feet at rest. Pigs never take this disease while they are mere 
sucklings. The pimples may be got rid of by feeding on this kind 
of spelt called tiphe; and this spelt, by the way, is very good for 
ordinary food. The best food for rearing and fattening pigs is 



1711 



chickpeas and figs, but the one thing essential is to vary the 
food as much as possible, for this animal, like animals in 
general lights in a change of diet; and it is said that one kind of 
food blows the animal out, that another superinduces flesh, and 
that another puts on fat, and that acorns, though liked by the 
animal, render the flesh flaccid. Besides, if a sow eats acorns in 
great quantities, it will miscarry, as is also the case with the 
ewe; and, indeed, the miscarriage is more certain in the case of 
the ewe than in the case of the sow. The pig is the only animal 
known to be subject to measles. 



22 

Dogs suffer from three diseases; rabies, quinsy, and sore feet. 
Rabies drives the animal mad, and ary animal whatever, 
excepting man, will take the disease if bitten by a dog so 
afflicted; the disease is fatal to the dog itself, and to any animal 
it may bite, man excepted. Quinsy also is fatal to dogs; and only 
a few recover from disease of the feet. The camel, like the dog, is 
subject to rabies. The elephant, which is reputed to enjoy 
immunity from all other illnesses, is occasionally subject to 
flatulency. 



23 

Cattle in herds are liable to two diseases, foot, sickness and 
craurus. In the former their feet suffer from eruptions, but the 
animal recovers from the disease without even the loss of the 
hoof. It is found of service to smear the horny parts with warm 



1712 



pitch. In craurus, the breath comes warm at short intervals; in 
fact, craurus in cattle answers to fever in man. The symptoms of 
the disease are drooping of the ears and disinclination for food. 
The animal soon succumbs, and when the carcase is opened 
the lungs are found to be rotten. 



24 

Horses out at pasture are free from all diseases excepting 
disease of the feet. From this disease they sometimes lose their 
hooves: but after losing them they grow them soon again, for as 
one hoof is decaying it is being replaced by another. Symptoms 
of the malady are a sinking in and wrinkling of the lip in the 
middle under the nostrils, and in the case of the male, a 
twitching of the right testicle. 

Stall-reared horses are subject to very numerous forms of 
disease. They are liable to disease called 'eileus'. Under this 
disease the animal trails its hind-legs under its belly so far 
forward as almost to fall back on its haunches; if it goes without 
food for several days and turns rabid, it may be of service to 
draw blood, or to castrate the male. The animal is subject also to 
tetanus: the veins get rigid, as also the head and neck, and the 
animal walks with its legs stretched out straight. The horse 
suffers also from abscesses. Another painful illness afflicts 
them called the 'barley-surfeit'. The are a softening of the palate 
and heat of the breath; the animal may recover through the 
strength of its own constitution, but no formal remedies are of 
any avail. 

There is also a disease called nymphia, in which the animal is 
said to stand still and droop its head on hearing flute-music; if 
during this ailment the horse be mounted, it will run off at a 



1713 



gallop until it is pulled. Even with this rabies in full force, it 
preserves a dejected spiritless appearance; some of the 
symptoms are a throwing back of the ears followed by a 
projection of them, great languor, and heavy breathing. Heart- 
ache also is incurable, of which the symptom is a drawing in of 
the flanks; and so is displacement of the bladder, which is 
accompanied by a retention of urine and a drawing up of the 
hooves and haunches. Neither is there any cure if the animal 
swallow the grape-beetle, which is about the size of the 
sphondyle or knuckle-beetle. The bite of the shrewmouse is 
dangerous to horses and other draught animals as well; it is 
followed by boils. The bite is all the more dangerous if the 
mouse be pregnant when she bites, for the boils then burst, but 
do not burst otherwise. The cicigna-called 'chalcis' by some, and 
'zignis' by others - either causes death by its bite or, at all 
events, intense pain; it is like a small lizard, with the colour of 
the blind snake. In point of fact, according to experts, the horse 
and the sheep have pretty well as many ailments as the human 
species. The drug known under the name of 'sandarace' or 
realgar, is extremely injurious to a horse, and to all draught 
animals; it is given to the animal as a medicine in a solution of 
water, the liquid being filtered through a colander. The mare 
when pregnant apt to miscarry when disturbed by the odour of 
an extinguished candle; and a similar accident happens 
occasionally to women in their pregnancy. So much for the 
diseases of the horse. 

The so-called hippomanes grows, as has stated, on the foal, and 
the mare nibbles it off as she licks and cleans the foal. All the 
curious stories connected with the hippomanes are due to old 
wives and to the venders of charms. What is called the 'polium' 
or foal's membrane, is, as all the accounts state, delivered by the 
mother before the foal appears. 



1714 



A horse will recognize the neighing of any other horse with 
which it may have fought at any previous period. The horse 
delights in meadows and marshes, and likes to drink muddy 
water; in fact, if water be clear, the horse will trample in it to 
make it turbid, will then drink it, and afterwards will wallow in 
it. The animal is fond of water in every way, whether for 
drinking or for bathing purposes; and this explains the peculiar 
constitution of the hippopotamus or river-horse. In regard to 
water the ox is the opposite of the horse; for if the water be 
impure or cold, or mixed up with alien matter, it will refuse to 
drink it. 



25 

The ass suffers chiefly from one particular disease which they 
call 'melis'. It arises first in the head, and a clammy humour 
runs down the nostrils, thick and red; if it stays in the head the 
animal may recover, but if it descends into the lungs the animal 
will die. Of all animals on its of its kind it is the least capable of 
enduring extreme cold, which circumstance will account for the 
fact that the animal is not found on the shores of the Euxine, 
nor in Scythia. 



26 

Elephants suffer from flatulence, and when thus afflicted can 
void neither solid nor liquid residuum. If the elephant swallow 
earth-mould it suffers from relaxation; but if it go on taking it 
steadily, it will experience no harm. From time to time it takes 



1715 



to swallowing stones. It suffers also from diarrhoea: in this case 
they administer draughts of lukewarm water or dip its fodder in 
honey, and either one or the other prescription will prove a 
costive. When they suffer from insomnia, they will be restored 
to health if their shoulders be rubbed with salt, olive-oil, and 
warm water; when they have aches in their shoulders they will 
derive great benefit from the application of roast pork. Some 
elephants like olive oil, and others do not. If there is a bit of iron 
in the inside of an elephant it is said that it will pass out if the 
animal takes a drink of olive-oil; if the animal refuses olive-oil, 
they soak a root in the oil and give it the root to swallow. So 
much, then, for quadrupeds. 



27 

Insects, as a general rule, thrive best in the time of year in 
which they come into being, especially if the season be moist 
and warm, as in spring. 

In bee-hives are found creatures that do great damage to the 
combs; for instance, the grub that spins a web and ruins the 
honeycomb: it is called the 'cleros'. It engenders an insect like 
itself, of a spider-shape, and brings disease into the swarm. 
There is another insect resembling the moth, called by some the 
'pyraustes', that flies about a lighted candle: this creature 
engenders a brood full of a fine down. It is never stung by a bee, 
and can only be got out of a hive by fumigation. A caterpillar 
also is engendered in hives, of a species nicknamed the teredo, 
or 'borer', with which creature the bee never interferes. Bees 
suffer most when flowers are covered with mildew, or in 
seasons of drought. 



1716 



All insects, without exception, die if they be smeared over with 
oil; and they die all the more rapidly if you smear their head 
with the oil and lay them out in the sun. 



28 

Variety in animal life may be produced by variety of locality: 
thus in one place an animal will not be found at all, in another 
it will be small, or short-lived, or will not thrive. Sometimes this 
sort of difference is observed in closely adjacent districts. Thus, 
in the territory of Miletus, in one district cicadas are found 
while there are none in the district close adjoining; and in 
Cephalenia there is a river on one side of which the cicada is 
found and not on the other. In Pordoselene there is a public road 
one side of which the weasel is found but not on the other. In 
Boeotia the mole is found in great abundance in the 
neighbourhood of Orchomenus, but there are none in Lebadia 
though it is in the immediate vicinity, and if a mole be 
transported from the one district to the other it will refuse to 
burrow in the soil. The hare cannot live in Ithaca if introduced 
there; in fact it will be found dead, turned towards the point of 
the beach where it was landed. The horseman-ant is not found 
in Sicily; the croaking frog has only recently appeared in the 
neighbourhood of Cyrene. In the whole of Libya there is neither 
wild boar, nor stag, nor wild goat; and in India, according to 
Ctesias - no very good authority, by the way - there are no 
swine, wild or tame, but animals that are devoid of blood and 
such as go into hiding or go torpid are all of immense size there. 
In the Euxine there are no small molluscs nor testaceans, 
except a few here and there; but in the Red Sea all the 
testaceans are exceedingly large. In Syria the sheep have tails a 
cubit in breadth; the goats have ears a span and a palm long, 



1717 



and some have ears that flap down to the ground; and the cattle 
have humps on their shoulders, like the camel. In Lycia goats 
are shorn for their fleece, just as sheep are in all other 
countries. In Libya the long-horned ram is born with horns, and 
not the ram only, as Homer' words it, but the ewe as well; in 
Pontus, on the confines of Scythia, the ram is without horns. 

In Egypt animals, as a rule, are larger than their congeners in 
Greece, as the cow and the sheep; but some are less, as the dog, 
the wolf, the hare, the fox, the raven, and the hawk; others are 
of pretty much the same size, as the crow and the goat. The 
difference, where it exists, is attributed to the food, as being 
abundant in one case and insufficient in another, for instance 
for the wolf and the hawk; for provision is scanty for the 
carnivorous animals, small birds being scarce; food is scanty 
also for the hare and for all frugivorous animals, because 
neither the nuts nor the fruit last long. 

In many places the climate will account for peculiarities; thus in 
Illyria, Thrace, and Epirus the ass is small, and in Gaul and in 
Scythia the ass is not found at all owing to the coldness of the 
climate of these countries. In Arabia the lizard is more than a 
cubit in length, and the mouse is much larger than our field- 
mouse, with its hind-legs a span long and its front legs the 
length of the first finger-joint. In Libya, according to all 
accounts, the length of the serpents is something appalling; 
sailors spin a yarn to the effect that some crews once put 
ashore and saw the bones of a number of oxen, and that they 
were sure that the oxen had been devoured by serpents, for, just 
as they were putting out to sea, serpents came chasing their 
galleys at full speed and overturned one galley and set upon the 
crew. Again, lions are more numerous in Libya, and in that 
district of Europe that lies between the Achelous and the 
Nessus; the leopard is more abundant in Asia Minor, and is not 
found in Europe at all. As a general rule, wild animals are at 



1718 



their wildest in Asia, at their boldest in Europe, and most 
diverse in form in Libya; in fact, there is an old saying, 'Always 
something fresh in Libya.' 

It would appear that in that country animals of diverse species 
meet, on account of the rainless climate, at the watering-places, 
and there pair together; and that such pairs will often breed if 
they be nearly of the same size and have periods of gestation of 
the same length. For it is said that they are tamed down in their 
behaviour towards each other by extremity of thirst. And, by the 
way, unlike animals elsewhere, they require to drink more in 
wintertime than in summer: for they acquire the habit of not 
drinking in summer, owing to the circumstance that there is 
usually no water then; and the mice, if they drink, die. 
Elsewhere also bastard-animals are born to heterogeneous 
pairs; thus in Cyrene the wolf and the bitch will couple and 
breed; and the Laconian hound is a cross between the fox and 
the dog. They say that the Indian dog is a cross between the 
tiger and the bitch, not the first cross, but a cross in the third 
generation; for they say that the first cross is a savage creature. 
They take the bitch to a lonely spot and tie her up: if the tiger be 
in an amorous mood he will pair with her; if not he will eat her 
up, and this casualty is of frequent occurrence. 



29 

Locality will differentiate habits also: for instance, rugged 
highlands will not produce the same results as the soft 
lowlands. The animals of the highlands look fiercer and bolder, 
as is seen in the swine of Mount Athos; for a lowland boar is no 
match even for a mountain sow. 



1719 



Again, locality is an important element in regard to the bite of 
an animal. Thus, in Pharos and other places, the bite of the 
scorpion is not dangerous; elsewhere - in Caria, for instances - 
where scorpions are venomous as well as plentiful and of large 
size, the sting is fatal to man or beast, even to the pig, and 
especially to a black pig, though the pig, by the way, is in general 
most singularly indifferent to the bite of any other creature. If a 
pig goes into water after being struck by the scorpion of Caria, it 
will surely die. 

There is great variety in the effects produced by the bites of 
serpents. The asp is found in Libya; the so-called 'septic' drug is 
made from the body of the animal, and is the only remedy 
known for the bite of the original. Among the silphium, also, a 
snake is found, for the bite or which a certain stone is said to be 
a cure: a stone that is brought from the grave of an ancient king, 
which stone is put into water and drunk off. In certain parts of 
Italy the bite of the gecko is fatal. But the deadliest of all bites of 
venomous creatures is when one venomous animal has bitten 
another; as, for instance, a viper's after it has bitten a scorpion. 
To the great majority of such creatures man's is fatal. There is a 
very little snake, by some entitled the 'holy-snake', which is 
dreaded by even the largest serpents. It is about an ell long, and 
hairy-looking; whenever it bites an animal, the flesh all round 
the wound will at once mortify. There is in India a small snake 
which is exceptional in this respect, that for its bite no specific 
whatever is known. 



30 

Animals also vary as to their condition of health in connexion 
with their pregnancy. 



1720 



Testaceans, such as scallops and all the oyster- family, and 
crustaceans, such as the lobster family, are best when with 
spawn. Even in the case of the testacean we speak of spawning 
(or pregnancy); but whereas the crustaceans may be seen 
coupling and laying their spawn, this is never the case with 
testaceans. Molluscs are best in the breeding time, as the 
calamary, the sepia, and the octopus. 

Fishes, when they begin to breed, are nearly all good for the 
table; but after the female has gone long with spawn they are 
good in some cases, and in others are out of season. The 
maenis, for instance, is good at the breeding time. The female of 
this fish is round, the male longer and flatter; when the female 
is beginning to breed the male turns black and mottled, and is 
quite unfit for the table; at this period he is nicknamed the 
'goat'. 

The wrasses called the owzel and the thrush, and the smaris 
have different colours at different seasons, as is the case with 
the plumage of certain birds; that is to say, they become black in 
the spring and after the spring get white again. The phycis also 
changes its hue: in general it is white, but in spring it is mottled; 
it is the only sea-fish which is said make a bed for itself, and the 
female lays her spawn in this bed or nest. The maenis, as was 
observed, changes its colour as does the smaris, and in 
summer-time changes back from whitish to black, the change 
being especially marked about the fins and gills. The coracine, 
like the maenis, is in best condition at breeding time; the 
mullet, the basse, and scaly fishes in general are in bad 
condition at this period. A few fish are in much the same 
condition at all times, whether with spawn or not, as the 
glaucus. Old fishes also are bad eating; the old tunny is unfit 
even for pickling, as a great part of its flesh wastes away with 
age, and the same wasting is observed in all old fishes. The age 
of a scaly fish may be told by the size and the hardness of its 



1721 



scales. An old tunny has been caught weighing fifteen talents, 
with the span of its tail two cubits and a palm broad. 

River-fish and lake-fish are best after they have discharged the 
spawn in the case of the female and the milt in the case of the 
male: that is, when they have fully recovered from the 
exhaustion of such discharge. Some are good in the breeding 
time, as the saperdis, and some bad, as the sheat-fish. As a 
general rule, the male fish is better eating than the female; but 
the reverse holds good of the sheat-fish. The eels that are called 
females are the best for the table: they look as though they were 
female, but they really are not so. 



Book IX 



Of the animals that are comparatively obscure and short-lived 
the characters or dispositions are not so obvious to recognition 
as are those of animals that are longer-lived. These latter 
animals appear to have a natural capacity corresponding to 
each of the passions: to cunning or simplicity, courage or 
timidity, to good temper or to bad, and to other similar 
dispositions of mind. 

Some also are capable of giving or receiving instruction - of 
receiving it from one another or from man: those that have the 
faculty of hearing, for instance; and, not to limit the matter to 



1722 



audible sound, such as can differentiate the suggested 
meanings of word and gesture. 

In all genera in which the distinction of male and female is 
found, Nature makes a similar differentiation in the mental 
characteristics of the two sexes. This differentiation is the most 
obvious in the case of human kind and in that of the larger 
animals and the viviparous quadrupeds. In the case of these 
latter the female softer in character, is the sooner tamed, 
admits more readily of caressing, is more apt in the way of 
learning; as, for instance, in the Laconian breed of dogs the 
female is cleverer than the male. Of the Molossian breed of 
dogs, such as are employed in the chase are pretty much the 
same as those elsewhere; but sheep-dogs of this breed are 
superior to the others in size, and in the courage with which 
they face the attacks of wild animals. 

Dogs that are born of a mixed breed between these two kinds 
are remarkable for courage and endurance of hard labour. 

In all cases, excepting those of the bear and leopard, the female 
is less spirited than the male; in regard to the two exceptional 
cases, the superiority in courage rests with the female. With all 
other animals the female is softer in disposition than the male, 
is more mischievous, less simple, more impulsive, and more 
attentive to the nurture of the young: the male, on the other 
hand, is more spirited than the female, more savage, more 
simple and less cunning. The traces of these differentiated 
characteristics are more or less visible everywhere, but they are 
especially visible where character is the more developed, and 
most of all in man. 

The fact is, the nature of man is the most rounded off and 
complete, and consequently in man the qualities or capacities 
above referred to are found in their perfection. Hence woman is 
more compassionate than man, more easily moved to tears, at 



1723 



the same time is more jealous, more querulous, more apt to 
scold and to strike. She is, furthermore, more prone to 
despondency and less hopeful than the man, more void of 
shame or self-respect, more false of speech, more deceptive, 
and of more retentive memory. She is also more wakeful, more 
shrinking, more difficult to rouse to action, and requires a 
smaller quantity of nutriment. 

As was previously stated, the male is more courageous than the 
female, and more sympathetic in the way of standing by to help. 
Even in the case of molluscs, when the cuttle-fish is struck with 
the trident the male stands by to help the female; but when the 
male is struck the female runs away. 

There is enmity between such animals as dwell in the same 
localities or subsist on the food. If the means of subsistence run 
short, creatures of like kind will fight together. Thus it is said 
that seals which inhabit one and the same district will fight, 
male with male, and female with female, until one combatant 
kills the other, or one is driven away by the other; and their 
young do even in like manner. 

All creatures are at enmity with the carnivores, and the 
carnivores with all the rest, for they all subsist on living 
creatures. Soothsayers take notice of cases where animals keep 
apart from one another, and cases where they congregate 
together; calling those that live at war with one another 
'dissociates', and those that dwell in peace with one another 
'associates'. One may go so far as to say that if there were no 
lack or stint of food, then those animals that are now afraid of 
man or are wild by nature would be tame and familiar with 
him, and in like manner with one another. This is shown by the 
way animals are treated in Egypt, for owing to the fact that food 
is constantly supplied to them the very fiercest creatures live 
peaceably together. The fact is they are tamed by kindness, and 



1724 



in some places crocodiles are tame to their priestly keeper from 
being fed by him. And elsewhere also the same phenomenon is 
to be observed. 

The eagle and the snake are enemies, for the eagle lives on 
snakes; so are the ichneumon and the venom-spider, for the 
ichneumon preys upon the latter. In the case of birds, there is 
mutual enmity between the poecilis, the crested lark, the 
woodpecker (?), and the chloreus, for they devour one another's 
eggs; so also between the crow and the owl; for, owing to the 
fact that the owl is dim-sighted by day, the crow at midday 
preys upon the owl's eggs, and the owl at night upon the crow's, 
each having the whip-hand of the other, turn and turn about, 
night and day. 

There is enmity also between the owl and the wren; for the 
latter also devours the owl's eggs. In the daytime all other little 
birds flutter round the owl - a practice which is popularly 
termed 'admiring him' - buffet him, and pluck out his feathers; 
in consequence of this habit, bird-catchers use the owl as a 
decoy for catching little birds of all kinds. 

The so-called presbys or 'old man' is at war with the weasel and 
the crow, for they prey on her eggs and her brood; and so the 
turtle-dove with the pyrallis, for they live in the same districts 
and on the same food; and so with the green wood pecker and 
the libyus; and so with kite and the raven, for, owing to his 
having the advantage from stronger talons and more rapid 
flight the former can steal whatever the latter is holding, so that 
it is food also that makes enemies of these. In like manner there 
is war between birds that get their living from the sea, as 
between the brenthus, the gull, and the harpe; and so between 
the buzzard on one side and the toad and snake on the other, 
for the buzzard preys upon the eggs of the two others; and so 



1725 



between the turtle-dove and the chloreus; the chloreus kills the 
dove, and the crow kills the so-called drummer-bird. 

The aegolius, and birds of prey in general, prey upon the calaris, 
and consequently there is war between it and them; and so is 
there war between the gecko-lizard and the spider, for the 
former preys upon the latter; and so between the woodpecker 
and the heron, for the former preys upon the eggs and brood of 
the latter. And so between the aegithus and the ass, owing to 
the fact that the ass, in passing a furze-bush, rubs its sore and 
itching parts against the prickles; by so doing, and all the more 
if it brays, it topples the eggs and the brood out of the nest, the 
young ones tumble out in fright, and the mother-bird, to avenge 
this wrong, flies at the beast and pecks at his sore places. 

The wolf is at war with the ass, the bull, and the fox, for as 
being a carnivore, he attacks these other animals; and so for the 
same reason with the fox and the circus, for the circus, being 
carnivorous and furnished with crooked talons, attacks and 
maims the animal. And so the raven is at war with the bull and 
the ass, for it flies at them, and strikes them, and pecks at their 
eyes; and so with the eagle and the heron, for the former, 
having crooked talons, attacks the latter, and the latter usually 
succumbs to the attack; and so the merlin with the vulture; and 
the crex with the eleus-owl, the blackbird, and the oriole (of this 
latter bird, by the way, the story goes that he was originally born 
out of a funeral pyre): the cause of warfare is that the crex 
injures both them and their young. The nuthatch and the wren 
are at war with the eagle; the nuthatch breaks the eagle's eggs, 
so the eagle is at war with it on special grounds, though, as a 
bird of prey, it carries on a general war all round. The horse and 
the anthus are enemies, and the horse will drive the bird out of 
the field where he is grazing: the bird feeds on grass, and sees 
too dimly to foresee an attack; it mimics the whinnying of the 
horse, flies at him, and tries to frighten him away; but the horse 



1726 



drives the bird away, and whenever he catches it he kills it: this 
bird lives beside rivers or on marsh ground; it has pretty 
plumage, and finds its without trouble. The ass is at enmity 
with the lizard, for the lizard sleeps in his manger, gets into his 
nostril, and prevents his eating. 

Of herons there are three kinds: the ash coloured, the white, 
and the starry heron (or bittern). Of these the first mentioned 
submits with reluctance to the duties of incubation, or to union 
of the sexes; in fact, it screams during the union, and it is said 
drips blood from its eyes; it lays its eggs also in an awkward 
manner, not unattended with pain. It is at war with certain 
creatures that do it injury: with the eagle for robbing it, with the 
fox for worrying it at night, and with the lark for stealing its 
eggs. 

The snake is at war with the weasel and the pig; with the 
weasel when they are both at home, for they live on the same 
food; with the pig for preying on her kind. The merlin is at war 
with the fox; it strikes and claws it, and, as it has crooked 
talons, it kills the animal's young. The raven and the fox are 
good friends, for the raven is at enmity with the merlin; and so 
when the merlin assails the fox the raven comes and helps the 
animal. The vulture and the merlin are mutual enemies, as 
being both furnished with crooked talons. The vulture fights 
with the eagle, and so, by the way, does does swan; and the 
swan is often victorious: moreover, of all birds swans are most 
prone to the killing of one another. 

In regard to wild creatures, some sets are at enmity with other 
sets at all times and under all circumstances; others, as in the 
case of man and man, at special times and under incidental 
circumstances. The ass and the acanthis are enemies; for the 
bird lives on thistles, and the ass browses on thistles when they 
are young and tender. The anthus, the acanthis, and the 



1727 



aegithus are at enmity with one another; it is said that the 
blood of the anthus will not intercommingle with the blood of 
the aegithus. The crow and the heron are friends, as also are the 
sedge-bird and lark, the laedus and the celeus or green 
woodpecker; the woodpecker lives on the banks of rivers and 
beside brakes, the laedus lives on rocks and bills, and is greatly 
attached to its nesting-place. The piphinx, the harpe, and the 
kite are friends; as are the fox and the snake, for both burrow 
underground; so also are the blackbird and the turtle-dove. The 
lion and the thos or civet are enemies, for both are carnivorous 
and live on the same food. Elephants fight fiercely with one 
another, and stab one another with their tusks; of two 
combatants the beaten one gets completely cowed, and dreads 
the sound of his conqueror's voice. These animals differ from 
one another an extraordinary extent in the way of courage. 
Indians employ these animals for war purposes, irrespective of 
sex; the females, however, are less in size and much inferior in 
point of spirit. An elephant by pushing with his big tusks can 
batter down a wall, and will butt with his forehead at a palm 
until he brings it down, when he stamps on it and lays it in 
orderly fashion on the ground. Men hunt the elephant in the 
following way: they mount tame elephants of approved spirit 
and proceed in quest of wild animals; when they come up with 
these they bid the tame brutes to beat the wild ones until they 
tire the latter completely. Hereupon the driver mounts a wild 
brute and guides him with the application of his metal prong; 
after this the creature soon becomes tame, and obeys guidance. 
Now when the driver is on their back they are all tractable, but 
after he has dismounted, some are tame and others vicious; in 
the case of these latter, they tie their front-legs with ropes to 
keep them quiet. The animal is hunted whether young or full 
grown. 



1728 



Thus we see that in the case of the creatures above mentioned 
their mutual friendship or the is due to the food they feed on 
and the life they lead. 



Of fishes, such as swim in shoals together are friendly to one 
another; such as do not so swim are enemies. Some fishes 
swarm during the spawning season; others after they have 
spawned. To state the matter comprehensively, we may say that 
the following are shoaling fish: the tunny, the maenis, the sea- 
gudgeon, the bogue, the horse-mackerel, the coracine, the 
synodon or dentex, the red mullet, the sphyraena, the anthias, 
the eleginus, the atherine, the sarginus, the gar-fish, (the squid,) 
the rainbow-wrasse, the pelamyd, the mackerel, the coly- 
mackerel. Of these some not only swim in shoals, but go in pairs 
inside the shoal; the rest without exception swim in pairs, and 
only swim in shoals at certain periods: that is, as has been said, 
when they are heavy with spawn or after they have spawned. 

The basse and the grey mullet are bitter enemies, but they 
swarm together at certain times; for at times not only do fishes 
of the same species swarm together, but also those whose 
feeding-grounds are identical or adjacent, if the food-supply be 
abundant. The grey mullet is often found alive with its tail 
lopped off, and the conger with all that part of its body removed 
that lies to the rear of the vent; in the case of the mullet the 
injury is wrought by the basse, in that of the conger-eel by the 
muraena. There is war between the larger and the lesser fishes: 
for the big fishes prey on the little ones. So much on the subject 
of marine animals. 



1729 



The characters of animals, as has been observed, differ in 
respect to timidity, to gentleness, to courage, to tameness, to 
intelligence, and to stupidity. 

The sheep is said to be naturally dull and stupid. Of all 
quadrupeds it is the most foolish: it will saunter away to lonely 
places with no object in view; oftentimes in stormy weather it 
will stray from shelter; if it be overtaken by a snowstorm, it will 
stand still unless the shepherd sets it in motion; it will stay 
behind and perish unless the shepherd brings up the rams; it 
will then follow home. 

If you catch hold of a goat's beard at the extremity - the beard is 
of a substance resembling hair - all the companion goats will 
stand stock still, staring at this particular goat in a kind of 
dumbfounderment. 

You will have a warmer bed in amongst the goats than among 
the sheep, because the goats will be quieter and will creep up 
towards you; for the goat is more impatient of cold than the 
sheep. 

Shepherds train sheep to close in together at a clap of their 
hands, for if, when a thunderstorm comes on, a ewe stays 
behind without closing in, the storm will kill it if it be with 
young; consequently if a sudden clap or noise is made, they 
close in together within the sheepfold by reason of their 
training. 

Even bulls, when they are roaming by themselves apart from 
the herd, are killed by wild animals. 



1730 



Sheep and goats lie crowded together, kin by kin. When the sun 
turns early towards its setting, the goats are said to lie no longer 
face to face, but back to back. 



Cattle at pasture keep together in their accustomed herds, and 
if one animal strays away the rest will follow; consequently if 
the herdsmen lose one particular animal, they keep close watch 
on all the rest. 

When mares with their colts pasture together in the same field, 
if one dam dies the others will take up the rearing of the colt. In 
point of fact, the mare appears to be singularly prone by nature 
to maternal fondness; in proof whereof a barren mare will steal 
the foal from its dam, will tend it with all the solicitude of a 
mother, but, as it will be unprovided with mother's milk, its 
solicitude will prove fatal to its charge. 



Among wild quadrupeds the hind appears to be pre-eminently 
intelligent; for example, in its habit of bringing forth its young 
on the sides of public roads, where the fear of man forbids the 
approach of wild animals. Again, after parturition, it first 
swallows the afterbirth, then goes in quest of the seseli shrub, 
and after eating of it returns to its young. The mother takes its 
young betimes to her lair, so leading it to know its place of 
refuge in time of danger; this lair is a precipitous rock, with only 
one approach, and there it is said to hold its own against all 



1731 



comers. The male when it gets fat, which it does in a high 
degree in autumn, disappears, abandoning its usual resorts, 
apparently under an idea that its fatness facilitates its capture. 
They shed their horns in places difficult of access or discovery, 
whence the proverbial expression of 'the place where the stag 
sheds his horns'; the fact being that, as having parted with their 
weapons, they take care not to be seen. The saying is that no 
man has ever seen the animal's left horn; that the creature 
keeps it out of sight because it possesses some medicinal 
property. 

In their first year stags grow no horns, but only an excrescence 
indicating where horns will be, this excrescence being short and 
thick. In their second year they grow their horns for the first 
time, straight in shape, like pegs for hanging clothes on; and on 
this account they have an appropriate nickname. In the third 
year the antlers are bifurcate; in the fourth year they grow 
trifurcate; and so they go on increasing in complexity until the 
creature is six years old: after this they grow their horns 
without any specific differentiation, so that you cannot by 
observation of them tell the animal's age. But the patriarchs of 
the herd may be told chiefly by two signs; in the first place they 
have few teeth or none at all, and, in the second place, they 
have ceased to grow the pointed tips to their antlers. The 
forward-pointing tips of the growing horns (that is to say the 
brow antlers), with which the animal meets attack, are 
technically termed its 'defenders'; with these the patriarchs are 
unprovided, and their antlers merely grow straight upwards. 
Stags shed their horns annually, in or about the month of May; 
after shedding, they conceal themselves, it is said, during the 
daytime, and, to avoid the flies, hide in thick copses; during this 
time, until they have grown their horns, they feed at night-time. 
The horns at first grow in a kind of skin envelope, and get rough 
by degrees; when they reach their full size the animal basks in 
the sun, to mature and dry them. When they need no longer rub 



1732 



them against tree-trunks they quit their hiding places, from a 
sense of security based upon the possession of arms defensive 
and offensive. An Achaeine stag has been caught with a 
quantity of green ivy grown over its horns, it having grown 
apparently, as on fresh green wood, when the horns were young 
and tender. When a stag is stung by a venom-spider or similar 
insect, it gathers crabs and eats them; it is said to be a good 
thing for man to drink the juice, but the taste is disagreeable. 
The hinds after parturition at once swallow the afterbirth, and it 
is impossible to secure it, for the hind catches it before it falls to 
the ground: now this substance is supposed to have medicinal 
properties. When hunted the creatures are caught by singing or 
pipe-playing on the part of the hunters; they are so pleased 
with the music that they lie down on the grass. If there be two 
hunters, one before their eyes sings or plays the pipe, the other 
keeps out of sight and shoots, at a signal given by the 
confederate. If the animal has its ears cocked, it can hear well 
and you cannot escape its ken; if its ears are down, you can. 



When bears are running away from their pursuers they push 
their cubs in front of them, or take them up and carry them; 
when they are being overtaken they climb up a tree. When 
emerging from their winter-den, they at once take to eating 
cuckoo-pint, as has been said, and chew sticks of wood as 
though they were cutting teeth. 

Many other quadrupeds help themselves in clever ways. Wild 
goats in Crete are said, when wounded by arrows, to go in 
search of dittany, which is supposed to have the property of 
ejecting arrows in the body. Dogs, when they are ill, eat some 



1733 



kind of grass and produce vomiting. The panther, after eating 
panther's-bane, tries to find some human excrement, which is 
said to heal its pain. This panther's-bane kills lions as well. 
Hunters hang up human excrement in a vessel attached to the 
boughs of a tree, to keep the animal from straying to any 
distance; the animal meets its end in leaping up to the branch 
and trying to get at the medicine. They say that the panther has 
found out that wild animals are fond of the scent it emits; that, 
when it goes a-hunting, it hides itself; that the other animals 
come nearer and nearer, and that by this stratagem it can catch 
even animals as swift of foot as stags. 

The Egyptian ichneumon, when it sees the serpent called the 
asp, does not attack it until it has called in other ichneumons to 
help; to meet the blows and bites of their enemy the assailants 
beplaster themselves with mud, by first soaking in the river and 
then rolling on the ground. 

When the crocodile yawns, the trochilus flies into his mouth 
and cleans his teeth. The trochilus gets his food thereby, and the 
crocodile gets ease and comfort; it makes no attempt to injure 
its little friend, but, when it wants it to go, it shakes its neck in 
warning, lest it should accidentally bite the bird. 

The tortoise, when it has partaken of a snake, eats marjoram; 
this action has been actually observed. A man saw a tortoise 
perform this operation over and over again, and every time it 
plucked up some marjoram go back to partake of its prey; he 
thereupon pulled the marjoram up by the roots, and the 
consequence was the tortoise died. The weasel, when it fights 
with a snake, first eats wild rue, the smell of which is noxious to 
the snake. The dragon, when it eats fruit, swallows endive-juice; 
it has been seen in the act. Dogs, when they suffer from worms, 
eat the standing corn. Storks, and all other birds, when they get 
a wound fighting, apply marjoram to the place injured. 



1734 



Many have seen the locust, when fighting with the snake get a 
tight hold of the snake by the neck. The weasel has a clever way 
of getting the better of birds; it tears their throats open, as 
wolves do with sheep. Weasels fight desperately with mice- 
catching snakes, as they both prey on the same animal. 

In regard to the instinct of hedgehogs, it has been observed in 
many places that, when the wind is shifting from north to 
south, and from south to north, they shift the outlook of their 
earth-holes, and those that are kept in domestication shift over 
from one wall to the other. The story goes that a man in 
Byzantium got into high repute for foretelling a change of 
weather, all owing to his having noticed this habit of the 
hedgehog. 

The polecat or marten is about as large as the smaller breed of 
Maltese dogs. In the thickness of its fur, in its look, in the white 
of its belly, and in its love of mischief, it resembles the weasel; it 
is easily tamed; from its liking for honey it is a plague to bee- 
hives; it preys on birds like the cat. Its genital organ, as has been 
said, consists of bone: the organ of the male is supposed to be a 
cure for strangury; doctors scrape it into powder, and 
administer it in that form. 



In a general way in the lives of animals many resemblances to 
human life may be observed. Pre-eminent intelligence will be 
seen more in small creatures than in large ones, as is 
exemplified in the case of birds by the nest building of the 
swallow. In the same way as men do, the bird mixes mud and 
chaff together; if it runs short of mud, it souses its body in water 
and rolls about in the dry dust with wet feathers; furthermore, 



1735 



just as man does, it makes a bed of straw, putting hard material 
below for a foundation, and adapting all to suit its own size. 
Both parents co-operate in the rearing of the young; each of the 
parents will detect, with practised eye, the young one that has 
had a helping, and will take care it is not helped twice over; at 
first the parents will rid the nest of excrement, but, when the 
young are grown, they will teach their young to shift their 
position and let their excrement fall over the side of the nest. 

Pigeons exhibit other phenomena with a similar likeness to the 
ways of humankind. In pairing the same male and the same 
female keep together; and the union is only broken by the death 
of one of the two parties. At the time of parturition in the 
female the sympathetic attentions of the male are 
extraordinary; if the female is afraid on account of the 
impending parturition to enter the nest, the male will beat her 
and force her to come in. When the young are born, he will take 
and masticate pieces of suitable food, will open the beaks of the 
fledglings, and inject these pieces, thus preparing them betimes 
to take food. (When the male bird is about to expel the the 
young ones from the nest he cohabits with them all.) As a 
general rule these birds show this conjugal fidelity, but 
occasionally a female will cohabit with other than her mate. 
These birds are combative, and quarrel with one another, and 
enter each other's nests, though this occurs but seldom; at a 
distance from their nests this quarrelsomeness is less marked, 
but in the close neighbourhood of their nests they will fight 
desperately. A peculiarity common to the tame pigeon, the ring- 
dove and the turtle-dove is that they do not lean the head back 
when they are in the act of drinking, but only when they have 
fully quenched their thirst. The turtle-dove and the ring-dove 
both have but one mate, and let no other come nigh; both sexes 
co-operate in the process of incubation. It is difficult to 
distinguish between the sexes except by an examination of 
their interiors. Ring-doves are long-lived; cases have been 



1736 



known where such birds were twenty-five years old, thirty years 
old, and in some cases forty. As they grow old their claws 
increase in size, and pigeon-fanciers cut the claws; as far as one 
can see, the birds suffer no other perceptible disfigurement by 
their increase in age. Turtle-doves and pigeons that are blinded 
by fanciers for use as decoys, live for eight years. Partridges live 
for about fifteen years. Ring-doves and turtle-doves always build 
their nests in the same place year after year. The male, as a 
general rule, is more long-lived than the female; but in the case 
of pigeons some assert that the male dies before the female, 
taking their inference from the statements of persons who keep 
decoy-birds in captivity. Some declare that the male sparrow 
lives only a year, pointing to the fact that early in spring the 
male sparrow has no black beard, but has one later on, as 
though the blackbearded birds of the last year had all died out; 
they also say that the females are the longer lived, on the 
grounds that they are caught in amongst the young birds and 
that their age is rendered manifest by the hardness about their 
beaks. Turtle-doves in summer live in cold places, (and in warm 
places during the winter); chaffinches affect warm habitations 
in summer and cold ones in winter. 



8 

Birds of a heavy build, such as quails, partridges, and the like, 
build no nests; indeed, where they are incapable of flight, it 
would be of no use if they could do so. After scraping a hole on a 
level piece of ground - and it is only in such a place that they 
lay their eggs - they cover it over with thorns and sticks for 
security against hawks and eagles, and there lay their eggs and 
hatch them; after the hatching is over, they at once lead the 
young out from the nest, as they are not able to fly afield for 



1737 



food for them. Quails and partridges, like barn-door hens, when 
they go to rest, gather their brood under their wings. Not to be 
discovered, as might be the case if they stayed long in one spot, 
they do not hatch the eggs where they laid them. When a man 
comes by chance upon a young brood, and tries to catch them, 
the hen-bird rolls in front of the hunter, pretending to be lame: 
the man every moment thinks he is on the point of catching 
her, and so she draws him on and on, until every one of her 
brood has had time to escape; hereupon she returns to the nest 
and calls the young back. The partridge lays not less than ten 
eggs, and often lays as many as sixteen. As has been observed, 
the bird has mischievous and deceitful habits. In the spring- 
time, a noisy scrimmage takes place, out of which the male- 
birds emerge each with a hen. Owing to the lecherous nature of 
the bird, and from a dislike to the hen sitting, the males, if they 
find any eggs, roll them over and over until they break them in 
pieces; to provide against this the female goes to a distance and 
lays the eggs, and often, under the stress of parturition, lays 
them in any chance spot that offers; if the male be near at hand, 
then to keep the eggs intact she refrains from visiting them. If 
she be seen by a man, then, just as with her fledged brood, she 
entices him off by showing herself close at his feet until she has 
drawn him to a distance. When the females have run away and 
taken to sitting, the males in a pack take to screaming and 
fighting; when thus engaged, they have the nickname of 
'widowers'. The bird who is beaten follows his victor, and 
submits to be covered by him only; and the beaten bird is 
covered by a second one or by any other, only clandestinely 
without the victor's knowledge; this is so, not at all times, but at 
a particular season of the year, and with quails as well as with 
partridges. A similar proceeding takes place occasionally with 
barn-door cocks: for in temples, where cocks are set apart as 
dedicate without hens, they all as a matter of course tread any 
new-comer. Tame partridges tread wild birds, pecket their 



1738 



heads, and treat them with every possible outrage. The leader of 
the wild birds, with a counter-note of challenge, pushes forward 
to attack the decoy-bird, and after he has been netted, another 
advances with a similar note. This is what is done if the decoy 
be a male; but if it be a female that is the decoy and gives the 
note, and the leader of the wild birds give a counter one, the 
rest of the males set upon him and chase him away from the 
female for making advances to her instead of to them; in 
consequence of this the male often advances without uttering 
any cry, so that no other may hear him and come and give him 
battle; and experienced fowlers assert that sometimes the male 
bird, when he approaches the female, makes her keep silence, 
to avoid having to give battle to other males who might have 
heard him. The partridge has not only the note here referred to, 
but also a thin shrill cry and other notes. Oftentimes the hen- 
bird rises from off her brood when she sees the male showing 
attentions to the female decoy; she will give the counter note 
and remain still, so as to be trodden by him and divert him from 
the decoy. The quail and the partridge are so intent upon sexual 
union that they often come right in the way of the decoy-birds, 
and not seldom alight upon their heads. So much for the sexual 
proclivities of the partridge, for the way in which it is hunted, 
and the general nasty habits of the bird. 

As has been said, quails and partridges build their nests upon 
the ground, and so also do some of the birds that are capable of 
sustained flight. Further, for instance, of such birds, the lark and 
the woodcock, as well as the quail, do not perch on a branch, 
but squat upon the ground. 



1739 



The woodpecker does not squat on the ground, but pecks at the 
bark of trees to drive out from under it maggots and gnats; 
when they emerge, it licks them up with its tongue, which is 
large and flat. It can run up and down a tree in any way, even 
with the head downwards, like the gecko-lizard. For secure hold 
upon a tree, its claws are better adapted than those of the daw; 
it makes its way by sticking these claws into the bark. One 
species of woodpecker is smaller than a blackbird, and has 
small reddish speckles; a second species is larger than the 
blackbird, and a third is not much smaller than a barn-door hen. 
It builds a nest on trees, as has been said, on olive trees 
amongst others. It feeds on the maggots and ants that are under 
the bark: it is so eager in the search for maggots that it is said 
sometimes to hollow a tree out to its downfall. A woodpecker 
once, in course of domestication, was seen to insert an almond 
into a hole in a piece of timber, so that it might remain steady 
under its pecking; at the third peck it split the shell of the fruit, 
and then ate the kernel. 



10 

Many indications of high intelligence are given by cranes. They 
will fly to a great distance and up in the air, to command an 
extensive view; if they see clouds and signs of bad weather they 
fly down again and remain still. They, furthermore, have a 
leader in their flight, and patrols that scream on the confines of 
the flock so as to be heard by all. When they settle down, the 
main body go to sleep with their heads under their wing, 
standing first on one leg and then on the other, while their 



1740 



leader, with his head uncovered, keeps a sharp look out, and 
when he sees anything of importance signals it with a cry. 

Pelicans that live beside rivers swallow the large smooth 
mussel-shells: after cooking them inside the crop that precedes 
the stomach, they spit them out, so that, now when their shells 
are open, they may pick the flesh out and eat it. 



11 

Of wild birds, the nests are fashioned to meet the exigencies of 
existence and ensure the security of the young. Some of these 
birds are fond of their young and take great care of them, others 
are quite the reverse; some are clever in procuring subsistence, 
others are not so. Some of these birds build in ravines and 
clefts, and on cliffs, as, for instance, the so-called charadrius, or 
stone-curlew; this bird is in no way noteworthy for plumage or 
voice; it makes an appearance at night, but in the daytime 
keeps out of sight. 

The hawk also builds in inaccessible places. Although a 
ravenous bird, it will never eat the heart of any bird it catches; 
this has been observed in the case of the quail, the thrush, and 
other birds. They modify betimes their method of hunting, for in 
summer they do not grab their prey as they do at other seasons. 

Of the vulture, it is said that no one has ever seen either its 
young or its nest; on this account and on the ground that all of 
a sudden great numbers of them will appear without any one 
being able to tell from whence they come, Herodorus, the father 
of Bryson the sophist, says that it belongs to some distant and 
elevated land. The reason is that the bird has its nest on 



1741 



inaccessible crags, and is found only in a few localities. The 
female lays one egg as a rule, and two at the most. 

Some birds live on mountains or in forests, as the hoopoe and 
the brenthus; this latter bird finds his food with ease and has a 
musical voice. The wren lives in brakes and crevices; it is 
difficult of capture, keeps out of sight, is gentle of disposition, 
finds its food with ease, and is something of a mechanic. It goes 
by the nickname of 'old man' or 'king'; and the story goes that 
for this reason the eagle is at war with him. 



12 

Some birds live on the sea-shore, as the wagtail; the bird is of a 
mischievous nature, hard to capture, but when caught capable 
of complete domestication; it is a cripple, as being weak in its 
hinder quarters. 

Web-footed birds without exception live near the sea or rivers or 
pools, as they naturally resort to places adapted to their 
structure. Several birds, however, with cloven toes live near 
pools or marshes, as, for instance, the anthus lives by the side of 
rivers; the plumage of this bird is pretty, and it finds its food 
with ease. The catarrhactes lives near the sea; when it makes a 
dive, it will keep under water for as long as it would take a man 
to walk a furlong; it is less than the common hawk. Swans are 
web-footed, and live near pools and marshes; they find their 
food with ease, are good-tempered, are fond of their young, and 
live to a green old age. If the eagle attacks them they will repel 
the attack and get the better of their assailant, but they are 
never the first to attack. They are musical, and sing chiefly at 
the approach of death; at this time they fly out to sea, and men, 
when sailing past the coast of Libya, have fallen in with many of 



1742 



them out at sea singing in mournful strains, and have actually 
seen some of them dying. 

The cymindis is seldom seen, as it lives on mountains; it is 
black in colour, and about the size of the hawk called the 'dove- 
killer'; it is long and slender in form. The Ionians call the bird by 
this name; Homer in the Iliad mentions it in the line: 

Chalcis its name with those of heavenly birth, 

But called Cymindis by the sons of earth. 

The hybris, said by some to be the same as the eagle-owl, is 
never seen by daylight, as it is dim-sighted, but during the night 
it hunts like the eagle; it will fight the eagle with such 
desperation that the two combatants are often captured alive by 
shepherds; it lays two eggs, and, like others we have mentioned, 
it builds on rocks and in caverns. Cranes also fight so 
desperately among themselves as to be caught when fighting, 
for they will not leave off; the crane lays two eggs. 



13 

The jay has a great variety of notes: indeed, might almost say it 
had a different note for every day in the year. It lays about nine 
eggs; builds its nest on trees, out of hair and tags of wool; when 
acorns are getting scarce, it lays up a store of them in hiding. 

It is a common story of the stork that the old birds are fed by 
their grateful progeny. Some tell a similar story of the bee-eater, 
and declare that the parents are fed by their young not only 
when growing old, but at an early period, as soon as the young 
are capable of feeding them; and the parent-birds stay inside 
the nest. The under part of the bird's wing is pale yellow; the 



1743 



upper part is dark blue, like that of the halcyon; the tips of the 
wings are About autumn-time it lays six or seven eggs, in 
overhanging banks where the soil is soft; there it burrows into 
the ground to a depth of six feet. 

The greenfinch, so called from the colour of its belly, is as large 
as a lark; it lays four or five eggs, builds its nest out of the plant 
called comfrey, pulling it up by the roots, and makes an under- 
mattress to lie on of hair and wool. The blackbird and the jay 
build their nests after the same fashion. The nest of the 
penduline tit shows great mechanical skill; it has the 
appearance of a ball of flax, and the hole for entry is very small. 

People who live where the bird comes from say that there exists 
a cinnamon bird which brings the cinnamon from some 
unknown localities, and builds its nest out of it; it builds on 
high trees on the slender top branches. They say that the 
inhabitants attach leaden weights to the tips of their arrows 
and therewith bring down the nests, and from the intertexture 
collect the cinnamon sticks. 



14 

The halcyon is not much larger than the sparrow. Its colour is 
dark blue, green, and light purple; the whole body and wings, 
and especially parts about the neck, show these colours in a 
mixed way, without any colour being sharply defined; the beak 
is light green, long and slender: such, then, is the look of the 
bird. Its nest is like sea-balls, i.e. the things that by the name of 
halosachne or seafoam, only the colour is not the same. The 
colour of the nest is light red, and the shape is that of the long- 
necked gourd. The nests are larger than the largest sponge, 
though they vary in size; they are roofed over, and great part of 



1744 



them is solid and great part hollow. If you use a sharp knife it is 
not easy to cut the nest through; but if you cut it, and at the 
same time bruise it with your hand, it will soon crumble to 
pieces, like the halosachne. The opening is small, just enough 
for a tiny entrance, so that even if the nest upset the sea does 
not enter in; the hollow channels are like those in sponges. It is 
not known for certain of what material the nest is constructed; 
it is possibly made of the backbones of the gar-fish; for, by the 
way, the bird lives on fish. Besides living on the shore, it ascends 
fresh-water streams. It lays generally about five eggs, and lays 
eggs all its life long, beginning to do so at the age of four 
months. 



15 

The hoopoe usually constructs its nest out of human 
excrement. It changes its appearance in summer and in winter, 
as in fact do the great majority of wild birds. (The titmouse is 
said to lay a very large quantity of eggs: next to the ostrich the 
blackheaded tit is said by some to lay the largest number of 
eggs; seventeen eggs have been seen; it lays, however, more 
than twenty; it is said always to lay an odd number. Like others 
we have mentioned, it builds in trees; it feeds on caterpillars.) A 
peculiarity of this bird and of the nightingale is that the outer 
extremity of the tongue is not sharp-pointed. 

The aegithus finds its food with ease, has many young, and 
walks with a limp. The golden oriole is apt at learning, is clever 
at making a living, but is awkward in flight and has an ugly 
plumage. 



1745 



16 

The reed-warbler makes its living as easily as any other bird, 
sits in summer in a shady spot facing the wind, in winter in a 
sunny and sheltered place among reeds in a marsh; it is small 
in size, with a pleasant note. The so-called chatterer has a 
pleasant note, beautiful plumage, makes a living cleverly, and is 
graceful in form; it appears to be alien to our country; at all 
events it is seldom seen at a distance from its own immediate 
home. 



17 

The crake is quarrelsome, clever at making a living, but in other 
ways an unlucky bird. The bird called sitta is quarrelsome, but 
clever and tidy, makes its living with ease, and for its 
knowingness is regarded as uncanny; it has a numerous brood, 
of which it is fond, and lives by pecking the bark of trees. The 
aegolius-owl flies by night, is seldom seen by day; like others we 
have mentioned, it lives on cliffs or in caverns; it feeds on two 
kinds of food; it has a strong hold on life and is full of resource. 
The tree-creeper is a little bird, of fearless disposition; it lives 
among trees, feeds on caterpillars, makes a living with ease, and 
has a loud clear note. The acanthis finds its food with difficulty; 
its plumage is poor, but its note is musical. 



1746 



18 

Of the herons, the ashen-coloured one, as has been said, unites 
with the female not without pain; it is full of resource, carries 
its food with it, is eager in the quest of it, and works by day; its 
plumage is poor, and its excrement is always wet. Of the other 
two species - for there are three in all - the white heron has 
handsome plumage, unites without harm to itself with the 
female, builds a nest and lays its eggs neatly in trees; it 
frequents marshes and lakes and Plains and meadow land. The 
speckled heron, which is nicknamed 'the skulker', is said in 
folklore stories to be of servile origin, and, as its nickname 
implies, it is the laziest bird of the three species. Such are the 
habits of herons. The bird that is called the poynx has this 
peculiarity, that it is more prone than any other bird to peck at 
the eyes of an assailant or its prey; it is at war with the harpy, as 
the two birds live on the same food. 



19 

There are two kinds of owsels; the one is black, and is found 
everywhere, the other is quite white, about the same size as the 
other, and with the same pipe. This latter is found on Cyllene in 
Arcadia, and is found nowhere else. The laius, or blue-thrush, is 
like the black owsel, only a little smaller; it lives on cliffs or on 
tile roofings; it has not a red beak as the black owsel has. 



1747 



20 

Of thrushes there are three species. One is the misselthrush; it 
feeds only on mistletoe and resin; it is about the size of the jay. 
A second is the song-thrush; it has a sharp pipe, and is about 
the size of the owsel. There is another species called the Illas; it 
is the smallest species of the three, and is less variegated in 
plumage than the others. 



21 

There is a bird that lives on rocks, called the blue-bird from its 
colour. It is comparatively common in Nisyros, and is somewhat 
less than the owsel and a little bigger than the chaffinch. It has 
large claws, and climbs on the face of the rocks. It is steel-blue 
all over; its beak is long and slender; its legs are short, like those 
of the woodpecker. 



22 

The oriole is yellow all over; it is not visible during winter, but 
puts in an appearance about the time of the summer solstice, 
and departs again at the rising of Arcturus; it is the size of the 
turtle-dove. The so-called soft-head (or shrike) always settles on 
one and the same branch, where it falls a prey to the 
birdcatcher. Its head is big, and composed of gristle; it is a little 
smaller than the thrush; its beak is strong, small, and round; it 
is ashen-coloured all over; is fleet of foot, but slow of wing. The 
bird-catcher usually catches it by help of the owl. 



1748 



23 

There is also the pardalus. As a rule, it is seen in flocks and not 
singly; it is ashen-coloured all over, and about the size of the 
birds last described; it is fleet of foot and strong of wing, and its 
pipe is loud and high-pitched. The collyrion (or fieldfare) feeds 
on the same food as the owsel; is of the same size as the above 
mentioned birds; and is trapped usually in the winter. All these 
birds are found at all times. Further, there are the birds that live 
as a rule in towns, the raven and the crow. These also are visible 
at all seasons, never shift their place of abode, and never go into 
winter quarters. 



24 

Of daws there are three species. One is the chough; it is as large 
as the crow, but has a red beak. There is another, called the 
'wolf; and further there is the little daw, called the 'railer'. There 
is another kind of daw found in Lybia and Phrygia, which is 
web-footed. 



25 

Of larks there are two kinds. One lives on the ground and has a 
crest on its head; the other is gregarious, and not sporadic like 



1749 



the first; it is, however, of the same coloured plumage, but is 
smaller, and has no crest; it is an article of human food. 



26 

The woodcock is caught with nets in gardens. It is about the 
size of a barn-door hen; it has a long beak, and in plumage is 
like the francolin-partridge. It runs quickly, and is pretty easily 
domesticated. The starling is speckled; it is of the same size as 
the owsel. 



27 

Of the Egyptian ibis there are two kinds, the white and the 
black. The white ones are found over Egypt, excepting in 
Pelusium; the black ones are found in Pelusium, and nowhere 
else in Egypt. 



28 

Of the little horned owls there are two kinds, and one is visible 
at all seasons, and for that reason has the nickname of 'all-the- 
year-round owl'; it is not sufficiently palatable to come to table; 
another species makes its appearance sometimes in the 
autumn, is seen for a single day or at the most for two days, and 
is regarded as a table delicacy; it scarcely differs from the first 
species save only in being fatter; it has no note, but the other 



1750 



species has. With regard to their origin, nothing is known from 
ocular observation; the only fact known for certain is that they 
are first seen when a west wind is blowing. 



29 

The cuckoo, as has been said elsewhere, makes no nest, but 
deposits its eggs in an alien nest, generally in the nest of the 
ring-dove, or on the ground in the nest of the hypolais or lark, or 
on a tree in the nest of the green linnet, it lays only one egg and 
does not hatch it itself, but the mother-bird in whose nest it has 
deposited it hatches and rears it; and, as they say, this mother 
bird, when the young cuckoo has grown big, thrusts her own 
brood out of the nest and lets them perish; others say that this 
mother-bird kills her own brood and gives them to the alien to 
devour, despising her own young owing to the beauty of the 
cuckoo. Personal observers agree in telling most of these stories, 
but are not in agreement as to the instruction of the young. 
Some say that the mother-cuckoo comes and devours the brood 
of the rearing mother; others say that the young cuckoo from its 
superior size snaps up the food brought before the smaller 
brood have a chance, and that in consequence the smaller 
brood die of hunger; others say that, by its superior strength, it 
actually kills the other ones whilst it is being reared up with 
them. The cuckoo shows great sagacity in the disposal of its 
progeny; the fact is, the mother cuckoo is quite conscious of her 
own cowardice and of the fact that she could never help her 
young one in an emergency, and so, for the security of the 
young one, she makes of him a supposititious child in an alien 
nest. The truth is, this bird is pre-eminent among birds in the 
way of cowardice; it allows itself to be pecked at by little birds, 
and flies away from their attacks. 



1751 



30 

It has already been stated that the footless bird, which some 
term the cypselus, resembles the swallow; indeed, it is not easy 
to distinguish between the two birds, excepting in the fact that 
the cypselus has feathers on the shank. These birds rear their 
young in long cells made of mud, and furnished with a hole just 
big enough for entry and exit; they build under cover of some 
roofing - under a rock or in a cavern - for protection against 
animals and men. 

The so-called goat-sucker lives on mountains; it is a little larger 
than the owsel, and less than the cuckoo; it lays two eggs, or 
three at the most, and is of a sluggish disposition. It flies up to 
the she-goat and sucks its milk, from which habit it derives its 
name; it is said that, after it has sucked the teat of the animal, 
the teat dries up and the animal goes blind. It is dim-sighted in 
the day-time, but sees well enough by night. 



31 

In narrow circumscribed districts where the food would be 
insufficient for more birds than two, ravens are only found in 
isolated pairs; when their young are old enough to fly, the 
parent couple first eject them from the nest, and by and by 
chase them from the neighbourhood. The raven lays four or five 
eggs. About the time when the mercenaries under Medius were 
slaughtered at Pharsalus, the districts about Athens and the 
Peloponnese were left destitute of ravens, from which it would 



1752 



appear that these birds have some means of 
intercommunicating with one another. 



32 

Of eagles there are several species. One of them, called 'the 
white-tailed eagle', is found on low lands, in groves, and in the 
neighbourhood of cities; some call it the 'heron-killer'. It is bold 
enough to fly to mountains and the interior of forests. The other 
eagles seldom visit groves or low-lying land. There is another 
species called the 'plangus'; it ranks second in point of size and 
strength; it lives in mountain combes and glens, and by marshy 
lakes, and goes by the name of 'duck-killer' and 'swart-eagle.' It 
is mentioned by Homer in his account of the visit made by 
Priam to the tent of Achilles. There is another species with black 
Plumage, the smallest but boldest of all the kinds. It dwells on 
mountains or in forests, and is called 'the black-eagle' or 'the 
hare-killer'; it is the only eagle that rears its young and 
thoroughly takes them out with it. It is swift of flight, is neat 
and tidy in its habits, too proud for jealousy, fearless, 
quarrelsome; it is also silent, for it neither whimpers nor 
screams. There is another species, the percnopterus, very large, 
with white head, very short wings, long tail-feathers, in 
appearance like a vulture. It goes by the name of 'mountain- 
stork' or 'half-eagle'. It lives in groves; has all the bad qualities 
of the other species, and none of the good ones; for it lets itself 
be chased and caught by the raven and the other birds. It is 
clumsy in its movements, has difficulty in procuring its food, 
preys on dead animals, is always hungry, and at all times 
whining and screaming. There is another species, called the 
'sea-eagle' or 'osprey'. This bird has a large thick neck, curved 
wings, and broad tailfeathers; it lives near the sea, grasps its 



1753 



prey with its talons, and often, from inability to carry it, tumbles 
down into the water. There is another species called the 'true- 
bred'; people say that these are the only true-bred birds to be 
found, that all other birds - eagles, hawks, and the smallest 
birds - are all spoilt by the interbreeding of different species. 
The true-bred eagle is the largest of all eagles; it is larger than 
the phene; is half as large again as the ordinary eagle, and has 
yellow plumage; it is seldom seen, as is the case with the so- 
called cymindis. The time for an eagle to be on the wing in 
search of prey is from midday to evening; in the morning until 
the market-hour it remains on the nest. In old age the upper 
beak of the eagle grows gradually longer and more crooked, and 
the bird dies eventually of starvation; there is a folklore story 
that the eagle is thus punished because it once was a man and 
refused entertainment to a stranger. The eagle puts aside its 
superfluous food for its young; for owing to the difficulty in 
procuring food day by day, it at times may come back to the nest 
with nothing. If it catch a man prowling about in the 
neighbourhood of its nest, it will strike him with its wings and 
scratch him with its talons. The nest is built not on low ground 
but on an elevated spot, generally on an inaccessible ledge of a 
cliff; it does, however, build upon a tree. The young are fed until 
they can fly; hereupon the parent-birds topple them out of the 
nest, and chase them completely out of the locality. The fact is 
that a pair of eagles demands an extensive space for its 
maintenance, and consequently cannot allow other birds to 
quarter themselves in close neighbourhood. They do not hunt in 
the vicinity of their nest, but go to a great distance to find their 
prey. When the eagle has captured a beast, it puts it down 
without attempting to carry it off at once; if on trial it finds the 
burden too heavy, it will leave it. When it has spied a hare, it 
does not swoop on it at once, but lets it go on into the open 
ground; neither does it descend to the ground at one swoop, but 
goes gradually down from higher flights to lower and lower: 



1754 



these devices it adopts by way of security against the stratagem 
of the hunter. It alights on high places by reason of the difficulty 
it experiences in soaring up from the level ground; it flies high 
in the air to have the more extensive view; from its high flight it 
is said to be the only bird that resembles the gods. Birds of prey, 
as a rule, seldom alight upon rock, as the crookedness of their 
talons prevents a stable footing on hard stone. The eagle hunts 
hares, fawns, foxes, and in general all such animals as he can 
master with ease. It is a long-lived bird, and this fact might be 
inferred from the length of time during which the same nest is 
maintained in its place. 



33 

In Scythia there is found a bird as large as the great bustard. The 
female lays two eggs, but does not hatch them, but hides them 
in the skin of a hare or fox and leaves them there, and, when it 
is not in quest of prey, it keeps a watch on them on a high tree; 
if any man tries to climb the tree, it fights and strikes him with 
its wing, just as eagles do. 



34 

The owl and the night-raven and all the birds see poorly in the 
daytime seek their prey in the night, but not all the night 
through, but at evening and dawn. Their food consists of mice, 
lizards, chafers and the like little creatures. The so-called phene, 
or lammergeier, is fond of its young, provides its food with ease, 
fetches food to its nest, and is of a kindly disposition. It rears its 



1755 



own young and those of the eagle as well; for when the eagle 
ejects its young from the nest, this bird catches them up as they 
fall and feeds them. For the eagle, by the way, ejects the young 
birds prematurely, before they are able to feed themselves, or to 
fly. It appears to do so from jealousy; for it is by nature jealous, 
and is so ravenous as to grab furiously at its food; and when it 
does grab at its food, it grabs it in large morsels. It is accordingly 
jealous of the young birds as they approach maturity, since they 
are getting good appetites, and so it scratches them with its 
talons. The young birds fight also with one another, to secure a 
morsel of food or a comfortable position, whereupon the 
mother-bird beats them and ejects them from the nest; the 
young ones scream at this treatment, and the phene hearing 
them catches them as they fall. The phene has a film over its 
eyes and sees badly, but the sea-eagle is very keen-sighted, and 
before its young are fledged tries to make them stare at the sun, 
and beats the one that refuses to do so, and twists him back in 
the sun's direction; and if one of them gets watery eyes in the 
process, it kills him, and rears the other. It lives near the sea, 
and feeds, as has been said, on sea-birds; when in pursuit of 
them it catches them one by one, watching the moment when 
the bird rises to the surface from its dive. When a sea-bird, 
emerging from the water, sees the sea-eagle, he in terror dives 
under, intending to rise again elsewhere; the eagle, however, 
owing to its keenness of vision, keeps flying after him until he 
either drowns the bird or catches him on the surface. The eagle 
never attacks these birds when they are in a swarm, for they 
keep him off by raising a shower of water-drops with their 
wings. 



1756 



35 

The cepphus is caught by means of sea-foam; the bird snaps at 
the foam, and consequently fishermen catch it by sluicing with 
showers of sea-water. These birds grow to be plump and fat; 
their flesh has a good odour, excepting the hinder quarters, 
which smell of shoreweed. 



36 

Of hawks, the strongest is the buzzard; the next in point of 
courage is the merlin; and the circus ranks third; other diverse 
kinds are the asterias, the pigeon-hawk, and the pternis; the 
broaded-winged hawk is called the half-buzzard; others go by 
the name of hobby-hawk, or sparrow-hawk, or 'smooth- 
feathered', or 'toad-catcher'. Birds of this latter species find 
their food with very little difficulty, and flutter along the ground. 
Some say that there are ten species of hawks, all differing from 
one another. One hawk, they say, will strike and grab the pigeon 
as it rests on the ground, but never touch it while it is in flight; 
another hawk attacks the pigeon when it is perched upon a tree 
or any elevation, but never touches it when it is on the ground 
or on the wing; other hawks attack their prey only when it is on 
the wing. They say that pigeons can distinguish the various 
species: so that, when a hawk is an assailant, if it be one that 
attacks its prey when the prey is on the wing, the pigeon will sit 
still; if it be one that attacks sitting prey, the pigeon will rise up 
and fly away. 

In Thrace, in the district sometimes called that of Cedripolis, 
men hunt for little birds in the marshes with the aid of hawks. 
The men with sticks in their hands go beating at the reeds and 
brushwood to frighten the birds out, and the hawks show 



1757 



themselves overhead and frighten them down. The men then 
strike them with their sticks and capture them. They give a 
portion of their booty to the hawks; that is, they throw some of 
the birds up in the air, and the hawks catch them. 

In the neighbourhood of Lake Maeotis, it is said, wolves act in 
concert with the fishermen, and if the fishermen decline to 
share with them, they tear their nets in pieces as they lie drying 
on the shore of the lake. 



37 

So much for the habits of birds. 

In marine creatures, also, one In marine creatures, also, one 
may observe many ingenious devices adapted to the 
circumstances of their lives. For the accounts commonly given 
of the so-called fishing-frog are quite true; as are also those 
given of the torpedo. The fishing- frog has a set of filaments that 
project in front of its eyes; they are long and thin like hairs, and 
are round at the tips; they lie on either side, and are used as 
baits. Accordingly, when the animal stirs up a place full of sand 
and mud and conceals itself therein, it raises the filaments, and, 
when the little fish strike against them, it draws them in 
underneath into its mouth. The torpedo narcotizes the 
creatures that it wants to catch, overpowering them by the 
power of shock that is resident in its body, and feeds upon 
them; it also hides in the sand and mud, and catches all the 
creatures that swim in its way and come under its narcotizing 
influence. This phenomenon has been actually observed in 
operation. The sting-ray also conceals itself, but not exactly in 
the same way. That the creatures get their living by this means 
is obvious from the fact that, whereas they are peculiarly 



1758 



inactive, they are often caught with mullets in their interior, the 
swiftest of fishes. Furthermore, the fishing-frog is unusually 
thin when he is caught after losing the tips of his filaments, and 
the torpedo is known to cause a numbness even in human 
beings. Again, the hake, the ray, the flat-fish, and the angelfish 
burrow in the sand, and after concealing themselves angle with 
the filaments on their mouths, that fishermen call their fishing- 
rods, and the little creatures on which they feed swim up to the 
filaments taking them for bits of sea-weed, such as they feed 
upon. 

Wherever an anthias-fish is seen, there will be no dangerous 
creatures in the vicinity, and sponge-divers will dive in security, 
and they call these signal-fishes 'holy-fish'. It is a sort of 
perpetual coincidence, like the fact that wherever snails are 
present you may be sure there is neither pig nor partridge in the 
neighbourhood; for both pig and partridge eat up the snails. 

The sea-serpent resembles the conger in colour and shape, but 
is of lesser bulk and more rapid in its movements. If it be caught 
and thrown away, it will bore a hole with its snout and burrow 
rapidly in the sand; its snout, by the way, is sharper than that of 
ordinary serpents. The so-called sea-scolopendra, after 
swallowing the hook, turns itself inside out until it ejects it, and 
then it again turns itself outside in. The sea-scolopendra, like 
the land-scolopendra, will come to a savoury bait; the creature 
does not bite with its teeth, but stings by contact with its entire 
body, like the so-called sea-nettle. The so-called fox-shark, 
when it finds it has swallowed the hook, tries to get rid of it as 
the scolopendra does, but not in the same way; in other words, 
it runs up the fishing-line, and bites it off short; it is caught in 
some districts in deep and rapid waters, with night-lines. 

The bonitos swarm together when they espy a dangerous 
creature, and the largest of them swim round it, and if it 



1759 



touches one of the shoal they try to repel it; they have strong 
teeth. Amongst other large fish, a lamia-shark, after falling in 
amongst a shoal, has been seen to be covered with wounds. 

Of river-fish, the male of the sheat-fish is remarkably attentive 
to the young. The female after parturition goes away; the male 
stays and keeps on guard where the spawn is most abundant, 
contenting himself with keeping off all other little fishes that 
might steal the spawn or fry, and this he does for forty or fifty 
days, until the young are sufficiently grown to make away from 
the other fishes for themselves. The fishermen can tell where 
he is on guard: for, in warding off the little fishes, he makes a 
rush in the water and gives utterance to a kind of muttering 
noise. He is so earnest in the performance of his parental duties 
that the fishermen at times, if the eggs be attached to the roots 
of water-plants deep in the water, drag them into as shallow a 
place as possible; the male fish will still keep by the young, and, 
if it so happen, will be caught by the hook when snapping at the 
little fish that come by; if, however, he be sensible by experience 
of the danger of the hook, he will still keep by his charge, and 
with his extremely strong teeth will bite the hook in pieces. 

All fishes, both those that wander about and those that are 
stationary, occupy the districts where they were born or very 
similar places, for their natural food is found there. Carnivorous 
fish wander most; and all fish are carnivorous with the 
exception of a few, such as the mullet, the saupe, the red mullet, 
and the chalcis. The so-called pholis gives out a mucous 
discharge, which envelops the creature in a kind of nest. Of 
shell-fish, and fish that are finless, the scallop moves with 
greatest force and to the greatest distance, impelled along by 
some internal energy; the murex or purple-fish, and others that 
resemble it, move hardly at all. Out of the lagoon of Pyrrha all 
the fishes swim in winter-time, except the sea-gudgeon; they 
swim out owing to the cold, for the narrow waters are colder 



1760 



than the outer sea, and on the return of the early summer they 
all swim back again. In the lagoon no scarus is found, nor 
thritta, nor any other species of the spiny fish, no spotted 
dogfish, no spiny dogfish, no sea-crawfish, no octopus either of 
the common or the musky kinds, and certain other fish are also 
absent; but of fish that are found in the lagoon the white 
gudgeon is not a marine fish. Of fishes the oviparous are in their 
prime in the early summer until the spawning time; the 
viviparous in the autumn, as is also the case with the mullet, 
the red mullet, and all such fish. In the neighbourhood of 
Lesbos, the fishes of the outer sea, or of the lagoon, bring forth 
their eggs or young in the lagoon; sexual union takes place in 
the autumn, and parturition in the spring. With fishes of the 
cartilaginous kind, the males and females swarm together in 
the autumn for the sake of sexual union; in the early summer 
they come swimming in, and keep apart until after parturition; 
the two sexes are often taken linked together in sexual union. 

Of molluscs the sepia is the most cunning, and is the only 
species that employs its dark liquid for the sake of concealment 
as well as from fear: the octopus and calamary make the 
discharge solely from fear. These creatures never discharge the 
pigment in its entirety; and after a discharge the pigment 
accumulates again. The sepia, as has been said, often uses its 
colouring pigment for concealment; it shows itself in front of 
the pigment and then retreats back into it; it also hunts with its 
long tentacles not only little fishes, but oftentimes even mullets. 
The octopus is a stupid creature, for it will approach a man's 
hand if it be lowered in the water; but it is neat and thrifty in its 
habits: that is, it lays up stores in its nest, and, after eating up 
all that is eatable, it ejects the shells and sheaths of crabs and 
shell-fish, and the skeletons of little fishes. It seeks its prey by 
so changing its colour as to render it like the colour of the 
stones adjacent to it; it does so also when alarmed. By some the 
sepia is said to perform the same trick; that is, they say it can 



1761 



change its colour so as to make it resemble the colour of its 
habitat. The only fish that can do this is the angelfish, that is, it 
can change its colour like the octopus. The octopus as a rule 
does not live the year out. It has a natural tendency to run off 
into liquid; for, if beaten and squeezed, it keeps losing 
substance and at last disappears. The female after parturition is 
peculiarly subject to this colliquefaction; it becomes stupid; if 
tossed about by waves, it submits impassively; a man, if he 
dived, could catch it with the hand; it gets covered over with 
slime, and makes no effort to catch its wonted prey. The male 
becomes leathery and clammy. As a proof that they do not live 
into a second year there is the fact that, after the birth of the 
little octopuses in the late summer or beginning of autumn, it is 
seldom that a large-sized octopus is visible, whereas a little 
before this time of year the creature is at its largest. After the 
eggs are laid, they say that both the male and the female grow 
so old and feeble that they are preyed upon by little fish, and 
with ease dragged from their holes; and that this could not have 
been done previously; they say also that this is not the case 
with the small and young octopus, but that the young creature 
is much stronger than the grown-up one. Neither does the sepia 
live into a second year. The octopus is the only mollusc that 
ventures on to dry land; it walks by preference on rough ground; 
it is firm all over when you squeeze it, excepting in the neck. So 
much for the mollusca. 

It is also said that they make a thin rough shell about them like 
a hard sheath, and that this is made larger and larger as the 
animal grows larger, and that it comes out of the sheath as 
though out of a den or dwelling place. 

The nautilus (or argonaut) is a poulpe or octopus, but one 
peculiar both in its nature and its habits. It rises up from deep 
water and swims on the surface; it rises with its shell down- 
turned in order that it may rise the more easily and swim with 



1762 



it empty, but after reaching the surface it shifts the position of 
the shell. In between its feelers it has a certain amount of web- 
growth, resembling the substance between the toes of web- 
footed birds; only that with these latter the substance is thick, 
while with the nautilus it is thin and like a spider's web. It uses 
this structure, when a breeze is blowing, for a sail, and lets 
down some of its feelers alongside as rudder-oars. If it be 
frightened it fills its shell with water and sinks. With regard to 
the mode of generation and the growth of the shell knowledge 
from observation is not yet satisfactory; the shell, however, does 
not appear to be there from the beginning, but to grow in their 
cases as in that of other shell-fish; neither is it ascertained for 
certain whether the animal can live when stripped of the shell. 



38 

Of all insects, one may also say of all living creatures, the most 
industrious are the ant, the bee, the hornet, the wasp, and in 
point of fact all creatures akin to these; of spiders some are 
more skilful and more resourceful than others. The way in 
which ants work is open to ordinary observation; how they all 
march one after the other when they are engaged in putting 
away and storing up their food; all this may be seen, for they 
carry on their work even during bright moonlight nights. 



39 

Of spiders and phalangia there are many species. Of the 
venomous phalangia there are two; one that resembles the so- 



1763 



called wolf-spider, small, speckled, and tapering to a point; it 
moves with leaps, from which habit it is nicknamed 'the flea': 
the other kind is large, black in colour, with long front legs; it is 
heavy in its movements, walks slowly, is not very strong, and 
never leaps. (Of all the other species wherewith poison-vendors 
supply themselves, some give a weak bite, and others never bite 
at all. There is another kind, comprising the so-called wolf- 
spiders.) Of these spiders the small one weaves no web, and the 
large weaves a rude and poorly built one on the ground or on 
dry stone walls. It always builds its web over hollow places 
inside of which it keeps a watch on the end-threads, until some 
creature gets into the web and begins to struggle, when out the 
spider pounces. The speckled kind makes a little shabby web 
under trees. 

There is a third species of this animal, preeminently clever and 
artistic. It first weaves a thread stretching to all the exterior 
ends of the future web; then from the centre, which it hits upon 
with great accuracy, it stretches the warp; on the warp it puts 
what corresponds to the woof, and then weaves the whole 
together. It sleeps and stores its food away from the centre, but 
it is at the centre that it keeps watch for its prey. Then, when 
any creature touches the web and the centre is set in motion, it 
first ties and wraps the creature round with threads until it 
renders it helpless, then lifts it and carries it off, and, if it 
happens to be hungry, sucks out the life-juices - for that is the 
way it feeds; but, if it be not hungry, it first mends any damage 
done and then hastens again to its quest of prey. If something 
comes meanwhile into the net, the spider at first makes for the 
centre, and then goes back to its entangled prey as from a fixed 
starting point. If any one injures a portion of the web, it 
recommences weaving at sunrise or at sunset, because it is 
chiefly at these periods that creatures are caught in the web. It 
is the female that does the weaving and the hunting, but the 
male takes a share of the booty captured. 



1764 



Of the skilful spiders, weaving a substantial web, there are two 
kinds, the larger and the smaller. The one has long legs and 
keeps watch while swinging downwards from the web: from its 
large size it cannot easily conceal itself, and so it keeps 
underneath, so that its prey may not be frightened off, but may 
strike upon the web's upper surface; the less awkwardly formed 
one lies in wait on the top, using a little hole for a lurking-place. 
Spiders can spin webs from the time of their birth, not from 
their interior as a superfluity or excretion, as Democritus avers, 
but off their body as a kind of tree-bark, like the creatures that 
shoot out with their hair, as for instance the porcupine. The 
creature can attack animals larger than itself, and enwrap them 
with its threads: in other words, it will attack a small lizard, run 
round and draw threads about its mouth until it closes the 
mouth up; then it comes up and bites it. 



40 

So much for the spider. Of insects, there is a genus that has no 
one name that comprehends all the species, though all the 
species are akin to one another in form; it consists of all the 
insects that construct a honeycomb: to wit, the bee, and all the 
insects that resemble it in form. 

There are nine varieties, of which six are gregarious - the bee, 
the king-bee, the drone bee, the annual wasp, and, furthermore, 
the anthrene (or hornet), and the tenthredo (or ground-wasp); 
three are solitary - the smaller siren, of a dun colour, the larger 
siren, black and speckled, and the third, the largest of all, that is 
called the humble-bee. Now ants never go a-hunting, but gather 
up what is ready to hand; the spider makes nothing, and lays up 
no store, but simply goes a-hunting for its food; while the bee - 



1765 



for we shall by and by treat of the nine varieties - does not go a- 
hunting, but constructs its food out of gathered material and 
stores it away, for honey is the bee's food. This fact is shown by 
the beekeepers' attempt to remove the combs; for the bees, 
when they are fumigated, and are suffering great distress from 
the process, then devour the honey most ravenously, whereas at 
other times they are never observed to be so greedy, but 
apparently are thrifty and disposed to lay by for their future 
sustenance. They have also another food which is called bee- 
bread; this is scarcer than honey and has a sweet figlike taste; 
this they carry as they do the wax on their legs. 

Very remarkable diversity is observed in their methods of 
working and their general habits. When the hive has been 
delivered to them clean and empty, they build their waxen cells, 
bringing in the juice of all kinds of flowers and the 'tears' or 
exuding sap of trees, such as willows and elms and such others 
as are particularly given to the exudation of gum. With this 
material they besmear the groundwork, to provide against 
attacks of other creatures; the bee-keepers call this stuff 'stop- 
wax'. They also with the same material narrow by side-building 
the entrances to the hive if they are too wide. They first build 
cells for themselves; then for the so-called kings and the 
drones; for themselves they are always building, for the kings 
only when the brood of young is numerous, and cells for the 
drones they build if a superabundance of honey should suggest 
their doing so. They build the royal cells next to their own, and 
they are of small bulk; the drones' cells they build near by, and 
these latter are less in bulk than the bee's cells. 

They begin building the combs downwards from the top of the 
hive, and go down and down building many combs connected 
together until they reach the bottom. The cells, both those for 
the honey and those also for the grubs, are double-doored; for 
two cells are ranged about a single base, one pointing one way 



1766 



and one the other, after the manner of a double (or hour-glass- 
shaped) goblet. The cells that lie at the commencement of the 
combs and are attached to the hives, to the extent of two or 
three concentric circular rows, are small and devoid of honey; 
the cells that are well filled with honey are most thoroughly 
luted with wax. At the entry to the hive the aperture of the 
doorway is smeared with mitys; this substance is a deep black, 
and is a sort of dross or residual by-product of wax; it has a 
pungent odour, and is a cure for bruises and suppurating sores. 
The greasy stuff that comes next is pitch-wax; it has a less 
pungent odour and is less medicinal than the mitys. Some say 
that the drones construct combs by themselves in the same 
hive and in the same comb that they share with the bees; but 
that they make no honey, but subsist, they and their grubs also, 
on the honey made by the bees. The drones, as a rule, keep 
inside the hive; when they go out of doors, they soar up in the 
air in a stream, whirling round and round in a kind of 
gymnastic exercise; when this is over, they come inside the hive 
and feed to repletion ravenously. The kings never quit the hive, 
except in conjunction with the entire swarm, either for food or 
for any other reason. They say that, if a young swarm go astray, 
it will turn back upon its route and by the aid of scent seek out 
its leader. It is said that if he is unable to fly he is carried by the 
swarm, and that if he dies the swarm perishes; and that, if this 
swarm outlives the king for a while and constructs combs, no 
honey is produced and the bees soon die out. 

Bees scramble up the stalks of flowers and rapidly gather the 
bees-wax with their front legs; the front legs wipe it off on to 
the middle legs, and these pass it on to the hollow curves of the 
hind-legs; when thus laden, they fly away home, and one may 
see plainly that their load is a heavy one. On each expedition 
the bee does not fly from a flower of one kind to a flower of 
another, but flies from one violet, say, to another violet, and 
never meddles with another flower until it has got back to the 



1767 



hive; on reaching the hive they throw off their load, and each 
bee on his return is accompanied by three or four companions. 
One cannot well tell what is the substance they gather, nor the 
exact process of their work. Their mode of gathering wax has 
been observed on olive-trees, as owing to the thickness of the 
leaves the bees remain stationary for a considerable while. After 
this work is over, they attend to the grubs. There is nothing to 
prevent grubs, honey, and drones being all found in one and the 
same comb. As long as the leader is alive, the drones are said to 
be produced apart by themselves; if he be no longer living, they 
are said to be reared by the bees in their own cells, and under 
these circumstances to become more spirited: for this reason 
they are called 'sting-drones', not that they really have stings, 
but that they have the wish without the power, to use such 
weapons. The cells for the drones are larger than the others; 
sometimes the bees construct cells for the drones apart, but 
usually they put them in amongst their own; and when this is 
the case the bee-keepers cut the drone-cells out of the combs. 

There are several species of bees, as has been said; two of 
'kings', the better kind red, the other black and variegated, and 
twice as big as the working-bee. The best workingbee is small, 
round, and speckled: another kind is long and like an anthrene 
wasp; another kind is what is called the robber-bee, black and 
flat-bellied; then there is the drone, the largest of all, but devoid 
of sting, and lazy. There is a difference between the progeny of 
bees that inhabit cultivated land and of those from the 
mountains: the forest-bees are more shaggy, smaller, more 
industrious and more fierce. Working-bees make their combs all 
even, with the superficial covering quite smooth. Each comb is 
of one kind only: that is, it contains either bees only, or grubs 
only, or drones only; if it happen, however, that they make in 
one and the same comb all these kinds of cells, each separate 
kind will be built in a continuous row right through. The long 
bees build uneven combs, with the lids of the cells protuberant, 



1768 



like those of the anthrene; grubs and everything else have no 
fixed places, but are put anywhere; from these bees come 
inferior kings, a large quantity of drones, and the so-called 
robber-bee; they produce either no honey at all, or honey in very 
small quantities. Bees brood over the combs and so mature 
them; if they fail to do so, the combs are said to go bad and to 
get covered with a sort of spider's web. If they can keep 
brooding over the part undamaged, the damaged part simply 
eats itself away; if they cannot so brood, the entire comb 
perishes; in the damaged combs small worms are engendered, 
which take on wings and fly away. When the combs keep 
settling down, the bees restore the level surface, and put props 
underneath the combs to give themselves free passage-room; 
for if such free passage be lacking they cannot brood, and the 
cobwebs come on. When the robber-bee and the drone appear, 
not only do they do no work themselves, but they actually 
damage the work of the other bees; if they are caught in the act, 
they are killed by the working-bees. These bees also kill without 
mercy most of their kings, and especially kings of the inferior 
sort; and this they do for fear a multiplicity of kings should lead 
to a dismemberment of the hive. They kill them especially when 
the hive is deficient in grubs, and a swarm is not intended to 
take place; under these circumstances they destroy the cells of 
the kings if they have been prepared, on the ground that these 
kings are always ready to lead out swarms. They destroy also 
the combs of the drones if a failure in the supply be threatening 
and the hive runs short of provisions; under such circumstances 
they fight desperately with all who try to take their honey, and 
eject from the hive all the resident drones; and oftentimes the 
drones are to be seen sitting apart in the hive. The little bees 
fight vigorously with the long kind, and try to banish them from 
the hives; if they succeed, the hive will be unusually productive, 
but if the bigger bees get left mistresses of the field they pass 
the time in idleness, and no good at all but die out before the 



1769 



autumn. Whenever the working-bees kill an enemy they try to 
do so out of doors; and whenever one of their own body dies, 
they carry the dead bee out of doors also. The so-called robber- 
bees spoil their own combs, and, if they can do so unnoticed, 
enter and spoil the combs of other bees; if they are caught in 
the act they are put to death. It is no easy task for them to 
escape detection, for there are sentinels on guard at every entry; 
and, even if they do escape detection on entering, afterwards 
from a surfeit of food they cannot fly, but go rolling about in 
front of the hive, so that their chances of escape are small 
indeed. The kings are never themselves seen outside the hive 
except with a swarm in flight: during which time all the other 
bees cluster around them. When the flight of a swarm is 
imminent, a monotonous and quite peculiar sound made by all 
the bees is heard for several days, and for two or three days in 
advance a few bees are seen flying round the hive; it has never 
as yet been ascertained, owing to the difficulty of the 
observation, whether or no the king is among these. When they 
have swarmed, they fly away and separate off to each of the 
kings; if a small swarm happens to settle near to a large one, it 
will shift to join this large one, and if the king whom they have 
abandoned follows them, they put him to death. So much for 
the quitting of the hive and the swarmflight. Separate 
detachments of bees are told off for diverse operations; that is, 
some carry flower-produce, others carry water, others smooth 
and arrange the combs. A bee carries water when it is rearing 
grubs. No bee ever settles on the flesh of any creature, or ever 
eats animal food. They have no fixed date for commencing 
work; but when their provender is forthcoming and they are in 
comfortable trim, and by preference in summer, they set to 
work, and when the weather is fine they work incessantly. 

The bee, when quite young and in fact only three days old, after 
shedding its chrysalis-case, begins to work if it be well fed. 
When a swarm is settling, some bees detach themselves in 



1770 



search of food and return back to the swarm. In hives that are in 
good condition the production of young bees is discontinued 
only for the forty days that follow the winter solstice. When the 
grubs are grown, the bees put food beside them and cover them 
with a coating of wax; and, as soon as the grub is strong 
enough, he of his own accord breaks the lid and comes out. 
Creatures that make their appearance in hives and spoil the 
combs the working-bees clear out, but the other bees from 
sheer laziness look with indifference on damage done to their 
produce. When the bee-masters take out the combs, they leave 
enough food behind for winter use; if it be sufficient in quantity, 
the occupants of the hive will survive; if it be insufficient, then, 
if the weather be rough, they die on the spot, but if it be fair, 
they fly away and desert the hive. They feed on honey summer 
and winter; but they store up another article of food resembling 
wax in hardness, which by some is called sandarace, or bee- 
bread. Their worst enemies are wasps and the birds named 
titmice, and furthermore the swallow and the bee-eater. The 
frogs in the marsh also catch them if they come in their way by 
the water-side, and for this reason bee-keepers chase the frogs 
from the ponds from which the bees take water; they destroy 
also wasps' nests, and the nests of swallows, in the 
neighbourhood of the hives, and also the nests of bee-eaters. 
Bees have fear only of one another. They fight with one another 
and with wasps. Away from the hive they attack neither their 
own species nor any other creature, but in the close proximity 
of the hive they kill whatever they get hold of. Bees that sting 
die from their inability to extract the sting without at the same 
time extracting their intestines. True, they often recover, if the 
person stung takes the trouble to press the sting out; but once it 
loses its sting the bee must die. They can kill with their stings 
even large animals; in fact, a horse has been known to have 
been stung to death by them. The kings are the least disposed to 
show anger or to inflict a sting. Bees that die are removed from 



1771 



the hive, and in every way the creature is remarkable for its 
cleanly habits; in point of fact, they often fly away to a distance 
to void their excrement because it is malodorous; and, as has 
been said, they are annoyed by all bad smells and by the scent 
of perfumes, so much so that they sting people that use 
perfumes. 

They perish from a number of accidental causes, and when 
their kings become too numerous and try each to carry away a 
portion of the swarm. 

The toad also feeds on bees; he comes to the doorway of the 
hive, puffs himself out as he sits on the watch, and devours the 
creatures as they come flying out; the bees can in no way 
retaliate, but the bee-keeper makes a point of killing him. 

As for the class of bee that has been spoken of as inferior or 
good-for-nothing, and as constructing its combs so roughly, 
some bee-keepers say that it is the young bees that act so from 
inexperience; and the bees of the current year are termed 
young. The young bees do not sting as the others do; and it is 
for this reason that swarms may be safely carried, as it is of 
young bees that they are composed. When honey runs short 
they expel the drones, and the bee-keepers supply the bees with 
figs and sweet-tasting articles of food. The elder bees do the 
indoor work, and are rough and hairy from staying indoors; the 
young bees do the outer carrying, and are comparatively 
smooth. They kill the drones also when in their work they are 
confined for room; the drones, by the way, live in the innermost 
recess of the hive. On one occasion, when a hive was in a poor 
condition, some of the occupants assailed a foreign hive; 
proving victorious in a combat they took to carrying off the 
honey; when the bee-keeper tried to kill them, the other bees 
came out and tried to beat off the enemy but made no attempt 
to sting the man. 



1772 



The diseases that chiefly attack prosperous hives are first of all 
the clerus-this consists in a growth of little worms on the floor, 
from which, as they develop, a kind of cobweb grows over the 
entire hive, and the combs decay; another diseased condition is 
indicated in a lassitude on the part of the bees and in 
malodorousness of the hive. Bees feed on thyme; and the white 
thyme is better than the red. In summer the place for the hive 
should be cool, and in winter warm. They are very apt to fall 
sick if the plant they are at work on be mildewed. In a high wind 
they carry a stone by way of ballast to steady them. If a stream 
be near at hand, they drink from it and from it only, but before 
they drink they first deposit their load; if there be no water near 
at hand, they disgorge their honey as they drink elsewhere, and 
at once make off to work. There are two seasons for making 
honey, spring and autumn; the spring honey is sweeter, whiter, 
and in every way better than the autumn honey. Superior honey 
comes from fresh comb, and from young shoots; the red honey 
is inferior, and owes its inferiority to the comb in which it is 
deposited, just as wine is apt to be spoiled by its cask; 
consequently, one should have it looked to and dried. When the 
thyme is in flower and the comb is full, the honey does not 
harden. The honey that is golden in hue is excellent. White 
honey does not come from thyme pure and simple; it is good as 
a salve for sore eyes and wounds. Poor honey always floats on 
the surface and should be skimmed off; the fine clear honey 
rests below. When the floral world is in full bloom, then they 
make wax; consequently you must then take the wax out of the 
hive, for they go to work on new wax at once. The flowers from 
which they gather honey are as follows: the spindle-tree, the 
melilot-clover, king's-spear, myrtle, flowering-reed, withy, and 
broom. When they work at thyme, they mix in water before 
sealing up the comb. As has been already stated, they all either 
fly to a distance to discharge their excrement or make the 
discharge into one single comb. The little bees, as has been said, 



1773 



are more industrious than the big ones; their wings are 
battered; their colour is black, and they have a burnt-up aspect. 
Gaudy and showy bees, like gaudy and showy women, are good- 
for-nothings. 

Bees seem to take a pleasure in listening to a rattling noise; and 
consequently men say that they can muster them into a hive by 
rattling with crockery or stones; it is uncertain, however, 
whether or no they can hear the noise at all and also whether 
their procedure is due to pleasure or alarm. They expel from the 
hive all idlers and unthrifts. As has been said, they differentiate 
their work; some make wax, some make honey, some make bee- 
bread, some shape and mould combs, some bring water to the 
cells and mingle it with the honey, some engage in out-of-door 
work. At early dawn they make no noise, until some one 
particular bee makes a buzzing noise two or three times and 
thereby awakes the rest; hereupon they all fly in a body to work. 
By and by they return and at first are noisy; then the noise 
gradually decreases, until at last some one bee flies round 
about, making a buzzing noise, and apparently calling on the 
others to go to sleep; then all of a sudden there is a dead 
silence. 

The hive is known to be in good condition if the noise heard 
within it is loud, and if the bees make a flutter as they go out 
and in; for at this time they are constructing brood-cells. They 
suffer most from hunger when they recommence work after 
winter. They become somewhat lazy if the bee-keeper, in 
robbing the hive, leave behind too much honey; still one should 
leave cells numerous in proportion to the population, for the 
bees work in a spiritless way if too few combs are left. They 
become idle also, as being dispirited, if the hive be too big. A 
hive yields to the bee-keeper six or nine pints of honey; a 
prosperous hive will yield twelve or fifteen pints, exceptionally 
good hives eighteen. Sheep and, as has been said, wasps are 



1774 



enemies to the bees. Bee-keepers entrap the latter, by putting a 
flat dish on the ground with pieces of meat on it; when a 
number of the wasps settle on it, they cover them with a lid and 
put the dish and its contents on the fire. It is a good thing to 
have a few drones in a hive, as their presence increases the 
industry of the workers. Bees can tell the approach of rough 
weather or of rain; and the proof is that they will not fly away, 
but even while it is as yet fine they go fluttering about within a 
restricted space, and the bee-keeper knows from this that they 
are expecting bad weather. When the bees inside the hive hang 
clustering to one another, it is a sign that the swarm is 
intending to quit; consequently, occasion, when a bee-keepers, 
on seeing this, besprinkle the hive with sweet wine. It is 
advisable to plant about the hives pear-trees, beans, Median- 
grass, Syrian-grass, yellow pulse, myrtle, poppies, creeping- 
thyme, and almond-trees. Some bee-keepers sprinkle their bees 
with flour, and can distinguish them from others when they are 
at work out of doors. If the spring be late, or if there be drought 
or blight, then grubs are all the fewer in the hives. So much for 
the habits of bees. 



41 

Of wasps, there are two kinds. Of these kinds one is wild and 
scarce, lives on the mountains, engenders grubs not 
underground but on oak-trees, is larger, longer, and blacker than 
the other kind, is invariably speckled and furnished with a sting, 
and is remarkably courageous. The pain from its sting is more 
severe than that caused by the others, for the instrument that 
causes the pain is larger, in proportion to its own larger size. 
These wild live over into a second year, and in winter time, 
when oaks have been in course of felling, they may be seen 



1775 



coming out and flying away. They lie concealed during the 
winter, and live in the interior of logs of wood. Some of them are 
mother-wasps and some are workers, as with the tamer kind; 
but it is by observation of the tame wasps that one may learn 
the varied characteristics of the mothers and the workers. For in 
the case of the tame wasps also there are two kinds; one 
consists of leaders, who are called mothers, and the other of 
workers. The leaders are far larger and milder-tempered than 
the others. The workers do not live over into a second year, but 
all die when winter comes on; and this can be proved, for at the 
commencement of winter the workers become drowsy, and 
about the time of the winter solstice they are never seen at all. 
The leaders, the so-called mothers, are seen all through the 
winter, and live in holes underground; for men when ploughing 
or digging in winter have often come upon mother-wasps, but 
never upon workers. The mode of reproduction of wasps is as 
follows. At the approach of summer, when the leaders have 
found a sheltered spot, they take to moulding their combs, and 
construct the so-called sphecons, - little nests containing four 
cells or thereabouts, and in these are produced working-wasps 
but not mothers. When these are grown up, then they construct 
other larger combs upon the first, and then again in like 
manner others; so that by the close of autumn there are 
numerous large combs in which the leader, the so-called 
mother, engenders no longer working-wasps but mothers. 
These develop high up in the nest as large grubs, in cells that 
occur in groups of four or rather more, pretty much in the same 
way as we have seen the grubs of the king-bees to be produced 
in their cells. After the birth of the working-grubs in the cells, 
the leaders do nothing and the workers have to supply them 
with nourishment; and this is inferred from the fact that the 
leaders (of the working- wasps) no longer fly out at this time, but 
rest quietly indoors. Whether the leaders of last year after 
engendering new leaders are killed by the new brood, and 



1776 



whether this occurs invariably or whether they can live for a 
longer time, has not been ascertained by actual observation; 
neither can we speak with certainty, as from observation, as to 
the age attained by the mother-wasp or by the wild wasps, or as 
to any other similar phenomenon. The mother-wasp is broad 
and heavy, fatter and larger than the ordinary wasp, and from 
its weight not very strong on the wing; these wasps cannot fly 
far, and for this reason they always rest inside the nest, building 
and managing its indoor arrangements. The so-called mother- 
wasps are found in most of the nests; it is a matter of doubt 
whether or no they are provided with stings; in all probability, 
like the king-bees, they have stings, but never protrude them for 
offence. Of the ordinary wasps some are destitute of stings, like 
the drone-bees, and some are provided with them. Those 
unprovided therewith are smaller and less spirited and never 
fight, while the others are big and courageous; and these latter, 
by some, are called males, and the stingless, females. At the 
approach of winter many of the wasps that have stings appear 
to lose them; but we have never met an eyewitness of this 
phenomenon. Wasps are more abundant in times of drought 
and in wild localities. They live underground; their combs they 
mould out of chips and earth, each comb from a single origin, 
like a kind of root. They feed on certain flowers and fruits, but 
for the most part on animal food. Some of the tame wasps have 
been observed when sexually united, but it was not determined 
whether both, or neither, had stings, or whether one had a sting 
and the other had not; wild wasps have been seen under similar 
circumstances, when one was seen to have a sting but the case 
of the other was left undetermined. The wasp-grub does not 
appear to come into existence by parturition, for at the outset 
the grub is too big to be the offspring of a wasp. If you take a 
wasp by the feet and let him buzz with the vibration of his 
wings, wasps that have no stings will fly toward it, and wasps 
that have stings will not; from which fact it is inferred by some 



1777 



that one set are males and the other females. In holes in the 
ground in winter-time wasps are found, some with stings, and 
some without. Some build cells, small and few in number; 
others build many and large ones. The so-called mothers are 
caught at the change of season, mostly on elm-trees, while 
gathering a substance sticky and gumlike. A large number of 
mother-wasps are found when in the previous year wasps have 
been numerous and the weather rainy; they are captured in 
precipitous places, or in vertical clefts in the ground, and they 
all appear to be furnished with stings. 



42 

So much for the habits of wasps. 

Anthrenae do not subsist by culling from flowers as bees do, but 
for the most part on animal food: for this reason they hover 
about dung; for they chase the large flies, and after catching 
them lop off their heads and fly away with the rest of the 
carcases; they are furthermore fond of sweet fruits. Such is their 
food. They have also kings or leaders like bees and wasps; and 
their leaders are larger in proportion to themselves than are 
wasp-kings to wasps or bee-kings to bees. The anthrena-king, 
like the wasp-king, lives indoors. Anthrenae build their nests 
underground, scraping out the soil like ants; for neither 
anthrenae nor wasps go off in swarms as bees do, but 
successive layers of young anthrenae keep to the same habitat, 
and go on enlarging their nest by scraping out more and more 
of soil. The nest accordingly attains a great size; in fact, from a 
particularly prosperous nest have been removed three and even 
four baskets full of combs. They do not, like bees, store up food, 
but pass the winter in a torpid condition; the greater part of 



1778 



them die in the winter, but it is uncertain whether that can be 
said of them all, In the hives of bees several kings are found and 
they lead off detachments in swarms, but in the anthrena's nest 
only one king is found. When individual anthrenae have strayed 
from their nest, they cluster on a tree and construct combs, as 
may be often seen above-ground, and in this nest they produce 
a king; when the king is full-grown, he leads them away and 
settles them along with himself in a hive or nest. With regard to 
their sexual unions, and the method of their reproduction, 
nothing is known from actual observation. Among bees both the 
drones and the kings are stingless, and so are certain wasps, as 
has been said; but anthrenae appear to be all furnished with 
stings: though, by the way, it would well be worth while to carry 
out investigation as to whether the anthrena-king has a sting or 
not. 



43 

Humble-bees produce their young under a stone, right on the 
ground, in a couple of cells or little more; in these cells is found 
an attempt at honey, of a poor description. The tenthredon is 
like the anthrena, but speckled, and about as broad as a bee. 
Being epicures as to their food, they fly, one at a time, into 
kitchens and on to slices of fish and the like dainties. The 
tenthredon brings forth, like the wasp, underground, and is very 
prolific; its nest is much bigger and longer than that of the 
wasp. So much for the methods of working and the habits of life 
of the bee, the wasp, and all the other similar insects. 



1779 



44 

As regards the disposition or temper of animals, as has been 
previously observed, one may detect great differences in respect 
to courage and timidity, as also, even among wild animals, in 
regard to tameness and wildness. The lion, while he is eating, is 
most ferocious; but when he is not hungry and has had a good 
meal, he is quite gentle. He is totally devoid of suspicion or 
nervous fear, is fond of romping with animals that have been 
reared along with him and to whom he is accustomed, and 
manifests great affection towards them. In the chase, as long as 
he is in view, he makes no attempt to run and shows no fear, 
but even if he be compelled by the multitude of the hunters to 
retreat, he withdraws deliberately, step by step, every now and 
then turning his head to regard his pursuers. If, however, he 
reach wooded cover, then he runs at full speed, until he comes 
to open ground, when he resumes his leisurely retreat. When, in 
the open, he is forced by the number of the hunters to run while 
in full view, he does run at the top of his speed, but without 
leaping and bounding. This running of his is evenly and 
continuously kept up like the running of a dog; but when he is 
in pursuit of his prey and is close behind, he makes a sudden 
pounce upon it. The two statements made regarding him are 
quite true; the one that he is especially afraid of fire, as Homer 
pictures him in the line - 'and glowing torches, which, though 
fierce he dreads,' - and the other, that he keeps a steady eye 
upon the hunter who hits him, and flings himself upon him. If a 
hunter hit him, without hurting him, then if with a bound he 
gets hold of him, he will do him no harm, not even with his 
claws, but after shaking him and giving him a fright will let him 
go again. They invade the cattle-folds and attack human beings 
when they are grown old and so by reason of old age and the 
diseased condition of their teeth are unable to pursue their 
wonted prey. They live to a good old age. The lion who was 
captured when lame, had a number of his teeth broken; which 



1780 



fact was regarded by some as a proof of the longevity of lions, as 
he could hardly have been reduced to this condition except at 
an advanced age. There are two species of lions, the plump, 
curly-maned, and the long-bodied, straight maned; the latter 
kind is courageous, and the former comparatively timid; 
sometimes they run away with their tail between their legs, like 
a dog. A lion was once seen to be on the point of attacking a 
boar, but to run away when the boar stiffened his bristles in 
defence. It is susceptible of hurt from a wound in the flank, but 
on any other part of its frame will endure any number of blows, 
and its head is especially hard. Whenever it inflicts a wound, 
either by its teeth or its claws, there flows from the wounded 
parts suppurating matter, quite yellow, and not to be stanched 
by bandage or sponge; the treatment for such a wound is the 
same as that for the bite of a dog. 

The thos, or civet, is fond of man's company; it does him no 
harm and is not much afraid of him, but it is an enemy to the 
dog and the lion, and consequently is not found in the same 
habitat with them. The little ones are the best. Some say that 
there are two species of the animal, and some say, three; there 
are probably not more than three, but, as is the case with 
certain of the fishes, birds, and quadrupeds, this animal 
changes in appearance with the change of season. His colour in 
winter is not the same as it is in summer; in summer the 
animal is smooth-haired, in winter he is clothed in fur. 



45 

The bison is found in Paeonia on Mount Messapium, which 
separates Paeonia from Maedica; and the Paeonians call it the 
monapos. It is the size of a bull, but stouter in build, and not 



1781 



long in the body; its skin, stretched tight on a frame, would give 
sitting room for seven people. In general it resembles the ox in 
appearance, except that it has a mane that reaches down to the 
point of the shoulder, as that of the horse reaches down to its 
withers; but the hair in its mane is softer than the hair in the 
horse's mane, and clings more closely. The colour of the hair is 
brown-yellow; the mane reaches down to the eyes, and is deep 
and thick. The colour of the body is half red, half ashen-grey, 
like that of the so-called chestnut horse, but rougher. It has an 
undercoat of woolly hair. The animal is not found either very 
black or very red. It has the bellow of a bull. Its horns are 
crooked, turned inwards towards each other and useless for 
purposes of self-defence; they are a span broad, or a little more, 
and in volume each horn would hold about three pints of liquid; 
the black colour of the horn is beautiful and bright. The tuft of 
hair on the forehead reaches down to the eyes, so that the 
animal sees objects on either flank better than objects right in 
front. It has no upper teeth, as is the case also with kine and all 
other horned animals. Its legs are hairy; it is cloven-footed, and 
the tail, which resembles that of the ox, seems not big enough 
for the size of its body. It tosses up dust and scoops out the 
ground with its hooves, like the bull. Its skin is impervious to 
blows. Owing to the savour of its flesh it is sought for in the 
chase. When it is wounded it runs away, and stops only when 
thoroughly exhausted. It defends itself against an assailant by 
kicking and projecting its excrement to a distance of eight 
yards; this device it can easily adopt over and over again, and 
the excrement is so pungent that the hair of hunting-dogs is 
burnt off by it. It is only when the animal is disturbed or 
alarmed that the dung has this property; when the animal is 
undisturbed it has no blistering effect. So much for the shape 
and habits of the animal. When the season comes for 
parturition the mothers give birth to their young in troops upon 
the mountains. Before dropping their young they scatter their 



1782 



dung in all directions, making a kind of circular rampart around 
them; for the animal has the faculty of ejecting excrement in 
most extraordinary quantities. 



46 

Of all wild animals the most easily tamed and the gentlest is 
the elephant. It can be taught a number of tricks, the drift and 
meaning of which it understands; as, for instance, it can taught 
to kneel in presence of the king. It is very sensitive, and 
possessed of an intelligence superior to that of other animals. 
When the male has had sexual union with the female, and the 
female has conceived, the male has no further intercourse with 
her. 

Some say that the elephant lives for two hundred years; others, 
for one hundred and twenty; that the female lives nearly as 
long as the male; that they reach their prime about the age of 
sixty, and that they are sensitive to inclement weather and 
frost. The elephant is found by the banks of rivers, but he is not 
a river animal; he can make his way through water, as long as 
the tip of his trunk can be above the surface, for he blows with 
his trunk and breathes through it. The animal is a poor 
swimmer owing to the heavy weight of his body. 



47 

The male camel declines intercourse with its mother; if his 
keeper tries compulsion, he evinces disinclination. On one 
occasion, when intercourse was being declined by the young 



1783 



male, the keeper covered over the mother and put the young 
male to her; but, when after the intercourse the wrapping had 
been removed, though the operation was completed and could 
not be revoked, still by and by he bit his keeper to death. A story 
goes that the king of Scythia had a highly-bred mare, and that 
all her foals were splendid; that wishing to mate the best of the 
young males with the mother, he had him brought to the stall 
for the purpose; that the young horse declined; that, after the 
mother's head had been concealed in a wrapper he, in 
ignorance, had intercourse; and that, when immediately 
afterwards the wrapper was removed and the head of the mare 
was rendered visible, the young horse ran way and hurled 
himself down a precipice. 



48 

Among the sea-fishes many stories are told about the dolphin, 
indicative of his gentle and kindly nature, and of manifestations 
of passionate attachment to boys, in and about Tarentum, Caria, 
and other places. The story goes that, after a dolphin had been 
caught and wounded off the coast of Caria, a shoal of dolphins 
came into the harbour and stopped there until the fisherman 
let his captive go free; whereupon the shoal departed. A shoal of 
young dolphins is always, by way of protection, followed by a 
large one. On one occasion a shoal of dolphins, large and small, 
was seen, and two dolphins at a little distance appeared 
swimming in underneath a little dead dolphin when it was 
sinking, and supporting it on their backs, trying out of 
compassion to prevent its being devoured by some predaceous 
fish. Incredible stories are told regarding the rapidity of 
movement of this creature. It appears to be the fleetest of all 
animals, marine and terrestrial, and it can leap over the masts 



1784 



of large vessels. This speed is chiefly manifested when they are 
pursuing a fish for food; then, if the fish endeavours to escape, 
they pursue him in their ravenous hunger down to deep waters; 
but, when the necessary return swim is getting too long, they 
hold in their breath, as though calculating the length of it, and 
then draw themselves together for an effort and shoot up like 
arrows, trying to make the long ascent rapidly in order to 
breathe, and in the effort they spring right over the a ship's 
masts if a ship be in the vicinity. This same phenomenon is 
observed in divers, when they have plunged into deep water; 
that is, they pull themselves together and rise with a speed 
proportional to their strength. Dolphins live together in pairs, 
male and female. It is not known for what reason they run 
themselves aground on dry land; at all events, it is said that 
they do so at times, and for no obvious reason. 



49 

Just as with all animals a change of action follows a change of 
circumstance, so also a change of character follows a change of 
action, and often some portions of the physical frame undergo a 
change, occurs in the case of birds. Hens, for instance, when 
they have beaten the cock in a fight, will crow like the cock and 
endeavour to tread him; the crest rises up on their head and the 
tail-feathers on the rump, so that it becomes difficult to 
recognize that they are hens; in some cases there is a growth of 
small spurs. On the death of a hen a cock has been seen to 
undertake the maternal duties, leading the chickens about and 
providing them with food, and so intent upon these duties as to 
cease crowing and indulging his sexual propensities. Some 
cock-birds are congenitally so feminine that they will submit 
patiently to other males who attempt to tread them. 



1785 



50 

Some animals change their form and character, not only at 
certain ages and at certain seasons, but in consequence of being 
castrated; and all animals possessed of testicles may be 
submitted to this operation. Birds have their testicles inside, 
and oviparous quadrupeds close to the loins; and of viviparous 
animals that walk some have them inside, and most have them 
outside, but all have them at the lower end of the belly. Birds are 
castrated at the rump at the part where the two sexes unite in 
copulation. If you burn this twice or thrice with hot irons, then, 
if the bird be full-grown, his crest grows sallow, he ceases to 
crow, and foregoes sexual passion; but if you cauterize the bird 
when young, none of these male attributes propensities will 
come to him as he grows up. The case is the same with men: if 
you mutilate them in boyhood, the later-growing hair never 
comes, and the voice never changes but remains high-pitched; 
if they be mutilated in early manhood, the late growths of hair 
quit them except the growth on the groin, and that diminishes 
but does not entirely depart. The congenital growths of hair 
never fall out, for a eunuch never grows bald. In the case of all 
castrated or mutilated male quadrupeds the voice changes to 
the feminine voice. All other quadrupeds when castrated, 
unless the operation be performed when they are young, 
invariably die; but in the case of boars, and in their case only, 
the age at which the operation is performed produces no 
difference. All animals, if operated on when they are young, 
become bigger and better looking than their unmutilated 
fellows; if they be mutilated when full-grown, they do not take 
on any increase of size. If stags be mutilated, when, by reason of 
their age, they have as yet no horns, they never grow horns at 



1786 



all; if they be mutilated when they have horns, the horns 
remain unchanged in size, and the animal does not lose them. 
Calves are mutilated when a year old; otherwise, they turn out 
uglier and smaller. Steers are mutilated in the following way: 
they turn the animal over on its back, cut a little off the scrotum 
at the lower end, and squeeze out the testicles, then push back 
the roots of them as far as they can, and stop up the incision 
with hair to give an outlet to suppurating matter; if 
inflammation ensues, they cauterize the scrotum and put on a 
plaster. If a full-grown bull be mutilated, he can still to all 
appearance unite sexually with the cow. The ovaries of sows are 
excised with the view of quenching in them sexual appetites 
and of stimulating growth in size and fatness. The sow has first 
to be kept two days without food, and, after being hung up by 
the hind legs, it is operated on; they cut the lower belly, about 
the place where the boars have their testicles, for it is there that 
the ovary grows, adhering to the two divisions (or horns) of the 
womb; they cut off a little piece and stitch up the incision. 
Female camels are mutilated when they are wanted for war 
purposes, and are mutilated to prevent their being got with 
young. Some of the inhabitants of Upper Asia have as many as 
three thousand camels: when they run, they run, in 
consequence of the length of their stride, much quicker than 
the horses of Nisaea. As a general rule, mutilated animals grow 
to a greater length than the unmutilated. 

All animals that ruminate derive profit and pleasure from the 
process of rumination, as they do from the process of eating. It 
is the animals that lack the upper teeth that ruminate, such as 
kine, sheep, and goats. In the case of wild animals no 
observation has been possible; save in the case of animals that 
are occasionally domesticated, such as the stag, and it, we 
know, chews the cud. All animals that ruminate generally do so 
when lying down on the ground. They carry on the process to 
the greatest extent in winter, and stall-fed ruminants carry it on 



1787 



for about seven months in the year; beasts that go in herds, as 
they get their food out of doors, ruminate to a lesser degree and 
over a lesser period. Some, also, of the animals that have teeth 
in both jaws ruminate; as, for instance, the Pontic mice, and the 
fish which from the habit is by some called 'the Ruminant', (as 
well as other fish). 

Long-limbed animals have loose faeces, and broad-chested 
animals vomit with comparative facility, and these remarks are, 
in a general way, applicable to quadrupeds, birds, and men. 



49B 

A considerable number of birds change according to season the 
colour of their plumage and their note; as, for instance, the 
owsel becomes yellow instead of black, and its note gets altered, 
for in summer it has a musical note and in winter a discordant 
chatter. The thrush also changes its colour; about the throat it is 
marked in winter with speckles like a starling, in summer 
distinctly spotted: however, it never alters its note. The 
nightingale, when the hills are taking on verdure, sings 
continually for fifteen days and fifteen nights; afterwards it 
sings, but not continuously. As summer advances it has a 
different song, not so varied as before, nor so deep, nor so 
intricately modulated, but simple; it also changes its colour, and 
in Italy about this season it goes by a different name. It goes 
into hiding, and is consequently visible only for a brief period. 
The erithacus (or redbreast) and the so-called redstart change 
into one another; the former is a winter bird, the latter a 
summer one, and the difference between them is practically 
limited to the coloration of their plumage. In the same way with 
the beccafico and the blackcap; these change into one another. 



1788 



The beccafico appears about autumn, and the blackcap as soon 
as autumn has ended. These birds, also, differ from one another 
only in colour and note; that these birds, two in name, are one 
in reality is proved by the fact that at the period when the 
change is in progress each one has been seen with the change 
as yet incomplete. It is not so very strange that in these cases 
there is a change in note and in plumage, for even the ring-dove 
ceases to coo in winter, and recommences cooing when spring 
comes in; in winter, however, when fine weather has succeeded 
to very stormy weather, this bird has been known to give its 
cooing note, to the astonishment of such as were acquainted 
with its usual winter silence. As a general rule, birds sing most 
loudly and most diversely in the pairing season. The cuckoo 
changes its colour, and its note is not clearly heard for a short 
time previous to its departure. It departs about the rising of the 
Dog-star, and it reappears from springtime to the rising of the 
Dog-star. At the rise of this star the bird called by some 
oenanthe disappears, and reappears when it is setting: thus 
keeping clear at one time of extreme cold, and at another time 
of extreme heat. The hoopoe also changes its colour and 
appearance, as Aeschylus has represented in the following lines: 

The Hoopoe, witness to his own distress, 

Is clad by Zeus in variable dress: 

Now a gay mountain-bird, with knightly crest, 

Now in the white hawk's silver plumage drest, 

For, timely changing, on the hawk's white wing 

He greets the apparition of the Spring. 

Thus twofold form and colour are conferred, 

In youth and age, upon the selfsame bird. 



1789 



The spangled raiment marks his youthful days, 

The argent his maturity displays; 

And when the fields are yellow with ripe corn 

Again his particoloured plumes are worn. 

But evermore, in sullen discontent, 

He seeks the lonely hills, in self-sought banishment. 

Of birds, some take a dust-bath by rolling in dust, some take a 
water-bath, and some take neither the one bath nor the other. 
Birds that do not fly but keep on the ground take the dust-bath, 
as for instance the hen, the partridge, the francolin, the crested 
lark, the pheasant; some of the straight-taloned birds, and such 
as live on the banks of a river, in marshes, or by the sea, take a 
water-bath; some birds take both the dust-bath and the 
waterbath, as for instance the pigeon and the sparrow; of the 
crooked-taloned birds the greater part take neither the one bath 
nor the other. So much for the ways of the above-mentioned, 
but some birds have a peculiar habit of making a noise at their 
hinder quarters, as, for instance, the turtle-dove; and they make 
a violent movement of their tails at the same time that they 
produce this peculiar sound. 



1790 



Aristotle - On the Parts of Animals 
[Translated by William Ogle] 



Book I 



Every systematic science, the humblest and the noblest alike, 
seems to admit of two distinct kinds of proficiency; one of 
which may be properly called scientific knowledge of the 
subject, while the other is a kind of educational acquaintance 
with it. For an educated man should be able to form a fair off- 
hand judgement as to the goodness or badness of the method 
used by a professor in his exposition. To be educated is in fact to 
be able to do this; and even the man of universal education we 
deem to be such in virtue of his having this ability. It will, 
however, of course, be understood that we only ascribe 
universal education to one who in his own individual person is 
thus critical in all or nearly all branches of knowledge, and not 
to one who has a like ability merely in some special subject. For 
it is possible for a man to have this competence in some one 
branch of knowledge without having it in all. 

It is plain then that, as in other sciences, so in that which 
inquires into nature, there must be certain canons, by reference 
to which a hearer shall be able to criticize the method of a 
professed exposition, quite independently of the question 
whether the statements made be true or false. Ought we, for 
instance (to give an illustration of what I mean), to begin by 
discussing each separate species - man, lion, ox, and the like - 



1791 



taking each kind in hand independently of the rest, or ought we 
rather to deal first with the attributes which they have in 
common in virtue of some common element of their nature, 
and proceed from this as a basis for the consideration of them 
separately? For genera that are quite distinct yet oftentimes 
present many identical phenomena, sleep, for instance, 
respiration, growth, decay, death, and other similar affections 
and conditions, which may be passed over for the present, as 
we are not yet prepared to treat of them with clearness and 
precision. Now it is plain that if we deal with each species 
independently of the rest, we shall frequently be obliged to 
repeat the same statements over and over again; for horse and 
dog and man present, each and all, every one of the phenomena 
just enumerated. A discussion therefore of the attributes of each 
such species separately would necessarily involve frequent 
repetitions as to characters, themselves identical but recurring 
in animals specifically distinct. (Very possibly also there may be 
other characters which, though they present specific 
differences, yet come under one and the same category. For 
instance, flying, swimming, walking, creeping, are plainly 
specifically distinct, but yet are all forms of animal progression.) 
We must, then, have some clear understanding as to the 
manner in which our investigation is to be conducted; whether, 
I mean, we are first to deal with the common or generic 
characters, and afterwards to take into consideration special 
peculiarities; or whether we are to start straight off with the 
ultimate species. For as yet no definite rule has been laid down 
in this matter. So also there is a like uncertainty as to another 
point now to be mentioned. Ought the writer who deals with 
the works of nature to follow the plan adopted by the 
mathematicians in their astronomical demonstrations, and 
after considering the phenomena presented by animals, and 
their several parts, proceed subsequently to treat of the causes 
and the reason why; or ought he to follow some other method? 



1792 



And when these questions are answered, there yet remains 
another. The causes concerned in the generation of the works of 
nature are, as we see, more than one. There is the final cause 
and there is the motor cause. Now we must decide which of 
these two causes comes first, which second. Plainly, however, 
that cause is the first which we call the final one. For this is the 
Reason, and the Reason forms the starting-point, alike in the 
works of art and in works of nature. For consider how the 
physician or how the builder sets about his work. He starts by 
forming for himself a definite picture, in the one case 
perceptible to mind, in the other to sense, of his end - the 
physician of health, the builder of a house - and this he holds 
forward as the reason and explanation of each subsequent step 
that he takes, and of his acting in this or that way as the case 
may be. Now in the works of nature the good end and the final 
cause is still more dominant than in works of art such as these, 
nor is necessity a factor with the same significance in them all; 
though almost all writers, while they try to refer their origin to 
this cause, do so without distinguishing the various senses in 
which the term necessity is used. For there is absolute necessity, 
manifested in eternal phenomena; and there is hypothetical 
necessity, manifested in everything that is generated by nature 
as in everything that is produced by art, be it a house or what it 
may. For if a house or other such final object is to be realized, it 
is necessary that such and such material shall exist; and it is 
necessary that first this then that shall be produced, and first 
this and then that set in motion, and so on in continuous 
succession, until the end and final result is reached, for the sake 
of which each prior thing is produced and exists. As with these 
productions of art, so also is it with the productions of nature. 
The mode of necessity, however, and the mode of ratiocination 
are different in natural science from what they are in the 
theoretical sciences; of which we have spoken elsewhere. For in 
the latter the starting-point is that which is; in the former that 



1793 



which is to be. For it is that which is yet to be - health, let us say, 
or a man - that, owing to its being of such and such characters, 
necessitates the pre-existence or previous production of this 
and that antecedent; and not this or that antecedent which, 
because it exists or has been generated, makes it necessary that 
health or a man is in, or shall come into, existence. Nor is it 
possible to track back the series of necessary antecedents to a 
starting-point, of which you can say that, existing itself from 
eternity, it has determined their existence as its consequent. 
These however again, are matters that have been dealt with in 
another treatise. There too it was stated in what cases absolute 
and hypothetical necessity exist; in what cases also the 
proposition expressing hypothetical necessity is simply 
convertible, and what cause it is that determines this 
convertibility. 

Another matter which must not be passed over without 
consideration is, whether the proper subject of our exposition is 
that with which the ancient writers concerned themselves, 
namely, what is the process of formation of each animal; or 
whether it is not rather, what are the characters of a given 
creature when formed. For there is no small difference between 
these two views. The best course appears to be that we should 
follow the method already mentioned, and begin with the 
phenomena presented by each group of animals, and, when this 
is done, proceed afterwards to state the causes of those 
phenomena, and to deal with their evolution. For elsewhere, as 
for instance in house building, this is the true sequence. The 
plan of the house, or the house, has this and that form; and 
because it has this and that form, therefore is its construction 
carried out in this or that manner. For the process of evolution 
is for the sake of the thing Anally evolved, and not this for the 
sake of the process. Empedocles, then, was in error when he 
said that many of the characters presented by animals were 
merely the results of incidental occurrences during their 



1794 



development; for instance, that the backbone was divided as it 
is into vertebrae, because it happened to be broken owing to the 
contorted position of the foetus in the womb. In so saying he 
overlooked the fact that propagation implies a creative seed 
endowed with certain formative properties. Secondly, he 
neglected another fact, namely, that the parent animal pre- 
exists, not only in idea, but actually in time. For man is 
generated from man; and thus it is the possession of certain 
characters by the parent that determines the development of 
like characters in the child. The same statement holds good also 
for the operations of art, and even for those which are 
apparently spontaneous. For the same result as is produced by 
art may occur spontaneously. Spontaneity, for instance, may 
bring about the restoration of health. The products of art, 
however, require the pre-existence of an efficient cause 
homogeneous with themselves, such as the statuary's art, 
which must necessarily precede the statue; for this cannot 
possibly be produced spontaneously. Art indeed consists in the 
conception of the result to be produced before its realization in 
the material. As with spontaneity, so with chance; for this also 
produces the same result as art, and by the same process. 

The fittest mode, then, of treatment is to say, a man has such 
and such parts, because the conception of a man includes their 
presence, and because they are necessary conditions of his 
existence, or, if we cannot quite say this, which would be best of 
all, then the next thing to it, namely, that it is either quite 
impossible for him to exist without them, or, at any rate, that it 
is better for him that they should be there; and their existence 
involves the existence of other antecedents. Thus we should 
say, because man is an animal with such and such characters, 
therefore is the process of his development necessarily such as 
it is; and therefore is it accomplished in such and such an order, 
this part being formed first, that next, and so on in succession; 



1795 



and after a like fashion should we explain the evolution of all 
other works of nature. 

Now that with which the ancient writers, who first 
philosophized about Nature, busied themselves, was the 
material principle and the material cause. They inquired what 
this is, and what its character; how the universe is generated 
out of it, and by what motor influence, whether, for instance, by 
antagonism or friendship, whether by intelligence or 
spontaneous action, the substratum of matter being assumed to 
have certain inseparable properties; fire, for instance, to have a 
hot nature, earth a cold one; the former to be light, the latter 
heavy. For even the genesis of the universe is thus explained by 
them. After a like fashion do they deal also with the 
development of plants and of animals. They say, for instance, 
that the water contained in the body causes by its currents the 
formation of the stomach and the other receptacles of food or of 
excretion; and that the breath by its passage breaks open the 
outlets of the nostrils; air and water being the materials of 
which bodies are made; for all represent nature as composed of 
such or similar substances. 

But if men and animals and their several parts are natural 
phenomena, then the natural philosopher must take into 
consideration not merely the ultimate substances of which they 
are made, but also flesh, bone, blood, and all other 
homogeneous parts; not only these, but also the heterogeneous 
parts, such as face, hand, foot; and must examine how each of 
these comes to be what it is, and in virtue of what force. For to 
say what are the ultimate substances out of which an animal is 
formed, to state, for instance, that it is made of fire or earth, is 
no more sufficient than would be a similar account in the case 
of a couch or the like. For we should not be content with saying 
that the couch was made of bronze or wood or whatever it 
might be, but should try to describe its design or mode of 



1796 



composition in preference to the material; or, if we did deal 
with the material, it would at any rate be with the concretion of 
material and form. For a couch is such and such a form 
embodied in this or that matter, or such and such a matter with 
this or that form; so that its shape and structure must be 
included in our description. For the formal nature is of greater 
importance than the material nature. 

Does, then, configuration and colour constitute the essence of 
the various animals and of their several parts? For if so, what 
Democritus says will be strictly correct. For such appears to 
have been his notion. At any rate he says that it is evident to 
every one what form it is that makes the man, seeing that he is 
recognizable by his shape and colour. And yet a dead body has 
exactly the same configuration as a living one; but for all that is 
not a man. So also no hand of bronze or wood or constituted in 
any but the appropriate way can possibly be a hand in more 
than name. For like a physician in a painting, or like a flute in a 
sculpture, in spite of its name it will be unable to do the office 
which that name implies. Precisely in the same way no part of a 
dead body, such I mean as its eye or its hand, is really an eye or 
a hand. To say, then, that shape and colour constitute the 
animal is an inadequate statement, and is much the same as if 
a woodcarver were to insist that the hand he had cut out was 
really a hand. Yet the physiologists, when they give an account 
of the development and causes of the animal form, speak very 
much like such a craftsman. What, however, I would ask, are the 
forces by which the hand or the body was fashioned into its 
shape? The woodcarver will perhaps say, by the axe or the 
auger; the physiologist, by air and by earth. Of these two 
answers the artificer's is the better, but it is nevertheless 
insufficient. For it is not enough for him to say that by the 
stroke of his tool this part was formed into a concavity, that into 
a flat surface; but he must state the reasons why he struck his 
blow in such a way as to effect this, and what his final object 



1797 



was; namely, that the piece of wood should develop eventually 
into this or that shape. It is plain, then, that the teaching of the 
old physiologists is inadequate, and that the true method is to 
state what the definitive characters are that distinguish the 
animal as a whole; to explain what it is both in substance and 
in form, and to deal after the same fashion with its several 
organs; in fact, to proceed in exactly the same way as we should 
do, were we giving a complete description of a couch. 

If now this something that constitutes the form of the living 
being be the soul, or part of the soul, or something that without 
the soul cannot exist; as would seem to be the case, seeing at 
any rate that when the soul departs, what is left is no longer a 
living animal, and that none of the parts remain what they were 
before, excepting in mere configuration, like the animals that in 
the fable are turned into stone; if, I say, this be so, then it will 
come within the province of the natural philosopher to inform 
himself concerning the soul, and to treat of it, either in its 
entirety, or, at any rate, of that part of it which constitutes the 
essential character of an animal; and it will be his duty to say 
what this soul or this part of a soul is; and to discuss the 
attributes that attach to this essential character, especially as 
nature is spoken of in two senses, and the nature of a thing is 
either its matter or its essence; nature as essence including 
both the motor cause and the final cause. Now it is in the latter 
of these two senses that either the whole soul or some part of it 
constitutes the nature of an animal; and inasmuch as it is the 
presence of the soul that enables matter to constitute the 
animal nature, much more than it is the presence of matter 
which so enables the soul, the inquirer into nature is bound on 
every ground to treat of the soul rather than of the matter. For 
though the wood of which they are made constitutes the couch 
and the tripod, it only does so because it is capable of receiving 
such and such a form. 



1798 



What has been said suggests the question, whether it is the 
whole soul or only some part of it, the consideration of which 
comes within the province of natural science. Now if it be of the 
whole soul that this should treat, then there is no place for any 
other philosophy beside it. For as it belongs in all cases to one 
and the same science to deal with correlated subjects - one and 
the same science, for instance, deals with sensation and with 
the objects of sense - and as therefore the intelligent soul and 
the objects of intellect, being correlated, must belong to one and 
the same science, it follows that natural science will have to 
include the whole universe in its province. But perhaps it is not 
the whole soul, nor all its parts collectively, that constitutes the 
source of motion; but there may be one part, identical with that 
in plants, which is the source of growth, another, namely the 
sensory part, which is the source of change of quality, while still 
another, and this not the intellectual part, is the source of 
locomotion. I say not the intellectual part; for other animals 
than man have the power of locomotion, but in none but him is 
there intellect. Thus then it is plain that it is not of the whole 
soul that we have to treat. For it is not the whole soul that 
constitutes the animal nature, but only some part or parts of it. 
Moreover, it is impossible that any abstraction can form a 
subject of natural science, seeing that everything that Nature 
makes is means to an end. For just as human creations are the 
products of art, so living objects are manifest in the products of 
an analogous cause or principle, not external but internal, 
derived like the hot and the cold from the environing universe. 
And that the heaven, if it had an origin, was evolved and is 
maintained by such a cause, there is therefore even more 
reason to believe, than that mortal animals so originated. For 
order and definiteness are much more plainly manifest in the 
celestial bodies than in our own frame; while change and 
chance are characteristic of the perishable things of earth. Yet 
there are some who, while they allow that every animal exists 



1799 



and was generated by nature, nevertheless hold that the heaven 
was constructed to be what it is by chance and spontaneity; the 
heaven, in which not the faintest sign of haphazard or of 
disorder is discernible! Again, whenever there is plainly some 
final end, to which a motion tends should nothing stand in the 
way, we always say that such final end is the aim or purpose of 
the motion; and from this it is evident that there must be a 
something or other really existing, corresponding to what we 
call by the name of Nature. For a given germ does not give rise 
to any chance living being, nor spring from any chance one; but 
each germ springs from a definite parent and gives rise to a 
definite progeny. And thus it is the germ that is the ruling 
influence and fabricator of the offspring. For these it is by 
nature, the offspring being at any rate that which in nature will 
spring from it. At the same time the offspring is anterior to the 
germ; for germ and perfected progeny are related as the 
developmental process and the result. Anterior, however, to 
both germ and product is the organism from which the germ 
was derived. For every germ implies two organisms, the parent 
and the progeny. For germ or seed is both the seed of the 
organism from which it came, of the horse, for instance, from 
which it was derived, and the seed of the organism that will 
eventually arise from it, of the mule, for example, which is 
developed from the seed of the horse. The same seed then is the 
seed both of the horse and of the mule, though in different ways 
as here set forth. Moreover, the seed is potentially that which 
will spring from it, and the relation of potentiality to actuality 
we know. 

There are then two causes, namely, necessity and the final end. 
For many things are produced, simply as the results of 
necessity. It may, however, be asked, of what mode of necessity 
are we speaking when we say this. For it can be of neither of 
those two modes which are set forth in the philosophical 
treatises. There is, however, the third mode, in such things at 



1800 



any rate as are generated. For instance, we say that food is 
necessary; because an animal cannot possibly do without it. 
This third mode is what may be called hypothetical necessity. 
Here is another example of it. If a piece of wood is to be split 
with an axe, the axe must of necessity be hard; and, if hard, 
must of necessity be made of bronze or iron. Now exactly in the 
same way the body, which like the axe is an instrument - for 
both the body as a whole and its several parts individually have 
definite operations for which they are made - just in the same 
way, I say, the body, if it is to do its work, must of necessity be of 
such and such a character, and made of such and such 
materials. 

It is plain then that there are two modes of causation, and that 
both of these must, so far as possible, be taken into account in 
explaining the works of nature, or that at any rate an attempt 
must be made to include them both; and that those who fail in 
this tell us in reality nothing about nature. For primary cause 
constitutes the nature of an animal much more than does its 
matter. There are indeed passages in which even Empedocles 
hits upon this, and following the guidance of fact, finds himself 
constrained to speak of the ratio (olugos) as constituting the 
essence and real nature of things. Such, for instance, is the case 
when he explains what is a bone. For he does not merely 
describe its material, and say it is this one element, or those two 
or three elements, or a compound of all the elements, but states 
the ratio (olugos) of their combination. As with a bone, so 
manifestly is it with the flesh and all other similar parts. 

The reason why our predecessors failed in hitting upon this 
method of treatment was, that they were not in possession of 
the notion of essence, nor of any definition of substance. The 
first who came near it was Democritus, and he was far from 
adopting it as a necessary method in natural science, but was 
merely brought to it, spite of himself, by constraint of facts. In 



1801 



the time of Socrates a nearer approach was made to the 
method. But at this period men gave up inquiring into the works 
of nature, and philosophers diverted their attention to political 
science and to the virtues which benefit mankind. 

Of the method itself the following is an example. In dealing 
with respiration we must show that it takes place for such or 
such a final object; and we must also show that this and that 
part of the process is necessitated by this and that other stage 
of it. By necessity we shall sometimes mean hypothetical 
necessity, the necessity, that is, that the requisite antecedants 
shall be there, if the final end is to be reached; and sometimes 
absolute necessity, such necessity as that which connects 
substances and their inherent properties and characters. For the 
alternate discharge and re-entrance of heat and the inflow of air 
are necessary if we are to live. Here we have at once a necessity 
in the former of the two senses. But the alternation of heat and 
refrigeration produces of necessity an alternate admission and 
discharge of the outer air, and this is a necessity of the second 
kind. 

In the foregoing we have an example of the method which we 
must adopt, and also an example of the kind of phenomena, the 
causes of which we have to investigate. 



Some writers propose to reach the definitions of the ultimate 
forms of animal life by bipartite division. But this method is 
often difficult, and often impracticable. 

Sometimes the final differentia of the subdivision is sufficient 
by itself, and the antecedent differentiae are mere surplusage. 



1802 



Thus in the series Footed, Two-footed, Cleft-footed, the last term 
is all-expressive by itself, and to append the higher terms is 
only an idle iteration. Again it is not permissible to break up a 
natural group, Birds for instance, by putting its members under 
different bifurcations, as is done in the published dichotomies, 
where some birds are ranked with animals of the water, and 
others placed in a different class. The group Birds and the group 
Fishes happen to be named, while other natural groups have no 
popular names; for instance, the groups that we may call 
Sanguineous and Bloodless are not known popularly by any 
designations. If such natural groups are not to be broken up, the 
method of Dichotomy cannot be employed, for it necessarily 
involves such breaking up and dislocation. The group of the 
Many-footed, for instance, would, under this method, have to be 
dismembered, and some of its kinds distributed among land 
animals, others among water animals. 



Again, privative terms inevitably form one branch of 
dichotomous division, as we see in the proposed dichotomies. 
But privative terms in their character of privatives admit of no 
subdivision. For there can be no specific forms of a negation, of 
Featherless for instance or of Footless, as there are of Feathered 
and of Footed. Yet a generic differentia must be subdivisible; for 
otherwise what is there that makes it generic rather than 
specific? There are to be found generic, that is specifically 
subdivisible, differentiae; Feathered for instance and Footed. For 
feathers are divisible into Barbed and Unbarbed, and feet into 
Manycleft, and Twocleft, like those of animals with bifid hoofs, 
and Uncleft or Undivided, like those of animals with solid hoofs. 
Now even with differentiae capable of this specific subdivision 



1803 



it is difficult enough so to make the classification, as that each 
animal shall be comprehended in some one subdivision and in 
not more than one; but far more difficult, nay impossible, is it to 
do this, if we start with a dichotomy into two contradictories. 
(Suppose for instance we start with the two contradictories, 
Feathered and Unfeathered; we shall find that the ant, the glow- 
worm, and some other animals fall under both divisions.) For 
each differentia must be presented by some species. There must 
be some species, therefore, under the privative heading. Now 
specifically distinct animals cannot present in their essence a 
common undifferentiated element, but any apparently common 
element must really be differentiated. (Bird and Man for 
instance are both Two-footed, but their two-footedness is 
diverse and differentiated. So any two sanguineous groups must 
have some difference in their blood, if their blood is part of their 
essence.) From this it follows that a privative term, being 
insusceptible of differentiation, cannot be a generic differentia; 
for, if it were, there would be a common undifferentiated 
element in two different groups. 

Again, if the species are ultimate indivisible groups, that is, are 
groups with indivisible differentiae, and if no differentia be 
common to several groups, the number of differentiae must be 
equal to the number of species. If a differentia though not 
divisible could yet be common to several groups, then it is plain 
that in virtue of that common differentia specifically distinct 
animals would fall into the same division. It is necessary then, if 
the differentiae, under which are ranged all the ultimate and 
indivisible groups, are specific characters, that none of them 
shall be common; for otherwise, as already said, specifically 
distinct animals will come into one and the same division. But 
this would violate one of the requisite conditions, which are as 
follows. No ultimate group must be included in more than a 
single division; different groups must not be included in the 
same division; and every group must be found in some division. 



1804 



It is plain then that we cannot get at the ultimate specific forms 
of the animal, or any other, kingdom by bifurcate division. If we 
could, the number of ultimate differentiae would equal the 
number of ultimate animal forms. For assume an order of 
beings whose prime differentiae are White and Black. Each of 
these branches will bifurcate, and their branches again, and so 
on till we reach the ultimate differentiae, whose number will be 
four or some other power of two, and will also be the number of 
the ultimate species comprehended in the order. 

(A species is constituted by the combination differentia and 
matter. For no part of an animal is purely material or purely 
immaterial; nor can a body, independently of its condition, 
constitute an animal or any of its parts, as has repeatedly been 
observed.) 

Further, the differentiae must be elements of the essence, and 
not merely essential attributes. Thus if Figure is the term to be 
divided, it must not be divided into figures whose angles are 
equal to two right angles, and figures whose angles are together 
greater than two right angles. For it is only an attribute of a 
triangle and not part of its essence that its angles are equal to 
two right angles. 

Again, the bifurcations must be opposites, like White and Black, 
Straight and Bent; and if we characterize one branch by either 
term, we must characterize the other by its opposite, and not, 
for example, characterize one branch by a colour, the other by a 
mode of progression, swimming for instance. 

Furthermore, living beings cannot be divided by the functions 
common to body and soul, by Flying, for instance, and Walking, 
as we see them divided in the dichotomies already referred to. 
For some groups, Ants for instance, fall under both divisions, 
some ants flying while others do not. Similarly as regards the 
division into Wild and Tame; for it also would involve the 



1805 



disruption of a species into different groups. For in almost all 
species in which some members are tame, there are other 
members that are wild. Such, for example, is the case with Men, 
Horses, Oxen, Dogs in India, Pigs, Goats, Sheep; groups which, if 
double, ought to have what they have not, namely, different 
appellations; and which, if single, prove that Wildness and 
Tameness do not amount to specific differences. And whatever 
single element we take as a basis of division the same difficulty 
will occur. 

The method then that we must adopt is to attempt to recognize 
the natural groups, following the indications afforded by the 
instincts of mankind, which led them for instance to form the 
class of Birds and the class of Fishes, each of which groups 
combines a multitude of differentiae, and is not defined by a 
single one as in dichotomy. The method of dichotomy is either 
impossible (for it would put a single group under different 
divisions or contrary groups under the same division), or it only 
furnishes a single ultimate differentia for each species, which 
either alone or with its series of antecedents has to constitute 
the ultimate species. 

If, again, a new differential character be introduced at any stage 
into the division, the necessary result is that the continuity of 
the division becomes merely a unity and continuity of 
agglomeration, like the unity and continuity of a series of 
sentences coupled together by conjunctive particles. For 
instance, suppose we have the bifurcation Feathered and 
Featherless, and then divide Feathered into Wild and Tame, or 
into White and Black. Tame and White are not a differentiation 
of Feathered, but are the commencement of an independent 
bifurcation, and are foreign to the series at the end of which 
they are introduced. 



1806 



As we said then, we must define at the outset by multiplicity of 
differentiae. If we do so, privative terms will be available, which 
are unavailable to the dichotomist. 

The impossibility of reaching the definition of any of the 
ultimate forms by dichotomy of the larger group, as some 
propose, is manifest also from the following considerations. It is 
impossible that a single differentia, either by itself or with its 
antecedents, shall express the whole essence of a species. (In 
saying a single differentia by itself I mean such an isolated 
differentia as Cleft-footed; in saying a single differentia with 
antecedent I mean, to give an instance, Manycleft-footed 
preceded by Cleft-footed. The very continuity of a series of 
successive differentiae in a division is intended to show that it 
is their combination that expresses the character of the 
resulting unit, or ultimate group. But one is misled by the 
usages of language into imagining that it is merely the final 
term of the series, Manycleft-footed for instance, that 
constitutes the whole differentia, and that the antecedent 
terms, Footed, Cleft-footed, are superfluous. Now it is evident 
that such a series cannot consist of many terms. For if one 
divides and subdivides, one soon reaches the final differential 
term, but for all that will not have got to the ultimate division, 
that is, to the species.) No single differentia, I repeat, either by 
itself or with its antecedents, can possibly express the essence 
of a species. Suppose, for example, Man to be the animal to be 
defined; the single differentia will be Cleft-footed, either by 
itself or with its antecedents, Footed and Two-footed. Now if 
man was nothing more than a Cleft-footed animal, this single 
differentia would duly represent his essence. But seeing that 
this is not the case, more differentiae than this one will 
necessarily be required to define him; and these cannot come 
under one division; for each single branch of a dichotomy ends 
in a single differentia, and cannot possibly include several 
differentiae belonging to one and the same animal. 



1807 



It is impossible then to reach any of the ultimate animal forms 
by dichotomous division. 



It deserves inquiry why a single name denoting a higher group 
was not invented by mankind, as an appellation to comprehend 
the two groups of Water animals and Winged animals. For even 
these have certain attributes in common. However, the present 
nomenclature is just. Groups that only differ in degree, and in 
the more or less of an identical element that they possess, are 
aggregated under a single class; groups whose attributes are not 
identical but analogous are separated. For instance, bird differs 
from bird by gradation, or by excess and defect; some birds have 
long feathers, others short ones, but all are feathered. Bird and 
Fish are more remote and only agree in having analogous 
organs; for what in the bird is feather, in the fish is scale. Such 
analogies can scarcely, however, serve universally as indications 
for the formation of groups, for almost all animals present 
analogies in their corresponding parts. 

The individuals comprised within a species, such as Socrates 
and Coriscus, are the real existences; but inasmuch as these 
individuals possess one common specific form, it will suffice to 
state the universal attributes of the species, that is, the 
attributes common to all its individuals, once for all, as 
otherwise there will be endless reiteration, as has already been 
pointed out. 

But as regards the larger groups - such as Birds - which 
comprehend many species, there may be a question. For on the 
one hand it may be urged that as the ultimate species represent 
the real existences, it will be well, if practicable, to examine 



1808 



these ultimate species separately, just as we examine the 
species Man separately; to examine, that is, not the whole class 
Birds collectively, but the Ostrich, the Crane, and the other 
indivisible groups or species belonging to the class. 

On the other hand, however, this course would involve repeated 
mention of the same attribute, as the same attribute is common 
to many species, and so far would be somewhat irrational and 
tedious. Perhaps, then, it will be best to treat generically the 
universal attributes of the groups that have a common nature 
and contain closely allied subordinate forms, whether they are 
groups recognized by a true instinct of mankind, such as Birds 
and Fishes, or groups not popularly known by a common 
appellation, but withal composed of closely allied subordinate 
groups; and only to deal individually with the attributes of a 
single species, when such species, man, for instance, and any 
other such, if such there be - stands apart from others, and does 
not constitute with them a larger natural group. 

It is generally similarity in the shape of particular organs, or of 
the whole body, that has determined the formation of the larger 
groups. It is in virtue of such a similarity that Birds, Fishes, 
Cephalopoda, and Testacea have been made to form each a 
separate class. For within the limits of each such class, the parts 
do not differ in that they have no nearer resemblance than that 
of analogy - such as exists between the bone of man and the 
spine of fish - but differ merely in respect of such corporeal 
conditions as largeness smallness, softness hardness, 
smoothness roughness, and other similar oppositions, or, in one 
word, in respect of degree. 

We have now touched upon the canons for criticizing the 
method of natural science, and have considered what is the 
most systematic and easy course of investigation; we have also 
dealt with division, and the mode of conducting it so as best to 



1809 



attain the ends of science, and have shown why dichotomy is 
either impracticable or inefficacious for its professed purposes. 

Having laid this foundation, let us pass on to our next topic. 



Of things constituted by nature some are ungenerated, 
imperishable, and eternal, while others are subject to 
generation and decay. The former are excellent beyond compare 
and divine, but less accessible to knowledge. The evidence that 
might throw light on them, and on the problems which we long 
to solve respecting them, is furnished but scantily by sensation; 
whereas respecting perishable plants and animals we have 
abundant information, living as we do in their midst, and ample 
data may be collected concerning all their various kinds, if only 
we are willing to take sufficient pains. Both departments, 
however, have their special charm. The scanty conceptions to 
which we can attain of celestial things give us, from their 
excellence, more pleasure than all our knowledge of the world 
in which we live; just as a half glimpse of persons that we love 
is more delightful than a leisurely view of other things, 
whatever their number and dimensions. On the other hand, in 
certitude and in completeness our knowledge of terrestrial 
things has the advantage. Moreover, their greater nearness and 
affinity to us balances somewhat the loftier interest of the 
heavenly things that are the objects of the higher philosophy. 
Having already treated of the celestial world, as far as our 
conjectures could reach, we proceed to treat of animals, without 
omitting, to the best of our ability, any member of the kingdom, 
however ignoble. For if some have no graces to charm the sense, 
yet even these, by disclosing to intellectual perception the 



1810 



artistic spirit that designed them, give immense pleasure to all 
who can trace links of causation, and are inclined to philosophy. 
Indeed, it would be strange if mimic representations of them 
were attractive, because they disclose the mimetic skill of the 
painter or sculptor, and the original realities themselves were 
not more interesting, to all at any rate who have eyes to discern 
the reasons that determined their formation. We therefore must 
not recoil with childish aversion from the examination of the 
humbler animals. Every realm of nature is marvellous: and as 
Heraclitus, when the strangers who came to visit him found 
him warming himself at the furnace in the kitchen and 
hesitated to go in, reported to have bidden them not to be afraid 
to enter, as even in that kitchen divinities were present, so we 
should venture on the study of every kind of animal without 
distaste; for each and all will reveal to us something natural and 
something beautiful. Absence of haphazard and conduciveness 
of everything to an end are to be found in Nature's works in the 
highest degree, and the resultant end of her generations and 
combinations is a form of the beautiful. 

If any person thinks the examination of the rest of the animal 
kingdom an unworthy task, he must hold in like disesteem the 
study of man. For no one can look at the primordia of the 
human frame - blood, flesh, bones, vessels, and the like - 
without much repugnance. Moreover, when any one of the parts 
or structures, be it which it may, is under discussion, it must not 
be supposed that it is its material composition to which 
attention is being directed or which is the object of the 
discussion, but the relation of such part to the total form. 
Similarly, the true object of architecture is not bricks, mortar, or 
timber, but the house; and so the principal object of natural 
philosophy is not the material elements, but their composition, 
and the totality of the form, independently of which they have 
no existence. 



1811 



The course of exposition must be first to state the attributes 
common to whole groups of animals, and then to attempt to 
give their explanation. Many groups, as already noticed, present 
common attributes, that is to say, in some cases absolutely 
identical affections, and absolutely identical organs, - feet, 
feathers, scales, and the like - while in other groups the 
affections and organs are only so far identical as that they are 
analogous. For instance, some groups have lungs, others have 
no lung, but an organ analogous to a lung in its place; some 
have blood, others have no blood, but a fluid analogous to blood, 
and with the same office. To treat of the common attributes in 
connexion with each individual group would involve, as already 
suggested, useless iteration. For many groups have common 
attributes. So much for this topic. 

As every instrument and every bodily member subserves some 
partial end, that is to say, some special action, so the whole 
body must be destined to minister to some Plenary sphere of 
action. Thus the saw is made for sawing, for sawing is a 
function, and not sawing for the saw. Similarly, the body too 
must somehow or other be made for the soul, and each part of 
it for some subordinate function, to which it is adapted. 

We have, then, first to describe the common functions, 
common, that is, to the whole animal kingdom, or to certain 
large groups, or to the members of a species. In other words, we 
have to describe the attributes common to all animals, or to 
assemblages, like the class of Birds, of closely allied groups 
differentiated by gradation, or to groups like Man not 
differentiated into subordinate groups. In the first case the 
common attributes may be called analogous, in the second 
generic, in the third specific. 

When a function is ancillary to another, a like relation 
manifestly obtains between the organs which discharge these 



1812 



functions; and similarly, if one function is prior to and the end 
of another, their respective organs will stand to each other in 
the same relation. Thirdly, the existence of these parts involves 
that of other things as their necessary consequents. 

Instances of what I mean by functions and affections are 
Reproduction, Growth, Copulation, Waking, Sleep, Locomotion, 
and other similar vital actions. Instances of what I mean by 
parts are Nose, Eye, Face, and other so-called members or limbs, 
and also the more elementary parts of which these are made. 
So much for the method to be pursued. Let us now try to set 
forth the causes of all vital phenomena, whether universal or 
particular, and in so doing let us follow that order of exposition 
which conforms, as we have indicated, to the order of nature. 



Book II 



The nature and the number of the parts of which animals are 
severally composed are matters which have already been set 
forth in detail in the book of Researches about Animals. We 
have now to inquire what are the causes that in each case have 
determined this composition, a subject quite distinct from that 
dealt with in the Researches. 

Now there are three degrees of composition; and of these the 
first in order, as all will allow, is composition out of what some 



1813 



call the elements, such as earth, air, water, fire. Perhaps, 
however, it would be more accurate to say composition out of 
the elementary forces; nor indeed out of all of these, but out of a 
limited number of them, as defined in previous treatises. For 
fluid and solid, hot and cold, form the material of all composite 
bodies; and all other differences are secondary to these, such 
differences, that is, as heaviness or lightness, density or rarity, 
roughness or smoothness, and any other such properties of 
matter as there may be. second degree of composition is that by 
which the homogeneous parts of animals, such as bone, flesh, 
and the like, are constituted out of the primary substances. The 
third and last stage is the composition which forms the 
heterogeneous parts, such as face, hand, and the rest. 

Now the order of actual development and the order of logical 
existence are always the inverse of each other. For that which is 
posterior in the order of development is antecedent in the order 
of nature, and that is genetically last which in nature is first. 

(That this is so is manifest by induction; for a house does not 
exist for the sake of bricks and stones, but these materials for 
the sake of the house; and the same is the case with the 
materials of other bodies. Nor is induction required to show 
this, it is included in our conception of generation. For 
generation is a process from a something to a something; that 
which is generated having a cause in which it originates and a 
cause in which it ends. The originating cause is the primary 
efficient cause, which is something already endowed with 
tangible existence, while the final cause is some definite form 
or similar end; for man generates man, and plant generates 
plant, in each case out of the underlying material.) 

In order of time, then, the material and the generative process 
must necessarily be anterior to the being that is generated; but 
in logical order the definitive character and form of each being 



1814 



precedes the material. This is evident if one only tries to define 
the process of formation. For the definition of house-building 
includes and presupposes that of the house; but the definition 
of the house does not include nor presuppose that of house- 
building; and the same is true of all other productions. So that it 
must necessarily be that the elementary material exists for the 
sake of the homogeneous parts, seeing that these are 
genetically posterior to it, just as the heterogeneous parts are 
posterior genetically to them. For these heterogeneous parts 
have reached the end and goal, having the third degree of 
composition, in which degree generation or development often 
attains its final term. 

Animals, then, are composed of homogeneous parts, and are 
also composed of heterogeneous parts. The former, however, 
exist for the sake of the latter. For the active functions and 
operations of the body are carried on by these; that is, by the 
heterogeneous parts, such as the eye, the nostril, the whole face, 
the fingers, the hand, and the whole arm. But inasmuch as 
there is a great variety in the functions and motions not only of 
aggregate animals but also of the individual organs, it is 
necessary that the substances out of which these are composed 
shall present a diversity of properties. For some purposes 
softness is advantageous, for others hardness; some parts must 
be capable of extension, others of flexion. Such properties, then, 
are distributed separately to the different homogeneous parts, 
one being soft another hard, one fluid another solid, one viscous 
another brittle; whereas each of the heterogeneous parts 
presents a combination of multifarious properties. For the hand, 
to take an example, requires one property to enable it to effect 
pressure, and another and different property for simple 
prehension. For this reason the active or executive parts of the 
body are compounded out of bones, sinews, flesh, and the like, 
but not these latter out of the former. 



1815 



So far, then, as has yet been stated, the relations between these 
two orders of parts are determined by a final cause. We have, 
however, to inquire whether necessity may not also have a 
share in the matter; and it must be admitted that these mutual 
relations could not from the very beginning have possibly been 
other than they are. For heterogeneous parts can be made up 
out of homogeneous parts, either from a plurality of them, or 
from a single one, as is the case with some of the viscera which, 
varying in configuration, are yet, to speak broadly, formed from 
a single homogeneous substance; but that homogeneous 
substances should be formed out of a combination of 
heterogeneous parts is clearly an impossibility. For these 
causes, then, some parts of animals are simple and 
homogeneous, while others are composite and heterogeneous; 
and dividing the parts into the active or executive and the 
sensitive, each one of the former is, as before said, 
heterogeneous, and each one of the latter homogeneous. For it 
is in homogeneous parts alone that sensation can occur, as the 
following considerations show. 

Each sense is confined to a single order of sensibles, and its 
organ must be such as to admit the action of that kind or order. 
But it is only that which is endowed with a property in posse 
that is acted on by that which has the like property in esse, so 
that the two are the same in kind, and if the latter is single so 
also is the former. Thus it is that while no physiologists ever 
dream of saying of the hand or face or other such part that one 
is earth, another water, another fire, they couple each separate 
sense-organ with a separate element, asserting this one to be 
air and that other to be fire. 

Sensation, then, is confined to the simple or homogeneous 
parts. But, as might reasonably be expected, the organ of touch, 
though still homogeneous, is yet the least simple of all the 
sense-organs. For touch more than any other sense appears to 



1816 



be correlated to several distinct kinds of objects, and to 
recognize more than one category of contrasts, heat and cold, 
for instance, solidity and fluidity, and other similar oppositions. 
Accordingly, the organ which deals with these varied objects is 
of all the sense-organs the most corporeal, being either the 
flesh, or the substance which in some animals takes the place 
of flesh. 

Now as there cannot possibly be an animal without sensation, it 
follows as a necessary consequence that every animal must 
have some homogeneous parts; for these alone are capable of 
sensation, the heterogeneous parts serving for the active 
functions. Again, as the sensory faculty, the motor faculty, and 
the nutritive faculty are all lodged in one and the same part of 
the body, as was stated in a former treatise, it is necessary that 
the part which is the primary seat of these principles shall on 
the one hand, in its character of general sensory recipient, be 
one of the simple parts; and on the other hand shall, in its 
motor and active character, be one of the heterogeneous parts. 
For this reason it is the heart which in sanguineous animals 
constitutes this central part, and in bloodless animals it is that 
which takes the place of a heart. For the heart, like the other 
viscera, is one of the homogeneous parts; for, if cut up, its pieces 
are homogeneous in substance with each other. But it is at the 
same time heterogeneous in virtue of its definite configuration. 
And the same is true of the other so-called viscera, which are 
indeed formed from the same material as the heart. For all 
these viscera have a sanguineous character owing to their being 
situated upon vascular ducts and branches. For just as a stream 
of water deposits mud, so the various viscera, the heart 
excepted, are, as it were, deposits from the stream of blood in 
the vessels. And as to the heart, the very starting-point of the 
vessels, and the actual seat of the force by which the blood is 
first fabricated, it is but what one would naturally expect, that 
out of the selfsame nutriment of which it is the recipient its 



1817 



own proper substance shall be formed. Such, then, are the 
reasons why the viscera are of sanguineous aspect; and why in 
one point of view they are homogeneous, in another 
heterogeneous. 



Of the homogeneous parts of animals, some are soft and fluid, 
others hard and solid; and of the former some are fluid 
permanently, others only so long as they are in the living body. 
Such are blood, serum, lard, suet, marrow, semen, bile, milk 
when present, flesh, and their various analogues. For the parts 
enumerated are not to be found in all animals, some animals 
only having parts analogous to them. Of the hard and solid 
homogeneous parts bone, fish-spine, sinew, blood-vessel, are 
examples. The last of these points to a sub-division that may be 
made in the class of homogeneous parts. For in some of them 
the whole and a portion of the whole in one sense are 
designated by the same term - as, for example, is the case with 
blood-vessel and bit of blood-vessel - while in another sense 
they are not; but a portion of a heterogeneous part, such as face, 
in no sense has the same designation as the whole. 

The first question to be asked is what are the causes to which 
these homogeneous parts owe their existence? The causes are 
various; and this whether the parts be solid or fluid. Thus one 
set of homogeneous parts represent the material out of which 
the heterogeneous parts are formed; for each separate organ is 
constructed of bones, sinews, flesh, and the like; which are 
either essential elements in its formation, or contribute to the 
proper discharge of its function. A second set are the nutriment 
of the first, and are invariably fluid, for all growth occurs at the 



1818 



expense of fluid matter; while a third set are the residue of the 
second. Such, for instance, are the faeces and, in animals that 
have a bladder, the urine; the former being the dregs of the solid 
nutriment, the latter of the fluid. 

Even the individual homogeneous parts present variations, 
which are intended in each case to render them more 
serviceable for their purpose. The variations of the blood may be 
selected to illustrate this. For different bloods differ in their 
degrees of thinness or thickness, of clearness or turbidity, of 
coldness or heat; and this whether we compare the bloods from 
different parts of the same individual or the bloods of different 
animals. For, in the individual, all the differences just 
enumerated distinguish the blood of the upper and of the lower 
halves of the body; and, dealing with classes, one section of 
animals is sanguineous, while the other has no blood, but only 
something resembling it in its place. As regards the results of 
such differences, the thicker and the hotter blood is, the more 
conducive is it to strength, while in proportion to its thinness 
and its coldness is its suitability for sensation and intelligence. 
A like distinction exists also in the fluid which is analogous to 
blood. This explains how it is that bees and other similar 
creatures are of a more intelligent nature than many 
sanguineous animals; and that, of sanguineous animals, those 
are the most intelligent whose blood is thin and cold. Noblest of 
all are those whose blood is hot, and at the same time thin and 
clear. For such are suited alike for the development of courage 
and of intelligence. Accordingly, the upper parts are superior in 
these respects to the lower, the male superior to the female, and 
the right side to the left. As with the blood so also with the 
other parts, homogeneous and heterogeneous alike. For here 
also such variations as occur must be held either to be related 
to the essential constitution and mode of life of the several 
animals, or, in other cases, to be merely matters of slightly 
better or slightly worse. Two animals, for instance, may have 



1819 



eyes. But in one these eyes may be of fluid consistency, while in 
the other they are hard; and in one there may be eyelids, in the 
other no such appendages. In such a case, the fluid consistency 
and the presence of eyelids, which are intended to add to the 
accuracy of vision, are differences of degree. As to why all 
animals must of necessity have blood or something of a similar 
character, and what the nature of blood may be, these are 
matters which can only be considered when we have first 
discussed hot and cold. For the natural properties of many 
substances are referable to these two elementary principles; 
and it is a matter of frequent dispute what animals or what 
parts of animals are hot and what cold. For some maintain that 
water animals are hotter than such as live on land, asserting 
that their natural heat counterbalances the coldness of their 
medium; and again, that bloodless animals are hotter than 
those with blood, and females than males. Parmenides, for 
instance, and some others declare that women are hotter than 
men, and that it is the warmth and abundance of their blood 
which causes their menstrual flow, while Empedocles maintains 
the opposite opinion. Again, comparing the blood and the bile, 
some speak of the former as hot and of the latter as cold, while 
others invert the description. If there be this endless disputing 
about hot and cold, which of all things that affect our senses are 
the most distinct, what are we to think as to our other sensory 
impressions? 

The explanation of the difficulty appears to be that the term 
'hotter' is used in several senses; so that different statements, 
though in verbal contradiction with each other, may yet all be 
more or less true. There ought, then, to be some clear 
understanding as to the sense in which natural substances are 
to be termed hot or cold, solid or fluid. For it appears manifest 
that these are properties on which even life and death are 
largely dependent, and that they are moreover the causes of 
sleep and waking, of maturity and old age, of health and 



1820 



disease; while no similar influence belongs to roughness and 
smoothness, to heaviness and lightness, nor, in short, to any 
other such properties of matter. That this should be so is but in 
accordance with rational expectation. For hot and cold, solid 
and fluid, as was stated in a former treatise, are the foundations 
of the physical elements. 

Is then the term hot used in one sense or in many? To answer 
this we must ascertain what special effect is attributed to a 
hotter substance, and if there be several such, how many these 
may be. A body then is in one sense said to be hotter than 
another, if it impart a greater amount of heat to an object in 
contact with it. In a second sense, that is said to be hotter which 
causes the keener sensation when touched, and especially if the 
sensation be attended with pain. This criterion, however, would 
seem sometimes to be a false one; for occasionally it is the 
idiosyncrasy of the individual that causes the sensation to be 
painful. Again, of two things, that is the hotter which the more 
readily melts a fusible substance, or sets on fire an inflammable 
one. Again, of two masses of one and the same substance, the 
larger is said to have more heat than the smaller. Again, of two 
bodies, that is said to be the hotter which takes the longer time 
in cooling, as also we call that which is rapidly heated hotter 
than that which is long about it; as though the rapidity implied 
proximity and this again similarity of nature, while the want of 
rapidity implied distance and this again dissimilarity of nature. 
The term hotter is used then in all the various senses that have 
been mentioned, and perhaps in still more. Now it is impossible 
for one body to be hotter than another in all these different 
fashions. Boiling water for instance, though it is more scalding 
than flame, yet has no power of burning or melting combustible 
or fusible matter, while flame has. So again this boiling water is 
hotter than a small fire, and yet gets cold more rapidly and 
completely. For in fact fire never becomes cold; whereas water 
invariably does so. Boiling water, again, is hotter to the touch 



1821 



than oil; yet it gets cold and solid more rapidly than this other 
fluid. Blood, again, is hotter to the touch than either water or oil, 
and yet coagulates before them. Iron, again, and stones and 
other similar bodies are longer in getting heated than water, but 
when once heated burn other substances with a much greater 
intensity. Another distinction is this. In some of the bodies 
which are called hot the heat is derived from without, while in 
others it belongs to the bodies themselves; and it makes a most 
important difference whether the heat has the former or the 
latter origin. For to call that one of two bodies the hotter, which 
is possessed of heat, we may almost say, accidentally and not of 
its own essence, is very much the same thing as if, finding that 
some man in a fever was a musician, one were to say that 
musicians are hotter than healthy men. Of that which is hot per 
se and that which is hot per accidens, the former is the slower 
to cool, while not rarely the latter is the hotter to the touch. The 
former again is the more burning of the two - flame, for 
instance, as compared with boiling water - while the latter, as 
the boiling water, which is hot per accidens, is the more heating 
to the touch. From all this it is clear that it is no simple matter 
to decide which of two bodies is the hotter. For the first may be 
the hotter in one sense, the second the hotter in another. 
Indeed in some of these cases it is impossible to say simply 
even whether a thing is hot or not. For the actual substratum 
may not itself be hot, but may be hot when coupled witb heat as 
an attribute, as would be the case if one attached a single name 
to hot water or hot iron. It is after this manner that blood is hot. 
In such cases, in those, that is, in which the substratum owes its 
heat to an external influence, it is plain that cold is not a mere 
privation, but an actual existence. 

There is no knowing but that even fire may be another of these 
cases. For the substratum of fire may be smoke or charcoal, and 
though the former of these is always hot, smoke being an 
uprising vapour, yet the latter becomes cold when its flame is 



1822 



extinguished, as also would oil and pinewood under similar 
circumstances. But even substances that have been burnt nearly 
all possess some heat, cinders, for example, and ashes, the 
dejections also of animals, and, among the excretions, bile; 
because some residue of heat has been left in them after their 
combustion. It is in another sense that pinewood and fat 
substances are hot; namely, because they rapidly assume the 
actuality of fire. 

Heat appears to cause both coagulation and melting. Now such 
things as are formed merely of water are solidified by cold, 
while such as are formed of nothing but earth are solidified by 
fire. Hot substances again are solidified by cold, and, when they 
consist chiefly of earth, the process of solidification is rapid, and 
the resulting substance is insoluble; but, when their main 
constituent is water, the solid matter is again soluble. What 
kinds of substances, however, admit of being solidified, and 
what are the causes of solidification, are questions that have 
already been dealt with more precisely in another treatise. 

In conclusion, then, seeing that the terms hot and hotter are 
used in many different senses, and that no one substance can 
be hotter than others in all these senses, we must, when we 
attribute this character to an object, add such further 
statements as that this substance is hotter per se, though that 
other is often hotter per accidens; or again, that this substance 
is potentially hot, that other actually so; or again, that this 
substance is hotter in the sense of causing a greater feeling of 
heat when touched, while that other is hotter in the sense of 
producing flame and burning. The term hot being used in all 
these various senses, it plainly follows that the term cold will 
also be used with like ambiguity. 

So much then as to the signification of the terms hot and cold, 
hotter and colder. 



1823 



In natural sequence we have next to treat of solid and fluid. 
These terms are used in various senses. Sometimes, for 
instance, they denote things that are potentially, at other times 
things that are actually, solid or fluid. Ice for example, or any 
other solidified fluid, is spoken of as being actually and 
accidentally solid, while potentially and essentially it is fluid. 
Similarly earth and ashes and the like, when mixed with water, 
are actually and accidentally fluid, but potentially and 
essentially are solid. Now separate the constituents in such a 
mixture and you have on the one hand the watery components 
to which its fluidity was due, and these are both actually and 
potentially fluid, and on the other hand the earthy components, 
and these are in every way solid; and it is to bodies that are 
solid in this complete manner that the term 'solid' is most 
properly and absolutely applicable. So also the opposite term 
'fluid' is strictly and absolutely applicable to that only which is 
both potentially and actually fluid. The same remark applies 
also to hot bodies and to cold. 

These distinctions, then, being laid down, it is plain that blood 
is essentially hot in so far as that heat is connoted in its name; 
just as if boiling water were denoted by a single term, boiling 
would be connoted in that term. But the substratum of blood, 
that which it is in substance while it is blood in form, is not hot. 
Blood then in a certain sense is essentially hot, and in another 
sense is not so. For heat is included in the definition of blood, 
just as whiteness is included in the definition of a white man, 
and so far therefore blood is essentially hot. But so far as blood 
becomes hot from some external influence, it is not hot 
essentially. 



1824 



As with hot and cold, so also is it with solid and fluid. We can 
therefore understand how some substances are hot and fluid so 
long as they remain in the living body, but become perceptibly 
cold and coagulate so soon as they are separated from it; while 
others are hot and consistent while in the body, but when 
withdrawn under a change to the opposite condition, and 
become cold and fluid. Of the former blood is an example, of the 
latter bile; for while blood solidifies when thus separated, 
yellow bile under the same circumstances becomes more fluid. 
We must attribute to such substances the possession of 
opposite properties in a greater or less degree. 

In what sense, then, the blood is hot and in what sense fluid, 
and how far it partakes of the opposite properties, has now 
been fairly explained. Now since everything that grows must 
take nourishment, and nutriment in all cases consists of fluid 
and solid substances, and since it is by the force of heat that 
these are concocted and changed, it follows that all living 
things, animals and plants alike, must on this account, if on no 
other, have a natural source of heat. This natural heat, 
moreover, must belong to many parts, seeing that the organs by 
which the various elaborations of the food are effected are 
many in number. For first of all there is the mouth and the parts 
inside the mouth, on which the first share in the duty clearly 
devolves, in such animals at least as live on food which requires 
disintegration. The mouth, however, does not actually concoct 
the food, but merely facilitates concoction; for the subdivision 
of the food into small bits facilitates the action of heat upon it. 
After the mouth come the upper and the lower abdominal 
cavities, and here it is that concoction is effected by the aid of 
natural heat. Again, just as there is a channel for the admission 
of the unconcocted food into the stomach, namely the mouth, 
and in some animals the so-called oesophagus, which is 
continuous with the mouth and reaches to the stomach, so 
must there also be other and more numerous channels by 



1825 



which the concocted food or nutriment shall pass out of the 
stomach and intestines into the body at large, and to which 
these cavities shall serve as a kind of manger. For plants get 
their food from the earth by means of their roots; and this food 
is already elaborated when taken in, which is the reason why 
plants produce no excrement, the earth and its heat serving 
them in the stead of a stomach. But animals, with scarcely an 
exception, and conspicuously all such as are capable of 
locomotion, are provided with a stomachal sac, which is as it 
were an internal substitute for the earth. They must therefore 
have some instrument which shall correspond to the roots of 
plants, with which they may absorb their food from this sac, so 
that the proper end of the successive stages of concoction may 
at last be attained. The mouth then, its duty done, passes over 
the food to the stomach, and there must necessarily be 
something to receive it in turn from this. This something is 
furnished by the bloodvessels, which run throughout the whole 
extent of the mesentery from its lowest part right up to the 
stomach. A description of these will be found in the treatises on 
Anatomy and Natural History. Now as there is a receptacle for 
the entire matter taken as food, and also a receptacle for its 
excremental residue, and again a third receptacle, namely the 
vessels, which serve as such for the blood, it is plain that this 
blood must be the final nutritive material in such animals as 
have it; while in bloodless animals the same is the case with the 
fluid which represents the blood. This explains why the blood 
diminishes in quantity when no food is taken, and increases 
when much is consumed, and also why it becomes healthy and 
unhealthy according as the food is of the one or the other 
character. These facts, then, and others of a like kind, make it 
plain that the purpose of the blood in sanguineous animals is to 
subserve the nutrition of the body. They also explain why no 
more sensation is produced by touching the blood than by 
touching one of the excretions or the food, whereas when the 



1826 



flesh is touched sensation is produced. For the blood is not 
continuous nor united by growth with the flesh, but simply lies 
loose in its receptacle, that is in the heart and vessels. The 
manner in which the parts grow at the expense of the blood, 
and indeed the whole question of nutrition, will find a more 
suitable place for exposition in the treatise on Generation, and 
in other writings. For our present purpose all that need be said 
is that the blood exists for the sake of nutrition, that is the 
nutrition of the parts; and with this much let us therefore 
content ourselves. 



What are called fibres are found in the blood of some animals 
but not of all. There are none, for instance, in the blood of deer 
and of roes; and for this reason the blood of such animals as 
these never coagulates. For one part of the blood consists 
mainly of water and therefore does not coagulate, this process 
occurring only in the other and earthy constituent, that is to say 
in the fibres, while the fluid part is evaporating. 

Some at any rate of the animals with watery blood have a 
keener intellect than those whose blood is of an earthier nature. 
This is due not to the coldness of their blood, but rather to its 
thinness and purity; neither of which qualities belongs to the 
earthy matter. For the thinner and purer its fluid is, the more 
easily affected is an animal's sensibility. Thus it is that some 
bloodless animals, notwithstanding their want of blood, are yet 
more intelligent than some among the sanguineous kinds. Such 
for instance, as already said, is the case with the bee and the 
tribe of ants, and whatever other animals there may be of a like 
nature. At the same time too great an excess of water makes 



1827 



animals timorous. For fear chills the body; so that in animals 
whose heart contains so watery a mixture the way is prepared 
for the operation of this emotion. For water is congealed by cold. 
This also explains why bloodless animals are, as a general rule, 
more timorous than such as have blood, so that they remain 
motionless, when frightened, and discharge their excretions, 
and in some instances change colour. Such animals, on the 
other hand, as have thick and abundant fibres in their blood are 
of a more earthy nature, and of a choleric temperament, and 
liable to bursts of passion. For anger is productive of heat; and 
solids, when they have been made hot, give off more heat than 
fluids. The fibres therefore, being earthy and solid, are turned 
into so many hot embers in the blood, like the embers in a 
vapour-bath, and cause ebullition in the fits of passion. 

This explains why bulls and boars are so choleric and so 
passionate. For their blood is exceedingly rich in fibres, and the 
bull's at any rate coagulates more rapidly than that of any other 
animal. If these fibres, that is to say if the earthy constituents of 
which we are speaking, are taken out of the blood, the fluid that 
remains behind will no longer coagulate; just as the watery 
residue of mud will not coagulate after removal of the earth. But 
if the fibres are left the fluid coagulates, as also does mud, 
under the influence of cold. For when the heat is expelled by the 
cold, the fluid, as has been already stated, passes off with it by 
evaporation, and the residue is dried up and solidified, not by 
heat but by cold. So long, however, as the blood is in the body, it 
is kept fluid by animal heat. 

The character of the blood affects both the temperament and 
the sensory faculties of animals in many ways. This is indeed 
what might reasonably be expected, seeing that the blood is the 
material of which the whole body is made. For nutriment 
supplies the material, and the blood is the ultimate nutriment. 



1828 



It makes then a considerable difference whether the blood be 
hot or cold, thin or thick, turbid or clear. 

The watery part of the blood is serum; and it is watery, either 
owing to its not being yet concocted, or owing to its having 
become corrupted; so that one part of the serum is the resultant 
of a necessary process, while another part is material intended 
to serve for the formation of the blood. 



The differences between lard and suet correspond to 
differences of blood. For both are blood concocted into these 
forms as a result of abundant nutrition, being that surplus blood 
that is not expended on the fleshy part of the body, and is of an 
easily concocted and fatty character. This is shown by the 
unctuous aspect of these substances; for such unctuous aspect 
in fluids is due to a combination of air and fire. It follows from 
what has been said that no non-sanguineous animals have 
either lard or suet; for they have no blood. Among sanguineous 
animals those whose blood is dense have suet rather than lard. 
For suet is of an earthy nature, that is to say, it contains but a 
small proportion of water and is chiefly composed of earth; and 
this it is that makes it coagulate, just as the fibrous matter of 
blood coagulates, or broths which contain such fibrous matter. 
Thus it is that in those horned animals that have no front teeth 
in the upper jaw the fat consists of suet. For the very fact that 
they have horns and huckle-bones shows that their 
composition is rich in this earthy element; for all such 
appurtenances are solid and earthy in character. On the other 
hand in those hornless animals that have front teeth in both 
jaws, and whose feet are divided into toes, there is no suet, but 



1829 



in its place lard; and this, not being of an earthy character, 
neither coagulates nor dries up into a friable mass. 

Both lard and suet when present in moderate amount are 
beneficial; for they contribute to health and strength, while they 
are no hindrance to sensation. But when they are present in 
great excess, they are injurious and destructive. For were the 
whole body formed of them it would perish. For an animal is an 
animal in virtue of its sensory part, that is in virtue of its flesh, 
or of the substance analogous to flesh. But the blood, as before 
stated, is not sensitive; as therefore is neither lard nor suet, 
seeing that they are nothing but concocted blood. Were then the 
whole body composed of these substances, it would be utterly 
without sensation. Such animals, again, as are excessively fat 
age rapidly. For so much of their blood is used in forming fat, 
that they have but little left; and when there is but little blood 
the way is already open for decay. For decay may be said to be 
deficiency of blood, the scantiness of which renders it liable, like 
all bodies of small bulk, to be injuriously affected by any chance 
excess of heat or cold. For the same reason fat animals are less 
prolific than others. For that part of the blood which should go 
to form semen and seed is used up in the production of lard and 
suet, which are nothing but concocted blood; so that in these 
animals there is either no reproductive excretion at all, or only a 
scanty amount. 



So much then of blood and serum, and of lard and suet. Each of 
these has been described, and the purposes told for which they 
severally exist. The marrow also is of the nature of blood, and 
not, as some think, the germinal force of the semen. That this is 



1830 



the case is quite evident in very young animals. For in the 
embryo the marrow of the bones has a blood-like appearance, 
which is but natural, seeing that the parts are all constructed 
out of blood, and that it is on blood that the embryo is 
nourished. But, as the young animal grows up and ripens into 
maturity, the marrow changes its colour, just as do the external 
parts and the viscera. For the viscera also in animals, so long as 
they are young, have each and all a blood-like look, owing to the 
large amount of this fluid which they contain. 

The consistency of the marrow agrees with that of the fat. For 
when the fat consists of lard, then the marrow also is unctuous 
and lard-like; but when the blood is converted by concoction 
into suet, and does not assume the form of lard, then the 
marrow also has a suety character. In those animals, therefore, 
that have horns and are without upper front teeth, the marrow 
has the character of suet; while it takes the form of lard in those 
that have front teeth in both jaws, and that also have the foot 
divided into toes. What has ben said hardly applies to the spinal 
marrow. For it is necessary that this shall be continuous and 
extend without break through the whole backbone, inasmuch 
as this bone consists of separate vertebrae. But were the spinal 
marrow either of unctuous fat or of suet, it could not hold 
together in such a continuous mass as it does, but would either 
be too fluid or too frangible. 

There are some animals that can hardly be said to have any 
marrow. These are those whose bones are strong and solid, as is 
the case with the lion. For in this animal the marrow is so 
utterly insignificant that the bones look as though they had 
none at all. However, as it is necessary that animals shall have 
bones or something analogous to them, such as the fish-spines 
of water-animals, it is also a matter of necessity that some of 
these bones shall contain marrow; for the substance contained 
within the bones is the nutriment out of which these are 



1831 



formed. Now the universal nutriment, as already stated, is 
blood; and the blood within the bone, owing to the heat which 
is developed in it from its being thus surrounded, undergoes 
concoction, and self-concocted blood is suet or lard; so that it is 
perfectly intelligible how the marrow within the bone comes to 
have the character of these substances. So also it is easy to 
understand why, in those animals that have strong and 
compact bones, some of these should be entirely void of 
marrow, while the rest contain but little of it; for here the 
nutriment is spent in forming the bones. 

Those animals that have fish-spines in place of bones have no 
other marrow than that of the chine. For in the first place they 
have naturally but a small amount of blood; and secondly the 
only hollow fish-spine is that of the chine. In this then marrow 
is formed; this being the only spine in which there is space for 
it, and, moreover, being the only one which owing to its division 
into parts requires a connecting bond. This too is the reason 
why the marrow of the chine, as already mentioned, is 
somewhat different from that of other bones. For, having to act 
the part of a clasp, it must be of glutinous character, and at the 
same time sinewy so as to admit of stretching. 

Such then are the reasons for the existence of marrow, in those 
animals that have any, and such its nature. It is evidently the 
surplus of the sanguineous nutriment apportioned to the bones 
and fish-spines, which has undergone concoction owing to its 
being enclosed within them. 



From the marrow we pass on in natural sequence to the brain. 
For there are many who think that the brain itself consists of 



1832 



marrow, and that it forms the commencement of that 
substance, because they see that the spinal marrow is 
continuous with it. In reality the two may be said to be utterly 
opposite to each other in character. For of all the parts of the 
body there is none so cold as the brain; whereas the marrow is 
of a hot nature, as is plainly shown by its fat and unctuous 
character. Indeed this is the very reason why the brain and 
spinal marrow are continuous with each other. For, wherever 
the action of any part is in excess, nature so contrives as to set 
by it another part with an excess of contrary action, so that the 
excesses of the two may counterbalance each other. Now that 
the marrow is hot is clearly shown by many indications. The 
coldness of the brain is also manifest enough. For in the first 
place it is cold even to the touch; and, secondly, of all the fluid 
parts of the body it is the driest and the one that has the least 
blood; for in fact it has no blood at all in its proper substance. 
This brain is not residual matter, nor yet is it one of the parts 
which are anatomically continuous with each other; but it has a 
character peculiar to itself, as might indeed be expected. That it 
has no continuity with the organs of sense is plain from simple 
inspection, and is still more clearly shown by the fact, that, 
when it is touched, no sensation is produced; in which respect it 
resembles the blood of animals and their excrement. The 
purpose of its presence in animals is no less than the 
preservation of the whole body. For some writers assert that the 
soul is fire or some such force. This, however, is but a rough and 
inaccurate assertion; and it would perhaps be better to say that 
the soul is incorporate in some substance of a fiery character. 
The reason for this being so is that of all substances there is 
none so suitable for ministering to the operations of the soul as 
that which is possessed of heat. For nutrition and the imparting 
of motion are offices of the soul, and it is by heat that these are 
most readily effected. To say then that the soul is fire is much 
the same thing as to confound the auger or the saw with the 



1833 



carpenter or his craft, simply because the work is wrought by 
the two in conjunction. So far then this much is plain, that all 
animals must necessarily have a certain amount of heat. But as 
all influences require to be counterbalanced, so that they may 
be reduced to moderation and brought to the mean (for in the 
mean, and not in either extreme, lies the true and rational 
position), nature has contrived the brain as a counterpoise to 
the region of the heart with its contained heat, and has given it 
to animals to moderate the latter, combining in it the properties 
of earth and water. For this reason it is, that every sanguineous 
animal has a brain; whereas no bloodless creature has such an 
organ, unless indeed it be, as the Poulp, by analogy. For where 
there is no blood, there in consequence there is but little heat. 
The brain, then, tempers the heat and seething of the heart. In 
order, however, that it may not itself be absolutely without heat, 
but may have a moderate amount, branches run from both 
blood-vessels, that is to say from the great vessel and from what 
is called the aorta, and end in the membrane which surrounds 
the brain; while at the same time, in order to prevent any injury 
from the heat, these encompassing vessels, instead of being few 
and large, are numerous and small, and their blood scanty and 
clear, instead of being abundant and thick. We can now 
understand why defluxions have their origin in the head, and 
occur whenever the parts about the brain have more than a due 
proportion of coldness. For when the nutriment steams 
upwards through the blood-vessels, its refuse portion is chilled 
by the influence of this region, and forms defluxions of phlegm 
and serum. We must suppose, to compare small things with 
great, that the like happens here as occurs in the production of 
showers. For when vapour steams up from the earth and is 
carried by the heat into the upper regions, so soon as it reaches 
the cold air that is above the earth, it condenses again into 
water owing to the refrigeration, and falls back to the earth as 
rain. These, however, are matters which may be suitably 



1834 



considered in the Principles of Diseases, so far as natural 
philosophy has anything to say to them. 

It is the brain again - or, in animals that have no brain, the part 
analogous to it - which is the cause of sleep. For either by 
chilling the blood that streams upwards after food, or by some 
other similar influences, it produces heaviness in the region in 
which it lies (which is the reason why drowsy persons hang the 
head), and causes the heat to escape downwards in company 
with the blood. It is the accumulation of this in excess in the 
lower region that produces complete sleep, taking away the 
power of standing upright from those animals to whom that 
posture is natural, and from the rest the power of holding up 
the head. These, however, are matters which have been 
separately considered in the treatises on Sensation and on 
Sleep. 

That the brain is a compound of earth and water is shown by 
what occurs when it is boiled. For, when so treated, it turns hard 
and solid, inasmuch as the water is evaporated by the heat, and 
leaves the earthy part behind. Just the same occurs when pulse 
and other fruits are boiled. For these also are hardened by the 
process, because the water which enters into their composition 
is driven off and leaves the earth, which is their main 
constituent, behind. 

Of all animals, man has the largest brain in proportion to his 
size; and it is larger in men than in women. This is because the 
region of the heart and of the lung is hotter and richer in blood 
in man than in any other animal; and in men than in women. 
This again explains why man, alone of animals, stands erect. 
For the heat, overcoming any opposite inclination, makes 
growth take its own line of direction, which is from the centre of 
the body upwards. It is then as a counterpoise to his excessive 
heat that in man's brain there is this superabundant fluidity 



1835 



and coldness; and it is again owing to this superabundance that 
the cranial bone, which some call the Bregma, is the last to 
become solidified; so long does evaporation continue to occur 
through it under the influence of heat. Man is the only 
sanguineous animal in which this takes place. Man, again, has 
more sutures in his skull than any other animal, and the male 
more than the female. The explanation is again to be found in 
the greater size of the brain, which demands free ventilation, 
proportionate to its bulk. For if the brain be either too fluid or 
too solid, it will not perform its office, but in the one case will 
freeze the blood, and in the other will not cool it at all; and thus 
will cause disease, madness, and death. For the cardiac heat 
and the centre of life is most delicate in its sympathies, and is 
immediately sensitive to the slightest change or affection of the 
blood on the outer surface of the brain. 

The fluids which are present in the animal body at the time of 
birth have now nearly all been considered. Amongst those that 
appear only at a later period are the residua of the food, which 
include the deposits of the belly and also those of the bladder. 
Besides these there is the semen and the milk, one or the other 
of which makes its appearance in appropriate animals. Of these 
fluids the excremental residua of the food may be suitably 
discussed by themselves, when we come to examine and 
consider the subject of nutrition. Then will be the time to 
explain in what animals they are found, and what are the 
reasons for their presence. Similarly all questions concerning 
the semen and the milk may be dealt with in the treatise on 
Generation, for the former of these fluids is the very starting- 
point of the generative process, and the latter has no other 
ground of existence than generative purposes. 



1836 



8 

We have now to consider the remaining homogeneous parts, 
and will begin with flesh, and with the substance that, in 
animals that have no flesh, takes its place. The reason for so 
beginning is that flesh forms the very basis of animals, and is 
the essential constituent of their body. Its right to this 
precedence can also be demonstrated logically. For an animal is 
by our definition something that has sensibility and chief of all 
the primary sensibility, which is that of Touch; and it is the 
flesh, or analogous substance, which is the organ of this sense. 
And it is the organ, either in the same way as the pupil is the 
organ of sight, that is it constitutes the primary organ of the 
sense; or it is the organ and the medium through which the 
object acts combined, that is it answers to the pupil with the 
whole transparent medium attached to it. Now in the case of 
the other senses it was impossible for nature to unite the 
medium with the sense-organ, nor would such a junction have 
served any purpose; but in the case of touch she was compelled 
by necessity to do so. For of all the sense-organs that of touch is 
the only one that has corporeal substance, or at any rate it is 
more corporeal than any other, and its medium must be 
corporeal like itself. 

It is obvious also to sense that it is for the sake of the flesh that 
all the other parts exist. By the other parts I mean the bones, 
the skin, the sinews, and the blood-vessels, and, again, the hair 
and the various kinds of nails, and anything else there may be 
of a like character. Thus the bones are a contrivance to give 
security to the soft parts, to which purpose they are adapted by 
their hardness; and in animals that have no bones the same 
office is fulfilled by some analogous substance, as by fishspine 
in some fishes, and by cartilage in others. 



1837 



Now in some animals this supporting substance is situated 
within the body, while in some of the bloodless species it is 
placed on the outside. The latter is the case in all the Crustacea, 
as the Carcini (Crabs) and the Carabi (Prickly Lobsters); it is the 
case also in the Testacea, as for instance in the several species 
known by the general name of oysters. For in all these animals 
the fleshy substance is within, and the earthy matter, which 
holds the soft parts together and keeps them from injury, is on 
the outside. For the shell not only enables the soft parts to hold 
together, but also, as the animal is bloodless and so has but 
little natural warmth, surrounds it, as a chaufferette does the 
embers, and keeps in the smouldering heat. Similar to this 
seems to be the arrangement in another and distinct tribe of 
animals, namely the Tortoises, including the Chelone and the 
several kinds of Emys. But in Insects and in Cephalopods the 
plan is entirely different, there being moreover a contrast 
between these two themselves. For in neither of these does 
there appear to be any bony or earthy part, worthy of notice, 
distinctly separated from the rest of the body. Thus in the 
Cephalopods the main bulk of the body consists of a soft flesh- 
like substance, or rather of a substance which is intermediate to 
flesh and sinew, so as not to be so readily destructible as actual 
flesh. I call this substance intermediate to flesh and sinew, 
because it is soft like the former, while it admits of stretching 
like the latter. Its cleavage, however, is such that it splits not 
longitudinally, like sinew, but into circular segments, this being 
the most advantageous condition, so far as strength is 
concerned. These animals have also a part inside them 
corresponding to the spinous bones of fishes. For instance, in 
the Cuttle-fishes there is what is known as the os sepiae, and in 
the Calamaries there is the so-called gladius. In the Poulps, on 
the other hand, there is no such internal part, because the body, 
or, as it is termed in them, the head, forms but a short sac, 
whereas it is of considerable length in the other two; and it was 



1838 



this length which led nature to assign to them their hard 
support, so as to ensure their straightness and inflexibility; just 
as she has assigned to sanguineous animals their bones or their 
fish-spines, as the case may be. To come now to Insects. In these 
the arrangement is quite different from that of the 
Cephalopods; quite different also from that which obtains in 
sanguineous animals, as indeed has been already stated. For in 
an insect there is no distinction into soft and hard parts, but the 
whole body is hard, the hardness, however, being of such a 
character as to be more flesh-like than bone, and more earthy 
and bone-like than flesh. The purpose of this is to make the 
body of the insect less liable to get broken into pieces. 



There is a resemblance between the osseous and the vascular 
systems; for each has a central part in which it begins, and each 
forms a continuous whole. For no bone in the body exists as a 
separate thing in itself, but each is either a portion of what may 
be considered a continuous whole, or at any rate is linked with 
the rest by contact and by attachments; so that nature may use 
adjoining bones either as though they were actually continuous 
and formed a single bone, or, for purposes of flexure, as though 
they were two and distinct. And similarly no blood-vessel has in 
itself a separate individuality; but they all form parts of one 
whole. For an isolated bone, if such there were, would in the 
first place be unable to perform the office for the sake of which 
bones exist; for, were it discontinuous and separated from the 
rest by a gap, it would be perfectly unable to produce either 
flexure or extension; nor only so, but it would actually be 
injurious, acting like a thorn or an arrow lodged in the flesh. 
Similarly if a vessel were isolated, and not continuous with the 



1839 



vascular centre, it would be unable to retain the blood within it 
in a proper state. For it is the warmth derived from this centre 
that hinders the blood from coagulating; indeed the blood, 
when withdrawn from its influence, becomes manifestly putrid. 
Now the centre or origin of the blood-vessels is the heart, and 
the centre or origin of the bones, in all animals that have bones, 
is what is called the chine. With this all the other bones of the 
body are in continuity; for it is the chine that holds together the 
whole length of an animal and preserves its straightness. But 
since it is necessary that the body of an animal shall bend 
during locomotion, this chine, while it is one in virtue of the 
continuity of its parts, yet its division into vertebrae is made to 
consist of many segments. It is from this chine that the bones of 
the limbs, in such animals as have these parts, proceed, and 
with it they are continuous, being fastened together by the 
sinews where the limbs admit of flexure, and having their 
extremities adapted to each other, either by the one being 
hollowed and the other rounded, or by both being hollowed and 
including between them a hucklebone, as a connecting bolt, so 
as to allow of flexure and extension. For without some such 
arrangement these movements would be utterly impossible, or 
at any rate would be performed with great difficulty. There are 
some joints, again, in which the lower end of the one bone and 
the upper end of the other are alike in shape. In these cases the 
bones are bound together by sinews, and cartilaginous pieces 
are interposed in the joint, to serve as a kind of padding, and 
prevent the two extremities from grating against each other. 

Round about the bones, and attached to them by thin fibrous 
bands, grow the fleshy parts, for the sake of which the bones 
themselves exist. For just as an artist, when he is moulding an 
animal out of clay or other soft substance, takes first some solid 
body as a basis, and round this moulds the clay, so also has 
nature acted in fashioning the animal body out of flesh. Thus 
we find all the fleshy parts, with one exception, supported by 



1840 



bones, which serve, when the parts are organs of motion, to 
facilitate flexure, and, when the parts are motionless, act as a 
protection. The ribs, for example, which enclose the chest are 
intended to ensure the safety of the heart and neighbouring 
viscera. The exception of which mention was made is the belly. 
The walls of this are in all animals devoid of bones; in order 
that there may be no hindrance to the expansion which 
necessarily occurs in this part after a meal, nor, in females, any 
interference with the growth of the foetus, which is lodged here. 

Now the bones of viviparous animals, of such, that is, as are not 
merely externally but also internally viviparous, vary but very 
little from each other in point of strength, which in all of them 
is considerable. For the Vivipara in their bodily proportions are 
far above other animals, and many of them occasionally grow to 
an enormous size, as is the case in Libya and in hot and dry 
countries generally. But the greater the bulk of an animal, the 
stronger, the bigger, and the harder, are the supports which it 
requires; and comparing the big animals with each other, this 
requirement will be most marked in those that live a life of 
rapine. Thus it is that the bones of males are harder than those 
of females; and the bones of flesh-eaters, that get their food by 
fighting, are harder than those of Herbivora. Of this the Lion is 
an example; for so hard are its bones, that, when struck, they 
give off sparks, as though they were stones. It may be 
mentioned also that the Dolphin, in as much as it is viviparous, 
is provided with bones and not with fish-spines. 

In those sanguineous animals, on the other hand, that are 
oviparous, the bones present successive slight variations of 
character. Thus in Birds there are bones, but these are not so 
strong as the bones of the Vivipara. Then come the Oviparous 
fishes, where there is no bone, but merely fish-spine. In the 
Serpents too the bones have the character of fish-spine, 
excepting in the very large species, where the solid foundation 



1841 



of the body requires to be stronger, in order that the animal 
itself may be strong, the same reason prevailing as in the case 
of the Vivipara. Lastly, in the Selachia, as they are called, the 
fish-spines are replaced by cartilage. For it is necessary that the 
movements of these animals shall be of an undulating 
character; and this again requires the framework that supports 
the body to be made of a pliable and not of a brittle substance. 
Moreover, in these Selachia nature has used all the earthy 
matter on the skin; and she is unable to allot to many different 
parts one and the same superfluity of material. Even in 
viviparous animals many of the bones are cartilaginous. This 
happens in those parts where it is to the advantage of the 
surrounding flesh that its solid base shall be soft and 
mucilaginous. Such, for instance, is the case with the ears and 
nostrils; for in projecting parts, such as these, brittle substances 
would soon get broken. Cartilage and bone are indeed 
fundamentally the same thing, the differences between them 
being merely matters of degree. Thus neither cartilage nor bone, 
when once cut off, grows again. Now the cartilages of these land 
animals are without marrow, that is without any distinctly 
separate marrow. For the marrow, which in bones is distinctly 
separate, is here mixed up with the whole mass, and gives a soft 
and mucilaginous consistence to the cartilage. But in the 
Selachia the chine, though it is cartilaginous, yet contains 
marrow; for here it stands in the stead of a bone. 

Very nearly resembling the bones to the touch are such parts as 
nails, hoofs, whether solid or cloven, horns, and the beaks of 
birds, all of which are intended to serve as means of defence. 
For the organs which are made out of these substances, and 
which are called by the same names as the substances 
themselves, the organ hoof, for instance, and the organ horn, 
are contrivances to ensure the preservation of the animals to 
which they severally belong. In this class too must be reckoned 
the teeth, which in some animals have but a single function, 



1842 



namely the mastication of the food, while in others they have 
an additional office, namely to serve as weapons; as is the case 
with all animals that have sharp interfitting teeth or that have 
tusks. All these parts are necessarily of solid and earthy 
character; for the value of a weapon depends on such 
properties. Their earthy character explains how it is that all 
such parts are more developed in four-footed vivipara than in 
man. For there is always more earth in the composition of these 
animals than in that of the human body. However, not only all 
these parts but such others as are nearly connected with them, 
skin for instance, bladder, membrane, hairs, feathers, and their 
analogues, and any other similar parts that there may be, will 
be considered farther on with the heterogeneous parts. There 
we shall inquire into the causes which produce them, and into 
the objects of their presence severally in the bodies of animals. 
For, as with the heterogeneous parts, so with these, it is from a 
consideration of their functions that alone we can derive any 
knowledge of them. The reason for dealing with them at all in 
this part of the treatise, and classifying them with the 
homogeneous parts, is that under one and the same name are 
confounded the entire organs and the substances of which they 
are composed. But of all these substances flesh and bone form 
the basis. Semen and milk were also passed over when we were 
considering the homogeneous fluids. For the treatise on 
Generation will afford a more suitable place for their 
examination, seeing that the former of the two is the very 
foundation of the thing generated, while the latter is its 
nourishment. 



1843 



10 

Let us now make, as it were, a fresh beginning, and consider the 
heterogeneous parts, taking those first which are the first in 
importance. For in all animals, at least in all the perfect kinds, 
there are two parts more essential than the rest, namely the 
part which serves for the ingestion of food, and the part which 
serves for the discharge of its residue. For without food growth 
and even existence is impossible. Intervening again between 
these two parts there is invariably a third, in which is lodged the 
vital principle. As for plants, though they also are included by us 
among things that have life, yet are they without any part for 
the discharge of waste residue. For the food which they absorb 
from the ground is already concocted, and they give off as its 
equivalent their seeds and fruits. Plants, again, inasmuch as 
they are without locomotion, present no great variety in their 
heterogeneous parts. For, where the functions are but few, few 
also are the organs required to effect them. The configuration of 
plants is a matter then for separate consideration. Animals, 
however, that not only live but feel, present a greater 
multiformity of parts, and this diversity is greater in some 
animals than in others, being most varied in those to whose 
share has fallen not mere life but life of high degree. Now such 
an animal is man. For of all living beings with which we are 
acquainted man alone partakes of the divine, or at any rate 
partakes of it in a fuller measure than the rest. For this reason, 
then, and also because his external parts and their forms are 
more familiar to us than those of other animals, we must speak 
of man first; and this the more fitly, because in him alone do the 
natural parts hold the natural position; his upper part being 
turned towards that which is upper in the universe. For, of all 
animals, man alone stands erect. 

In man, then, the head is destitute of flesh; this being the 
necessary consequence of what has already been stated 



1844 



concerning the brain. There are, indeed, some who hold that the 
life of man would be longer than it is, were his head more 
abundantly furnished with flesh; and they account for the 
absence of this substance by saying that it is intended to add to 
the perfection of sensation. For the brain they assert to be the 
organ of sensation; and sensation, they say, cannot penetrate to 
parts that are too thickly covered with flesh. But neither part of 
this statement is true. On the contrary, were the region of the 
brain thickly covered with flesh, the very purpose for which 
animals are provided with a brain would be directly 
contravened. For the brain would itself be heated to excess and 
so unable to cool any other part; and, as to the other half of 
their statement, the brain cannot be the cause of any of the 
sensations, seeing that it is itself as utterly without feeling as 
any one of the excretions. These writers see that certain of the 
senses are located in the head, and are unable to discern the 
reason for this; they see also that the brain is the most peculiar 
of all the animal organs; and out of these facts they form an 
argument, by which they link sensation and brain together. It 
has, however, already been clearly set forth in the treatise on 
Sensation, that it is the region of the heart that constitutes the 
sensory centre. There also it was stated that two of the senses, 
namely touch and taste, are manifestly in immediate connexion 
with the heart; and that as regards the other three, namely 
hearing, sight, and the centrally placed sense of smell, it is the 
character of their sense-organs which causes them to be lodged 
as a rule in the head. Vision is so placed in all animals. But such 
is not invariably the case with hearing or with smell. For fishes 
and the like hear and smell, and yet have no visible organs for 
these senses in the head; a fact which demonstrates the 
accuracy of the opinion here maintained. Now that vision, 
whenever it exists, should be in the neighbourhood of the brain 
is but what one would rationally expect. For the brain is fluid 
and cold, and vision is of the nature of water, water being of all 



1845 



transparent substances the one most easily confined. Moreover 
it cannot but necessarily be that the more precise senses will 
have their precision rendered still greater if ministered to by 
parts that have the purest blood. For the motion of the heat of 
blood destroys sensory activity. For these reasons the organs of 
the precise senses are lodged in the head. 

It is not only the fore part of the head that is destitute of flesh, 
but the hind part also. For, in all animals that have a head, it is 
this head which more than any other part requires to be held 
up. But, were the head heavily laden with flesh, this would be 
impossible; for nothing so burdened can be held upright. This is 
an additional proof that the absence of flesh from the head has 
no reference to brain sensation. For there is no brain in the 
hinder part of the head, and yet this is as much without flesh as 
is the front. 

In some animals hearing as well as vision is lodged in the 
region of the head. Nor is this without a rational explanation. 
For what is called the empty space is full of air, and the organ of 
hearing is, as we say, of the nature of air. Now there are 
channels which lead from the eyes to the blood-vessels that 
surround the brain; and similarly there is a channel which leads 
back again from each ear and connects it with the hinder part 
of the head. But no part that is without blood is endowed with 
sensation, as neither is the blood itself, but only some one of 
the parts that are formed of blood. 

The brain in all animals that have one is placed in the front part 
of the head; because the direction in which sensation acts is in 
front; and because the heart, from which sensation proceeds, is 
in the front part of the body; and lastly because the instruments 
of sensation are the blood-containing parts, and the cavity in 
the posterior part of the skull is destitute of blood-vessels. 



1846 



As to the position of the sense-organs, they have been arranged 
by nature in the following well-ordered manner. The organs of 
hearing are so placed as to divide the circumference of the head 
into two equal halves; for they have to hear not only sounds 
which are directly in line with themselves, but sounds from all 
quarters. The organs of vision are placed in front, because sight 
is exercised only in a straight line, and moving as we do in a 
forward direction it is necessary that we should see before us, in 
the direction of our motion. Lastly, the organs of smell are 
placed with good reason between the eyes. For as the body 
consists of two parts, a right half and a left, so also each organ 
of sense is double. In the case of touch this is not apparent, the 
reason being that the primary organ of this sense is not the 
flesh or analogous part, but lies internally. In the case of taste, 
which is merely a modification of touch and which is placed in 
the tongue, the fact is more apparent than in the case of touch, 
but still not so manifest as in the case of the other senses. 
However, even in taste it is evident enough; for in some animals 
the tongue is plainly forked. The double character of the 
sensations is, however, more conspicuous in the other organs of 
sense. For there are two ears and two eyes, and the nostrils, 
though joined together, are also two. Were these latter 
otherwise disposed, and separated from each other as are the 
ears, neither they nor the nose in which they are placed would 
be able to perform their office. For in such animals as have 
nostrils olfaction is effected by means of inspiration, and the 
organ of inspiration is placed in front and in the middle line. 
This is the reason why nature has brought the two nostrils 
together and placed them as the central of the three sense- 
organs, setting them side by side on a level with each other, to 
avail themselves of the inspiratory motion. In other animals 
than man the arrangement of these sense-organs is also such 
as is adapted in each case to the special requirements. 



1847 



11 

For instance, in quadrupeds the ears stand out freely from the 
head and are set to all appearance above the eyes. Not that they 
are in reality above the eyes; but they seem to be so, because the 
animal does not stand erect, but has its head hung downwards. 
This being the usual attitude of the animal when in motion, it is 
of advantage that its ears shall be high up and movable; for by 
turning themselves about they can the better take in sounds 
from every quarter. 



12 

In birds, on the other hand, there are no ears, but only the 
auditory passages. This is because their skin is hard and 
because they have feathers instead of hairs, so that they have 
not got the proper material for the formation of ears. Exactly the 
same is the case with such oviparous quadrupeds as are clad 
with scaly plates, and the same explanation applies to them. 
There is also one of the viviparous quadrupeds, namely the seal, 
that has no ears but only the auditory passages. The 
explanation of this is that the seal, though a quadruped, is a 
quadruped of stunted formation. 



13 

Men, and Birds, and Quadrupeds, viviparous and oviparous 
alike, have their eyes protected by lids. In the Vivipara there are 



1848 



two of these; and both are used by these animals not only in 
closing the eyes, but also in the act of blinking; whereas the 
oviparous quadrupeds, and the heavy-bodied birds as well as 
some others, use only the lower lid to close the eye; while birds 
blink by means of a membrane that issues from the canthus. 
The reason for the eyes being thus protected is that nature has 
made them of fluid consistency, in order to ensure keenness of 
vision. For had they been covered with hard skin, they would, it 
is true, have been less liable to get injured by anything falling 
into them from without, but they would not have been sharp- 
sighted. It is then to ensure keenness of vision that the skin 
over the pupil is fine and delicate; while the lids are superadded 
as a protection from injury. It is as a still further safeguard that 
all these animals blink, and man most of all; this action (which 
is not performed from deliberate intention but from a natural 
instinct) serving to keep objects from falling into the eyes; and 
being more frequent in man than in the rest of these animals, 
because of the greater delicacy of his skin. These lids are made 
of a roll of skin; and it is because they are made of skin and 
contain no flesh that neither they, nor the similarly constructed 
prepuce, unite again when once cut. 

As to the oviparous quadrupeds, and such birds as resemble 
them in closing the eye with the lower lid, it is the hardness of 
the skin of their heads which makes them do so. For such birds 
as have heavy bodies are not made for flight; and so the 
materials which would otherwise have gone to increase the 
growth of the feathers are diverted thence, and used to 
augment the thickness of the skin. Birds therefore of this kind 
close the eye with the lower lid; whereas pigeons and the like 
use both upper and lower lids for the purpose. As birds are 
covered with feathers, so oviparous quadrupeds are covered 
with scaly plates; and these in all their forms are harder than 
hairs, so that the skin also to which they belong is harder than 
the skin of hairy animals. In these animals, then, the skin on 



1849 



the head is hard, and so does not allow of the formation of an 
upper eyelid, whereas lower down the integument is of a flesh- 
like character, so that the lower lid can be thin and extensible. 

The act of blinking is performed by the heavy-bodied birds by 
means of the membrane already mentioned, and not by this 
lower lid. For in blinking rapid motion is required, and such is 
the motion of this membrane, whereas that of the lower lid is 
slow. It is from the canthus that is nearest to the nostrils that 
the membrane comes. For it is better to have one starting-point 
for nictitation than two; and in these birds this starting-point is 
the junction of eye and nostrils, an anterior starting-point being 
preferable to a lateral one. Oviparous quadrupeds do not blink 
in like manner as the birds; for, living as they do on the ground, 
they are free from the necessity of having eyes of fluid 
consistency and of keen sight, whereas these are essential 
requisites for birds, inasmuch as they have to use their eyes at 
long distances. This too explains why birds with talons, that 
have to search for prey by eye from aloft, and therefore soar to 
greater heights than other birds, are sharpsighted; while 
common fowls and the like, that live on the ground and are not 
made for flight, have no such keenness of vision. For there is 
nothing in their mode of life which imperatively requires it. 

Fishes and Insects and the hard-skinned Crustacea present 
certain differences in their eyes, but so far resemble each other 
as that none of them have eyelids. As for the hard-skinned 
Crustacea it is utterly out of the question that they should have 
any; for an eyelid, to be of use, requires the action of the skin to 
be rapid. These animals then have no eyelids and, in default of 
this protection, their eyes are hard, just as though the lid were 
attached to the surface of the eye, and the animal saw through 
it. Inasmuch, however, as such hardness must necessarily blunt 
the sharpness of vision, nature has endowed the eyes of Insects, 
and still more those of Crustacea, with mobility (just as she has 



1850 



given some quadrupeds movable ears), in order that they may 
be able to turn to the light and catch its rays, and so see more 
plainly. Fishes, however, have eyes of a fluid consistency. For 
animals that move much about have to use their vision at 
considerable distances. If now they live on land, the air in which 
they move is transparent enough. But the water in which fishes 
live is a hindrance to sharp sight, though it has this advantage 
over the air, that it does not contain so many objects to knock 
against the eyes. The risk of collision being thus small, nature, 
who makes nothing in vain, has given no eyelids to fishes, while 
to counterbalance the opacity of the water she has made their 
eyes of fluid consistency. 



14 

All animals that have hairs on the body have lashes on the 
eyelids; but birds and animals with scale-like plates, being 
hairless, have none. The Libyan ostrich, indeed, forms an 
exception; for, though a bird, it is furnished with eyelashes. This 
exception, however, will be explained hereafter. Of hairy 
animals, man alone has lashes on both lids. For in quadrupeds 
there is a greater abundance of hair on the back than on the 
under side of the body; whereas in man the contrary is the case, 
and the hair is more abundant on the front surface than on the 
back. The reason for this is that hair is intended to serve as a 
protection to its possessor. Now, in quadrupeds, owing to their 
inclined attitude, the under or anterior surface does not require 
so much protection as the back, and is therefore left 
comparatively bald, in spite of its being the nobler of the two 
sides. But in man, owing to his upright attitude, the anterior and 
posterior surfaces of the body are on an equality as regards 
need of protection. Nature therefore has assigned the protective 



1851 



covering to the nobler of the two surfaces; for invariably she 
brings about the best arrangement of such as are possible. This 
then is the reason that there is no lower eyelash in any 
quadruped; though in some a few scattered hairs sprout out 
under the lower lid. This also is the reason that they never have 
hair in the axillae, nor on the pubes, as man has. Their hair, 
then, instead of being collected in these parts, is either thickly 
set over the whole dorsal surface, as is the case for instance in 
dogs, or, sometimes, forms a mane, as in horses and the like, or 
as in the male lion where the mane is still more flowing and 
ample. So, again, whenever there is a tail of any length, nature 
decks it with hair, with long hair if the stem of the tail be short, 
as in horses, with short hair if the stem be long, regard also 
being had to the condition of the rest of the body. For nature 
invariably gives to one part what she subtracts from another. 
Thus when she has covered the general surface of an animal's 
body with an excess of hair, she leaves a deficiency in the region 
of the tail. This, for instance, in the case with bears. 

No animal has so much hair on the head as man. This, in the 
first place, is the necessary result of the fluid character of his 
brain, and of the presence of so many sutures in his skull. For 
wherever there is the most fluid and the most heat, there also 
must necessarily occur the greatest outgrowth. But, secondly, 
the thickness of the hair in this part has a final cause, being 
intended to protect the head, by preserving it from excess of 
either heat or cold. And as the brain of man is larger and more 
fluid than that of any other animal, it requires a proportionately 
greater amount of protection. For the more fluid a substance is, 
the more readily does it get excessively heated or excessively 
chilled, while substances of an opposite character are less liable 
to such injurious affections. 

These, however, are matters which by their close connexion 
with eyelashes have led us to digress from our real topic, 



1852 



namely the cause to which these lashes owe their existence. We 
must therefore defer any further remarks we may have to make 
on these matters till the proper occasion arises and then return 
to their consideration. 



15 

Both eyebrows and eyelashes exist for the protection of the 
eyes; the former that they may shelter them, like the eaves of a 
house, from any fluids that trickle down from the head; the 
latter to act like the palisades which are sometimes placed in 
front of enclosures, and keep out any objects which might 
otherwise get in. The brows are placed over the junction of two 
bones, which is the reason that in old age they often become so 
bushy as to require cutting. The lashes are set at the 
terminations of small blood-vessels. For the vessels come to an 
end where the skin itself terminates; and, in all places where 
these endings occur, the exudation of moisture of a corporeal 
character necessitates the growth of hairs, unless there be some 
operation of nature which interferes, by diverting the moisture 
to another purpose. 



16 

Viviparous quadrupeds, as a rule, present no great variety of 
form in the organ of smell. In those of them, however, whose 
jaws project forwards and taper to a narrow end, so as to form 
what is called a snout, the nostrils are placed in this projection, 
there being no other available plan; while, in the rest, there is a 



1853 



more definite demarcation between nostrils and jaws. But in no 
animal is this part so peculiar as in the elephant, where it 
attains an extraordinary and strength. For the elephant uses its 
nostril as a hand; this being the instrument with which it 
conveys food, fluid and solid alike, to its mouth. With it, too, it 
tears up trees, coiling it round their stems. In fact it applies it 
generally to the purposes of a hand. For the elephant has the 
double character of a land animal, and of one that lives in 
swamps. Seeing then that it has to get its food from the water, 
and yet must necessarily breathe, inasmuch as it is a land 
animal and has blood; seeing, also, that its excessive weight 
prevents it from passing rapidly from water to land, as some 
other sanguineous vivipara that breathe can do, it becomes 
necessary that it shall be suited alike for life in the water and 
for life on dry land, just then as divers are sometimes provided 
with instruments for respiration, through which they can draw 
air from above the water, and thus may remain for a long time 
under the sea, so also have elephants been furnished by nature 
with their lengthened nostril; and, whenever they have to 
traverse the water, they lift this up above the surface and 
breathe through it. For the elephant's proboscis, as already said, 
is a nostril. Now it would have been impossible for this nostril to 
have the form of a proboscis, had it been hard and incapable of 
bending. For its very length would then have prevented the 
animal from supplying itself with food, being as great an 
impediment as the of certain oxen, that are said to be obliged to 
walk backwards while they are grazing. It is therefore soft and 
flexible, and, being such, is made, in addition to its own proper 
functions, to serve the office of the fore-feet; nature in this 
following her wonted plan of using one and the same part for 
several purposes. For in polydactylous quadrupeds the fore-feet 
are intended not merely to support the weight of the body, but 
to serve as hands. But in elephants, though they must be 
reckoned polydactylous, as their foot has neither cloven nor 



1854 



solid hoof, the fore-feet, owing to the great size and weight of 
the body, are reduced to the condition of mere supports; and 
indeed their slow motion and unfitness for bending make them 
useless for any other purpose. A nostril, then, is given to the 
elephant for respiration, as to every other animal that has a 
lung, and is lengthened out and endowed with its power of 
coiling because the animal has to remain for considerable 
periods of time in the water, and is unable to pass thence to dry 
ground with any rapidity. But as the feet are shorn of their full 
office, this same part is also, as already said, made by nature to 
supply their place, and give such help as otherwise would be 
rendered by them. 

As to other sanguineous animals, the Birds, the Serpents, and 
the Oviparous quadrupeds, in all of them there are the nostril- 
holes, placed in front of the mouth; but in none are there any 
distinctly formed nostrils, nothing in fact which can be called 
nostrils except from a functional point of view. A bird at any rate 
has nothing which can properly be called a nose. For its so- 
called beak is a substitute for jaws. The reason for this is to be 
found in the natural conformation of birds. For they are winged 
bipeds; and this makes it necessary that their heads and neck 
shall be of light weight; just as it makes it necessary that their 
breast shall be narrow. The beak therefore with which they are 
provided is formed of a bone-like substance, in order that it may 
serve as a weapon as well as for nutritive purposes, but is made 
of narrow dimensions to suit the small size of the head. In this 
beak are placed the olfactory passages. But there are no nostrils; 
for such could not possibly be placed there. 

As for those animals that have no respiration, it has already 
been explained why it is that they are without nostrils, and 
perceive odours either through gills, or through a blowhole, or, if 
they are insects, by the hypozoma; and how the power of 
smelling depends, like their motion, upon the innate spirit of 



1855 



their bodies, which in all of them is implanted by nature and 
not introduced from without. 

Under the nostrils are the lips, in such sanguineous animals, 
that is, as have teeth. For in birds, as already has been said, the 
purposes of nutrition and defence are fulfilled by a bonelike 
beak, which forms a compound substitute for teeth and lips. For 
supposing that one were to cut off a man's lips, unite his upper 
teeth together, and similarly his under ones, and then were to 
lengthen out the two separate pieces thus formed, narrowing 
them on either side and making them project forwards, 
supposing, I say, this to be done, we should at once have a bird- 
like beak. 

The use of the lips in all animals except man is to preserve and 
guard the teeth; and thus it is that the distinctness with which 
the lips are formed is in direct proportion to the degree of nicety 
and perfection with which the teeth are fashioned. In man the 
lips are soft and flesh-like and capable of separating from each 
other. Their purpose, as in other animals, is to guard the teeth, 
but they are more especially intended to serve a higher office, 
contributing in common with other parts to man's faculty of 
speech. For just as nature has made man's tongue unlike that of 
other animals, and, in accordance with what I have said is her 
not uncommon practice, has used it for two distinct operations, 
namely for the perception of savours and for speech, so also has 
she acted with regard to the lips, and made them serve both for 
speech and for the protection of the teeth. For vocal speech 
consists of combinations of the letters, and most of these would 
be impossible to pronounce, were the lips not moist, nor the 
tongue such as it is. For some letters are formed by closures of 
the lips and others by applications of the tongue. But what are 
the differences presented by these and what the nature and 
extent of such differences, are questions to which answers must 
be sought from those who are versed in metrical science. It was 



1856 



necessary that the two parts which we are discussing should, in 
conformity with the requirements, be severally adapted to fulfil 
the office mentioned above, and be of appropriate character. 
Therefore are they made of flesh, and flesh is softer in man 
than in any other animal, the reason for this being that of all 
animals man has the most delicate sense of touch. 



17 

The tongue is placed under the vaulted roof of the mouth. In 
land animals it presents but little diversity. But in other animals 
it is variable, and this whethe+r we compare them as a class 
with such as live on land, or compare their several species with 
each other. It is in man that the tongue attains its greatest 
degree of freedom, of softness, and of breadth; the object of this 
being to render it suitable for its double function. For its 
softness fits it for the perception of savours, a sense which is 
more delicate in man than in any other animal, softness being 
most impressionable by touch, of which sense taste is but a 
variety. This same softness again, together with its breadth, 
adapts it for the articulation of letters and for speech. For these 
qualities, combined with its freedom from attachment, are 
those which suit it best for advancing and retiring in every 
direction. That this is so is plain, if we consider the case of those 
who are tongue-tied in however slight a degree. For their speech 
is indistinct and lisping; that is to say there are certain letters 
which they cannot pronounce. In being broad is comprised the 
possibility of becoming narrow; for in the great the small is 
included, but not the great in the small. 

What has been said explains why, among birds, those that are 
most capable of pronouncing letters are such as have the 



1857 



broadest tongues; and why the viviparous and sanguineous 
quadrupeds, where the tongue is hard and thick and not free in 
its motions, have a very limited vocal articulation. Some birds 
have a considerable variety of notes. These are the smaller 
kinds. But it is the birds with talons that have the broader 
tongues. All birds use their tongues to communicate with each 
other. But some do this in a greater degree than the rest; so that 
in some cases it even seems as though actual instruction were 
imparted from one to another by its agency. These, however, are 
matters which have already been discussed in the Researches 
concerning Animals. 

As to those oviparous and sanguineous animals that live not in 
the air but on the earth, their tongue in most cases is tied down 
and hard, and is therefore useless for vocal purposes; in the 
serpents, however, and in the lizards it is long and forked, so as 
to be suited for the perception of savours. So long indeed is this 
part in serpents, that though small while in the mouth it can be 
protruded to a great distance. In these animals it is forked and 
has a fine and hair-like extremity, because of their great liking 
for dainty food. For by this arrangement they derive a twofold 
pleasure from savours, their gustatory sensation being as it 
were doubled. 

Even some bloodless animals have an organ that serves for the 
perception of savours; and in sanguineous animals such an 
organ is invariably variably For even in such of these as would 
seem to an ordinary observer to have nothing of the kind, some 
of the fishes for example, there is a kind of shabby 
representative of a tongue, much like what exists in river 
crocodiles. In most of these cases the apparent absence of the 
part can be rationally explained on some ground or other. For in 
the first place the interior of the mouth in animals of this 
character is invariably spinous. Secondly, in water animals there 
is but short space of time for the perception of savours, and as 



1858 



the use of this sense is thus of short duration, shortened also is 
the separate part which subserves it. The reason for their food 
being so rapidly transmitted to the stomach is that they cannot 
possibly spend any time in sucking out the juices; for were they 
to attempt to do so, the water would make its way in during the 
process. Unless therefore one pulls their mouth very widely 
open, the projection of this part is quite invisible. The region 
exposed by thus opening the mouth is spinous; for it is formed 
by the close apposition of the gills, which are of a spinous 
character. 

In crocodiles the immobility of the lower jaw also contributes in 
some measure to stunt the development of the tongue. For the 
crocodile's tongue is adherent to the lower jaw. For its upper 
and lower jaws are, as it were, inverted, it being the upper jaw 
which in other animals is the immovable one. The tongue, 
however, on this animal is not attached to the upper jaw, 
because that would interfere with the ingestion of food, but 
adheres to the lower jaw, because this is, as it were, the upper 
one which has changed its place. Moreover, it is the crocodile's 
lot, though a land animal, to live the life of a fish, and this again 
necessarily involves an indistinct formation of the part in 
question. 

The roof of the mouth resembles flesh, even in many of the 
fishes; and in some of the river species, as for instance in the 
fishes known as Cyprini, is so very flesh-like and soft as to be 
taken by careless observers for a tongue. The tongue of fishes, 
however, though it exists as a separate part, is never formed 
with such distinctness as this, as has been already explained. 
Again, as the gustatory sensibility is intended to serve animals 
in the selection of food, it is not diffused equally over the whole 
surface of the tongue-like organ, but is placed chiefly in the tip; 
and for this reason it is the tip which is the only part of the 
tongue separated in fishes from the rest of the mouth. As all 



1859 



animals are sensible to the pleasure derivable from food, they 
all feel a desire for it. For the object of desire is the pleasant. The 
part, however, by which food produces the sensation is not 
precisely alike in all of them, but while in some it is free from 
attachments, in others, where it is not required for vocal pur, 
poses, it is adherent. In some again it is hard, in others soft or 
flesh-like. Thus even the Crustacea, the Carabi for instance and 
the like, and the Cephalopods, such as the Sepias and the 
Poulps, have some such part inside the mouth. As for the 
Insects, some of them have the part which serves as tongue 
inside the mouth, as is the case with ants, and as is also the 
case with many Testacea, while in others it is placed externally. 
In this latter case it resembles a sting, and is hollow and spongy, 
so as to serve at one and the same time for the tasting and for 
the sucking up of nutriment. This is plainly to be seen in flies 
and bees and all such animals, and likewise in some of the 
Testacea. In the Purpurae, for instance, so strong is this part 
that it enables them to bore holes through the hard covering of 
shell-fish, of the spiral snails, for example, that are used as bait 
to catch them. So also the gad-flies and cattle-flies can pierce 
through the skin of man, and some of them even through the 
skins of other animals. Such, then, in these animals is the 
nature of the tongue, which is thus as it were the counterpart of 
the elephant's nostril. For as in the elephant the nostril is used 
as a weapon, so in these animals the tongue serves as a sting. 

In all other animals the tongue agrees with description already 
given. 



I860 



Book III 



We have next to consider the teeth, and with these the mouth, 
that is the cavity which they enclose and form. The teeth have 
one invariable office, namely the reduction of food; but besides 
this general function they have other special ones, and these 
differ in different groups. Thus in some animals the teeth serve 
as weapons; but this with a distinction. For there are offensive 
weapons and there are defensive weapons; and while in some 
animals, as the wild Carnivora, the teeth answer both purposes, 
in many others, both wild and domesticated, they serve only for 
defence. In man the teeth are admirably constructed for their 
general office, the front ones being sharp, so as to cut the food 
into bits, and the hinder ones broad and flat, so as to grind it to 
a pulp; while between these and separating them are the dog- 
teeth, which, in accordance with the rule that the mean 
partakes of both extremes, share in the characters of those on 
either side, being broad in one part but sharp in another. Similar 
distinctions of shape are presented by the teeth of other 
animals, with the exception of those whose teeth are one and 
all of the sharp kind. In man, however, the number and the 
character even of these sharp teeth have been mainly 
determined by the requirements of speech. For the front teeth 
of man contribute in many ways to the formation of letter- 
sounds. 

In some animals, however, the teeth, as already said, serve 
merely for the reduction of food. When, besides this, they serve 
as offensive and defensive weapons, they may either be formed 
into tusks, as for instance is the case in swine, or may be sharp- 



1861 



pointed and interlock with those of the opposite jaw, in which 
case the animal is said to be saw-toothed. The explanation of 
this latter arrangement is as follows. The strength of such an 
animal is in its teeth, and these depend for their efficiency on 
their sharpness. In order, then, to prevent their getting blunted 
by mutual friction, such of them as serve for weapons fit into 
each other's interspaces, and are so kept in proper condition. No 
animal that has sharp interfitting teeth is at the same time 
furnished with tusks. For nature never makes anything 
superfluous or in vain. She gives, therefore, tusks to such 
animals as strike in fighting, and serrated teeth to such as bite. 
Sows, for instance, have no tusks, and accordingly sows bite 
instead of striking. 

A general principle must here be noted, which will be found 
applicable not only in this instance but in many others that will 
occur later on. Nature allots each weapon, offensive and 
defensive alike, to those animals alone that can use it; or, if not 
to them alone, to them in a more marked degree; and she allots 
it in its most perfect state to those that can use it best; and this 
whether it be a sting, or a spur, or horns, or tusks, or what it 
may of a like kind. 

Thus as males are stronger and more choleric than females, it is 
in males that such parts as those just mentioned are found, 
either exclusively, as in some species, or more fully developed, 
as in others. For though females are of course provided with 
such parts as are no less necessary to them than to males, the 
parts, for instance, which subserve nutrition, they have even 
these in an inferior degree, and the parts which answer no such 
necessary purpose they do not possess at all. This explains why 
stags have horns, while does have none; why the horns of cows 
are different from those of bulls, and, similarly, the horns of 
ewes from those of rams. It explains also why the females are 
often without spurs in species where the males are provided 



1862 



with them, and accounts for similar facts relating to all other 
such parts. 

All fishes have teeth of the serrated form, with the single 
exception of the fish known as the Scarus. In many of them 
there are teeth even on the tongue and on the roof of the 
mouth. The reason for this is that, living as they do in the water, 
they cannot but allow this fluid to pass into the mouth with the 
food. The fluid thus admitted they must necessarily discharge 
again without delay. For were they not to do so, but to retain it 
for a time while triturating the food, the water would run into 
their digestive cavities. Their teeth therefore are all sharp, being 
adapted only for cutting, and are numerous and set in many 
parts, that their abundance may serve in lieu of any grinding 
faculty, to mince the food into small bits. They are also curved, 
because these are almost the only weapons which fishes 
possess. 

In all these offices of the teeth the mouth also takes its part; but 
besides these functions it is subservient to respiration, in all 
such animals as breathe and are cooled by external agency. For 
nature, as already said, uses the parts which are common to all 
animals for many special purposes, and this of her own accord. 
Thus the mouth has one universal function in all animals alike, 
namely its alimentary office; but in some, besides this, the 
special duty of serving as a weapon is attached to it; in others 
that of ministering to speech; and again in many, though not in 
all, the office of respiration. All these functions are thrown by 
nature upon one single organ, the construction of which she 
varies so as to suit the variations of office. Therefore it is that in 
some animals the mouth is contracted, while in others it is of 
wide dimensions. The contracted form belongs to such animals 
as use the mouth merely for nutritive, respiratory, and vocal 
purposes; whereas in such as use it as a means of defence it has 
a wide gape. This is its invariable form in such animals as are 



1863 



saw-toothed. For seeing that their mode of warfare consists in 
biting, it is advantageous to them that their mouth shall have a 
wide opening; for the wider it opens, the greater will be the 
extent of the bite, and the more numerous will be the teeth 
called into play. 

What has just been said applies to fishes as well as to other 
animals; and thus in such of them as are carnivorous, and made 
for biting, the mouth has a wide gape; whereas in the rest it is 
small, being placed at the extremity of a tapering snout. For this 
form is suited for their purposes, while the other would be 
useless. 

In birds the mouth consists of what is called the beak, which in 
them is a substitute for lips and teeth. This beak presents 
variations in harmony with the functions and protective 
purposes which it serves. Thus in those birds that are called 
Crooked-clawed it is invariably hooked, inasmuch as these birds 
are carnivorous, and eat no kind of vegetable food whatsoever. 
For this form renders it serviceable to them in obtaining the 
mastery over their prey, and is better suited for deeds of 
violence than any other. Moreover, as their weapons of offence 
consist of this beak and of their claws, these latter also are more 
crooked in them than in the generality of birds. Similarly in 
each other kind of bird the beak is suited to the mode of life. 
Thus, in woodpeckers it is hard and strong, as also in crows and 
birds of crowlike habit, while in the smaller birds it is delicate, 
so as to be of use in collecting seeds and picking up minute 
animals. In such birds, again, as eat herbage, and such as live 
about marshes - those, for example, that swim and have 
webbed feet - the bill is broad, or adapted in some other way to 
the mode of life. For a broad bill enables a bird to dig into the 
ground with ease, just as, among quadrupeds, does the broad 
snout of the pig, an animal which, like the birds in question, 
lives on roots. Moreover, in these root-eating birds and in some 



1864 



others of like habits of life, the tips of the bill end in hard points, 
which gives them additional facility in dealing with herbaceous 
food. 

The several parts which are set on the head have now, pretty 
nearly all, been considered. In man, however, the part which lies 
between the head and the neck is called the face, this name, 
(prosopon) being, it would seem, derived from the function of 
the part. For as man is the only animal that stands erect, he is 
also the only one that looks directly in front (proso) and the 
only one whose voice is emitted in that direction. 



We have now to treat of horns; for these also, when present, are 
appendages of the head. They exist in none but viviparous 
animals; though in some ovipara certain parts are 
metaphorically spoken of as horns, in virtue of a certain 
resemblance. To none of such parts, however, does the proper 
office of a horn belong; for they are never used, as are the horns 
of vivipara, for purposes which require strength, whether it be 
in self-protection or in offensive strife. So also no polydactylous 
animal is furnished with horns. For horns are defensive 
weapons, and these polydactylous animals possess other 
means of security. For to some of them nature has given claws, 
to others teeth suited for combat, and to the rest some other 
adequate defensive appliance. There are horns, however, in 
most of the cloven-hoofed animals, and in some of those that 
have a solid hoof, serving them as an offensive weapon, and in 
some cases also as a defensive one. There are horns also in all 
animals that have not been provided by nature with some other 
means of security; such means, for instance, as speed, which 



1865 



has been given to horses; or great size, as in camels; for 
excessive bulk, such as has been given to these animals, and in 
a still greater measure to elephants, is sufficient in itself to 
protect an animal from being destroyed by others. Other 
animals again are protected by the possession of tusks; and 
among these are the swine, though they have a cloven hoof. 

All animals again, whose horns are but useless appendages, 
have been provided by nature with some additional means of 
security. Thus deer are endowed with speed; for the large size 
and great branching of their horns makes these a source of 
detriment rather than of profit to their possessors. Similarly 
endowed are the Bubalus and gazelle; for though these animals 
will stand up against some enemies and defend themselves 
with their horns, yet they run away from such as are fierce and 
pugnacious. The Bonasus again, whoe horns curve inwards 
towards each other, is provided with a means of protection in 
the discharge of its excrement; and of this it avails itself when 
frightened. There are some other animals besides the Bonasus 
that have a similar mode of defence. In no case, however, does 
nature ever give more than one adequate means of protection 
to one and the same animal. 

Most of the animals that have horns are cloven-hoofed; but the 
Indian ass, as they call it, is also reported to be horned, though 
its hoof is solid. 

Again as the body, so far as regards its organs of motion, 
consists of two distinct parts, the right and the left, so also and 
for like reasons the horns of animals are, in the great majority 
of cases, two in number. Still there are some that have but a 
single horn; the Oryx, for instance, and the so-called Indian ass; 
in the former of which the hoof is cloven, while in the latter it is 
solid. In such animals the horn is set in the centre of the head; 
for as the middle belongs equally to both extremes, this 



1866 



arrangement is the one that comes nearest to each side having 
its own horn. 

Again, it would appear consistent with reason that the single 
horn should go with the solid rather than with the cloven hoof. 
For hoof, whether solid or cloven, is of the same nature as horn; 
so that the two naturally undergo division simultaneously and 
in the same animals. Again, since the division of the cloven 
hoof depends on deficiency of material, it is but rationally 
consistent, that nature, when she gave an animal an excess of 
material for the hoofs, which thus became solid, should have 
taken away something from the upper parts and so made the 
animal to have but one horn. Rightly too did she act when she 
chose the head whereon to set the horns; and AEsop's Momus is 
beside the mark, when he finds fault with the bull for not 
having its horns upon its shoulders. For from this position, says 
he, they would have delivered their blow with the greatest force, 
whereas on the head they occupy the weakest part of the whole 
body. Momus was but dull-sighted in making this hostile 
criticism. For had the horns been set on the shoulders, or had 
they been set on any other part than they are, the encumbrance 
of their weight would have been increased, not only without 
any compensating gain whatsoever, but with the disadvantage 
of impeding many bodily operations. For the point whence the 
blows could be delivered with the greatest force was not the 
only matter to be considered, but the point also whence they 
could be delivered with the widest range. But as the bull has no 
hands and cannot possibly have its horns on its feet or on its 
knees, where they would prevent flexion, there remains no 
other site for them but the head; and this therefore they 
necessarily occupy. In this position, moreover, they are much 
less in the way of the movements of the body than they would 
be elsewhere. 



1867 



Deer are the only animals in which the horns are solid 
throughout, and are also the only animals that cast them. This 
casting is not simply advantageous to the deer from the 
increased lightness which it produces, but, seeing how heavy 
the horns are, is a matter of actual necessity. 

In all other animals the horns are hollow for a certain distance, 
and the end alone is solid, this being the part of use in a blow. 
At the same time, to prevent even the hollow part from being 
weak, the horn, though it grows out of the skin, has a solid piece 
from the bones fitted into its cavity. For this arrangement is not 
only that which makes the horns of the greatest service in 
fighting, but that which causes them to be as little of an 
impediment as possible in the other actions of life. 

Such then are the reasons for which horns exist; and such the 
reasons why they are present in some animals, absent from 
others. 

Let us now consider the character of the material nature whose 
necessary results have been made available by rational nature 
for a final cause. 

In the first place, then, the larger the bulk of animals, the 
greater is the proportion of corporeal and earthy matter which 
they contain. Thus no very small animal is known to have 
horns, the smallest horned animal that we are acquainted with 
being the gazelle. But in all our speculations concerning nature, 
what we have to consider is the general rule; for that is natural 
which applies either universally or generally. And thus when we 
say that the largest animals have most earthy matter, we say so 
because such is the general rule. Now this earthy matter is used 
in the animal body to form bone. But in the larger animals there 
is an excess of it, and this excess is turned by nature to useful 
account, being converted into weapons of defence. Part of it 
necessarily flows to the upper portion of the body, and this is 



1868 



allotted by her in some cases to the formation of tusks and 
teeth, in others to the formation of horns. Thus it is that no 
animal that has horns has also front teeth in both jaws, those in 
the upper jaw being deficient. For nature by subtracting from 
the teeth adds to the horns; the nutriment which in most 
animals goes to the former being here spent on the 
augmentation of the latter. Does, it is true, have no horns and 
yet are equally deficient with the males as regards the teeth. 
The reason, however, for this is that they, as much as the males, 
are naturally horn-bearing animals; but they have been stripped 
of their horns, because these would not only be useless to them 
but actually baneful; whereas the greater strength of the males 
causes these organs, though equally useless, to be less of an 
impediment. In other animals, where this material is not 
secreted from the body in the shape of horns, it is used to 
increase the size of the teeth; in some cases of all the teeth, in 
others merely of the tusks, which thus become so long as to 
resemble horns projecting from the jaws. 

So much, then, of the parts which appertain to the head. 



Below the head lies the neck, in such animals as have one. This 
is the case with those only that have the parts to which a neck 
is subservient. These parts are the larynx and what is called the 
oesophagus. Of these the former, or larynx, exists for the sake of 
respiration, being the instrument by which such animals as 
breathe inhale and discharge the air. Therefore it is that, when 
there is no lung, there is also no neck. Of this condition the 
Fishes are an example. The other part, or oesophagus, is the 
channel through which food is conveyed to the stomach; so that 



1869 



all animals that are without a neck are also without a distinct 
oesophagus; Such a part is in fact not required of necessity for 
nutritive purposes; for it has no action whatsoever on the food. 
Indeed there is nothing to prevent the stomach from being 
placed directly after the mouth. This, however, is quite 
impossible in the case of the lung. For there must be some sort 
of tube common to the two divisions of the lung, by which - it 
being bipartite - the breath may be apportioned to their 
respective bronchi, and thence pass into the air-pipes; and such 
an arrangement will be the best for giving perfection to 
inspiration and expiration. The organ then concerned in 
respiration must of necessity be of some length; and this, again, 
necessitates there being an oesophagus to unite mouth and 
stomach. This oesophagus is of a flesh-like character, and yet 
admits of extension like a sinew. This latter property is given to 
it, that it may stretch when food is introduced; while the flesh- 
like character is intended to make it soft and yielding, and to 
prevent it from being rasped by particles as they pass 
downwards, and so suffering damage. On the other hand, the 
windpipe and the so-called larynx are constructed out of a 
cartilaginous substance. For they have to serve not only for 
respiration, but also for vocal purposes; and an instrument that 
is to produce sounds must necessarily be not only smooth but 
firm. The windpipe lies in front of the oesophagus, although this 
position causes it to be some hindrance to the latter in the act 
of deglutition. For if a morsel of food, fluid or solid, slips into it 
by accident, choking and much distress and violent fits of 
coughing ensue. This must be a matter of astonishment to any 
of those who assert that it is by the windpipe that an animal 
imbibes fluid. For the consequences just mentioned occur 
invariably, whenever a particle of food slips in, and are quite 
obvious. Indeed on many grounds it is ridiculous to say that this 
is the channel through which animals imbibe fluid. For there is 
no passage leading from the lung to the stomach, such as the 



1870 



oesophagus which we see leading thither from the mouth. 
Moreover, when any cause produces sickness and vomiting, it is 
plain enough when the fluid is discharged. It is manifest also 
that fluid, when swallowed, does not pass directly into the 
bladder and collect there, but goes first into the stomach. For, 
when red wine is taken, the dejections of the stomach are seen 
to be coloured by its dregs; and such discoloration has been 
even seen on many occasions inside the stomach itself, in cases 
where there have been wounds opening into that organ. 
However, it is perhaps silly to be minutely particular in dealing 
with silly statements such as this. 

The windpipe then, owing to its position in front of the 
oesophagus, is exposed, as we have said, to annoyance from the 
food. To obviate this, however, nature has contrived the 
epiglottis. This part is not found in all sanguineous animals, but 
only in such of them as have a lung; nor in all of these, but only 
in such as at the same time have their skin covered with hairs, 
and not either with scaly plates or with feathers. In such scaly 
and feathered animals there is no epiglottis, but its office is 
supplied by the larynx, which closes and opens, just as in the 
other case the epiglottis falls down and rises up; rising up 
during the ingress or egress of breath, and falling down during 
the ingestion of food, so as to prevent any particle from slipping 
into the windpipe. Should there be the slightest want of 
accuracy in this movement, or should an inspiration be made 
during the ingestion of food, choking and coughing ensue, as 
already has been noticed. So admirably contrived, however, is 
the movement both of the epiglottis and of the tongue, that, 
while the food is being ground to a pulp in the mouth, the 
tongue very rarely gets caught between the teeth; and, while the 
food is passing over the epiglottis seldom does a particle of it 
slip into the windpipe. 



1871 



The animals which have been mentioned as having no 
epiglottis owe this deficiency to the dryness of their flesh and to 
the hardness of their skin. For an epiglottis made of such 
materials would not admit of easy motion. It would, indeed, 
take a longer time to shut down an epiglottis made of the 
peculiar flesh of these animals, and shaped like that of those 
with hairy skins, than to bring the edges of the windpipe itself 
into contact with each other. 

Thus much then as to the reason why some animals have an 
epiglottis while others have none, and thus much also as to its 
use. It is a contrivance of nature to remedy the vicious position 
of the windpipe in front of the oesophagus. That position is the 
result of necessity. For it is in the front and centre of the body 
that the heart is situated, in which we say is the principle of life 
and the source of all motion and sensation. (For sensation and 
motion are exercised in the direction which we term forwards, 
and it is on this very relation that the distinction of before and 
behind is founded.) But where the heart is, there and 
surrounding it is the lung. Now inspiration, which occurs for the 
sake of the lung and for the sake of the principle which has its 
seat in the heart, is effected through the windpipe. Since then 
the heart must of necessity lie in the very front place of all, it 
follows that the larynx also and the windpipe must of necessity 
lie in front of the oesophagus. For they lead to the lung and 
heart, whereas the oesophagus leads to the stomach. And it is a 
universal law that, as regards above and below, front and back, 
right and left, the nobler and more honourable part invariably is 
placed uppermost, in front, and on the right, rather than in the 
opposite positions, unless some more important object stands 
in the way. 



1872 



We have now dealt with the neck, the oesophagus, and the 
windpipe, and have next to treat of the viscera. These are 
peculiar to sanguineous animals, some of which have all of 
them, others only a part, while no bloodless animals have any 
at all. Democritus then seems to have been mistaken in the 
notion he formed of the viscera, if, that is to say, he fancied that 
the reason why none were discoverable in bloodless animals 
was that these animals were too small to allow them to be seen. 
For, in sanguineous animals, both heart and liver are visible 
enough when the body is only just formed, and while it is still 
extremely small. For these parts are to be seen in the egg 
sometimes as early as the third day, being then no bigger than a 
point; and are visible also in aborted embryos, while still 
excessively minute. Moreover, as the external organs are not 
precisely alike in all animals, but each creature is provided with 
such as are suited to its special mode of life and motion, so is it 
with the internal parts, these also differing in different animals. 
Viscera, then, are peculiar to sanguineous animals; and 
therefore are each and all formed from sanguineous material, as 
is plainly to be seen in the new-born young of these animals. 
For in such the viscera are more sanguineous, and of greater 
bulk in proportion to the body, than at any later period of life, it 
being in the earliest stage of formation that the nature of the 
material and its abundance are most conspicuous. There is a 
heart, then, in all sanguineous animals, and the reason for this 
has already been given. For that sanguineous animals must 
necessarily have blood is self-evident. And, as the blood is fluid, 
it is also a matter of necessity that there shall be a receptacle 
for it; and it is apparently to meet this requirement that nature 
has devised the blood-vessels. These, again, must necessarily 
have one primary source. For it is preferable that there shall be 
one such, when possible, rather than several. This primary 
source of the vessels is the heart. For the vessels manifestly 



1873 



issue from it and do not go through it. Moreover, being as it is 
homogeneous, it has the character of a blood-vessel. Again its 
position is that of a primary or dominating part. For nature, 
when no other more important purpose stands in her way, 
places the more honourable part in the more honourable 
position; and the heart lies about the centre of the body, but 
rather in its upper than its lower half, and also more in front 
than behind. This is most evident in the case of man, but even 
in other animals there is a tendency in the heart to assume a 
similar position, in the centre of the necessary part of the body, 
that is to say of the part which terminates in the vent for 
excrement. For the limbs vary in position in different animals, 
and are not to be counted with the parts which are necessary 
for life. For life can be maintained even when they are removed; 
while it is self-evident that the addition of them to an animal is 
not destructive of it. 

There are some who say that the vessels commence in the 
head. In this they are clearly mistaken. For in the first place, 
according to their representation, there would be many sources 
for the vessels, and these scattered; and secondly, these sources 
would be in a region that is manifestly cold, as is shown by its 
intolerance of chill, whereas the region of the heart is as 
manifestly hot. Again, as already said, the vessels continue their 
course through the other viscera, but no vessel spreads through 
the heart. From this it is quite evident that the heart is a part of 
the vessels and their origin; and for this it is well suited by its 
structure. For its central part consists of a dense and hollow 
substance, and is moreover full of blood, as though the vessels 
took thence their origin. It is hollow to serve for the reception of 
the blood, while its wall is dense, that it may serve to protect 
the source of heat. For here, and here alone in all the viscera 
and indeed in all the body, there is blood without blood-vessels, 
the blood elsewhere being always contained within vessels. Nor 
is this but consistent with reason. For the blood is conveyed into 



1874 



the vessels from the heart, but none passes into the heart from 
without. For in itself it constitutes the origin and fountain, or 
primary receptacle, of the blood. It is however, from dissections 
and from observations on the process of development that the 
truth of these statements receives its clearest demonstration. 
For the heart is the first of all the parts to be formed; and no 
sooner is it formed than it contains blood. Moreover, the 
motions of pain and pleasure, and generally of all sensation, 
plainly have their source in the heart, and find in it their 
ultimate termination. This, indeed, reason would lead us to 
expect. For the source must, when, ever possible, be one; and, of 
all places, the best suited for a source is the centre. For the 
centre is one, and is equally or almost equally within reach of 
every part. Again, as neither the blood itself, nor yet any part 
which is bloodless, is endowed with sensation, it is plain that 
that part which first has blood, and which holds it as it were in 
a receptacle, must be the primary source of sensation. And that 
this part is the heart is not only a rational inference, but also 
evident to the senses. For no sooner is the embryo formed, than 
its heart is seen in motion as though it were a living creature, 
and this before any of the other parts, it being, as thus shown, 
the starting-point of their nature in all animals that have blood. 
A further evidence of the truth of what has been stated is the 
fact that no sanguineous animal is without a heart. For the 
primary source of blood must of necessity be present in them 
all. It is true that sanguineous animals not only have a heart but 
also invariably have a liver. But no one could ever deem the liver 
to be the primary organ either of the whole body or of the blood. 
For the position in which it is placed is far from being that of a 
primary or dominating part; and, moreover, in the most 
perfectly finished animals there is another part, the spleen, 
which as it were counterbalances it. Still further, the liver 
contains no spacious receptacle in its substance, as does the 
heart; but its blood is in a vessel as in all the other viscera. The 



1875 



vessel, moreover, extends through it, and no vessel whatsoever 
originates in it; for it is from the heart that all the vessels take 
their rise. Since then one or other of these two parts must be 
the central source, and since it is not the liver which is such, it 
follows of necessity that it is the heart which is the source of 
the blood, as also the primary organ in other respects. For the 
definitive characteristic of an animal is the possession of 
sensation; and the first sensory part is that which first has 
blood; that is to say is the heart, which is the source of blood 
and the first of the parts to contain it. 

The apex of the heart is pointed and more solid than the rest of 
the organ. It lies against the breast, and entirely in the anterior 
part of the body, in order to prevent that region from getting 
chilled. For in all animals there is comparatively little flesh over 
the breast, whereas there is a more abundant covering of that 
substance on the posterior surface, so that the heat has in the 
back a sufficient amount of protection. In all animals but man 
the heart is placed in the centre of the pectoral region; but in 
man it inclines a little towards the left, so that it may 
counterbalance the chilliness of that side. For the left side is 
colder in man, as compared with the right, than in any other 
animal. It has been stated in an earlier treatise that even in 
fishes the heart holds the same position as in other animals; 
and the reason has been given why it appears not to do so. The 
apex of the heart, it is true, is in them turned towards the head, 
but this in fishes is the front aspect, for it is the direction in 
which their motion occurs. 

The heart again is abundantly supplied with sinews, as might 
reasonably be expected. For the motions of the body commence 
from the heart, and are brought about by traction and 
relaxation. The heart therefore, which, as already said,' as it 
were a living creature inside its possessor, requires some such 
subservient and strengthening parts. 



1876 



In no animals does the heart contain a bone, certainly in none 
of those that we have ourselves inspected, with the exception of 
the horse and a certain kind of ox. In these exceptional cases 
the heart, owing to its large bulk, is provided with a bone as a 
support; just as the bones serve as supports for the body 
generally. 

In animals of great size the heart has three cavities; in smaller 
animals it has two; and in all has at least one, for, as already 
stated, there must be some place in the heart to serve as a 
receptacle for the first blood; which, as has been mentioned 
more than once, is formed in this organ. But inasmuch as the 
main blood-vessels are two in number, namely the so-called 
great vessel and the aorta, each of which is the origin of other 
vessels; inasmuch, moreover, as these two vessels present 
differences, hereafter to be discussed, when compared with 
each other, it is of advantage that they also shall themselves 
have distinct origins. This advantage will be obtained if each 
side have its own blood, and the blood of one side be kept 
separate from that of the other. For this reason the heart, 
whenever it is possible, has two receptacles. And this possibility 
exists in the case of large animals, for in them the heart, as the 
body generally, is of large size. Again it is still better that there 
shall be three cavities, so that the middle and odd one may 
serve as a centre common to both sides. But this requires the 
heart to be of greater magnitude, so that it is only in the largest 
hearts that there are three cavities. 

Of these three cavities it is the right that has the most abundant 
and the hottest blood, and this explains why the limbs also on 
the right side of the body are warmer than those on the left. The 
left cavity has the least blood of all, and the coldest; while in the 
middle cavity the blood, as regards quantity and heat, is 
intermediate to the other two, being however of purer quality 
than either. For it behoves the supreme part to be as tranquil as 



1877 



possible, and this tranquillity can be ensured by the blood being 
pure, and of moderate amount and warmth. 

In the heart of animals there is also a kind of joint-like division, 
something like the sutures of the skull. This is not, however, 
attributable to the heart being formed by the union of several 
parts into a compound whole, but is rather, as already said, the 
result of a joint-like division. These jointings are most distinct 
in animals of keen sensibility, and less so in those that are of 
duller feeling, in swine for instance. Different hearts differ also 
from each other in their sizes, and in their degrees of firmness; 
and these differences somehow extend their influence to the 
temperaments of the animals. For in animals of low sensibility 
the heart is hard and dense in texture, while it is softer in such 
as are endowed with keener feeling. So also when the heart is of 
large size the animal is timorous, while it is more courageous if 
the organ be smaller and of moderate bulk. For in the former 
the bodily affection which results from terror already pre-exists; 
for the bulk of the heart is out of all proportion to the animal's 
heat, which being small is reduced to insignificance in the large 
space, and thus the blood is made colder than it would 
otherwise be. 

The heart is of large size in the hare, the deer, the mouse, the 
hyena, the ass, the leopard, the marten, and in pretty nearly all 
other animals that either are manifestly timorous, or betray 
their cowardice by their spitefulness. 

What has been said of the heart as a whole is no less true of its 
cavities and of the blood-vessels; these also if of large size being 
cold. For just as a fire of equal size gives less heat in a large 
room than in a small one, so also does the heat in a large cavity 
or a large blood-vessel, that is in a large receptacle, have less 
effect than in a small one. Moreover, all hot bodies are cooled by 
motions external to themselves, and the more spacious the 



1878 



cavities and vessels are, the greater the amount of spirit they 
contain, and the more potent its action. Thus it is that no 
animal that has large cavities in its heart, or large blood-vessels, 
is ever fat, the vessels being indistinct and the cavities small in 
all or most fat animals. 

The heart again is the only one of the viscera, and indeed the 
only part of the body, that is unable to tolerate any serious 
affection. This is but what might reasonably be expected. For, if 
the primary or dominant part be diseased, there is nothing from 
which the other parts which depend upon it can derive succour. 
A proof that the heart is thus unable to tolerate any morbid 
affection is furnished by the fact that in no sacrificial victim has 
it ever been seen to be affected with those diseases that are 
observable in the other viscera. For the kidneys are frequently 
found to be full of stones, and growths, and small abscesses, as 
also are the liver, the lung, and more than all the spleen. There 
are also many other morbid conditions which are seen to occur 
in these parts, those which are least liable to such being the 
portion of the lung which is close to the windpipe, and the 
portion of the liver which lies about the junction with the great 
blood-vessel. This again admits of a rational explanation. For it 
is in these parts that the lung and liver are most closely in 
communion with the heart. On the other hand, when animals 
die not by sacrifice but from disease, and from affections such 
as are mentioned above, they are found on dissection to have 
morbid affections of the heart. 

Thus much of the heart, its nature, and the end and cause of its 
existence in such animals as have it. 



1879 



In due sequence we have next to discuss the blood-vessels, that 
is to say the great vessel and the aorta. For it is into these two 
that the blood first passes when it quits the heart; and all the 
other vessels are but offshoots from them. Now that these 
vessels exist on account of the blood has already been stated. 
For every fluid requires a receptacle, and in the case of the blood 
the vessels are that receptacle. Let us now explain why these 
vessels are two, and why they spring from one single source, 
and extend throughout the whole body. 

The reason, then, why these two vessels coalesce into one 
centre, and spring from one source, is that the sensory soul is in 
all animals actually one; and this one-ness of the sensory soul 
determines a corresponding one-ness of the part in which it 
primarily abides. In sanguineous animals this one-ness is not 
only actual but potential, whereas in some bloodless animals it 
is only actual. Where, however, the sensory soul is lodged, there 
also and in the selfsame place must necessarily be the source of 
heat; and, again, where this is there also must be the source of 
the blood, seeing that it thence derives its warmth and fluidity. 
Thus, then, in the oneness of the part in which is lodged the 
prime source of sensation and of heat is involved the one-ness 
of the source in which the blood originates; and this, again, 
explains why the blood-vessels have one common starting- 
point. 

The vessels, again, are two, because the body of every 
sanguineous animal that is capable of locomotion is bilateral; 
for in all such animals there is a distinguishable before and 
behind, a right and left, an above and below. Now as the front is 
more honourable and of higher supremacy than the hinder 
aspect, so also and in like degree is the great vessel superior to 
the aorta. For the great vessel is placed in front, while the aorta 



1880 



is behind; the former again is plainly visible in all sanguineous 
animals, while the latter is in some indistinct and in some not 
discernible at all. 

Lastly, the reason for the vessels being distributed throughout 
the entire body is that in them, or in parts analogous to them, is 
contained the blood, or the fluid which in bloodless animals 
takes the place of blood, and that the blood or analogous fluid is 
the material from which the whole body is made. Now as to the 
manner in which animals are nourished, and as to the source 
from which they obtain nutriment and as to the way in which 
they absorb this from the stomach, these are matters which 
may be more suitably considered and explained in the treatise 
on Generation. But inasmuch as the parts are, as already said, 
formed out of the blood, it is but rational that the flow of the 
blood should extend, as it does, throughout the whole of the 
body. For since each part is formed of blood, each must have 
blood about and in its substance. 

To give an illustration of this. The water-courses in gardens are 
so constructed as to distribute water from one single source or 
fount into numerous channels, which divide and subdivide so 
as to convey it to all parts; and, again, in house-building stones 
are thrown down along the whole ground-plan of the 
foundation walls; because the garden-plants in the one case 
grow at the expense of the water, and the foundation walls in 
the other are built out of the stones. Now just after the same 
fashion has nature laid down channels for the conveyance of 
the blood throughout the whole body, because this blood is the 
material out of which the whole fabric is made. This becomes 
very evident in bodies that have undergone great emaciation. 
For in such there is nothing to be seen but the blood-vessels; 
just as when fig-leaves or vine-leaves or the like have dried up, 
there is nothing left of them but their vessels. The explanation 
of this is that the blood, or fluid which takes its place, is 



1881 



potentially body and flesh, or substance analogous to flesh. Now 
just as in irrigation the largest dykes are permanent, while the 
smallest are soon filled up with mud and disappear, again to 
become visible when the deposit of mud ceases; so also do the 
largest blood-vessels remain permanently open, while the 
smallest are converted actually into flesh, though potentially 
they are no whit less vessels than before. This too explains why, 
so long as the flesh of an animal is in its integrity, blood will 
flow from any part of it whatsoever that is cut, though no 
vessel, however small, be visible in it. Yet there can be no blood, 
unless there be a blood-vessel. The vessels then are there, but 
are invisible owing to their being clogged up, just as the dykes 
for irrigation are invisible until they have been cleared of mud. 

As the blood-vessels advance, they become gradually smaller 
and smaller, until at last their tubes are too fine to admit the 
blood. This fluid can therefore no longer find its way through 
them, though they still give passage to the humour which we 
call sweat; and especially so when the body is heated, and the 
mouths of the small vessels are dilated. Instances, indeed, are 
not unknown of persons who in consequence of a cachectic 
state have secreted sweat that resembled blood, their body 
having become loose and flabby, and their blood watery, owing 
to the heat in the small vessels having been too scanty for its 
concoction. For, as was before said, every compound of earth 
and water - and both nutriment and blood are such - becomes 
thicker from concoction. The inability of the heat to effect 
concoction may be due either to its being absolutely small in 
amount, or to its being small in proportion to the quantity of 
food, when this has been taken excess. This excess again may 
be of two kinds, either quantitative or qualitative; for all 
substances are not equally amenable to concoction. 

The widest passages in the body are of all parts the most liable 
to haemorrhage; so that bleeding occurs not infrequently from 



1882 



the nostrils, the gums, and the fundament, occasionally also 
from the mouth. Such haemorrhages are of a passive kind, and 
not violent as are those from the windpipe. 

The great vessel and the aorta, which above lie somewhat apart, 
lower down exchange positions, and by so doing give 
compactness to the body. For when they reach the point where 
the legs diverge, they each split into two, and the great vessel 
passes from the front to the rear, and the aorta from the rear to 
the front. By this they contribute to the unity of the whole 
fabric. For as in plaited work the parts hold more firmly together 
because of the interweaving, so also by the interchange of 
position between the blood-vessels are the anterior and 
posterior parts of the body more closely knit together. A similar 
exchange of position occurs also in the upper part of the body, 
between the vessels that have issued from the heart. The details 
however of the mutual relations of the different vessels must be 
looked for in the treatises on Anatomy and the Researches 
concerning Animals. 

So much, then, as concerns the heart and the blood-vessels. We 
must now pass on to the other viscera and apply the same 
method of inquiry to them. 



The lung, then, is an organ found in all the animals of a certain 
class, because they live on land. For there must of necessity be 
some means or other of tempering the heat of the body; and in 
sanguineous animals, as they are of an especially hot nature, 
the cooling agency must be external, whereas in the bloodless 
kinds the innate spirit is sufficient of itself for the purpose. The 
external cooling agent must be either air or water. In fishes the 



1883 



agent is water. Fishes therefore never have a lung, but have gills 
in its place, as was stated in the treatise on Respiration. But 
animals that breathe are cooled by air. These therefore are all 
provided with a lung. 

All land animals breathe, and even some water animals, such as 
the whale, the dolphin, and all the spouting Cetacea. For many 
animals lie half-way between terrestrial and aquatic; some that 
are terrestrial and that inspire air being nevertheless of such a 
bodily constitution that they abide for the most time in the 
water; and some that are aquatic partaking so largely of the 
land character, that respiration constitutes for them the man 
condition of life. 

The organ of respiration is the lung. This derives its motion 
from the heart; but it is its own large size and spongy texture 
that affords amplitude of space for entrance of the breath. For 
when the lung rises up the breath streams in, and is again 
expelled when the lung collapses. It has been said that the lung 
exists as a provision to meet the jumping of the heart. But this 
is out of the question. For man is practically the only animal 
whose heart presents this phenomenon of jumping, inasmuch 
as he alone is influenced by hope and anticipation of the future. 
Moreover, in most animals the lung is separated from the heart 
by a considerable interval and lies above it, so that it can 
contribute nothing to mitigate any jumping. 

The lung differs much in different animals. For in some it is of 
large size and contains blood; while in others it is smaller and 
of spongy texture. In the vivipara it is large and rich in blood, 
because of their natural heat; while in the ovipara it is small 
and dry but capable of expanding to a vast extent when 
inflated. Among terrestrial animals, the oviparous quadrupeds, 
such as lizards, tortoises, and the like, have this kind of lung; 
and, among inhabitants of the air, the animals known as birds. 



1884 



For in all these the lung is spongy, and like foam. For it is 
membranous and collapses from a large bulk to a small one, as 
does foam when it runs together. In this too lies the explanation 
of the fact that these animals are little liable to thirst and drink 
but sparingly, and that they are able to remain for a 
considerable time under water. For, inasmuch as they have but 
little heat, the very motion of the lung, airlike and void, suffices 
by itself to cool them for a considerable period. 

These animals, speaking generally, are also distinguished from 
others by their smaller bulk. For heat promotes growth, and 
abundance of blood is a sure indication of heat. Heat, again, 
tends to make the body erect; and thus it is that man is the 
most erect of animals, and the vivipara more erect than other 
quadrupeds. For no viviparous animal, be it apodous or be it 
possessed of feet, is so given to creep into holes as are the 
ovipara. 

The lung, then, exists for respiration; and this is its universal 
office; but in one order of animals it is bloodless and has the 
structure described above, to suit the special requirements 
There is, however, no one term to denote all animals that have a 
lung; no designation, that is, like the term Bird, applicable to the 
whole of a certain class. Yet the possession of a lung is a part of 
their essence, just as much as the presence of certain characters 
constitutes the essence of a bird. 



Of the viscera some appear to be single, as the heart and lung; 
others to be double, as the kidneys; while of a third kind it is 
doubtful in which class they should be reckoned. For the liver 
and the spleen would seem to lie half-way between the single 



1885 



and the double organs. For they may be regarded either as 
constituting each a single organ, or as a pair of organs 
resembling each other in character. 

In reality, however, all the organs are double. The reason for this 
is that the body itself is double, consisting of two halves, which 
are however combined together under one supreme centre. For 
there is an upper and a lower half, a front and a rear, a right side 
and a left. 

This explains why it is that even the brain and the several 
organs of sense tend in all animals to consist of two parts; and 
the same explanation applies to the heart with its cavities. The 
lung again in Ovipara is divided to such an extent that these 
animals look as though they had actually two lungs. As to the 
kidneys, no one can overlook their double character. But when 
we come to the liver and the spleen, any one might fairly be in 
doubt. The reason of this is, that, in animals that necessarily 
have a spleen, this organ is such that it might be taken for a 
kind of bastard liver; while in those in which a spleen is not an 
actual necessity but is merely present, as it were, by way of 
token, in an extremely minute form, the liver plainly consists of 
two parts; of which the larger tends to lie on the right side and 
the smaller on the left. Not but what there are some even of the 
Ovipara in which this condition is comparatively indistinctly 
marked; while, on the other hand, there are some Vivipara in 
which the liver is manifestly divided into two parts. Examples of 
such division are furnished by the hares of certain regions, 
which have the appearance of having two livers, and by the 
cartilaginous and some other fishes. 

It is the position of the liver on the right side of the body that is 
the main cause for the formation of the spleen; the existence of 
which thus becomes to a certain extent a matter of necessity in 
all animals, though not of very stringent necessity. 



1886 



The reason, then, why the viscera are bilateral is, as we have 
said, that there are two sides to the body, a right and a left. For 
each of these sides aims at similarity with the other, and so 
likewise do their several viscera; and as the sides, though dual, 
are knit together into unity, so also do the viscera tend to be 
bilateral and yet one by unity of constitution. 

Those viscera which lie below the diaphragm exist one and all 
on account of the blood-vessels; serving as a bond, by which 
these vessels, while floating freely, are yet held in connexion 
with the body. For the vessels give off branches which run to the 
body through the outstretched structures, like so many 
anchorlines thrown out from a ship. The great vessel sends such 
branches to the liver and the spleen; and these viscera - the 
liver and spleen on either side with the kidneys behind - attach 
the great vessel to the body with the firmness of nails. The aorta 
sends similar branches to each kidney, but none to the liver or 
spleen. 

These viscera, then, contribute in this manner to the 
compactness of the animal body. The liver and spleen assist, 
moreover, in the concoction of the food; for both are of a hot 
character, owing to the blood which they contain. The kidneys, 
on the other hand, take part in the separation of the excretion 
which flows into the bladder. 

The heart then and the liver are essential constituents of every 
animal; the liver that it may effect concoction, the heart that it 
may lodge the central source of heat. For some part or other 
there must be which, like a hearth, shall hold the kindling fire; 
and this part must be well protected, seeing that it is, as it were, 
the citadel of the body. 

All sanguineous animals, then, need these two parts; and this 
explains why these two viscera, and these two alone, are 
invariably found in them all. In such of them, however, as 



1887 



breathe, there is also as invariably a third, namely the lung. The 
spleen, on the other hand, is not invariably present; and, in 
those animals that have it, is only present of necessity in the 
same sense as the excretions of the belly and of the bladder are 
necessary, in the sense, that is, of being an inevitable 
concomitant. Therefore it is that in some animals the spleen is 
but scantily developed as regards size. This, for instance, is the 
case in such feathered animals as have a hot stomach. Such are 
the pigeon, the hawk, and the kite. It is the case also in 
oviparous quadrupeds, where the spleen is excessively minute, 
and in many of the scaly fishes. These same animals are also 
without a bladder, because the loose texture of their flesh 
allows the residual fluid to pass through and to be applied to 
the formation of feathers and scales. For the spleen attracts the 
residual humours from the stomach, and owing to its bloodlike 
character is enabled to assist in their concoction. Should, 
however, this residual fluid be too abundant, or the heat of the 
spleen be too scanty, the body becomes sickly from over- 
repletion with nutriment. Often, too, when the spleen is 
affected by disease, the belly becomes hard owing to the reflux 
into it of the fluid; just as happens to those who form too much 
urine, for they also are liable to a similar diversion of the fluids 
into the belly. But in those animals that have but little 
superfluous fluid to excrete, such as birds and fishes, the spleen 
is never large, and in some exists no more than by way of token. 
So also in the oviparous quadrupeds it is small, compact, and 
like a kidney. For their lung is spongy, and they drink but little, 
and such superfluous fluid as they have is applied to the growth 
of the body and the formation of scaly plates, just as in birds it 
is applied to the formation of feathers. 

On the other hand, in such animals as have a bladder, and 
whose lung contains blood, the spleen is watery, both for the 
reason already mentioned, and also because the left side of the 
body is more watery and colder than the right. For each of two 



1888 



contraries has been so placed as to go together with that which 
is akin to it in another pair of contraries. Thus right and left, hot 
and cold, are pairs of contraries; and right is conjoined with hot, 
after the manner described, and left with cold. 

The kidneys when they are present exist not of actual necessity, 
but as matters of greater finish and perfection. For by their 
special character they are suited to serve in the excretion of the 
fluid which collects in the bladder. In animals therefore where 
this fluid is very abundantly formed, their presence enables the 
bladder to perform its proper office with greater perfection. 

Since then both kidneys and bladder exist in animals for one 
and the same function, we must next treat of the bladder, 
though in so doing we disregard the due order of succession in 
which the parts should be enumerated. For not a word has yet 
been said of the midriff, which is one of the parts that environ 
the viscera and therefore has to be considered with them. 



8 

It is not every animal that has a bladder; those only being 
apparently intended by nature to have one, whose lung contains 
blood. To such it was but reasonable that she should give this 
part. For the superabundance in their lung of its natural 
constituents causes them to be the thirstiest of animals, and 
makes them require a more than ordinary quantity not merely 
of solid but also of liquid nutriment. This increased 
consumption necessarily entails the production of an increased 
amount of residue; which thus becomes too abundant to be 
concocted by the stomach and excreted with its own residual 
matter. The residual fluid must therefore of necessity have a 
receptacle of its own; and thus it comes to pass that all animals 



1889 



whose lung contains blood are provided with a bladder. Those 
animals, on the other hand, that are without a lung of this 
character, and that either drink but sparingly owing to their 
lung being of a spongy texture, or never imbibe fluid at all for 
drinking's sake but only as nutriment, insects for instance and 
fishes, and that are moreover clad with feathers or scales or 
scaly plates - all these animals, owing to the small amount of 
fluid which they imbibe, and owing also to such residue as there 
may be being converted into feathers and the like, are invariably 
without a bladder. The Tortoises, which are comprised among 
animals with scaly plates, form the only exception; and this is 
merely due to the imperfect development of their natural 
conformation; the explanation of the matter being that in the 
sea-tortoises the lung is flesh-like and contains blood, 
resembling the lung of the ox, and that in the land-tortoises it is 
of disproportionately large size. Moreover, inasmuch as the 
covering which invests them is dense and shell-like, so that the 
moisture cannot exhale through the porous flesh, as it does in 
birds and in snakes and other animals with scaly plates, such 
an amount of secretion is formed that some special part is 
required to receive and hold it. This then is the reason why 
these animals, alone of their kind, have a bladder, the sea- 
tortoise a large one, the land-tortoises an extremely small one. 



What has been said of the bladder is equally true of the kidneys. 
For these also are wanting in all animals that are clad with 
feathers or with scales or with scale-like plates; the sea and 
land tortoises forming the only exception. In some of the birds, 
however, there are flattened kidney like bodies, as though the 



1890 



flesh allotted to the formation of the kidneys, unable to find one 
single place of sufficient size, had been scattered over several. 

The Emys has neither bladder nor kidneys. For the softness of 
its shell allows of the ready transpiration of fluid; and for this 
reason neither of the organs mentioned exists in this animal. 
All other animals, however, whose lung contains blood are, as 
before said, provided with kidneys. For nature uses these organs 
for two separate purposes, namely for the excretion of the 
residual fluid, and to subserve the blood-vessels, a channel 
leading to them from the great vessel. 

In the centre of the kidney is a cavity of variable size. This is the 
case in all animals, excepting the seal. The kidneys of this 
animal are more solid than those of any other, and in form 
resemble the kidneys of the ox. The human kidneys are of 
similar shape; being as it were made up of numerous small 
kidneys, and not presenting one unbroken surface like the 
kidneys of sheep and other quadrupeds. For this reason, should 
the kidneys of a man be once attacked by disease, the malady is 
not easily expelled. For it is as though many kidneys were 
diseased and not merely one; which naturally enhances the 
difficulties of a cure. 

The duct which runs to the kidney from the great vessel does 
not terminate in the central cavity, but is expended on the 
substance of the organ, so that there is no blood in the cavity, 
nor is any coagulum found there after death. A pair of stout 
ducts, void of blood, run, one from the cavity of each kidney, to 
the bladder; and other ducts, strong and continuous, lead into 
the kidneys from the aorta. The purpose of this arrangement is 
to allow the superfluous fluid to pass from the blood-vessel into 
the kidney, and the resulting renal excretion to collect by the 
percolation of the fluid through the solid substance of the 
organ, in its centre, where as a general rule there is a cavity. 



1891 



(This by the way explains why the kidney is the most ill- 
savoured of all the viscera.) From the central cavity the fluid is 
discharged into the bladder by the ducts that have been 
mentioned, having already assumed in great degree the 
character of excremental residue. The bladder is as it were 
moored to the kidneys; for, as already has been stated, it is 
attached to them by strong ducts. These then are the purposes 
for which the kidneys exist, and such the functions of these 
organs. 

In all animals that have kidneys, that on the right is placed 
higher than that on the left. For inasmuch as motion 
commences from the right, and the organs on this side are in 
consequence stronger than those on the left, they must all push 
upwards in advance of their opposite fellows; as may be seen in 
the fact that men even raise the right eyebrow more than the 
left, and that the former is more arched than the latter. The 
right kidney being thus drawn upwards is in all animals brought 
into contact with the liver; for the liver lies on the right side. 

Of all the viscera the kidneys are those that have the most fat. 
This is in the first place the result of necessity, because the 
kidneys are the parts through which the residual matters 
percolate. For the blood which is left behind after this excretion, 
being of pure quality, is of easy concoction, and the final result 
of thorough blood-concoction is lard and suet. For just as a 
certain amount of fire is left in the ashes of solid substances 
after combustion, so also does a remnant of the heat that has 
been developed remain in fluids after concoction; and this is the 
reason why oily matter is light, and floats on the surface of 
other fluids. The fat is not formed in the kidneys themselves, 
the density of their substance forbidding this, but is deposited 
about their external surface. It consists of lard or of suet, 
according as the animal's fat is of the former or latter character. 
The difference between these two kinds of fat has already been 



1892 



set forth in other passages. The formation, then, of fat in the 
kidneys is the result of necessity; being, as explained, a 
consequence of the necessary conditions which accompany the 
possession of such organs. But at the same time the fat has a 
final cause, namely to ensure the safety of the kidneys, and to 
maintain their natural heat. For placed, as these organs are, 
close to the surface, they require a greater supply of heat than 
other parts. For while the back is thickly covered with flesh, so 
as to form a shield for the heart and neighbouring viscera, the 
loins, in accordance with a rule that applies to all bendings, are 
destitute of flesh; and fat is therefore formed as a substitute for 
it, so that the kidneys may not be without protection. The 
kidneys, moreover, by being fat are the better enabled to secrete 
and concoct their fluid; for fat is hot, and it is heat that effects 
concoction. 

Such, then, are the reasons why the kidneys are fat. But in all 
animals the right kidney is less fat than its fellow. The reason 
for this is, that the parts on the right side are naturally more 
solid and more suited for motion than those on the left. But 
motion is antagonistic to fat, for it tends to melt it. 

Animals then, as a general rule, derive advantage from their 
kidneys being fat; and the fat is often very abundant and 
extends over the whole of these organs. But, should the like 
occur in the sheep, death ensues. Be its kidneys, however, as fat 
as they may, they are never so fat but that some part, if not in 
both at any rate in the right one, is left free. The reason why 
sheep are the only animals that suffer in this manner, or suffer 
more than others, is that in animals whose fat is composed of 
lard this is of fluid consistency, so that there is not the same 
chance in their case of wind getting shut in and causing 
mischief. But it is to such an enclosure of wind that rot is due. 
And thus even in men, though it is beneficial to them to have 
fat kidneys, yet should these organs become over-fat and 



1893 



diseased, deadly pains ensue. As to those animals whose fat 
consists of suet, in none is the suet so dense as in the sheep, 
neither is it nearly so abundant; for of all animals there is none 
in which the kidneys become so soon gorged with fat as in the 
sheep. Rot, then, is produced by the moisture and the wind 
getting shut up in the kidneys, and is a malady that carries off 
sheep with great rapidity. For the disease forthwith reaches the 
heart, passing thither by the aorta and the great vessel, the 
ducts which connect these with the kidneys being of unbroken 
continuity. 



10 

We have now dealt with the heart and the lung, as also with the 
liver, spleen, and kidneys. The latter are separated from the 
former by the midriff or, as some call it, the Phrenes. This 
divides off the heart and lung, and, as already said, is called 
Phrenes in sanguineous animals, all of which have a midriff, 
just as they all have a heart and a liver. For they require a 
midriff to divide the region of the heart from the region of the 
stomach, so that the centre wherein abides the sensory soul 
may be undisturbed, and not be overwhelmed, directly food is 
taken, by its up-steaming vapour and by the abundance of heat 
then superinduced. For it was to guard against this that nature 
made a division, constructing the midriff as a kind of partition- 
wall and fence, and so separated the nobler from the less noble 
parts, in all cases where a separation of upper from lower is 
possible. For the upper part is the more honourable, and is that 
for the sake of which the rest exists; while the lower part exists 
for the sake of the upper and constitutes the necessary element 
in the body, inasmuch as it is the recipient of the food. 



1894 



That portion of the midriff which is near the ribs is fleshier and 
stronger than the rest, but the central part has more of a 
membranous character; for this structure conduces best to its 
strength and its extensibility. Now that the midriff, which is a 
kind of outgrowth from the sides of the thorax, acts as a screen 
to prevent heat mounting up from below, is shown by what 
happens, should it, owing to its proximity to the stomach, 
attract thence the hot and residual fluid. For when this occurs 
there ensues forthwith a marked disturbance of intellect and of 
sensation. It is indeed because of this that the midriff is called 
Phrenes, as though it had some share in the process of thinking 
(Phronein). in reality, however, it has no part whatsoever itself in 
the matter, but, lying in close proximity to organs that have, it 
brings about the manifest changes of intelligence in question by 
acting upon them. This too explains why its central part is thin. 
For though this is in some measure the result of necessity, 
inasmuch as those portions of the fleshy whole which lie 
nearest to the ribs must necessarily be fleshier than the rest, yet 
besides this there is a final cause, namely to give it as small a 
proportion of humour as possible; for, had it been made of flesh 
throughout, it would have been more likely to attract and hold a 
large amount of this. That heating of it affects sensation rapidly 
and in a notable manner is shown by the phenomena of 
laughing. For when men are tickled they are quickly set a- 
laughing, because the motion quickly reaches this part, and 
heating it though but slightly nevertheless manifestly so 
disturbs the mental action as to occasion movements that are 
independent of the will. That man alone is affected by tickling is 
due firstly to the delicacy of his skin, and secondly to his being 
the only animal that laughs. For to be tickled is to be set in 
laughter, the laughter being produced such a motion as 
mentioned of the region of the armpit. 

It is said also that when men in battle are wounded anywhere 
near the midriff, they are seen to laugh, owing to the heat 



1895 



produced by the wound. This may possibly be the case. At any 
rate it is a statement made by much more credible persons than 
those who tell the story of the human head, how it speaks after 
it is cut off. For so some assert, and even call in Homer to 
support them, representing him as alluding to this when he 
wrote, 'His head still speaking rolled into the dust,' instead of 
'The head of the speaker'. So fully was the possibility of such an 
occurrence accepted in Caria, that one of that country was 
actually brought to trial under the following circumstances. The 
priest of Zeus Hoplosmios had been murdered; but as yet it had 
not been ascertained who was the assassin; when certain 
persons asserted that they had heard the murdered man's head, 
which had been severed from the body, repeat several times the 
words, 'Cercidas slew man on mam.' Search was thereupon 
made and a man of those parts who bore the name of Cercidas 
hunted out and put upon his trial. But it is impossible that any 
one should utter a word when the windpipe is severed and no 
motion any longer derived from the lung. Moreover, among the 
Barbarians, where heads are chopped off with great rapidity, 
nothing of the kind has ever yet occurred. Why, again, does not 
the like occur in the case of other animals than man? For that 
none of them should laugh, when their midriff is wounded, is 
but what one would expect; for no animal but man ever laughs. 
So, too, there is nothing irrational in supposing that the trunk 
may run forwards to a certain distance after the head has been 
cut seeing that bloodless animals at any rate can live, and that 
for a considerable time, after decapitation, as has been set forth 
and explained in other passages. 

The purposes, then, for which the viscera severally exist have 
now been stated. It is of necessity upon the inner terminations 
of the vessels that they are developed; for humour, and that of a 
bloody character, cannot but exude at these points, and it is of 
this, solidified and coagulated, that the substance of the viscera 



1896 



is formed. Thus they are of a bloody character, and in substance 
resemble each other while they differ from other parts. 



11 

The viscera are enclosed each in a membrane. For they require 
some covering to protect them from injury, and require, 
moreover, that this covering shall be light. To such requirements 
membrane is well adapted; for it is close in texture so as to form 
a good protection, destitute of flesh so as neither to attract 
humour nor retain it, and thin so as to be light and not add to 
the weight of the body. Of the membranes those are the stoutest 
and strongest which invest the heart and the brain; as is but 
consistent with reason. For these are the parts which require 
most protection, seeing that they are the main governing 
powers of life, and that it is to governing powers that guard is 
due. 



12 

Some animals have all the viscera that have been enumerated; 
others have only some of them. In what kind of animals this 
latter is the case, and what is the explanation, has already been 
stated. Moreover, the self-same viscera present differences in 
different possessors. For the heart is not precisely alike in all 
animals that have one; nor, in fact, is any viscus whatsoever. 
Thus the liver is in some animals split into several parts, while 
in others it is comparatively undivided. Such differences in its 
form present themselves even among those sanguineous 



1897 



animals that are viviparous, but are more marked in fishes and 
in the oviparous quadrupeds, and this whether we compare 
them with each other or with the Vivipara. As for birds, their 
liver very nearly resembles that of the Vivipara; for in them, as 
in these, it is of a pure and blood-like colour. The reason of this 
is that the body in both these classes of animals admits of the 
freest exhalation, so that the amount of foul residual matter 
within is but small. Hence it is that some of the Vivipara are 
without any gall-bladder at all. For the liver takes a large share 
in maintaining the purity of composition and the healthiness of 
the body. For these are conditions that depend finally and in the 
main upon the blood, and there is more blood in the liver than 
in any of the other viscera, the heart only excepted. On the 
other hand, the liver of oviparous quadrupeds and fishes 
inclines, as a rule, to a yellow hue, and there are even some of 
them in which it is entirely of this bad colour, in accordance 
with the bad composition of their bodies generally. Such, for 
instance, is the case in the toad, the tortoise, and other similar 
animals. 

The spleen, again, varies in different animals. For in those that 
have horns and cloven hoofs, such as the goat, the sheep, and 
the like, it is of a rounded form; excepting when increased size 
has caused some part of it to extend its growth longitudinally, 
as has happened in the case of the ox. On the other hand, it is 
elongated in all polydactylous animals. Such, for instance, is the 
case in the pig, in man, and in the dog. While in animals with 
solid hoofs it is of a form intermediate to these two, being broad 
in one part, narrow in another. Such, for example, is its shape in 
the horse, the mule, and the ass. 



1898 



13 

The viscera differ from the flesh not only in the turgid aspect of 
their substance, but also in position; for they lie within the body, 
whereas the flesh is placed on the outside. The explanation of 
this is that these parts partake of the character of blood-vessels, 
and that while the former exist for the sake of the vessels, the 
latter cannot exist without them. 



14 

Below the midriff lies the stomach, placed at the end of the 
oesophagus when there is one, and in immediate contiguity 
with the mouth when the oesophagus is wanting. Continuous 
with this stomach is what is called the gut. These parts are 
present in all animals, for reasons that are self-evident. For it is 
a matter of necessity that an animal shall receive the incoming 
food; and necessary also that it shall discharge the same when 
its goodness is exhausted. This residual matter, again, must not 
occupy the same place as the yet unconcocted nutriment. For as 
the ingress of food and the discharge of the residue occur at 
distinct periods, so also must they necessarily occur in distinct 
places. Thus there must be one receptacle for the ingoing food 
and another for the useless residue, and between these, 
therefore, a part in which the change from one condition to the 
other may be effected. These, however, are matters which will 
be more suitably set forth when we come to deal with 
Generation and Nutrition. What we have at present to consider 
are the variations presented by the stomach and its subsidiary 
parts. For neither in size nor in shape are these parts uniformly 
alike in all animals. Thus the stomach is single in all such 
sanguineous and viviparous animals as have teeth in front of 



1899 



both jaws. It is single therefore in all the polydactylous kinds, 
such as man, dog, lion, and the rest; in all the solid-hoofed 
animals also, such as horse, mule, ass; and in all those which, 
like the pig, though their hoof is cloven, yet have front teeth in 
both jaws. When, however, an animal is of large size, and feeds 
on substances of so thorny and ligneous a character as to be 
difficult of concoction, it may in consequence have several 
stomachs, as for instance is the case with the camel. A similar 
multiplicity of stomachs exists also in the horned animals; the 
reason being that horn-bearing animals have no front teeth in 
the upper jaw. The camel also, though it has no horns, is yet 
without upper front teeth. The explanation of this is that it is 
more essential for the camel to have a multiple stomach than to 
have these teeth. Its stomach, then, is constructed like that of 
animals without upper front teeth, and, its dental arrangements 
being such as to match its stomach, the teeth in question are 
wanting. They would indeed be of no service. Its food, moreover, 
being of a thorny character, and its tongue necessarily made of 
a fleshy substance, nature uses the earthy matter which is 
saved from the teeth to give hardness to the palate. The camel 
ruminates like the horned animals, because its multiple 
stomach resembles theirs. For all animals that have horns, the 
sheep for instance, the ox, the goat, the deer, and the like, have 
several stomachs. For since the mouth, owing to its lack of 
teeth, only imperfectly performs its office as regards the food, 
this multiplicity of stomachs is intended to make up for its 
shortcomings; the several cavities receiving the food one from 
the other in succession; the first taking the unreduced 
substances, the second the same when somewhat reduced, the 
third when reduction is complete, and the fourth when the 
whole has become a smooth pulp. Such is the reason why there 
is this multiplicity of parts and cavities in animals with such 
dentition. The names given to the several cavities are the 
paunch, the honeycomb bag, the manyplies, and the reed. How 



1900 



these parts are related to each other, in position and in shape, 
must be looked for in the treatises on Anatomy and the 
Researches concerning Animals. 

Birds also present variations in the part which acts as a 
recipient of the food; and the reason for these variations is the 
same as in the animals just mentioned. For here again it is 
because the mouth fails to perform its office and fails even 
more completely - for birds have no teeth at all, nor any 
instrument whatsoever with which to comminute or grind 
down their food - it is, I say, because of this, that in some of 
them what is called the crop precedes the stomach and does 
the work of the mouth; while in others the oesophagus is either 
wide throughout or a part of it bulges just before it enters the 
stomach, so as to form a preparatory store-house for the 
unreduced food; or the stomach itself has a protuberance in 
some part, or is strong and fleshy, so as to be able to store up 
the food for a considerable period and to concoct it, in spite of 
its not having been ground into a pulp. For nature retrieves the 
inefficiency of the mouth by increasing the efficiency and heat 
of the stomach. Other birds there are, such, namely, as have 
long legs and live in marshes, that have none of these 
provisions, but merely an elongated oesophagus. The 
explanation of this is to be found in the moist character of their 
food. For all these birds feed on substances easy of reduction, 
and their food being moist and not requiring much concoction, 
their digestive cavities are of a corresponding character. 

Fishes are provided with teeth, which in almost all of them are 
of the sharp interfitting kind. For there is but one small section 
in which it is otherwise. Of these the fish called Scarus (Parrot- 
fish) is an example. And this is probably the reason why this 
fish apparently ruminates, though no other fishes do so. For 
those horned animals that have no front teeth in the upper jaw 
also ruminate. 



1901 



In fishes the teeth are all sharp; so that these animals can 
divide their food, though imperfectly. For it is impossible for a 
fish to linger or spend time in the act of mastication, and 
therefore they have no teeth that are flat or suitable for 
grinding; for such teeth would be to no purpose. The 
oesophagus again in some fishes is entirely wanting, and in the 
rest is but short. In order, however, to facilitate the concoction of 
the food, some of them, as the Cestreus (mullet), have a fleshy 
stomach resembling that of a bird; while most of them have 
numerous processes close against the stomach, to serve as a 
sort of antechamber in which the food may be stored up and 
undergo putrefaction and concoction. There is contrast between 
fishes and birds in the position of these processes. For in fishes 
they are placed close to the stomach; while in birds, if present 
at all, they are lower down, near the end of the gut. Some of the 
Vivipara also have processes connected with the lower part of 
the gut which serve the same purpose as that stated above. 

The whole tribe of fishes is of gluttonous appetite, owing to the 
arrangements for the reduction of their food being very 
imperfect, and much of it consequently passing through them 
without undergoing concoction; and, of all, those are the most 
gluttonous that have a straight intestine. For as the passage of 
food in such cases is rapid, and the enjoyment derived from it in 
consequence but brief, it follows of necessity that the return of 
appetite is also speedy. 

It has already been mentioned that in animals with front teeth 
in both jaws the stomach is of small size. It may be classed 
pretty nearly always under one or other of two headings, 
namely as resembling the stomach of the dog, or as resembling 
the stomach of the pig. In the pig the stomach is larger than in 
the dog, and presents certain folds of moderate size, the 
purpose of which is to lengthen out the period of concoction; 



1902 



while the stomach of the dog is of small size, not much larger in 
calibre than the gut, and smooth on the internal surface. 

Not much larger, I say, than the gut; for in all animals after the 
stomach comes the gut. This, like the stomach, presents 
numerous modifications. For in some animals it is uniform, 
when uncoiled, and alike throughout, while in others it differs 
in different portions. Thus in some cases it is wider in the 
neighbourhood of the stomach, and narrower towards the other 
end; and this explains by the way why dogs have to strain so 
much in discharging their excrement. But in most animals it is 
the upper portion that is the narrower and the lower that is of 
greater width. 

Of greater length than in other animals, and much convoluted, 
are the intestines of those that have horns. These intestines, 
moreover, as also the stomach, are of ampler volume, in 
accordance with the larger size of the body. For animals with 
horns are, as a rule, animals of no small bulk, because of the 
thorough elaboration which their food undergoes. The gut, 
except in those animals where it is straight, invariably widens 
out as we get farther from the stomach and come to what is 
called the colon, and to a kind of caecal dilatation. After this it 
again becomes narrower and convoluted. Then succeeds a 
straight portion which runs right on to the vent. This vent is 
known as the anus, and is in some animals surrounded by fat, 
in others not so. All these parts have been so contrived by 
nature as to harmonize with the various operations that relate 
to the food and its residue. For, as the residual food gets farther 
on and lower down, the space to contain it enlarges, allowing it 
to remain stationary and undergo conversion. Thus is it in those 
animals which, owing either to their large size, or to the heat of 
the parts concerned, require more nutriment, and consume 
more fodder than the rest. 



1903 



Neither is it without a purpose, that, just as a narrower gut 
succeeds to the upper stomach, so also does the residual food, 
when its goodness is thoroughly exhausted, pass from the colon 
and the ample space of the lower stomach into a narrower 
channel and into the spiral coil. For so nature can regulate her 
expenditure and prevent the excremental residue from being 
discharged all at once. 

In all such animals, however, as have to be comparatively 
moderate in their alimentation, the lower stomach presents no 
wide and roomy spaces, though their gut is not straight, but has 
a number of convolutions. For amplitude of space causes desire 
for ample food, and straightness of the intestine causes quick 
return of appetite. And thus it is that all animals whose food 
receptacles are either simple or spacious are of gluttonous 
habits, the latter eating enormously at a meal, the former 
making meals at short intervals. 

Again, since the food in the upper stomach, having just been 
swallowed, must of necessity be quite fresh, while that which 
has reached the lower stomach must have had its juices 
exhausted and resemble dung, it follows of necessity that there 
must also be some intermediate part, in which the change may 
be effected, and where the food will be neither perfectly fresh 
nor yet dung. And thus it is that, in all such animals as we are 
now considering, there is found what is called the jejunum; 
which is a part of the small gut, of the gut, that is, which comes 
next to the stomach. For this jejunum lies between the upper 
cavity which contains the yet unconcocted food and the lower 
cavity which holds the residual matter, which by the time it has 
got here has become worthless. There is a jejunum in all these 
animals, but it is only plainly discernible in those of large size, 
and this only when they have abstained from food for a certain 
time. For then alone can one hit on the exact period when the 
food lies half-way between the upper and lower cavities; a 



1904 



period which is very short, for the time occupied in the 
transition of food is but brief. In females this jejunum may 
occupy any part whatsoever of the upper intestine, but in males 
it comes just before the caecum and the lower stomach. 



15 

What is known as rennet is found in all animals that have a 
multiple stomach, and in the hare among animals whose 
stomach is single. In the former the rennet neither occupies the 
large paunch, nor the honeycomb bag, nor the terminal reed, 
but is found in the cavity which separates this terminal one 
from the two first, namely in the so-called manyplies. It is the 
thick character of their milk which causes all these animals to 
have rennet; whereas in animals with a single stomach the milk 
is thin, and consequently no rennet is formed. It is this 
difference in thickness which makes the milk of horned 
animals coagulate, while that of animals without horns does 
not. Rennet forms in the hare because it feeds on herbage that 
has juice like that of the fig; for juice of this kind coagulates the 
milk in the stomach of the sucklings. Why it is in the manyplies 
that rennet is formed in animals with multiple stomachs has 
been stated in the Problems. 



1905 



Book IV 



The account which has now been given of the viscera, the 
stomach, and the other several parts holds equally good not 
only for the oviparous quadrupeds, but also for such apodous 
animals as the Serpents. These two classes of animals are 
indeed nearly akin, a serpent resembling a lizard which has 
been lengthened out and deprived of its feet. Fishes, again, 
resemble these two groups in all their parts, excepting that, 
while these, being land animals, have a lung, fishes have no 
lung, but gills in its place. None of these animals, excepting the 
tortoise, as also no fish, has a urinary bladder. For owing to the 
bloodlessness of their lung, they drink but sparingly; and such 
fluid as they have is diverted to the scaly plates, as in birds it is 
diverted to the feathers, and thus they come to have the same 
white matter on the surface of their excrement as we see on 
that of birds. For in animals that have a bladder, its excretion 
when voided throws down a deposit of earthy brine in the 
containing vessel. For the sweet and fresh elements, being light, 
are expended on the flesh. 

Among the Serpents, the same peculiarity attaches to vipers, as 
among fishes attaches to Selachia. For both these and vipers are 
externally viviparous, but previously produce ova internally. 

The stomach in all these animals is single, just as it is single in 
all other animals that have teeth in front of both jaws; and their 
viscera are excessively small, as always happens when there is 
no bladder. In serpents these viscera are, moreover, differently 
shaped from those of other animals. For, a serpent's body being 



1906 



long and narrow, its contents are as it were moulded into a 
similar form, and thus come to be themselves elongated. 

All animals that have blood possess an omentum, a mesentery, 
intestines with their appendages, and, moreover, a diaphragm 
and a heart; and all, excepting fishes, a lung and a windpipe. 
The relative positions, moreover, of the windpipe and the 
oesophagus are precisely similar in them all; and the reason is 
the same as has already been given. 



Almost all sanguineous animals have a gall-bladder. In some 
this is attached to the liver, in others separated from that organ 
and attached to the intestines, being apparently in the latter 
case no less than in the former an appendage of the lower 
stomach. It is in fishes that this is most clearly seen. For all 
fishes have a gall-bladder; and in most of them it is attached to 
the intestine, being in some, as in the Amia, united with this, 
like a border, along its whole length. It is similarly placed in 
most serpents There are therefore no good grounds for the view 
entertained by some writers, that the gall exists for the sake of 
some sensory action. For they say that its use is to affect that 
part of the soul which is lodged in the neighbourhood of the 
liver, vexing this part when it is congealed, and restoring it to 
cheerfulness when it again flows free. But this cannot be. For in 
some animals there is absolutely no gall-bladder at all - in the 
horse, for instance, the mule, the ass, the deer, and the roe; and 
in others, as the camel, there is no distinct bladder, but merely 
small vessels of a biliary character. Again, there is no such organ 
in the seal, nor, of purely sea-animals, in the dolphin. Even 
within the limits of the same genus, some animals appear to 



1907 



have and others to be without it. Such, for instance, is the case 
with mice; such also with man. For in some individuals there is 
a distinct gall-bladder attached to the liver, while in others 
there is no gall-bladder at all. This explains how the existence of 
this part in the whole genus has been a matter of dispute. For 
each observer, according as he has found it present or absent in 
the individual cases he has examined, has supposed it to be 
present or absent in the whole genus. The same has occurred in 
the case of sheep and of goats. For these animals usually have a 
gall-bladder; but, while in some localities it is so enormously big 
as to appear a monstrosity, as is the case in Naxos, in others it is 
altogether wanting, as is the case in a certain district belonging 
to the inhabitants of Chalcis in Euboea. Moreover, the gall- 
bladder in fishes is separated, as already mentioned, by a 
considerable interval from the liver. No less mistaken seems to 
be the opinion of Anaxagoras and his followers, that the gall- 
bladder is the cause of acute diseases, inasmuch as it becomes 
over-full, and spirts out its excess on to the lung, the blood- 
vessels, and the ribs. For, almost invariably, those who suffer 
from these forms of disease are persons who have no gall- 
bladder at all, as would be quite evident were they to be 
dissected. Moreover, there is no kind of correspondence 
between the amount of bile which is present in these diseases 
and the amount which is exuded. The most probable opinion is 
that, as the bile when it is present in any other part of the body 
is a mere residuum or a product of decay, so also when it is 
present in the region of the liver it is equally excremental and 
has no further use; just as is the case with the dejections of the 
stomach and intestines. For though even the residua are 
occasionally used by nature for some useful purpose, yet we 
must not in all cases expect to find such a final cause; for 
granted the existence in the body of this or that constituent, 
with such and such properties, many results must ensue merely 
as necessary consequences of these properties. All animals, 



1908 



then, whose is healthy in composition and supplied with none 
but sweet blood, are either entirely without a gall-bladder on 
this organ, or have merely small bile-containing vessels; or are 
some with and some without such parts. Thus it is that the liver 
in animals that have no gall-bladder is, as a rule, of good colour 
and sweet; and that, when there is a gall-bladder, that part of 
the liver is sweetest which lies immediately underneath it. But, 
when animals are formed of blood less pure in composition, the 
bile serves for the excretion of its impure residue. For the very 
meaning of excrement is that it is the opposite of nutriment, 
and of bitter that it is the opposite of sweet; and healthy blood 
is sweet. So that it is evident that the bile, which is bitter, 
cannot have any use, but must simply be a purifying excretion. 
It was therefore no bad saying of old writers that the absence of 
a gall-bladder gave long life. In so saying they had in mind deer 
and animals with solid hoofs. For such have no gall-bladder and 
live long. But besides these there are other animals that have no 
gall-bladder, though those old writers had not noticed the fact, 
such as the camel and the dolphin; and these also are, as it 
happens, long-lived. Seeing, indeed, that the liver is not only 
useful, but a necessary and vital part in all animals that have 
blood, it is but reasonable that on its character should depend 
the length or the shortness of life. Nor less reasonable is it that 
this organ and none other should have such an excretion as the 
bile. For the heart, unable as it is to stand any violent affection, 
would be utterly intolerant of the proximity of such a fluid; and, 
as to the rest of the viscera, none excepting the liver are 
necessary parts of an animal. It is the liver therefore that alone 
has this provision. In conclusion, wherever we see bile we must 
take it to be excremental. For to suppose that it has one 
character in this part, another in that, would be as great an 
absurdity as to suppose mucus or the dejections of the stomach 
to vary in character according to locality and not to be 
excremental wherever found. 



1909 



So much then of the gall-bladder, and of the reasons why some 
animals have one, while others have not. We have still to speak 
of the mesentery and the omentum; for these are associated 
with the parts already described and contained in the same 
cavity. The omentum, then, is a membrane containing fat; the 
fat being suet or lard, according as the fat of the animal 
generally is of the former or latter description. What kinds of 
animals are so distinguished has been already set forth in an 
earlier part of this treatise. This membrane, alike in animals 
that have a single and in those that have a multiple stomach, 
grows from the middle of that organ, along a line which is 
marked on it like a seam. Thus attached, it covers the rest of the 
stomach and the greater part of the bowels, and this alike in all 
sanguineous animals, whether they live on land or in water. 
Now the development of this part into such a form as has been 
described is the result of necessity. For, whenever solid and fluid 
are mixed together and heated, the surface invariably becomes 
membranous and skin-like. But the region in which the 
omentum lies is full of nutriment of such a mixed character. 
Moreover, in consequence of the close texture of the membrane, 
that portion of the sanguineous nutriment will alone filter into 
it which is of a greasy character; for this portion is composed of 
the finest particles; and when it has so filtered in, it will be 
concocted by the heat of the part, and will be converted into 
suet or lard, and will not acquire a flesh-like or sanguineous 
constitution. The development, then, of the omentum is simply 
the result of necessity. But when once formed, it is used by 
nature for an end, namely, to facilitate and to hasten the 
concoction of food. For all that is hot aids concoction; and fat is 



1910 



hot, and the omentum is fat. This too explains why it hangs 
from the middle of the stomach; for the upper part of the 
stomach has no need of it, being assisted in concoction by the 
adjacent liver. Thus much as concerns the omentum. 



The so-called mesentery is also a membrane; and extends 
continuously from the long stretch of intestine to the great 
vessel and the aorta. In it are numerous and close-packed 
vessels, which run from the intestines to the great vessel and to 
the aorta. The formation of this membrane we shall find to be 
the result of necessity, as is that of the other [similar] parts. 
What, however, is the final cause of its existence in sanguineous 
animals is manifest on reflection. For it is necessary that 
animals shall get nutriment from without; and, again, that this 
shall be converted into the ultimate nutriment, which is then 
distributed as sustenance to the various parts; this ultimate 
nutriment being, in sanguineous animals, what we call blood, 
and having, in bloodless animals, no definite name. This being 
so, there must be channels through which the nutriment shall 
pass, as it were through roots, from the stomach into the blood- 
vessels. Now the roots of plants are in the ground; for thence 
their nutriment is derived. But in animals the stomach and 
intestines represent the ground from which the nutriment is to 
be taken. The mesentery, then, is an organ to contain the roots; 
and these roots are the vessels that traverse it. This then is the 
final cause of its existence. But how it absorbs nutriment, and 
how that portion of the food which enters into the vessels is 
distributed by them to the various parts of the body, are 
questions which will be considered when we come to deal with 
the generation and nutrition of animals. 



1911 



The constitution of sanguineous animals, so far as the parts as 
yet mentioned are concerned, and the reasons for such 
constitution, have now been set forth. In natural sequence we 
should next go on to the organs of generation, as yet 
undescribed, on which depend the distinctions of male and 
female. But, inasmuch as we shall have to deal specially with 
generation hereafter, it will be more convenient to defer the 
consideration of these parts to that occasion. 



Very different from the animals we have as yet considered are 
the Cephalopoda and the Crustacea. For these have absolutely 
no viscera whatsoever; as is indeed the case with all bloodless 
animals, in which are included two other genera, namely the 
Testacea and the Insects. For in none of them does the material 
out of which viscera are formed exist. None of them, that is, 
have blood. The cause of this lies in their essential constitution. 
For the presence of blood in some animals, its absence from 
others, must be included in the conception which determines 
their respective essences. Moreover, in the animals we are now 
considering, none of those final causes will be found to exist 
which in sanguineous animals determine the presence of 
viscera. For they have no blood vessels nor urinary bladder, nor 
do they breathe; the only part that it is necessary for them to 
have being that which is analogous to a heart. For in all animals 
there must be some central and commanding part of the body, 
to lodge the sensory portion of the soul and the source of life. 
The organs of nutrition are also of necessity present in them all. 
They differ, however, in character because of differences of the 
habitats in which they get their subsistence. 



1912 



In the Cephalopoda there are two teeth, enclosing what is called 
the mouth; and inside this mouth is a flesh-like substance 
which represents a tongue and serves for the discrimination of 
pleasant and unpleasant food. The Crustacea have teeth 
corresponding to those of the Cephalopoda, namely their 
anterior teeth, and also have the fleshy representative of a 
tongue. This latter part is found, moreover, in all Testacea, and 
serves, as in sanguineous animals, for gustatory sensations. 
Similarly provided also are the Insects. For some of these, such 
as the Bees and the Flies, have, as already described, their 
proboscis protruding from the mouth; while those others that 
have no such instrument in front have a part which acts as a 
tongue inside the mouth. Such, for instance, is the case in the 
Ants and the like. As for teeth, some insects have them, the 
Bees and the Ants for instance, though in a somewhat modified 
form, while others that live on fluid nutriment are without 
them. For in many insects the teeth are not meant to deal with 
the food, but to serve as weapons. 

In some Testacea, as was said in the first treatise, the organ 
which is called the tongue is of considerable strength; and in 
the Cochli (Sea-snails) there are also two teeth, just as in the 
Crustacea. The mouth in the Cephalopoda is succeeded by a 
long gullet. This leads to a crop, like that of a bird, and directly 
continuous with this is the stomach, from which a gut runs 
without windings to the vent. The Sepias and the Poulps 
resemble each other completely, so far as regards the shape and 
consistency of these parts. But not so the Teuthides 
(Calamaries). Here, as in the other groups there are the two 
stomach-like receptacles; but the first of these cavities has less 
resemblance to a crop, and in neither is the form [or the 
consistency] the same as in the other kinds, the whole body 
indeed being made of a softer kind of flesh. 



1913 



The object of this arrangement of the parts in question is the 
same in the Cephalopoda as in Birds; for these also are all 
unable to masticate their food; and therefore it is that a crop 
precedes their stomach. 

For purposes of defence, and to enable them to escape from 
their foes, the Cephalopoda have what is called their ink. This is 
contained in a membranous pouch, which is attached to the 
body and provided with a terminal outlet just at the point 
where what is termed the funnel gives issue to the residua of 
the stomach. This funnel is placed on the ventral surface of the 
animal. All Cephalopoda alike have this characteristic ink, but 
chief of all the Sepia, where it is more abundant than in the rest. 
When the animal is disturbed and frightened it uses this ink to 
make the surrounding water black and turbid, and so, as it were, 
puts a shield in front of its body. 

In the Calamaries and the Poulps the ink-bag is placed in the 
upper part of the body, in close proximity to the mytis, whereas 
in the Sepia it is lower down, against the stomach. For the Sepia 
has a more plentiful supply of ink than the rest, inasmuch as it 
makes more use of it. The reasons for this are, firstly, that it 
lives near the shore, and, secondly, that it has no other means 
of protection; whereas the Poulp has its long twining feet to use 
in its defence, and is, moreover, endowed with the power of 
changing colour. This changing of colour, like the discharge of 
ink, occurs as the result of fright. As to the Calamary, it lives far 
out at sea, being the only one of the Cephalopoda that does so; 
and this gives it protection. These then are the reasons why the 
ink is more abundant in the Sepia than in the Calamary, and 
this greater abundance explains the lower position; for it allows 
the ink to be ejected with ease even from a distance. The ink 
itself is of an earthy character, in this resembling the white 
deposit on the surface of a bird's excrement and the 
explanation in both cases is the same, namely, the absence of a 



1914 



urinary bladder. For, in default of this, it is the ink that serves 
for the excretion of the earthiest matter. And this is more 
especially the case in the Sepia, because there is a greater 
proportion of earth in its composition than in that of the other 
Cephalopoda. The earthy character of its bone is a clear 
indication of this. For in the Poulp there is no bone at all, and in 
the Calamary it is thin and cartilaginous. Why this bone should 
be present in some Cephalopoda, and wanting in others, and 
how its character varies in those that have it, has now been set 
forth. 

These animals, having no blood, are in consequence cold and of 
a timid character. Now, in some animals, fear causes a 
disturbance of the bowels, and, in others, a flow of urine from 
the bladder. Similarly in these it produces a discharge of ink, 
and, though the ejection of this ink in fright, like that of the 
urine, is the result of necessity, and, though it is of excremental 
character, yet it is used by nature for a purpose, namely, the 
protection and safety of the animal that excretes it. 

The Crustacea also, both the Caraboid forms and the Crabs, are 
provided with teeth, namely their two anterior teeth; and 
between these they also present the tongue-like piece of flesh, 
as has indeed been already mentioned. Directly after their 
mouth comes a gullet, which, if we compare relative sizes, is but 
small in proportion to the body: and then a stomach, which in 
the Carabi and some of the Crabs is furnished with a second set 
of teeth, the anterior teeth being insufficient for adequate 
mastication. From the stomach a uniform gut runs in a direct 
line to the excremental vent. 

The parts described are to be found also in all the various 
Testacea. The degree of distinctness, however, with which they 
are formed varies in the different kinds, and the larger the size 
of the animal the more easily distinguishable are all these parts 



1915 



severally. In the Sea-snails, for example, we find teeth, hard and 
sharp, as before mentioned, and between them the flesh-like 
substance, just as in the Crustacea and Cephalopoda, and again 
the proboscis, which, as has been stated, is something between 
a sting and a tongue. Directly after the mouth comes a kind of 
bird-like crop, then a gullet, succeeded by a stomach, in which is 
the mecon, as it is styled; and continuous with this mecon is an 
intestine, starting directly from it. It is this residual substance 
which appears in all the Testacea to form the most palatable 
morsel. Purpuras and Whelks, and all other Testacea that have 
turbinate shells, in structure resemble the Sea-snail. The genera 
and species of Testacea are very numerous. For there are those 
with turbinate shells, of which some have just been mentioned; 
and, besides these, there are bivalves and univalves. Those with 
turbinate shells may, indeed, after a certain fashion be said to 
resemble bivalves. For they all from their very birth have an 
operculum to protect that part of their body which is exposed to 
view. This is the case with the Purpuras, with Whelks, with the 
Nerites, and the like. Were it not for this, the part which is 
undefended by the shell would be very liable to injury by 
collision with external objects. The univalves also are not 
without protection. For on their dorsal surface they have a shell, 
and by the under surface they attach themselves to the rocks, 
and so after a manner become bivalved, the rock representing 
the second valve. Of these the animals known as Limpets are an 
example. The bivalves, scallops and mussels, for instance, are 
protected by the power they have of closing their valves; and 
the Turbinata by the operculum just mentioned, which 
transforms them, as it were, crom univalves into bivalves. But of 
all there is none so perfectly protected as the sea-urchin. For 
here there is a globular shell which encloses the body 
completely, and which is, moreover, set with sharp spines. This 
peculiarity distinguishes the sea-urchin from all other Testacea, 
as has already been mentioned. 



1916 



The structure of the Testacea and of the Crustacea is exactly the 
reverse of that of the Cephalopoda. For in the latter the fleshy 
substance is on the outside and the earthy substance within, 
whereas in the former the soft parts are inside and the hard 
part without. In the sea-urchin, however, there is no fleshy part 
whatsoever. 

All the Testacea then, those that have not been mentioned as 
well as those that have, agree as stated in possessing a mouth 
with the tongue-like body, a stomach, and a vent for excrement, 
but they differ from each other in the positions and proportions 
of these parts. The details, however, of these differences must 
be looked for in the Researches concerning Animals and the 
treatises on Anatomy. For while there are some points which 
can be made clear by verbal description, there are others which 
are more suited for ocular demonstration. 

Peculiar among the Testacea are the sea-urchins and the 
animals known as Tethya (Ascidians). The sea-urchins have five 
teeth, and in the centre of these the fleshy body which is 
common to all the animals we have been discussing. 
Immediately after this comes a gullet, and then the stomach, 
divided into a number of separate compartments, which look 
like so many distinct stomachs; for the cavities are separate and 
all contain abundant residual matter. They are all, however, 
connected with one and the same oesophagus, and they all end 
in one and the same excremental vent. There is nothing besides 
the stomach of a fleshy character, as has already been stated. 
All that can be seen are the so-called ova, of which there are 
several, contained each in a separate membrane, and certain 
black bodies which have no name, and which, beginning at the 
animal's mouth, are scattered round its body here and there 
promiscuously. These sea-urchins are not all of one species, but 
there are several different kinds, and in all of them the parts 
mentioned are to be found. It is not, however, in every kind that 



1917 



the so-called ova are edible. Neither do these attain to any size 
in any other species than that with which we are all familiar. A 
similar distinction may be made generally in the case of all 
Testacea. For there is a great difference in the edible qualities of 
the flesh of different kinds; and in some, moreover, the residual 
substance known as the mecon is good for food, while in others 
it is uneatable. This mecon in the turbinated genera is lodged in 
the spiral part of the shell, while in univalves, such as limpets, it 
occupies the fundus, and in bivalves is placed near the hinge, 
the so-called ovum lying on the right; while on the opposite side 
is the vent. The former is incorrectly termed ovum, for it merely 
corresponds to what in well-fed sanguineous animals is fat; and 
thus it is that it makes its appearance in Testacea at those 
seasons of the year when they are in good condition, namely, 
spring and autumn. For no Testacea can abide extremes of 
temperature, and they are therefore in evil plight in seasons of 
great cold or heat. This is clearly shown by what occurs in the 
case of the sea-urchins. For though the ova are to be found in 
these animals even directly they are born, yet they acquire a 
greater size than usual at the time of full moon; not, as some 
think, because sea-urchins eat more at that season, but because 
the nights are then warmer, owing to the moonlight. For these 
creatures are bloodless, and so are unable to stand cold and 
require warmth. Therefore it is that they are found in better 
condition in summer than at any other season; and this all over 
the world excepting in the Pyrrhean tidal strait. There the sea- 
urchins flourish as well in winter as in summer. But the reason 
for this is that they have a greater abundance of food in the 
winter, because the fish desert the strait at that season. 

The number of the ova is the same in all sea-urchins, and is an 
odd one. For there are five ova, just as there are also five teeth 
and five stomachs; and the explanation of this is to be found in 
the fact that the so-called ova are not really ova, but merely, as 
was said before, the result of the animal's well-fed condition. 



1918 



Oysters also have a so-called ovum, corresponding in character 
to that of the sea-urchins, but existing only on one side of their 
body. Now inasmuch as the sea-urchin is of a spherical form, 
and not merely a single disk like the oyster, and in virtue of its 
spherical shape is the same from whatever side it be examined, 
its ovum must necessarily be of a corresponding symmetry. For 
the spherical shape has not the asymmetry of the disk-shaped 
body of the oysters. For in all these animals the head is central, 
but in the sea-urchin the so-called ovum is above [and 
symmetrical, while in the oyster it is only one side]. Now the 
necessary symmetry would be observed were the ovum to form 
a continuous ring. But this may not be. For it would be in 
opposition to what prevails in the whole tribe of Testacea; for in 
all the ovum is discontinuous, and in all excepting the sea- 
urchins asymmetrical, being placed only on one side of the 
body. Owing then to this necessary discontinuity of the ovum, 
which belongs to the sea-urchin as a member of the class, and 
owing to the spherical shape of its body, which is its individual 
peculiarity, this animal cannot possibly have an even number of 
ova. For were they an even number, they would have to be 
arranged exactly opposite to each other, in pairs, so as to keep 
the necessary symmetry; one ovum of each pair being placed at 
one end, the other ovum at the other end of a transverse 
diameter. This again would violate the universal provision in 
Testacea. For both in the oysters and in the scallops we find the 
ovum only on one side of the circumference. The number then 
of the ova must be uneven, three for instance, or five. But if 
there were only three they would be much too far apart; while, 
if there were more than five, they would come to form a 
continuous mass. The former arrangement would be 
disadvantageous to the animal, the latter an impossibility. There 
can therefore be neither more nor less than five. For the same 
reason the stomach is divided into five parts, and there is a 
corresponding number of teeth. For seeing that the ova 



1919 



represent each of them a kind of body for the animal, their 
disposition must conform to that of the stomach, seeing that it 
is from this that they derive the material for their growth. Now 
if there were only one stomach, either the ova would be too far 
off from it, or it would be so big as to fill up the whole cavity, 
and the sea-urchin would have great difficulty in moving about 
and finding due nourishment for its repletion. As then there are 
five intervals between the five ova, so are there of necessity five 
divisions of the stomach, one for each interval. So also, and on 
like grounds, there are five teeth. For nature is thus enabled to 
allot to each stomachal compartment and ovum its separate 
and similar tooth. These, then, are the reasons why the number 
of ova in the sea-urchin is an odd one, and why that odd 
number is five. In some sea-urchins the ova are excessively 
small, in others of considerable size, the explanation being that 
the latter are of a warmer constitution, and so are able to 
concoct their food more thoroughly; while in the former 
concoction is less perfect, so that the stomach is found full of 
residual matter, while the ova are small and uneatable. Those of 
a warmer constitution are, moreover, in virtue of their warmth 
more given to motion, so that they make expeditions in search 
of food, instead of remaining stationary like the rest. As 
evidence of this, it will be found that they always have 
something or other sticking to their spines, as though they 
moved much about; for they use their spines as feet. 

The Ascidians differ but slightly from plants, and yet have more 
of an animal nature than the sponges, which are virtually 
plants and nothing more. For nature passes from lifeless objects 
to animals in such unbroken sequence, interposing between 
them beings which live and yet are not animals, that scarcely 
any difference seems to exist between two neighbouring groups 
owing to their close proximity. 



1920 



A sponge, then, as already said, in these respects completely 
resembles a plant, that throughout its life it is attached to a 
rock, and that when separated from this it dies. Slightly 
different from the sponges are the so-called Holothurias and 
the sea-lungs, as also sundry other sea-animals that resemble 
them. For these are free and unattached. Yet they have no 
feeling, and their life is simply that of a plant separated from 
the ground. For even among land-plants there are some that are 
independent of the soil, and that spring up and grow, either 
upon other plants, or even entirely free. Such, for example, is 
the plant which is found on Parnassus, and which some call the 
Epipetrum. This you may hang up on a peg and it will yet live 
for a considerable time. Sometimes it is a matter of doubt 
whether a given organism should be classed with plants or with 
animals. The Ascidians, for instance, and the like so far 
resemble plants as that they never live free and unattached, but, 
on the other hand, inasmuch as they have a certain flesh-like 
substance, they must be supposed to possess some degree of 
sensibility. 

An Ascidian has a body divided by a single septum and with two 
orifices, one where it takes in the fluid matter that ministers to 
its nutrition, the other where it discharges the surplus of 
unused juice, for it has no visible residual substance, such as 
have the other Testacea. This is itself a very strong justification 
for considering an Ascidian, and anything else there may be 
among animals that resembles it, to be of a vegetable character; 
for plants also never have any residuum. Across the middle of 
the body of these Ascidians there runs a thin transverse 
partition, and here it is that we may reasonably suppose the 
part on which life depends to be situated. 

The Acalephae, or Sea-nettles, as they are variously called, are 
not Testacea at all, but lie outside the recognized groups. Their 
constitution, like that of the Ascidians, approximates them on 



1921 



one side to plants, on the other to animals. For seeing that some 
of them can detach themselves and can fasten upon their food, 
and that they are sensible of objects which come in contact 
with them, they must be considered to have an animal nature. 
The like conclusion follows from their using the asperity of 
their bodies as a protection against their enemies. But, on the 
other hand, they are closely allied to plants, firstly by the 
imperfection of their structure, secondly by their being able to 
attach themselves to the rocks, which they do with great 
rapidity, and lastly by their having no visible residuum 
notwithstanding that they possess a mouth. 

Very similar again to the Acalephae are the Starfishes. For these 
also fasten on their prey, and suck out its juices, and thus 
destroy a vast number of oysters. At the same time they present 
a certain resemblance to such of the animals we have described 
as the Cephalopoda and Crustacea, inasmuch as they are free 
and unattached. The same may also be said of theTestacea. 

Such, then, is the structure of the parts that minister to 
nutrition and which every animal must possess. But besides 
these organs it is quite plain that in every animal there must be 
some part or other which shall be analogous to what in 
sanguineous animals is the presiding seat of sensation. 
Whether an animal has or has not blood, it cannot possibly be 
without this. In the Cephalopoda this part consists of a fluid 
substance contained in a membrane, through which runs the 
gullet on its way to the stomach. It is attached to the body 
rather towards its dorsal surface, and by some is called the 
mytis. Just such another organ is found also in the Crustacea 
and there too is known by the same name. This part is at once 
fluid and corporeal and, as before said, is traversed by the gullet. 
For had the gullet been placed between the mytis and the dorsal 
surface of the animal, the hardness of the back would have 
interfered with its due dilatation in the act of deglutition. On 



1922 



the outer surface of the mytis runs the intestine; and in contact 
with this latter is placed the ink-bag, so that it may be removed 
as far as possible from the mouth and its obnoxious fluid be 
kept at a distance from the nobler and sovereign part. The 
position of the mytis shows that it corresponds to the heart of 
sanguineous animals; for it occupies the self-same place. The 
same is shown by the sweetness of its fluid, which has the 
character of concocted matter and resembles blood. 

In the Testacea the presiding seat of sensation is in a 
corresponding position, but is less easily made out. It should, 
however, always be looked for in some midway position; 
namely, in such Testacea as are stationary, midway between the 
part by which food is taken in and the channel through which 
either the excrement or the spermatic fluid is voided, and, in 
those species which are capable of locomotion, invariably 
midway between the right and left sides. 

In Insects this organ, which is the seat of sensation, lies, as was 
stated in the first treatise, between the head and the cavity 
which contains the stomach. In most of them it consists of a 
single part; but in others, for instance in such as have long 
bodies and resemble the Juli (Millipedes), it is made up of 
several parts, so that such insects continue to live after they 
have been cut in pieces. For the aim of nature is to give to each 
animal only one such dominant part; and when she is unable to 
carry out this intention she causes the parts, though potentially 
many, to work together actually as one. This is much more 
clearly marked in some insects than in others. 

The parts concerned in nutrition are not alike in all insects, but 
show considerable diversity. Thus some have what is called a 
sting in the mouth, which is a kind of compound instrument 
that combines in itself the character of a tongue and of lips. In 
others that have no such instrument in front there is a part 



1923 



inside the mouth that answers the same sensory purposes. 
Immediately after the mouth comes the intestine, which is 
never wanting in any insect. This runs in a straight line and 
without further complication to the vent; occasionally, however, 
it has a spiral coil. There are, moreover, some insects in which a 
stomach succeeds to the mouth, and is itself succeeded by a 
convoluted intestine, so that the larger and more voracious 
insects may be enabled to take in a more abundant supply of 
food. More curious than any are the Cicadae. For here the mouth 
and the tongue are united so as to form a single part, through 
which, as through a root, the insect sucks up the fluids on 
which it lives. Insects are always small eaters, not so much 
because of their diminutive size as because of their cold 
temperament. For it is heat which requires sustenance; just as it 
is heat which speedily concocts it. But cold requires no 
sustenance. In no insects is this so conspicuous as in these 
Cicadae. For they find enough to live on in the moisture which 
is deposited from the air. So also do the Ephemera that are 
found about the Black sea. But while these latter only live for a 
single day, the Cicadae subsist on such food for several days, 
though still not many. 

We have now done with the internal parts of animals, and must 
therefore return to the consideration of the external parts 
which have not yet been described. It will be better to change 
our order of exposition and begin with the animals we have just 
been describing, so that proceeding from these, which require 
less discussion, our account may have more time to spend on 
the perfect kinds of animals, those namely that have blood. 



1924 



We will begin with Insects. These animals, though they present 
no great multiplicity of parts, are not without diversities when 
compared with each other. They are all manyfooted; the object 
of this being to compensate their natural slowness and frigidity, 
and give greater activity to their motions. Accordingly we find 
that those which, as the (Millipedes), have long bodies, and are 
therefore the most liable to refrigeration, have also the greatest 
number of feet. Again, the body in these animals is insected - 
the reason for this being that they have not got one vital centre 
but many - and the number of their feet corresponds to that of 
the insections. 

Should the feet fall short of this, their deficiency is 
compensated by the power of flight. Of such flying insects some 
live a wandering life, and are forced to make long expeditions in 
search of food. These have a body of light weight, and four 
feathers, two on either side, to support it. Such are bees and the 
insects akin to them. When, however, such insects are of very 
small bulk, their feathers are reduced to two, as is the case with 
flies. Insects with heavy bodies and of stationary habits, though 
not polypterous in the same way as bees, yet have sheaths to 
their feathers to maintain their efficiency. Such are the 
Melolonthae and the like. For their stationary habits expose 
their feathers to much greater risks than are run by those of 
insects that are more constantly in flight, and on this account 
they are provided with this protecting shield. The feather of an 
insect has neither barbs nor shaft. For, though it is called a 
feather, it is no feather at all, but merely a skin-like membrane 
that, owing to its dryness, necessarily becomes detached from 
the surface of the body, as the fleshy substance grows cold. 

These animals then have their bodies insected, not only for the 
reasons already assigned, but also to enable them to curl round 



1925 



in such a manner as may protect them from injury; for such 
insects as have long bodies can roll themselves up, which would 
be impossible were it not for the insections; and those that 
cannot do this can yet draw their segments up into the insected 
spaces, and so increase the hardness of their bodies. This can be 
felt quite plainly by putting the finger on one of the insects, for 
instance, known as Canthari. The touch frightens the insect, 
and it remains motionless, while its body becomes hard. The 
division of the body into segments is also a necessary result of 
there being several supreme organs in place of one; and this 
again is a part of the essential constitution of insects, and is a 
character which approximates them to plants. For as plants, 
though cut into pieces, can still live, so also can insects. There 
is, however, this difference between the two cases, that the 
portions of the divided insect live only for a limited time, 
whereas the portions of the plant live on and attain the perfect 
form of the whole, so that from one single plant you may obtain 
two or more. 

Some insects are also provided with another means of 
protection against their enemies, namely a sting. In some this is 
in front, connected with the tongue, in others behind at the 
posterior end. For just as the organ of smell in elephants 
answers several uses, serving alike as a weapon and for 
purposes of nutrition, so does also the sting, when placed in 
connexion with the tongue, as in some insects, answer more 
than one end. For it is the instrument through which they 
derive their sensations of food, as well as that with which they 
suck it up and bring it to the mouth. Such of these insects as 
have no anterior sting are provided with teeth, which serve in 
some of them for biting the food, and in others for its 
prehension and conveyance to the mouth. Such are their uses, 
for instance, in ants and all the various kinds of bees. As for the 
insects that have a sting behind, this weapon is given them 
because they are of a fierce disposition. In some of them the 



1926 



sting is lodged inside the body, in bees, for example, and wasps. 
For these insects are made for flight, and were their sting 
external and of delicate make it would soon get spoiled; and if, 
on the other hand, it were of thicker build, as in scorpions, its 
weight would be an incumbrance. As for scorpions that live on 
the ground and have a tail, their sting must be set upon this, as 
otherwise it would be of no use as a weapon. Dipterous insects 
never have a posterior sting. For the very reason of their being 
dipterous is that they are small and weak, and therefore require 
no more than two feathers to support their light weight; and the 
same reason which reduces their feathers to two causes their 
sting to be in front; for their strength is not sufficient to allow 
them to strike efficiently with the hinder part of the body. 
Polypterous insects, on the other hand, are of greater bulk - 
indeed it is this which causes them to have so many feathers; 
and their greater size makes them stronger in their hinder 
parts. The sting of such insects is therefore placed behind. Now 
it is better, when possible, that one and the same instrument 
shall not be made to serve several dissimilar uses; but that 
there shall be one organ to serve as a weapon, which can then 
be very sharp, and a distinct one to serve as a tongue, which can 
then be of spongy texture and fit to absorb nutriment. 
Whenever, therefore, nature is able to provide two separate 
instruments for two separate uses, without the one hampering 
the other, she does so, instead of acting like a coppersmith who 
for cheapness makes a spit and lampholder in one. It is only 
when this is impossible that she uses one organ for several 
functions. 

The anterior legs are in some cases longer than the others, that 
they may serve to wipe away any foreign matter that may lodge 
on the insect's eyes and obstruct its sight, which already is not 
very distinct owing to the eyes being made of a hard substance. 
Flies and bees and the like may be constantly seen thus 
dressing themselves with crossed forelegs. Of the other legs, the 



1927 



hinder are bigger than the middle pair, both to aid in running 
and also that the insect, when it takes flight, may spring more 
easily from the ground. This difference is still more marked in 
such insects as leap, in locusts for instance, and in the various 
kinds of fleas. For these first bend and then extend the legs, 
and, by doing so, are necessarily shot up from the ground. It is 
only the. hind legs of locusts, and not the front ones, that 
resemble the steering oars of a ship. For this requires that the 
joint shall be deflected inwards, and such is never the case with 
the anterior limbs. The whole number of legs, including those 
used in leaping, is six in all these insects. 



In the Testacea the body consists of but few parts, the reason 
being that these animals live a stationary life. For such animals 
as move much about must of necessity have more numerous 
parts than such as remain quiet; for their activities are many, 
and the more diversified the movements the greater the 
number of organs required to effect them. Some species of 
Testacea are absolutely motionless, and others not quite but 
nearly so. Nature, however, has provided them with a protection 
in the hardness of the shell with which she has invested their 
body. This shell, as already has been said, may have one valve, 
or two valves, or be turbinate. In the latter case it may be either 
spiral, as in whelks, or merely globular, as in sea-urchins. When 
it has two valves, these may be gaping, as in scallops and 
mussels, where the valves are united together on one side only, 
so as to open and shut on the other; or they may be united 
together on both sides, as in the Solens (razor- fishes). In all 
cases alike the Testacea have, like plants, the head downwards. 
The reason for this is, that they take in their nourishment from 



1928 



below, just as do plants with their roots. Thus the under parts 
come in them to be above, and the upper parts to be below. The 
body is enclosed in a membrane, and through this the animal 
filters fluid free from salt and absorbs its nutriment. In all there 
is a head; but none of the parts, excepting this recipient of food, 
has any distinctive name. 



8 

All the Crustacea can crawl as well as swim, and accordingly 
they are provided with numerous feet. There are four main 
genera, viz. the Carabi, as they are called, the Astaci, the 
Carides, and the Carcini. In each of these genera, again, there 
are numerous species, which differ from each other not only as 
regards shape, but also very considerably as regards size. For, 
while in some species the individuals are large, in others they 
are excessively minute. The Carcinoid and Caraboid Crustacea 
resemble each other in possessing claws. These claws are not 
for locomotion, but to serve in place of hands for seizing and 
holding objects; and they are therefore bent in the opposite 
direction to the feet, being so twisted as to turn their convexity 
towards the body, while their feet turn towards it their 
concavity. For in this position the claws are best suited for 
laying hold of the food and carrying it to the mouth. The 
distinction between the Carabi and the Carcini (Crabs) consists 
in the former having a tail while the latter have none. For the 
Carabi swim about and a tail is therefore of use to them, serving 
for their propulsion like the blade of an oar. But it would be of 
no use to the Crabs; for these animals live habitually close to 
the shore, and creep into holes and corners. In such of them as 
live out at sea, the feet are much less adapted for locomotion 
than in the rest, because they are little given to moving about 



1929 



but depend for protection on their shell-like covering. The Maiae 
and the crabs known as Heracleotic are examples of this; the 
legs in the former being very thin, in the latter very short. 

The very minute crabs that are found among the small fry at 
the bottom of the net have their hindermost feet flattened out 
into the semblance of fins or oar-blades, so as to help the 
animal in swimming. 

The Carides are distinguished from the Carcinoid species by the 
presence of a tail; and from the Caraboids by the absence of 
claws. This is explained by their large number of feet, on which 
has been expended the material for the growth of claws. Their 
feet again are numerous to suit their mode of progression, 
which is mainly by swimming. 

Of the parts on the ventral surface, those near the head are in 
some of these animals formed like gills, for the admission and 
discharge of water; while the parts lower down differ in the two 
sexes. For in the female Carabi these are more laminar than in 
the males, and in the female crabs the flap is furnished with 
hairier appendages. This gives ampler space for the disposal of 
the ova, which the females retain in these parts instead of 
letting them go free, as do fishes and all other oviparous 
animals. In the Carabi and in the Crabs the right claw is 
invariably the larger and the stronger. For it is natural to every 
animal in active operations to use the parts on its right side in 
preference to those on its left; and nature, in distributing the 
organs, invariably assigns each, either exclusively or in a more 
perfect condition, to such animals as can use it. So it is with 
tusks, and teeth, and horns, and spurs, and all such defensive 
and offensive weapons. 

In the Lobsters alone it is a matter of chance which claw is the 
larger, and this in either sex. Claws they must have, because 
they belong to a genus in which this is a constant character; but 



1930 



they have them in this indeterminate way, owing to imperfect 
formation and to their not using them for their natural purpose, 
but for locomotion. 

For a detailed account of the several parts of these animals, of 
their position and their differences, those parts being also 
included which distinguish the sexes, reference must be made 
to the treatises on Anatomy and to the Researches concerning 
Animals. 



We come now to the Cephalopoda. Their internal organs have 
already been described with those of other animals. Externally 
there is the trunk of the body, not distinctly defined, and in 
front of this the head surrounded by feet, which form a circle 
about the mouth and teeth, and are set between these and the 
eyes. Now in all other animals the feet, if there are any, are 
disposed in one of two ways; either before and behind or along 
the sides, the latter being the plan in such of them, for instance, 
as are bloodless and have numerous feet. But in the 
Cephalopoda there is a peculiar arrangement, different from 
either of these. For their feet are all placed at what may be 
called the fore end. The reason for this is that the hind part of 
their body has been drawn up close to the fore part, as is also 
the case in the turbinated Testacea. For the Testacea, while in 
some points they resemble the Crustacea, in others resemble 
the Cephalopoda. Their earthy matter is on the outside, and 
their fleshy substance within. So far they are like the Crustacea. 
But the general plan of their body is that of the Cephalopoda; 
and, though this is true in a certain degree of all the Testacea, it 
is more especially true of those turbinated species that have a 



1931 



spiral shell. Of this general plan, common to the two, we will 
speak presently. But let us first consider the case of quadrupeds 
and of man, where the arrangement is that of a straight line. Let 
A at the upper end of such a line be supposed to represent the 
mouth, then B the gullet, and C the stomach, and the intestine 
to run from this C to the excremental vent where D is inscribed. 
Such is the plan in sanguineous animals; and round this 
straight line as an axis are disposed the head and so-called 
trunk; the remaining parts, such as the anterior and posterior 
limbs, having been superadded by nature, merely to minister to 
these and for locomotion. 

In the Crustacea also and in Insects there is a tendency to a 
similar arrangement of the internal parts in a straight line; the 
distinction between these groups and the sanguineous animals 
depending on differences of the external organs which minister 
to locomotion. But the Cephalopoda and the turbinated 
Testacea have in common an arrangement which stands in 
contrast with this. For here the two extremities are brought 
together by a curve, as if one were to bend the straight line 
marked E until D came close to Such, then, is the disposition of 
the internal parts; and round these, in the Cephalopoda, is 
placed the sac (in the Poulps alone called a head), and, in the 
Testacea, the turbinate shell which corresponds to the sac. 
There is, in fact, only this difference between them, that the 
investing substance of the Cephalopoda is soft while the shell of 
the Testacea is hard, nature having surrounded their fleshy part 
with this hard coating as a protection because of their limited 
power of locomotion. In both classes, owing to this arrangement 
of the internal organs, the excrement is voided near the mouth; 
at a point below this orifice in the Cephalopoda, and in the 
Turbinata on one side of it. 

Such, then, is the explanation of the position of the feet in the 
Cephalopoda, and of the contrast they present to other animals 



1932 



in this matter. The arrangement, however, in the Sepias and the 
Calamaries is not precisely the same as in the Poulps, owing to 
the former having no other mode of progression than by 
swimming, while the latter not only swim but crawl. For in the 
former six of the feet are above the teeth and small, the outer 
one on either side being the biggest; while the remaining two, 
which make up the total weight, are below the mouth and are 
the biggest of all, just as the hind limbs in quadrupeds are 
stronger than the fore limbs. For it is these that have to support 
the weight, and to take the main part in locomotion. And the 
outer two of the upper six are bigger than the pair which 
intervene between them and the uppermost of all, because they 
have to assist the lowermost pair in their office. In the Poulps, 
on the other hand, the four central feet are the biggest. Again, 
though the number of feet is the same in all the Cephalopoda, 
namely eight, their length varies in different kinds, being short 
in the Sepias and the Calamaries, but greater in the Poulps. For 
in these latter the trunk of the body is of small bulk, while in 
the former it is of considerable size; and so in the one case 
nature has used the materials subtracted from the body to give 
length to the feet, while in the other she has acted in precisely 
the opposite way, and has given to the growth of the body what 
she has first taken from the feet. The Poulps, then, owing to the 
length of their feet, can not only swim but crawl, whereas in the 
other genera the feet are useless for the latter mode of 
progression, being small while the bulk of the body is 
considerable. These short feet would not enable their possessors 
to cling to the rocks and keep themselves from being torn off by 
the waves when these run high in times of storm; neither would 
they serve to lay hold of objects at all remote and bring them in; 
but, to supply these defects, the animal is furnished with two 
long proboscises, by which it can moor itself and ride at anchor 
like a ship in rough weather. These same processes serve also to 
catch prey at a distance and to bring it to the mouth. They are 



1933 



so used by both the Sepias and the Calamaries. In the Poulps 
the feet are themselves able to perform these offices, and there 
are consequently no proboscises. Proboscises and twining 
tentacles, with acetabula set upon them, act in the same way 
and have the same structure as those plaited instruments 
which were used by physicians of old to reduce dislocations of 
the fingers. Like these they are made by the interlacing of their 
fibres, and they act by pulling upon pieces of flesh and yielding 
substances. For the plaited fibres encircle an object in a 
slackened condition, and when they are put on the stretch they 
grasp and cling tightly to whatever it may be that is in contact 
with their inner surface. Since, then, the Cephalopoda have no 
other instruments with which to convey anything to themselves 
from without, than either twining tentacles, as in some species, 
or proboscises as in others, they are provided with these to 
serve as hands for offence and defence and other necessary 
uses. 

The acetabula are set in double line in all the Cephalopoda 
excepting in one kind of poulp, where there is but a single row. 
The length and the slimness which is part of the nature of this 
kind of poulp explain the exception. For a narrow space cannot 
possibly admit of more than a single row. This exceptional 
character, then, belongs to them, not because it is the most 
advantageous arrangement, but because it is the necessary 
consequence of their essential specific constitution. 

In all these animals there is a fin, encircling the sac. In the 
Poulps and the Sepias this fin is unbroken and continuous, as is 
also the case in the larger calamaries known as Teuthi. But in 
the smaller kind, called Teuthides, the fin is not only broader 
than in the Sepias and the Poulps, where it is very narrow, but, 
moreover, does not encircle the entire sac, but only begins in 
the middle of the side. The use of this fin is to enable the animal 
to swim, and also to direct its course. It acts, that is, like the 



1934 



rump-feathers in birds, or the tail-fin in fishes. In none is it so 
small or so indistinct as in the Poulps. For in these the body is of 
small bulk and can be steered by the feet sufficiently well 
without other assistance. 

The Insects, the Crustacea, the Testacea, and the Cephalopoda, 
have now been dealt with in turn; and their parts have been 
described, whether internal or external. 



10 

We must now go back to the animals that have blood, and 
consider such of their parts, already enumerated, as were before 
passed over. We will take the viviparous animals first, and, we 
have done with these, will pass on to the oviparous, and treat of 
them in like manner. 

The parts that border on the head, and on what is known as the 
neck and throat, have already been taken into consideration. All 
animals that have blood have a head; whereas in some 
bloodless animals, such as crabs, the part which represents a 
head is not clearly defined. As to the neck, it is present in all the 
Vivipara, but only in some of the Ovipara; for while those that 
have a lung also have a neck, those that do not inhale the outer 
air have none. The head exists mainly for the sake of the brain. 
For every animal that has blood must of necessity have a brain; 
and must, moreover, for reasons already given, have it placed in 
an opposite region to the heart. But the head has also been 
chosen by nature as the part in which to set some of the senses; 
because its blood is mixed in such suitable proportions as to 
ensure their tranquillity and precision, while at the same time it 
can supply the brain with such warmth as it requires. There is 
yet a third constituent superadded to the head, namely the part 



1935 



which ministers to the ingestion of food. This has been placed 
here by nature, because such a situation accords best with the 
general configuration of the body. For the stomach could not 
possibly be placed above the heart, seeing that this is the 
sovereign organ; and if placed below, as in fact it is, then the 
mouth could not possibly be placed there also. For this would 
have necessitated a great increase in the length of the body; and 
the stomach, moreover, would have been removed too far from 
the source of motion and of concoction. 

The head, then, exists for the sake of these three parts; while 
the neck, again, exists for the sake of the windpipe. For it acts as 
a defence to this and to the oesophagus, encircling them and 
keeping them from injury. In all other animals this neck is 
flexible and contains several vertebrae; but in wolves and lions 
it contains only a single bone. For the object of nature was to 
give these animals an organ which should be serviceable in the 
way of strength, rather than one that should be useful for any of 
the other purposes to which necks are subservient. 

Continuous with the head and neck is the trunk with the 
anterior limbs. In man the forelegs and forefeet are replaced by 
arms and by what we call hands. For of all animals man alone 
stands erect, in accordance with his godlike nature and essence. 
For it is the function of the god-like to think and to be wise; and 
no easy task were this under the burden of a heavy body, 
pressing down from above and obstructing by its weight the 
motions of the intellect and of the general sense. When, 
moreover, the weight and corporeal substance become 
excessive, the body must of necessity incline towards the 
ground. In such cases therefore nature, in order to give support 
to the body, has replaced the arms and hands by forefeet, and 
has thus converted the animal into a quadruped. For, as every 
animal that walks must of necessity have the two hinder feet, 
such an animal becomes a quadruped, its body inclining 



1936 



downwards in front from the weight which its soul cannot 
sustain. For all animals, man alone excepted, are dwarf-like in 
form. For the dwarf-like is that in which the upper part is large, 
while that which bears the weight and is used in progression is 
small. This upper part is what we call the trunk, which reaches 
from the mouth to the vent. In man it is duly proportionate to 
the part below, and diminishes much in its comparative size as 
the man attains to full growth. But in his infancy the contrary 
obtains, and the upper parts are large, while the lower part is 
small; so that the infant can only crawl, and is unable to walk; 
nay, at first cannot even crawl, but remains without motion. For 
all children are dwarfs in shape, but cease to be so as they 
become men, from the growth of their lower part; whereas in 
quadrupeds the reverse occurs, their lower parts being largest in 
youth, and advance of years bringing increased growth above, 
that is in the trunk, which extends from the rump to the head. 
Thus it is that colts are scarcely, if at all, below full-grown 
horses in height; and that while still young they can touch their 
heads with the hind legs, though this is no longer possible 
when they are older. Such, then, is the form of animals that 
have either a solid or a cloven hoof. But such as are 
polydactylous and without horns, though they too are of dwarf- 
like shape, are so in a less degree; and therefore the greater 
growth of the lower parts as compared with the upper is also 
small, being proportionate to this smaller deficiency. 

Dwarf-like again is the race of birds and fishes; and so in fact, as 
already has been said, is every animal that has blood. This is the 
reason why no other animal is so intelligent as man. For even 
among men themselves if we compare children with adults, or 
such adults as are of dwarf-like shape with such as are not, we 
find that, whatever other superiority the former may possess, 
they are at any rate deficient as compared with the latter in 
intelligence. The explanation, as already stated, is that their 
psychical principle is corporeal, and much impeded in its 



1937 



motions. Let now a further decrease occur in the elevating heat, 
and a further increase in the earthy matter, and the animals 
become smaller in bulk, and their feet more numerous, until at 
a later stage they become apodous, and extended full length on 
the ground. Then, by further small successions of change, they 
come to have their principal organ below; and at last their 
cephalic part becomes motionless and destitute of sensation. 
Thus the animal becomes a plant, that has its upper parts 
downwards and its lower parts above. For in plants the roots are 
the equivalents of mouth and head, while the seed has an 
opposite significance, for it is produced above it the extremities 
of the twigs. 

The reasons have now been stated why some animals have 
many feet, some only two, and others none; why, also, some 
living things are plants and others animals; and, lastly, why 
man alone of all animals stands erect. Standing thus erect, man 
has no need of legs in front, and in their stead has been 
endowed by nature with arms and hands. Now it is the opinion 
of Anaxagoras that the possession of these hands is the cause 
of man being of all animals the most intelligent. But it is more 
rational to suppose that his endowment with hands is the 
consequence rather than the cause of his superior intelligence. 
For the hands are instruments or organs, and the invariable 
plan of nature in distributing the organs is to give each to such 
animal as can make use of it; nature acting in this matter as 
any prudent man would do. For it is a better plan to take a 
person who is already a flute-player and give him a flute, than 
to take one who possesses a flute and teach him the art of flute- 
playing. For nature adds that which is less to that which is 
greater and more important, and not that which is more 
valuable and greater to that which is less. Seeing then that such 
is the better course, and seeing also that of what is possible 
nature invariably brings about the best, we must conclude that 
man does not owe his superior intelligence to his hands, but his 



1938 



hands to his superior intelligence. For the most intelligent of 
animals is the one who would put the most organs to use; and 
the hand is not to be looked on as one organ but as many; for it 
is, as it were, an instrument for further instruments. This 
instrument, therefore, - the hand - of all instruments the most 
variously serviceable, has been given by nature to man, the 
animal of all animals the most capable of acquiring the most 
varied handicrafts. 

Much in error, then, are they who say that the construction of 
man is not only faulty, but inferior to that of all other animals; 
seeing that he is, as they point out, bare-footed, naked, and 
without weapon of which to avail himself. For other animals 
have each but one mode of defence, and this they can never 
change; so that they must perform all the offices of life and 
even, so to speak, sleep with sandals on, never laying aside 
whatever serves as a protection to their bodies, nor changing 
such single weapon as they may chance to possess. But to man 
numerous modes of defence are open, and these, moreover, he 
may change at will; as also he may adopt such weapon as he 
pleases, and at such times as suit him. For the hand is talon, 
hoof, and horn, at will. So too it is spear, and sword, and 
whatsoever other weapon or instrument you please; for all 
these can it be from its power of grasping and holding them all. 
In harmony with this varied office is the form which nature has 
contrived for it. For it is split into several divisions, and these 
are capable of divergence. Such capacity of divergence does not 
prevent their again converging so as to form a single compact 
body, whereas had the hand been an undivided mass, 
divergence would have been impossible. The divisions also may 
be used singly or two together and in various combinations. The 
joints, moreover, of the fingers are well constructed for 
prehension and for pressure. One of these also, and this not 
long like the rest but short and thick, is placed laterally. For 
were it not so placed all prehension would be as impossible, as 



1939 



were there no hand at all. For the pressure of this digit is 
applied from below upwards, while the rest act from above 
downwards; an arrangement which is essential, if the grasp is 
to be firm and hold like a tight clamp. As for the shortness of 
this digit, the object is to increase its strength, so that it may be 
able, though but one, to counterbalance its more numerous 
opponents. Moreover, were it long it would be of no use. This is 
the explanation of its being sometimes called the great digit, in 
spite of its small size; for without it all the rest would be 
practically useless. The finger which stands at the other end of 
the row is small, while the central one of all is long, like a centre 
oar in a ship. This is rightly so; for it is mainly by the central 
part of the encircling grasp that a tool must be held when put to 
use. 

No less skilfully contrived are the nails. For, while in man these 
serve simply as coverings to protect the tips of the fingers, in 
other animals they are also used for active purposes; and their 
form in each case is suited to their office. 

The arms in man and the fore limbs in quadrupeds bend in 
contrary directions, this difference having reference to the 
ingestion of food and to the other offices which belong to these 
parts. For quadrupeds must of necessity bend their anterior 
limbs inwards that they may serve in locomotion, for they use 
them as feet. Not but what even among quadrupeds there is at 
any rate a tendency for such as are polydactylous to use their 
forefeet not only for locomotion but as hands. And they are in 
fact so used, as any one may see. For these animals seize hold of 
objects, and also repel assailants with their anterior limbs; 
whereas quadrupeds with solid hoofs use their hind legs for 
this latter purpose. For their fore limbs are not analogous to the 
arms and hands of man. 



1940 



It is this hand-like office of the anterior limbs which explains 
why in some of the polydactylous quadrupeds, such as wolves, 
lions, dogs, and leopards, there are actually five digits on each 
forefoot, though there are only four on each hind one. For the 
fifth digit of the foot corresponds to the fifth digit of the hand, 
and like it is called the big one. It is true that in the smaller 
polydactylous quadrupeds the hind feet also have each five 
toes. But this is because these animals are creepers; and the 
increased number of nails serves to give them a tighter grip, and 
so enables them to creep up steep places with greater facility, or 
even to run head downwards. 

In man between the arms, and in other animals between the 
forelegs, lies what is called the breast. This in man is broad, as 
one might expect; for as the arms are set laterally on the body, 
they offer no impediment to such expansion in this part. But in 
quadrupeds the breast is narrow, owing to the legs having to be 
extended in a forward direction in progression and locomotion. 

Owing to this narrowness the mammae of quadrupeds are 
never placed on the breast. But in the human body there is 
ample space in this part; moreover, the heart and neighbouring 
organs require protection, and for these reasons this part is 
fleshy and the mammae are placed upon it separately, side by 
side, being themselves of a fleshy substance in the male and 
therefore of use in the way just stated; while in the female, 
nature, in accordance with what we say is her frequent practice, 
makes them minister to an additional function, employing 
them as a store-place of nutriment for the offspring. The human 
mammae are two in number, in accordance with the division of 
the body into two halves, a right and a left. They are somewhat 
firmer than they would otherwise be, because the ribs in this 
region are joined together; while they form two separate 
masses, because their presence is in no wise burdensome. In 
other animals than man, it is impossible for the mammae to be 



1941 



placed on the breast between the forelegs, for they would 
interfere with locomotion; they are therefore disposed of 
otherwise, and in a variety of ways. Thus in such animals as 
produce but few at a birth, whether horned quadrupeds or 
those with solid hoofs, the mammae are placed in the region of 
the thighs, and are two in number, while in such as produce 
litters, or such as are polydactylous, the dugs are either 
numerous and placed laterally on the belly, as in swine and 
dogs, or are only two in number, being set, however, in the 
centre of the abdomen, as is the case in the lion. The 
explanation of this latter condition is not that the lion produces 
few at a birth, for sometimes it has more than two cubs at a 
time, but is to be found in the fact that this animal has no 
plentiful supply of milk. For, being a flesheater, it gets food at 
but rare intervals, and such nourishment as it obtains is all 
expended on the growth of its body. 

In the elephant also there are but two mammae, which are 
placed under the axillae of the fore limbs. The mammae are not 
more than two, because this animal has only a single young one 
at a birth; and they are not placed in the region of the thighs, 
because they never occupy that position in any polydactylous 
animal such as this. Lastly, they are placed above, close to the 
axillae, because this is the position of the foremost dugs in all 
animals whose dugs are numerous, and the dugs so placed give 
the most milk. Evidence of this is furnished by the sow. For she 
always presents these foremost dugs to the first-born of her 
litter. A single young one is of course a first-born, and so such 
animals as only produce a single young one must have these 
anterior dugs to present to it; that is they must have the dugs 
which are under the axillae. This, then, is the reason why the 
elephant has but two mammae, and why they are so placed. 
But, in such animals as have litters of young, the dugs are 
disposed about the belly; the reason being that more dugs are 
required by those that will have more young to nourish. Now it 



1942 



is impossible that these dugs should be set transversely in rows 
of more than two, one, that is, for each side of the body, the 
right and the left; they must therefore be placed lengthways, 
and the only place where there is sufficient length for this is the 
region between the front and hind legs. As to the animals that 
are not polydactylous but produce few at a birth, or have horns, 
their dugs are placed in the region of the thighs. The horse, the 
ass, the camel are examples; all of which bear but a single 
young one at a time, and of which the two former have solid 
hoofs, while in the last the hoof is cloven. As still further 
examples may be mentioned the deer, the ox, the goat, and all 
other similar animals. 

The explanation is that in these animals growth takes place in 
an upward direction; so that there must be an abundant 
collection of residual matter and of blood in the lower region, 
that is to say in the neighbourhood of the orifices for efflux, and 
here therefore nature has placed the mammae. For the place in 
which the nutriment is set in motion must also be the place 
whence nutriment can be derived by them. In man there are 
mammae in the male as well as in the female; but some of the 
males of other animals are without them. Such, for instance, is 
the case with horses, some stallions being destitute of these 
parts, while others that resemble their dams have them. Thus 
much then concerning the mammae. 

Next after the breast comes the region of the belly, which is left 
unenclosed by the ribs for a reason which has already been 
given; namely that there may be no impediment to the swelling 
which necessarily occurs in the food as it gets heated, nor to the 
expansion of the womb in pregnancy. 

At the extreme end of what is called the trunk are the parts 
concerned in the evacuation of the solid and also of the fluid 
residue. In all sanguineous animals with some few exceptions, 



1943 



and in all Vivipara without any exception at all, the same part 
which serves for the evacuation of the fluid residue is also 
made by nature to serve in sexual congress, and this alike in 
male and female. For the semen is a kind of fluid and residual 
matter. The proof of this will be given hereafter, but for the 
present let it taken for granted. (The like holds good of the 
menstrual fluid in women, and of the part where they emit 
semen. This also, however, is a matter of which a more accurate 
account will be given hereafter. For the present let it be simply 
stated as a fact, that the catamenia of the female like the semen 
of the male are residual matter. Both of them, moreover, being 
fluid, it is only natural that the parts which serve for voidance 
of the urine should give issue to residues which resemble it in 
character.) Of the internal structure of these parts, and of the 
differences which exist between the parts concerned with 
semen and the parts concerned with conception, a clear 
account is given in the book of Researches concerning Animals 
and in the treatises on Anatomy. Moreover, I shall have to speak 
of them again when I come to deal with Generation. As regards, 
however, the external shape of these parts, it is plain enough 
that they are adapted to their operations, as indeed of necessity 
they must be. There are, however, differences in the male organ 
corresponding to differences in the body generally. For all 
animals are not of an equally sinewy nature. This organ, again, 
is the only one that, independently of any morbid change, 
admits of augmentation and of diminution of bulk. The former 
condition is of service in copulation, while the other is required 
for the advantage of the body at large. For, were the organ 
constantly in the former condition, it would be an incumbrance. 
The organ therefore has been formed of such constituents as 
will admit of either state. For it is partly sinewy, partly 
cartilaginous, and thus is enabled either to contract or to 
become extended, and is capable of admitting air. 



1944 



All female quadrupeds void their urine backwards, because the 
position of the parts which this implies is useful to them in the 
act of copulation. This is the case with only some few males, 
such as the lynx, the lion, the camel, and the hare. No 
quadruped with a solid hoof is retromingent. 

The posterior portion of the body and the parts about the legs 
are peculiar in man as compared with quadrupeds. Nearly all 
these latter have a tail, and this whether they are viviparous or 
oviparous. For, even if the tail be of no great size, yet they have a 
kind of scut, as at any rate a small representative of it. But man 
is tail-less. He has, however, buttocks, which exist in none of the 
quadrupeds. His legs also are fleshy (as too are his thighs and 
feet); while the legs in all other animals that have any, whether 
viviparous or not, are fleshless, being made of sinew and bone 
and spinous substance. For all these differences there is, so to 
say, one common explanation, and this is that of all animals 
man alone stands erect. It was to facilitate the maintenance of 
this position that Nature made his upper parts light, taking 
away some of their corporeal substance, and using it to increase 
the weight of lithe parts below, so that the buttocks, the thighs, 
and the calves of the legs were all made fleshy. The character 
which she thus gave to the buttocks renders them at the same 
time useful in resting the body. For standing causes no fatigue 
to quadrupeds, and even the long continuance of this posture 
produces in them no weariness; for they are supported the 
whole time by four props, which is much as though they were 
lying down. But to man it is no task to remain for any length of 
time on his feet, his body demanding rest in a sitting position. 
This, then, is the reason why man has buttocks and fleshy legs; 
and the presence of these fleshy parts explains why he has no 
tail. For the nutriment which would otherwise go to the tail is 
used up in the production of these parts, while at the same time 
the existence of buttocks does away with the necessity of a tail. 
But in quadrupeds and other animals the reverse obtains. For 



1945 



they are of dwarf-like form, so that all the pressure of their 
weight and corporeal substance is on their upper part, and is 
withdrawn from the parts below. On this account they are 
without buttocks and have hard legs. In order, however, to cover 
and protect that part which serves for the evacuation of 
excrement, nature has given them a tail of some kind or other, 
subtracting for the purpose some of the nutriment which would 
otherwise go to the legs. Intermediate in shape between man 
and quadrupeds is the ape, belonging therefore to neither or to 
both, and having on this account neither tail nor buttocks; no 
tail in its character of biped, no buttocks in its character of 
quadruped. There is great diversity of so-called tails; and this 
organ like others is sometimes used by nature for by-purposes, 
being made to serve not only as a covering and protection to the 
fundament, but also for other uses and advantages of its 
possessor. 

There are differences in the feet of quadrupeds. For in some of 
these animals there is a solid hoof, and in others a hoof cloven 
into two, and again in others a foot divided into many parts. 

The hoof is solid when the body is large and the earthy matter 
present in great abundance; in which case the earth, instead of 
forming teeth and horns, is separated in the character of a nail, 
and being very abundant forms one continuous nail, that is a 
hoof, in place of several. This consumption of the earthy matter 
on the hoof explains why these animals, as a rule, have no 
huckle-bones; a second reason being that the presence of such a 
bone in the joint of the hind leg somewhat impedes its free 
motion. For extension and flexion can be made more rapidly in 
parts that have but one angle than in parts that have several. 
But the presence of a huckle-bone, as a connecting bolt, is the 
introduction as it were of a new limb-segment between the two 
ordinary ones. Such an addition adds to the weight of the foot, 
but renders the act of progression more secure. Thus it is that in 



1946 



such animals as have a hucklebone, it is only in the posterior 
and not in the anterior limbs that this bone is found. For the 
anterior limbs, moving as they do in advance of the others, 
require to be light and capable of ready flexion, whereas 
firmness and extensibility are what are wanted in the hind 
limbs. Moreover, a huckle-bone adds weight to the blow of a 
limb, and so renders it a suitable weapon of defence; and these 
animals all use their hind legs to protect themselves, kicking 
out with their heels against anything which annoys them. In 
the cloven-hoofed quadrupeds the lighter character of the hind 
legs admits of there being a huckle-bone; and the presence of 
the huckle-bone prevents them from having a solid hoof, the 
bony substance remaining in the joint, and therefore being 
deficient in the foot. As to the polydactylous quadrupeds, none 
of them have huckle-bones. For if they had they would not be 
polydactylous, but the divisions of the foot would only extend to 
that amount of its breadth which was covered by the huckle- 
bone. Thus it is that most of the animals that have huckle- 
bones are cloven-hoofed. 

Of all animals man has the largest foot in proportion to the size 
of the body. This is only what might be expected. For seeing that 
he is the only animal that stands erect, the two feet which are 
intended to bear all the weight of the body must be both long 
and broad. Equally intelligible is it that the proportion between 
the size of the fingers and that of the whole hand should be 
inverted in the case of the toes and feet. For the function of the 
hands is to take hold of objects and retain them by pressure; so 
that the fingers require to be long. For it is by its flexed portion 
that the hand grasps an object. But the function of the feet is to 
enable us to stand securely, and for this the undivided part of 
the foot requires to be of larger size than the toes. However, it is 
better for the extremity to be divided than to be undivided. For 
in an undivided foot disease of any one part would extend to 
the whole organ; whereas, if the foot be divided into separate 



1947 



digits, there is not an equal liability to such an occurrence. The 
digits, again, by being short would be less liable to injury. For 
these reasons the feet in man are many-toed, while the 
separate digits are of no great length. The toes, finally, are 
furnished with nails for the same reason as are the fingers, 
namely because such projecting parts are weak and therefore 
require special protection. 



11 

We have now done with such sanguineous animals as live on 
land and bring forth their young alive; and, having dealt with all 
their main kinds, we may pass on to such sanguineous animals 
as are oviparous. Of these some have four feet, while others 
have none. The latter form a single genus, namely the Serpents; 
and why these are apodous has been already explained in the 
dissertation on Animal Progression. Irrespective of this absence 
of feet, serpents resemble the oviparous quadrupeds in their 
conformation. 

In all these animals there is a head with its component parts; 
its presence being determined by the same causes as obtain in 
the case of other sanguineous animals; and in all, with the 
single exception of the river crocodile, there is a tongue inside 
the mouth. In this one exception there would seem to be no 
actual tongue, but merely a space left vacant for it. The reason is 
that a crocodile is in a way a land-animal and a water-animal 
combined. In its character of land-animal it has a space for a 
tongue; but in its character of water-animal it is without the 
tongue itself. For in some fishes, as has already been 
mentioned, there is no appearance whatsoever of a tongue, 
unless the mouth be stretched open very widely indeed; while 



1948 



in others it is indistinctly separated from the rest of the mouth. 
The reason for this is that a tongue would be of but little service 
to such animals, seeing that they are unable to chew their food 
or to taste it before swallowing, the pleasurable sensations they 
derive from it being limited to the act of deglutition. For it is in 
their passage down the gullet that solid edibles cause 
enjoyment, while it is by the tongue that the savour of fluids is 
perceived. Thus it is during deglutition that the oiliness, the 
heat, and other such qualities of food are recognized; and, in 
fact, the satisfaction from most solid edibles and dainties is 
derived almost entirely from the dilatation of the oesophagus 
during deglutition. This sensation, then, belongs even to 
animals that have no tongue, but while other animals have in 
addition the sensations of taste, tongueless animals have, we 
may say, no other satisfaction than it. What has now been said 
explains why intemperance as regards drinks and savoury fluids 
does not go hand in hand with intemperance as regards eating 
and solid relishes. 

In some oviparous quadrupeds, namely in lizards, the tongue is 
bifid, as also it is in serpents, and its terminal divisions are of 
hair-like fineness, as has already been described. (Seals also 
have a forked tongue.) This it is which accounts for all these 
animals being so fond of dainty food. The teeth in the four- 
footed Ovipara are of the sharp interfitting kind, like the teeth 
of fishes. The organs of all the senses are present and resemble 
those of other animals. Thus there are nostrils for smell, eves 
for vision, and ears for hearing. The latter organs, however, do 
not project from the sides of the head, but consist simply of the 
duct, as also is the case in birds. This is due in both cases to the 
hardness of the integument; birds having their bodies covered 
with feathers, and these oviparous quadrupeds with horny 
plates. These plates are equivalent to scales, but of a harder 
character. This is manifest in tortoises and river crocodiles, and 
also in the large serpents. For here the plates become stronger 



1949 



than the bones, being seemingly of the same substance as 
these. 

These animals have no upper eyelid, but close the eye with the 
lower lid In this they resemble birds, and the reason is the same 
as was assigned in their case. Among birds there are some that 
can not only thus close the eye, but can also blink by means of a 
membrane which comes from its corner. But none of the 
oviparous quadrupeds blink; for their eyes are harder than 
those of birds. The reason for this is that keen vision and far- 
sightedness are of very considerable service to birds, flying as 
they do in the air, whereas they would be of comparatively 
small use to the oviparous quadrupeds, seeing that they are all 
of troglodytic habits. 

Of the two separate portions which constitute the head, namely 
the upper part and the lower jaw, the latter in man and in the 
viviparous quadrupeds moves not only upwards and 
downwards, but also from side to side; while in fishes, and birds 
and oviparous quadrupeds, the only movement is up and down. 
The reason is that this latter movement is the one required in 
biting and dividing food, while the lateral movement serve to 
reduce substances to a pulp. To such animals, therefore, as have 
grinder-teeth this lateral motion is of service; but to those 
animals that have no grinders it would be quite useless, and 
they are therefore invariably without it. For nature never makes 
anything that is superfluous. While in all other animals it is the 
lower jaw that is movable, in the river crocodile it is 
exceptionally the upper. This is because the feet in this creature 
are so excessively small as to be useless for seizing and holding 
prey; on which account nature has given it a mouth that can 
serve for these purposes in their stead. For that direction of 
motion which will give the greater force to a blow will be the 
more serviceable one in holding or in seizing prey; and a blow 
from above is always more forcible than one from below. Seeing, 



1950 



then, that both the prehension and the mastication of food are 
offices of the mouth, and that the former of these two is the 
more essential in an animal that has neither hands nor suitably 
formed feet, these crocodiles will derive greater benefit from a 
motion of the upper jaw downwards than from a motion of the 
lower jaw upwards. The same considerations explain why crabs 
also move the upper division of each claw and not the lower. For 
their claws are substitutes for hands, and so require to be 
suitable for the prehension of food, and not for its 
comminution; for such comminution and biting is the office of 
teeth. In crabs, then, and in such other animals as are able to 
seize their food in a leisurely manner, inasmuch as their mouth 
is not called on to perform its office while they are still in the 
water, the two functions are assigned to different parts, 
prehension to the hands or feet, biting and comminution of 
food to the mouth. But in crocodiles the mouth has been so 
framed by nature as to serve both purposes, the jaws being 
made to move in the manner just described. 

Another part present in these animals is a neck, this being the 
necessary consequence of their having a lung. For the windpipe 
by which the air is admitted to the lung is of some length. If, 
however, the definition of a neck be correct, which calls it the 
portion between the head and the shoulders, a serpent can 
scarcely be said with the same right as the rest of these animals 
to have a neck, but only to have something analogous to that 
part of the body. It is a peculiarity of serpents, as compared with 
other animals allied to them, that they are able to turn their 
head backwards without stirring the rest of the body. The reason 
of this is that a serpent, like an insect, has a body that admits of 
being curled up, its vertebrae being cartilaginous and easily 
bent. The faculty in question belongs then to serpents simply as 
a necessary consequence of this character of their vertebrae; 
but at the same time it has a final cause, for it enables them to 
guard against attacks from behind. For their body, owing to its 



1951 



length and the absence of feet, is ill-suited for turning round 
and protecting the hinder parts; and merely to lift the head, 
without the power of turning it round, would be of no use 
whatsoever. 

The animals with which we are dealing have, moreover, a part 
which corresponds to the breast; but neither here nor elsewhere 
in their body have they any mammae, as neither has any bird or 
fish. This is a consequence of their having no milk; for a 
mamma is a receptacle for milk and, as it were, a vessel to 
contain it. This absence of milk is not peculiar to these animals, 
but is common to all such as are not internally viviparous. For 
all such produce eggs, and the nutriment which in Vivipara has 
the character of milk is in them engendered in the egg. Of all 
this, however, a clearer account will be given in the treatise on 
Generation. As to the mode in which the legs bend, a general 
account, in which all animals are considered, has already been 
given in the dissertation on Progression. These animals also 
have a tail, larger in some of them, smaller in others, and the 
reason for this has been stated in general terms in an earlier 
passage. 

Of all oviparous animals that live on land there is none so lean 
as the Chamaeleon. For there is none that has so little blood. 
The explanation of this is to be found in the psychical 
temperament of the creature. For it is of a timid nature, as the 
frequent changes it undergoes in its outward aspect testify. But 
fear is a refrigeration, and results from deficiency of natural 
heat and scantiness of blood. We have now done with such 
sanguineous animals as are quadrupedous and also such as are 
apodous, and have stated with sufficient completeness what 
external parts they possess, and for what reason they have 
them. 



1952 



12 

The differences of birds compared one with another are 
differences of magnitude, and of the greater or smaller 
development of parts. Thus some have long legs, others short 
legs; some have a broad tongue, others a narrow tongue; and so 
on with the other parts. There are few of their parts that differ 
save in size, taking birds by themselves. But when birds are 
compared with other animals the parts present differences of 
form also. For in some animals these are hairy, in others scaly, 
and in others have scale-like plates, while birds are feathered. 

Birds, then, are feathered, and this is a character common to 
them all and peculiar to them. Their feathers, too, are split and 
distinct in kind from the undivided feathers of insects; for the 
bird's feather is barbed, these are not; the bird's feather has a 
shaft, these have none. A second strange peculiarity which 
distinguishes birds from all other animals is their beak. For as in 
elephants the nostril serves in place of hands, and as in some 
insects the tongue serves in place of mouth, so in birds there is 
a beak, which, being bony, serves in place of teeth and lips. 
Their organs of sense have already been considered. 

All birds have a neck extending from the body; and the purpose 
of this neck is the same as in such other animals as have one. 
This neck in some birds is long, in others short; its length, as a 
general rule, being pretty nearly determined by that of the legs. 
For long-legged birds have a long neck, short-legged birds a 
short one, to which rule, however, the web-footed birds form an 
exception. For to a bird perched up on long legs a short neck 
would be of no use whatsoever in collecting food from the 
ground; and equally useless would be a long neck, if the legs 
were short. Such birds, again, as are carnivorous would find 
length in this part interfere greatly with their habits of life. For a 



1953 



long neck is weak, and it is on their superior strength that 
carnivorous birds depend for their subsistence. No bird, 
therefore, that has talons ever has an elongated neck. In web- 
footed birds, however, and in those other birds belonging to the 
same class, whose toes though actually separate have flat 
marginal lobes, the neck is elongated, so as to be suitable for 
collecting food from the water; while the legs are short, so as to 
serve in swimming. The beaks of birds, as their feet, vary with 
their modes of life. For in some the beak is straight, in others 
crooked; straight, in those who use it merely for eating; crooked, 
in those that live on raw flesh. For a crooked beak is an 
advantage in fighting; and these birds must, of course, get their 
food from the bodies of other animals, and in most cases by 
violence. In such birds, again, as live in marshes and are 
herbivorous the beak is broad and flat, this form being best 
suited for digging and cropping, and for pulling up plants. In 
some of these marsh birds, however, the beak is elongated, as 
too is the neck, the reason for this being that the bird get its 
food from some depth below the surface. For most birds of this 
kind, and most of those whose feet are webbed, either in their 
entirety or each part separately, live by preying on some of the 
smaller animals that are to be found in water, and use these 
parts for their capture, the neck acting as a fishing-rod, and the 
beak representing the line and hook. 

The upper and under sides of the body, that is of what in 
quadrupeds is called the trunk, present in birds one unbroken 
surface, and they have no arms or forelegs attached to it, but in 
their stead wings, which are a distinctive peculiarity of these 
animals; and, as these wings are substitutes for arms, their 
terminal segments lie on the back in the place of a shoulder- 
blade. 

The legs are two in number, as in man; not however, as in man, 
bent outwards, but bent inwards like the legs of a quadruped. 



1954 



The wings are bent like the forelegs of a quadruped, having 
their convexity turned outwards. That the feet should be two in 
number is a matter of necessity. For a bird is essentially a 
sanguineous animal, and at the same time essentially a winged 
animal; and no sanguineous animal has more than four points 
for motion In birds, then, as in those other sanguineous animals 
that live and move upon the ground, the limbs attached to the 
trunk are four in number. But, while in all the rest these four 
limbs consist of a pair of arms and a pair of legs, or of four legs 
as in quadrupeds, in birds the arms or forelegs are replaced by a 
pair of wings, and this is their distinctive character. For it is of 
the essence of a bird that it shall be able to fly; and it is by the 
extension of wings that this is made possible. Of all 
arrangements, then, the only possible, and so the necessary, one 
is that birds shall have two feet; for this with the wings will give 
them four points for motion. The breast in all birds is sharp- 
edged, and fleshy. The sharp edge is to minister to flight, for 
broad surfaces move with considerable difficulty, owing to the 
large quantity of air which they have to displace; while the 
fleshy character acts as a protection, for the breast, owing to its 
form, would be weak, were it not amply covered. 

Below the breast lies the belly, extending, as in quadrupeds and 
in man, to the vent and to the place where the legs are jointed 
to the trunk. 

Such, then, are the parts which lie between the wings and the 
legs. Birds like all other animals, whether produced viviparously 
or from eggs, have an umbilicus during their development, but, 
when the bird has attained to fuller growth, no signs of this 
remain visible. The cause of this is plainly to be seen during the 
process of development; for in birds the umbilical cord unites 
with the intestine, and is not a portion of the vascular system, 
as is the case in viviparous animals. 



1955 



Some birds, again, are well adapted for flight, their wings being 
large and strong. Such, for instance, are those that have talons 
and live on flesh. For their mode of life renders the power of 
flight a necessity, and it is on this account that their feathers 
are so abundant and their wings so large. Besides these, 
however, there are also other genera of birds that can fly well; 
all those, namely, that depend on speed for security, or that are 
of migratory habits. On the other hand, some kinds of birds 
have heavy bodies and are not constructed for flight. These are 
birds that are frugivorous and live on the ground, or that are 
able to swim and get their living in watery places. In those that 
have talons the body, without the wings, is small; for the 
nutriment is consumed in the production of these wings, and of 
the weapons and defensive appliances; whereas in birds that 
are not made for flight the contrary obtains, and the body is 
bulky and so of heavy weight. In some of these heavy-bodied 
birds the legs are furnished with what are called spurs, which 
replace the wings as a means of defence. Spurs and talons never 
co-exist in the same bird. For nature never makes anything 
superfluous; and if a bird can fly, and has talons, it has no use 
for spurs; for these are weapons for fighting on the ground, and 
on this account are an appanage of certain heavy-bodied birds. 
These latter, again, would find the possession of talons not only 
useless but actually injurious; for the claws would stick into the 
ground and interfere with progression. This is the reason why 
all birds with talons walk so badly, and why they never settle 
upon rocks. For the character of their claws is ill-suited for 
either action. 

All this is the necessary consequence of the process of 
development. For the earthy matter in the body issuing from it 
is converted into parts that are useful as weapons. That which 
flows upwards gives hardness or size to the beak; and, should 
any flow downwards, it either forms spurs upon the legs or 
gives size and strength to the claws upon the feet. But it does 



1956 



not at one and the same time produce both these results, one in 
the legs, the other in the claws; for such a dispersion of this 
residual matter would destroy all its efficiency. In other birds 
this earthy residue furnishes the legs with the material for their 
elongation; or sometimes, in place of this, fills up the 
interspaces between the toes. Thus it is simply a matter of 
necessity, that such birds as swim shall either be actually web- 
footed, or shall have a kind of broad blade-like margin running 
along the whole length of each distinct toe. The forms, then, of 
these feet are simply the necessary results of the causes that 
have been mentioned. Yet at the same time they are intended 
for the animal's advantage. For they are in harmony with the 
mode of life of these birds, who, living on the water, where their 
wings are useless, require that their feet shall be such as to 
serve in swimming. For these feet are so developed as to 
resemble the oars of a boat, or the fins of a fish; and the 
destruction of the foot-web has the same effect as the 
destruction of the fins; that is to say, it puts an end to all power 
of swimming. 

In some birds the legs are very long, the cause of this being that 
they inhabit marshes. I say the cause, because nature makes the 
organs for the function, and not the function for the organs. It 
is, then, because these birds are not meant for swimming that 
their feet are without webs, and it is because they live on 
ground that gives way under the foot that their legs and toes are 
elongated, and that these latter in most of them have an extra 
number of joints. Again, though all birds have the same material 
composition, they are not all made for flight; and in these, 
therefore, the nutriment that should go to their tail-feathers is 
spent on the legs and used to increase their size. This is the 
reason why these birds when they fly make use of their legs as a 
tail, stretching them out behind, and so rendering them 
serviceable, whereas in any other position they would be simply 
an impediment. 



1957 



In other birds, where the legs are short, these are held close 
against the belly during flight. In some cases this is merely to 
keep the feet out of the way, but in birds that have talons the 
position has a further purpose, being the one best suited for 
rapine. Birds that have a long and a thick neck keep it stretched 
out during flight; but those whose neck though long is slender 
fly with it coiled up. For in this position it is protected, and less 
likely to get broken, should the bird fly against any obstacle. 

In all birds there is an ischium, but so placed and of such length 
that it would scarcely be taken for an ischium, but rather for a 
second thigh-bone; for it extends as far as to the middle of the 
belly. The reason for this is that the bird is a biped, and yet is 
unable to stand erect. For if its ischium extended but a short 
way from the fundament, and then immediately came the leg, 
as is the case in man and in quadrupeds, the bird would be 
unable to stand up at all. For while man stands erect, and while 
quadrupeds have their heavy bodies propped up in front by the 
forelegs, birds can neither stand erect owing to their dwarf-like 
shape, nor have anterior legs to prop them up, these legs being 
replaced by wings. As a remedy for this Nature has given them a 
long ischium, and brought it to the centre of the body, fixing it 
firmly; and she has placed the legs under this central point, that 
the weight on either side may be equally balanced, and 
standing or progression rendered possible. Such then is the 
reason why a bird, though it is a biped, does not stand erect. 
Why its legs are destitute of flesh has also already been stated; 
for the reasons are the same as in the case of quadrupeds. 

In all birds alike, whether web-footed or not, the number of toes 
in each foot is four. For the Libyan ostrich may be disregarded 
for the present, and its cloven hoof and other discrepancies of 
structure as compared with the tribe of birds will be considered 
further on. Of these four toes three are in front, while the fourth 
points backward, serving, as a heel, to give steadiness. In the 



1958 



long-legged birds this fourth toe is much shorter than the 
others, as is the case with the Crex, but the number of their toes 
is not increased. The arrangement of the toes is such as has 
been described in all birds with the exception of the wryneck. 
Here only two of the toes are in front, the other two behind; and 
the reason for this is that the body of the wryneck is not 
inclined forward so much as that of other birds. All birds have 
testicles; but they are inside the body. The reason for this will be 
given in the treatise On the Generation of Animals. 



13 

Thus then are fashioned the parts of birds. But in fishes a still 
further stunting has occurred in the external parts. For here, for 
reasons already given, there are neither legs nor hands nor 
wings, the whole body from head to tail presenting one 
unbroken surface. This tail differs in different fishes, in some 
approximating in character to the fins, while in others, namely 
in some of the flat kinds, it is spinous and elongated, because 
the material which should have gone to the tail has been 
diverted thence and used to increase the breadth of the body. 
Such, for instance, is the case with the Torpedos, the Trygons, 
and whatever other Selachia there may be of like nature. In 
such fishes, then, the tail is spinous and long; while in some 
others it is short and fleshy, for the same reason which makes it 
spinous and long in the Torpedo. For to be short and fleshy 
comes to the same thing as to be long and less amply furnished 
with flesh. 

What has occurred in the Fishing- frog is the reverse of what has 
occurred in the other instances just given. For here the anterior 
and broad part of the body is not of a fleshy character, and so all 



1959 



the fleshy substance which has been thence diverted has been 
placed by nature in the tail and hinder portion of the body. 

In fishes there are no limbs attached to the body. For in 
accordance with their essential constitution they are swimming 
animals; and nature never makes anything superfluous or void 
of use. Now inasmuch as fishes are made swimming they have 
fins, and as they are not made for walking they are without feet; 
for feet are attached to the body that they may be of use in 
progression on land. Moreover, fishes cannot have feet, or any 
other similar limbs, as well as four fins; for they are essentially 
sanguineous animals. The Cordylus, though it has gills, has feet, 
for it has no fins but merely has its tail flattened out and loose 
in texture. 

Fishes, unless, like the Batos and the Trygon, they are broad and 
flat, have four fins, two on the upper and two on the under side 
of the body; and no fish ever has more than these. For, if it had, 
it would be a bloodless animal. 

The upper pair of fins is present in nearly all fishes, but not so 
the under pair; for these are wanting in some of those fishes 
that have long thick bodies, such as the eel, the conger, and a 
certain kind of Cestreus that is found in the lake at Siphae. 
When the body is still more elongated, and resembles that of a 
serpent rather than that of a fish, as is the case in the 
Smuraena, there are absolutely no fins at all; and locomotion is 
effected by the flexures of the body, the water being put to the 
same use by these fishes as is the ground by serpents. For 
serpents swim in water exactly in the same way as they glide on 
the ground. The reason for these serpent-like fishes being 
without fins is the same as that which causes serpents to be 
without feet; and what this is has been already stated in the 
dissertations on the Progression and the Motion of Animals. The 
reason was this. If the points of motion were four, motion would 



I960 



be effected under difficulties; for either the two pairs of fins 
would be close to each other, in which case motion would 
scarcely be possible, or they would be at a very considerable 
distance apart, in which case the long interval between them 
would be just as great an evil. On the other hand, to have more 
than four such motor points would convert the fishes into 
bloodless animals. A similar explanation applies to the case of 
those fishes that have only two fins. For here again the body is 
of great length and like that of a serpent, and its undulations do 
the office of the two missing fins. It is owing to this that such 
fishes can even crawl on dry ground, and can live there for a 
considerable time; and do not begin to gasp until they have 
been for a considerable time out of the water, while others, 
whose nature is akin to that of land-animals, do not even do as 
much as that. In such fishes as have but two fins it is the upper 
pair (pectorals) that is present, excepting when the flat broad 
shape of the body prevents this. The fins in such cases are 
placed at the head, because in this region there is no elongation, 
which might serve in the absence of fins as a means of 
locomotion; whereas in the direction of the tail there is a 
considerable lengthening out in fishes of this conformation. As 
for the Bati and the like, they use the marginal part of their 
flattened bodies in place of fins for swimming. 

In the Torpedo and the Fishing-frog the breadth of the anterior 
part of the body is not so great as to render locomotion by fins 
impossible, but in consequence of it the upper pair (pectorals) 
are placed further back and the under pair (ventrals) are placed 
close to the head, while to compensate for this advancement 
they are reduced in size so as to be smaller than the upper ones. 
In the Torpedo the two upper fins (pectorals) are placed on the 
tail, and the fish uses the broad expansion of its body to supply 
their place, each lateral half of its circumference serving the 
office of a fin. 



1961 



The head, with its several parts, as also the organs of sense, 
have already come under consideration. 

There is one peculiarity which distinguishes fishes from all 
other sanguineous animals, namely, the possession of gills. Why 
they have these organs has been set forth in the treatise on 
Respiration. These gills are in most fishes covered by opercula, 
but in the Selachia, owing to the skeleton being cartilaginous, 
there are no such coverings. For an operculum requires fish- 
spine for its formation, and in other fishes the skeleton is made 
of this substance, whereas in the Selachia it is invariably formed 
of cartilage. Again, while the motions of spinous fishes are 
rapid, those of the Selachia are sluggish, inasmuch as they have 
neither fish-spine nor sinew; but an operculum requires 
rapidity of motion, seeing that the office of the gills is to 
minister as it were to expiration. For this reason in Selachia the 
branchial orifices themselves effect their own closure, and thus 
there is no need for an operculum to ensure its taking place 
with due rapidity. In some fishes the gills are numerous, in 
others few in number; in some again they are double, in others 
single. The last gill in most cases is single. For a detailed 
account of all this, reference must be made to the treatises on 
Anatomy, and to the book of Researches concerning Animals. 

It is the abundance or the deficiency of the cardiac heat which 
determines the numerical abundance or deficiency of the gills. 
For, the greater an animal's heat, the more rapid and the more 
forcible does it require the branchial movement to be; and 
numerous and double gills act with more force and rapidity 
than such as are few and single. Thus, too, it is that some fishes 
that have but few gills, and those of comparatively small 
efficacy, can live out of water for a considerable time; for in 
them there is no great demand for refrigeration. Such, for 
example, are the eel and all other fishes of serpent-like form. 



1962 



Fishes also present diversities as regards the mouth. For in 
some this is placed in front, at the very extremity of the body, 
while in others, as the dolphin and the Selachia, it is placed on 
the under surface; so that these fishes turn on the back in order 
to take their food. The purpose of Nature in this was apparently 
not merely to provide a means of salvation for other animals, by 
allowing them opportunity of escape during the time lost in the 
act of turning - for all the fishes with this kind of mouth prey 
on living animals - but also to prevent these fishes from giving 
way too much to their gluttonous ravening after food. For had 
they been able to seize their prey more easily than they do, they 
would soon have perished from over-repletion. An additional 
reason is that the projecting extremity of the head in these 
fishes is round and small, and therefore cannot admit of a wide 
opening. 

Again, even when the mouth is not placed on the under surface, 
there are differences in the extent to which it can open. For in 
some cases it can gape widely, while in others it is set at the 
point of a small tapering snout; the former being the case in 
carnivorous fishes, such as those with sharp interfitting teeth, 
whose strength lies in their mouth, while the latter is its form 
in all such as are not carnivorous. 

The skin is in some fishes covered with scales (the scale of a 
fish is a thin and shiny film, and therefore easily becomes 
detached from the surface of the body). In others it is rough, as 
for instance in the Rhine, the Batos, and the like. Fewest of all 
are those whose skin is smooth. The Selachia have no scales, 
but a rough skin. This is explained by their cartilaginous 
skeleton. For the earthy material which has been thence 
diverted is expended by nature upon the skin. 

No fish has testicles either externally or internally; as indeed 
have no apodous animals, among which of course are included 



1963 



the serpents. One and the same orifice serves both for the 
excrement and for the generative secretions, as is the case also 
in all other oviparous animals, whether two-footed or four- 
footed, inasmuch as they have no urinary bladder and form no 
fluid excretion. 

Such then are the characters which distinguish fishes from all 
other animals. But dolphins and whales and all such Cetacea 
are without gills; and, having a lung, are provided with a blow- 
hole; for this serves them to discharge the sea-water which has 
been taken into the mouth. For, feeding as they do in the water, 
they cannot but let this fluid enter into their mouth, and, having 
let it in, they must of necessity let it out again. The use of gills, 
however, as has been explained in the treatise on Respiration, is 
limited to such animals as do not breathe; for no animal can 
possibly possess gills and at the same time be a respiratory 
animal. In order, therefore, that these Cetacea may discharge 
the water, they are provided with a blow-hole. This is placed in 
front of the brain; for otherwise it would have cut off the brain 
from the spine. The reason for these animals having a lung and 
breathing, is that animals of large size require an excess of heat, 
to facilitate their motion. A lung, therefore, is placed within 
their body, and is fully supplied with blood-heat. These 
creatures are after a fashion land and water animals in one. For 
so far as they are inhalers of air they resemble land-animals, 
while they resemble water-animals in having no feet and in 
deriving their food from the sea. So also seals lie halfway 
between land and water animals, and bats half-way between 
animals that live on the ground and animals that fly; and so 
belong to both kinds or to neither. For seals, if looked on as 
water-animals, are yet found to have feet; and, if looked on as 
land-animals, are yet found to have fins. For their hind feet are 
exactly like the fins of fishes; and their teeth also are sharp and 
interfitting as in fishes. Bats again, if regarded as winged 
animals, have feet; and, if regarded as quadrupeds, are without 



1964 



them. So also they have neither the tail of a quadruped nor the 
tail of a bird; no quadruped's tail, because they are winted 
animals; no bird's tail, because they are terrestrial. This absence 
of tail is the result of necessity. For bats fly by means of a 
membrane, but no animal, unless it has barbed feathers, has the 
tail of a bird; for a bird's tail is composed of such feathers. As for 
a quadruped's tail, it would be an actual impediment, if present 
among the feathers. 



14 

Much the same may be said also of the Libyan ostrich. For it has 
some of the characters of a bird, some of the characters of a 
quadruped. It differs from a quadruped in being feathered; and 
from a bird in being unable to soar aloft and in having feathers 
that resemble hair and are useless for flight. Again, it agrees 
with quadrupeds in having upper eyelashes, which are the more 
richly supplied with hairs because the parts about the head and 
the upper portion of the neck are bare; and it agrees with birds 
in being feathered in all the parts posterior to these. Further, it 
resembles a bird in being a biped, and a quadruped in having a 
cloven hoof; for it has hoofs and not toes. The explanation of 
these peculiarities is to be found in its bulk, which is that of a 
quadruped rather than that of a bird. For, speaking generally, a 
bird must necessarily be of very small size. For a body of heavy 
bulk can with difficulty be raised into the air. 

Thus much then as regards the parts of animals. We have 
discussed them all, and set forth the cause why each exists; and 
in so doing we have severally considered each group of animals. 
We must now pass on, and in due sequence must next deal 
with the question of their generation. 



1965 



Aristotle - On the Motion of Animals 
[Translated by A. S. L. Farquharson] 



Elsewhere we have investigated in detail the movement of 
animals after their various kinds, the differences between them, 
and the reasons for their particular characters (for some 
animals fly, some swim, some walk, others move in various 
other ways); there remains an investigation of the common 
ground of any sort of animal movement whatsoever. 

Now we have already determined (when we were discussing 
whether eternal motion exists or not, and its definition, if it 
does exist) that the origin of all other motions is that which 
moves itself, and that the origin of this is the immovable, and 
that the prime mover must of necessity be immovable. And we 
must grasp this not only generally in theory, but also by 
reference to individuals in the world of sense, for with these in 
view we seek general theories, and with these we believe that 
general theories ought to harmonize. Now in the world of sense 
too it is plainly impossible for movement to be initiated if there 
is nothing at rest, and before all else in our present subject - 
animal life. For if one of the parts of an animal be moved, 
another must be at rest, and this is the purpose of their joints; 
animals use joints like a centre, and the whole member, in 
which the joint is, becomes both one and two, both straight and 
bent, changing potentially and actually by reason of the joint. 
And when it is bending and being moved one of the points in 
the joint is moved and one is at rest, just as if the points A and 
D of a diameter were at rest, and B were moved, and DAC were 



1966 



generated. However, in the geometrical illustration, the centre is 
held to be altogether indivisible (for in mathematics motion is a 
fiction, as the phrase goes, no mathematical entity being really 
moved), whereas in the case of joints the centres become now 
one potentially and divided actually, and now one actually and 
divided potentially. But still the origin of movement, qua origin, 
always remains at rest when the lower part of a limb is moved; 
for example, the elbow joint, when the forearm is moved, and 
the shoulder, when the whole arm; the knee when the tibia is 
moved, and the hip when the whole leg. Accordingly it is plain 
that each animal as a whole must have within itself a point at 
rest, whence will be the origin of that which is moved, and 
supporting itself upon which it will be moved both as a 
complete whole and in its members. 



But the point of rest in the animal is still quite ineffectual 
unless there be something without which is absolutely at rest 
and immovable. Now it is worth while to pause and consider 
what has been said, for it involves a speculation which extends 
beyond animals even to the motion and march of the universe. 
For just as there must be something immovable within the 
animal, if it is to be moved, so even more must there be without 
it something immovable, by supporting itself upon which that 
which is moved moves. For were that something always to give 
way (as it does for mice walking in grain or persons walking in 
sand) advance would be impossible, and neither would there be 
any walking unless the ground were to remain still, nor any 
flying or swimming were not the air and the sea to resist. And 
this which resists must needs be different from what is moved, 
the whole of it from the whole of that, and what is thus 



1967 



immovable must be no part of what is moved; otherwise there 
will be no movement. Evidence of this lies in the problem why it 
is that a man easily moves a boat from outside, if he push with 
a pole, putting it against the mast or some other part, but if he 
tried to do this when in the boat itself he would never move it, 
no not giant Tityus himself nor Boreas blowing from inside the 
ship, if he really were blowing in the way painters represent 
him; for they paint him sending the breath out from the boat. 
For whether one blew gently or so stoutly as to make a very 
great wind, and whether what were thrown or pushed were 
wind or something else, it is necessary in the first place to be 
supported upon one of one's own members which is at rest and 
so to push, and in the second place for this member, either 
itself, or that of which it is a part, to remain at rest, fixing itself 
against something external to itself. Now the man who is 
himself in the boat, if he pushes, fixing himself against the boat, 
very naturally does not move the boat, because what he pushes 
against should properly remain at rest. Now what he is trying to 
move, and what he is fixing himself against is in his case the 
same. If, however, he pushes or pulls from outside he does move 
it, for the ground is no part of the boat. 



Here we may ask the difficult question whether if something 
moves the whole heavens this mover must be immovable, and 
moreover be no part of the heavens, nor in the heavens. For 
either it is moved itself and moves the heavens, in which case it 
must touch something immovable in order to create movement, 
and then this is no part of that which creates movement; or if 
the mover is from the first immovable it will equally be no part 
of that which is moved. In this point at least they argue 



1968 



correctly who say that as the Sphere is carried round in a circle 
no single part remains still, for then either the whole would 
necessarily stand still or its continuity be torn asunder; but they 
argue less well in supposing that the poles have a certain force, 
though conceived as having no magnitude, but as merely 
termini or points. For besides the fact that no such things have 
any substantial existence it is impossible for a single movement 
to be initiated by what is twofold; and yet they make the poles 
two. From a review of these difficulties we may conclude that 
there is something so related to the whole of Nature, as the 
earth is to animals and things moved by them. 

And the mythologists with their fable of Atlas setting his feet 
upon the earth appear to have based the fable upon intelligent 
grounds. They make Atlas a kind of diameter twirling the 
heavens about the poles. Now as the earth remains still this 
would be reasonable enough, but their theory involves them in 
the position that the earth is no part of the universe. And 
further the force of that which initiates movement must be 
made equal to the force of that which remains at rest. For there 
is a definite quantity of force or power by dint of which that 
which remains at rest does so, just as there is of force by dint of 
which that which initiates movement does so; and as there is a 
necessary proportion between opposite motions, so there is 
between absences of motion. Now equal forces are unaffected 
by one another, but are overcome by a superiority of force. And 
so in their theory Atlas, or whatever similar power initiates 
movement from within, must exert no more force than will 
exactly balance the stability of the earth - otherwise the earth 
will be moved out of her place in the centre of things. For as the 
pusher pushes so is the pushed pushed, and with equal force. 
But the prime mover moves that which is to begin with at rest, 
so that the power it exerts is greater, rather than equal and like 
to the power which produces absence of motion in that which is 
moved. And similarly also the power of what is moved and so 



1969 



moves must be greater than the power of that which is moved 
but does not initiate movement. Therefore the force of the earth 
in its immobility will have to be as great as the force of the 
whole heavens, and of that which moves the heavens. But if 
that is impossible, it follows that the heavens cannot possibly 
be moved by any force of this kind inside them. 



There is a further difficulty about the motions of the parts of 
the heavens which, as akin to what has gone before, may be 
considered next. For if one could overcome by force of motion 
the immobility of the earth he would clearly move it away from 
the centre. And it is plain that the power from which this force 
would originate will not be infinite, for the earth is not infinite 
and therefore its weight is not. Now there are more senses than 
one of the word 'impossible'. When we say it is impossible to 
see a sound, and when we say it is impossible to see the men in 
the moon, we use two senses of the word; the former is of 
necessity, the latter, though their nature is to be seen, cannot as 
a fact be seen by us. Now we suppose that the heavens are of 
necessity impossible to destroy and to dissolve, whereas the 
result of the present argument would be to do away with this 
necessity. For it is natural and possible for a motion to exist 
greater than the force by dint of which the earth is at rest, or 
than that by dint of which Fire and Aether are moved. If then 
there are superior motions, these will be dissolved in succession 
by one another: and if there actually are not, but might possibly 
be (for the earth cannot be infinite because no body can 
possibly be infinite), there is a possibility of the heavens being 
dissolved. For what is to prevent this coming to pass, unless it 



1970 



be impossible? And it is not impossible unless the opposite is 
necessary. This difficulty, however, we will discuss elsewhere. 

To resume, must there be something immovable and at rest 
outside of what is moved, and no part of it, or not? And must 
this necessarily be so also in the case of the universe? Perhaps it 
would be thought strange were the origin of movement inside. 
And to those who so conceive it the word of Homer would 
appear to have been well spoken: 

'Nay, ye would not pull Zeus, highest of all from heaven to the 
plain, no not even if ye toiled right hard; come, all ye gods and 
goddesses! Set hands to the chain'; for that which is entirely 
immovable cannot possibly be moved by anything. And herein 
lies the solution of the difficulty stated some time back, the 
possibility or impossibility of dissolving the system of the 
heavens, in that it depends from an original which is 
immovable. 

Now in the animal world there must be not only an immovable 
without, but also within those things which move in place, and 
initiate their own movement. For one part of an animal must be 
moved, and another be at rest, and against this the part which 
is moved will support itself and be moved; for example, if it 
move one of its parts; for one part, as it were, supports itself 
against another part at rest. 

But about things without life which are moved one might ask 
the question whether all contain in themselves both that which 
is at rest and that which initiates movement, and whether they 
also, for instance fire, earth, or any other inanimate thing, must 
support themselves against something outside which is at rest. 
Or is this impossible and must it not be looked for rather in 
those primary causes by which they are set in motion? For all 
things without life are moved by something other, and the 
origin of all things so moved are things which move themselves. 



1971 



And out of these we have spoken about animals (for they must 
all have in themselves that which is at rest, and without them 
that against which they are supported); but whether there is 
some higher and prime mover is not clear, and an origin of that 
kind involves a different discussion. Animals at any rate which 
move themselves are all moved supporting themselves on what 
is outside them, even when they inspire and expire; for there is 
no essential difference between casting a great and a small 
weight, and this is what men do when they spit and cough and 
when they breathe in and breathe out. 



But is it only in that which moves itself in place that there must 
be a point at rest, or does this hold also of that which causes its 
own qualitative changes, and its own growth? Now the question 
of original generation and decay is different; for if there is, as 
we hold, a primary movement, this would be the cause of 
generation and decay, and probably of all the secondary 
movements too. And as in the universe, so in the animal world 
this is the primary movement, when the creature attains 
maturity; and therefore it is the cause of growth, when the 
creature becomes the cause of its own growth, and the cause 
too of alteration. But if this is not the primary movement then 
the point at rest is not necessary. However, the earliest growth 
and alteration in the living creature arise through another and 
by other channels, nor can anything possibly be the cause of its 
own generation and decay, for the mover must exist before the 
moved, the begetter before the begotten, and nothing is prior to 
itself. 



1972 



Now whether the soul is moved or not, and how it is moved if it 
be moved, has been stated before in our treatise concerning it. 
And since all inorganic things are moved by some other thing - 
and the manner of the movement of the first and eternally 
moved, and how the first mover moves it, has been determined 
before in our Metaphysics, it remains to inquire how the soul 
moves the body, and what is the origin of movement in a living 
creature. For, if we except the movement of the universe, things 
with life are the causes of the movement of all else, that is of all 
that are not moved by one another by mutual impact. And so all 
their motions have a term or limit, inasmuch as the movements 
of things with life have such. For all living things both move and 
are moved with some object, so that this is the term of all their 
movement, the end, that is, in view. Now we see that the living 
creature is moved by intellect, imagination, purpose, wish, and 
appetite. And all these are reducible to mind and desire. For 
both imagination and sensation are on common ground with 
mind, since all three are faculties of judgement though differing 
according to distinctions stated elsewhere. Will, however, 
impulse, and appetite, are all three forms of desire, while 
purpose belongs both to intellect and to desire. Therefore the 
object of desire or of intellect first initiates movement, not, that 
is, every object of intellect, only the end in the domain of 
conduct. Accordingly among goods that which moves is a 
practical end, not the good in its whole extent. For it initiates 
movement only so far as something else is for its sake, or so far 
as it is the object of that which is for the sake of something else. 
And we must suppose that a seeming good may take the room 
of actual good, and so may the pleasant, which is itself a 
seeming good. From these considerations it is clear that in one 
regard that which is eternally moved by the eternal mover is 



1973 



moved in the same way as every living creature, in another 
regard differently, and so while it is moved eternally, the 
movement of living creatures has a term. Now the eternal 
beautiful, and the truly and primarily good (which is not at one 
time good, at another time not good), is too divine and precious 
to be relative to anything else. The prime mover then moves, 
itself being unmoved, whereas desire and its faculty are moved 
and so move. But it is not necessary for the last in the chain of 
things moved to move something else; wherefore it is plainly 
reasonable that motion in place should be the last of what 
happens in the region of things happening, since the living 
creature is moved and goes forward by reason of desire or 
purpose, when some alteration has been set going on the 
occasion of sensation or imagination. 



But how is it that thought (viz. sense, imagination, and thought 
proper) is sometimes followed by action, sometimes not; 
sometimes by movement, sometimes not? What happens 
seems parallel to the case of thinking and inferring about the 
immovable objects of science. There the end is the truth seen 
(for, when one conceives the two premisses, one at once 
conceives and comprehends the conclusion), but here the two 
premisses result in a conclusion which is an action - for 
example, one conceives that every man ought to walk, one is a 
man oneself: straightway one walks; or that, in this case, no 
man should walk, one is a man: straightway one remains at 
rest. And one so acts in the two cases provided that there is 
nothing in the one case to compel or in the other to prevent. 
Again, I ought to create a good, a house is good: straightway I 
make a house. I need a covering, a coat is a covering: I need a 



1974 



coat. What I need I ought to make, I need a coat: I make a coat. 
And the conclusion I must make a coat is an action. And the 
action goes back to the beginning or first step. If there is to be a 
coat, one must first have B, and if B then A, so one gets A to 
begin with. Now that the action is the conclusion is clear. But 
the premisses of action are of two kinds, of the good and of the 
possible. 

And as in some cases of speculative inquiry we suppress one 
premise so here the mind does not stop to consider at all an 
obvious minor premise; for example if walking is good for man, 
one does not dwell upon the minor 'I am a man'. And so what 
we do without reflection, we do quickly. For when a man 
actualizes himself in relation to his object either by perceiving, 
or imagining or conceiving it, what he desires he does at once. 
For the actualizing of desire is a substitute for inquiry or 
reflection. I want to drink, says appetite; this is drink, says sense 
or imagination or mind: straightway I drink. In this way living 
creatures are impelled to move and to act, and desire is the last 
or immediate cause of movement, and desire arises after 
perception or after imagination and conception. And things that 
desire to act now create and now act under the influence of 
appetite or impulse or of desire or wish. 

The movements of animals may be compared with those of 
automatic puppets, which are set going on the occasion of a 
tiny movement; the levers are released, and strike the twisted 
strings against one another; or with the toy wagon. For the child 
mounts on it and moves it straight forward, and then again it is 
moved in a circle owing to its wheels being of unequal diameter 
(the smaller acts like a centre on the same principle as the 
cylinders). Animals have parts of a similar kind, their organs, 
the sinewy tendons to wit and the bones; the bones are like the 
wooden levers in the automaton, and the iron; the tendons are 
like the strings, for when these are tightened or leased 



1975 



movement begins. However, in the automata and the toy wagon 
there is no change of quality, though if the inner wheels became 
smaller and greater by turns there would be the same circular 
movement set up. In an animal the same part has the power of 
becoming now larger and now smaller, and changing its form, 
as the parts increase by warmth and again contract by cold and 
change their quality. This change of quality is caused by 
imaginations and sensations and by ideas. Sensations are 
obviously a form of change of quality, and imagination and 
conception have the same effect as the objects so imagined and 
conceived For in a measure the form conceived be it of hot or 
cold or pleasant or fearful is like what the actual objects would 
be, and so we shudder and are frightened at a mere idea. Now 
all these affections involve changes of quality, and with those 
changes some parts of the body enlarge, others grow smaller. 
And it is not hard to see that a small change occurring at the 
centre makes great and numerous changes at the 
circumference, just as by shifting the rudder a hair's breadth 
you get a wide deviation at the prow. And further, when by 
reason of heat or cold or some kindred affection a change is set 
up in the region of the heart, even in an imperceptibly small 
part of the heart, it produces a vast difference in the periphery 
of the body, - blushing, let us say, or turning white, goose-skin 
and shivers and their opposites. 



8 

But to return, the object we pursue or avoid in the field of action 
is, as has been explained, the original of movement, and upon 
the conception and imagination of this there necessarily follows 
a change in the temperature of the body. For what is painful we 
avoid, what is pleasing we pursue. We are, however, 



1976 



unconscious of what happens in the minute parts; still anything 
painful or pleasing is generally speaking accompanied by a 
definite change of temperature in the body. One may see this by 
considering the affections. Blind courage and panic fears, erotic 
motions, and the rest of the corporeal affections, pleasant and 
painful, are all accompanied by a change of temperature, some 
in a particular member, others in the body generally. So, 
memories and anticipations, using as it were the reflected 
images of these pleasures and pains, are now more and now 
less causes of the same changes of temperature. And so we see 
the reason of nature's handiwork in the inward parts, and in the 
centres of movement of the organic members; they change from 
solid to moist, and from moist to solid, from soft to hard and 
vice versa. And so when these are affected in this way, and 
when besides the passive and active have the constitution we 
have many times described, as often as it comes to pass that 
one is active and the other passive, and neither of them falls 
short of the elements of its essence, straightway one acts and 
the other responds. And on this account thinking that one 
ought to go and going are virtually simultaneous, unless there 
be something else to hinder action. The organic parts are 
suitably prepared by the affections, these again by desire, and 
desire by imagination. Imagination in its turn depends either 
upon conception or sense-perception. And the simultaneity and 
speed are due to the natural correspondence of the active and 
passive. 

However, that which first moves the animal organism must be 
situate in a definite original. Now we have said that a joint is 
the beginning of one part of a limb, the end of another. And so 
nature employs it sometimes as one, sometimes as two. When 
movement arises from a joint, one of the extreme points must 
remain at rest, and the other be moved (for as we explained 
above the mover must support itself against a point at rest); 
accordingly, in the case of the elbow-joint, the last point of the 



1977 



forearm is moved but does not move anything, while, in the 
flexion, one point of the elbow, which lies in the whole forearm 
that is being moved, is moved, but there must also be a point 
which is unmoved, and this is our meaning when we speak of a 
point which is in potency one, but which becomes two in actual 
exercise. Now if the arm were the living animal, somewhere in 
its elbow-joint would be situate the original seat of the moving 
soul. Since, however, it is possible for a lifeless thing to be so 
related to the hand as the forearm is to the upper (for example, 
when a man moves a stick in his hand), it is evident that the 
soul, the original of movement, could not lie in either of the two 
extreme points, neither, that is, in the last point of the stick 
which is moved, nor in the original point which causes 
movement. For the stick too has an end point and an originative 
point by reference to the hand. Accordingly, this example shows 
that the moving original which derives from the soul is not in 
the stick and if not, then not in the hand; for a precisely similar 
relation obtains between the hand and the wrist, as between 
the wrist and the elbow. In this matter it makes no difference 
whether the part is a continuous part of the body or not; the 
stick may be looked at as a detached part of the whole. It 
follows then of necessity that the original cannot lie in any 
individual origin which is the end of another member, even 
though there may lie another part outside the one in question. 
For example, relatively to the end point of the stick the hand is 
the original, but the original of the hand's movement is in the 
wrist. And so if the true original is not in the hand, be-there is 
still something higher up, neither is the true original in the 
wrist, for once more if the elbow is at rest the whole part below 
it can be moved as a continuous whole. 



1978 



Now since the left and the right sides are symmetrical, and 
these opposites are moved simultaneously, it cannot be that the 
left is moved by the right remaining stationary, nor vice versa; 
the original must always be in what lies above both. Therefore, 
the original seat of the moving soul must be in that which lies 
in the middle, for of both extremes the middle is the limiting 
point; and this is similarly related to the movements from 
above [and below,] those that is from the head, and to the bones 
which spring from the spinal column, in creatures that have a 
spinal column. 

And this is a reasonable arrangement. For the sensorium is in 
our opinion in the centre too; and so, if the region of the original 
of movement is altered in structure through sense-perception 
and thus changes, it carries with it the parts that depend upon 
it and they too are extended or contracted, and in this way the 
movement of the creature necessarily follows. And the middle 
of the body must needs be in potency one but in action more 
than one; for the limbs are moved simultaneously from the 
original seat of movement, and when one is at rest the other is 
moved. For example, in the line BAC, B is moved, and A is the 
mover. There must, however, be a point at rest if one is to move, 
the other to be moved. A (AE) then being one in potency must be 
two in action, and so be a definite spatial magnitude not a 
mathematical point. Again, C may be moved simultaneously 
with B. Both the originals then in A must move and be, and so 
there must be something other than them which moves but is 
not moved. For otherwise, when the movement begins, the 
extremes, i.e. the originals, in A would rest upon one another, 
like two men putting themselves back to back and so moving 
their legs. There must then be some one thing which moves 
both. This something is the soul, distinct from the spatial 
magnitude just described and yet located therein. 



1979 



10 

Although from the point of view of the definition of movement 
- a definition which gives the cause - desire is the middle term 
or cause, and desire moves being moved, still in the material 
animated body there must be some material which itself moves 
being moved. Now that which is moved, but whose nature is not 
to initiate movement, is capable of being passive to an external 
force, while that which initiates movement must needs possess 
a kind of force and power. Now experience shows us that 
animals do both possess connatural spirit and derive power 
from this. (How this connatural spirit is maintained in the body 
is explained in other passages of our works.) And this spirit 
appears to stand to the soul-centre or original in a relation 
analogous to that between the point in a joint which moves 
being moved and the unmoved. Now since this centre is for 
some animals in the heart, in the rest in a part analogous with 
the heart, we further see the reason for the connatural spirit 
being situate where it actually is found. The question whether 
the spirit remains always the same or constantly changes and is 
renewed, like the cognate question about the rest of the parts of 
the body, is better postponed. At all events we see that it is well 
disposed to excite movement and to exert power; and the 
functions of movement are thrusting and pulling. Accordingly, 
the organ of movement must be capable of expanding and 
contracting; and this is precisely the characteristic of spirit. It 
contracts and expands naturally, and so is able to pull and to 
thrust from one and the same cause, exhibiting gravity 
compared with the fiery element, and levity by comparison with 
the opposites of fire. Now that which is to initiate movement 
without change of structure must be of the kind described, for 



1980 



the elementary bodies prevail over one another in a compound 
body by dint of disproportion; the light is overcome and kept 
down by the heavier, and the heavy kept up by the lighter. 

We have now explained what the part is which is moved when 
the soul originates movement in the body, and what is the 
reason for this. And the animal organism must be conceived 
after the similitude of a well-governed commonwealth. When 
order is once established in it there is no more need of a 
separate monarch to preside over each several task. The 
individuals each play their assigned part as it is ordered, and 
one thing follows another in its accustomed order. So in 
animals there is the same orderliness - nature taking the place 
of custom - and each part naturally doing his own work as 
nature has composed them. There is no need then of a soul in 
each part, but she resides in a kind of central governing place of 
the body, and the remaining parts live by continuity of natural 
structure, and play the parts Nature would have them play. 



11 

So much then for the voluntary movements of animal bodies, 
and the reasons for them. These bodies, however, display in 
certain members involuntary movements too, but most often 
non-voluntary movements. By involuntary I mean motions of 
the heart and of the privy member; for often upon an image 
arising and without express mandate of the reason these parts 
are moved. By non-voluntary I mean sleep and waking and 
respiration, and other similar organic movements. For neither 
imagination nor desire is properly mistress of any of these; but 
since the animal body must undergo natural changes of quality, 
and when the parts are so altered some must increase and 



1981 



other decrease, the body must straightway be moved and 
change with the changes that nature makes dependent upon 
one another. Now the causes of the movements are natural 
changes of temperature, both those coming from outside the 
body, and those taking place within it. So the involuntary 
movements which occur in spite of reason in the aforesaid 
parts occur when a change of quality supervenes. For 
conception and imagination, as we said above, produce the 
conditions necessary to affections, since they bring to bear the 
images or forms which tend to create these states. And the two 
parts aforesaid display this motion more conspicuously than 
the rest, because each is in a sense a separate vital organism, 
the reason being that each contains vital moisture. In the case 
of the heart the cause is plain, for the heart is the seat of the 
senses, while an indication that the generative organ too is vital 
is that there flows from it the seminal potency, itself a kind of 
organism. Again, it is a reasonable arrangement that the 
movements arise in the centre upon movements in the parts, 
and in the parts upon movements in the centre, and so reach 
one another. Conceive A to be the centre or starting point. The 
movements then arrive at the centre from each letter in the 
diagram we have drawn, and flow back again from the centre 
which is moved and changes, (for the centre is potentially 
multiple) the movement of B goes to B, that of C to C, the 
movement of both to both; but from B to C the movements flow 
by dint of going from B to A as to a centre, and then from A to C 
as from a centre. 

Moreover a movement contrary to reason sometimes does and 
sometimes does not arise in the organs on the occasion of the 
same thoughts; the reason is that sometimes the matter which 
is passive to the impressions is there in sufficient quantity and 
of the right quality and sometimes not. 



1982 



And so we have finished our account of the reasons for the 
parts of each kind of animal, of the soul, and furthere of sense- 
perception, of sleep, of memory, and of movement in general; it 
remains to speak of animal generation. 



1983 



Aristotle - On the Gait of Animals 
[Translated by A. S. L. Farquharson] 



We have now to consider the parts which are useful to animals 
for movement in place (locomotion); first, why each part is such 
as it is and to what end they possess them; and second, the 
differences between these parts both in one and the same 
creature, and again by comparison of the parts of creatures of 
different species with one another. First then let us lay down 
how many questions we have to consider. 

The first is what are the fewest points of motion necessary to 
animal progression, the second why sanguineous animals have 
four points and not more, but bloodless animals more than four, 
and generally why some animals are footless, others bipeds, 
others quadrupeds, others polypods, and why all have an even 
number of feet, if they have feet at all; why in fine the points on 
which progression depends are even in number. 

Next, why are man and bird bipeds, but fish footless; and why 
do man and bird, though both bipeds, have an opposite 
curvature of the legs. For man bends his legs convexly, a bird 
has his bent concavely; again, man bends his arms and legs in 
opposite directions, for he has his arms bent convexly, but his 
legs concavely. And a viviparous quadruped bends his limbs in 
opposite directions to a man's, and in opposite directions to one 
another; for he has his forelegs bent convexly, his hind legs 
concavely. Again, quadrupeds which are not viviparous but 
oviparous have a peculiar curvature of the limbs laterally away 



1984 



from the body. Again, why do quadrupeds move their legs criss- 
cross? 

We have to examine the reasons for all these facts, and others 
cognate to them; that the facts are such is clear from our 
Natural History, we have now to ask reasons for the facts. 



At the beginning of the inquiry we must postulate the principles 
we are accustomed constantly to use for our scientific 
investigation of nature, that is we must take for granted 
principles of this universal character which appear in all 
Nature's work. Of these one is that Nature creates nothing 
without a purpose, but always the best possible in each kind of 
living creature by reference to its essential constitution. 
Accordingly if one way is better than another that is the way of 
Nature. Next we must take for granted the different species of 
dimensions which inhere in various things; of these there are 
three pairs of two each, superior and inferior, before and behind, 
to the right and to the left. Further we must assume that the 
originals of movements in place are thrusts and pulls. (These 
are the essential place-movements, it is only accidentally that 
what is carried by another is moved; it is not thought to move 
itself, but to be moved by something else.) 



After these preliminaries, we go on to the next questions in 
order. 



1985 



Now of animals which change their position some move with 
the whole body at once, for example jumping animals, others 
move one part first and then the other, for example walking 
(and running) animals. In both these changes the moving 
creature always changes its position by pressing against what 
lies below it. Accordingly if what is below gives way too quickly 
for that which is moving upon it to lean against it, or if it affords 
no resistance at all to what is moving, the latter can of itself 
effect no movement upon it. For an animal which jumps makes 
its jump both by leaning against its own upper part and also 
against what is beneath its feet; for at the joints the parts do in 
a sense lean upon one another, and in general that which 
pushes down leans upon what is pushed down. That is why 
athletes jump further with weights in their hands than without, 
and runners run faster if they swing their arms; there is in 
extending the arms a kind of leaning against the hands and 
wrists. In all cases then that which moves makes its change of 
position by the use of at least two parts of the body; one part so 
to speak squeezes, the other is squeezed; for the part that is still 
is squeezed as it has to carry the weight, the part that is lifted 
strains against that which carries the weight. It follows then 
that nothing without parts can move itself in this way, for it has 
not in it the distinction of the part which is passive and that 
which is active. 



Again, the boundaries by which living beings are naturally 
determined are six in number, superior and inferior, before and 
behind, right and left. Of these all living beings have a superior 
and an inferior part; for superior and inferior is in plants too, 
not only in animals. And this distinction is one of function, not 



1986 



merely of position relatively to our earth and the sky above our 
heads. The superior is that from which flows in each kind the 
distribution of nutriment and the process of growth; the inferior 
is that to which the process flows and in which it ends. One is a 
starting-point, the other an end, and the starting-point is the 
superior. And yet it might be thought that in the case of plants 
at least the inferior is rather the appropriate starting-point, for 
in them the superior and inferior are in position other than in 
animals. Still they are similarly situated from the point of view 
of function, though not in their position relatively to the 
universe. The roots are the superior part of a plant, for from 
them the nutriment is distributed to the growing members, and 
a plant takes it with its roots as an animal does with its mouth. 

Things that are not only alive but are animals have both a front 
and a back, because they all have sense, and front and back are 
distinguished by reference to sense. The front is the part in 
which sense is innate, and whence each thing gets its 
sensations, the opposite parts are the back. 

All animals which partake not only in sense, but are able of 
themselves to make a change of place, have a further 
distinction of left and right besides those already enumerated; 
like the former these are distinctions of function and not of 
position. The right is that from which change of position 
naturally begins, the opposite which naturally depends upon 
this is the left. 

This distinction (of right and left) is more articulate and detailed 
in some than in others. For animals which make the aforesaid 
change (of place) by the help of organized parts (I mean feet for 
example, or wings or similar organs) have the left and right 
distinguished in greater detail, while those which are not 
differentiated into such parts, but make the differentiation in 
the body itself and so progress, like some footless animals (for 



1987 



example snakes and caterpillars after their kind, and besides 
what men call earth-worms), all these have the distinction 
spoken of, although it is not made so manifest to us. That the 
beginning of movement is on the right is indicated by the fact 
that all men carry burdens on the left shoulder; in this way they 
set free the side which initiates movement and enable the side 
which bears the weight to be moved. And so men hop easier on 
the left leg; for the nature of the right is to initiate movement, 
that of the left to be moved. The burden then must rest on the 
side which is to be moved, not on that which is going to cause 
movement, and if it be set on the moving side, which is the 
original of movement, it will either not be moved at all or with 
more labour. Another indication that the right is the source of 
movement is the way we put our feet forward; all men lead off 
with the left, and after standing still prefer to put the left foot 
forward, unless something happens to prevent it. The reason is 
that their movement comes from the leg they step off, not from 
the one put forward. Again, men guard themselves with their 
right. And this is the reason why the right is the same in all, for 
that from which motion begins is the same for all, and has its 
natural position in the same place, and for this reason the 
spiral-shaped Testaceans have their shells on the right, for they 
do not move in the direction of the spire, but all go forward in 
the direction opposite to the spire. Examples are the murex and 
the ceryx. As all animals then start movement from the right, 
and the right moves in the same direction as the whole, it is 
necessary for all to be alike right-handed. And man has the left 
limbs detached more than any other animal because he is 
natural in a higher degree than the other animals; now the right 
is naturally both better than the left and separate from it, and 
so in man the right is more especially the right, more dextrous 
that is, than in other animals. The right then being 
differentiated it is only reasonable that in man the left should 
be most movable, and most detached. In man, too, the other 



1988 



starting-points are found most naturally and clearly distinct, 
the superior part that is and the front. 



Animals which, like men and birds, have the superior part 
distinguished from the front are two-footed (biped). In them, of 
the four points of motion, two are wings in the one, hands and 
arms in the other. Animals which have the superior and the 
front parts identically situated are four-footed, many-footed, or 
footless (quadruped, polypod, limbless). I use the term foot for a 
member employed for movement in place connected with a 
point on the ground, for the feet appear to have got their name 
from the ground under our feet. 

Some animals, too, have the front and back parts identically 
situated, for example, Cephalopods (molluscs) and spiral- 
shaped Testaceans, and these we have discussed elsewhere in 
another connexion. 

Now there is in place a superior, an intermediate, and an 
inferior; in respect to place bipeds have their superior part 
corresponding to the part of the universe; quadrupeds, 
polypods, and footless animals to the intermediate part, and 
plants to the inferior. The reason is that these have no power of 
locomotion, and the superior part is determined relatively to the 
nutriment, and their nutriment is from the earth. Quadrupeds, 
polypods, and footless animals again have their superior part 
corresponding to the intermediate, because they are not erect. 
Bipeds have theirs corresponding to the superior part of the 
universe because they are erect, and of bipeds, man par 
excellence; for man is the most natural of bipeds. And it is 
reasonable for the starting points to be in these parts; for the 



1989 



starting-point is honourable, and the superior is more 
honourable than the inferior, the front than the back, and the 
right than the left. Or we may reverse the argument and say 
quite well that these parts are more honourable than their 
opposites just because the starting-points are in them. 



The above discussion has made it clear that the original of 
movement is in the parts on the right. Now every continuous 
whole, one part of which is moved while the other remains at 
rest must, in order to be able to move as a whole while one part 
stands still, have in the place where both parts have opposed 
movements some common part which connects the moving 
parts with one another. Further in this common part the 
original of the motion (and similarly of the absence of motion) 
of each of the parts must lie. 

Clearly then if any of the opposite pairs of parts (right and left, 
that is, superior and inferior, before and behind) have a 
movement of their own, each of them has for common original 
of its movements the juncture of the parts in question. 

Now before and behind are not distinctions relatively to that 
which sets up its own motion, because in nature nothing has a 
movement backwards, nor has a moving animal any division 
whereby it may make a change of position towards its front or 
back; but right and left, superior and inferior are so 
distinguished. Accordingly, all animals which progress by the 
use of distinct members have these members distinguished not 
by the differences of before and behind, but only of the 
remaining two pairs; the prior difference dividing these 
members into right and left (a difference which must appear as 



1990 



soon as you have division into two), and the other difference 
appearing of necessity where there is division into four. 

Since then these two pairs, the superior and inferior and the 
right and left, are linked to one another by the same common 
original (by which I mean that which controls their movement), 
and further, everything which is intended to make a movement 
in each such part properly must have the original cause of all 
the said movements arranged in a certain definite position 
relatively to the distances from it of the originals of the 
movements of the individual members (and these centres of the 
individual parts are in pairs arranged coordinately or diagonally, 
and the common centre is the original from which the animal's 
movements of right and left, and similarly of superior and 
inferior, start); each animal must have this original at a point 
where it is equally or nearly equally related to each of the 
centres in the four parts described. 



It is clear then how locomotion belongs to those animals only 
which make their changes of place by means of two or four 
points in their structure, or to such animals par excellence. 
Moreover, since this property belongs almost peculiarly to 
Sanguineous animals, we see that no Sanguineous animal can 
progress at more points than four, and that if it is the nature of 
anything so to progress at four points it must of necessity be 
Sanguineous. 

What we observe in the animal world is in agreement with the 
above account. For no Sanguineous animal if it be divided into 
more parts can live for any appreciable length of time, nor can it 
enjoy the power of locomotion which it possessed while it was a 



1991 



continuous and undivided whole. But some bloodless animals 
and polypods can live a long time, if divided, in each of the 
severed parts, and can move in the same way as before they 
were dismembered. Examples are what is termed the centipede 
and other insects that are long in shape, for even the hinder 
portion of all these goes on progressing in the same direction as 
before when they are cut in two. 

The explanation of their living when thus divided is that each of 
them is constructed like a continuous body of many separate 
living beings. It is plain, too, from what was said above why they 
are like this. Animals constructed most naturally are made to 
move at two or four points, and even limbless Sanguinea are no 
exception. They too move by dint of four points, whereby they 
achieve progression. They go forward by means of two flexions. 
For in each of their flexions there is a right and a left, both 
before and behind in their flat surface, in the part towards the 
head a right and a left front point, and in the part towards the 
tail the two hinder points. They look as if they moved at two 
points only, where they touch before and behind, but that is 
only because they are narrow in breadth. Even, in them the right 
is the sovereign part, and there is an alternate correspondence 
behind, exactly as in quadrupeds. The reason of their flexions is 
their great length, for just as tall men walk with their spines 
bellied (undulated) forward, and when their right shoulder is 
leading in a forward direction their left hip rather inclined 
backwards, so that their middle becomes hollow and bellied 
(undulated), so we ought to conceive snakes as moving in 
concave curves (undulations) upon the ground. And this is 
evidence that they move themselves like the quadrupeds, for 
they make the concave in its turn convex and the convex 
concave. When in its turn the left of the forward parts is 
leading, the concavity is in its turn reversed, for the right 
becomes the inner. (Let the right front point be A, the left B, the 
right hind C, the left D.) 



1992 



Among land animals this is the character of the movement of 
snakes, and among water animals of eels, and conger-eels and 
also lampreys, in fact of all that have their form snakelike. 
However, some marine animals of this shape have no fin, 
lampreys for example, but put the sea to the same use as 
snakes do both land and water (for snakes swim precisely as 
they move on the ground). Others have two fins only, for 
example conger-eels and eels and a kind of cestreus which 
breeds in the lake of Siphae. On this account too those that are 
accustomed to live on land, for example all the eels, move with 
fewer flexions in a fluid than on land, while the kind of cestreus 
which has two fins, by its flexion in a fluid makes up the 
remaining points. 



8 

The reason why snakes are limbless is first that nature makes 
nothing without purpose, but always regards what is the best 
possible for each individual, preserving the peculiar essence of 
each and its intended character, and secondly the principle we 
laid down above that no Sanguineous creature can move itself 
at more than four points. Granting this it is evident that 
Sanguineous animals like snakes, whose length is out of 
proportion to the rest of their dimensions, cannot possibly have 
limbs; for they cannot have more than four (or they would be 
bloodless), and if they had two or four they would be practically 
stationary; so slow and unprofitable would their movement 
necessarily be. 

But every limbed animal has necessarily an even number of 
such limbs. For those which only jump and so move from place 
to place do not need limbs for this movement at least, but those 



1993 



which not only jump but also need to walk, finding that 
movement not sufficient for their purposes, evidently either are 
better able to progress with even limbs or cannot otherwise 
progress at all every animal which has limbs must have an even 
us for as this kind of movement is effected by part of the body 
at a time, and not by the whole at once as in the movement of 
leaping, some of the limbs must in turn remain at rest, and 
others be moved, and the animal must act in each of these 
cases with opposite limbs, shifting the weight from the limbs 
that are being moved to those at rest. And so nothing can walk 
on three limbs or on one; in the latter case it has no support at 
all on which to rest the body's weight, in the former only in 
respect of one pair of opposites, and so it must necessarily fall 
in endeavouring so to move. 

Polypods however, like the Centipede, can indeed make progress 
on an odd number of limbs, as may be seen by the experiment 
of wounding one of their limbs; for then the mutilation of one 
row of limbs is corrected by the number of limbs which remain 
on either side. Such mutilated creatures, however, drag the 
wounded limb after them with the remainder, and do not 
properly speaking walk. Moreover, it is plain that they, too, 
would make the change of place better if they had an even 
number, in fact if none were missing and they had the limbs 
which correspond to one another. In this way they could 
equalize their own weight, and not oscillate to one side, if they 
had corresponding supports instead of one section of the 
opposite sides being unoccupied by a limb. A walking creature 
advances from each of its members alternately, for in this way it 
recovers the same figure that it had at first. 



1994 



The fact that all animals have an even number of feet, and the 
reasons for the fact have been set forth. What follows will 
explain that if there were no point at rest flexion and 
straightening would be impossible. Flexion is a change from a 
right line to an arc or an angle, straightening a change from 
either of these to a right line. Now in all such changes the 
flexion or the straightening must be relative to one point. 
Moreover, without flexion there could not be walking or 
swimming or flying. For since limbed creatures stand and take 
their weight alternately on one or other of the opposite legs, if 
one be thrust forward the other of necessity must be bent. For 
the opposite limbs are naturally of equal length, and the one 
which is under the weight must be a kind of perpendicular at 
right angles to the ground. 

When then one leg is advanced it becomes the hypotenuse of a 
right-angled triangle. Its square then is equal to the square on 
the other side together with the square on the base. As the legs 
then are equal, the one at rest must bend either at the knee or, 
if there were any kneeless animal which walked, at some other 
articulation. The following experiment exhibits the fact. If a 
man were to walk parallel to a wall in sunshine, the line 
described (by the shadow of his head> would be not straight but 
zigzag, becoming lower as he bends, and higher when he stands 
and lifts himself up. 

It is, indeed, possible to move oneself even if the leg be not bent, 
in the way in which children crawl. This was the old though 
erroneous account of the movement of elephants. But these 
kinds of movements involve a flexion in the shoulders or in the 
hips. Nothing at any rate could walk upright continuously and 
securely without flexions at the knee, but would have to move 
like men in the wrestling schools who crawl forward through 



1995 



the sand on their knees. For the upper part of the upright 
creature is long so that its leg has to be correspondingly long; in 
consequence there must be flexion. For since a stationary 
position is perpendicular, if that which moves cannot bend it 
will either fall forward as the right angle becomes acute or will 
not be able to progress. For if one leg is at right angles to the 
ground and the other is advanced, the latter will be at once 
equal and greater. For it will be equal to the stationary leg and 
also equivalent to the hypotenuse of a right-angled triangle. 
That which goes forward therefore must bend, and while 
bending one, extend the other leg simultaneously, so as to 
incline forward and make a stride and still remain above the 
perpendicular; for the legs form an isosceles triangle, and the 
head sinks lower when it is perpendicularly above the base on 
which it stands. 

Of limbless animals, some progress by undulations (and this 
happens in two ways, either they undulate on the ground, like 
snakes, or up and down, like caterpillars), and undulation is a 
flexion; others by a telescopic action, like what are called 
earthworms and leeches. These go forward, first one part 
leading and then drawing the whole of the rest of the body up 
to this, and so they change from place to place. It is plain too 
that if the two curves were not greater than the one line which 
subtends them undulating animals could not move themselves; 
when the flexure is extended they would not have moved 
forward at all if the flexure or arc were equal to the chord 
subtended; as it is, it reaches further when it is straightened 
out, and then this part stays still and it draws up what is left 
behind. 

In all the changes described that which moves now extends 
itself in a straight line to progress, and now is hooped; it 
straightens itself in its leading part, and is hooped in what 
follows behind. Even jumping animals all make a flexion in the 



1996 



part of the body which is underneath, and after this fashion 
make their leaps. So too flying and swimming things progress, 
the one straightening and bending their wings to fly, the other 
their fins to swim. Of the latter some have four fins, others 
which are rather long, for example eels, have only two. These 
swim by substituting a flexion of the rest of their body for the 
(missing) pair of fins to complete the movement, as we have 
said before. Flat fish use two fins, and the flat of their body as a 
substitute for the absent pair of fins. Quite flat fish, like the Ray, 
produce their swimming movement with the actual fins and 
with the two extremes or semicircles of their body, bending and 
straightening themselves alternately. 



10 

A difficulty might perhaps be raised about birds. How, it may be 
said, can they, either when they fly or when they walk, be said 
to move at four points? Now we did not say that all Sanguinea 
move at four points, but merely at not more than four. 
Moreover, they cannot as a fact fly if their legs be removed, nor 
walk without their wings. Even a man does not walk without 
moving his shoulders. Everything indeed, as we have said, 
makes a change of place by flexion and straightening, for all 
things progress by pressing upon what being beneath them up 
to a point gives way as it were gradually; accordingly, even if 
there be no flexion in another member, there must be at least in 
the point whence motion begins, is in feathered (flying) insects 
at the base of the 'scale-wing', in birds at the base of the wing, 
in others at the base of the corresponding member, the fins, for 
instance, in fish. In others, for example snakes, the flexion 
begins in the joints of the body. 



1997 



In winged creatures the tail serves, like a ship's rudder, to keep 
the flying thing in its course. The tail then must like other limbs 
be able to bend at the point of attachment. And so flying 
insects, and birds (Schizoptera) whose tails are ill-adapted for 
the use in question, for example peacocks, and domestic cocks, 
and generally birds that hardly fly, cannot steer a straight 
course. Flying insects have absolutely no tail, and so drift along 
like a rudderless vessel, and beat against anything they happen 
upon; and this applies equally to sharded insects, like the 
scarab-beetle and the chafer, and to unsharded, like bees and 
wasps. Further, birds that are not made for flight have a tail that 
is of no use; for instance the purple coot and the heron and all 
water-fowl. These fly stretching out their feet as a substitute for 
a tail, and use their legs instead of a tail to direct their flight. 
The flight of insects is slow and frail because the character of 
their feathery wings is not proportionate to the bulk of their 
body; this is heavy, their wings small and frail, and so the flight 
they use is like a cargo boat attempting to make its voyage with 
oars; now the frailty both of the actual wings and of the 
outgrowths upon them contributes in a measure to the flight 
described. Among birds, the peacock's tail is at one time useless 
because of its size, at another because it is shed. But birds are in 
general at the opposite pole to flying insects as regards their 
feathers, but especially the swiftest flyers among them. (These 
are the birds with curved talons, for swiftness of wing is useful 
to their mode of life.) The rest of their bodily structure is in 
harmony with their peculiar movement, the small head, the 
slight neck, the strong and acute breastbone (acute like the 
prow of a clipper-built vessel, so as to be well-girt, and strong by 
dint of its mass of flesh), in order to be able to push away the air 
that beats against it, and that easily and without exhaustion. 
The hind-quarters, too, are light and taper again, in order to 
conform to the movement of the front and not by their breadth 
to suck the air. 



1998 



11 

So much then for these questions. But why an animal that is to 
stand erect must necessarily be not only a biped, but must also 
have the superior parts of the body lighter, and those that lie 
under these heavier, is plain. Only if situated like this could it 
possibly carry itself easily. And so man, the only erect animal, 
has legs longer and stouter relatively to the upper parts of his 
body than any other animal with legs. What we observe in 
children also is evidence of this. Children cannot walk erect 
because they are always dwarf-like, the upper parts of their 
bodies being longer and stouter than the lower. With advancing 
years the lower increase disproportionately, until the children 
get their appropriate size, and then and not till then they 
succeed in walking erect. Birds are hunchbacked yet stand on 
two legs because their weight is set back, after the principle of 
horses fashioned in bronze with their forelegs prancing. But 
their being bipeds and able to stand is above all due to their 
having the hip-bone shaped like a thigh, and so large that it 
looks as if they had two thighs, one in the leg before the knee- 
joint, the other joining his part to the fundament. Really this is 
not a thigh but a hip, and if it were not so large the bird could 
not be a biped. As in a man or a quadruped, the thigh and the 
rest of the leg would be attached immediately to quite a small 
hip; consequently the whole body would be tilted forward. As it 
is, however, the hip is long and extends right along to the 
middle of the belly, so that the legs are attached at that point 
and carry as supports the whole frame. It is also evident from 
these considerations that a bird cannot possibly be erect in the 
sense in which man is. For as it holds its body now the wings 
are naturally useful to it, but if it were erect they would be as 



1999 



useless as the wings of Cupids we see in pictures. It must have 
been clear as soon as we spoke that the form of no human nor 
any similar being permits of wings; not only because it would, 
though Sanguineous, be moved at more than four points, but 
also because to have wings would be useless to it when moving 
naturally. And Nature makes nothing contrary to her own 
nature. 



12 

We have stated above that without flexion in the legs or 
shoulders and hips no Sanguineous animal with feet could 
progress, and that flexion is impossible except some point be at 
rest, and that men and birds, both bipeds, bend their legs in 
opposite directions, and further that quadrupeds bend their in 
opposite directions, and each pair in the opposite way to a 
man's limbs. For men bend their arms backwards, their legs 
forwards; quadrupeds their forelegs forwards, their back legs 
backwards, and in like manner also birds bend theirs. The 
reason is that Nature's workmanship is never purposeless, as 
we said above, but everything for the best possible in the 
circumstances. Inasmuch, therefore, as all creatures which 
naturally have the power of changing position by the use of 
limbs, must have one leg stationary with the weight of the body 
on it, and when they move forward the leg which has the 
leading position must be unencumbered, and the progression 
continuing the weight must shift and be taken off on this 
leading leg, it is evidently necessary for the back leg from being 
bent to become straight again, while the point of movement of 
the leg thrust forward and its lower part remain still. And so the 
legs must be jointed. And it is possible for this to take place and 
at the same time for the animal to go forward, if the leading leg 



2000 



has its articulation forwards, impossible if it be backwards. For, 
if it be forwards, the stretching out of the leg will be while the 
body is going forwards, but, if the other way, while it is going 
backwards. And again, if the flexion were backwards, the 
placing of the foot would be made by two movements and those 
contrary to one another, one, that is, backwards and one 
forwards; for in the bending together of the limb the lower end 
of the thigh would go backwards, and the shin would move the 
foot forwards away from the flexion; whereas, with the flexion 
forwards, the progression described will be performed not with 
contrary motions, but with one forward motion. 

Now man, being a biped and making his change of position in 
the natural way with his two legs, bends them forward for the 
reasons set forth, but his arms bend backwards reasonably 
enough. If they bent the opposite way they would be useless for 
the work of the hands, and for taking food. But quadrupeds 
which are also viviparous necessarily bend their front legs 
forwards. For these lead off first when they move, and are also 
in the forepart of their body. The reason that they bend forward 
is the same as in the case of man, for in this respect they are 
like mankind. And so quadrupeds as well as men bend these 
legs forward in the manner described. Moreover, if the flexion is 
like this, they are enabled to lift their feet high; if they bent 
them in the opposite way they would only lift them a little way 
from the ground, because the whole thigh and the joint from 
which the shin-bone springs would lie under the belly as the 
beast moved forward. If, however, the flexion of the hind legs 
were forwards the lifting of these feet would be similar to that 
of the forefeet (for the hind legs, too, would in this case have 
only a little room for their lifting inasmuch as both the thigh 
and the knee-joint would fall under the position of the belly); 
but the flexion being backwards, as in fact it is, nothing comes 
in the way of their progression with this mode of moving the 
feet. Moreover, it is necessary or at least better for their legs to 



2001 



bend thus when they are suckling their young, with a view to 
such ministrations. If the flexion were inwards it would be 
difficult to keep their young under them and to shelter them. 



13 

Now there are four modes of flexion if we take the 
combinations in pairs. Fore and hind may bend either both 
backwards, as the figures marked A, or in the opposite way both 
forwards, as in B, or in converse ways and not in the same 
direction, as in C where the fore bend forwards and the hind 
bend backwards, or as in D, the opposite way to C, where the 
convexities are turned towards one another and the concavities 
outwards. Now no biped or quadruped bends his limbs like the 
figures A or B, but the quadrupeds like C, and like D only the 
elephant among quadrupeds and man if you consider his arms 
as well as his legs. For he bends his arms concavely and his legs 
convexly. 

In man, too, the flexions of the limbs are always alternately 
opposite, for example the elbow bends back, but the wrist of the 
hand forwards, and again the shoulder forwards. In like fashion, 
too, in the case of the legs, the hip backwards, the knee 
forwards, the ankle in the opposite way backwards. And plainly 
the lower limbs are opposed in this respect to the upper, 
because the first joints are opposites, the shoulder bending 
forwards, the hip backwards; wherefore also the ankle bends 
backwards, and the wrist of the hand forwards. 



2002 



14 

This is the way then the limbs bend, and for the reasons given. 
But the hind limbs move criss-cross with the fore limbs; after 
the off fore they move the near hind, then the near fore, and 
then the off hind. The reason is that (a) if they moved the 
forelegs together and first, the animal would be wrenched, and 
the progression would be a stumbling forwards with the hind 
parts as it were dragged after. Again, that would not be walking 
but jumping, and it is hard to make a continuous change of 
place, jumping all the time. Here is evidence of what I say; even 
as it is, all horses that move in this way soon begin to refuse, for 
example the horses in a religious procession. For these reasons 
the fore limbs and the hind limbs move in this separate way. 
Again, (b) if they moved both the right legs first the weight 
would be outside the supporting limbs and they would fall. If 
then it is necessary to move in one or other of these ways or 
criss-cross fashion, and neither of these two is satisfactory, they 
must move criss-cross; for moving in the way we have said they 
cannot possibly experience either of these untoward results. 
And this is why horses and such-like animals stand still with 
their legs put forward criss-cross, not with the right or the left 
put forward together at once. In the same fashion animals with 
more than four legs make their movements; if you take two 
consecutive pairs of legs the hind move criss-cross with the 
forelegs; you can see this if you watch them moving slowly. 
Even crabs move in this way, and they are polypods. They, too, 
always move criss-cross in whichever direction they are making 
progress. For in direction this animal has a movement all its 
own; it is the only animal that moves not forwards, but 
obliquely. Yet since forwards is a distinction relative to the line 
of vision, Nature has made its eyes able to conform to its limbs, 
for its eyes can move themselves obliquely, and therefore after a 
fashion crabs are no exception but in this sense move forwards. 



2003 



15 

Birds bend their legs in the same way as quadrupeds. For their 
natural construction is broadly speaking nearly the same. That 
is, in birds the wings are a substitute for the forelegs; and so 
they are bent in the same way as the forelegs of a quadruped, 
since when they move to progress the natural beginning of 
change is from the wings (as in quadrupeds from the forelegs). 
Flight in fact is their appropriate movement. And so if the wings 
be cut off a bird can neither stand still nor go forwards. 

Again, the bird though a biped is not erect, and has the forward 
parts of the body lighter than the hind, and so it is necessary (or 
at least preferable for the standing posture) to have the thigh so 
placed below the body as it actually is, I mean growing towards 
the back. If then it must have this situation the flexion of the leg 
must be backwards, as in the hind legs of quadrupeds. The 
reasons are the same as those given in the case of viviparous 
quadrupeds. 

If now we survey generally birds and winged insects, and 
animals which swim in a watery medium, all I mean that make 
their progress in water by dint of organs of movement, it is not 
difficult to see that it is better to have the attachment of the 
parts in question oblique to the frame, exactly as in fact we see 
it to be both in birds and insects. And this same arrangement 
obtains also among fishes. Among birds the wings are attached 
obliquely; so are the fins in water animals, and the feather-like 
wings of insects. In this way they divide the air or water most 
quickly and with most force and so effect their movement. For 
the hinder parts in this way would follow forwards as they are 



2004 



carried along in the yielding medium, fish in the water, birds in 
the air. 

Of oviparous quadrupeds all those that live in holes, like 
crocodiles, lizards, spotted lizards, freshwater tortoises, and 
turtles, have their legs attached obliquely as their whole body 
sprawls over the ground, and bend them obliquely. The reason is 
that this is useful for ease in creeping into holes, and for sitting 
upon their eggs and guarding them. And as they are splayed 
outwards they must of necessity tuck in their thighs and put 
them under them in order to achieve the lifting of the whole 
body. In view of this they cannot bend them otherwise than 
outwards. 



16 

We have already stated the fact that non-sanguineous animals 
with limbs are polypods and none of them quadrupeds. And the 
reason why their legs, except the extreme pairs, were 
necessarily attached obliquely and had their flexions upwards, 
and the legs themselves were somewhat turned under (bandy- 
shape) and backwards is plain. In all such creatures the 
intermediate legs both lead and follow. If then they lay under 
them, they must have had their flexion both forwards and 
backwards; on account of leading, forwards; and on account of 
following, backwards. Now since they have to do both, for this 
reason their limbs are turned under and bent obliquely, except 
the two extreme pairs. (These two are more natural in their 
movement, the front leading and the back following.) Another 
reason for this kind of flexion is the number of their legs; 
arranged in this way they would interfere less with one another 
in progression and not knock together. But the reason that they 



2005 



are bandy is that all of them or most of them live in holes, for 
creatures living so cannot possibly be high above the ground. 

But crabs are in nature the oddest of all polypods; they do not 
progress forwards except in the sense explained above, they are 
the only animals which have more than one pair of leading 
limbs. The explanation of this is the hardness of their limbs, 
and the fact that they use them not for swimming but for 
walking; they always keep on the ground. However, the flexion 
of the limbs of all polypods is oblique, like that of the 
quadrupeds which live in holes - for example lizards and 
crocodiles and most of the oviparous quadrupeds. And the 
explanation is that some of them in their breeding periods, and 
some all their life, live in holes. 



17 

Now the rest have bandy legs because they are soft-skinned, but 
the crayfish is hard-skinned and its limbs are for swimming and 
not for walking (and so are not bandy). Crabs, too, have their 
limbs bent obliquely, but not bandy like oviparous quadrupeds 
and non-sanguineous polypods, because their limbs have a hard 
and shell-like skin, although they don't swim but live in holes; 
they live in fact on the ground. Moreover, their shape is like a 
disk, as compared with the crayfish which is elongated, and 
they haven't a tail like the crayfish; a tail is useful to the 
crayfish for swimming, but the crab is not a swimming creature. 
Further, it alone has its side equivalent to a hinder part, because 
it has many leading feet. The explanation of this is that its 
flexions are not forward nor its legs turned in under (bandy). We 
have given above the reason why its legs are not turned in 



2006 



under, that is the hardness and shell-like character of its 
integument. 

For these reasons then it must lead off with more than one 
limb, and move obliquely; obliquely, because the flexion is 
oblique; and with more than one limb, because otherwise the 
limbs that were still would have got in the way of those that 
were moving. 

Fishes of the flat kind swim with their heads twisted, as one- 
eyed men walk; they have their natural shape distorted. Web- 
footed birds swim with their feet; because they breath the air 
and have lungs they are bipeds, but because they have their 
home in the water they are webbed; by this arrangement their 
feet serve them instead of fins. They have their legs too, not like 
the rest of birds in the centre of their body, but rather set back. 
Their legs are short, and being set back are serviceable for 
swimming. The reason for their having short legs is that nature 
has added to their feet by subtracting from the length of their 
limbs; instead of length she gives stoutness to the legs and 
breadth to the feet. Broad feet are more useful than long for 
pushing away the water when they are swimming. 



18 

There is reason, too, for winged creatures having feet, but fish 
none. The former have their home in the dry medium, and 
cannot remain always in mid air; they must therefore have feet. 
Fish on the contrary live in the wet medium, and take in water, 
not air. Fins are useful for swimming, but feet not. And if they 
had both they would be non-sanguineous. There is a broad 
similarity between birds and fishes in the organs of locomotion. 
Birds have their wings on the superior part, similarly fish have 



2007 



two pectoral fins; again, birds have legs on their under parts and 
near the wings; similarly, most fish have two fins on the under 
parts and near the pectorals. Birds, too, have a tail and fish a 
tail-fin. 



19 

A difficulty may be suggested as to the movements of molluscs, 
that is, as to where that movement originates; for they have no 
distinction of left and right. Now observation shows them 
moving. We must, I think, treat all this class as mutilated, and 
as moving in the way in which limbed creatures do when one 
cuts off their legs, or as analogous with the seal and the bat. 
Both the latter are quadrupeds but misshapen. Now molluscs 
do move, but move in a manner contrary to nature. They are not 
moving things, but are moving if as sedentary creatures they are 
compared with zoophytes, and sedentary if classed with 
progressing animals. 

As to right and left, crabs, too, show the distinction poorly, still 
they do show it. You can see it in the claw; the right claw is 
larger and stronger, as though the right and left sides were 
trying to get distinguished. 

The structure of animals, both in their other parts, and 
especially in those which concern progression and any 
movement in place, is as we have now described. It remains, 
after determining these questions, to investigate the problems 
of Life and Death. 



2008 



Aristotle - On the Generation of Animals 
[Translated by Arthur Piatt] 



Book I 



We have now discussed the other parts of animals, both 
generally and with reference to the peculiarities of each kind, 
explaining how each part exists on account of such a cause, and 
I mean by this the final cause. 

There are four causes underlying everything: first, the final 
cause, that for the sake of which a thing exists; secondly, the 
formal cause, the definition of its essence (and these two we 
may regard pretty much as one and the same); thirdly, the 
material; and fourthly, the moving principle or efficient cause. 

We have then already discussed the other three causes, for the 
definition and the final cause are the same, and the material of 
animals is their parts of the whole animal the non- 
homogeneous parts, of these again the homogeneous, and of 
these last the so-called elements of all matter. It remains to 
speak of those parts which contribute to the generation of 
animals and of which nothing definite has yet been said, and to 
explain what is the moving or efficient cause. To inquire into 
this last and to inquire into the generation of each animal is in 
a way the same thing; and, therefore, my plan has united them 
together, arranging the discussion of these parts last, and the 
beginning of the question of generation next to them. 



2009 



Now some animals come into being from the union of male and 
female, i.e. all those kinds of animal which possess the two 
sexes. This is not the case with all of them; though in the 
sanguinea with few exceptions the creature, when its growth is 
complete, is either male or female, and though some bloodless 
animals have sexes so that they generate offspring of the same 
kind, yet other bloodless animals generate indeed, but not 
offspring of the same kind; such are all that come into being not 
from a union of the sexes, but from decaying earth and 
excrements. To speak generally, if we take all animals which 
change their locality, some by swimming, others by flying, 
others by walking, we find in these the two sexes, not only in 
the sanguinea but also in some of the bloodless animals; and 
this applies in the case of the latter sometimes to the whole 
class, as the cephalopoda and Crustacea, but in the class of 
insects only to the majority. Of these, all which are produced by 
union of animals of the same kind generate also after their 
kind, but all which are not produced by animals, but from 
decaying matter, generate indeed, but produce another kind, 
and the offspring is neither male nor female; such are some of 
the insects. This is what might have been expected, for if those 
animals which are not produced by parents had themselves 
united and produced others, then their offspring must have 
been either like or unlike to themselves. If like, then their 
parents ought to have come into being in the same way; this is 
only a reasonable postulate to make, for it is plainly the case 
with other animals. If unlike, and yet able to copulate, then 
there would have come into being again from them another 
kind of creature and again another from these, and this would 
have gone on to infinity. But Nature flies from the infinite, for 
the infinite is unending or imperfect, and Nature ever seeks an 
end. 

But all those creatures which do not move, as the testacea and 
animals that live by clinging to something else, inasmuch as 



2010 



their nature resembles that of plants, have no sex any more 
than plants have, but as applied to them the word is only used 
in virtue of a similarity and analogy. For there is a slight 
distinction of this sort, since even in plants we find in the same 
kind some trees which bear fruit and others which, while 
bearing none themselves, yet contribute to the ripening of the 
fruits of those which do, as in the case of the fig-tree and 
caprifig. 

The same holds good also in plants, some coming into being 
from seed and others, as it were, by the spontaneous action of 
Nature, arising either from decomposition of the earth or of 
some parts in other plants, for some are not formed by 
themselves separately but are produced upon other trees, as the 
mistletoe. Plants, however, must be investigated separately. 



Of the generation of animals we must speak as various 
questions arise in order in the case of each, and we must 
connect our account with what has been said. For, as we said 
above, the male and female principles may be put down first 
and foremost as origins of generation, the former as containing 
the efficient cause of generation, the latter the material of it. 
The most conclusive proof of this is drawn from considering 
how and whence comes the semen; for there is no doubt that it 
is out of this that those creatures are formed which are 
produced in the ordinary course of Nature; but we must observe 
carefully the way in which this semen actually comes into being 
from the male and female. For it is just because the semen is 
secreted from the two sexes, the secretion taking place in them 
and from them, that they are first principles of generation. For 



2011 



by a male animal we mean that which generates in another, 
and by a female that which generates in itself; wherefore men 
apply these terms to the macrocosm also, naming Earth mother 
as being female, but addressing Heaven and the Sun and other 
like entities as fathers, as causing generation. 

Male and female differ in their essence by each having a 
separate ability or faculty, and anatomically by certain parts; 
essentially the male is that which is able to generate in another, 
as said above; the female is that which is able to generate in 
itself and out of which comes into being the offspring 
previously existing in the parent. And since they are 
differentiated by an ability or faculty and by their function, and 
since instruments or organs are needed for all functioning, and 
since the bodily parts are the instruments or organs to serve the 
faculties, it follows that certain parts must exist for union of 
parents and production of offspring. And these must differ from 
each other, so that consequently the male will differ from the 
female. (For even though we speak of the animal as a whole as 
male or female, yet really it is not male or female in virtue of 
the whole of itself, but only in virtue of a certain faculty and a 
certain part - just as with the part used for sight or locomotion 
- which part is also plain to sense-perception.) 

Now as a matter of fact such parts are in the female the so- 
called uterus, in the male the testes and the penis, in all the 
sanguinea; for some of them have testes and others the 
corresponding passages. There are corresponding differences of 
male and female in all the bloodless animals also which have 
this division into opposite sexes. But if in the sanguinea it is the 
parts concerned in copulation that differ primarily in their 
forms, we must observe that a small change in a first principle 
is often attended by changes in other things depending on it. 
This is plain in the case of castrated animals, for, though only 
the generative part is disabled, yet pretty well the whole form of 



2012 



the animal changes in consequence so much that it seems to be 
female or not far short of it, and thus it is clear than an animal 
is not male or female in virtue of an isolated part or an isolated 
faculty. Clearly, then, the distinction of sex is a first principle; at 
any rate, when that which distinguishes male and female 
suffers change, many other changes accompany it, as would be 
the case if a first principle is changed. 



The sanguinea are not all alike as regards testes and uterus. 
Taking the former first, we find that some of them have not 
testes at all, as the classes of fish and of serpents, but only two 
spermatic ducts. Others have testes indeed, but internally by 
the loin in the region of the kidneys, and from each of these a 
duct, as in the case of those animals which have no testes at all, 
these ducts unite also as with those animals; this applies 
(among animals breathing air and having a lung) to all birds and 
oviparous quadrupeds. For all these have their testes internal 
near the loin, and two ducts from these in the same way as 
serpents; I mean the lizards and tortoises and all the scaly 
reptiles. But all the vivipara have their testes in front; some of 
them inside at the end of the abdomen, as the dolphin, not with 
ducts but with a penis projecting externally from them; others 
outside, either pendent as in man or towards the fundament as 
in swine. They have been discriminated more accurately in the 
Enquiries about Animals. 

The uterus is always double, just as the testes are always two in 
the male. It is situated either near the pudendum (as in women, 
and all those animals which bring forth alive not only externally 
but also internally, and all fish that lay eggs externally) or up 



2013 



towards the hypozoma (as in all birds and in viviparous fishes). 
The uterus is also double in the Crustacea and the cephalopoda, 
for the membranes which include their so-called eggs are of the 
nature of a uterus. It is particularly hard to distinguish in the 
case of the poulps, so that it seems to be single, but the reason 
of this is that the bulk of the body is everywhere similar. 

It is double also in the larger insects; in the smaller the question 
is uncertain owing to the small size of the body. 

Such is the description of the aforesaid parts of animals. 



With regard to the difference of the spermatic organs in males, 
if we are to investigate the causes of their existence, we must 
first grasp the final cause of the testes. Now if Nature makes 
everything either because it is necessary or because it is better 
so, this part also must be for one of these two reasons. But that 
it is not necessary for generation is plain; else had it been 
possessed by all creatures that generate, but as it is neither 
serpents have testes nor have fish; for they have been seen 
uniting and with their ducts full of milt. It remains then that it 
must be because it is somehow better so. Now it is true that the 
business of most animals is, you may say, nothing else than to 
produce young, as the business of a plant is to produce seed and 
fruit. But still as, in the case of nutriment, animals with straight 
intestines are more violent in their desire for food, so those 
which have not testes but only ducts, or which have them 
indeed but internally, are all quicker in accomplishing 
copulation. But those which are to be more temperate in the 
one case have not straight intestines, and in the other have 
their ducts twisted to prevent their desire being too violent and 



2014 



hasty. It is for this that the testes are contrived; for they make 
the movement of the spermatic secretion steadier, preserving 
the folding back of the passages in the vivipara, as horses and 
the like, and in man. (For details see the Enquiries about 
Animals.) For the testes are no part of the ducts but are only 
attached to them, as women fasten stones to the loom when 
weaving; if they are removed the ducts are drawn up internally, 
so that castrated animals are unable to generate; if they were 
not drawn up they would be able, and before now a bull 
mounting immediately after castration has caused conception 
in the cow because the ducts had not yet been drawn up. In 
birds and oviparous quadrupeds the testes receive the 
spermatic secretion, so that its expulsion is slower than in 
fishes. This is clear in the case of birds, for their testes are much 
enlarged at the time of copulation, and all those which pair at 
one season of the year have them so small when this is past 
that they are almost indiscernible, but during the season they 
are very large. When the testes are internal the act of copulation 
is quicker than when they are external, for even in the latter 
case the semen is not emitted before the testes are drawn up. 



Besides, quadrupeds have the organ of copulation, since it is 
possible for them to have it, but for birds and the footless 
animals it is not possible, because the former have their legs 
under the middle of the abdomen and the latter have no legs at 
all; now the penis depends from that region and is situated 
there. (Wherefore also the legs are strained in intercourse, both 
the penis and the legs being sinewy.) So that, since it is not 
possible for them to have this organ, they must necessarily 
either have no testes also, or at any rate not have them there, as 



2015 



those animals that have both penis and testes have them in the 
same situation. 

Further, with those animals at any rate that have external 
testes, the semen is collected together before emission, and 
emission is due to the penis being heated by its movement; it is 
not ready for emission at immediate contact as in fishes. 

All the vivipira have their testes in front, internally or externally, 
except the hedgehog; he alone has them near the loin. This is 
for the same reason as with birds, because their union must be 
quick, for the hedgehog does not, like the other quadrupeds, 
mount upon the back of the female, but they conjugate standing 
upright because of their spines. 

So much for the reasons why those animals have testes which 
have them, and why they are sometimes external and 
sometimes internal. 



All those animals which have no testes are deficient in this part, 
as has been said, not because it is better to be so but simply 
because of necessity, and secondly because it is necessary that 
their copulation should be speedy. Such is the nature of fish and 
serpents. Fish copulate throwing themselves alongside of the 
females and separating again quickly. For as men and all such 
creatures must hold their breath before emitting the semen, so 
fish at such times must cease taking in the sea-water, and then 
they perish easily. Therefore they must not mature the semen 
during copulation, as viviparous land-animals do, but they have 
it all matured together before the time, so as not to be maturing 
it while in contact but to emit it ready matured. So they have no 



2016 



testes, and the ducts are straight and simple. There is a small 
part similar to this connected with the testes in the system of 
quadrupeds, for part of the reflected duct is sanguineous and 
part is not; the fluid is already semen when it is received by and 
passes through this latter part, so that once it has arrived there 
it is soon emitted in these quadrupeds also. Now in fishes the 
whole passage resembles the last section of the reflected part of 
the duct in man and similar animals. 



Serpents copulate twining round one another, and, as said 
above, have neither testes nor penis, the latter because they 
have no legs, the former because of their length, but they have 
ducts like for on account of their extreme length the seminal 
fluid would take too long in its passage and be cooled if it were 
further delayed by testes. (This happens also if the penis is 
large; such men are less fertile than when it is smaller because 
the semen, if cold, is not generative, and that which is carried 
too far is cooled.) So much for the reason why some animals 
have testes and others not. Serpents intertwine because of their 
inaptitude to cast themselves alongside of one another. For they 
are too long to unite closely with so small a part and have no 
organs of attachment, so they make use of the suppleness of 
their bodies, intertwining. Wherefore also they seem to be 
slower in copulation than fish, not only on account of the 
length of the ducts but also of this elaborate arrangement in 
uniting. 



2017 



8 

It is not easy to state the facts about the uterus in female 
animals, for there are many points of difference. The vivipara 
are not alike in this part; women and all the vivipara with feet 
have the uterus low down by the pudendum, but the 
cartilaginous viviparous fish have it higher up near the 
hypozoma. In the ovipara, again, it is low in fish (as in women 
and the viviparous quadrupeds), high in birds and all oviparous 
quadrupeds. Yet even these differences are on a principle. To 
begin with the ovipara, they differ in the manner of laying their 
eggs, for some produce them imperfect, as fishes whose eggs 
increase and are finally developed outside of them. The reason 
is that they produce many young, and this is their function as it 
is with plants. If then they perfected the egg in themselves they 
must needs be few in number, but as it is, they have so many 
that each uterus seems to be an egg, at any rate in the small 
fishes. For these are the most productive, just as with the other 
animals and plants whose nature is analogous to theirs, for the 
increase of size turns with them to seed. 

But the eggs of birds and the quadrupedal ovipara are perfect 
when produced. In order that these may be preserved they must 
have a hard covering (for their envelope is soft so long as they 
are increasing in size), and the shell is made by heat squeezing 
out the moisture for the earthy material; consequently the place 
must be hot in which this is to happen. But the part about the 
hypozoma is hot, as is shown by that being the part which 
concocts the food. If then the eggs must be within the uterus, 
then the uterus must be near the hypozoma in those creatures 
which produce their eggs in a perfect form. Similarly it must be 
low down in those which produce them imperfect, for it is 
profitable that it should be so. And it is more natural for the 
uterus to be low down than high up, when Nature has no other 
business in hand to hinder it; for its end is low down, and where 



2018 



is the end, there is the function, and the uterus itself is 
naturally where the function is. 



We find differences in the vivipara also as compared with one 
another. Some produce their young alive, not only externally, 
but also internally, as men, horses, dogs, and all those which 
have hair, and among aquatic animals, dolphins, whales, and 
such cetacea. 



10 

But the cartilaginous fish and the vipers produce their young 
alive externally, but first produce eggs internally. The egg is 
perfect, for so only can an animal be generated from an egg, and 
nothing comes from an imperfect one. It is because they are of a 
cold nature, not hot as some assert, that they do not lay their 
eggs externally. 



11 

At least they certainly produce their eggs in a soft envelope, the 
reason being that they have but little heat and so their nature 
does not complete the process of drying the egg-shell. Because, 
then, they are cold they produce soft-shelled eggs, and because 



2019 



the eggs are soft they do not produce them externally; for that 
would have caused their destruction. 

The process is for the most part the same as in birds, for the egg 
descends and the young is hatched from it near the vagina, 
where the young is produced in those animals which are 
viviparous from the beginning. Therefore in such animals the 
uterus is dissimilar to that of both the vivipara and ovipara, 
because they participate in both classes; for it is at once near 
the hypozoma and also stretching along downwards in all the 
cartilaginous fishes. But the facts about this and the other kinds 
of uterus must be gathered from inspection of the drawings of 
dissections and from the Enquiries. Thus, because they are 
oviparous, laying perfect eggs, they have the uterus placed high, 
but, as being viviparous, low, participating in both classes. 

Animals that are viviparous from the beginning all have it low, 
Nature here having no other business to interfere with her, and 
their production having no double character. Besides this, it is 
impossible for animals to be produced alive near the hypozoma, 
for the foetus must needs be heavy and move, and that region 
in the mother is vital and would not be able to bear the weight 
and the movement. Thirdly, parturition would be difficult 
because of the length of the passage to be traversed; even as it 
is there is difficulty with women if they draw up the uterus in 
parturition by yawning or anything of the kind, and even when 
empty it causes a feeling of suffocation if moved upwards. For if 
a uterus is to hold a living animal it must be stronger than in 
ovipara, and therefore in all the vivipara it is fleshy, whereas 
when the uterus is near the hypozoma it is membranous. And 
this is clear also in the case of the animals which produce 
young by the mixed method, for their eggs are high up and 
sideways, but the living young are produced in the lower part of 
the uterus. 



2020 



So much for the reason why differences are found in the uterus 
of various animals, and generally why it is low in some and high 
in others near the hypozoma. 



12 

Why is the uterus always internal, but the testes sometimes 
internal, sometimes external? The reason for the uterus always 
being internal is that in this is contained the egg or foetus, 
which needs guarding, shelter, and maturation by concoction, 
while the outer surface of the body is easily injured and cold. 
The testes vary in position because they also need shelter and a 
covering to preserve them and to mature the semen; for it 
would be impossible for them, if chilled and stiffened, to be 
drawn up and discharge it. Therefore, whenever the testes are 
visible, they have a cuticular covering known as the scrotum. If 
the nature of the skin is opposed to this, being too hard to be 
adapted for enclosing them or for being soft like a true 'skin', as 
with the scaly integument of fish and reptiles, then the testes 
must needs be internal. Therefore they are so in dolphins and 
all the cetacea which have them, and in the oviparous 
quadrupeds among the scaly animals. The skin of birds also is 
hard so that it will not conform to the size of anything and 
enclose it neatly. (This is another reason with all these animals 
for their testes being internal besides those previously 
mentioned as arising necessarily from the details of copulation.) 
For the same reason they are internal in the elephant and 
hedgehog, for the skin of these, too, is not well suited to keep 
the protective part separate. 

[The position of the uterus differs in animals viviparous within 
themselves and those externally oviparous, and in the latter 



2021 



class again it differs in those which have the uterus low and 
those which have it near the hypozoma, as in fishes compared 
with birds and oviparous quadrupeds. And it is different again 
in those which produce young in both ways, being oviparous 
internally and viviparous externally. For those which are 
viviparous both internally and externally have the uterus placed 
on the abdomen, as men, cattle, dogs, and the like, since it is 
expedient for the safety and growth of the foetus that no weight 
should be upon the uterus.] 



13 

The passages also are different through which the solid and 
liquid excreta pass out in all the vivipara. Wherefore both males 
and females in this class all have a part whereby the urine is 
voided, and this serves also for the issue of the semen in males, 
of the offspring in females. This passage is situated above and 
in front of the passage of the solid excreta. The passage is the 
same as that of the solid nutriment in all those animals that 
have no penis, in all the ovipara, even those of them that have a 
bladder, as the tortoises. For it is for the sake of generation, not 
for the evacuation of the urine, that the passages are double; 
but because the semen is naturally liquid, the liquid excretion 
also shares the same passage. This is clear from the fact that all 
animals produce semen, but all do not void liquid excrement. 
Now the spermatic passages of the male must be fixed and 
must not wander, and the same applies to the uterus of the 
female, and this fixing must take place at either the front or the 
back of the body. To take the uterus first, it is in the front of the 
body in vivipara because of the foetus, but at the loin and the 
back in ovipara. All animals which are internally oviparous and 
externally viviparous are in an intermediate condition because 



2022 



they participate in both classes, being at once oviparous and 
viviparous. For the upper part of the uterus, where the eggs are 
produced, is under the hypozoma by the loin and the back, but 
as it advances is low at the abdomen; for it is in that part that 
the animal is viviparous. In these also the passage for solid 
excrement and for copulation is the same, for none of these, as 
has been said already, has a separate pudendum. 

The same applies to the passages in the male, whether they 
have testes or no, as to the uterus of the ovipara. For in all of 
them, not only in the ovipara, the ducts adhere to the back and 
the region of the spine. For they must not wander but be settled, 
and that is the character of the region of the back, which gives 
continuity and stability. Now in those which have internal 
testes, the ducts are fixed from the first, and they are fixed in 
like manner if the testes are external; then they meet together 
towards the region of the penis. 

The like applies to the ducts in the dolphins, but they have their 
testes hidden under the abdominal cavity. 

We have now discussed the situation of the parts contributing 
to generation, and the causes thereof. 



14 

The bloodless animals do not agree either with the sanguinea or 
with each other in the fashion of the parts contributing to 
generation. There are four classes still left to deal with, first the 
Crustacea, secondly the cephalopoda, thirdly the insects, and 
fourthly the testacea. We cannot be certain about all of them, 
but that most of them copulate is plain; in what manner they 
unite must be stated later. 



2023 



The Crustacea copulate like the retromingent quadrupeds, 
fitting their tails to one another, the one supine and the other 
prone. For the flaps attached to the sides of the tail being long 
prevent them from uniting with the belly against the back. The 
males have fine spermatic ducts, the females a membranous 
uterus alongside the intestine, cloven on each side, in which the 
egg is produced. 



15 

The cephalopoda entwine together at the mouth, pushing 
against one another and enfolding their arms. This attitude is 
necessary, because Nature has bent backwards the end of the 
intestine and brought it round near the mouth, as has been said 
before in the treatise on the parts of animals. The female has a 
part corresponding to the uterus, plainly to be seen in each of 
these animals, for it contains an egg which is at first indivisible 
to the eye but afterwards splits up into many; each of these eggs 
is imperfect when deposited, as with the oviparous fishes. In 
the cephalopoda (as also in the Crustacea) the same passage 
serves to void the excrement and leads to the part like a uterus, 
for the male discharges the seminal fluid through this passage. 
And it is on the lower surface of the body, where the mantle is 
open and the sea-water enters the cavity. Hence the union of 
the male with the female takes place at this point, for it is 
necessary, if the male discharges either semen or a part of 
himself or any other force, that he should unite with her at the 
uterine passage. But the insertion, in the case of the poulps, of 
the arm of the male into the funnel of the female, by which arm 
the fishermen say the male copulates with her, is only for the 
sake of attachment, and it is not an organ useful for generation, 



2024 



for it is outside the passage in the male and indeed outside the 
body of the male altogether. 

Sometimes also cephalopoda unite by the male mounting on 
the back of the female, but whether for generation or some 
other cause has not yet been observed. 



16 

Some insects copulate and the offspring are produced from 
animals of the same name, just as with the sanguinea; such are 
the locusts, cicadae, spiders, wasps, and ants. Others unite 
indeed and generate; but the result is not a creature of the same 
kind, but only a scolex, and these insects do not come into 
being from animals but from putrefying matter, liquid or solid; 
such are fleas, flies, and cantharides. Others again are neither 
produced from animals nor unite with each other; such are 
gnats, 'conopes', and many similar kinds. In most of those 
which unite the female is larger than the male. The males do 
not appear to have spermatic passages. In most cases the male 
does not insert any part into the female, but the female from 
below upwards into the male; this has been observed in many 
cases (as also that the male mounts the female), the opposite in 
few cases; but observations are not yet comprehensive enough 
to enable us to make a distinction of classes. And generally it is 
the rule with most of the oviparous fish and oviparous 
quadrupeds that the female is larger than the because this is 
expedient in view of the increase of bulk in conception by 
reason of the eggs. In the female the part analogous to the 
uterus is cleft and extends along the intestine, as with the other 
animals; in this are produced the results of conception. This is 



2025 



clear in locusts and all other large insects whose nature it is to 
unite; most insects are too small to be observed in this respect. 

Such is the character of the generative organs in animals which 
were not spoken of before. It remains now to speak of the 
homogeneous parts concerned, the seminal fluid and milk. We 
will take the former first, and treat of milk afterwards. 



17 

Some animals manifestly emit semen, as all the sanguinea, but 
whether the insects and cephalopoda do so is uncertain. 
Therefore this is a question to be considered, whether all males 
do so, or not all; and if not all, why some do and some not; and 
whether the female also contributes any semen or not; and, if 
not semen, whether she does not contribute anything else 
either, or whether she contributes something else which is not 
semen. We must also inquire what those animals which emit 
semen contribute by means of it to generation, and generally 
what is the nature of semen, and of the so-called catamenia in 
all animals which discharge this liquid. 

Now it is thought that all animals are generated out of semen, 
and that the semen comes from the parents. Wherefore it is 
part of the same inquiry to ask whether both male and female 
produce it or only one of them, and to ask whether it comes 
from the whole of the body or not from the whole; for if the 
latter is true it is reasonable to suppose that it does not come 
from both parents either. Accordingly, since some say that it 
comes from the whole of the body, we must investigate this 
question first. 



2026 



The proofs from which it can be argued that the semen comes 
from each and every part of the body may be reduced to four. 
First, the intensity of the pleasure of coition; for the same state 
of feeling is more pleasant if multiplied, and that which affects 
all the parts is multiplied as compared with that which affects 
only one or a few. Secondly, the alleged fact that mutilations are 
inherited, for they argue that since the parent is deficient in this 
part the semen does not come from thence, and the result is 
that the corresponding part is not formed in the offspring. 
Thirdly, the resemblances to the parents, for the young are born 
like them part for part as well as in the whole body; if then the 
coming of the semen from the whole body is cause of the 
resemblance of the whole, so the parts would be like because it 
comes from each of the parts. Fourthly, it would seem to be 
reasonable to say that as there is some first thing from which 
the whole arises, so it is also with each of the parts, and 
therefore if semen or seed is cause of the whole so each of the 
parts would have a seed peculiar to itself. And these opinions 
are plausibly supported by such evidence as that children are 
born with a likeness to their parents, not in congenital but also 
in acquired characteristics; for before now, when the parents 
have had scars, the children have been born with a mark in the 
form of the scar in the same place, and there was a case at 
Chalcedon where the father had a brand on his arm and the 
letter was marked on the child, only confused and not clearly 
articulated. That is pretty much the evidence on which some 
believe that the semen comes from all the body. 



18 

On examining the question, however, the opposite appears 
more likely, for it is not hard to refute the above arguments and 



2027 



the view involves impossibilities. First, then, the resemblance of 
children to parents is no proof that the semen comes from the 
whole body, because the resemblance is found also in voice, 
nails, hair, and way of moving, from which nothing comes. And 
men generate before they yet have certain characters, such as a 
beard or grey hair. Further, children are like their more remote 
ancestors from whom nothing has come, for the resemblances 
recur at an interval of many generations, as in the case of the 
woman in Elis who had intercourse with the Aethiop; her 
daughter was not an Aethiop but the son of that daughter was. 
The same thing applies also to plants, for it is clear that if this 
theory were true the seed would come from all parts of plants 
also; but often a plant does not possess one part, and another 
part may be removed, and a third grows afterwards. Besides, the 
seed does not come from the pericarp, and yet this also comes 
into being with the same form as in the parent plant. 

We may also ask whether the semen comes from each of the 
homogeneous parts only, such as flesh and bone and sinew, or 
also from the heterogeneous, such as face and hands. For if 
from the former only, we object that resemblance exists rather 
in the heterogeneous parts, such as face and hands and feet; if 
then it is not because of the semen coming from all parts that 
children resemble their parents in these, what is there to stop 
the homogeneous parts also from being like for some other 
reason than this? If the semen comes from the heterogeneous 
alone, then it does not come from all parts; but it is more fitting 
that it should come from the homogeneous parts, for they are 
prior to the heterogeneous which are composed of them; and as 
children are born like their parents in face and hands, so they 
are, necessarily, in flesh and nails. If the semen comes from 
both, what would be the manner of generation? For the 
heteroeneous parts are composed of the homogneous, so that to 
come from the former would be to come from the latter and 
from their composition. To make this clearer by an illustration, 



2028 



take a written name; if anything came from the whole of it, it 
would be from each of the syllables, and if from these, from the 
letters and their composition. So that if really flesh and bones 
are composed of fire and the like elements, the semen would 
come rather from the elements than anything else, for how can 
it come from their composition? Yet without this composition 
there would be no resemblance. If again something creates this 
composition later, it would be this that would be the cause of 
the resemblance, not the coming of the semen from every part 
of the body. 

Further, if the parts of the future animal are separated in the 
semen, how do they live? and if they are connected, they would 
form a small animal. 

And what about the generative parts? For that which comes 
from the male is not similar to what comes from the female. 

Again, if the semen comes from all parts of both parents alike, 
the result is two animals, for the offspring will have all the parts 
of both. Wherefore Empedocles seems to say what agrees pretty 
well with this view (if we are to adopt it), to a certain extent at 
any rate, but to be wrong if we think otherwise. What he says 
agrees with it when he declares that there is a sort of tally in 
the male and female, and that the whole offspring does not 
come from either, 'but sundered is the fashion of limbs, some in 
man's...' For why does not the female generate from herself if 
the semen comes from all parts alike and she has a receptacle 
ready in the uterus? But, it seems, either it does not come from 
all the parts, or if it does it is in the way Empedocles says, not 
the same parts coming from each parent, which is why they 
need intercourse with each other. 

Yet this also is impossible, just as much as it is impossible for 
the parts when full grown to survive and have life in them 
when torn apart, as Empedocles accounts for the creation of 



2029 



animals; in the time of his 'Reign of Love', says he, 'many heads 
sprang up without necks,' and later on these isolated parts 
combined into animals. Now that this is impossible is plain, for 
neither would the separate parts be able to survive without 
having any soul or life in them, nor if they were living things, so 
to say, could several of them combine so as to become one 
animal again. Yet those who say that semen comes from the 
whole of the body really have to talk in that way, and as it 
happened then in the earth during the 'Reign of Love', so it 
happens according to them in the body. Now it is impossible 
that the parts should be united together when they come into 
being and should come from different parts of the parent, 
meeting together in one place. Then how can the upper and 
lower, right and left, front and back parts have been 'sundered? 
All these points are unintelligible. Further, some parts are 
distinguished by possessing a faculty, others by being in certain 
states or conditions; the heterogeneous, as tongue and hand, by 
the faculty of doing something, the homogeneous by hardness 
and softness and the other similar states. Blood, then, will not 
be blood, nor flesh flesh, in any and every state. It is clear, then, 
that that which comes from any part, as blood from blood or 
flesh from flesh, will not be identical with that part. But if it is 
something different from which the blood of the offspring 
comes, the coming of the semen from all the parts will not be 
the cause of the resemblance, as is held by the supporters of 
this theory. For if blood is formed from something which is not 
blood, it is enough that the semen come from one part only, for 
why should not all the other parts of the offspring as well as 
blood be formed from one part of the parent? Indeed, this 
theory seems to be the same as that of Anaxagoras, that none of 
the homogeneous parts come into being, except that these 
theorists assume, in the case of the generation of animals, what 
he assumed of the universe. 



2030 



Then, again, how will these parts that came from all the body of 
the parent be increased or grow? It is true that Anaxagoras 
plausibly says that particles of flesh out of the food are added to 
the flesh. But if we do not say this (while saying that semen 
comes from all parts of the body), how will the foetus become 
greater by the addition of something else if that which is added 
remain unchanged? But if that which is added can change, then 
why not say that the semen from the very first is of such a kind 
that blood and flesh can be made out of it, instead of saying 
that it itself is blood and flesh? Nor is there any other 
alternative, for surely we cannot say that it is increased later by 
a process of mixing, as wine when water is poured into it. For in 
that case each element of the mixture would be itself at first 
while still unmixed, but the fact rather is that flesh and bone 
and each of the other parts is such later. And to say that some 
part of the semen is sinew and bone is quite above us, as the 
saying is. 

Besides all this there is a difficulty if the sex is determined in 
conception (as Empedocles says: 'it is shed in clean vessels; 
some wax female, if they fall in with cold'). Anyhow, it is plain 
that both men and women change not only from infertile to 
fertile, but also from bearing female to bearing male offspring, 
which looks as if the cause does not lie in the semen coming 
from all the parent or not, but in the mutual proportion or 
disproportion of that comes from the woman and the man, or in 
something of this kind. It is clear, then, if we are to put this 
down as being so, that the female sex is not determined by the 
semen coming from any particular part, and consequently 
neither is the special sexual part so determined (if really the 
same semen can become either male or female child, which 
shows that the sexual part does not exist in the semen). Why, 
then, should we assert this of this part any more than of others? 
For if semen does not come from this part, the uterus, the same 
account may be given of the others. 



2031 



Again, some creatures come into being neither from parents of 
the same kind nor from parents of a different kind, as flies and 
the various kinds of what are called fleas; from these are 
produced animals indeed, but not in this case of similar nature 
but a kind of scolex. It is plain in this case that the young of a 
different kind are not produced by semen coming from all parts 
of the parent, for they would then resemble them, if indeed 
resemblance is a sign of its coming from all parts. 

Further even among animals some produce many young from a 
single coition (and something like this is universal among 
plants, for it is plain that they bear all the fruit of a whole 
season from a single movement). And yet how would this be 
possible if the semen were secreted from all the body? For from 
a single coition and a single segregation of the semen scattered 
throughout the body must needs follow only a single secretion. 
Nor is it possible for it to be separated in the uterus, for this 
would no longer be a mere separation of semen, but, as it were, 
a severance from a new plant or animal. 

Again, the cuttings from a plant bear seed; clearly, therefore, 
even before they were cut from the parent plant, they bore their 
fruit from their own mass alone, and the seed did not come 
from all the plant. 

But the greatest proof of all is derived from observations we 
have sufficiently established on insects. For, if not in all, at least 
in most of these, the female in the act of copulation inserts a 
part of herself into the male. This, as we said before, is the way 
they copulate, for the females manifestly insert this from below 
into the males above, not in all cases, but in most of those 
observed. Hence it seems clear that, when the males do emit 
semen, then also the cause of the generation is not its coming 
from all the body, but something else which must be 
investigated hereafter. For even if it were true that it comes 



2032 



from all the body, as they say, they ought not to claim that it 
comes from all parts of it, but only from the creative part - from 
the workman, so to say, not the material he works in. Instead of 
that, they talk as if one were to say that the semen comes from 
the shoes, for, generally speaking, if a son is like his father, the 
shoes he wears are like his father's shoes. 

As to the vehemence of pleasure in sexual intercourse, it is not 
because the semen comes from all the body, but because there 
is a strong friction (wherefore if this intercourse is often 
repeated the pleasure is diminished in the persons concerned). 
Moreover, the pleasure is at the end of the act, but it ought, on 
the theory, to be in each of the parts, and not at the same time, 
but sooner in some and later in others. 

If mutilated young are born of mutilated parents, it is for the 
same reason as that for which they are like them. And the 
young of mutilated parents are not always mutilated, just as 
they are not always like their parents; the cause of this must be 
inquired into later, for this problem is the same as that. 

Again, if the female does not produce semen, it is reasonable to 
suppose it does not come from all the body of the male either. 
Conversely, if it does not come from all the male it is not 
unreasonable to suppose that it does not come from the female, 
but that the female is cause of the generation in some other 
way. Into this we must next inquire, since it is plain that the 
semen is not secreted from all the parts. 

In this investigation and those which follow from it, the first 
thing to do is to understand what semen is, for then it will be 
easier to inquire into its operations and the phenomena 
connected with it. Now the object of semen is to be of such a 
nature that from it as their origin come into being those things 
which are naturally formed, not because there is any agent 
which makes them from it as simply because this is the semen. 



2033 



Now we speak of one thing coming from another in many 
senses; it is one thing when we say that night comes from day 
or a man becomes man from boy, meaning that A follows B; it is 
another if we say that a statue is made from bronze and a bed 
from wood, and so on in all the other cases where we say that 
the thing made is made from a material, meaning that the 
whole is formed from something preexisting which is only put 
into shape. In a third sense a man becomes unmusical from 
being musical, sick from being well, and generally in this sense 
contraries arise from contraries. Fourthly, as in the 'climax' of 
Epicharmus; thus from slander comes railing and from this 
fighting, and all these are from something in the sense that it is 
the efficient cause. In this last class sometimes the efficient 
cause is in the things themselves, as in the last mentioned (for 
the slander is a part of the whole trouble), and sometimes 
external, as the art is external to the work of art or the torch to 
the burning house. Now the offspring comes from the semen, 
and it is plainly in one of the two following senses that it does 
so - either the semen is the material from which it is made, or it 
is the first efficient cause. For assuredly it is not in the sense of 
A being after B, as the voyage comes from, i.e. after, the 
Panathenaea; nor yet as contraries come from contraries, for 
then one of the two contraries ceases to be, and a third 
substance must exist as an immediate underlying basis from 
which the new thing comes into being. We must discover then, 
in which of the two other classes the semen is to be put, 
whether it is to be regarded as matter, and therefore acted upon 
by something else, or as a form, and therefore acting upon 
something else, or as both at once. For perhaps at the same 
time we shall see clearly also how all the products of semen 
come into being from contraries, since coming into being from 
contraries is also a natural process, for some animals do so, i.e. 
from male and female, others from only one parent, as is the 
case with plants and all those animals in which male and 



2034 



female are not separately differentiated. Now that which comes 
from the generating parent is called the seminal fluid, being 
that which first has in it a principle of generation, in the case of 
all animals whose nature it is to unite; semen is that which has 
in it the principles from both united parents, as the first 
mixture which arises from the union of male and female, be it a 
foetus or an ovum, for these already have in them that which 
comes from both. (Semen, or seed, and grain differ only in the 
one being earlier and the other later, grain in that it comes from 
something else, i.e. the seed, and seed in that something else, 
the grain, comes from it, for both are really the same thing.) 

We must again take up the question what the primary nature of 
what is called semen is. Needs must everything which we find 
in the body either be (1) one of the natural parts, whether 
homogeneous or heterogeneous, or (2) an unnatural part such 
as a growth, or (3) a secretion or excretion, or (4) waste-product, 
or (5) nutriment. (By secretion or excretion I mean the residue of 
the nutriment, by waste-product that which is given off from 
the tissues by an unnatural decomposition.) 

Now that semen cannot be a part of the body is plain, for it is 
homogeneous, and from the homogeneous nothing is 
composed, e.g. from only sinew or only flesh; nor is it separated 
as are all the other parts. But neither is it contrary to Nature nor 
a defect, for it exists in all alike, and the development of the 
young animal comes from it. Nutriment, again, is obviously 
introduced from without. 

It remains, then, that it must be either a waste-product or a 
secretion or excretion. Now the ancients seem to think that it is 
a waste-product, for when they say that it comes from all the 
body by reason of the heat of the movement of the body in 
copulation, they imply that it is a kind of waste-product. But 



2035 



these are contrary to Nature, and from such arises nothing 
according to Nature. So then it must be a secretion or excretion. 

But, to go further into it, every secretion or excretion is either of 
useless or useful nutriment; by 'useless' I mean that from which 
nothing further is contributed to natural growth, but which is 
particularly mischievous to the body if too much of it is 
consumed; by 'useful' I mean the opposite. Now it is evident 
that it cannot be of the former character, for such is most 
abundant in persons of the worst condition of body through age 
or sickness; semen, on the contrary, is least abundant in them 
for either they have none at all or it is not fertile, because a 
useless and morbid secretion is mingled with it. 

Semen, then, is part of a useful secretion. But the most useful is 
the last and that from which finally is formed each of the parts 
of the body. For secretions are either earlier or later; of the 
nutriment in the first stage the secretion is phlegm and the like, 
for phlegm also is a secretion of the useful nutriment, an 
indication of this being that if it is mixed with pure nutriment it 
is nourishing, and that it is used up in cases of illness. The final 
secretion is the smallest in proportion to the quantity of 
nutriment. But we must reflect that the daily nutriment by 
which animals and plants grow is but small, for if a very little be 
added continually to the same thing the size of it will become 
excessive. 

So we must say the opposite of what the ancients said. For 
whereas they said that semen is that which comes from all the 
body, we shall say it is that whose nature is to go to all of it, and 
what they thought a waste-product seems rather to be a 
secretion. For it is more reasonable to suppose that the last 
extract of the nutriment which goes to all parts resembles that 
which is left over from it, just as part of a painter's colour is 
often left over resembling that which he has used up. Waste- 



2036 



products, on the contrary, are always due to corruption or decay 
and to a departure from Nature. 

A further proof that it is not a waste-product, but rather a 
secretion, is the fact that the large animals have few young, the 
small many For the large must have more waste and less 
secretion, since the great size of the body causes most of the 
nutriment to be used up, so that the residue or secretion is 
small. 

Again, no place has been set apart by Nature for waste-products 
but they flow wherever they can find an easy passage in the 
body, but a place has been set apart for all the natural 
secretions; thus the lower intestine serves for the excretion of 
the solid nutriment, the bladder for that of the liquid; for the 
useful part of the nutriment we have the upper intestine, for the 
spermatic secretions the uterus and pudenda and breasts, for it 
is collected and flows together into them. 

And the resulting phenomena are evidence that semen is what 
we have said, and these result because such is the nature of the 
secretion. For the exhaustion consequent on the loss of even a 
very little of the semen is conspicuous because the body is 
deprived of the ultimate gain drawn from the nutriment. With 
some few persons, it is true, during a short time in the flower of 
their youth the loss of it, if it be excessive in quantity, is an 
alleviation (just as in the case of the nutriment in its first stage, 
if too much have been taken, since getting rid of this also makes 
the body more comfortable), and so it may be also when other 
secretions come away with it, for in that case it is not only 
semen that is lost but also other influences come away mingled 
with it, and these are morbid. Wherefore, with some men at 
least, that which comes from them proves sometimes incapable 
of procreation because the seminal element in it is so small. But 
still in most men and as a general rule the result of intercourse 



2037 



is exhaustion and weakness rather than relief, for the reason 
given. Moreover, semen does not exist in them either in 
childhood or in old age or in sickness - in the last case because 
of weakness, in old age because they do not sufficiently concoct 
their food, and in childhood because they are growing and so all 
the nutriment is used up too soon, for in about five years, in the 
case of human beings at any rate, the body seems to gain half 
the height that is gained in all the rest of life. 

In many animals and plants we find a difference in this 
connexion not only between kinds as compared with kinds, but 
also between similar individuals of the same kind as compared 
with each other, e.g. man with man or vine with vine. Some 
have much semen, others little, others again none at all, not 
through weakness but the contrary, at any rate in some cases. 
This is because the nutriment is used up to form the body, as 
with some human beings, who, being in good condition and 
developing much flesh or getting rather too fat, produce less 
semen and are less desirous of intercourse. Like this is what 
happens with those vines which 'play the goat', that is, 
luxuriate wantonly through too much nutrition, for he-goats 
when fat are less inclined to mount the female; for which 
reason they thin them before breeding from them, and say that 
the vines 'play the goat', so calling it from the condition of the 
goats. And fat people, women as well as men, appear to be less 
fertile than others from the fact that the secretion when in 
process of concoction turns to fat with those who are too well- 
nourished. For fat also is a healthy secretion due to good living. 

In some cases no semen is produced at all, as by the willow and 
poplar. This condition is due to each of the two causes, 
weakness and strength; the former prevents concoction of the 
nutriment, the latter causes it to be all consumed, as said above. 
In like manner other animals produce much semen through 
weakness as well as through strength, when a great quantity of 



2038 



a useless secretion is mixed with it; this sometimes results in 
actual disease when a passage is not found to carry off the 
impurity, and though some recover of this, others actually die of 
it. For corrupt humours collect here as in the urine, which also 
has been known to cause disease. 

[Further the same passage serves for urine and semen; and 
whatever animals have both kinds of excrement, that of liquid 
and that of solid nutriment, discharge the semen by the same 
passage as the liquid excrement (for it is a secretion of a liquid, 
since the nutriment of all animals is rather liquid than solid), 
but those which have no liquid excrement discharge it at the 
passage of the solid residua. Moreover, waste-products are 
always morbid, but the removal of the secretion is useful; now 
the discharge of the semen participates in both characteristics 
because it takes up some of the non-useful nutriment. But if it 
were a waste-product it would be always harmful; as it is, it is 
not so.] 

From what has been said, it is clear that semen is a secretion of 
useful nutriment, and that in its last stage, whether it is 
produced by all or no. 



19 

After this we must distinguish of what sort of nutriment it is a 
secretion, and must discuss the catamenia which occur in 
certain of the vivipara. For thus we shall make it clear (1) 
whether the female also produces semen like the male and the 
foetus is a single mixture of two semens, or whether no semen 
is secreted by the female, and, (2) if not, whether she 
contributes nothing else either to generation but only provides a 



2039 



receptacle, or whether she does contribute something, and, if so, 
how and in what manner she does so. 

We have previously stated that the final nutriment is the blood 
in the sanguinea and the analogous fluid in the other animals. 
Since the semen is also a secretion of the nutriment, and that in 
its final stage, it follows that it will be either (1) blood or that 
which is analogous to blood, or (2) something formed from this. 
But since it is from the blood, when concocted and somehow 
divided up, that each part of the body is made, and since the 
semen if properly concocted is quite of a different character 
from the blood when it is separated from it, but if not properly 
concocted has been known in some cases to issue in a bloody 
condition if one forces oneself too often to coition, therefore it is 
plain that semen will be a secretion of the nutriment when 
reduced to blood, being that which is finally distributed to the 
parts of the body. And this is the reason why it has so great 
power, for the loss of the pure and healthy blood is an 
exhausting thing; for this reason also it is natural that the 
offspring should resemble the parents, for that which goes to all 
the parts of the body resembles that which is left over. So that 
the semen which is to form the hand or the face or the whole 
animal is already the hand or face or whole animal 
undifferentiated, and what each of them is actually such is the 
semen potentially, either in virtue of its own mass or because it 
has a certain power in itself. I mention these alternatives here 
because we have not yet made it clear from the distinctions 
drawn hitherto whether it is the matter of the semen that is the 
cause of generation, or whether it has in it some faculty and 
efficient cause thereof, for the hand also or any other bodily 
part is not hand or other part in a true sense if it be without 
soul or some other power, but is only called by the same name 
as the living hand. 



2040 



On this subject, then, so much may be laid down. But since it is 
necessary (1) that the weaker animal also should have a 
secretion greater in quantity and less concocted, and (2) that 
being of such a nature it should be a mass of sanguineous 
liquid, and (3) since that which Nature endows with a smaller 
portion of heat is weaker, and (4) since it has already been 
stated that such is the character of the female - putting all 
these considerations together we see that the sanguineous 
matter discharged by the female is also a secretion. And such is 
the discharge of the so-called catamenia. 

It is plain, then, that the catamenia are a secretion, and that 
they are analogous in females to the semen in males. The 
circumstances connected with them are evidence that this view 
is correct. For the semen begins to appear in males and to be 
emitted at the same time of life that the catamenia begin to 
flow in females, and that they change their voice and their 
breasts begin to develop. So, too, in the decline of life the 
generative power fails in the one sex and the catamenia in the 
other. 

The following signs also indicate that this discharge in females 
is a secretion. Generally speaking women suffer neither from 
haemorrhoids nor bleeding at the nose nor anything else of the 
sort except when the catamenia are ceasing, and if anything of 
the kind occurs the flow is interfered with because the 
discharge is diverted to it. 

Further, the blood-vessels of women stand out less than those 
of men, and women are rounder and smoother because the 
secretion which in men goes to these vessels is drained away 
with the catamenia. We must suppose, too, that the same cause 
accounts for the fact that the bulk of the body is smaller in 
females than in males among the vivipara, since this is the only 
class in which the catamenia are discharged from the body. And 



2041 



in this class the fact is clearest in women, for the discharge is 
greater in women than in the other animals. Wherefore her 
pallor and the absence of prominent blood-vessels is most 
conspicuous, and the deficient development of her body 
compared with a man's is obvious. 

Now since this is what corresponds in the female to the semen 
in the male, and since it is not possible that two such discharges 
should be found together, it is plain that the female does not 
contribute semen to the generation of the offspring. For if she 
had semen she would not have the catamenia; but, as it is, 
because she has the latter she has not the former. 

It has been stated then that the catamenia are a secretion as 
the semen is, and confirmation of this view may be drawn from 
some of the phenomena of animals. For fat creatures produce 
less semen than lean ones, as observed before. The reason is 
that fat also, like semen, is a secretion, is in fact concocted 
blood, only not concocted in the same way as the semen. Thus, 
if the secretion is consumed to form fat the semen is naturally 
deficient. And so among the bloodless animals the cephalopoda 
and Crustacea are in best condition about the time of producing 
eggs, for, because they are bloodless and no fat is formed in 
them, that which is analogous in them to fat is at that season 
drawn off to form the spermatic secretion. 

And a proof that the female does not emit similar semen to the 
male, and that the offspring is not formed by a mixture of both, 
as some say, is that often the female conceives without the 
sensation of pleasure in intercourse, and if again the pleasure is 
experience by her no less than by the male and the two sexes 
reach their goal together, yet often no conception takes place 
unless the liquid of the so-called catamenia is present in a right 
proportion. Hence the female does not produce young if the 
catamenia are absent altogether, nor often when, they being 



2042 



present, the efflux still continues; but she does so after the 
purgation. For in the one case she has not the nutriment or 
material from which the foetus can be framed by the power 
coming from the male and inherent in the semen, and in the 
other it is washed away with the catamenia because of their 
abundance. But when after their occurrence the greater part has 
been evacuated, the remainder is formed into a foetus. Cases of 
conception when the catamenia do not occur at all, or of 
conception during their discharge instead of after it, are due to 
the fact that in the former instance there is only so much liquid 
to begin with as remains behind after the discharge in fertile 
women, and no greater quantity is secreted so as to come away 
from the body, while in the latter instance the mouth of the 
uterus closes after the discharge. When, therefore, the quantity 
already expelled from the body is great but the discharge still 
continues, only not on such a scale as to wash away the semen, 
then it is that conception accompanies coition. Nor is it at all 
strange that the catamenia should still continue after 
conception (for even after it they recur to some extent, but are 
scanty and do not last during all the period of gestation; this, 
however, is a morbid phenomenon, wherefore it is found only in 
a few cases and then seldom, whereas it is that which happens 
as a regular thing that is according to Nature). 

It is clear then that the female contributes the material for 
generation, and that this is in the substance of the catamenia, 
and that they are a secretion. 



20 

Some think that the female contributes semen in coition 
because the pleasure she experiences is sometimes similar to 



2043 



that of the male, and also is attended by a liquid discharge. But 
this discharge is not seminal; it is merely proper to the part 
concerned in each case, for there is a discharge from the uterus 
which occurs in some women but not in others. It is found in 
those who are fair-skinned and of a feminine type generally, but 
not in those who are dark and of a masculine appearance. The 
amount of this discharge, when it occurs, is sometimes on a 
different scale from the emission of semen and far exceeds it. 
Moreover, different kinds of food cause a great difference in the 
quantity of such discharges; for instance some pungently- 
flavoured foods cause them to be conspicuously increased. And 
as to the pleasure which accompanies coition it is due to 
emission not only of semen, but also of a spiritus, the coming 
together of which precedes the emission. This is plain in the 
case of boys who are not yet able to emit semen, but are near 
the proper age, and of men who are impotent, for all these are 
capable of pleasure by attrition. And those who have been 
injured in the generative organs sometimes suffer from 
diarrhoea because the secretion, which they are not able to 
concoct and turn into semen, is diverted into the intestine. Now 
a boy is like a woman in form, and the woman is as it were an 
impotent male, for it is through a certain incapacity that the 
female is female, being incapable of concocting the nutriment 
in its last stage into semen (and this is either blood or that 
which is analogous to it in animals which are bloodless owing 
to the coldness of their nature). As then diarrhoea is caused in 
the bowels by the insufficient concoction of the blood, so are 
caused in the blood-vessels all discharges of blood, including 
that of the catamenia, for this also is such a discharge, only it is 
natural whereas the others are morbid. 

Thus it is clear that it is reasonable to suppose that generation 
comes from this. For the catamenia are semen not in a pure 
state but in need of working up, as in the formation of fruits the 
nutriment is present, when it is not yet sifted thoroughly, but 



2044 



needs working up to purify it. Thus the catamenia cause 
generation mixture with the semen, as this impure nutriment 
in plants is nutritious when mixed with pure nutriment. 

And a sign that the female does not emit semen is the fact that 
the pleasure of intercourse is caused by touch in the same 
region of the female as of the male; and yet is it not from 
thence that this flow proceeds. Further, it is not all females that 
have it at all, but only the sanguinea, and not all even of these, 
but only those whose uterus is not near the hypozoma and 
which do not lay eggs; it is not found in the animals which have 
no blood but only the analogous fluid (for what is blood in the 
former is represented by another fluid in the latter). The reason 
why neither the latter nor those sanguinea mentioned (i.e. 
those whose uterus is low and which do not lay eggs) have this 
effluxion is the dryness of their bodies; this allows but little 
matter to be secreted, only enough for generation but not 
enough to be discharged from the body. All animals that are 
viviparous without producing eggs first (such are man and all 
quadrupeds which bend their hind-legs outwards, for all these 
are viviparous without producing eggs) - all these have the 
catamenia, unless they are defective in development as the 
mule, only the efflux is not abundant as in women. Details of 
the facts in each animal have been given in the Enquiries 
concerning animals. 

The catamenia are more abundant in women than in the other 
animals, and men emit the most semen in proportion to their 
size. The reason is that the composition of their bodies is liquid 
and hot compared to others, for more matter must be secreted 
in such a case. Further, man has no such parts in his body as 
those to which the superfluous matter is diverted in the other 
animals; for he has no great quantity of hair in proportion to his 
body, nor outgrowths of bones, horns, and teeth. 



2045 



There is evidence that the semen is in the catamenia, for, as 
said before, this secretion appears in the male at the same time 
of life as the catamenia in the female; this indicates that the 
parts destined to receive each of these secretions are 
differentiated at the same time in both sexes; and as the 
neighboring parts in both become swollen the hair of puberty 
springs forth in both alike. As the parts in question are on the 
point of differentiating they are distended by the spiritus; this is 
clearer in males in the testes, but appears also about the 
breasts; in females it is more marked in the breasts, for it is 
when they have risen two fingers' breadth that the catamenia 
generally begin. 

Now, in all living things in which the male and female are not 
separated the semen (or seed) is a sort of embryo; by embryo I 
mean the first mixture of male and female; hence, from one 
semen comes one bodys - for example, one stalk of wheat from 
one grain, as one animal from one egg (for twin eggs are really 
two eggs). But in whatever kinds the sexes are distinguished, in 
these many animals may come from one emission of semen, 
showing that the semen differs in its nature in plants and 
animals. A proof of this is that animals which can bear more 
than one young one at a time do so in consequence of only one 
coition. Whereby, too, it is plain that the semen does not come 
from the whole of the body; for neither would the different 
parts of the semen already be separated as soon as discharged 
from the same part, nor could they be separated in the uterus if 
they had once entered it all together; but what does happen is 
just what one would expect, since what the male contributes to 
generation is the form and the efficient cause, while the female 
contributes the material. In fact, as in the coagulation of milk, 
the milk being the material, the fig-juice or rennet is that which 
contains the curdling principle, so acts the secretion of the 
male, being divided into parts in the female. Why it is 
sometimes divided into more or fewer parts, and sometimes not 



2046 



divided at all, will be the subject of another discussion. But 
because it does not differ in kind at any rate this does not 
matter, but what does matter is only that each part should 
correspond to the material, being neither too little to concoct it 
and fix it into form, nor too much so as to dry it up; it then 
generates a number of offspring. But from this first formative 
semen, if it remains one, and is not divided, only one young one 
comes into being. 

That, then, the female does not contribute semen to generation, 
but does contribute something, and that this is the matter of 
the catamenia, or that which is analogous to it in bloodless 
animals, is clear from what has been said, and also from a 
general and abstract survey of the question. For there must 
needs be that which generates and that from which it 
generates; even if these be one, still they must be distinct in 
form and their essence must be different; and in those animals 
that have these powers separate in two sexes the body and 
nature of the active and the passive sex must also differ. If, 
then, the male stands for the effective and active, and the 
female, considered as female, for the passive, it follows that 
what the female would contribute to the semen of the male 
would not be semen but material for the semen to work upon. 
This is just what we find to be the case, for the catamenia have 
in their nature an affinity to the primitive matter. 



21 

So much for the discussion of this question. At the same time 
the answer to the next question we have to investigate is clear 
from these considerations, I mean how it is that the male 
contributes to generation and how it is that the semen from the 



2047 



male is the cause of the offspring. Does it exist in the body of 
the embryo as a part of it from the first, mingling with the 
material which comes from the female? Or does the semen 
communicate nothing to the material body of the embryo but 
only to the power and movement in it? For this power is that 
which acts and makes, while that which is made and receives 
the form is the residue of the secretion in the female. Now the 
latter alternative appears to be the right one both a priori and in 
view of the facts. For, if we consider the question on general 
grounds, we find that, whenever one thing is made from two of 
which one is active and the other passive, the active agent does 
not exist in that which is made; and, still more generally, the 
same applies when one thing moves and another is moved; the 
moving thing does not exist in that which is moved. But the 
female, as female, is passive, and the male, as male, is active, 
and the principle of the movement comes from him. Therefore, 
if we take the highest genera under which they each fall, the 
one being active and motive and the other passive and moved, 
that one thing which is produced comes from them only in the 
sense in which a bed comes into being from the carpenter and 
the wood, or in which a ball comes into being from the wax and 
the form. It is plain then that it is not necessary that anything 
at all should come away from the male, and if anything does 
come away it does not follow that this gives rise to the embryo 
as being in the embryo, but only as that which imparts the 
motion and as the form; so the medical art cures the patient. 

This a priori argument is confirmed by the facts. For it is for this 
reason that some males which unite with the female do not, it 
appears, insert any part of themselves into the female, but on 
the contrary the female inserts a part of herself into the male; 
this occurs in some insects. For the effect produced by the 
semen in the female (in the case of those animals whose males 
do insert a part) is produced in the case of these insects by the 
heat and power in the male animal itself when the female 



2048 



inserts that part of herself which receives the secretion. And 
therefore such animals remain united a long time, and when 
they are separated the young are produced quickly. For the 
union lasts until that which is analogous to the semen has done 
its work, and when they separate the female produces the 
embryo quickly; for the young is imperfect inasmuch as all such 
creatures give birth to scoleces. 

What occurs in birds and oviparous fishes is the greatest proof 
that neither does the semen come from all parts of the male 
nor does he emit anything of such a nature as to exist within 
that which is generated, as part of the material embryo, but that 
he only makes a living creature by the power which resides in 
the semen (as we said in the case of those insects whose 
females insert a part of themselves into the male). For if a hen- 
bird is in process of producing wind-eggs and is then trodden by 
the cock before the egg has begun to whiten and while it is all 
still yellow, then they become fertile instead of being wind-eggs. 
And if while it is still yellow she be trodden by another cock, the 
whole brood of chicks turn out like the second cock. Hence 
some of those who are anxious to rear fine birds act thus; they 
change the cocks for the first and second treading, not as if they 
thought that the semen is mingled with the egg or exists in it, 
or that it comes from all parts of the cock; for if it did it would 
have come from both cocks, so that the chick would have all its 
parts doubled. But it is by its force that the semen of the male 
gives a certain quality to the material and the nutriment in the 
female, for the second semen added to the first can produce 
this effect by heat and concoction, as the egg acquires 
nutriment so long as it is growing. 

The same conclusion is to be drawn from the generation of 
oviparous fishes. When the female has laid her eggs, the male 
spinkles the milt over them, and those eggs are fertilized which 
it reaches, but not the others; this shows that the male does not 



2049 



contribute anything to the quantity but only to the quality of 
the embryo. 

From what has been said it is plain that the semen does not 
come from the whole of the body of the male in those animals 
which emit it, and that the contribution of the female to the 
generative product is not the same as that of the male, but the 
male contributes the principle of movement and the female the 
material. This is why the female does not produce offspring by 
herself, for she needs a principle, i.e. something to begin the 
movement in the embryo and to define the form it is to assume. 
Yet in some animals, as birds, the nature of the female 
unassisted can generate to a certain extent, for they do form 
something, only it is incomplete; I mean the so-called wind- 
eggs. 



22 

For the same reason the development of the embryo takes place 
in the female; neither the male himself nor the female emits 
semen into the male, but the female receives within herself the 
share contributed by both, because in the female is the material 
from which is made the resulting product. Not only must the 
mass of material exist there from which the embryo is formed 
in the first instance, but further material must constantly be 
added that it may increase in size. Therefore the birth must take 
place in the female. For the carpenter must keep in close 
connexion with his timber and the potter with his clay, and 
generally all workmanship and the ultimate movement 
imparted to matter must be connected with the material 
concerned, as, for instance, architecture is in the buildings it 
makes. 



2050 



From these considerations we may also gather how it is that the 
male contributes to generation. The male does not emit semen 
at all in some animals, and where he does this is no part of the 
resulting embryo; just so no material part comes from the 
carpenter to the material, i.e. the wood in which he works, nor 
does any part of the carpenter's art exist within what he makes, 
but the shape and the form are imparted from him to the 
material by means of the motion he sets up. It is his hands that 
move his tools, his tools that move the material; it is his 
knowledge of his art, and his soul, in which is the form, that 
moves his hands or any other part of him with a motion of 
some definite kind, a motion varying with the varying nature of 
the object made. In like manner, in the male of those animals 
which emit semen Nature uses the semen as a tool and as 
possessing motion in actuality, just as tools are used in the 
products of any art, for in them lies in a certain sense the 
motion of the art. Such, then, is the way in which these males 
contribute to generation. But when the male does not emit 
semen, but the female inserts some part of herself into the 
male, this is parallel to a case in which a man should carry the 
material to the workman. For by reason of weakness in such 
males Nature is not able to do anything by any secondary 
means, but the movements imparted to the material are 
scarcely strong enough when Nature herself watches over them. 
Thus here she resembles a modeller in clay rather than a 
carpenter, for she does not touch the work she is forming by 
means of tools, but, as it were, with her own hands. 



23 

In all animals which can move about, the sexes are separated, 
one individual being male and one female, though both are the 



2051 



same in species, as with man and horse. But in plants these 
powers are mingled, female not being separated from male. 
Wherefore they generate out of themselves, and do not emit 
semen but produce an embryo, what is called the seed. 
Empedocles puts this well in the line: 'and thus the tall trees 
oviposit; first olives...' For as the egg is an embryo, a certain part 
of it giving rise to the animal and the rest being nutriment, so 
also from a part of the seed springs the growing plant, and the 
rest is nutriment for the shoot and the first root. 

In a certain sense the same thing happens also in those animals 
which have the sexes separate. For when there is need for them 
to generate the sexes are no longer separated any more than in 
plants, their nature desiring that they shall become one; and 
this is plain to view when they copulate and are united, that 
one animal is made out of both. 

It is the nature of those creatures which do not emit semen to 
remain united a long time until the male element has formed 
the embryo, as with those insects which copulate. The others so 
remain only until the male has discharged from the parts of 
himself introduced something which will form the embryo in a 
longer time, as among the sanguinea. For the former remain 
paired some part of a day, while the semen forms the embryo in 
several days. And after emitting this they cease their union. 

And animals seem literally to be like divided plants, as though 
one should separate and divide them, when they bear seed, into 
the male and female existing in them. 

In all this Nature acts like an intelligent workman. For to the 
essence of plants belongs no other function or business than 
the production of seed; since, then, this is brought about by the 
union of male and female, Nature has mixed these and set 
them together in plants, so that the sexes are not divided in 
them. Plants, however, have been investigated elsewhere. But 



2052 



the function of the animal is not only to generate (which is 
common to all living things), but they all of them participate 
also in a kind of knowledge, some more and some less, and 
some very little indeed. For they have sense-perception, and 
this is a kind of knowledge. (If we consider the value of this we 
find that it is of great importance compared with the class of 
lifeless objects, but of little compared with the use of the 
intellect. For against the latter the mere participation in touch 
and taste seems to be practically nothing, but beside absolute 
insensibility it seems most excellent; for it would seem a 
treasure to gain even this kind of knowledge rather than to lie 
in a state of death and non-existence.) Now it is by sense- 
perception that an animal differs from those organisms which 
have only life. But since, if it is a living animal, it must also live; 
therefore, when it is necessary for it to accomplish the function 
of that which has life, it unites and copulates, becoming like a 
plant, as we said before. 

Testaceous animals, being intermediate between animals and 
plants, perform the function of neither class as belonging to 
both. As plants they have no sexes, and one does not generate 
in another; as animals they do not bear fruit from themselves 
like plants; but they are formed and generated from a liquid and 
earthy concretion. However, we must speak later of the 
generation of these animals. 



2053 



Book II 



That the male and the female are the principles of generation 
has been previously stated, as also what is their power and their 
essence. But why is it that one thing becomes and is male, 
another female? It is the business of our discussion as it 
proceeds to try and point out (1) that the sexes arise from 
Necessity and the first efficient cause, (2) from what sort of 
material they are formed. That (3) they exist because it is better 
and on account of the final cause, takes us back to a principle 
still further remote. 

Now (1) some existing things are eternal and divine whilst 
others admit of both existence and non-existence. But (2) that 
which is noble and divine is always, in virtue of its own nature, 
the cause of the better in such things as admit of being better or 
worse, and what is not eternal does admit of existence and non- 
existence, and can partake in the better and the worse. And (3) 
soul is better than body, and living, having soul, is thereby better 
than the lifeless which has none, and being is better than not 
being, living than not living. These, then, are the reasons of the 
generation of animals. For since it is impossible that such a 
class of things as animals should be of an eternal nature, 
therefore that which comes into being is eternal in the only way 
possible. Now it is impossible for it to be eternal as an 
individual (though of course the real essence of things is in the 
individual) - were it such it would be eternal - but it is possible 
for it as a species. This is why there is always a class of men and 
animals and plants. But since the male and female essences are 
the first principles of these, they will exist in the existing 



2054 



individuals for the sake of generation. Again, as the first 
efficient or moving cause, to which belong the definition and 
the form, is better and more divine in its nature than the 
material on which it works, it is better that the superior 
principle should be separated from the inferior. Therefore, 
wherever it is possible and so far as it is possible, the male is 
separated from the female. For the first principle of the 
movement, or efficient cause, whereby that which comes into 
being is male, is better and more divine than the material 
whereby it is female. The male, however, comes together and 
mingles with the female for the work of generation, because 
this is common to both. 

A thing lives, then, in virtue of participating in the male and 
female principles, wherefore even plants have some kind of life; 
but the class of animals exists in virtue of sense-perception. The 
sexes are divided in nearly all of these that can move about, for 
the reasons already stated, and some of them, as said before, 
emit semen in copulation, others not. The reason of this is that 
the higher animals are more independent in their nature, so 
that they have greater size, and this cannot exist without vital 
heat; for the greater body requires more force to move it, and 
heat is a motive force. Therefore, taking a general view, we may 
say that sanguinea are of greater size than bloodless animals, 
and those which move about than those which remain fixed. 
And these are just the animals which emit semen on account of 
their heat and size. 

So much for the cause of the existence of the two sexes. Some 
animals bring to perfection and produce into the world a 
creature like themselves, as all those which bring their young 
into the world alive; others produce something undeveloped 
which has not yet acquired its own form; in this latter division 
the sanguinea lay eggs, the bloodless animals either lay an egg 
or give birth to a scolex. The difference between egg and scolex 



2055 



is this: an egg is that from a part of which the young comes into 
being, the rest being nutriment for it; but the whole of a scolex 
is developed into the whole of the young animal. Of the 
vivipara, which bring into the world an animal like themselves, 
some are internally viviparous (as men, horses, cattle, and of 
marine animals dolphins and the other cetacea); others first lay 
eggs within themselves, and only after this are externally 
viviparous (as the cartilaginous fishes). Among the ovipara 
some produce the egg in a perfect condition (as birds and all 
oviparous quadrupeds and footless animals, e.g. lizards and 
tortoises and most snakes; for the eggs of all these do not 
increase when once laid). The eggs of others are imperfect; such 
are those of fishes, crustaceans, and cephalopods, for their eggs 
increase after being produced. 

All the vivipara are sanguineous, and the sanguinea are either 
viviparous or oviparous, except those which are altogether 
infertile. Among bloodless animals the insects produce a scolex, 
alike those that are generated by copulation and those that 
copulate themselves though not so generated. For there are 
some insects of this sort, which though they come into being by 
spontaneous generation are yet male and female; from their 
union something is produced, only it is imperfect; the reason of 
this has been previously stated. 

These classes admit of much cross-division. Not all bipeds are 
viviparous (for birds are oviparous), nor are they all oviparous 
(for man is viviparous), nor are all quadrupeds oviparous (for 
horses, cattle, and countless others are viviparous), nor are they 
all viviparous (for lizards, crocodiles, and many others lay eggs). 
Nor does the presence or absence of feet make the difference 
between them, for not only are some footless animals 
viviparous, as vipers and the cartilaginous fishes, while others 
are oviparous, as the other fishes and serpents, but also among 
those which have feet many are oviparous and many 



2056 



viviparous, as the quadrupeds above mentioned. And some 
which have feet, as man, and some which have not, as the 
whale and dolphin, are internally viviparous. By this character 
then it is not possible to divide them, nor is any of the 
locomotive organs the cause of this difference, but it is those 
animals which are more perfect in their nature and participate 
in a purer element which are viviparous, for nothing is 
internally viviparous unless it receive and breathe out air. But 
the more perfect are those which are hotter in their nature and 
have more moisture and are not earthy in their composition. 
And the measure of natural heat is the lung when it has blood 
in it, for generally those animals which have a lung are hotter 
than those which have not, and in the former class again those 
whose lung is not spongy nor solid nor containing only a little 
blood, but soft and full of blood. And as the animal is perfect but 
the egg and the scolex are imperfect, so the perfect is naturally 
produced from the more perfect. If animals are hotter as shown 
by their possessing a lung but drier in their nature, or are colder 
but have more moisture, then they either lay a perfect egg or are 
viviparous after laying an egg within themselves. For birds and 
scaly reptiles because of their heat produce a perfect egg, but 
because of their dryness it is only an egg; the cartilaginous 
fishes have less heat than these but more moisture, so that they 
are intermediate, for they are both oviparous and viviparous 
within themselves, the former because they are cold, the latter 
because of their moisture; for moisture is vivifying, whereas 
dryness is furthest removed from what has life. Since they have 
neither feathers nor scales such as either reptiles or other fishes 
have, all which are signs rather of a dry and earthy nature, the 
egg they produce is soft; for the earthy matter does not come to 
the surface in their eggs any more than in themselves. This is 
why they lay eggs in themselves, for if the egg were laid 
externally it would be destroyed, having no protection. 



2057 



Animals that are cold and rather dry than moist also lay eggs, 
but the egg is imperfect; at the same time, because they are of 
an earthy nature and the egg they produce is imperfect, 
therefore it has a hard integument that it may be preserved by 
the protection of the shell-like covering. Hence fishes, because 
they are scaly, and Crustacea, because they are of an earthy 
nature, lay eggs with a hard integument. 

The cephalopods, having themselves bodies of a sticky nature, 
preserve in the same way the imperfect eggs they lay, for they 
deposit a quantity of sticky material about the embryo. All 
insects produce a scolex. Now all the insects are bloodless, 
wherefore all creatures that produce a scolex from themselves 
are so. But we cannot say simply that all bloodless animals 
produce a scolex, for the classes overlap one another, (1) the 
insects, (2) the animals that produce a scolex, (3) those that lay 
their egg imperfect, as the scaly fishes, the Crustacea, and the 
cephalopoda. I say that these form a gradation, for the eggs of 
these latter resemble a scolex, in that they increase after 
oviposition, and the scolex of insects again as it develops 
resembles an egg; how so we shall explain later. 

We must observe how rightly Nature orders generation in 
regular gradation. The more perfect and hotter animals produce 
their young perfect in respect of quality (in respect of quantity 
this is so with no animal, for the young always increase in size 
after birth), and these generate living animals within 
themselves from the first. The second class do not generate 
perfect animals within themselves from the first (for they are 
only viviparous after first laying eggs), but still they are 
externally viviparous. The third class do not produce a perfect 
animal, but an egg, and this egg is perfect. Those whose nature 
is still colder than these produce an egg, but an imperfect one, 
which is perfected outside the body, as the class of scaly fishes, 
the Crustacea, and the cephalopods. The fifth and coldest class 



2058 



does not even lay an egg from itself; but so far as the young ever 
attain to this condition at all, it is outside the body of the 
parent, as has been said already. For insects produce a scolex 
first; the scolex after developing becomes egg-like (for the so- 
called chrysalis or pupa is equivalent to an egg); then from this 
it is that a perfect animal comes into being, reaching the end of 
its development in the second change. 

Some animals then, as said before, do not come into being from 
semen, but all the sanguinea do so which are generated by 
copulation, the male emitting semen into the female when this 
has entered into her the young are formed and assume their 
peculiar character, some within the animals themselves when 
they are viviparous, others in eggs. 

There is a considerable difficulty in understanding how the 
plant is formed out of the seed or any animal out of the semen. 
Everything that comes into being or is made must (1) be made 
out of something, (2) be made by the agency of something, and 
(3) must become something. Now that out of which it is made is 
the material; this some animals have in its first form within 
themselves, taking it from the female parent, as all those which 
are not born alive but produced as a scolex or an egg; others 
receive it from the mother for a long time by sucking, as the 
young of all those which are not only externally but also 
internally viviparous. Such, then, is the material out of which 
things come into being, but we now are inquiring not out of 
what the parts of an animal are made, but by what agency. 
Either it is something external which makes them, or else 
something existing in the seminal fluid and the semen; and this 
must either be soul or a part of soul, or something containing 
soul. 

Now it would appear irrational to suppose that any of either the 
internal organs or the other parts is made by something 



2059 



external, since one thing cannot set up a motion in another 
without touching it, nor can a thing be affected in any way by 
another if it does not set up a motion in it. Something then of 
the sort we require exists in the embryo itself, being either a 
part of it or separate from it. To suppose that it should be 
something else separate from it is irrational. For after the 
animal has been produced does this something perish or does it 
remain in it? But nothing of the kind appears to be in it, nothing 
which is not a part of the whole plant or animal. Yet, on the 
other hand, it is absurd to say that it perishes after making 
either all the parts or only some of them. If it makes some of 
the parts and then perishes, what is to make the rest of them? 
Suppose this something makes the heart and then perishes, 
and the heart makes another organ, by the same argument 
either all the parts must perish or all must remain. Therefore it 
is preserved and does not perish. Therefore it is a part of the 
embryo itself which exists in the semen from the beginning; 
and if indeed there is no part of the soul which does not exist in 
some part of the body, it would also be a part containing soul in 
it from the beginning. 

How, then, does it make the other parts? Either all the parts, as 
heart, lung, liver, eye, and all the rest, come into being together 
or in succession, as is said in the verse ascribed to Orpheus, for 
there he says that an animal comes into being in the same way 
as the knitting of a net. That the former is not the fact is plain 
even to the senses, for some of the parts are clearly visible as 
already existing in the embryo while others are not; that it is 
not because of their being too small that they are not visible is 
clear, for the lung is of greater size than the heart, and yet 
appears later than the heart in the original development. Since, 
then, one is earlier and another later, does the one make the 
other, and does the later part exist on account of the part which 
is next to it, or rather does the one come into being only after 
the other? I mean, for instance, that it is not the fact that the 



2060 



heart, having come into being first, then makes the liver, and 
the liver again another organ, but that the liver only comes into 
being after the heart, and not by the agency of the heart, as a 
man becomes a man after being a boy, not by his agency. An 
explanation of this is that, in all the productions of Nature or of 
art, what already exists potentially is brought into being only by 
what exists actually; therefore if one organ formed another the 
form and the character of the later organ would have to exist in 
the earlier, e.g. the form of the liver in the heart. And otherwise 
also the theory is strange and fictitious. 

Yet again, if the whole animal or plant is formed from semen or 
seed, it is impossible that any part of it should exist ready made 
in the semen or seed, whether that part be able to make the 
other parts or no. For it is plain that, if it exists in it from the 
first, it was made by that which made the semen. But semen 
must be made first, and that is the function of the generating 
parent. So, then, it is not possible that any part should exist in 
it, and therefore it has not within itself that which makes the 
parts. 

But neither can this agent be external, and yet it must needs be 
one or other of the two. We must try, then, to solve this 
difficulty, for perhaps some one of the statements made cannot 
be made without qualification, e.g. the statement that the parts 
cannot be made by what is external to the semen. For if in a 
certain sense they cannot, yet in another sense they can. (Now 
it makes no difference whether we say 'the semen' or 'that from 
which the semen comes', in so far as the semen has in itself the 
movement initiated by the other.) It is possible, then, that A 
should move B, and B move C; that, in fact, the case should be 
the same as with the automatic machines shown as curiosities. 
For the parts of such machines while at rest have a sort of 
potentiality of motion in them, and when any external force 
puts the first of them in motion, immediately the next is moved 



2061 



in actuality. As, then, in these automatic machines the external 
force moves the parts in a certain sense (not by touching any 
part at the moment, but by having touched one previously), in 
like manner also that from which the semen comes, or in other 
words that which made the semen, sets up the movement in 
the embryo and makes the parts of it by having first touched 
something though not continuing to touch it. In a way it is the 
innate motion that does this, as the act of building builds the 
house. Plainly, then, while there is something which makes the 
parts, this does not exist as a definite object, nor does it exist in 
the semen at the first as a complete part. 

But how is each part formed? We must answer this by starting 
in the first instance from the principle that, in all products of 
Nature or art, a thing is made by something actually existing 
out of that which is potentially such as the finished product. 
Now the semen is of such a nature, and has in it such a 
principle of motion, that when the motion is ceasing each of the 
parts comes into being, and that as a part having life or soul. For 
there is no such thing as face or flesh without life or soul in it; it 
is only equivocally that they will be called face or flesh if the life 
has gone out of them, just as if they had been made of stone or 
wood. And the homogeneous parts and the organic come into 
being together. And just as we should not say that an axe or 
other instrument or organ was made by the fire alone, so 
neither shall we say that foot or hand were made by heat alone. 
The same applies also to flesh, for this too has a function. 
While, then, we may allow that hardness and softness, 
stickiness and brittleness, and whatever other qualities are 
found in the parts that have life and soul, may be caused by 
mere heat and cold, yet, when we come to the principle in 
virtue of which flesh is flesh and bone is bone, that is no longer 
so; what makes them is the movement set up by the male 
parent, who is in actuality what that out of which the offspring 
is made is in potentiality. This is what we find in the products of 



2062 



art; heat and cold may make the iron soft and hard, but what 
makes a sword is the movement of the tools employed, this 
movement containing the principle of the art. For the art is the 
starting-point and form of the product; only it exists in 
something else, whereas the movement of Nature exists in the 
product itself, issuing from another nature which has the form 
in actuality. 

Has the semen soul, or not? The same argument applies here as 
in the question concerning the parts. As no part, if it participate 
not in soul, will be a part except in an equivocal sense (as the 
eye of a dead man is still called an 'eye'), so no soul will exist in 
anything except that of which it is soul; it is plain therefore that 
semen both has soul, and is soul, potentially. 

But a thing existing potentially may be nearer or further from 
its realization in actuality, as e.g. a mathematician when asleep 
is further from his realization in actuality as engaged in 
mathematics than when he is awake, and when awake again 
but not studying mathematics he is further removed than when 
he is so studying. Accordingly it is not any part that is the cause 
of the soul's coming into being, but it is the first moving cause 
from outside. (For nothing generates itself, though when it has 
come into being it thenceforward increases itself.) Hence it is 
that only one part comes into being first and not all of them 
together. But that must first come into being which has a 
principle of increase (for this nutritive power exists in all alike, 
whether animals or plants, and this is the same as the power 
that enables an animal or plant to generate another like itself, 
that being the function of them all if naturally perfect). And this 
is necessary for the reason that whenever a living thing is 
produced it must grow. It is produced, then, by something else 
of the same name, as e.g. man is produced by man, but it is 
increased by means of itself. There is, then, something which 
increases it. If this is a single part, this must come into being 



2063 



first. Therefore if the heart is first made in some animals, and 
what is analogous to the heart in the others which have no 
heart, it is from this or its analogue that the first principle of 
movement would arise. 

We have thus discussed the difficulties previously raised on the 
question what is the efficient cause of generation in each case, 
as the first moving and formative power. 



The next question to be mooted concerns the nature of semen. 
For whereas when it issues from the animal it is thick and 
white, yet on cooling it becomes liquid as water, and its colour 
is that of water. This would appear strange, for water is not 
thickened by heat; yet semen is thick when it issues from 
within the animal's body which is hot, and becomes liquid on 
cooling. Again, watery fluids freeze, but semen, if exposed in 
frosts to the open air, does not freeze but liquefies, as if it was 
thickened by the opposite of cold. Yet it is unreasonable, again, 
to suppose that it is thickened by heat. For it is only substances 
having a predominance of earth in their composition that 
coagulate and thicken on boiling, e.g. milk. It ought then to 
solidify on cooling, but as a matter of fact it does not become 
solid in any part but the whole of it goes like water. 

This then is the difficulty. If it is water, water evidently does not 
thicken through heat, whereas the semen is thick and both it 
and the body whence it issues are hot. If it is made of earth or a 
mixture of earth and water, it ought not to liquefy entirely and 
turn to water. 



2064 



Perhaps, however, we have not discriminated all the 
possibilities. It is not only the liquids composed of water and 
earthy matter that thicken, but also those composed of water 
and air; foam, for instance, becomes thicker and white, and the 
smaller and less visible the bubbles in it, the whiter and firmer 
does the mass appear. The same thing happens also with oil; on 
mixing with air it thickens, wherefore that which is whitening 
becomes thicker, the watery part in it being separated off by the 
heat and turning to air. And if oxide of lead is mixed with water 
or even with oil, the mass increases greatly and changes from 
liquid and dark to firm and white, the reason being that air is 
mixed in with it which increases the mass and makes the white 
shine through, as in foam and snow (for snow is foam). And 
water itself on mingling with oil becomes thick and white, 
because air is entangled in it by the act of pounding them 
together, and oil itself has much air in it (for shininess is a 
property of air, not of earth or water). This too is why it floats on 
the surface of the water, for the air contained in it as in a vessel 
bears it up and makes it float, being the cause of its lightness. 
So too oil is thickened without freezing in cold weather and 
frosts; it does not freeze because of its heat (for the air is hot 
and will not freeze), but because the air is forced together and 
compressed, as..., by the cold, the oil becomes thicker. These are 
the reasons why semen is firm and white when it issues from 
within the animal; it has a quantity of hot air in it because of 
the internal heat; afterwards, when the heat has evaporated 
and the air has cooled, it turns liquid and dark; for the water, 
and any small quantity of earthy matter there may be, remain 
in semen as it dries, as they do in phlegm. 

Semen, then, is a compound of spirit (pneuma) and water, and 
the former is hot air (aerh); hence semen is liquid in its nature 
because it is made of water. What Ctesias the Cnidian has 
asserted of the semen of elephants is manifestly untrue; he 
says that it hardens so much in drying that it becomes like 



2065 



amber. But this does not happen, though it is true that one 
semen must be more earthy than another, and especially so 
with animals that have much earthy matter in them because of 
the bulk of their bodies. And it is thick and white because it is 
mixed with spirit, for it is also an invariable rule that it is white, 
and Herodotus does not report the truth when he says that the 
semen of the Aethiopians is black, as if everything must needs 
be black in those who have a black skin, and that too when he 
saw their teeth were white. The reason of the whiteness of 
semen is that it is a foam, and foam is white, especially that 
which is composed of the smallest parts, small in the sense that 
each bubble is invisible, which is what happens when water and 
oil are mixed and shaken together, as said before. (Even the 
ancients seem to have noticed that semen is of the nature of 
foam; at least it was from this they named the goddess who 
presides over union.) 

This then is the explanation of the problem proposed, and it is 
plain too that this is why semen does not freeze; for air will not 
freeze. 



The next question to raise and to answer is this. If, in the case 
of those animals which emit semen into the female, that which 
enters makes no part of the resulting embryo, where is the 
material part of it diverted if (as we have seen) it acts by means 
of the power residing in it? It is not only necessary to decide 
whether what is forming in the female receives anything 
material, or not, from that which has entered her, but also 
concerning the soul in virtue of which an animal is so called 
(and this is in virtue of the sensitive part of the soul) - does this 



2066 



exist originally in the semen and in the unfertilized embryo or 
not, and if it does whence does it come? For nobody would put 
down the unfertilized embryo as soulless or in every sense 
bereft of life (since both the semen and the embryo of an 
animal have every bit as much life as a plant), and it is 
productive up to a certain point. That then they possess the 
nutritive soul is plain (and plain is it from the discussions 
elsewhere about soul why this soul must be acquired first). As 
they develop they also acquire the sensitive soul in virtue of 
which an animal is an animal. For e.g. an animal does not 
become at the same time an animal and a man or a horse or 
any other particular animal. For the end is developed last, and 
the peculiar character of the species is the end of the generation 
in each individual. Hence arises a question of the greatest 
difficulty, which we must strive to solve to the best of our ability 
and as far as possible. When and how and whence is a share in 
reason acquired by those animals that participate in this 
principle? It is plain that the semen and the unfertilized 
embryo, while still separate from each other, must be assumed 
to have the nutritive soul potentially, but not actually, except 
that (like those unfertilized embryos that are separated from 
the mother) it absorbs nourishment and performs the function 
of the nutritive soul. For at first all such embryos seem to live 
the life of a plant. And it is clear that we must be guided by this 
in speaking of the sensitive and the rational soul. For all three 
kinds of soul, not only the nutritive, must be possessed 
potentially before they are possessed in actuality. And it is 
necessary either (1) that they should all come into being in the 
embryo without existing previously outside it, or (2) that they 
should all exist previously, or (3), that some should so exist and 
others not. Again, it is necessary that they should either (1) 
come into being in the material supplied by the female without 
entering with the semen of the male, or (2) come from the male 
and be imparted to the material in the female. If the latter, then 



2067 



either all of them, or none, or some must come into being in the 
male from outside. 

Now that it is impossible for them all to preexist is clear from 
this consideration. Plainly those principles whose activity is 
bodily cannot exist without a body, e.g. walking cannot exist 
without feet. For the same reason also they cannot enter from 
outside. For neither is it possible for them to enter by 
themselves, being inseparable from a body, nor yet in a body, for 
the semen is only a secretion of the nutriment in process of 
change. It remains, then, for the reason alone so to enter and 
alone to be divine, for no bodily activity has any connexion with 
the activity of reason. 

Now it is true that the faculty of all kinds of soul seems to have 
a connexion with a matter different from and more divine than 
the so-called elements; but as one soul differs from another in 
honour and dishonour, so differs also the nature of the 
corresponding matter. All have in their semen that which 
causes it to be productive; I mean what is called vital heat. This 
is not fire nor any such force, but it is the spiritus included in 
the semen and the foam-like, and the natural principle in the 
spiritus, being analogous to the element of the stars. Hence, 
whereas fire generates no animal and we do not find any living 
thing forming in either solids or liquids under the influence of 
fire, the heat of the sun and that of animals does generate 
them. Not only is this true of the heat that works through the 
semen, but whatever other residuum of the animal nature there 
may be, this also has still a vital principle in it. From such 
considerations it is clear that the heat in animals neither is fire 
nor derives its origin from fire. 

Let us return to the material of the semen, in and with which 
comes away from the male the spiritus conveying the principle 
of soul. Of this principle there are two kinds; the one is not 



2068 



connected with matter, and belongs to those animals in which 
is included something divine (to wit, what is called the reason), 
while the other is inseparable from matter. This material of the 
semen dissolves and evaporates because it has a liquid and 
watery nature. Therefore we ought not to expect it always to 
come out again from the female or to form any part of the 
embryo that has taken shape from it; the case resembles that of 
the fig-juice which curdles milk, for this too changes without 
becoming any part of the curdling masses. 

It has been settled, then, in what sense the embryo and the 
semen have soul, and in what sense they have not; they have it 
potentially but not actually. 

Now semen is a secretion and is moved with the same 
movement as that in virtue of which the body increases (this 
increase being due to subdivision of the nutriment in its last 
stage). When it has entered the uterus it puts into form the 
corresponding secretion of the female and moves it with the 
same movement wherewith it is moved itself. For the female's 
contribution also is a secretion, and has all the arts in it 
potentially though none of them actually; it has in it potentially 
even those parts which differentiate the female from the male, 
for just as the young of mutilated parents are sometimes born 
mutilated and sometimes not, so also the young born of a 
female are sometimes female and sometimes male instead. For 
the female is, as it were, a mutilated male, and the catamenia 
are semen, only not pure; for there is only one thing they have 
not in them, the principle of soul. For this reason, whenever a 
wind-egg is produced by any animal, the egg so forming has in 
it the parts of both sexes potentially, but has not the principle in 
question, so that it does not develop into a living creature, for 
this is introduced by the semen of the male. When such a 
principle has ben imparted to the secretion of the female it 
becomes an embryo. 



2069 



Liquid but corporeal substances become surrounded by some 
kind of covering on heating, like the solid scum which forms on 
boiled foods when cooling. All bodies are held together by the 
glutinous; this quality, as the embryo develops and increases in 
size, is acquired by the sinewy substance, which holds together 
the parts of animals, being actual sinew in some and its 
analogue in others. To the same class belong also skin, blood- 
vessels, membranes, and the like, for these differ in being more 
or less glutinous and generally in excess and deficiency. 



In those animals whose nature is comparatively imperfect, 
when a perfect embryo (which, however, is not yet a perfect 
animal) has been formed, it is cast out from the mother, for 
reasons previously stated. An embryo is then complete when it 
is either male or female, in the case of those animals who 
possess this distinction, for some (i.e. all those which are not 
themselves produced from a male or female parent nor from a 
union of the two) produce an offspring which is neither male 
nor female. Of the generation of these we shall speak later. 

The perfect animals, those internally viviparous, keep the 
developing embryo within themselves and in close connexion 
until they give birth to a complete animal and bring it to light. 

A third class is externally viviparous but first internally 
oviparous; they develop the egg into a perfect condition, and 
then in some cases the egg is set free as with creatures 
externally oviparous, and the animal is produced from the egg 
within the mother's body; in other cases, when the nutriment 
from the egg is consumed, development is completed by 
connection with the uterus, and therefore the egg is not set free 



2070 



from the uterus. This character marks the cartilaginous fish, of 
which we must speak later by themselves. 

Here we must make our first start from the first class; these are 
the perfect or viviparous animals, and of these the first is man. 
Now the secretion of the semen takes place in all of them just 
as does that of any other residual matter. For each is conveyed 
to its proper place without any force from the breath or 
compulsion of any other cause, as some assert, saying that the 
generative parts attract the semen like cupping-glasses, aided 
by the force of the breath, as if it were possible for either this 
secretion or the residue of the solid and liquid nutriment to go 
anywhere else than they do without the exertion of such a 
force. Their reason is that the discharge of both is attended by 
holding the breath, but this is a common feature of all cases 
when it is necessary to move anything, because strength arises 
through holding the breath. Why, even without this force the 
secretions or excretions are discharged in sleep if the parts 
concerned are full of them and are relaxed. One might as well 
say that it is by the breath that the seeds of plants are always 
segregated to the places where they are wont to bear fruit. No, 
the real cause, as has been stated already, is that there are 
special parts for receiving all the secretions, alike the useless (as 
the residues of the liquid and solid nutriment), and the blood, 
which has the so-called blood-vessels. 

To consider now the region of the uterus in the female - the two 
blood-vessels, the great vessel and the aorta, divide higher up, 
and many fine vessels from them terminate in the uterus. These 
become over-filled from the nourishment they convey, nor is the 
female nature able to concoct it, because it is colder than man's; 
so the blood is excreted through very fine vessels into the 
uterus, these being unable on account of their narrowness to 
receive the excessive quantity, and the result is a sort of 
haemorrhage. The period is not accurately defined in women, 



2071 



but tends to return during the waning of the moon. This we 
should expect, for the bodies of animals are colder when the 
environment happens to become so, and the time of change 
from one month to another is cold because of the absence of 
the moon, whence also it results that this time is stormier than 
the middle of the month. When then the residue of the 
nourishment has changed into blood, the catamenia tend to 
occur at the above-mentioned period, but when it is not 
concocted a little matter at a time is always coming away, and 
this is why 'whites' appear in females while still small, in fact 
mere children. If both these discharges of the secretions are 
moderate, the body remains in good health, for they act as a 
purification of the secretions which are the causes of a morbid 
state of body; if they do not occur at all or if they are excessive, 
they are injurious, either causing illness or pulling down the 
patient; hence whites, if continuous and excessive, prevent girls 
from growing. This secretion then is necessarily discharged by 
females for the reasons given; for, the female nature being 
unable to concoct the nourishment thoroughly, there must not 
only be left a residue of the useless nutriment, but also there 
must be a residue in the blood-vessels, and this filling the 
channels of the finest vessels must overflow. Then Nature, 
aiming at the best end, uses it up in this place for the sake of 
generation, that another creature may come into being of the 
same kind as the former was going to be, for the menstrual 
blood is already potentially such as the body from which it is 
discharged. 

In all females, then, there must necessarily be such a secretion, 
more indeed in those that have blood and of these most of all in 
man, but in the others also some matter must be collected in 
the uterine region. The reason why there is more in those that 
have blood and most in man has been already given, but why, if 
all females have such a secretion, have not all males one to 
correspond? For some of them do not emit semen but, just as 



2072 



those which do emit it fashion by the movement in the semen 
the mass forming from the material supplied by the female, so 
do the animals in question bring the same to pass and exert the 
same formative power by the movement within themselves in 
that part from whence the semen is secreted. This is the region 
about the diaphragm in all those animals which have one, for 
the heart or its analogue is the first principle of a natural body, 
while the lower part is a mere addition for the sake of it. Now 
the reason why it is not all males that have a generative 
secretion, while all females do, is that the animal is a body with 
Soul or life; the female always provides the material, the male 
that which fashions it, for this is the power that we say they 
each possess, and this is what is meant by calling them male 
and female. Thus while it is necessary for the female to provide 
a body and a material mass, it is not necessary for the male, 
because it is not within the work of art or the embryo that the 
tools or the maker must exist. While the body is from the 
female, it is the soul that is from the male, for the soul is the 
reality of a particular body. For this reason if animals of a 
different kind are crossed (and this is possible when the periods 
of gestation are equal and conception takes place nearly at the 
same season and there is no great difference in the of the 
animals), the first cross has a common resemblance to both 
parents, as the hybrid between fox and dog, partridge and 
domestic fowl, but as time goes on and one generation springs 
from another, the final result resembles the female in form, just 
as foreign seeds produce plants varying in accordance with the 
country in which they are sown. For it is the soil that gives to 
the seeds the material and the body of the plant. And hence the 
part of the female which receives the semen is not a mere 
passage, but the uterus has a considerable width, whereas the 
males that emit semen have only passages for this purpose, and 
these are bloodless. 



2073 



Each of the secretions becomes such at the moment when it is 
in its proper place; before that there is nothing of the sort 
unless with much violence and contrary to nature. 

We have thus stated the reason for which the generative 
secretions are formed in animals. But when the semen from the 
male (in those animals which emit semen) has entered, it puts 
into form the purest part of the female secretion (for the greater 
part of the catamenia also is useless and fluid, as is the most 
fluid part of the male secretion, i.e. in a single emission, the 
earlier discharge being in most cases apt to be infertile rather 
than the later, having less vital heat through want of 
concoction, whereas that which is concocted is thick and of a 
more material nature). 

If there is no external discharge, either in women or other 
animals, on account of there not being much useless and 
superfluous matter in the secretion, then the quantity forming 
within the female altogether is as much as what is retained 
within those animals which have an external discharge; this is 
put into form by the power of the male residing in the semen 
secreted by him, or, as is clearly seen to happen in some insects, 
by the part in the female analogous to the uterus being inserted 
into the male. 

It has been previously stated that the discharge accompanying 
sexual pleasure in the female contributes nothing to the 
embryo. The chief argument for the opposite view is that what 
are called bad dreams occur by night with women as with men; 
but this is no proof, for the same thing happens to young men 
also who do not yet emit semen, and to those who do emit 
semen but whose semen is infertile. 

It is impossible to conceive without the emission of the male in 
union and without the secretion of the corresponding female 
material, whether it be discharged externally or whether there 



2074 



is only enough within the body. Women conceive, however, 
without experiencing the pleasure usual in such intercourse, if 
the part chance to be in heat and the uterus to have descended. 
But generally speaking the opposite is the case, because the os 
uteri is not closed when the discharge takes place which is 
usually accompanied by pleasure in women as well as men, and 
when this is so there is a readier way for the semen of the male 
to be drawn into the uterus. 

The actual discharge does not take place within the uterus as 
some think, the os uteri being too narrow, but it is in the region 
in front of this, where the female discharges the moisture found 
in some cases, that the male emits the semen. Sometimes it 
remains in this place; at other times, if the uterus chance to be 
conveniently placed and hot on account of the purgation of the 
catamenia, it draws it within itself. A proof of this is that 
pessaries, though wet when applied, are removed dry. Moreover, 
in all those animals which have the uterus near the hypozoma, 
as birds and viviparous fishes, it is impossible that the semen 
should be so discharged as to enter it; it must be drawn into it. 
This region, on account of the heat which is in it, attracts the 
semen. The discharge and collection of the catamenia also 
excite heat in this part. Hence it acts like cone-shaped vessels 
which, when they have been washed out with hot water, their 
mouth being turned downwards, draw water into themselves. 
And this is the way things are drawn up, but some say that 
nothing of the kind happens with the organic parts concerned 
in copulation. Precisely the opposite is the case of those who 
say the woman emits semen as well as the man, for if she emits 
it outside the uterus this must then draw it back again into 
itself if it is to be mixed with the semen of the male. But this is 
a superfluous proceeding, and Nature does nothing superfluous. 

When the material secreted by the female in the uterus has 
been fixed by the semen of the male (this acts in the same way 



2075 



as rennet acts upon milk, for rennet is a kind of milk containing 
vital heat, which brings into one mass and fixes the similar 
material, and the relation of the semen to the catamenia is the 
same, milk and the catamenia being of the same nature) - 
when, I say, the more solid part comes together, the liquid is 
separated off from it, and as the earthy parts solidify 
membranes form all round it; this is both a necessary result and 
for a final cause, the former because the surface of a mass must 
solidify on heating as well as on cooling, the latter because the 
foetus must not be in a liquid but be separated from it. Some of 
these are called membranes and others choria, the difference 
being one of more or less, and they exist in ovipara and vivipara 
alike. 

When the embryo is once formed, it acts like the seeds of 
plants. For seeds also contain the first principle of growth in 
themselves, and when this (which previously exists in them 
only potentially) has been differentiated, the shoot and the root 
are sent off from it, and it is by the root that the plant gets 
nourishment; for it needs growth. So also in the embryo all the 
parts exist potentially in a way at the same time, but the first 
principle is furthest on the road to realization. Therefore the 
heart is first differentiated in actuality. This is clear not only to 
the senses (for it is so) but also on theoretical grounds. For 
whenever the young animal has been separated from both 
parents it must be able to manage itself, like a son who has set 
up house away from his father. Hence it must have a first 
principle from which comes the ordering of the body at a later 
stage also, for if it is to come in from outside at later period to 
dwell in it, not only may the question be asked at what time it is 
to do so, but also we may object that, when each of the parts is 
separating from the rest, it is necessary that this principle 
should exist first from which comes growth and movement to 
the other parts. (Wherefore all who say, as did Democritus, that 
the external parts of animals are first differentiated and the 



2076 



internal later, are much mistaken; it is as if they were talking of 
animals of stone or wood. For such as these have no principle of 
growth at all, but all animals have, and have it within 
themselves.) Therefore it is that the heart appears first 
distinctly marked off in all the sanguinea, for this is the first 
principle or origin of both homogeneous and heterogeneous 
parts, since from the moment that the animal or organism 
needs nourishment, from that moment does this deserve to be 
called its principle or origin. For the animal grows, and the 
nutriment, in its final stage, of an animal is the blood or its 
analogue, and of this the blood-vessels are the receptacle, 
wherefore the heart is the principle or origin of these also. (This 
is clear from the Enquiries and the anatomical drawings.) 

Since the embryo is already potentially an animal but an 
imperfect one, it must obtain its nourishment from elsewhere; 
accordingly it makes use of the uterus and the mother, as a 
plant does of the earth, to get nourishment, until it is perfected 
to the point of being now an animal potentially locomotive. So 
Nature has first designed the two blood-vessels from the heart, 
and from these smaller vessels branch off to the uterus. These 
are what is called the umbilicus, for this is a blood-vessel, 
consisting of one or more vessels in different animals. Round 
these is a skin-like integument, because the weakness of the 
vessels needs protection and shelter. The vessels join on to the 
uterus like the roots of plants, and through them the embryo 
receives its nourishment. This is why the animal remains in the 
uterus, not, as Democritus says, that the parts of the embryo 
may be moulded in conformity with those of the mother. This is 
plain in the ovipara, for they have their parts differentiated in 
the egg after separation from the matrix. 

Here a difficulty may be raised. If the blood is the nourishment, 
and if the heart, which first comes into being, already contains 
blood, and the nourishment comes from outside, whence did 



2077 



the first nourishment enter? Perhaps it is not true that all of it 
comes from outside just as in the seeds of plants there is 
something of this nature, the substance which at first appears 
milky, so also in the material of the animal embryo the 
superfluous matter of which it is formed is its nourishment 
from the first. 

The embryo, then, grows by means of the umbilicus in the same 
way as a plant by its roots, or as animals themselves when 
separated from the nutriment within the mother, of which we 
must speak later at the time appropriate for discussing them. 
But the parts are not differentiated, as some suppose, because 
like is naturally carried to like. Besides many other difficulties 
involved in this theory, it results from it that the homogeneous 
parts ought to come into being each one separate from the rest, 
as bones and sinews by themselves, and flesh by itself, if one 
should accept this cause. The real cause why each of them 
comes into being is that the secretion of the female is 
potentially such as the animal is naturally, and all the parts are 
potentially present in it, but none actually. It is also because 
when the active and the passive come in contact with each 
other in that way in which the one is active and the other 
passive (I mean in the right manner, in the right place, and at 
the right time), straightway the one acts and the other is acted 
upon. The female, then, provides matter, the male the principle 
of motion. And as the products of art are made by means of the 
tools of the artist, or to put it more truly by means of their 
movement, and this is the activity of the art, and the art is the 
form of what is made in something else, so is it with the power 
of the nutritive soul. As later on in the case of mature animals 
and plants this soul causes growth from the nutriment, using 
heat and cold as its tools (for in these is the movement of the 
soul), and each thing comes into being in accordance with a 
certain formula, so also from the beginning does it form the 
product of nature. For the material by which this latter grows is 



2078 



the same as that from which it is constituted at first; 
consequently also the power which acts upon it is identical 
with that which originally generated it; if then this acting power 
is the nutritive soul, this is also the generative soul, and this is 
the nature of every organism, existing in all animals and plants. 
[But the other parts of the soul exist in some animals, not in 
others.] In plants, then, the female is not separated from the 
male, but in those animals in which it is separated the male 
needs the female besides. 



And yet the question may be raised why it is that, if indeed the 
female possesses the same soul and if it is the secretion of the 
female which is the material of the embryo, she needs the male 
besides instead of generating entirely from herself. The reason 
is that the animal differs from the plant by having sense- 
perception; if the sensitive soul is not present, either actually or 
potentially, and either with or without qualification, it is 
impossible for face, hand, flesh, or any other part to exist; it will 
be no better than a corpse or part of a corpse. If then, when the 
sexes are separated, it is the male that has the power of making 
the sensitive soul, it is impossible for the female to generate an 
animal from itself alone, for the process in question was seen to 
involve the male quality. Certainly that there is a good deal in 
the difficulty stated is plain in the case of the birds that lay 
wind-eggs, showing that the female can generate up to a certain 
point unaided. But this still involves a difficulty; in what way 
are we to say that their eggs live? It neither possible that they 
should live in the same way as fertile eggs (for then they would 
produce a chick actually alive), nor yet can they be called eggs 
only in the sense in which an egg of wood or stone is so called, 



2079 



for the fact that these eggs go bad shows that they previously 
participate in some way in life. It is plain, then, that they have 
some soul potentially. What sort of soul will this be? It must be 
the lowest surely, and this is the nutritive, for this exists in all 
animals and plants alike. Why then does it not perfect the parts 
and the animal? Because they must have a sensitive soul, for 
the parts of animals are not like those of a plant. And so the 
female animal needs the help of the male, for in these animals 
we are speaking of the male is separate. This is exactly what we 
find, for the wind-eggs become fertile if the male tread the 
female in a certain space of time. About the cause of these 
things, however, we shall enter into detail later. 

If there is any kind of animal which is female and has no male 
separate from it, it is possible that this may generate a young 
one from itself without copulation. No instance of this worthy 
of credit has been observed up to the present at any rate, but 
one case in the class of fishes makes us hesitate. No male of the 
so-called erythrinus has ever yet been seen, but females, and 
specimens full of roe, have been seen. Of this, however, we have 
as yet no proof worthy of credit. Again, some members of the 
class of fishes are neither male nor female, as eels and a kind of 
mullets found in stagnant waters. But whenever the sexes are 
separate the female cannot generate perfectly by herself alone, 
for then the male would exist in vain, and Nature makes 
nothing in vain. Hence in such animals the male always 
perfects the work of generation, for he imparts the sensitive 
soul, either by means of the semen or without it. Now the parts 
of the embryo already exist potentially in the material, and so 
when once the principle of movement has been imparted to 
them they develop in a chain one after another, as the wheels 
are moved one by another in the automatic machines. When 
some of the natural philosophers say that like is brought to like, 
this must be understood, not in the sense that the parts are 
moved as changing place, but that they stay where they are and 



2080 



the movement is a change of quality (such as softness, 
hardness, colour, and the other differences of the homogeneous 
parts); thus they become in actuality what they previously were 
in potentiality. And what comes into being first is the first 
principle; this is the heart in the sanguinea and its analogue in 
the rest, as has been often said already. This is plain not only to 
the senses (that it is first to come into being), but also in view of 
its end; for life fails in the heart last of all, and it happens in all 
cases that what comes into being last fails first, and the first 
last, Nature running a double course, so to say, and turning back 
to the point from whence she started. For the process of 
becoming is from the non-existent to the existent, and that of 
perishing is back again from the existent to the non-existent. 



After this, as said already, the internal parts come into being 
before the external. The greater become visible before the less, 
even if some of them do not come into being before them. First 
the parts above the hypozoma are differentiated and are 
superior in size; the part below is both smaller and less 
differentiated. This happens in all animals in which exists the 
distinction of upper and lower, except in the insects; the growth 
of those that produce a scolex is towards the upper part, for this 
is smaller in the beginning. The cephalopoda are the only 
locomotive animals in which the distinction of upper and lower 
does not exist. 

What has been said applies to plants also, that the upper 
portion is earlier in development than the lower, for the roots 
push out from the seed before the shoots. 



2081 



The agency by which the parts of animals are differentiated is 
air, not however that of the mother nor yet of the embryo itself, 
as some of the physicists say. This is manifest in birds, fishes, 
and insects. For some of these are separated from the mother 
and produced from an egg, within which the differentiation 
takes place; other animals do not breathe at all, but are 
produced as a scolex or an egg; those which do breathe and 
whose parts are differentiated within the mother's uterus yet do 
not breathe until the lung is perfected, and the lung and the 
preceding parts are differentiated before they breathe. 
Moreover, all polydactylous quadrupeds, as dog, lion, wolf, fox, 
jackal, produce their young blind, and the eyelids do not 
separate till after birth. Manifestly the same holds also in all the 
other parts; as the qualitative, so also the quantitative 
differentia comes into being, pre-existing potentially but being 
actualized later by the same causes by which the qualitative 
distinction is produced, and so the eyelids become two instead 
of one. Of course air must be present, because heat and 
moisture are present, the former acting and the latter being 
acted upon. 

Some of the ancient nature-philosolphers made an attempt to 
state which part comes into being after which, but were not 
sufficiently acquainted with the facts. It is with the parts as 
with other things; one naturally exists prior to another. But the 
word 'prior' is used in more senses than one. For there is a 
difference between the end or final cause and that which exists 
for the sake of it; the latter is prior in order of development, the 
former is prior in reality. Again, that which exists for the sake of 
the end admits of division into two classes, (1) the origin of the 
movement, (2) that which is used by the end; I mean, for 
instance, (1) that which can generate, (2) that which serves as 
an instrument to what is generated, for the one of these, that 
which makes, must exist first, as the teacher before the learner, 
and the other later, as the pipes are later than he who learns to 



2082 



play upon them, for it is superfluous that men who do not know 
how to play should have pipes. Thus there are three things: first, 
the end, by which we mean that for the sake of which 
something else exists; secondly, the principle of movement and 
of generation, existing for the sake of the end (for that which 
can make and generate, considered simply as such, exists only 
in relation to what is made and generated); thirdly, the useful, 
that is to say what the end uses. Accordingly, there must first 
exist some part in which is the principle of movement (I say a 
part because this is from the first one part of the end and the 
most important part too); next after this the whole and the end; 
thirdly and lastly, the organic parts serving these for certain 
uses. Hence if there is anything of this sort which must exist in 
animals, containing the principle and end of all their nature, 
this must be the first to come into being - first, that is, 
considered as the moving power, but simultaneous with the 
whole embryo if considered as a part of the end. Therefore all 
the organic parts whose nature is to bring others into being 
must always themselves exist before them, for they are for the 
sake of something else, as the beginning for the sake of the end; 
all those parts which are for the sake of something else but are 
not of the nature of beginnings must come into being later. So it 
is not easy to distinguish which of the parts are prior, those 
which are for the sake of another or that for the sake of which 
are the former. For the parts which cause the movement, being 
prior to the end in order of development, come in to cause 
confusion, and it is not easy to distinguish these as compared 
with the organic parts. And yet it is in accordance with this 
method that we must inquire what comes into being after what; 
for the end is later than some parts and earlier than others. And 
for this reason that part which contains the first principle 
comes into being first, next to this the upper half of the body. 
This is why the parts about the head, and particularly the eyes, 
appear largest in the embryo at an early stage, while the parts 



2083 



below the umbilicus, as the legs, are small; for the lower parts 
are for the sake of the upper, and are neither parts of the end 
nor able to form it. 

But they do not say well nor do they assign a necessary cause 
who say simply that 'it always happens so', and imagine that 
this is a first principle in these cases. Thus Democritus of 
Abdera says that 'there is no beginning of the infinite; now the 
cause is a beginning, and the eternal is infinite; in consequence, 
to ask the cause of anything of this kind is to seek for a 
beginning of the infinite'. Yet according to this argument, which 
forbids us to seek the cause, there will be no proof of any 
eternal truth whatever; but we see that there is a proof of many 
such, whether by 'eternal' we mean what always happens or 
what exists eternally; it is an eternal truth that the angles of a 
triangle are always equal to two right angles, or that the 
diagonal of a square is incommensurable with the side, and 
nevertheless a cause and a proof can be given for these truths. 
While, then, it is well said that we must not take on us to seek a 
beginning (or first principle) of all things, yet this is not well 
said of all things whatever that always are or always happen, 
but only of those which really are first principles of the eternal 
things; for it is by another method, not by proof, that we acquire 
knowledge of the first principle. Now in that which is 
immovable and unchanging the first principle is simply the 
essence of the thing, but when we come to those things which 
come into being the principles are more than one, varying in 
kind and not all of the same kind; one of this number is the 
principle of movement, and therefore in all the sanguinea the 
heart is formed first, as was said at the beginning, and in the 
other animals that which is analogous to the heart. 

From the heart the blood-vessels extend throughout the body as 
in the anatomical diagrams which are represented on the wall, 
for the parts lie round these because they are formed out of 



2084 



them. The homogeneous parts are formed by heat and cold, for 
some are put together and solidified by the one and some by 
the other. The difference between these has already been 
discussed elsewhere, and it has been stated what kinds of 
things are soluble by liquid and fire, and what are not soluble by 
liquid and cannot be melted by fire. The nutriment then oozes 
through the blood-vessels and the passages in each of the parts, 
like water in unbaked pottery, and thus is formed the flesh or its 
analogues, being solidified by cold, which is why it is also 
dissolved by fire. But all the particles given off which are too 
earthy, having but little moisture and heat, cool as the moisture 
evaporates along with the heat; so they become hard and earthy 
in character, as nails, horns, hoofs, and beaks, and therefore 
they are softened by fire but none of them is melted by it, while 
some of them, as egg-shells, are soluble in liquids. The sinews 
and bones are formed by the internal heat as the moisture dries, 
and hence the bones are insoluble by fire like pottery, for like it 
they have been as it were baked in an oven by the heat in the 
process of development. But it is not anything whatever that is 
made into flesh or bone by the heat, but only something 
naturally fitted for the purpose; nor is it made in any place or 
time whatever, but only in a place and time naturally so fitted. 
For neither will that which exists potentially be made except by 
that moving agent which possesses the actuality, nor will that 
which possesses the actuality make anything whatever; the 
carpenter would not make a box except out of wood, nor will a 
box be made out of the wood without the carpenter. The heat 
exists in the seminal secretion, and the movement and activity 
in it is sufficient in kind and in quantity to correspond to each 
of the parts. In so far as there is any deficiency or excess, the 
resulting product is in worse condition or physically defective, 
in like manner as in the case of external substances which are 
thickened by boiling that they may be more palatable or for any 
other purpose. But in the latter case it is we who apply the heat 



2085 



in due measure for the motion required; in the former it is the 
nature of the male parent that gives it, or with animals 
spontaneously generated it is the movement and heat imparted 
by the right season of the year that it is the cause. 

Cooling, again, is mere deprivation of heat. Nature makes use of 
both; they have of necessity the power of bringing about 
different results, but in the development of the embryo we find 
that the one cools and the other heats for some definite 
purpose, and so each of the parts is formed; thus it is in one 
sense by necessity, in another for a final cause, that they make 
the flesh soft, the sinews solid and elastic, the bones solid and 
brittle. The skin, again, is formed by the drying of the flesh, like 
the scum upon boiled substances; it is so formed not only 
because it is on the outside, but also because what is glutinous, 
being unable to evaporate, remains on the surface. While in 
other animals the glutinous is dry, for which reason the 
covering of the invertebrates is testaceous or crustaceous, in the 
vertebrates it is rather of the nature of fat. In all of these which 
are not of too earthy a nature the fat is collected under the 
covering of the skin, a fact which points to the skin being 
formed out of such a glutinous substance, for fat is somewhat 
glutinous. As we said, all these things must be understood to be 
formed in one sense of necessity, but in another sense not of 
necessity but for a final cause. 

The upper half of the body, then, is first marked out in the order 
of development; as time goes on the lower also reaches its full 
size in the sanguinea. All the parts are first marked out in their 
outlines and acquire later on their colour and softness or 
hardness, exactly as if Nature were a painter producing a work 
of art, for painters, too, first sketch in the animal with lines and 
only after that put in the colours. 



2086 



Because the source of the sensations is in the heart, therefore 
this is the part first formed in the whole animal, and because of 
the heat of this organ the cold forms the brain, where the blood- 
vessels terminate above, corresponding to the heat of the heart. 
Hence the parts about the head begin to form next in order after 
the heart, and surpass the other parts in size, for the brain is 
from the first large and fluid. 

There is a difficulty about what happens with the eyes of 
animals. Though from the beginning they appear very large in 
all creatures, whether they walk or swim or fly, yet they are the 
last of the parts to be formed completely, for in the intervening 
time they collapse. The reason is this. The sense-organ of the 
eyes is set upon certain passages, as are the other sense-organs. 
Whereas those of touch and taste are simply the body itself or 
some part of the body of animals, those of smell and hearing 
are passages connecting with the external air and full 
themselves of innate spiritus; these passages end at the small 
blood-vessels about the brain which run thither from the heart. 
But the eye is the only sense-organ that has a bodily 
constitution peculiar to itself. It is fluid and cold, and does not 
exist from the first in the place which it occupies later in the 
same way as the other parts do, for they exist potentially to 
begin with and actually come into being later, but the eye is the 
purest part of the liquidity about the brain drained off through 
the passages which are visible running from them to the 
membrane round the brain. A proof of this is that, apart from 
the brain, there is no other part in the head that is cold and 
fluid except the eye. Of necessity therefore this region is large at 
first but falls in later. For the same thing happens with the 
brain; at first it is liquid and large, but in course of evaporation 
and concoction it becomes more solid and falls in; this applies 
both to the brain and the eyes. The head is very large at first, on 
account of the brain, and the eyes appear large because of the 
liquid in them. They are the last organs to reach completion 



2087 



because the brain is formed with difficulty; for it is at a late 
period that it gets rid of its coldness and fluidity; this applies to 
all animals possessing a brain, but especially to man. For this 
reason the 'bregma' is the last of the bones to be formed; even 
after birth this bone is still soft in children. The cause of this 
being so with men more than with other animals is the fact that 
their brain is the most fluid and largest. This again is because 
the heat in man's heart is purest. His intellect shows how well 
he is tempered, for man is the wisest of animals. And children 
for a long time have no control over their heads on account of 
the heaviness of the brain; and the same applies to the parts 
which it is necessary to move, for it is late that the principle of 
motion gets control over the upper parts, and last of all over 
those whose motion is not connected directly with it, as that of 
the legs is not. Now the eyelid is such a part. But since Nature 
makes nothing superfluous nor in vain, it is clear also that she 
makes nothing too late or too soon, for if she did the result 
would be either in vain or superfluous. Hence it is necessary 
that the eyelids should be separated at the same time as the 
heart is able to move them. So then the eyes of animals are 
perfected late because of the amount of concoction required by 
the brain, and last of all the parts because the motion must be 
very strong before it can affect parts so far from the first 
principle of motion and so cold. And it is plain that such is the 
nature of the eyelids, for if the head is affected by never so little 
heaviness through sleepiness or drunkenness or anything else 
of the kind, we cannot raise the eyelids though their own 
weight is so small. So much for the question how the eyes come 
into being, and why and for what cause they are the last to be 
fully developed. 

Each of the other parts is formed out of the nutriment, those 
most honourable and participating in the sovereign principle 
from the nutriment which is first and purest and fully 
concocted, those which are only necessary for the sake of the 



2088 



former parts from the inferior nutriment and the residues left 
over from the other. For Nature, like a good householder, is not 
in the habit of throwing away anything from which it is possible 
to make anything useful. Now in a household the best part of 
the food that comes in is set apart for the free men, the inferior 
and the residue of the best for the slaves, and the worst is given 
to the animals that live with them. Just as the intellect acts thus 
in the outside world with a view to the growth of the persons 
concerned, so in the case of the embryo itself does Nature form 
from the purest material the flesh and the body of the other 
sense-organs, and from the residues thereof bones, sinews, hair, 
and also nails and hoofs and the like; hence these are last to 
assume their form, for they have to wait till the time when 
Nature has some residue to spare. 

The bones, then, are made in the first conformation of the parts 
from the seminal secretion or residue. As the animal grows the 
bones grow from the natural nourishment, being the same as 
that of the sovereign parts, but of this they only take up the 
superfluous residues. For everywhere the nutriment may be 
divided into two kinds, the first and the second; the former is 
'nutritious', being that which gives its essence both to the whole 
and to the parts; the latter is concerned with growth, being that 
which causes quantitative increase. But these must be 
distinguished more fully later on. The sinews are formed in the 
same way as the bones and out of the same materials, the 
Seminal and nutritious residue. Nails, hair, hoofs, horns, beaks, 
the spurs of cocks, and any other similar parts, are on the 
contrary formed from the nutriment which is taken later and 
only concerned with growth, in other words that which is 
derived from the mother, or from the outer world after birth. For 
this reason the bones on the one hand only grow up to a certain 
point (for there is a limit of size in all animals, and therefore 
also of the growth of the bones; if these had been always able to 
grow, all animals that have bone or its analogue would grow as 



2089 



long as they lived, for these set the limit of size to animals. 
What is the reason of their not always increasing in size must 
be stated later.) Hair, on the contrary, and growths akin to hair 
go on growing as long as they exist at all, and increase yet more 
in diseases and when the body is getting old and wasting, 
because more residual matter is left over, as owing to old age 
and disease less is expended on the important parts, though 
when the residual matter also fails through age the hair fails 
with it. But the contrary is the case with the bones, for they 
waste away along with the body and the other parts. Hair 
actually goes on growing after death; it does not, however, begin 
growing then. 

About the teeth a difficulty may be raised. They have actually 
the same nature as the bones, and are formed out of the bones, 
but nails, hair, horns, and the like are formed out of the skin, 
and that is why they change in colour along with it, for they 
become white, black, and all sorts of colours according to that of 
the skin. But the teeth do nothing of the sort, for they are made 
out of the bones in all animals that have both bones and teeth. 
Of all the bones they alone go on growing through life, as is 
plain with the teeth which grow out of the straight line so as no 
longer to touch each other. The reason for their growth, as a 
final cause, is their function, for they would soon be worn down 
if there were not some means of saving them; even as it is they 
are altogether worn down in old age in some animals which eat 
much and have not large teeth, their growth not being in 
proportion to their detrition. And so Nature has contrived well 
to meet the case in this also, for she causes the failure of the 
teeth to synchronize with old age and death. If life lasted for a 
thousand or ten thousand years the original teeth must have 
been very large indeed, and many sets of them must have been 
produced, for even if they had grown continuously they would 
still have been worn smooth and become useless for their work. 
The final cause of their growth has been now stated, but besides 



2090 



this as a matter of fact the growth of the teeth is not the same 
as that of the other bones. The latter all come into being in the 
first formation of the embryo and none of them later, but the 
teeth do so later. Therefore it is possible for them to grow again 
after the first set falls out, for though they touch the bones they 
are not connate with them. They are formed, however, out of 
the nutriment distributed to the bones, and so have the same 
nature, even when the bones have their own number complete. 

Other animals are born in possession of teeth or their analogue 
(unless in cases contrary to Nature), because when they are set 
free from the parent they are more perfect than man; but man 
(also unless in cases contrary to Nature) is born without them. 

The reason will be stated later why some teeth are formed and 
fall out but others do not fall out. 

It is because such parts are formed from a residue that man is 
the most naked in body of all animals and has the smallest 
nails in proportion to his size; he has the least amount of earthy 
residue, but that part of the blood which is not concocted is the 
residue, and the earthy part in the bodies of all animals is the 
least concocted. We have now stated how each of the parts is 
formed and what is the cause of their generation. 



In viviparous animals, as said before, the embryo gets its growth 
through the umbilical cord. For since the nutritive power of the 
soul, as well as the others, is present in animals, it straightway 
sends off this cord like a root to the uterus. The cord consists of 
blood-vessels in a sheath, more numerous in the larger animals 
as cattle and the like, one in the smallest, two in those of 



2091 



intermediate size. Through this cord the embryo receives its 
nourishment in the form of blood, for the uterus is the 
termination of many blood-vessels. All animals with no front 
teeth in the upper jaw, and all those which have them in both 
jaws and whose uterus has not one great blood-vessel running 
through it but many close together instead - all these have in 
the uterus the so-called cotyledons (with which the umbilical 
cord connects and is closely united; for the vessels which pass 
through the cord run backwards and forwards between embryo 
and uterus and split up into smaller vessels all over the uterus; 
where they terminate, there are found the cotyledons). Their 
convexity is turned towards the uterus, the concavity towards 
the embryo. Between uterus and embryo are the chorion and 
the membranes. As the embryo grows and approaches 
perfection the cotyledons become smaller and finally disappear 
when it is perfected. For Nature sends the sanguineous 
nutriment for the embryo into this part of the uterus as she 
sends milk into the breasts, and because the cotyledons are 
gradually aggregated from many into a few the body of the 
cotyledon becomes like an eruption or inflammation. So long as 
the embryo is comparatively small, being unable to receive 
much nutriment, they are plain and large, but when it has 
increased in size they fall in together. 

But most of the animals which have front teeth in both jaws 
and no horns have no cotyledons in the uterus, but the 
umbilical cord runs to meet one blood-vessel, which is large and 
extends throughout the uterus. Of such animals some produce 
one young at a time, some more than one, but the same 
description applies to both these classes. (This should be 
studied with the aid of the examples drawn in the Anatomy and 
the Enquiries.) For the young, if numerous, are attached each to 
its umbilical cord, and this to the blood-vessel of the mother; 
they are arranged next to one another along the stream of the 



2092 



blood-vessel as along a canal; and each embryo is enclosed in 
its membranes and chorion. 

Those who say that children are nourished in the uterus by 
sucking some lump of flesh or other are mistaken. If so, the 
same would have been the case with other animals, but as it is 
we do not find this (and this can easily be observed by 
dissection). Secondly, all embryos alike, whether of creatures 
that fly or swim or walk, are surrounded by fine membranes 
separating them from the uterus and from the fluids which are 
formed in it; but neither in these themselves is there anything 
of the kind, nor is it possible for the embryo to take 
nourishment by means of any of them. Thirdly, it is plain that 
all creatures developed in eggs grow when separated from the 
uterus. 

Natural intercourse takes place between animals of the same 
kind. However, those also unite whose nature is near akin and 
whose form is not very different, if their size is much the same 
and if the periods of gestation are equal. In other animals such 
cases are rare, but they occur with dogs and foxes and wolves; 
the Indian dogs also spring from the union of a dog with some 
wild dog-like animal. A similar thing has been seen to take 
place in those birds that are amative, as partridges and hens. 
Among birds of prey hawks of different form are thought to 
unite, and the same applies to some other birds. Nothing worth 
mentioning has been observed in the inhabitants of the sea, but 
the so-called 'rhinobates' especially is thought to spring from 
the union of the 'rhini' and 'batus'. And the proverb about Libya, 
that 'Libya is always producing something new', is said to have 
originated from animals of different species uniting with one 
another in that country, for it is said that because of the want of 
water all meet at the few places where springs are to be found, 
and that even different kinds unite in consequence. 



2093 



Of the animals that arise from such union all except mules are 
found to copulate again with each other and to be able to 
produce young of both sexes, but mules alone are sterile, for 
they do not generate by union with one another or with other 
animals. The problem why any individual, whether male or 
female, is sterile is a general one, for some men and women are 
sterile, and so are other animals in their several kinds, as horses 
and sheep. But this kind, of mules, is universally so. The causes 
of sterility in other animals are several. Both men and women 
are sterile from birth when the parts useful for union are 
imperfect, so that men never grow a beard but remain like 
eunuchs, and women do not attain puberty; the same thing may 
befall others as their years advance, sometimes on account of 
the body being too well nourished (for men who are in too good 
condition and women who are too fat the seminal secretion is 
taken up into the body, and the former have no semen, the 
latter no catamenia); at other times by reason of sickness men 
emit the semen in a cold and liquid state, and the discharges of 
women are bad and full of morbid secretions. Often, too, in both 
sexes this state is caused by injuries in the parts and regions 
contributory to copulation. Some such cases are curable, others 
incurable, but the subjects especially remain sterile if anything 
of the sort has happened in the first formation of the parts in 
the embryo, for then are produced women of a masculine and 
men of a feminine appearance, and in the former the catamenia 
do not occur, in the latter the semen is thin and cold. Hence it is 
with good reason that the semen of men is tested in water to 
find out if it is infertile, for that which is thin and cold is quickly 
spread out on the surface, but the fertile sinks to the bottom, for 
that which is well concocted is hot indeed, but that which is 
firm and thick is well concocted. They test women by pessaries 
to see if the smells thereof permeate from below upwards to the 
breath from the mouth and by colours smeared upon the eyes 
to see if they colour the saliva. If these results do not follow it is 



2094 



a sign that the passages of the body, through which the 
catamenia are secreted, are clogged and closed. For the region 
about the eyes is, of all the head, that most nearly connected 
with the generative secretions; a proof of this is that it alone is 
visibly changed in sexual intercourse, and those who indulge 
too much in this are seen to have their eyes sunken in. The 
reason is that the nature of the semen is similar to that of the 
brain, for the material of it is watery (the heat being acquired 
later). And the seminal purgations are from the region of the 
diaphragm, for the first principle of nature is there, so that the 
movements from the pudenda are communicated to the chest, 
and the smells from the chest are perceived through the 
respiration. 



8 

In men, then, and in other kinds, as said before, such deficiency 
occurs sporadically, but the whole of the mule kind is sterile. 
The reason has not been rightly given by Empedocles and 
Democritus, of whom the former expresses himself obscurely, 
the latter more intelligibly. For they offer their demonstration in 
the case of all these animals alike which unite against their 
affinities. Democritus says that the genital passages of mules 
are spoilt in the mother's uterus because the animals from the 
first are not produced from parents of the same kind. But we 
find that though this is so with other animals they are none the 
less able to generate; yet, if this were the reason, all others that 
unite in this manner ought to be barren. Empedocles assigns as 
his reason that the mixture of the 'seeds' becomes dense, each 
of the two seminal fluids out of which it is made being soft, for 
the hollows in each fit into the densities of the other, and in 
such cases a hard substance is formed out of soft ones, like 



2095 



bronze mingled with tin. Now he does not give the correct 
reason in the case of bronze and tin - (we have spoken of them 
in the Problems) - nor, to take general ground, does he take his 
principles from the intelligible. How do the 'hollows' and 'solids' 
fit into one another to make the mixing, e.g. in the case of wine 
and water? This saying is quite beyond us; for how we are to 
understand the 'hollows' of the wine and water is too far 
beyond our perception. Again, when, as a matter of fact, horse is 
born of horse, ass of ass, and mule of horse and ass in two ways 
according as the parents are stallion and she-ass or jackass and 
mare, why in the last case does there result something so 
'dense' that the offspring is sterile, whereas the offspring of 
male and female horse, male and female ass, is not sterile? And 
yet the generative fluid of the male and female horse is soft. But 
both sexes of the horse cross with both sexes of the ass, and the 
offspring of both crosses are barren, according to Empedocles, 
because from both is produced something 'dense', the 'seeds' 
being 'soft'. If so, the offspring of stallion and mare ought also to 
be sterile. If one of them alone united with the ass, it might be 
said that the cause of the mule's being unable to generate was 
the unlikeness of that one to the generative fluid of the ass; but, 
as it is, whatever be the character of that generative fluid with 
which it unites in the ass, such it is also in the animal of its own 
kind. Then, again, the argument is intended to apply to both 
male and female mules alike, but the male does generate at 
seven years of age, it is said; it is the female alone that is 
entirely sterile, and even she is so only because she does not 
complete the development of the embryo, for a female mule has 
been known to conceive. 

Perhaps an abstract proof might appear to be more plausible 
than those already given; I call it abstract because the more 
general it is the further is it removed from the special principles 
involved. It runs somewhat as follows. From male and female of 
the same species there are born in course of nature male and 



2096 



female of the same species as the parents, e.g. male and female 
puppies from male and female dog. From parents of different 
species is born a young one different in species; thus if a dog is 
different from a lion, the offspring of male dog and lioness or of 
lion and bitch will be different from both parents. If this is so, 
then since (1) mules are produced of both sexes and are not 
different in species from one another, and (2) a mule is born of 
horse and ass and these are different in species from mules, it 
is impossible that anything should be produced from mules. For 
(1) another kind cannot be, because the product of male and 
female of the same species is also of the same species, and (2) a 
mule cannot be, because that is the product of horse and ass 
which are different in form, [and it was laid down that from 
parents different in form is born a different animal]. Now this 
theory is too general and empty. For all theories not based on 
the special principles involved are empty; they only appear to 
be connected with the facts without being so really. As 
geometrical arguments must start from geometrical principles, 
so it is with the others; that which is empty may seem to be 
something, but is really nothing. Now the basis of this particular 
theory is not true, for many animals of different species are 
fertile with one another, as was said before. So we must not 
inquire into questions of natural science in this fashion any 
more than any other questions; we shall be more likely to find 
the reason by considering the facts peculiar to the two kinds 
concerned, horse and ass. In the first place, each of them, if 
mated with its own kind, bears only one young one; secondly, 
the females are not always able to conceive from the male 
(wherefore breeders put the horse to the mare again at 
intervals). Indeed, both the mare is deficient in catamenia, 
discharging less than any other quadruped, and the she-ass 
does not admit the impregnation, but ejects the semen with her 
urine, wherefore men follow flogging her after intercourse. 
Again the ass is an animal of cold nature, and so is not wont to 



2097 



be produced in wintry regions because it cannot bear cold, as in 
Scythia and the neighbouring country and among the Celts 
beyond Iberia, for this country also is cold. For this cause they 
do not put the jackasses to the females at the equinox, as they 
do with horses, but about the summer solstice, in order that the 
ass-foals may be born in a warm season, for the mothers bear at 
the same season as that in which they are impregnated, the 
period of gestation in both horse and ass being one year. The 
animal, then, being, as has been said of such a cold nature, its 
semen also must be cold. A proof of this is that if a horse mount 
a female already impregnated by an ass he does not destroy the 
impregnation of the ass, but if the ass be the second to mount 
her he does destroy that of the horse because of the coldness of 
his own semen. When, therefore, they unite with each other, the 
generative elements are preserved by the heat of the one of 
them, that contributed by the horse being the hotter; for in the 
ass both the semen of the male and the material contributed by 
the female are cold, and those of the horse, in both sexes, are 
hotter. Now when either hot is added to cold or cold to hot so as 
to mix, the result is that the embryo itself arising from these is 
preserved and thus these animals are fertile when crossed with 
one another, but the animal produced by them is no longer 
fertile but unable to produce perfect offspring. 

And in general each of these animals naturally tends towards 
sterility. The ass has all the disadvantages already mentioned, 
and if it should not begin to generate after the first shedding of 
teeth, it no longer generates at all; so near is the constitution of 
the ass to being sterile. The horse is much the same; it tends 
naturally towards sterility, and to make it entirely so it is only 
necessary that its generative secretion should become colder; 
now this is what happens to it when mixed with the 
corresponding secretion of the ass. The ass in like manner 
comes very near generating a sterile animal when mated with 
its own species. Thus when the difficulty of a cross contrary to 



2098 



nature is added, (when too even in the other case when united 
with their own species they with difficulty produce a single 
young one), the result of the cross, being still more sterile and 
contrary to nature, will need nothing further to make it sterile, 
but will be so of necessity. 

We find also that the bodies of female mules grow large because 
the matter which is secreted in other animals to form the 
catamenia is diverted to growth. But since the period of 
gestation in such animals is a year, the mule must not only 
conceive, if she is to be fertile, but must also nourish the 
embryo till birth, and this is impossible if there are no 
catamenia. But there are none in the mule; the useless part of 
the nutriment is discharged with the excretion from the bladder 
- this is why male mules do not smell to the pudenda of the 
females, as do the other solid-hoofed ungulates, but only to the 
evacuation itself - and the rest of the nutriment is used up to 
increase the size of the body. Hence it is sometimes possible for 
the female to conceive, as has been known to happen before 
now, but it is impossible for her to complete the process of 
nourishing the embryo and bringing it to birth. 

The male, again, may sometimes generate, both because the 
male sex is naturally hotter than the female and because it does 
not contribute any material substance to the mixture. The result 
in such cases is a 'ginnus', that is to say, a dwarf mule; for 'ginni' 
are produced also from the crossing of horse and ass when the 
embryo is diseased in the uterus. The ginnus is in fact like the 
so-called 'metachoera' in swine, for a 'metachoerum' also is a 
pig injured in the uterus; this may happen to any pig. The origin 
of human dwarfs is similar, for these also have their parts and 
their whole development injured during gestation, and 
resemble ginni and metachoera. 



2099 



Book III 



We have now spoken about the sterility of mules, and about 
those animals which are viviparous both externally and within 
themselves. The generation of the oviparous sanguinea is to a 
certain extent similar to that of the animals that walk, and all 
may be embraced in the same general statement; but in other 
respects there are differences in them both as compared with 
each other and with those that walk. All alike are generated 
from sexual union, the male emitting semen into the female. 
But among the ovipara (1) birds produce a perfect hard-shelled 
egg, unless it be injured by disease, and the eggs of birds are all 
two-coloured. (2) The cartilaginous fishes, as has been often 
said already, are oviparous internally but produce the young 
alive, the egg changing previously from one part of the uterus to 
another; and their egg is soft-shelled and of one colour. One of 
this class alone does not produce the young from the egg within 
itself, the so-called 'frog'; the reason of which must be stated 
later. (3) All other oviparous fishes produce an egg of one colour, 
but this is imperfect, for its growth is completed outside the 
mother's body by the same cause as are those eggs which are 
perfected within. 

Concerning the uterus of these classes of animals, what 
differences there are among them and for what reasons, has 
been stated previously. For in some of the viviparous creatures it 
is high up near the hypozoma, in others low down by the 



2100 



pudenda; the former in the cartilaginous fishes, the latter in 
animals both internally and externally viviparous, such as man 
and horse and the rest; in the ovipara it is sometimes low, as in 
the oviparous fish, and sometimes high, as in birds. 

Some embryos are formed in birds spontaneously, which are 
called wind-eggs and 'zephyria' by some; these occur in birds 
which are not given to flight nor rapine but which produce 
many young, for these birds have much residual matter, 
whereas in the birds of prey all such secretion is diverted to the 
wings and wing-feathers, while the body is small and dry and 
hot. (The secretion corresponding in hen-birds to catamenia, 
and the semen of the cock, are residues.) Since then both the 
wings and the semen are made from residual matter, nature 
cannot afford to spend much upon both. And for this same 
reason the birds of prey are neither given to treading much nor 
to laying many eggs, as are the heavy birds and those flying 
birds whose bodies are bulky, as the pigeon and so forth. For 
such residual matter is secreted largely in the heavy birds not 
given to flying, such as fowls, partridges, and so on, wherefore 
their males tread often and their females produce much 
material. Of such birds some lay many eggs at a time and some 
lay often; for instance, the fowl, the partridge, and the Libyan 
ostrich lay many eggs, while the pigeon family do not lay many 
but lay often. For these are between the birds of prey and the 
heavy ones; they are flyers like the former, but have bulky 
bodies like the latter; hence, because they are flyers and the 
residue is diverted that, way, they lay few eggs, but they lay 
often because of their having bulky bodies and their stomachs 
being hot and very active in concoction, and because moreover 
they can easily procure their food, whereas the birds of prey do 
so with difficulty. 

Small birds also tread often and are very fertile, as are 
sometimes small plants, for what causes bodily growth in 



2101 



others turn in them to a seminal residuum. Hence the Adrianic 
fowls lay most eggs, for because of the smallness of their bodies 
the nutriment is used up in producing young. And other birds 
are more fertile than game-fowl, for their bodies are more fluid 
and bulkier, whereas those of game-fowl are leaner and drier, 
since a passionate spirit is found rather in such bodies as the 
latter. Moreover the thinness and weakness of the legs 
contribute to making the former class of birds naturally inclined 
to tread and to be fertile, as we find also in the human species; 
for the nourishment which otherwise goes to the legs is turned 
in such into a seminal secretion, what Nature takes from the 
one place being added at the other. Birds of prey, on the 
contrary, have a strong walk and their legs are thick owing to 
their habits, so that for all these reasons they neither tread nor 
lay much. The kestrel is the most fertile; for this is nearly the 
only bird of prey which drinks, and its moisture, both innate 
and acquired, along with its heat is favourable to generative 
products. Even this bird does not lay very many eggs, but four at 
the outside. 

The cuckoo, though not a bird of prey, lays few eggs, because it 
is of a cold nature, as is shown by the cowardice of the bird, 
whereas a generative animal should be hot and moist. That it is 
cowardly is plain, for it is pursued by all the birds and lays eggs 
in the nests of others. 

The pigeon family are in the habit of laying two for the most 
part, for they neither lay one (no bird does except the cuckoo, 
and even that sometimes lays two) nor yet many, but they 
frequently produce two, or three at the most generally two, for 
this number lies between one and many. 

It is plain from the facts that with the birds that lay many eggs 
the nutriment is diverted to the semen. For most trees, if they 
bear too much fruit, wither away after the crop when nutriment 



2102 



is not reserved for themselves, and this seems to be what 
happens to annuals, as leguminous plants, corn, and the like. 
For they consume all their nutriment to make seed, their kind 
being prolific. And some fowls after laying too much, so as even 
to lay two eggs in a day, have died after this. For both the birds 
the plants become exhausted, and this condition is an excess of 
secretion of residual matter. A similar condition is the cause of 
the later sterility of the lioness, for at the first birth she 
produces five or six, then in the next year four, and again three 
cubs, then the next number down to one, then none at all, 
showing that the residue is being used up and the generative 
secretion is failing along with the advance of years. 

We have now stated in which birds wind-eggs are found, and 
also what sort of birds lay many eggs or few, and for what 
reasons. And wind-eggs, as said before, come into being because 
while it is the material for generation that exists in the female 
of all animals, birds have no discharge of catamenia like 
viviparous sanguinea (for they occur in all these latter, more in 
some, less in others, and in some only enough in quantity just 
to mark the class). The same applies to fish as to birds, and so in 
them as in birds is found an embryonic formation without 
impregnation, but it is less obvious because their nature is 
colder. The secretion corresponding to the catamenia of vivipara 
is formed in birds at the appropriate season for the discharge of 
superfluous matter, and, because the region near the hypozoma 
is hot, it is perfected so far as size is concerned, but in birds and 
fishes alike it is imperfect for generation without the seminal 
fluid of the male; the cause of this has been previously given. 
Wind-eggs are not formed in the flying birds, for the same 
reason as prevents their laying many eggs; for the residual 
matter in birds of prey is small, and they need the male to give 
an impulse for the discharge of it. The wind-eggs are produced 
in greater numbers than the impregnated but smaller in size for 
one and the same reason; they are smaller in size because they 



2103 



are imperfect, and because they are smaller in size they are 
more in number. They are less pleasant for food because they 
are less concocted, for in all foods the concocted is more 
agreeable. It has been sufficiently observed, then, that neither 
birds' nor fishes' eggs are perfected for generation without the 
males. As for embryos being formed in fish also (though in a 
less degree) without the males, the fact has been observed 
especially in river fish, for some are seen to have eggs from the 
first, as has been written in the Enquiries concerning them. And 
generally speaking in the case of birds even the impregnated 
eggs are not wont for the most part to attain their full growth 
unless the hen be trodden continually. The reason of this is that 
just as with women intercourse with men draws down the 
secretion of the catamenia (for the uterus being heated attracts 
the moisture and the passages are opened), so this happens 
also with birds; the residual matter corresponding to the 
catamenia advances a little at a time, and is not discharged 
externally, because its amount is small and the uterus is high 
up by the hypozoma, but trickles together into the uterus itself. 
For as the embryo of the vivipara grows by means of the 
umbilical cord, so the egg grows through this matter flowing to 
it through the uterus. For when once the hens have been 
trodden, they all continue to have eggs almost without 
intermission, though very small ones. Hence some are wont to 
speak of wind-eggs as not coming into being independently but 
as mere relics from a previous impregnation. But this is a false 
view, for sufficient observations have been made of their arising 
without impregnation in chickens and goslings. Also the female 
partridges which are taken out to act as decoys, whether they 
have ever been impregnated or not, immediately on smelling 
the male and hearing his call, become filled with eggs in the 
latter case and lay them in the former. The reason why this 
happens is the same as in men and quadrupeds, for if their 
bodies chance to be in rut they emit semen at the mere sight of 



2104 



the female or at a slight touch. And such birds are of a 
lascivious and fertile nature, so that the impulse they need is 
but small when they are in this excited condition, and the 
secreting activity takes place quickly in them, wind-eggs 
forming in the unimpregnated and the eggs in those which have 
been impregnated growing and reaching perfection swiftly. 

Among creatures that lay eggs externally birds produce their 
egg perfect, fish imperfect, but the eggs of the latter complete 
their growth outside as has been said before. The reason is that 
the fish kind is very fertile; now it is impossible for many eggs 
to reach completion within the mother and therefore they lay 
them outside. They are quickly discharged, for the uterus of 
externally oviparous fishes is near the generative passage. 
While the eggs of birds are two-coloured, those of all fish are 
one-coloured. The cause of the double colour may be seen from 
considering the power of each of the two parts, the white and 
the yolk. For the matter of the egg is secreted from the blood 
[No bloodless animal lays eggs,] and that the blood is the 
material of the body has been often said already. The one part, 
then, of the egg is nearer the form of the animal coming into 
being, that is the hot part; the more earthy part gives the 
substance of the body and is further removed. Hence in all two- 
coloured eggs the animal receives the first principle of 
generation from the white (for the vital principle is in that 
which is hot), but the nutriment from the yolk. Now in animals 
of a hotter nature the part from which the first principle arises 
is separated off from the part from which comes the nutriment, 
the one being white and the other yellow, and the white and 
pure is always more than the yellow and earthy; but in the 
moister and less hot the yolk is more in quantity and more 
fluid. This is what we find in lake birds, for they are of a moister 
nature and are colder than the land birds, so that the so-called 
'lecithus' or yolk in the eggs of such birds is large and less 
yellow because the white is less separated off from it. But when 



2105 



we come to the ovipara which are both of a cold nature and also 
moister (such is the fish kind) we find the white not separated 
at all because of the small size of the eggs and the quantity of 
the cold and earthy matter; therefore all fish eggs are of one 
colour, and white compared with yellow, yellow compared with 
white. Even the wind-eggs of birds have this distinction of 
colour, for they contain that out of which will come each of the 
two parts, alike that whence arises the principle of life and that 
whence comes the nutriment; only both these are imperfect 
and need the influence of the male in addition; for wind-eggs 
become fertile if impregnated by the male within a certain 
period. The difference in colour, however, is not due to any 
difference of sex, as if the white came from the male, the yolk 
from the female; both on the contrary come from the female, 
but the one is cold, the other hot. In all cases then where the 
hot part is considerable it is separated off, but where it is little it 
cannot be so; hence the eggs of such animals, as has been said, 
are of one colour. The semen of the male only puts them into 
form; and therefore at first the egg in birds appears white and 
small, but as it advances it is all yellow as more of the 
sanguineous material is continually mixed with it; finally as the 
hot part is separated the white takes up a position all round it 
and equally distributed on all sides, as when a liquid boils; for 
the white is naturally liquid and contains in itself the vital heat; 
therefore it is separated off all round, but the yellow and earthy 
part is inside. And if we enclose many eggs together in a bladder 
or something of the kind and boil them over a fire so as not to 
make the movement of the heat quicker than the separation of 
the white and yolk in the eggs, then the same process takes 
place in the whole mass of the eggs as in a single egg, all the 
yellow part coming into the middle and the white surrounding 
it. 

We have thus stated why some eggs are of one colour and 
others of two. 



2106 



The principle of the male is separated off in eggs at the point 
where the egg is attached to the uterus, and the reason why the 
shape of two-coloured eggs is unsymmetrical, and not perfectly 
round but sharper at one end, is that the part of the white in 
which is contained this principle must differ from the rest. 
Therefore the egg is harder at this point than below, for it is 
necessary to shelter and protect this principle. And this is why 
the sharp end of the egg comes out of the hen later than the 
blunt end; for the part attached to the uterus comes out later, 
and the egg is attached at the point where is the said principle, 
and the principle is in the sharp end. The same is the case also 
in the seeds of plants; the principle of the seed is attached 
sometimes to the twig, sometimes to the husk, sometimes to 
the pericarp. This is plain in the leguminous plants, for where 
the two cotyledons of beans and of similar seeds are united, 
there is the seed attached to the parent plant, and there is the 
principle of the seed. 

A difficulty may be raised about the growth of the egg; how is it 
derived from the uterus? For if animals derive their nutriment 
through the umbilical cord, through what do eggs derive it? 
They do not, like a scolex, acquire their growth by their own 
means. If there is anything by which they are attached to the 
uterus, what becomes of this when the egg is perfected? It does 
not come out with the egg as the cord does with animals; for 
when its egg is perfected the shell forms all round it. This 
problem is rightly raised, but it is not observed that the shell is 
at first only a soft membrane, and that it is only after the egg is 
perfected that it becomes hard and brittle; this is so nicely 
adjusted that it is still soft when it comes out (for otherwise it 



2107 



would cause pain in laying), but no sooner has it come out than 
it is fixed hard by cooling, the moisture quickly evaporating 
because there is but little of it, and the earthy part remaining. 
Now at first a certain part of this membrane at the sharp end of 
eggs resembles an umbilical cord, and projects like a pipe from 
them while they are still small. It is plainly visible in small 
aborted eggs, for if the bird be drenched with water or suddenly 
chilled in any other way and cast out the egg too soon, it 
appears still sanguineous and with a small tail like an umbilical 
cord running through it. As the egg becomes larger this is more 
twisted round and becomes smaller, and when the egg is 
perfected this end is the sharp end. Under this is the inner 
membrane which separates the white and the yolk from this. 
When the egg is perfected, the whole of it is set free, and 
naturally the umbilical cord does not appear, for it is now the 
extreme end of the egg itself. 

The egg is discharged in the opposite way from the young of 
vivipara; the latter are born head-first, the part where is the first 
principle leading, but the egg is discharged as it were feet first; 
the reason of this being what has been stated, that the egg is 
attached to the uterus at the point where is the first principle. 

The young bird is produced out of the egg by the mother's 
incubating and aiding the concoction, the creature developing 
out of part of the egg, and receiving growth and completion 
from the remaining part. For Nature not only places the 
material of the creature in the egg but also the nourishment 
sufficient for its growth; for since the mother bird cannot 
perfect her young within herself she produces the nourishment 
in the egg along with it. Whereas the nourishment, what is 
called milk, is produced for the young of vivipara in another 
part, in the breasts, Nature does this for birds in the egg. The 
opposite, however, is the case to what people think and what is 
asserted by Alcmaeon of Crotona. For it is not the white that is 



2108 



the milk, but the yolk, for it is this that is the nourishment of 
the chick, whereas they think it is the white because of the 
similarity of colour. 

The chick then, as has been said, comes into being by the 
incubation of the mother; yet if the temperature of the season is 
favourable, or if the place in which the eggs happen to lie is 
warm, the eggs are sufficiently concocted without incubation, 
both those of birds and those of oviparous quadrupeds. For 
these all lay their eggs upon the ground, where they are 
concocted by the heat in the earth. Such oviparous quadrupeds 
as do visit their eggs and incubate do so rather for the sake of 
protecting them than of incubation. 

The eggs of these quadrupeds are formed in the same way as 
those of birds, for they are hard-shelled and two-coloured, and 
they are formed near the hypozoma as are those of birds, and in 
all other respects resemble them both internally and externally, 
so that the inquiry into their causes is the same for all. But 
whereas the eggs of quadrupeds are hatched out by the mere 
heat of the weather owing to their strength, those of birds are 
more exposed to destruction and need the mother-bird. Nature 
seems to wish to implant in animals a special sense of care for 
their young: in the inferior animals this lasts only to the 
moment of giving birth to the incompletely developed animal; 
in others it continues till they are perfect; in all that are more 
intelligent, during the bringing up of the young also. In those 
which have the greatest portion in intelligence we find 
familiarity and love shown also towards the young when 
perfected, as with men and some quadrupeds; with birds we 
find it till they have produced and brought up their young, and 
therefore if the hens do not incubate after laying they get into 
worse condition, as if deprived of something natural to them. 



2109 



The young is perfected within the egg more quickly in sunshiny 
weather, the season aiding in the work, for concoction is a kind 
of heat. For the earth aids in the concoction by its heat, and the 
brooding hen does the same, for she applies the heat that is 
within her. And it is in the hot season, as we should expect, that 
the eggs are more apt to be spoilt and the so-called 'uria' or 
rotten eggs are produced; for just as wines turn sour in the 
heats from the sediment rising (for this is the cause of their 
being spoilt), so is it with the yolk in eggs, for the sediment and 
yolk are the earthy part in each case, wherefore the wine 
becomes turbid when the sediment mixes with it, and the like 
applies to the eggs that are spoiling because of the yolk. It is 
natural then that such should be the case with the birds that lay 
many eggs, for it is not easy to give the fitting amount of heat to 
all, but (while some have too little) others have too much and 
this makes them turbid, as it were by putrefaction. But this 
happens none the less with the birds of prey though they lay 
few eggs, for often one of the two becomes rotten, and the third 
practically always, for being of a hot nature they make the 
moisture in the eggs to overboil so to say. For the nature of the 
white is opposed to that of the yolk; the yolk congeals in frosts 
but liquefies on heating, and therefore it liquefies on concoction 
in the earth or by reason of incubation, and becoming liquid 
serves as nutriment for the developing chick. If exposed to heat 
and roasted it does not become hard, because though earthy in 
nature it is only so in the same way as wax is; accordingly on 
heating too much the eggs become watery and rotten, [if they be 
not from a liquid residue]. The white on the contrary is not 
congealed by frost but rather liquefies (the reason of which has 
been stated before), but on exposure to heat becomes solid. 
Therefore being concocted in the development of the chick it is 
thickened. For it is from this that the young is formed (whereas 
the yolk turns to nutriment) and it is from this that the parts 
derive their growth as they are formed one after another. This is 



2110 



why the white and the yolk are separated by membranes, as 
being different in nature. The precise details of the relation of 
the parts to one another both at the beginning of generation 
and as the animals are forming, and also the details of the 
membranes and umbilical cords, must be learnt from what has 
been written in the Enquiries; for the present investigation it is 
sufficient to understand this much clearly, that, when the heart 
has been first formed and the great blood-vessel has been 
marked off from it, two umbilical cords run from the vessel, the 
one to the membrane which encloses the yolk, the other to the 
membrane resembling a chorion which surrounds the whole 
embryo; this latter runs round on the inside of the membrane of 
the shell. Through the one of these the embryo receives the 
nutriment from the yolk, and the yolk becomes larger, for it 
becomes more liquid by heating. This is because the 
nourishment, being of a material character in its first form, 
must become liquid before it can be absorbed, just as it is with 
plants, and at first this embryo, whether in an egg or in the 
mother's uterus, lives the life of a plant, for it receives its first 
growth and nourishment by being attached to something else. 

The second umbilical cord runs to the surrounding chorion. For 
we must understand that, in the case of animals developed in 
eggs, the chick has the same relation to the yolk as the embryo 
of the vivipara has to the mother so long as it is within the 
mother (for since the nourishment of the embryo of the ovipara 
is not completed within the mother, the embryo takes part of it 
away from her). So also the relation of the chick to the 
outermost membrane, the sanguineous one, is like that of the 
mammalian embryo to the uterus. At the same time the egg- 
shell surrounds both the yolk and the membrane analogous to 
the uterus, just as if it should be put round both the embryo 
itself and the whole of the mother, in the vivipara. This is so 
because the embryo must be in the uterus and attached to the 
mother. Now in the vivipara the uterus is within the mother, but 



2111 



in the ovipara it is the other way about, as if one should say that 
the mother was in the uterus, for that which comes from the 
mother, the nutriment, is the yolk. The reason is that the 
process of nourishment is not completed within the mother. 

As the creature grows the umbilicus running the chorion 
collapses first, because it is here that the young is to come out; 
what is left of the yolk, and the umbilical cord running to the 
yolk, collapse later. For the young must have nourishment as 
soon as it is hatched; it is not nursed by the mother and cannot 
immediately procure its nourishment for itself; therefore the 
yolk enters within it along with its umbilicus and the flesh 
grows round it. 

This then is the manner in which animals produced from 
perfect eggs are hatched in all those, whether birds or 
quadrupeds, which lay the egg with a hard shell. These details 
are plainer in the larger creatures; in the smaller they are 
obscure because of the smallness of the masses concerned. 



The class of fishes is also oviparous. Those among them which 
have the uterus low down lay an imperfect egg for the reason 
previously given, but the so-called 'selache' or cartilaginous 
fishes produce a perfect egg within themselves but are 
externally viviparous except one which they call the 'frog'; this 
alone lays a perfect egg externally. The reason is the nature of 
its body, for its head is many times as large as the rest of the 
body and is spiny and very rough. This is also why it does not 
receive its young again within itself nor produce them alive to 
begin with, for as the size and roughness of the head prevents 
their entering so it would prevent their exit. And while the egg 



2112 



of the cartilaginous fishes is soft-shelled (for they cannot 
harden and dry its circumference, being colder than birds), the 
egg of the frog-fish alone is solid and firm to protect it outside, 
but those of the rest are of a moist and soft nature, for they are 
sheltered within and by the body of the mother. 

The young are produced from the egg in the same way both 
with those externally perfected (the frog-fishes) and those 
internally, and the process in these eggs is partly similar to, 
partly different from that in birds' eggs. In the first place they 
have not the second umbilicus which runs to the chorion under 
the surrounding shell. The reason of this is that they have not 
the surrounding shell, for it is no use to them since the mother 
shelters them, and the shell is a protection to the eggs against 
external injury between laying and hatching out. Secondly, the 
process in these also begins on the surface of the egg but not 
where it is attached to the uterus, as in birds, for the chick is 
developed from the sharp end and that is where the egg was 
attached. The reason is that the egg of birds is separated from 
the uterus before it is perfected, but in most though not all 
cartilaginous fishes the egg is still attached to the uterus when 
perfect. While the young develops upon the surface the egg is 
consumed by it just as in birds and the other animals detached 
from the uterus, and at last the umbilicus of the now perfect 
fish is left attached to the uterus. The like is the case with all 
those whose eggs are detached from the uterus, for in some of 
them the egg is so detached when it is perfect. 

The question may be asked why the development of birds and 
cartilaginous fishes differs in this respect. The reason is that in 
birds the white and yolk are separate, but fish eggs are one- 
coloured, the corresponding matter being completely mixed, so 
that there is nothing to stop the first principle being at the 
opposite end, for the egg is of the same nature both at the point 
of attachment and at the opposite end, and it is easy to draw 



2113 



the nourishment from the uterus by passages running from this 
principle. This is plain in the eggs which are not detached, for in 
some of the cartilaginous fish the egg is not detached from the 
uterus, but is still connected with it as it comes downwards 
with a view to the production of the young alive; in these the 
young fish when perfected is still connected by the umbilicus to 
the uterus when the egg has been consumed. From this it is 
clear that previously also, while the egg was still round the 
young, the passages ran to the uterus. This happens as we have 
said in the 'smooth hound'. 

In these respects and for the reasons given the development of 
cartilaginous fishes differs from that of birds, but otherwise it 
takes place in the same way. For they have the one umbilicus in 
like manner as that of birds connecting with the yolk, - only in 
these fishes it connects with the whole egg (for it is not divided 
into white and yolk but all one-coloured), - and get their 
nourishment from this, and as it is being consumed the flesh in 
like manner encroaches upon and grows round it. 

Such is the process of development in those fish that produce a 
perfect egg within themselves but are externally viviparous. 



Most of the other fish are externally oviparous, all laying an 
imperfect egg except the frog-fish; the reason of this exception 
has been previously stated, and the reason also why the others 
lay imperfect eggs. In these also the development from the egg 
runs on the same lines as that of the cartilaginous and 
internally oviparous fishes, except that the growth is quick and 
from small beginnings and the outside of the egg is harder. The 
growth of the egg is like that of a scolex, for those animals 



2114 



which produce a scolex give birth to a small thing at first and 
this grows by itself and not through any attachment to the 
parent. The reason is similar to that of the growth of yeast, for 
yeast also grows great from a small beginning as the more solid 
part liquefies and the liquid is aerated. This is effected in 
animals by the nature of the vital heat, in yeasts by the heat of 
the juice commingled with them. The eggs then grow of 
necessity through this cause (for they have in them superfluous 
yeasty matter), but also for the sake of a final cause, for it is 
impossible for them to attain their whole growth in the uterus 
because these animals have so many eggs. Therefore are they 
very small when set free and grow quickly, small because the 
uterus is narrow for the multitude of the eggs, and growing 
quickly that the race may not perish, as it would if much of the 
time required for the whole development were spent in this 
growth; even as it is most of those laid are destroyed before 
hatching. Hence the class of fish is prolific, for Nature makes up 
for the destruction by numbers. Some fish actually burst 
because of the size of the eggs, as the fish called 'belone', for its 
eggs are large instead of numerous, what Nature has taken 
away in number being added in size. 

So much for the growth of such eggs and its reason. 



A proof that these fish also are oviparous is the fact that even 
viviparous fish, such as the cartilaginous, are first internally 
oviparous, for hence it is plain that the whole class of fishes is 
oviparous. Where, however, both sexes exist and the eggs are 
produced in consequence of impregnation, the eggs do not 
arrive at completion unless the male sprinkle his milt upon 



2115 



them. Some erroneously assert that all fish are female except in 
the cartilaginous fishes, for they think that the females of fish 
differ from what are supposed to be males only in the same way 
as in those plants where the one bears fruit but the other is 
fruitless, as olive and oleaster, fig and caprifig. They think the 
like applies to fish except the cartilaginous, for they do not 
dispute the sexes in these. And yet there is no difference in the 
males of cartilaginous fishes and those belonging to the 
oviparous class in respect of the organs for the milt, and it is 
manifest that semen can be squeezed out of males of both 
classes at the right season. The female also has a uterus. But if 
the whole class were females and some of them unproductive 
(as with mules in the class of bushy-tailed animals), then not 
only should those which lay eggs have a uterus but also the 
others, only the uterus of the latter should be different from 
that of the former. But, as it is, some of them have organs for 
milt and others have a uterus, and this distinction obtains in all 
except two, the erythrinus and the channa, some of them 
having the milt organs, others a uterus. The difficulty which 
drives some thinkers to this conclusion is easily solved if we 
look at the facts. They say quite correctly that no animal which 
copulates produces many young, for of all those that generate 
from themselves perfect animals or perfect eggs none is prolific 
on the same scale as the oviparous fishes, for the number of 
eggs in these is enormous. But they had overlooked the fact that 
fish-eggs differ from those of birds in one circumstance. Birds 
and all oviparous quadrupeds, and any of the cartilaginous fish 
that are oviparous, produce a perfect egg, and it does not 
increase outside of them, whereas the eggs of fish are imperfect 
and do so complete their growth. Moreover the same thing 
applies to cephalopods also and Crustacea, yet these animals 
are actually seen copulating, for their union lasts a long time, 
and it is plain in these cases that the one is male and the other 
has a uterus. Finally, it would be strange if this distinction did 



2116 



not exist in the whole class, just as male and female in all the 
vivipara. The cause of the ignorance of those who make this 
statement is that the differences in the copulation and 
generation of various animals are of all kinds and not obvious, 
and so, speculating on a small induction, they think the same 
must hold good in all cases. 

So also those who assert that conception in female fishes is 
caused by their swallowing the semen of the male have not 
observed certain points when they say this. For the males have 
their milt and the females their eggs at about the same time of 
year, and the nearer the female is to laying the more abundant 
and the more liquid is the milt formed in the male. And just as 
the increase of the milt in the male and of the roe in the female 
takes place at the same time, so is it also with their emission, 
for neither do the females lay all their eggs together, but 
gradually, nor do the males emit all the milt at once. All these 
facts are in accordance with reason. For just as the class of birds 
in some cases has eggs without impregnation, but few and 
seldom, impregnation being generally required, so we find the 
same thing, though to a less degree, in fish. But in both classes 
these spontaneous eggs are infertile unless the male, in those 
kinds where the male exists, shed his fluid upon them. Now in 
birds this must take place while the eggs are still within the 
mother, because they are perfect when discharged, but in fish, 
because the eggs are imperfect and complete their growth 
outside the mother in all cases, those outside are preserved by 
the sprinkling of the milt over them, even if they come into 
being by impregnation, and here it is that the milt of the males 
is used up. Therefore it comes down the ducts and diminishes 
in quantity at the same time as this happens to the eggs of the 
females, for the males always attend them, shedding their milt 
upon the eggs as they are laid. Thus then they are male and 
female, and all of them copulate (unless in any kind the 



2117 



distinction of sex does not exist), and without the semen of the 
male no such animal comes into being. 

What helps in the deception is also the fact that the union of 
such fishes is brief, so that it is not observed even by many of 
the fishermen, for none of them ever watches anything of the 
sort for the sake of knowledge. Nevertheless their copulation 
has been seen, for fish [when the tail part does not prevent it] 
copulate like the dolphins by throwing themselves alongside of 
one another. But the dolphins take longer to get free again, 
whereas such fishes do so quickly. Hence, not seeing this, but 
seeing the swallowing of the milt and the eggs, even the 
fishermen repeat the same simple tale, so much noised abroad, 
as Herodotus the storyteller, as if fish were conceived by the 
mother's swallowing the milt, - not considering that this is 
impossible. For the passage which enters by way of the mouth 
runs to the intestines, not to the uterus, and what goes into the 
intestines must be turned into nutriment, for it is concocted; 
the uterus, however, is plainly full of eggs, and from whence did 
they enter it? 



A similar story is told also of the generation of birds. For there 
are some who say that the raven and the ibis unite at the 
mouth, and among quadrupeds that the weasel brings forth its 
young by the mouth; so say Anaxagoras and some of the other 
physicists, speaking too superficially and without consideration. 
Concerning the birds, they are deceived by a false reasoning, 
because the copulation of ravens is seldom seen, but they are 
often seen uniting with one another with their beaks, as do all 
the birds of the raven family; this is plain with domesticated 



2118 



jackdaws. Birds of the pigeon kind do the same, but, because 
they also plainly copulate, therefore they have not had the same 
legend told of them. But the raven family is not amorous, for 
they are birds that produce few young, though this bird also has 
been seen copulating before now. It is a strange thing, however, 
that these theorists do not ask themselves how the semen 
enters the uterus through the intestine, which always concocts 
whatever comes into it, as the nutriment; and these birds have 
a uterus like others, and eggs are found them near the 
hypozoma. And the weasel has a uterus in like manner to the 
other quadrupeds; by what passage is the embryo to get from it 
to the mouth? But this opinion has arisen because the young of 
the weasel are very small like those of the other fissipeds, of 
which we shall speak later, and because they often carry the 
young about in their mouths. 

Much deceived also are those who make a foolish statement 
about the trochus and the hyena. Many say that the hyena, and 
Herodorus the Heracleot says that the trochus, has two 
pudenda, those of the male and of the female, and that the 
trochus impregnates itself but the hyena mounts and is 
mounted in alternate years. This is untrue, for the hyena has 
been seen to have only one pudendum, there being no lack of 
opportunity for observation in some districts, but hyenas have 
under the tail a line like the pudendum of the female. Both 
male and female have such a mark, but the males are taken 
more frequently; this casual observation has given rise to this 
opinion. But enough has been said of this. 



2119 



Touching the generation of fish, the question may be raised, 
why it is that in the cartilaginous fish neither the females are 
seen discharging their eggs nor the males their milt, whereas in 
the non-viviparous fishes this is seen in both sexes. The reason 
is that the whole cartilaginous class do not produce much 
semen, and further the females have their uterus near 
hypozoma. For the males and females of the one class of fish 
differ from the males and females of the other class in like 
manner, for the cartilaginous are less productive of semen. But 
in the oviparous fish, as the females lay their eggs on account of 
their number, so do the males shed their milt on account of its 
abundance. For they have more milt than just what is required 
for copulation, as Nature prefers to expend the milt in helping 
to perfect the eggs, when the female has deposited them, rather 
than in forming them at first. For as has been said both further 
back and in our recent discussions, the eggs of birds are 
perfected internally but those of fish externally. The latter, 
indeed, resemble in a way those animals which produce a 
scolex, for the product discharged by them is still more 
imperfect than a fish's egg. It is the male that brings about the 
perfection of the egg both of birds and of fishes, only in the 
former internally, as they are perfected internally, and in the 
latter externally, because the egg is imperfect when deposited; 
but the result is the same in both cases. 

In birds the wind-eggs become fertile, and those previously 
impregnated by one kind of cock change their nature to that of 
the later cock. And if the eggs be behindhand in growth, then, if 
the same cock treads the hen again after leaving off treading for 
a time, he causes them to increase quickly, not, however, at any 
period whatever of their development, but if the treading take 
place before the egg changes so far that the white begins to 
separate from the yolk. But in the eggs of fishes no such limit of 



2120 



time has been laid down, but the males shed their milt quickly 
upon them to preserve them. The reason is that these eggs are 
not two-coloured, and hence there is no such limit of time fixed 
with them as with those of birds. This fact is what we should 
expect, for by the time that the white and yolk are separated off 
from one another, the birds egg already contains the principle 
that comes from the male parent.... for the male contributes to 
this. 

Wind-eggs, then, participate in generation so far as is possible 
for them. That they should be perfected into an animal is 
impossible, for an animal requires sense-perception; but the 
nutritive faculty of the soul is possessed by females as well as 
males, and indeed by all living things, as has been often said, 
wherefore the egg itself is perfect only as the embryo of a plant, 
but imperfect as that of an animal. If, then, there had been no 
male sex in the class of birds, the egg would have been 
produced as it is in some fishes, if indeed there is any kind of 
fish of such a nature as to generate without a male; but it has 
been said of them before that this has not yet been 
satisfactorily observed. But as it is both sexes exist in all birds, 
so that, considered as a plant, the egg is perfect, but in so far as 
it is not a plant it is not perfect, nor does anything else result 
from it; for neither has it come into being simply like a real 
plant nor from copulation like an animal. Eggs, however, 
produced from copulation but already separated into white and 
yolk take after the first cock; for they already contain both 
principles, which is why they do not change again after the 
second impregnation. 



2121 



8 

The young are produced in the same way also by the 
cephalopoda, e.g. sepias and the like, and by the Crustacea, e.g. 
carabi and their kindred, for these also lay eggs in consequence 
of copulation, and the male has often been seen uniting with 
the female. Therefore those who say that all fish are female and 
lay eggs without copulation are plainly speaking unscientifically 
from this point of view also. For it is a wonderful thing to 
suppose that the former animals lay eggs in consequence of 
copulation and that fish do not; if again they were unaware of 
this, it is a sign of ignorance. The union of all these creatures 
lasts a considerable time, as in insects, and naturally so, for they 
are bloodless and therefore of a cold nature. 

In the sepias and calamaries or squids the eggs appear to be 
two, because the uterus is divided and appears double, but that 
of the poulps appears to be single. The reason is that the shape 
of the uterus in the poulp is round in form and spherical, the 
cleavage being obscure when it is filled with eggs. The uterus of 
the carabi is also bifid. All these animals also lay an imperfect 
egg for the same reason as fishes. In the carabi and their like 
the females produce their eggs so as to keep them attached to 
themselves, which is why the side-flaps of the females are 
larger than those of the males, to protect the eggs; the 
cephalopoda lay them away from themselves. The males of the 
cephalopoda sprinkle their milt over the females, as the male 
fish do over the eggs, and it becomes a sticky and glutinous 
mass, but in the carabi and their like nothing of the sort has 
been seen or can be naturally expected, for the egg is under the 
female and is hard-shelled. Both these eggs and those of the 
cephalopoda grow after deposition like those of fishes. 

The sepia while developing is attached to the egg by its front 
part, for here alone is it possible, because this animal alone has 



2122 



its front and back pointing in the same direction. For the 
position and attitude of the young while developing you must 
look at the Enquiries. 



We have now spoken of the generation of other animals, those 
that walk, fly, and swim; it remains to speak of insects and 
testacea according to the plan laid down. Let us begin with the 
insects. It was observed previously that some of these are 
generated by copulation, others spontaneously, and besides this 
that they produce a scolex, and why this is so. For pretty much 
all creatures seem in a certain way to produce a scolex first, 
since the most imperfect embryo is of such a nature; and in all 
animals, even the viviparous and those that lay a perfect egg, 
the first embryo grows in size while still undifferentiated into 
parts; now such is the nature of the scolex. After this stage 
some of the ovipara produce the egg in a perfect condition, 
others in an imperfect, but it is perfected outside as has been 
often stated of fish. With animals internally viviparous the 
embryo becomes egg-like in a certain sense after its original 
formation, for the liquid is contained in a fine membrane, just 
as if we should take away the shell of the egg, wherefore they 
call the abortion of an embryo at that stage an 'efflux'. 

Those insects which generate at all generate a scolex, and those 
which come into being spontaneously and not from copulation 
do so at first from a formation this nature. I say that the former 
generate a scolex, for we must put down caterpillars also and 
the product of spiders as a sort of scolex. And yet some even of 
these and many of the others may be thought to resemble eggs 
because of their round shape, but we must not judge by shapes 



2123 



nor yet by softness and hardness (for what is produced by some 
is hard), but by the fact that the whole of them is changed into 
the body of the creature and the animal is not developed from a 
part of them. All these products that are of the nature of a 
scolex, after progressing and acquiring their full size, become a 
sort of egg, for the husk about them hardens and they are 
motionless during this period. This is plain in the scolex of bees 
and wasps and in caterpillars. The reason of this is that their 
nature, because of its imperfection, oviposits as it were before 
the right time, as if the scolex, while still growing in size, were a 
soft egg. Similar to this is also what happens with all other 
insects which come into being without copulation in wool and 
other such materials and in water. For all of them after the 
scolex stage become immovable and their integument dries 
round them, and after this the latter bursts and there comes 
forth as from an egg an animal perfected in its second 
metamorphosis, most of those which are not aquatic being 
winged. 

Another point is quite natural, which may wondered at by 
many. Caterpillars at first take nourishment, but after this stage 
do so no longer, but what is called by some the chrysalis is 
motionless. The same applies to the scolex of wasps and bees, 
but after this comes into being the so-called nymph.... and have 
nothing of the kind. For an egg is also of such a nature that 
when it has reached perfection it grows no more in size, but at 
first it grows and receives nourishment until it is differentiated 
and becomes a perfect egg. Sometimes the scolex contains in 
itself the material from which it is nourished and obtains such 
an addition to its size, e.g. in bees and wasps; sometimes it gets 
its nourishment from outside itself, as caterpillars and some 
others. 

It has thus been stated why such animals go through a double 
development and for what reason they become immovable 



2124 



again after moving. And some of them come into being by 
copulation, like birds and vivipara and most fishes, others 
spontaneously, like some plants. 



10 

There is much difficulty about the generation of bees. If it is 
really true that in the case of some fishes there is such a 
method of generation that they produce eggs without 
copulation, this may well happen also with bees, to judge from 
appearances. For they must (1) either bring the young brood 
from elsewhere, as some say, and if so the young must either be 
spontaneously generated or produced by some other animal, or 
(2) they must generate them themselves, or (3) they must bring 
some and generate others, for this also is maintained by some, 
who say that they bring the young of the drones only. Again, if 
they generate them it must be either with or without 
copulation; if the former, then either (1) each kind must 
generate its own kind, or (2) some one kind must generate the 
others, or (3) one kind must unite with another for the purpose 
(I mean for instance (1) that bees may be generated from the 
union of bees, drones from that of drones, and kings from that 
of kings, or (2) that all the others may be generated from one, as 
from what are called kings and leaders, or (3) from the union of 
drones and bees, for some say that the former are male, the 
latter female, while others say that the bees are male and the 
drones female). But all these views are impossible if we reason 
first upon the facts peculiar to bees and secondly upon those 
which apply more generally to other animals also. 

For if they do not generate the young but bring them from 
elsewhere, then bees ought to come into being also, if the bees 



2125 



did not carry them off, in the places from which the old bees 
carry the germs. For why, if new bees come into existence when 
the germs are transported, should they not do so if the germs 
are left there? They ought to do so just as much, whether the 
germs are spontaneously generated in the flowers or whether 
some animal generates them. And if the germs were of some 
other animal, then that animal ought to be produced from them 
instead of bees. Again, that they should collect honey is 
reasonable, for it is their food, but it is strange that they should 
collect the young if they are neither their own offspring nor 
food. With what object should they do so? for all animals that 
trouble themselves about the young labour for what appears to 
be their own offspring. 

But, again, it is also unreasonable to suppose that the bees are 
female and the drones male, for Nature does not give weapons 
for fighting to any female, and while the drones are stingless all 
the bees have a sting. Nor is the opposite view reasonable, that 
the bees are male and the drones female, for no males are in 
the habit of working for their offspring, but as it is the bees do 
this. And generally, since the brood of the drones is found 
coming into being among them even if there is no mature drone 
present, but that of the bees is not so found without the 
presence of the kings (which is why some say that the young of 
the drones alone is brought in from outside), it is plain that they 
are not produced from copulation, either (1) of bee with bee or 
drone with drone or (2) of bees with drones. (That they should 
import the brood of the drones alone is impossible for the 
reasons already given, and besides it is unreasonable that a 
similar state of things should not prevail with all the three 
kinds if it prevails with one.) Then, again, it is also impossible 
that the bees themselves should be some of them male and 
some female, for in all kinds of animals the two sexes differ. 
Besides they would in that case generate their own kind, but as 
it is their brood is not found to come into being if the leaders 



2126 



are not among them, as men say. And an argument against both 
theories, that the young are generated by union of the bees with 
one another or with the drones, separately or with one another, 
is this: none of them has ever yet been seen copulating, 
whereas this would have often happened if the sexes had 
existed in them. It remains then, if they are generated by 
copulation at all, that the kings shall unite to generate them. 
But the drones are found to come into being even if no leaders 
are present, and it is not possible that the bees should either 
import their brood or themselves generate them by copulation. 
It remains then, as appears to be the case in certain fishes, that 
the bees should generate the drones without copulation, being 
indeed female in respect of generative power, but containing in 
themselves both sexes as plants do. Hence also they have the 
instrument of offence, for we ought not to call that female in 
which the male sex is not separated. But if this is found to be 
the case with drones, if they come into being without 
copulation, then as it is necessary that the same account should 
be given of the bees and the kings and that they also should be 
generated without copulation. Now if the brood of the bees had 
been found to come into being among them without the 
presence of the kings, it would necessarily follow that the bees 
also are produced from bees themselves without copulation, but 
as it is, since those occupied with the tendance of these 
creatures deny this, it remains that the kings must generate 
both their own kind and the bees. 

As bees are a peculiar and extraordinary kind of animal so also 
their generation appears to be peculiar. That bees should 
generate without copulation is a thing which may be paralleled 
in other animals, but that what they generate should not be of 
the same kind is peculiar to them, for the erythrinus generates 
an erythrinus and the channa a channa. The reason is that bees 
themselves are not generated like flies and similar creatures, 
but from a kind different indeed but akin to them, for they are 



2127 



produced from the leaders. Hence in a sort of way their 
generation is analogous. For the leaders resemble the drones in 
size and the bees in possessing a sting; so the bees are like 
them in this respect, and the drones are like them in size. For 
there must needs be some overlapping unless the same kind is 
always to be produced from each; but this is impossible, for at 
that rate the whole class would consist of leaders. The bees, 
then, are assimilated to them their power of generation, the 
drones in size; if the latter had had a sting also they would have 
been leaders, but as it is this much of the difficulty has been 
solved, for the leaders are like both kinds at once, like the bees 
in possessing a sting, like the drones in size. 

But the leaders also must be generated from something. Since it 
is neither from the bees nor from the drones, it must be from 
their own kind. The grubs of the kings are produced last and are 
not many in number. 

Thus what happens is this: the leaders generate their own kind 
but also another kind, that of the bees; the bees again generate 
another kind, the drones, but do not also generate their own 
kind, but this has been denied them. And since what is 
according to Nature is always in due order, therefore it is 
necessary that it should be denied to the drones even to 
generate another kind than themselves. This is just what we 
find happening, for though the drones are themselves 
generated, they generate nothing else, but the process reaches 
its limit in the third stage. And so beautifully is this arranged by 
Nature that the three kinds always continue in existence and 
none of them fails, though they do not all generate. 

Another fact is also natural, that in fine seasons much honey is 
collected and many drones are produced but in rainy reasons a 
large brood of ordinary bees. For the wet causes more residual 
matter to be formed in the bodies of the leaders, the fine 



2128 



weather in that of the bees, for being smaller in size they need 
the fine weather more than the kings do. It is right also that the 
kings, being as it were made with a view to producing young, 
should remain within, freed from the labour of procuring 
necessaries, and also that they should be of a considerable size, 
their bodies being, as it were, constituted with a view to bearing 
young, and that the drones should be idle as having no weapon 
to fight for the food and because of the slowness of their bodies. 
But the bees are intermediate in size between the two other 
kinds, for this is useful for their work, and they are workers as 
having to support not only their young but also their fathers. 
And it agrees with our views that the bees attend upon their 
kings because they are their offspring (for if nothing of the sort 
had been the case the facts about their leadership would be 
unreasonable), and that, while they suffer the kings to do no 
work as being their parents, they punish the drones as their 
children, for it is nobler to punish one's children and those who 
have no work to perform. The fact that the leaders, being few, 
generate the bees in large numbers seems to be similar to what 
obtains in the generation of lions, which at first produce five, 
afterwards a smaller number each time at last one and 
thereafter none. So the leaders at first produce a number of 
workers, afterwards a few of their own kind; thus the brood of 
the latter is smaller in number than that of the former, but 
where Nature has taken away from them in number she has 
made it up again in size. 

Such appears to be the truth about the generation of bees, 
judging from theory and from what are believed to be the facts 
about them; the facts, however, have not yet been sufficiently 
grasped; if ever they are, then credit must be given rather to 
observation than to theories, and to theories only if what they 
affirm agrees with the observed facts. 



2129 



A further indication that bees are produced without copulation 
is the fact that the brood appears small in the cells of the comb, 
whereas, whenever insects are generated by copulation, the 
parents remain united for a long time but produce quickly 
something of the nature of a scolex and of a considerable size. 

Concerning the generation of animals akin to them, as hornets 
and wasps, the facts in all cases are similar to a certain extent, 
but are devoid of the extraordinary features which characterize 
bees; this we should expect, for they have nothing divine about 
them as the bees have. For the so-called 'mothers' generate the 
young and mould the first part of the combs, but they generate 
by copulation with one another, for their union has often been 
observed. As for all the differences of each of these kind from 
one another and from bees, they must be investigated with the 
aid of the illustrations to the Enquiries. 



11 

Having spoken of the generation of all insects, we must now 
speak of the testacea. Here also the facts of generation are 
partly like and partly unlike those in the other classes. And this 
is what might be expected. For compared with animals they 
resemble plants, compared with plants they resemble animals, 
so that in a sense they appear to come into being from semen, 
but in another sense not so, and in one way they are 
spontaneously generated but in another from their own kind, or 
some of them in the latter way, others in the former. Because 
their nature answers to that of plants, therefore few or no kinds 
of testacea come into being on land, e.g. the snails and any 
others, few as they are, that resemble them; but in the sea and 
similar waters there are many of all kinds of forms. But the 



2130 



class of plants has but few and one may say practically no 
representatives in the sea and such places, all such growing on 
the land. For plants and testacea are analogous; and in 
proportion as liquid has more quickening power than solid, 
water than earth, so much does the nature of testacea differ 
from that of plants, since the object of testacea is to be in such a 
relation to water as plants are to earth, as if plants were, so to 
say, land-oysters, oysters water-plants. 

For such a reason also the testacea in the water vary more in 
form than those on the land. For the nature of liquid is more 
plastic than that of earth and yet not much less material, and 
this is especially true of the inhabitants of the sea, for fresh 
water, though sweet and nutritious, is cold and less material. 
Wherefore animals having no blood and not of a hot nature are 
not produced in lakes nor in the fresher among brackish waters, 
but only exceptionally, but it is in estuaries and at the mouths 
of rivers that they come into being, as testacea and cephalopoda 
and Crustacea, all these being bloodless and of a cold nature. For 
they seek at the same time the warmth of the sun and food; 
now the sea is not only water but much more material than 
fresh water and hot in its nature; it has a share in all the parts 
of the universe, water and air and earth, so that it also has a 
share in all living things which are produced in connexion with 
each of these elements. Plants may be assigned to land, the 
aquatic animals to water, the land animals to air, but variations 
of quantity and distance make a great and wonderful difference. 
The fourth class must not be sought in these regions, though 
there certainly ought to be some animal corresponding to the 
element of fire, for this is counted in as the fourth of the 
elementary bodies. But the form which fire assumes never 
appears to be peculiar to it, but it always exists in some other of 
the elements, for that which is ignited appears to be either air 
or smoke or earth. Such a kind of animal must be sought in the 
moon, for this appears to participate in the element removed in 



2131 



the third degree from earth. The discussion of these things 
however belongs to another subject. 

To return to testacea, some of them are formed spontaneously, 
some emit a sort of generative substance from themselves, but 
these also often come into being from a spontaneous formation. 
To understand this we must grasp the different methods of 
generation in plants; some of these are produced from seed, 
some from slips, planted out, some by budding off alongside, as 
the class of onions. In the last way produced mussels, for 
smaller ones are always growing off alongside the original, but 
the whelks, the purple-fish, and those which are said to 'spawn' 
emit masses of a liquid slime as if originated by something of a 
seminal nature. We must not, however, consider that anything 
of the sort is real semen, but that these creatures participate in 
the resemblance to plants in the manner stated above. Hence 
when once one such creature has been produced, then is 
produced a number of them. For all these creatures are liable to 
be even spontaneously generated, and so to be formed still 
more plentifully in proportion if some are already existing. For it 
is natural that each should have some superfluous residue 
attached to it from the original, and from this buds off each of 
the creatures growing alongside of it. Again, since the nutriment 
and its residue possess a like power, it is likely that the product 
of those testacea which 'spawn' should resemble the original 
formation, and so it is natural that a new animal of the same 
kind should come into being from this also. 

All those which do not bud off or 'spawn' are spontaneously 
generated. Now all things formed in this way, whether in earth 
or water, manifestly come into being in connexion with 
putrefaction and an admixture of rain-water. For as the sweet is 
separated off into the matter which is forming, the residue of 
the mixture takes such a form. Nothing comes into being by 
putrefying, but by concocting; putrefaction and the thing 



2132 



putrefied is only a residue of that which is concocted. For 
nothing comes into being out of the whole of anything, any 
more than in the products of art; if it did art would have 
nothing to do, but as it is in the one case art removes the 
useless material, in the other Nature does so. Animals and 
plants come into being in earth and in liquid because there is 
water in earth, and air in water, and in all air is vital heat so 
that in a sense all things are full of soul. Therefore living things 
form quickly whenever this air and vital heat are enclosed in 
anything. When they are so enclosed, the corporeal liquids 
being heated, there arises as it were a frothy bubble. Whether 
what is forming is to be more or less honourable in kind 
depends on the embracing of the psychical principle; this again 
depends on the medium in which the generation takes place 
and the material which is included. Now in the sea the earthy 
matter is present in large quantities, and consequently the 
testaceous animals are formed from a concretion of this kind, 
the earthy matter hardening round them and solidifying in the 
same manner as bones and horns (for these cannot be melted 
by fire), and the matter (or body) which contains the life being 
included within it. 

The class of snails is the only class of such creatures that has 
been seen uniting, but it has never yet been sufficiently 
observed whether their generation is the result of the union or 
not. 

It may be asked, if we wish to follow the right line of 
investigation, what it is in such animals the formation of which 
corresponds to the material principle. For in the females this is 
a residual secretion of the animal, potentially such as that from 
which it came, by imparting motion to which the principle 
derived from the male perfects the animal. But here what must 
be said to correspond to this, and whence comes or what is the 
moving principle which corresponds to the male? We must 



2133 



understand that even in animals which generate it is from the 
incoming nourishment that the heat in the animal makes the 
residue, the beginning of the conception, by secretion and 
concoction. The like is the case also in plants, except that in 
these (and also in some animals) there is no further need of the 
male principle, because they have it mingled with the female 
principle within themselves, whereas the residual secretion in 
most animals does need it. The nourishment again of some is 
earth and water, of others the more complicated combinations 
of these, so that what the heat in animals produces from their 
nutriment, this does the heat of the warm season in the 
environment put together and combine by concoction out of the 
sea-water on the earth. And the portion of the psychical 
principle which is either included along with it or separated off 
in the air makes an embryo and puts motion into it. Now in 
plants which are spontaneously generated the method of 
formation is uniform; they arise from a part of something, and 
while some of it is the starting-point of the plant, some is the 
first nourishment of the young shoots.... Other animals are 
produced in the form of a scolex, not only those bloodless 
animals which are not generated from parents but even some 
sanguinea, as a kind of mullet and some other river fishes and 
also the eel kind. For all of these, though they have but little 
blood by nature, are nevertheless sanguinea, and have a heart 
with blood in it as the origin of the parts; and the so-called 
'entrails of earth', in which comes into being the body of the eel, 
have the nature of a scolex. 

Hence one might suppose, in connexion with the origin of men 
and quadrupeds, that, if ever they were really 'earth-born' as 
some say, they came into being in one of two ways; that either it 
was by the formation of a scolex at first or else it was out of 
eggs. For either they must have had in themselves the 
nutriment for growth (and such a conception is a scolex) or they 
must have got it from elsewhere, and that either from the 



2134 



mother or from part of the conception. If then the former is 
impossible (I mean that nourishment should flow to them from 
the earth as it does in animals from the mother), then they 
must have got it from some part of the conception, and such 
generation we say is from an egg. 

It is plain then that, if there really was any such beginning of 
the generation of all animals, it is reasonable to suppose to have 
been one of these two, scolex or egg. But it is less reasonable to 
suppose that it was from eggs, for we do not see such 
generation occurring with any animal, but we do see the other 
both in the sanguinea above mentioned and in the bloodless 
animals. Such are some of the insects and such are the testacea 
which we are discussing; for they do not develop out of a part of 
something (as do animals from eggs), and they grow like a 
scolex. For the scolex grows towards the upper part and the first 
principle, since in the lower part is the nourishment for the 
upper. And this resembles the development of animals from 
eggs, except that these latter consume the whole egg, whereas 
in the scolex, when the upper part has grown by taking up into 
itself part of the substance in the lower part, the lower part is 
then differentiated out of the rest. The reason is that in later life 
also the nourishment is absorbed by all animals in the part 
below the hypozoma. 

That the scolex grows in this way is plain in the case of bees 
and the like, for at first the lower part is large in them and the 
upper is smaller. The details of growth in the testacea are 
similar. This is plain in the whorls of the turbinata, for always as 
the animal grows the whorls become larger towards the front 
and what is called the head of the creature. 

We have now pretty well described the manner of the 
development of these and the other spontaneously generated 
animals. That all the testacea are formed spontaneously is clear 



2135 



from such facts as these. They come into being on the side of 
boats when the frothy mud putrefies. In many places where 
previously nothing of the kind existed, the so-called limnostrea, 
a kind of oyster, have come into being when the spot turned 
muddy through want of water; thus when a naval armament 
cast anchor at Rhodes a number of clay vessels were thrown out 
into the sea, and after some time, when mud had collected 
round them, oysters used to be found in them. Here is another 
proof that such animals do not emit any generative substance 
from themselves; when certain Chians carried some live oysters 
over from Pyrrha in Lesbos and placed them in narrow straits of 
the sea where tides clash, they became no more numerous as 
time passed, but increased greatly in size. The so-called eggs 
contribute to generation but are only a condition, like fat in the 
sanguinea, and therefore the oysters are savoury at these 
periods. A proof that this substance is not really eggs is the fact 
that such 'eggs' are always found in some testacea, as in pinnae, 
whelks, and purple-fish; only they are sometimes larger and 
sometimes smaller; in others as pectens, mussels, and the so- 
called limnostrea, they are not always present but only in the 
spring; as the season advances they dwindle and at last 
disappear altogether; the reason being that the spring is 
favourable to their being in good condition. In others again, as 
the ascidians, nothing of the sort is visible. (The details 
concerning these last, and the places in which they come into 
being, must be learnt from the Enquiry.) 



2136 



Book IV 



We have thus spoken of the generation of animals both 
generally and separately in all the different classes. But, since 
male and female are distinct in the most perfect of them, and 
since we say that the sexes are first principles of all living 
things whether animals or plants, only in some of them the 
sexes are separated and in others not, therefore we must speak 
first of the origin of the sexes in the latter. For while the animal 
is still imperfect in its kind the distinction is already made 
between male and female. 

It is disputed, however, whether the embryo is male or female, 
as the case may be, even before the distinction is plain to our 
senses, and further whether it is thus differentiated within the 
mother or even earlier. It is said by some, as by Anaxagoras and 
other of the physicists, that this antithesis exists from the 
beginning in the germs or seeds; for the germ, they say, comes 
from the male while the female only provides the place in 
which it is to be developed, and the male is from the right, the 
female from the left testis, and so also that the male embryo is 
in the right of the uterus, the female in the left. Others, as 
Empedocles, say that the differentiation takes place in the 
uterus; for he says that if the uterus is hot or cold what enters it 
becomes male or female, the cause of the heat or cold being the 
flow of the catamenia, according as it is colder or hotter, more 
'antique' or more 'recent'. Democritus of Abdera also says that 
the differentiation of sex takes place within the mother; that 
however it is not because of heat and cold that one embryo 
becomes female and another male, but that it depends on the 



2137 



question which parent it is whose semen prevails, - not the 
whole of the semen, but that which has come from the part by 
which male and female differ from one another. This is a better 
theory, for certainly Empedocles has made a rather light- 
hearted assumption in thinking that the difference between 
them is due only to cold and heat, when he saw that there was 
a great difference in the whole of the sexual parts, the 
difference in fact between the male pudenda and the uterus. For 
suppose two animals already moulded in embryo, the one 
having all the parts of the female, the other those of the male; 
suppose them then to be put into the uterus as into an oven, 
the former when the oven is hot, the latter when it is cold; then 
on the view of Empedocles that which has no uterus will be 
female and that which has will be male. But this is impossible. 
Thus the theory of Democritus would be the better of the two, at 
least as far as this goes, for he seeks for the origin of this 
difference and tries to set it forth; whether he does so well or 
not is another question. 

Again, if heat and cold were the cause of the difference of the 
parts, this ought to have been stated by those who maintain the 
view of Empedocles; for to explain the origin of male and 
female is practically the same thing as to explain this, which is 
the manifest difference between them. And it is no small 
matter, starting from temperature as a principle, to collect the 
cause of the origin of these parts, as if it were a necessary 
consequence for this part which they call the uterus to be 
formed in the embryo under the influence of cold but not under 
that of heat. The same applies also to the parts which serve for 
intercourse, since these also differ in the way stated previously. 

Moreover male and female twins are often found together in 
the same part of the uterus; this we have observed sufficiently 
by dissection in all the vivipara, both land animals and fish. 
Now if Empedocles had not seen this it was only natural for him 



2138 



to fall into error in assigning this cause of his; but if he had seen 
it it is strange that he should still think the heat or cold of the 
uterus to be the cause, since on his theory both these twins 
would have become either male or female, but as it is we do not 
see this to be the fact. 

Again he says that the parts of the embryo are 'sundered', some 
being in the male and some in the female parent, which is why 
they desire intercourse with one another. If so it is necessary 
that the sexual parts like the rest should be separated from one 
another, already existing as masses of a certain size, and that 
they should come into being in the embryo on account of 
uniting with one another, not on account of cooling or heating 
of the semen. But perhaps it would take too long to discuss 
thoroughly such a cause as this which is stated by Empedocles, 
for its whole character seems to be fanciful. If, however, the 
facts about semen are such as we have actually stated, if it does 
not come from the whole of the body of the male parent and if 
the secretion of the male does not give any material at all to the 
embryo, then we must make a stand against both Empedocles 
and Democritus and any one else who argues on the same lines. 
For then it is not possible that the body of the embryo should 
exist 'sundered', part in the female parent and part in the male, 
as Empedocles says in the words: 'But the nature of the limbs 
hath been sundered, part in the man's...'; nor yet that a whole 
embryo is drawn off from each parent and the combination of 
the two becomes male or female according as one part prevails 
over another. 

And, to take a more general view, though it is better to say that 
the one part makes the embryo female by prevailing through 
some superiority than to assign nothing but heat as the cause 
without any reflection, yet, as the form of the pudendum also 
varies along with the uterus from that of the father, we need an 
explanation of the fact that both these parts go along with each 



2139 



other. If it is because they are near each other, then each of the 
other parts also ought to go with them, for one of the prevailing 
parts is always near another part where the struggle is not yet 
decided; thus the offspring would be not only female or male 
but also like its mother or father respectively in all other details. 

Besides, it is absurd to suppose that these parts should come 
into being as something isolated, without the body as a whole 
having changed along with them. Take first and foremost the 
blood-vessels, round which the whole mass of the flesh lies as 
round a framework. It is not reasonable that these should 
become of a certain quality because of the uterus, but rather 
that the uterus should do so on account of them. For though it 
is true that each is a receptacle of blood of some kind, still the 
system of the vessels is prior to the other; the moving principle 
must needs always be prior to that which it moves, and it is 
because it is itself of a certain quality that it is the cause of the 
development. The difference, then, of these parts as compared 
with each other in the two sexes is only a concomitant result; 
not this but something else must be held to be the first 
principle and the cause of the development of an embryo as 
male or female; this is so even if no semen is secreted by either 
male or female, but the embryo is formed in any way you 
please. 

The same argument as that with which we meet Empedocles 
and Democritus will serve against those who say that the male 
comes from the right and the female from the left. If the male 
contributes no material to the embryo, there can be nothing in 
this view. If, as they say, he does contribute something of the 
sort, we must confront them in the same way as we did the 
theory of Empedocles, which accounts for the difference 
between male and female by the heat and cold of the uterus. 
They make the same mistake as he does, when they account for 
the difference by their 'right and left', though they see that the 



2140 



sexes differ actually by the whole of the sexual parts; for what 
reason then is the body of the uterus to exist in those embryos 
which come from the left and not in those from the right? For if 
an embryo have come from the left but has not acquired this 
part, it will be a female without a uterus, and so too there is 
nothing to stop another from being a male with a uterus! 
Besides as has been said before, a female embryo has been 
observed in the right part of the uterus, a male in the left, or 
again both at once in the same part, and this not only once but 
several times. 

Some again, persuaded of the truth of a view resembling that of 
these philosophers, say that if a man copulates with the right or 
left testis tied up the result is male or female offspring 
respectively; so at least Leophanes asserted. And some say that 
the same happens in the case of those who have one or other 
testis excised, not speaking truth but vaticinating what will 
happen from probabilities and jumping at the conclusion that it 
is so before seeing that it proves to be so. Moreover, they know 
not that these parts of animals contribute nothing to the 
production of one sex rather than the other; a proof of this is 
that many animals in which the distinction of sex exists, and 
which produce both male and female offspring, nevertheless 
have no testes, as the footless animals; I mean the classes of 
fish and of serpents. 

To suppose, then, either that heat and cold are the causes of 
male and female, or that the different sexes come from the right 
and left, is not altogether unreasonable in itself; for the right of 
the body is hotter than the left, and the concocted semen is 
hotter than the unconcocted; again, the thickened is concocted, 
and the more thickened is more fertile. Yet to put it in this way 
is to seek for the cause from too remote a starting-point; we 
must draw near the immediate causes in so far as it is possible 
for us. 



2141 



We have, then, previously spoken elsewhere of both the body as 
a whole and its parts, explaining what each part is and for what 
reason it exists. But (1) the male and female are distinguished 
by a certain capacity and incapacity. (For the male is that which 
can concoct the blood into semen and which can form and 
secrete and discharge a semen carrying with it the principle of 
form - by 'principle' I do not mean a material principle out of 
which comes into being an offspring resembling the parent, but 
I mean the first moving cause, whether it have power to act as 
such in the thing itself or in something else - but the female is 
that which receives semen, indeed, but cannot form it for itself 
or secrete or discharge it.) And (2) all concoction works by 
means of heat. Therefore the males of animals must needs be 
hotter than the females. For it is by reason of cold and 
incapacity that the female is more abundant in blood in certain 
parts of her anatomy, and this abundance is an evidence of the 
exact opposite of what some suppose, thinking that the female 
is hotter than the male for this reason, i.e. the discharge of the 
catamenia. It is true that blood is hot, and that which has more 
of it is hotter than that which has less. But they assume that 
this discharge occurs through excess of blood and of heat, as if 
it could be taken for granted that all blood is equally blood if 
only it be liquid and sanguineous in colour, and as if it might 
not become less in quantity but purer in quality in those who 
assimilate nourishment properly. In fact they look upon this 
residual discharge in the same light as that of the intestines, 
when they think that a greater amount of it is a sign of a hotter 
nature, whereas the truth is just the opposite. For consider the 
production of fruit; the nutriment in its first stage is abundant, 
but the useful product derived from it is small, indeed the final 
result is nothing at all compared to the quantity in the first 
stage. So is it with the body; the various parts receive and work 
up the nutriment, from the whole of which the final result is 
quite small. This is blood in some animals, in some its analogue. 



2142 



Now since (1) the one sex is able and the other is unable to 
reduce the residual secretion to a pure form, and (2) every 
capacity or power in an organism has a certain corresponding 
organ, whether the faculty produces the desired results in a 
lower degree or in a higher degree, and the two sexes 
correspond in this manner (the terms 'able' and 'unable' being 
used in more senses than one) - therefore it is necessary that 
both female and male should have organs. Accordingly the one 
has the uterus, the other the male organs. 

Again, Nature gives both the faculty and the organ to each 
individual at the same time, for it is better so. Hence each 
region comes into being along with the secretions and the 
faculties, as e.g. the faculty of sight is not perfected without the 
eye, nor the eye without the faculty of sight; and so too the 
intestine and bladder come into being along with the faculty of 
forming the excreta. And since that from which an organ comes 
into being and that by which it is increased are the same (i.e. 
the nutriment), each of the parts will be made out of such a 
material and such residual matter as it is able to receive. In the 
second place, again, it is formed, as we say, in a certain sense, 
out of its opposite. Thirdly, we must understand besides this 
that, if it is true that when a thing perishes it becomes the 
opposite of what it was, it is necessary also that what is not 
under the sway of that which made it must change into its 
opposite. After these premisses it will perhaps be now clearer 
for what reason one embryo becomes female and another male. 
For when the first principle does not bear sway and cannot 
concoct the nourishment through lack of heat nor bring it into 
its proper form, but is defeated in this respect, then must needs 
the material which it works on change into its opposite. Now 
the female is opposite to the male, and that in so far as the one 
is female and the other male. And since it differs in its faculty, 
its organ also is different, so that the embryo changes into this 
state. And as one part of first-rate importance changes, the 



2143 



whole system of the animal differs greatly in form along with it. 
This may be seen in the case of eunuchs, who, though mutilated 
in one part alone, depart so much from their original 
appearance and approximate closely to the female form. The 
reason of this is that some of the parts are principles, and when 
a principle is moved or affected needs must many of the parts 
that go along with it change with it. 

If then (1) the male quality or essence is a principle and a cause, 
and (2) the male is such in virtue of a certain capacity and the 
female is such in virtue of an incapacity, and (3) the essence or 
definition of the capacity and of the incapacity is ability or 
inability to concoct the nourishment in its ultimate stage, this 
being called blood in the sanguinea and the analogue of blood 
in the other animals, and (4) the cause of this capacity is in the 
first principle and in the part which contains the principle of 
natural heat - therefore a heart must be formed in the 
sanguinea (and the resulting animal will be either male or 
female), and in the other kinds which possess the sexes must be 
formed that which is analogous to the heart. 

This, then, is the first principle and cause of male and female, 
and this is the part of the body in which it resides. But the 
animal becomes definitely female or male by the time when it 
possesses also the parts by which the female differs from the 
male, for it is not in virtue of any part you please that it is male 
or female, any more than it is able to see or hear by possessing 
any part you please. 

To recapitulate, we say that the semen, which is the foundation 
of the embryo, is the ultimate secretion of the nutriment. By 
ultimate I mean that which is carried to every part of the body, 
and this is also the reason why the offspring is like the parent. 
For it makes no difference whether we say that the semen 
comes from all the parts or goes to all of them, but the latter is 



2144 



the better. But the semen of the male differs from the 
corresponding secretion of the female in that it contains a 
principle within itself of such a kind as to set up movements 
also in the embryo and to concoct thoroughly the ultimate 
nourishment, whereas the secretion of the female contains 
material alone. If, then, the male element prevails it draws the 
female element into itself, but if it is prevailed over it changes 
into the opposite or is destroyed. But the female is opposite to 
the male, and is female because of its inability to concoct and of 
the coldness of the sanguineous nutriment. And Nature assigns 
to each of the secretions the part fitted to receive it. But the 
semen is a secretion, and this in the hotter animals with blood, 
i.e. the males, is moderate in quantity, wherefore the recipient 
parts of this secretion in males are only passages. But the 
females, owing to inability to concoct, have a great quantity of 
blood, for it cannot be worked up into semen. Therefore they 
must also have a part to receive this, and this part must be 
unlike the passages of the male and of a considerable size. This 
is why the uterus is of such a nature, this being the part by 
which the female differs from the male. 



We have thus stated for what reason the one becomes female 
and the other male. Observed facts confirm what we have said. 
For more females are produced by the young and by those 
verging on old age than by those in the prime of life; in the 
former the vital heat is not yet perfect, in the latter it is failing. 
And those of a moister and more feminine state of body are 
more wont to beget females, and a liquid semen causes this 
more than a thicker; now all these characteristics come of 
deficiency in natural heat. 



2145 



Again, more males are born if copulation takes place when 
north than when south winds are blowing. For in the latter case 
the animals produce more secretion, and too much secretion is 
harder to concoct; hence the semen of the males is more liquid, 
and so is the discharge of the catamenia. 

Also the fact that the catamenia occur in the course of nature 
rather when the month is waning is due to the same causes. For 
this time of the month is colder and moister because of the 
waning and failure of the moon; as the sun makes winter and 
summer in the year as a whole, so does the moon in the month. 
This is not due to the turning of the moon, but it grows warmer 
as the light increases and colder as it wanes. 

The shepherds also say that it not only makes a difference in 
the production of males and females if copulation takes place 
during northern or southerly winds, but even if the animals 
while copulating look towards the south or north; so small a 
thing will sometimes turn the scale and cause cold or heat, and 
these again influence generation. 

The male and female, then, are distinguished generally, as 
compared with one another in connexion with the production 
of male and female offspring, for the causes stated. However, 
they also need a certain correspondence with one another to 
produce at all, for all things that come into being as products of 
art or of Nature exist in virtue of a certain ratio. Now if the hot 
preponderates too much it dries up the liquid; if it is very 
deficient it does not solidify it; for the artistic or natural product 
we need the due mean between the extremes. Otherwise it will 
be as in cooking; too much fire burns the meat, too little does 
not cook it, and in either case the process is a failure. So also 
there is need of due proportion in the mixture of the male and 
female elements. And for this cause it often happens to many of 
both sexes that they do not generate with one another, but if 



2146 



divorced and remarried to others do generate; and these 
oppositions show themselves sometimes in youth, sometimes 
in advanced age, alike as concerns fertility or infertility, and as 
concerns generation of male or female offspring. 

One country also differs from another in these respects, and 
one water from another, for the same reasons. For the 
nourishment and the medical condition of the body are of such 
or such a kind because of the tempering of the surrounding air 
and of the food entering the body, especially the water; for men 
consume more of this than of anything else, and this enters as 
nourishment into all food, even solids. Hence hard waters cause 
infertility, and cold waters the birth of females. 



The same causes must be held responsible for the following 
groups of facts. (1) Some children resemble their parents, while 
others do not; some being like the father and others like the 
mother, both in the body as a whole and in each part, male and 
female offspring resembling father and mother respectively 
rather than the other way about. (2) They resemble their parents 
more than remoter ancestors, and resemble those ancestors 
more than any chance individual. (3) Some, though resembling 
none of their relations, yet do at any rate resemble a human 
being, but others are not even like a human being but a 
monstrosity. For even he who does not resemble his parents is 
already in a certain sense a monstrosity; for in these cases 
Nature has in a way departed from the type. The first departure 
indeed is that the offspring should become female instead of 
male; this, however, is a natural necessity. (For the class of 
animals divided into sexes must be preserved, and as it is 



2147 



possible for the male sometimes not to prevail over the female 
in the mixture of the two elements, either through youth or age 
or some other such cause, it is necessary that animals should 
produce female young). And the monstrosity, though not 
necessary in regard of a final cause and an end, yet is necessary 
accidentally. As for the origin of it, we must look at it in this 
way. If the generative secretion in the catamenia is properly 
concocted, the movement imparted by the male will make the 
form of the embryo in the likeness of itself. (Whether we say 
that it is the semen or this movement that makes each of the 
parts grow, makes no difference; nor again whether we say that 
it 'makes them grow' or 'forms them from the beginning', for 
the formula of the movement is the same in either case.) Thus if 
this movement prevail, it will make the embryo male and not 
female, like the father and not like the mother; if it prevail not, 
the embryo is deficient in that faculty in which it has not 
prevailed. By 'each faculty' I mean this. That which generates is 
not only male but also a particular male, e.g. Coriscus or 
Socrates, and it is not only Coriscus but also a man. In this way 
some of the characteristics of the father are more near to him, 
others more remote from him considered simply as a parent 
and not in reference to his accidental qualities (as for instance 
if the parent is a scholar or the neighbour of some particular 
person). Now the peculiar and individual has always more force 
in generation than the more general and wider characteristics. 
Coriscus is both a man and an animal, but his manhood is 
nearer to his individual existence than is his animalhood. In 
generation both the individual and the class are operative, but 
the individual is the more so of the two, for this is the only true 
existence. And the offspring is produced indeed of a certain 
quality, but also as an individual, and this latter is the true 
existence. Therefore it is from the forces of all such existences 
that the efficient movements come which exist in the semen; 
potentially from remoter ancestors but in a higher degree and 



2148 



more nearly from the individual (and by the individual I mean 
e.g. Coriscus or Socrates). Now since everything changes not 
into anything haphazard but into its opposite, therefore also 
that which is not prevailed over in generation must change and 
become the opposite, in respect of that particular force in which 
the paternal and efficient or moving element has not prevailed. 
If then it has not prevailed in so far as it is male, the offspring 
becomes female; if in so far as it is Coriscus or Socrates, the 
offspring does not resemble the father but the mother. For as 
'father' and 'mother' are opposed as general terms, so also the 
individual father is opposed to the individual mother. The like 
applies also to the forces that come next in order, for the 
offspring always changes rather into the likeness of the nearer 
ancestor than the more remote, both in the paternal and in the 
maternal line. 

Some of the movements exist in the semen actually, others 
potentially; actually, those of the father and the general type, as 
man and animal; potentially those of the female and the 
remoter ancestors. Thus the male and efficient principle, if it 
lose its own nature, changes to its opposites, but the 
movements which form the embryo change into those nearly 
connected with them; for instance, if the movement of the male 
parent be resolved, it changes by a very slight difference into 
that of his father, and in the next instance into that of his 
grandfather; and in this way not only in the male but also in the 
female line the movement of the female parent changes into 
that of her mother, and, if not into this, then into that of her 
grandmother; and similarly also with the more remote 
ancestors. 

Naturally then it is most likely that the characteristics of 'male' 
and of the individual father will go together, whether they 
prevail or are prevailed over. For the difference between them is 
small so that there is no difficulty in both concurring, for 



2149 



Socrates is an individual man with certain characters. Hence for 
the most part the male offspring resemble the father, and the 
female the mother. For in the latter case the loss of both 
characters takes place at once, and the change is into the two 
opposites; now is opposed to male, and the individual mother to 
the individual father. 

But if the movement coming from the male principle prevails 
while that coming from the individual Socrates does not, or vice 
versa, then the result is that male children are produced 
resembling the mother and female children resembling the 
father. 

If again the movements be resolved, if the male character 
remain but the movement coming from the individual Socrates 
be resolved into that of the father of Socrates, the result will be 
a male child resembling its grandfather or some other of its 
more remote ancestors in the male line on the same principle. If 
the male principle be prevailed over, the child will be female 
and resembling most probably its mother, but, if the movement 
coming from the mother also be resolved, it will resemble its 
mother's mother or the resemblance will be to some other of its 
more remote ancestors in the female line on the same principle. 

The same applies also to the separate parts, for often some of 
these take after the father, and others after the mother, and yet 
others after some of the remoter ancestors. For, as has been 
often said already, some of the movements which form the 
parts exist in the semen actually and others potentially. We 
must grasp certain fundamental general principles, not only 
that just mentioned (that some of the movements exist 
potentially and others actually), but also two others, that if a 
character be prevailed over it changes into its opposite, and, if it 
be resolved, is resolved into the movement next allied to it - if 
less, into that which is near, if more, into that which is further 



2150 



removed. Finally, the movements are so confused together that 
there is no resemblance to any of the family or kindred, but the 
only character that remains is that common to the race, i.e. it is 
a human being. The reason of this is that this is closely knit up 
with the individual characteristics; 'human being' is the general 
term, while Socrates, the father, and the mother, whoever she 
may be, are individuals. 

The reason why the movements are resolved is this. The agent 
is itself acted upon by that on which it acts; thus that which 
cuts is blunted by that which is cut by it, that which heats is 
cooled by that which is heated by it, and in general the moving 
or efficient cause (except in the case of the first cause of all) 
does itself receive some motion in return; e.g. what pushes is 
itself in a way pushed again and what crushes is itself crushed 
again. Sometimes it is altogether more acted upon than is the 
thing on which it acts, so that what is heating or cooling 
something else is itself cooled or heated; sometimes having 
produced no effect, sometimes less than it has itself received. 
(This question has been treated in the special discussion of 
action and reaction, where it is laid down in what classes of 
things action and reaction exist.) Now that which is acted on 
escapes and is not mastered by the semen, either through 
deficiency of power in the concocting and moving agent or 
because what should be concocted and formed into distinct 
parts is too cold and in too great quantity. Thus the moving 
agent, mastering it in one part but not in another, makes the 
embryo in formation to be multiform, as happens with athletes 
because they eat so much. For owing to the quantity of their 
food their nature is not able to master it all, so as to increase 
and arrange their form symmetrically; therefore their limbs 
develop irregularly, sometimes indeed almost so much that no 
one of them resembles what it was before. Similar to this is also 
the disease known as satyrism, in which the face appears like 



2151 



that of a satyr owing to a quantity of unconcocted humour or 
wind being diverted into parts of the face. 

We have thus discussed the cause of all these phenomena, (1) 
female and male offspring are produced, (2) why some are 
similar to their parents, female to female and male to male, and 
others the other way about, females being similar to the father 
and males to the mother, and in general why some are like their 
ancestors while others are like none of them, and all this as 
concerns both the body as a whole and each of the parts 
separately. Different accounts, however, have been given of 
these phenomena by some of the nature-philosophers; I mean 
why children are like or unlike their parents. They give two 
versions of the reason. Some say that the child is more like that 
parent of the two from whom comes more semen, this applying 
equally both to the body as a whole and to the separate parts, 
on the assumption that semen comes from each part of both 
parents; if an equal part comes from each, then, they say, the 
child is like neither. But if this is false, if semen does not come 
off from the whole body of the parents, it is clear that the 
reason assigned cannot be the cause of likeness and unlikeness. 
Moreover, they are hard put to it to explain how it is that a 
female child can be like the father and a male like the mother. 
For (1) those who assign the same cause of sex as Empedocles 
or Democritus say what is on other grounds impossible, and (2) 
those who say that it is determined by the greater or smaller 
amount of semen coming the male or female parent, and that 
this is why one child is male and another female, cannot show 
how the female is to resemble the father and the male the 
mother, for it is impossible that more should come from both at 
once. Again, for what reason is a child generally like its 
ancestors, even the more remote? None of the semen has come 
from them at any rate. 



2152 



But those who account for the similarity in the manner which 
remains to be discussed, explain this point better, as well as the 
others. For there are some who say that the semen, though one, 
is as it were a common mixture (panspermia) of many 
elements; just as, if one should mix many juices in one liquid 
and then take some from it, it would be possible to take, not an 
equal quantity always from each juice, but sometimes more of 
one and sometimes more of another, sometimes some of one 
and none at all of another, so they say it is with the generative 
fluid, which is a mixture of many elements, for the offspring 
resembles that parent from which it has derived most. Though 
this theory is obscure and in many ways fictitious, it aims at 
what is better expressed by saying that what is called 
'panspermia' exists potentially, not actually; it cannot exist 
actually, but it can do so potentially. Also, if we assign only one 
sort of cause, it is not easy to explain all the phenomena, (1) the 
distinction of sex, (2) why the female is often like the father and 
the male like the mother, and again (3) the resemblance to 
remoter ancestors, and further (4) the reason why the offspring 
is sometimes unlike any of these but still a human being, but 
sometimes, (5) proceeding further on these lines, appears finally 
to be not even a human being but only some kind of animal, 
what is called a monstrosity. 

For, following what has been said, it remains to give the reason 
for such monsters. If the movements imparted by the semen are 
resolved and the material contributed by the mother is not 
controlled by them, at last there remains the most general 
substratum, that is to say the animal. Then people say that the 
child has the head of a ram or a bull, and so on with other 
animals, as that a calf has the head of a child or a sheep that of 
an ox. All these monsters result from the causes stated above, 
but they are none of the things they are said to be; there is only 
some similarity, such as may arise even where there is no defect 
of growth. Hence often jesters compare some one who is not 



2153 



beautiful to a 'goat breathing fire', or again to a 'ram butting', 
and a certain physiognomist reduced all faces to those of two or 
three animals, and his arguments often prevailed on people. 

That, however, it is impossible for such a monstrosity to come 
into existence - I mean one animal in another - is shown by the 
great difference in the period of gestation between man, sheep, 
dog, and ox, it being impossible for each to be developed except 
in its proper time. 

This is the description of some of the monsters talked about; 
others are such because certain parts of their form are 
multiplied so that they are born with many feet or many heads. 

The account of the cause of monstrosities is very close and 
similar in a way to that of the cause of animals being born 
defective in any part, for monstrosity is also a kind of deficiency. 



Democritus said that monstrosities arose because two 
emissions of seminal fluid met together, the one succeeding the 
other at an interval of time; that the later entering into the 
uterus reinforced the earlier so that the parts of the embryo 
grow together and get confused with one another. But in birds, 
he says, since copulation takes place quickly, both the eggs and 
their colour always cross one another. But if it is the fact, as it 
manifestly is, that several young are produced from one 
emission of semen and a single act of intercourse, it is better 
not to desert the short road to go a long way about, for in such 
cases it is absolutely necessary that this should occur when the 
semen is not separated but all enters the female at once. 



2154 



If, then, we must attribute the cause to the semen of the male, 
this will be the way we shall have to state it, but we must rather 
by all means suppose that the cause lies in the material 
contributed by the female and in the embryo as it is forming. 
Hence also such monstrosities appear very rarely in animals 
producing only one young one, more frequently in those 
producing many, most of all in birds and among birds in the 
common fowl. For this bird produces many young, not only 
because it lays often like the pigeon family, but also because it 
has many embryos at once and copulates all the year round. 
Therefore it produces many double eggs, for the embryos grow 
together because they are near one another, as often happens 
with many fruits. In such double eggs, when the yolks are 
separated by the membrane, two separate chickens are 
produced with nothing abnormal about them; when the yolks 
are continuous, with no division between them, the chickens 
produced are monstrous, having one body and head but four 
legs and four wings; this is because the upper parts are formed 
earlier from the white, their nourishment being drawn from the 
yolk, whereas the lower part comes into being later and its 
nourishment is one and indivisible. 

A snake has also been observed with two heads for the same 
reason, this class also being oviparous and producing many 
young. Monstrosities, however, are rarer among them owing to 
the shape of the uterus, for by reason of its length the 
numerous eggs are set in a line. 

Nothing of the kind occurs with bees and wasps, because their 
brood is in separate cells. But in the fowl the opposite is the 
case, whereby it is plain that we must hold the cause of such 
phenomena to lie in the material. So, too, monstrosities are 
commoner in other animals if they produce many young. Hence 
they are less common in man, for he produces for the most part 
only one young one and that perfect; even in man monstrosities 



2155 



occur more often in regions where the women give birth to 
more than one at a time, as in Egypt. And they are commoner in 
sheep and goats, since they produce more young. Still more 
does this apply to the fissipeds, for such animals produce many 
young and imperfect, as the dog, the young of these creatures 
being generally blind. Why this happens and why they produce 
many young must be stated later, but in them Nature has made 
an advance towards the production of monstrosities in that 
what they generate, being imperfect, is so far unlike the parent; 
now monstrosities also belong to the class of things unlike the 
parent. Therefore this accident also often invades animals of 
such a nature. So, too, it is in these that the so-called 
'metachoera' are most frequent, and the condition of these also 
is in a way monstrous, since both deficiency and excess are 
monstrous. For the monstrosity belongs to the class of things 
contrary to Nature, not any and every kind of Nature, but Nature 
in her usual operations; nothing can happen contrary to Nature 
considered as eternal and necessary, but we speak of things 
being contrary to her in those cases where things generally 
happen in a certain way but may also happen in another way. In 
fact, even in the case of monstrosities, whenever things occur 
contrary indeed to the established order but still always in a 
certain way and not at random, the result seems to be less of a 
monstrosity because even that which is contrary to Nature is in 
a certain sense according to Nature, whenever, that is, the 
formal nature has not mastered the material nature. Therefore 
they do not call such things monstrosities any more than in the 
other cases where a phenomenon occurs habitually, as in fruits; 
for instance, there is a vine which some call 'capneos'; if this 
bear black grapes they do not judge it a monstrosity because it 
is in the habit of doing this very often. The reason is that it is in 
its nature intermediate between white and black; thus the 
change is not a violent one nor, so to say, contrary to Nature; at 
least, is it not a change into another nature. But in animals 



2156 



producing many young not only do the same phenomena occur, 
but also the numerous embryos hinder one another from 
becoming perfect and interfere with the generative motions 
imparted by the semen. 

A difficulty may be raised concerning (1) the production of 
many young and the multiplication of the parts in a single 
young one, and (2) the production of few young or only one and 
the deficiency of the parts. Sometimes animals are born with 
too many toes, sometimes with one alone, and so on with the 
other parts, for they may be multiplied or they may be absent. 
Again, they may have the generative parts doubled, the one 
being male, the other female; this is known in men and 
especially in goats. For what are called 'tragaenae' are such 
because they have both male and female generative parts; there 
is a case also of a goat being born with a horn upon its leg. 
Changes and deficiencies are found also in the internal parts, 
animals either not possessing some at all, or possessing them 
in a rudimentary condition, or too numerous or in the wrong 
place. No animal, indeed, has ever been born without a heart, 
but they are born without a spleen or with two spleens or with 
one kidney; there is no case again of total absence of the liver, 
but there are cases of its being incomplete. And all these 
phenomena have been seen in animals perfect and alive. 
Animals also which naturally have a gall-bladder are found 
without one; others are found to have more than one. Cases are 
known, too, of the organs changing places, the liver being on the 
left, the spleen on the right. These phenomena have been 
observed, as stated above, in animals whose growth is 
perfected; at the time of birth great confusion of every kind has 
been found. Those deficiency which only depart a little from 
Nature commonly live; not so those which depart further, when 
the unnatural condition is in the parts which are sovereign over 
life. 



2157 



The question then about all these cases is this. Are we to 
suppose that a single cause is responsible for the production of 
a single young one and for the deficiency of the parts, and 
another but still a single cause for the production of many 
young and the multiplication of parts, or not? 

In the first place it seems only reasonable to wonder why some 
animals produce many young, others only one. For it is the 
largest animals that produce one, e.g. the elephant, camel, 
horse, and the other solid-hoofed ungulates; of these some are 
larger than all other animals, while the others are of a 
remarkable size. But the dog, the wolf, and practically all the 
fissipeds, produce many, even the small members of the class, 
as the mouse family. The cloven-footed animals again produce 
few, except the pig, which belongs to those that produce many. 
This certainly seems surprising, for we should expect the large 
animals to be able to generate more young and to secrete more 
semen. But precisely what we wonder at is the reason for not 
wondering; it is just because of their size that they do not 
produce many young, for the nutriment is expended in such 
animals upon increasing the body. But in the smaller animals 
Nature takes away from the size and adds the excess so gained 
to the seminal secretion. Moreover, more semen must needs be 
used in generation by the larger animal, and little by the 
smaller. Therefore many small ones may be produced together, 
but it is hard for many large ones to be so, and to those 
intermediate in size Nature has assigned the intermediate 
number. We have formerly given the reason why some animals 
are large, some smaller, and some between the two, and 
speaking generally, with regard to the number of young 
produced, the solid-hoofed produce one, the cloven-footed few, 
the many-toed many. (The reason of this is that, generally 
speaking, their sizes correspond to this difference.) It is not so, 
however, in all cases; for it is the largeness and smallness of the 
body that is cause of few or many young being born, not the fact 



2158 



that the kind of animal has one, two, or many toes. A proof of 
this is that the elephant is the largest of animals and yet is 
many-toed, and the camel, the next largest, is cloven-footed. 
And not only in animals that walk but also in those that fly or 
swim the large ones produce few, the small many, for the same 
reason. In like manner also it is not the largest plants that bear 
most fruit. 

We have explained then why some animals naturally produce 
many young, some but few, and some only one; in the difficulty 
now stated we may rather be surprised with reason at those 
which produce many, since such animals are often seen to 
conceive from a single copulation. Whether the semen of the 
male contributes to the material of the embryo by itself 
becoming a part of it and mixing with the semen of the female, 
or whether, as we say, it does not act in this way but brings 
together and fashions the material within the female and the 
generative secretion as the fig-juice does the liquid substance of 
milk, what is the reason why it does not form a single animal of 
considerable size? For certainly in the parallel case the fig-juice 
is not separated if it has to curdle a large quantity of milk, but 
the more the milk and the more the fig-juice put into it, so 
much the greater is the curdled mass. Now it is no use to say 
that the several regions of the uterus attract the semen and 
therefore more young than one are formed, because the regions 
are many and the cotyledons are more than one. For two 
embryos are often formed in the same region of the uterus, and 
they may be seen lying in a row in animals that produce many, 
when the uterus is filled with the embryos. (This is plain from 
the dissections.) Rather the truth is this. As animals complete 
their growth there are certain limits to their size, both upwards 
and downwards, beyond which they cannot go, but it is in the 
space between these limits that they exceed or fall short of one 
another in size, and it is within these limits that one man (or 
any other animal) is larger or smaller than another. So also the 



2159 



generative material from which each animal is formed is not 
without a quantitative limit in both directions, nor can it be 
formed from any quantity you please. Whenever then an 
animal, for the cause assigned, discharges more of the female 
secretion than is needed for beginning the existence of a single 
animal, it is not possible that only one should be formed out of 
all this, but a number limited by the appropriate size in each 
case; nor will the semen of the male, or the power residing in 
the semen, form anything either more or less than what is 
according to Nature. In like manner, if the male emits more 
semen than is necessary, or more powers in different parts of 
the semen as it is divided, however much it is it will not make 
anything greater; on the contrary it will dry up the material of 
the female and destroy it. So fire also does not continue to make 
water hotter in proportion as it is itself increased, but there is a 
fixed limit to the heat of which water is capable; if that is once 
reached and the fire is then increased, the water no longer gets 
hotter but rather evaporates and at last disappears and is dried 
up. Now since it appears that the secretion of the female and 
that from the male need to stand in some proportionate 
relation to one another (I mean in animals of which the male 
emits semen), what happens in those that produce many young 
is this: from the very first the semen emitted by the male has 
power, being divided, to form several embryos, and the material 
contributed by the female is so much that several can be formed 
out of it. (The parallel of curdling milk, which we spoke of 
before, is no longer in point here, for what is formed by the heat 
of the semen is not only of a certain quantity but also of a 
certain quality, whereas with fig-juice and rennet quantity 
alone is concerned.) This then is just the reason why in such 
animals the embryos formed are numerous and do not all unite 
into one whole; it is because an embryo is not formed out of any 
quantity you please, but whether there is too much or too little, 
in either case there will be no result, for there is a limit set alike 



2160 



to the power of the heat which acts on the material and to the 
material so acted upon. 

On the same principle many embryos are not formed, though 
the secretion is much, in the large animals which produce only 
one young one, for in them also both the material and that 
which works upon it are of a certain quantity. So then they do 
not secrete such material in too great quantity for the reason 
previously stated, and what they do secrete is naturally just 
enough for one embryo alone to be formed from it. If ever too 
much is secreted, then twins are born. Hence such cases seem 
to be more portentous, because they are contrary to the general 
and customary rule. 

Man belongs to all three classes, for he produces one only and 
sometimes many or few, though naturally he almost always 
produces one. Because of the moisture and heat of his body he 
may produce many [for semen is naturally fluid and hot], but 
because of his size he produces few or one. On account of this it 
results that in man alone among animals the period of 
gestation is irregular; whereas the period is fixed in the rest, 
there are several periods in man, for children are born at seven 
months and at ten months and at the times between, for even 
those of eight months do live though less often than the rest. 
The reason may be gathered from what has just been said, and 
the question has been discussed in the Problems. Let this 
explanation suffice for these points. 

The cause why the parts may be multiplied contrary to Nature 
is the same as the cause of the birth of twins. For the reason 
exists already in the embryo, whenever it aggregates more 
material at any point of itself than is required by the nature of 
the part. The result is then that either one of its parts is larger 
than the others, as a finger or hand or foot or any of the other 
extremities or limbs; or again if the embryo is cleft there may 



2161 



come into being more than one such part, as eddies do in rivers; 
as the water in these is carried along with a certain motion, if it 
dash against anything two systems or eddies come into being 
out of one, each retaining the same motion; the same thing 
happens also with the embryos. The abnormal parts generally 
are attached near those they resemble, but sometimes at a 
distance because of the movement - taking place in the embryo, 
and especially because of the excess of material returning to 
that place whence it was taken away while retaining the form 
of that part whence it arose as a superfluity. 

In certain cases we find a double set of generative organs [one 
male and the other female]. When such duplication occurs the 
one is always functional but not the other, because it is always 
insufficiently supplied with nourishment as being contrary to 
Nature; it is attached like a growth (for such growths also 
receive nourishment though they are a later development than 
the body proper and contrary to Nature.) If the formative power 
prevails, both are similar; if it is altogether vanquished, both are 
similar; but if it prevail here and be vanquished there, then the 
one is female and the other male. (For whether we consider the 
reason why the whole animal is male or female, or why the 
parts are so, makes no difference.) 

When we meet with deficiency in such parts, e.g. an extremity 
or one of the other members, we must assume the same cause 
as when the embryo is altogether aborted (abortion of embryos 
happens frequently). 

Outgrowths differ from the production of many young in the 
manner stated before; monsters differ from these in that most 
of them are due to embryos growing together. Some however 
are also of the following kind, when the monstrosity affects 
greater and more sovereign parts, as for instance some 
monsters have two spleens or more than two kidneys. Further, 



2162 



the parts may migrate, the movements which form the embryo 
being diverted and the material changing its place. We must 
decide whether the monstrous animal is one or is composed of 
several grown together by considering the vital principle; thus, if 
the heart is a part of such a kind then that which has one heart 
will be one animal, the multiplied parts being mere outgrowths, 
but those which have more than one heart will be two animals 
grown together through their embryos having been confused. 

It also often happens even in many animals that do not seem to 
be defective and whose growth is now complete, that some of 
their passages may have grown together or others may have 
been diverted from the normal course. Thus in some women 
before now the os uteri has remained closed, so that when the 
time for the catamenia has arrived pain has attacked them, till 
either the passage has burst open of its own accord or the 
physicians have removed the impediment; some such cases 
have ended in death if the rupture has been made too violently 
or if it has been impossible to make it at all. In some boys on the 
other hand the end of the penis has not coincided with the end 
of the passage where the urine is voided, but the passage has 
ended below, so that they crouch sitting to void it, and if the 
testes are drawn up they appear from a distance to have both 
male and female generative organs. The passage of the solid 
food also has been closed before now in sheep and some other 
animals; there was a cow in Perinthus which passed fine matter, 
as if it were sifted, through the bladder, and when the anus was 
cut open it quickly closed up again nor could they succeed in 
keeping it open. 

We have now spoken of the production of few and many young, 
and of the outgrowth of superfluous parts or of their deficiency, 
and also of monstrosities. 



2163 



Superfoetation does not occur at all in some animals but does 
in others; of the former some are able to bring the later formed 
embryo to birth, while others can only do so sometimes. The 
reason why it does not occur in some is that they produce only 
one young one, for it is not found in solid-hoofed animals and 
those larger than these, as owing to their size the secretion of 
the female is all used up for the one embryo. For all these have 
large bodies, and when an animal is large its foetus is large in 
proportion, e.g. the foetus of the elephant is as big as a calf. But 
superfoetation occurs in those which produce many young 
because the production of more than one at a birth is itself a 
sort of superfoetation, one being added to another. Of these all 
that are large, as man, bring to birth the later embryo, if the 
second impregnation takes place soon after the first, for such 
an event has been observed before now. The reason is that given 
above, for even in a single act of intercourse the semen 
discharged is more than enough for one embryo, and this being 
divided causes more than one child to be born, the one of which 
is later than the other. But when the embryo has already grown 
to some size and it so happens that copulation occurs again, 
superfoetation sometimes takes place, but rarely, since the 
uterus generally closes in women during the period of gestation. 
If this ever happens (for this also has occurred) the mother 
cannot bring the second embryo to perfection, but it is cast out 
in a state like what are called abortions. For just as, in those 
animals that bear only one, all the secretion of the female is 
converted to the first formed embryo because of its size, so it is 
here also; the only difference is that in the former case this 
happens at once, in the latter when the foetus has attained to 
some size, for then they are in the same state as those that bear 
only one. In like manner, since man naturally would produce 



2164 



many young, and since the size of the uterus and the quantity 
of the female secretion are both greater than is necessary for 
one embryo, only not so much so as to bring to birth a second, 
therefore women and mares are the only animals which admit 
the male during gestation, the former for the reason stated, and 
mares both because of the barrenness of their nature and 
because their uterus is of superfluous size, too large for one but 
too small to allow a second embryo to be brought to perfection 
by superfoetation. And the mare is naturally inclined to sexual 
intercourse because she is in the same case as the barren 
among women; these latter are barren because they have no 
monthly discharge (which corresponds to the act of intercourse 
in males) and mares have exceedingly little. And in all the 
vivipara the barren females are so inclined, because they 
resemble the males when the semen has collected in the testes 
but is not being got rid of. For the discharge of the catamenia is 
in females a sort of emission of semen, they being unconcocted 
semen as has been said before. Hence it is that those women 
also who are incontinent in regard to such intercourse cease 
from their passion for it when they have borne many children, 
for, the seminal secretion being then drained off, they no longer 
desire this intercourse. And among birds the hens are less 
disposed that way than the cocks, because the uterus of the 
hen-bird is up near the hypozoma; but with the cock-birds it is 
the other way, for their testes are drawn up within them, so 
that, if any kind of such birds has much semen naturally, it is 
always in need of this intercourse. In females then it 
encourages copulation to have the uterus low down, but in 
males to have the testes drawn up. 

It has been now stated why superfoetation is not found in some 
animals at all, why it is found in others which sometimes bring 
the later embryos to birth and sometimes not, and why some 
such animals are inclined to sexual intercourse while others are 
not. 



2165 



Some of those animals in which superfoetation occurs can bring 
the embryos to birth even if a long time elapses between the 
two impregnations, if their kind is spermatic, if their body is not 
of a large size, and if they bear many young. For because they 
bear many their uterus is spacious, because they are spermatic 
the generative discharge is copious, and because the body is not 
large but the discharge is excessive and in greater measure than 
is required for the nourishment wanted for the embryo, 
therefore they can not only form animals but also bring them to 
birth later on. Further, the uterus in such animals does not close 
up during gestation because there is a quantity of the residual 
discharge left over. This has happened before now even in 
women, for in some of them the discharge continues during all 
the time of pregnancy. In women, however, this is contrary to 
Nature, so that the embryo suffers, but in such animals it is 
according to Nature, for their body is so formed from the 
beginning, as with hares. For superfoetation occurs in these 
animals, since they are not large and they bear many young (for 
they have many toes and the many-toed animals bear many), 
and they are spermatic. This is shown by their hairiness, for the 
quantity of their hair is excessive, these animals alone having 
hair under the feet and within the jaws. Now hairiness is a sign 
of abundance of residual matter, wherefore among men also the 
hairy are given to sexual intercourse and have much semen 
rather than the smooth. In the hare it often happens that some 
of the embryos are imperfect while others of its young are 
produced perfect. 



Some of the vivipara produce their young imperfect, others 
perfect; the one-hoofed and cloven-footed perfect, most of the 



2166 



many-toed imperfect. The reason of this is that the one-hoofed 
produce one young one, and the cloven-footed either one or two 
generally speaking; now it is easy to bring the few to perfection. 
All the many-toed animals that bear their young imperfect give 
birth to many. Hence, though they are able to nourish the 
embryos while newly formed, their bodies are unable to 
complete the process when the embryos have grown and 
acquired some size. So they produce them imperfect, like those 
animals which generate a scolex, for some of them when born 
are scarcely brought into form at all, as the fox, bear, and lion, 
and some of the rest in like manner; and nearly all of them are 
blind, as not only the animals mentioned but also the dog, wolf, 
and jackal. The pig alone produces both many and perfect 
young, and thus here alone we find any overlapping; it produces 
many as do the many-toed animals, but is cloven-footed or 
solid-hoofed (for there certainly are solid-hoofed swine). They 
bear, then, many young because the nutriment which would 
otherwise go to increase their size is diverted to the generative 
secretion (for considered as a solid-hoofed animal the pig is not 
a large one), and also it is more often cloven-hoofed, striving as 
it were with the nature of the solid-hoofed animals. For this 
reason it produces sometimes only one, sometimes two, but 
generally many, and brings them to perfection before birth 
because of the good condition of its body, being like a rich soil - 
which has sufficient and abundant nutriment for plants. 

The young of some birds also are hatched imperfect, that is to 
say blind; this applies to all small birds which lay many eggs, as 
crows and rooks, jays, sparrows, swallows, and to all those 
which lay few eggs without producing abundant nourishment 
along with the young, as ring-doves, turtle-doves, and pigeons. 
Hence if the eyes of swallows while still young be put out they 
recover their sight again, for the birds are still developing, not 
yet developed, when the injury is inflicted, so that the eyes grow 
and sprout afresh. And in general the production of young 



2167 



before they are perfect is owing to inability to continue 
nourishing them, and they are born imperfect because they are 
born too soon. This is plain also with seven-months children, 
for since they are not perfected it often happens that even the 
passages, e.g. of the ears and nostrils, are not yet opened in 
some of them at birth, but only open later as they are growing, 
and many such infants survive. 

In man males are more often born defective than females, but 
in the other animals this is not the case. The reason is that in 
man the male is much superior to the female in natural heat, 
and so the male foetus moves about more than the female, and 
on account of moving is more liable to injury, for what is young 
is easily injured since it is weak. For this same reason also the 
female foetus is not perfected equally with the male in man 
(but they are so in the other animals, for in them the female is 
not later in developing than the male). For while within the 
mother the female takes longer in developing, but after birth 
everything is perfected more quickly in females than in males; I 
mean, for instance, puberty, the prime of life, and old age. For 
females are weaker and colder in nature, and we must look 
upon the female character as being a sort of natural deficiency. 
Accordingly while it is within the mother it develops slowly 
because of its coldness (for development is concoction, and it is 
heat that concocts, and what is hotter is easily concocted); but 
after birth it quickly arrives at maturity and old age on account 
of its weakness, for all inferior things come sooner to their 
perfection or end, and as this is true of works of art so it is of 
what is formed by Nature. For the reason just given also twins 
are less likely to survive in man if one be male and one female, 
but this is not at all so in the other animals; for in man it is 
contrary to Nature that they should run an equal course, as 
their development does not take place in equal periods, but the 
male must needs be too late or the female too early; in the other 
animals, however, it is not contrary to Nature. A difference is 



2168 



also found between man and the other animals in respect of 
gestation, for animals are in better bodily condition most of the 
time, whereas in most women gestation is attended with 
discomfort. Their way of life is partly responsible for this, for 
being sedentary they are full of more residual matter; among 
nations where the women live a laborious life gestation is not 
equally conspicuous and those who are accustomed to work 
bear children easily both there and elsewhere; for work 
consumes the residual matter, but those who are sedentary 
have a great deal of it in them because not only is there no 
monthly discharge during pregnancy but also they do no work; 
therefore their travail is painful. But work exercises them so 
that they can hold their breath, upon which depends the ease or 
difficulty of child-birth. These circumstances then, as we have 
said, contribute to cause the difference between women and the 
other animals in this state, but the most important thing is this: 
in some animals the discharge corresponding to the catamenia 
is but small, and in some not visible at all, but in women it is 
greater than in any other animal, so that when this discharge 
ceases owing to pregnancy they are troubled (for if they are not 
pregnant they are afflicted with ailments whenever the 
catamenia do not occur); and they are more troubled as a rule at 
the beginning of pregnancy, for the embryo is able indeed to 
stop the catamenia but is too small at first to consume any 
quantity of the secretion; later on it takes up some of it and so 
alleviates the mother. In the other animals, on the contrary, the 
residual matter is but small and so corresponds with the growth 
of the foetus, and as the secretions which hinder nourishment 
are being consumed by the foetus the mother is in better bodily 
condition than usual. The same holds good also with aquatic 
animals and birds. If it ever happens that the body of the 
mother is no longer in good condition when the foetus is now 
becoming large, the reason is that its growth needs more 
nourishment than the residual matter supplies. (In some few 



2169 



women it happens that the body is in a better state during 
pregnancy; these are women in whose body the residual matter 
is small so that it is all used up along with the nourishment that 
goes to the foetus.) 



We must also speak of what is known as mola uteri, which 
occurs rarely in women but still is found sometimes during 
pregnancy. For they produce what is called a mola; it has 
happened before now to a woman, after she had had 
intercourse with her husband and supposed she had conceived, 
that at first the size of her belly increased and everything else 
happened accordingly, but yet when the time for birth came on, 
she neither bore a child nor was her size reduced, but she 
continued thus for three or four years until dysentery came on, 
endangering her life, and she produced a lump of flesh which is 
called mola. Moreover this condition may continue till old age 
and death. Such masses when expelled from the body become 
so hard that they can hardly be cut through even by iron. 
Concerning the cause of this phenomenon we have spoken in 
the Problems; the same thing happens to the embryo in the 
womb as to meats half cooked in roasting, and it is not due to 
heat, as some say, but rather to the weakness of the maternal 
heat. (For their nature seems to be incapable, and unable to 
perfect or to put the last touches to the process of generation. 
Hence it is that the mola remains in them till old age or at any 
rate for a long time, for in its nature it is neither perfect nor 
altogether a foreign body.) It is want of concoction that is the 
reason of its hardness, as with half-cooked meat, for this half- 
dressing of meat is also a sort of want of concoction. 



2170 



A difficulty is raised as to why this does not occur in other 
animals, unless indeed it does occur and has entirely escaped 
observation. We must suppose the reason to be that woman 
alone among animals is subject to troubles of the uterus, and 
alone has a superfluous amount of catamenia and is unable to 
concoct them; when, then, the embryo has been formed of a 
liquid hard to concoct, then comes the so-called mola into 
being, and this happens naturally in women alone or at any rate 
more than in other animals. 



8 

Milk is formed in the females of all internally viviparous 
animals, becoming useful for the time of birth. For Nature has 
made it for the sake of the nourishment of animals after birth, 
so that it may neither fail at this time at all nor yet be at all 
superfluous; this is just what we find happening, unless 
anything chance contrary to Nature. In the other animals the 
period of gestation does not vary, and so the milk is concocted 
in time to suit this moment, but in man, since there are several 
times of birth, it must be ready at the first of these; hence in 
women the milk is useless before the seventh month and only 
then becomes useful. That it is only concocted at the last stages 
is what we should expect to happen also as being due to a 
necessary cause. For at first such residual matter when secreted 
is used up for the development of the embryo; now the 
nutritious part in all things is the sweetest and the most 
concocted, and thus when all such elements are removed what 
remains must become of necessity bitter and ill-flavoured. As 
the embryo is perfecting, the residual matter left over increases 
in quantity because the part consumed by the embryo is less; it 
is also sweeter since the easily concocted part is less drawn 



2171 



away from it. For it is no longer expended on moulding the 
embryo but only on slightly increasing its growth, it being now 
fixed because it has reached perfection (for in a sense there is a 
perfection even of an embryo). Therefore it comes forth from 
the mother and changes its mode of development, as now 
possessing what belongs to it; and no longer takes that which 
does not belong to it; and it is at this season that the milk 
becomes useful. 

The milk collects in the upper part of the body and the breasts 
because of the original plan of the organism. For the part above 
the hypozoma is the sovereign part of the animal, while that 
below is concerned with nourishment and residual matter, in 
order that all animals which move about may contain within 
themselves nourishment enough to make them independent 
when they move from one place to another. From this upper 
part also is produced the generative secretion for the reason 
mentioned in the opening of our discussion. But both the 
secretion of the male and the catamenia of the female are of a 
sanguineous nature, and the first principle of this blood and of 
the blood-vessels is the heart, and the heart is in this part of the 
body. Therefore it is here that the change of such a secretion 
must first become plain. This is why the voice changes in both 
sexes when they begin to bear seed (for the first principle of the 
voice resides there, and is itself changed when its moving cause 
changes). At the same time the parts about the breasts are 
raised visibly even in males but still more in females, for the 
region of the breasts becomes empty and spongy in them 
because so much material is drained away below. This is so not 
only in women but also in those animals which have the 
mammae low down. 

This change in the voice and the parts about the mammae is 
plain even in other creatures to those who have experience of 
each kind of animal, but is most remarkable in man. The reason 



2172 



is that in man the production of secretion is greatest in both 
sexes in proportion to their size as compared with other 
animals; I mean that of the catamenia in women and the 
emission of semen in men. When, therefore, the embryo no 
longer takes up the secretion in question but yet prevents its 
being discharged from the mother, it is necessary that the 
residual matter should collect in all those empty parts which 
are set upon the same passages. And such is the position of the 
mammae in each kind of animals for both causes; it is so both 
for the sake of what is best and of necessity. 

It is here, then, that the nourishment in animals is now formed 
and becomes thoroughly concocted. As for the cause of 
concoction, we may take that already given, or we may take the 
opposite, for it is a reasonable view also that the embryo being 
larger takes more nourishment, so that less is left over about 
this time, and the less is concocted more quickly. 

That milk has the same nature as the secretion from which 
each animal is formed is plain, and has been stated previously. 
For the material which nourishes is the same as that from 
which Nature forms the animal in generation. Now this is the 
sanguineous liquid in the sanguinea, and milk is blood 
concocted (not corrupted; Empedocles either mistook the fact or 
made a bad metaphor when he composed the line: 'On the 
tenth day of the eighth month the milk comes into being, a 
white pus', for putrefaction and concoction are opposite things, 
and pus is a kind of putrefaction but milk is concocted). While 
women are suckling children the catamenia do not occur 
according to Nature, nor do they conceive; if they do conceive, 
the milk dries up. This is because the nature of the milk and of 
the catamenia is the same, and Nature cannot be so productive 
as to supply both at once; if the secretion is diverted in the one 
direction it must needs cease in the other, unless some violence 
is done contrary to the general rule. But this is as much as to 



2173 



say that it is contrary to Nature, for in all cases where it is not 
impossible for things to be otherwise than they generally are 
but where they may so happen, still what is the general rule is 
what is 'according to Nature'. 

The time also at which the young animal is born has been well 
arranged. For when the nourishment coming through the 
umbilical cord is no longer sufficient for the foetus because of 
its size, then at the same time the milk becomes useful for the 
nourishment of the newly-born animal, and the blood-vessels 
round which the so-called umbilical cord lies as a coat collapse 
as the nourishment is no longer passing through it; for these 
reasons it is at that time also that the young animal enters into 
the world. 



The natural birth of all animals is head-foremost, because the 
parts above the umbilical cord are larger than those below. The 
body then, being suspended from the cord as in a balance, 
inclines towards the heavy end, and the larger parts are the 
heavier. 



10 

The period of gestation is, as a matter of fact, determined 
generally in each animal in proportion to the length of its life. 
This we should expect, for it is reasonable that the development 
of the long-lived animals should take a longer time. Yet this is 
not the cause of it, but the periods only correspond accidentally 



2174 



for the most part; for though the larger and more perfect 
sanguinea do live a long time, yet the larger are not all longer- 
lived. Man lives a longer time than any animal of which we have 
any credible experience except the elephant, and yet the human 
kind is smaller than that of the bushy-tailed animals and many 
others. The real cause of long life in any animal is its being 
tempered in a manner resembling the environing air, along with 
certain other circumstances of its nature, of which we will 
speak later; but the cause of the time of gestation is the size of 
the offspring. For it is not easy for large masses to arrive at their 
perfection in a small time, whether they be animals or, one may 
say, anything else whatever. That is why horses and animals 
akin to them, though living a shorter time than man, yet carry 
their young longer; for the time in the former is a year, but in 
the latter ten months at the outside. For the same reason also 
the time is long in elephants; they carry their young two years 
on account of their excessive size. 

We find, as we might expect, that in all animals the time of 
gestation and development and the length of life aims at being 
measured by naturally complete periods. By a natural period I 
mean, e.g. a day and night, a month, a year, and the greater 
times measured by these, and also the periods of the moon, that 
is to say, the full moon and her disappearance and the halves of 
the times between these, for it is by these that the moon's orbit 
fits in with that of the sun [the month being a period common 
to both]. 

The moon is a first principle because of her connexion with the 
sun and her participation in his light, being as it were a second 
smaller sun, and therefore she contributes to all generation and 
development. For heat and cold varying within certain limits 
make things to come into being and after this to perish, and it is 
the motions of the sun and moon that fix the limit both of the 
beginning and of the end of these processes. Just as we see the 



2175 



sea and all bodies of water settling and changing according to 
the movement or rest of the winds, and the air and winds again 
according to the course of the sun and moon, so also the things 
which grow out of these or are in these must needs follow suit. 
For it is reasonable that the periods of the less important should 
follow those of the more important. For in a sense a wind, too, 
has a life and birth and death. 

As for the revolutions of the sun and moon, they may perhaps 
depend on other principles. It is the aim, then, of Nature to 
measure the coming into being and the end of animals by the 
measure of these higher periods, but she does not bring this to 
pass accurately because matter cannot be easily brought under 
rule and because there are many principles which hinder 
generation and decay from being according to Nature, and often 
cause things to fall out contrary to Nature. 

We have now spoken of the nourishment of animals within the 
mother and of their birth into the world, both of each kind 
separately and of all in common. 



BookV 



We must now investigate the qualities by which the parts of 
animals differ. I mean such qualities of the parts as blueness 
and blackness in the eyes, height and depth of pitch in the 



2176 



voice, and differences in colour whether of the skin or of hair 
and feathers. Some such qualities are found to characterize the 
whole of a kind of animals sometimes, while in other kinds they 
occur at random, as is especially the case in man. Further, in 
connexion with the changes in the time of life, all animals are 
alike in some points, but are opposed in others as in the case of 
the voice and the colour of the hair, for some do not grow grey 
visibly in old age, while man is subject to this more than any 
other animal. And some of these affections appear immediately 
after birth, while others become plain as age advances or in old 
age. 

Now we must no longer suppose that the cause of these and all 
such phenomena is the same. For whenever things are not the 
product of Nature working upon the animal kingdom as a 
whole, nor yet characteristic of each separate kind, then none of 
these things is such as it is or is so developed for any final 
cause. The eye for instance exists for a final cause, but it is not 
blue for a final cause unless this condition be characteristic of 
the kind of animal. In fact in some cases this condition has no 
connexion with the essence of the animal's being, but we must 
refer the causes to the material and the motive principle or 
efficient cause, on the view that these things come into being by 
Necessity. For, as was said originally in the outset of our 
discussion, when we are dealing with definite and ordered 
products of Nature, we must not say that each is of a certain 
quality because it becomes so, but rather that they become so 
and so because they are so and so, for the process of Becoming 
or development attends upon Being and is for the sake of Being, 
not vice versa. 

The ancient Nature-philosophers however took the opposite 
view. The reason of this is that they did not see that the causes 
were numerous, but only saw the material and efficient and did 



2177 



not distinguish even these, while they made no inquiry at all 
into the formal and final causes. 

Everything then exists for a final cause, and all those things 
which are included in the definition of each animal, or which 
either are means to an end or are ends in themselves, come into 
being both through this cause and the rest. But when we come 
to those things which come into being without falling under the 
heads just mentioned, their course must be sought in the 
movement or process of coming into being, on the view that the 
differences which mark them arise in the actual formation of 
the animal. An eye, for instance, the animal must have of 
necessity (for the fundamental idea of the animal is of such a 
kind), but it will have an eye of a particular kind of necessity in 
another sense, not the sense mentioned just above, because it is 
its nature to act or be acted on in this or that way. 

These distinctions being drawn let us speak of what comes next 
in order. As soon then as the offspring of all animals are born, 
especially those born imperfect, they are in the habit of 
sleeping, because they continue sleeping also within the mother 
when they first acquire sensation. But there is a difficulty about 
the earliest period of development, whether the state of 
wakefulness exists in animals first, or that of sleep. Since they 
plainly wake up more as they grow older, it is reasonable to 
suppose that the opposite state, that of sleep, exists in the first 
stages of development. Moreover the change from not being to 
being must pass through the intermediate condition, and sleep 
seems to be in its nature such a condition, being as it were a 
boundary between living and not living, and the sleeper being 
neither altogether non-existent nor yet existent. For life most of 
all appertains to wakefulness, on account of sensation. But on 
the other hand, if it is necessary that the animal should have 
sensation and if it is then first an animal when it has acquired 
sensation, we ought to consider the original condition to be not 



2178 



sleep but only something resembling sleep, such a condition as 
we find also in plants, for indeed at this time animals do 
actually live the life of a plant. But it is impossible that plants 
should sleep, for there is no sleep which cannot be broken, and 
the condition in plants which is analogous to sleep cannot be 
broken. 

It is necessary then for the embryo animal to sleep most of the 
time because the growth takes place in the upper part of the 
body, which is consequently heavier (and we have stated 
elsewhere that such is the cause of sleep). But nevertheless they 
are found to wake even in the womb (this is clear in dissections 
and in the ovipara), and then they immediately fall into a sleep 
again. This is why after birth also they spend most of their time 
in sleep. 

When awake infants do not laugh, but while asleep they both 
laugh and cry. For animals have sensations even while asleep, 
not only what are called dreams but also others besides dreams, 
as those persons who arise while sleeping and do many things 
without dreaming. For there are some who get up while 
sleeping and walk about seeing just like those who are awake; 
these have perception of what is happening, and though they 
are not awake, yet this perception is not like a dream. So infants 
presumably have sense-perception and live in their sleep owing 
to previous habit, being as it were without knowledge of the 
waking state. As time goes on and their growth is transferred to 
the lower part of the body, they now wake up more and spend 
most of their time in that condition. Children continue asleep at 
first more than other animals, for they are born in a more 
imperfect condition than other animals that are produced in 
anything like a perfect state, and their growth has taken place 
more in the upper part of the body. 



2179 



The eyes of all children are bluish immediately after birth; later 
on they change to the colour which is to be theirs permanently. 
But in the case of other animals this is not visible. The reason of 
this is that the eyes of other animals are more apt to have only 
one colour for each kind of animal; e.g. cattle are dark-eyed, the 
eye of all sheep is pale, of others again the whole kind is blue or 
grey-eyed, and some are yellow (goat-eyed), as the majority of 
goats themselves, whereas the eyes of men happen to be of 
many colours, for they are blue or grey or dark in some cases 
and yellow in others. Hence, as the individuals in other kinds of 
animals do not differ from one another in the colour, so neither 
do they differ from themselves, for they are not of a nature to 
have more than one colour. Of the other animals the horse has 
the greatest variety of colour in the eye, for some of them are 
actually heteroglaucous; this phenomenon is not to be seen in 
any of the other animals, but man is sometimes 
heteroglaucous. 

Why then is it that there is no visible change in the other 
animals if we compare their condition when newly born with 
their condition at a more advanced age, but that there is such a 
change in children? We must consider just this to be a sufficient 
cause, that the part concerned has only one colour in the 
former but several colours in the latter. And the reason why the 
eyes of infants are bluish and have no other colour is that the 
parts are weaker in the newly born and blueness is a sort of 
weakness. 

We must also gain a general notion about the difference in eyes, 
for what reason some are blue, some grey, some yellow, and 
some dark. To suppose that the blue are fiery, as Empedocles 
says, while the dark have more water than fire in them, and 
that this is why the former, the blue, have not keen sight by day, 
viz. owing to deficiency of water in their composition, and the 
latter are in like condition by night, viz. owing to deficiency of 



2180 



fire - this is not well said if indeed we are to assume sight to be 
connected with water, not fire, in all cases. Moreover it is 
possible to render another account of the cause of the colours, 
but if indeed the fact is as was stated before in the treatise on 
the senses, and still earlier than that in the investigations 
concerning soul - if this sense organ is composed of water and 
if we were right in saying for what reason it is composed of 
water and not of air or fire - then we must assume the water to 
be the cause of the colours mentioned. For some eyes have too 
much liquid to be adapted to the movement, others have too 
little, others the due amount. Those eyes therefore in which 
there is much liquid are dark because much liquid is not 
transparent, those which have little are blue; (so we find in the 
sea that the transparent part of it appears light blue, the less 
transparent watery, and the unfathomable water is dark or 
deep-blue on account of its depth). When we come to the eyes 
between these, they differ only in degree. 

We must suppose the same cause also to be responsible for the 
fact that blue eyes are not keen-sighted by day nor dark eyes by 
night. Blue eyes, because there is little liquid in them, are too 
much moved by the light and by visible objects in respect of 
their liquidity as well as their transparency, but sight is the 
movement of this part in so far as it is transparent, not in so far 
as it is liquid. Dark eyes are less moved because of the quantity 
of liquid in them. And so they see less well in the dusk, for the 
nocturnal light is weak; at the same time also liquid is in 
general hard to move in the night. But if the eye is to see, it 
must neither not be moved at all nor yet more than in so far as 
it is transparent, for the stronger movement drives out the 
weaker. Hence it is that on changing from strong colours, or on 
going out of the sun into the dark, men cannot see, for the 
motion already existing in the eye, being strong, stops that from 
outside, and in general neither a strong nor a weak sight can 



2181 



see bright things because the liquid is acted upon and moved 
too much. 

The same thing is shown also by the morbid affections of each 
kind of sight. Cataract attacks the blue-eyed more, but what is 
called 'nyctalopia' the dark-eyed. Now cataract is a sort of 
dryness of the eyes and therefore it is found more in the aged, 
for this part also like the rest of the body gets dry towards old 
age; but is an excess of liquidity and so is found more in the 
younger, for their brain is more liquid. 

The sight of the eye which is intermediate between too much 
and too little liquid is the best, for it has neither too little so as 
to be disturbed and hinder the movement of the colours, nor 
too much so as to cause difficulty of movement. 

Not only the above-mentioned facts are causes of seeing keenly 
or the reverse, but also the nature of the skin upon what is 
called the pupil. This ought to be transparent, and it is 
necessary that the transparent should be thin and white and 
even, thin that the movement coming from without may pass 
straight through it, even that it may not cast a shade the liquid 
behind it by wrinkling (for this also is a reason why old men 
have not keen sight, the skin of the eye like the rest of the skin 
wrinkling and becoming thicker in old age), and white because 
black is not transparent, for that is just what is meant by 'black', 
what is not shone through, and that is why lanterns cannot give 
light if they be made of black skin. It is for these reasons then 
that the sight is not keen in old age nor in the diseases in 
question, but it is because of the small amount of liquid that the 
eyes of children appear blue at first. 

And the reason why men especially and horses occasionally are 
heteroglaucous is the same as the reason why man alone grows 
grey and the horse is the only other animal whose hairs whiten 
visibly in old age. For greyness is a weakness of the fluid in the 



2182 



brain and an incapacity to concoct properly, and so is blueness 
of the eyes; excess of thinness or of thickness produces the 
same effect, according as this liquidity is too little or too much. 
Whenever then Nature cannot make the eyes correspond 
exactly, either by concocting or by not concocting the liquid in 
both, but concocts the one and not the other, then the result is 
heteroglaucia. 

The cause of some animals being keen-sighted and others not 
so is not simple but double. For the word 'keen' has pretty much 
a double sense (and this is the case in like manner with hearing 
and smelling). In one sense keen sight means the power of 
seeing at a distance, in another it means the power of 
distinguishing as accurately as possible the objects seen. These 
two faculties are not necessarily combined in the same 
individual. For the same person, if he shades his eyes with his 
hand or look through a tube, does not distinguish the 
differences of colour either more or less in any way, but he will 
see further; in fact, men in pits or wells sometimes see the 
stars. Therefore if any animal's brows project far over the eye, 
but if the liquid in the pupil is not pure nor suited to the 
movement coming from external objects and if the skin over 
the surface is not thin, this animal will not distinguish 
accurately the differences of the colours but it will be able to see 
from a long distance (just as it can from a short one) better than 
those in which the liquid and the covering membrane are pure 
but which have no brows projecting over the eyes. For the cause 
of seeing keenly in the sense of distinguishing the differences is 
in the eye itself; as on a clean garment even small stains are 
visible, so also in a pure sight even small movements are plain 
and cause sensation. But it is the position of the eyes that is the 
cause of seeing things far off and of the movements in the 
transparent medium coming to the eyes from distant objects. A 
proof of this is that animals with prominent eyes do not see 
well at a distance, whereas those which have their eyes lying 



2183 



deep in the head can see things at a distance because the 
movement is not dispersed in space but comes straight to the 
eye. For it makes no difference whether we say, as some do, that 
seeing is caused by the sight going forth from the eye - on that 
view, if there is nothing projecting over the eyes, the sight must 
be scattered and so less of it will fall on the objects of vision 
and things at a distance will not be seen so well - or whether 
we say that seeing is due to the movement coming from the 
objects; for the sight also must see, in a manner resembling the 
movement. Things at a distance, then, would be seen best if 
there were, so to say, a continuous tube straight from the sight 
to its object, for the movement from the object would not then 
be dissipated; but, if that is impossible, still the further the tube 
extends the more accurately must distant objects be seen. 

Let these, then, be given as the causes of the difference in eyes. 



It is the same also with hearing and smell; to hear and smell 
accurately mean in one sense to perceive as precisely as 
possible all the distinctions of the objects of perception, in 
another sense to hear and smell far off. As with sight, so here 
the sense-organ is the cause of judging well the distinctions, if 
both that organ itself and the membrane round it be pure. For 
the passages of all the sense-organs, as has been said in the 
treatise on sensation, run to the heart, or to its analogue in 
creatures that have no heart. The passage of the hearing, then, 
since this sense-organ is of air, ends at the place where the 
innate spiritus causes in some animals the pulsation of the 
heart and in others respiration; wherefore also it is that we are 
able to understand what is said and repeat what we have heard, 



2184 



for as was the movement which entered through the sense- 
organ, such again is the movement which is caused by means of 
the voice, being as it were of one and the same stamp, so that a 
man can say what he has heard. And we hear less well during a 
yawn or expiration than during inspiration, because the 
starting-point of the sense-organ of hearing is set upon the part 
concerned with breathing and is shaken and moved as the 
organ moves the breath, for while setting the breath in motion 
it is moved itself. The same thing happens in wet weather or a 
damp atmosphere.... And the ears seemed to be filled with air 
because their starting-point is near the region of breathing. 

Accuracy then in judging the differences of sounds and smells 
depends on the purity of the sense-organ and of the membrane 
lying upon its surface, for then all the movements become clear 
in such cases, as in the case of sight. Perception and non- 
perception at a distance also depend on the same things with 
hearing and smell as with sight. For those animals can perceive 
at a distance which have channels, so to say, running through 
the parts concerned and projecting far in front of the sense- 
organs. Therefore all animals whose nostrils are long, as the 
Laconian hounds, are keen-scented, for the sense-organ being 
above them, the movements from a distance are not dissipated 
but go straight to the mark, just as the movements which cause 
sight do with those who shadow the eyes with the hand. 

Similar is the case of animals whose ears are long and project 
far like the eaves of a house, as in some quadrupeds, with the 
internal spiral passage long; these also catch the movement 
from afar and pass it on to the sense-organ. 

In respect of sense-perception at a distance, man is, one may 
say, the worst of all animals in proportion to his size, but in 
respect of judging the differences of quality in the objects he is 
the best of all. The reason is that the sense-organ in man is pure 



2185 



and least earthy and material, and he is by nature the thinnest- 
skinned of all animals for his size. 

The workmanship of Nature is admirable also in the seal, for 
though a viviparous quadruped it has no ears but only passages 
for hearing. This is because its life is passed in the water; now 
the ear is a part added to the passages to preserve the 
movement of the air at a distance; therefore an ear is no use to 
it but would even bring about the contrary result by receiving a 
mass of water into itself. 

We have thus spoken of sight, hearing, and smell. 



As for hair, men differ in this themselves at different ages, and 
also from all other kinds of animals that have hair. These are 
almost all which are internally viviparous, for even when the 
covering of such animals is spiny it must be considered as a 
kind of hair, as in the land hedgehog and any other such animal 
among the vivipara. Hairs differ in respect of hardness and 
softness, length and shortness, straightness and curliness, 
quantity and scantiness, and in addition to these qualities, in 
their colours, whiteness and blackness and the intermediate 
shades. They differ also in some of these respects according to 
age, as they are young or growing old. This is especially plain in 
man; the hair gets coarser as time goes on, and some go bald on 
the front of the head; children indeed do not go bald, nor do 
women, but men do so by the time their age is advancing. 
Human beings also go grey on the head as they grow old, but 
this is not visible in practically any other animal, though more 
so in the horse than others. Men go bald on the front of the 
head, but turn grey first on the temples; no one goes bald first 



2186 



on these or on the back of the head. Some such affections occur 
in a corresponding manner also in all animals which have not 
hair but something analogous to it, as the feathers of birds and 
scales in the class of fish. 

For what purpose Nature has made hair in general for animals 
has been previously stated in the work dealing with the causes 
of the parts of animals; it is the business of the present inquiry 
to show under what circumstances and for what necessary 
causes each particular kind of hair occurs. The principal cause 
then of thickness and thinness is the skin, for this is thick in 
some animals and thin in others, rare in some and dense in 
others. The different quality of the included moisture is also a 
helping cause, for in some animals this is greasy and in others 
watery. For generally speaking the substratum of the skin is of 
an earthy nature; being on the surface of the body it becomes 
solid and earthy as the moisture evaporates. Now the hairs or 
their analogue are not formed out of the flesh but out of the 
skin moisture evaporating and exhaling in them, and therefore 
thick hairs arise from a thick skin and thin from thin. If then the 
skin is rarer and thicker, the hairs are thick because of the 
quantity of earthy matter and the size of the pores, but if it is 
denser they are thin because of the narrowness of the pores. 
Further, if the moisture be watery it dries up quickly and the 
hairs do not gain in size, but if it be greasy the opposite 
happens, for the greasy is not easily dried up. Therefore the 
thicker-skinned animals are as a general rule thicker-haired for 
the causes mentioned; however, the thickest-skinned are not 
more so than other thick-skinned ones, as is shown by the class 
of swine compared to that of oxen and to the elephant and 
many others. And for the same reason also the hairs of the head 
in man are thickest, for this part of his skin is thickest and lies 
over most moisture and besides is very porous. 



2187 



The cause of the hairs being long or short depends on the 
evaporating moisture not being easily dried. Of this there are 
two causes, quantity and quality; if the liquid is much it does 
not dry up easily nor if it is greasy. And for this reason the hairs 
of the head are longest in man, for the brain, being fluid and 
cold, supplies great abundance of moisture. 

The hairs become straight or curly on account of the vapour 
arising in them. If it be smoke-like, it is hot and dry and so 
makes the hair curly, for it is twisted as being carried with a 
double motion, the earthy part tending downwards and the hot 
upwards. Thus, being easily bent, it is twisted owing to its 
weakness, and this is what is meant by curliness in hair. It is 
possible then that this is the cause, but it is also possible that, 
owing to its having but little moisture and much earthy matter 
in it, it is dried by the surrounding air and so coiled up together. 
For what is straight becomes bent, if the moisture in it is 
evaporated, and runs together as a hair does when burning 
upon the fire; curliness will then be a contraction owing to 
deficiency of moisture caused by the heat of the environment. A 
sign of this is the fact that curly hair is harder than straight, for 
the dry is hard. And animals with much moisture are straight- 
haired; for in these hairs the moisture advances as a stream, 
not in drops. For this reason the Scythians on the Black Sea and 
the Thracians are straight-haired, for both they themselves and 
the environing air are moist, whereas the Aethiopians and men 
in hot countries are curly-haired, for their brains and the 
surrounding air are dry. 

Some, however, of the thick-skinned animals are fine-haired for 
the cause previously stated, for the finer the pores are the finer 
must the hairs be. Hence the class of sheep have such hairs (for 
wool is only a multitude of hairs). 



2188 



There are some animals whose hair is soft and yet less fine, as 
is the case with the class of hares compared with that of sheep; 
in such animals the hair is on the surface of the skin, not deeply 
rooted in it, and so is not long but in much the same state as 
the scrapings from linen, for these also are not long but are soft 
and do not admit of weaving. 

The condition of sheep in cold climates is opposite to that of 
man; the hair of the Scythians is soft but that of the Sauromatic 
sheep is hard. The reason of this is the same as it is also all wild 
animals. The cold hardens and solidifies them by drying them, 
for as the heat is pressed out the moisture evaporates, and both 
hair and skin become earthy and hard. In wild animals then the 
exposure to the cold is the cause of hardness in the hair, in the 
others the nature of the climate is the cause. A proof of this is 
also what happens in the sea-urchins which are used as a 
remedy in stranguries. For these, too, though small themselves, 
have large and hard spines because the sea in which they live is 
cold on account of its depth (for they are found in sixty fathoms 
and even more). The spines are large because the growth of the 
body is diverted to them, since having little heat in them they 
do not concoct their nutriment and so have much residual 
matter and it is from this that spines, hairs, and such things are 
formed; they are hard and petrified through the congealing 
effect of the cold. In the same way also plants are found to be 
harder, more earthy, and stony, if the region in which they grow 
looks to the north than if it looks to the south, and those in 
windy places than those in sheltered, for they are all more 
chilled and their moisture evaporates. 

Hardening, then, comes of both heat and cold, for both cause 
the moisture to evaporate, heat per se and cold per accidens 
(since the moisture goes out of things along with the heat, there 
being no moisture without heat), but whereas cold not only 
hardens but also condenses, heat makes a substance rarer. 



2189 



For the same reason, as animals grow older, the hairs become 
harder in those which have hairs, and the feathers and scales in 
the feathered and scaly kinds. For their skins become harder 
and thicker as they get older, for they are dried up, and old age, 
as the word denotes, is earthy because the heat fails and the 
moisture along with it. 

Men go bald visibly more than any other animal, but still such a 
state is something general, for among plants also some are 
evergreens while others are deciduous, and birds which 
hibernate shed their feathers. Similar to this is the condition of 
baldness in those human beings to whom it is incident. For 
leaves are shed by all plants, from one part of the plant at a 
time, and so are feathers and hairs by those animals that have 
them; it is when they are all shed together that the condition is 
described by the terms mentioned, for it is called 'going bald' 
and 'the fall of the leaf and 'moulting'. The cause of the 
condition is deficiency of hot moisture, such moisture being 
especially the unctuous, and hence unctuous plants are more 
evergreen. (However we must elsewhere state the cause of this 
phenomena in plants, for other causes also contribute to it.) It is 
in winter that this happens to plants (for the change from 
summer to winter is more important to them than the time of 
life), and to those animals which hibernate (for these, too, are by 
nature less hot and moist than man); in the latter it is the 
seasons of life that correspond to summer and winter. Hence no 
one goes bald before the time of sexual intercourse, and at that 
time it is in those naturally inclined to such intercourse that 
baldness appears, for the brain is naturally the coldest part of 
the body and sexual intercourse makes men cold, being a loss of 
pure natural heat. Thus we should expect the brain to feel the 
effect of it first, for a little cause turns the scale where the thing 
concerned is weak and in poor condition. Thus if we reckon up 
these points, that the brain itself has but little heat, and further 
that the skin round it must needs have still less, and again that 



2190 



the hair must have still less than the skin inasmuch as it is 
furthest removed from the brain, we should reasonably expect 
baldness to come about this age upon those who have much 
semen. And it is for the same reason that the front part of the 
head alone goes bald in man and that he is the only animal to 
do so; the front part goes bald because the brain is there, and 
man is the only animal to go bald because his brain is much the 
largest and the moistest. Women do not go bald because their 
nature is like that of children, both alike being incapable of 
producing seminal secretion. Eunuchs do not become bald, 
because they change into the female condition. And as to the 
hair that comes later in life, eunuchs either do not grow it at all, 
or lose it if they happen to have it, with the exception of the 
pubic hair; for women also grow that though they have not the 
other, and this mutilation is a change from the male to the 
female condition. 

The reason why the hair does not grow again in cases of 
baldness, although both hibernating animals recover their 
feathers or hair and trees that have shed their leaves grow 
leaves again, is this. The seasons of the year are the turning- 
points of their lives, rather than their age, so that when these 
seasons change they change with them by growing and losing 
feathers, hairs, or leaves respectively. But the winter and 
summer, spring and autumn of man are defined by his age, so 
that, since his ages do not return, neither do the conditions 
caused by them return, although the cause of the change of 
condition is similar in man to what it is in the animals and 
plants in question. 

We have now spoken pretty much of all the other conditions of 
hair. 



2191 



But as to their colour, it is the nature of the skin that is the 
cause of this in other animals and also of their being uni- 
coloured or vari-coloured); but in man it is not the cause, except 
of the hair going grey through disease (not through old age), for 
in what is called leprosy the hairs become white; on the 
contrary, if the hairs are white the whiteness does not invade 
the skin. The reason is that the hairs grow out of skin; if, then, 
the skin is diseased and white the hair becomes diseased with 
it, and the disease of hair is greyness. But the greyness of hair 
which is due to age results from weakness and deficiency of 
heat. For as the body declines in vigour we tend to cold at every 
time of life, and especially in old age, this age being cold and 
dry. We must remember that the nutriment coming to each part 
of the body is concocted by the heat appropriate to the part; if 
the heat is inadequate the part loses its efficiency, and 
destruction or disease results. (We shall speak more in detail of 
causes in the treatise on growth and nutrition.) Whenever, then, 
the hair in man has naturally little heat and too much moisture 
enters it, its own proper heat is unable to concoct the moisture 
and so it is decayed by the heat in the environing air. All decay 
is caused by heat, not the innate heat but external heat, as has 
been stated elsewhere. And as there is a decay of water, of earth, 
and all such material bodies, so there is also of the earthy 
vapour, for instance what is called mould (for mould is a decay 
of earthy vapour). Thus also the liquid nutriment in the hair 
decays because it is not concocted, and what is called greyness 
results. It is white because mould also, practically alone among 
decayed things, is white. The reason of this is that it has much 
air in it, all earthy vapour being equivalent to thick air. For 
mould is, as it were, the antithesis of hoar-frost; if the ascending 
vapour be frozen it becomes hoar-frost, if it be decayed, mould. 
Hence both are on the surface of things, for vapour is 
superficial. And so the comic poets make a good metaphor in 



2192 



jest when they call grey hairs 'mould of old age' and For the one 
is generically the same as greyness, the other specifically; hoar- 
frost generically (for both are a vapour), mould specifically (for 
both are a form of decay). A proof that this is so is this: grey 
hairs have often grown on men in consequence of disease, and 
later on dark hairs instead of them after restoration to health. 
The reason is that in sickness the whole body is deficient in 
natural heat and so the parts besides, even the very small ones, 
participate in this weakness; and again, much residual matter is 
formed in the body and all its parts in illness, wherefore the 
incapacity in the flesh to concoct the nutriment causes the grey 
hairs. But when men have recovered health and strength again 
they change, becoming as it were young again instead of old; in 
consequence the states change also. Indeed, we may rightly call 
disease an acquired old age, old age a natural disease; at any 
rate, some diseases produce the same effects as old age. 

Men go grey on the temples first, because the back of the head 
is empty of moisture owing to its containing no brain, and the 
'bregma' has a great deal of moisture, a large quantity not being 
liable to decay; the hair on the temples however has neither so 
little that it can concoct it nor so much that it cannot decay, for 
this region of the head being between the two extremes is 
exempt from both states. The cause of greyness in man has now 
been stated. 



The reason why this change does not take place visibly on 
account of age in other animals is the same as that already 
given in the case of baldness; their brain is small and less fluid 
than in man, so that the heat required for concoction does not 



2193 



altogether fail. Among them it is most clear in horses of all 
animals that we know, because the bone about the brain is 
thinner in them than in others in proportion to their size. A sign 
of this is that a blow to this spot is fatal to them, wherefore 
Homer also has said: 'where the first hairs grow on the skull of 
horses, and a wound is most fatal.' As then the moisture easily 
flows to these hairs because of the thinness of the bone, whilst 
the heat fails on account of age, they go grey. The reddish hairs 
go grey sooner than the black, redness also being a sort of 
weakness of hair and all weak things ageing sooner. It is said, 
however, that cranes become darker as they grow old. The 
reason of this would be, if it should prove true, that their 
feathers are naturally moister than others and as they grow old 
the moisture in the feathers is too much to decay easily. 

Greyness comes about by some sort of decay, and is not, as 
some think, a withering. (1) A proof of the former statement is 
the fact that hair protected by hats or other coverings goes grey 
sooner (for the winds prevent decay and the protection keeps 
off the winds), and the fact that it is aided by anointing with a 
mixture of oil and water. For, though water cools things, the oil 
mingled with it prevents the hair from drying quickly, water 
being easily dried up. (2) That the process is not a withering, 
that the hair does not whiten as grass does by withering, is 
shown by the fact that some hairs grow grey from the first, 
whereas nothing springs up in a withered state. Many hairs also 
whiten at the tip, for there is least heat in the extremities and 
thinnest parts. 

When the hairs of other animals are white, this is caused by 
nature, not by any affection. The cause of the colours in other 
animals is the skin; if they are white, the skin is white, if they 
are dark it is dark, if they are piebald in consequence of a 
mixture of the hairs, it is found to be white in the one part and 
dark in the other. But in man the skin is in no way the cause, for 



2194 



even white-skinned men have very dark hair. The reason is that 
man has the thinnest skin of all animals in proportion to his 
size and therefore it has not strength to change the hairs; on 
the contrary the skin itself changes its colour through its 
weakness and is darkened by sun and wind, while the hairs do 
not change along with it at all. But in the other animals the 
skin, owing to its thickness, has the influence belonging to the 
soil in which a thing grows, therefore the hairs change 
according to the skin but the skin does not change at all in 
consequence of the winds and the sun. 



Of animals some are uni-coloured (I mean by this term those of 
which the kind as a whole has one colour, as all lions are tawny; 
and this condition exists also in birds, fish, and the other 
classes of animals alike); others though many-coloured are yet 
whole-coloured (I mean those whose body as a whole has the 
same colour, as a bull is white as a whole or dark as a whole); 
others are vari-coloured. This last term is used in both ways; 
sometimes the whole kind is vari-coloured, as leopards and 
peacocks, and some fish, e.g. the so-called 'thrattai'; sometimes 
the kind as a whole is not so, but such individuals are found in 
it, as with cattle and goats and, among birds, pigeons; the same 
applies also to other kinds of birds. The whole-coloured change 
much more than the uniformly coloured, both into the simple 
colour of another individual of the same kind (as dark changing 
into white and vice versa) and into both colours mingled. This is 
because it is a natural characteristic of the kind as a whole not 
to have one colour only, the kind being easily moved in both 
directions so that the colours both change more into one 
another and are more varied. The opposite holds with the 



2195 



uniformly coloured; they do not change except by an affection 
of the colour, and that rarely; but still they do so change, for 
before now white individuals have been observed among 
partridges, ravens, sparrows, and bears. This happens when the 
course of development is perverted, for what is small is easily 
spoilt and easily moved, and what is developing is small, the 
beginning of all such things being on a small scale. 

Change is especially found in those animals of which by nature 
the individual is whole-coloured but the kind many-coloured. 
This is owing to the water which they drink, for hot waters 
make the hair white, cold makes it dark, an effect found also in 
plants. The reason is that the hot have more air than water in 
them, and the air shining through causes whiteness, as also in 
froth. As, then, skins which are white by reason of some 
affection differ from those white by nature, so also in the hair 
the whiteness due to disease or age differs from that due to 
nature in that the cause is different; the latter are whitened by 
the natural heat, the former by the external heat. Whiteness is 
caused in all things by the vaporous air imprisoned in them. 
Hence also in all animals not uniformly coloured all the part 
under the belly is whiter. For practically all white animals are 
both hotter and better flavoured for the same reason; the 
concoction of their nutriment makes them well-flavoured, and 
heat causes the concoction. The same cause holds for those 
animals which are uniformly-coloured, but either dark or white; 
heat and cold are the causes of the nature of the skin and hair, 
each of the parts having its own special heat. 

The tongue also varies in colour in the simply coloured as 
compared with the vari-coloured animals, and again in the 
simply coloured which differ from one another, as white and 
dark. The reason is that assigned before, that the skins of the 
vari-coloured are vari-coloured, and the skins of the white- 
haired and dark-haired are white and dark in each case. Now 



2196 



we must conceive of the tongue as one of the external parts, not 
taking into account the fact that it is covered by the mouth but 
looking on it as we do on the hand or foot; thus since the skin of 
the vari-coloured animals is not uniformly coloured, this is the 
cause of the skin on the tongue being also vari-coloured. 

Some birds and some wild quadrupeds change their colour 
according to the seasons of the year. The reason is that, as men 
change according to their age, so the same thing happens to 
them according to the season; for this makes a greater 
difference to them than the change of age. 

The more omnivorous animals are more vari-coloured to speak 
generally, and this is what might be expected; thus bees are 
more uniformly coloured than hornets and wasps. For if the 
food is responsible for the change we should expect varied food 
to increase the variety in the movements which cause the 
development and so in the residual matter of the food, from 
which come into being hairs and feathers and skins. 

So much for colours and hairs. 



As to the voice, it is deep in some animals, high in others, in 
others again well-pitched and in due proportion between both 
extremes. Again, in some it is loud, in others small, and it differs 
in smoothness and roughness, flexibility and inflexibility. We 
must inquire then into the causes of each of these distinctions. 

We must suppose then that the same cause is responsible for 
high and deep voices as for the change which they undergo in 
passing from youth to age. The voice is higher in all other 



2197 



animals when younger, but in cattle that of calves is deeper. We 
find the same thing also in the male and female sexes; in the 
other kinds of animals the voice of the female is higher than 
that of the male (this being especially plain in man, for Nature 
has given this faculty to him in the highest degree because he 
alone of animals makes use of speech and the voice is the 
material of speech), but in cattle the opposite obtains, for the 
voice of cows is deeper than that of bulls. 

Now the purpose for which animals have a voice, and what is 
meant by 'voice' and by 'sound' generally, has been stated partly 
in the treatise on sensation, partly in that on the soul. But since 
lowness of voice depends on the movement of the air being 
slow and its highness on its being quick, there is a difficulty in 
knowing whether it is that which moves or that which is moved 
that is the cause of the slowness or quickness. For some say 
that what is much is moved slowly, what is little quickly, and 
that the quantity of the air is the cause of some animals having 
a deep and others a high voice. Up to a certain point this is well 
said (for it seems to be rightly said in a general way that the 
depth depends on a certain amount of the air put in motion), 
but not altogether, for if this were true it would not be easy to 
speak both soft and deep at once, nor again both loud and high. 
Again, the depth seems to belong to the nobler nature, and in 
songs the deep note is better than the high-pitched ones, the 
better lying in superiority, and depth of tone being a sort of 
superiority. But then depth and height in the voice are different 
from loudness and softness, and some high-voiced animals are 
loud-voiced, and in like manner some soft-voiced ones are 
deep-voiced, and the same applies to the tones lying between 
these extremes. And by what else can we define these (I mean 
loudness and softness of voice) except by the large and small 
amount of the air put in motion? If then height and depth are to 
be decided in accordance with the distinction postulated, the 
result will be that the same animals will be deep-and loud- 



2198 



voiced, and the same will be high - and not loud - voiced; but 
this is false. 

The reason of the difficulty is that the words 'great' and 'small', 
'much' and 'little' are used sometimes absolutely, sometimes 
relatively to one another. Whether an animal has a great (or 
loud) voice depends on the air which is moved being much 
absolutely, whether it has a small voice depends on its being 
little absolutely; but whether they have a deep or high voice 
depends on their being thus differentiated in relation to one 
another. For if that which is moved surpass the strength of that 
which moves it, the air that is sent forth must go slowly; if the 
opposite, quickly. The strong, then, on account of their strength, 
sometimes move much air and make the movement slow, 
sometimes, having complete command over it, make the 
movement swift. On the same principle the weak either move 
too much air for their strength and so make the movement 
slow, or if they make it swift move but little because of their 
weakness. 

These, then, are the reasons of these contrarieties, that neither 
are all young animals high-voiced nor all deep-voiced, nor are 
all the older, nor yet are the two sexes thus opposed, and again 
that not only the sick speak in a high voice but also those in 
good bodily condition, and, further, that as men verge on old 
age they become higher-voiced, though this age is opposite to 
that of youth. 

Most young animals, then, and most females set but little air in 
motion because of their want of power, and are consequently 
high-voiced, for a little air is carried along quickly, and in the 
voice what is quick is high. But in calves and cows, in the one 
case because of their age, in the other because of their female 
nature, the part by which they set the air in motion is not 
strong; at the same time they set a great quantity in motion and 



2199 



so are deep-voiced; for that which is borne along slowly is 
heavy, and much air is borne along slowly. And these animals 
set much in movement whereas the others set but little, 
because the vessel through which the breath is first borne has 
in them a large opening and necessarily sets much air in 
motion, whereas in the rest the air is better dispensed. As their 
age advances this part which moves the air gains more strength 
in each animal, so that they change into the opposite condition, 
the high-voiced becoming deeper-voiced than they were, and 
the deep-voiced higher-voiced, which is why bulls have a higher 
voice than calves and cows. Now the strength of all animals is 
in their sinews, and so those in the prime of life are stronger, 
the young being weaker in the joints and sinews; moreover, in 
the young they are not yet tense, and in those now growing old 
the tension relaxes, wherefore both these ages are weak and 
powerless for movement. And bulls are particularly sinewy, 
even their hearts, and therefore that part by which they set the 
air in motion is in a tense state, like a sinewy string stretched 
tight. (That the heart of bulls is of such a nature is shown by the 
fact that a bone is actually found in some of them, and bones 
are naturally connected with sinew.) 

All animals when castrated change to the female character, and 
utter a voice like that of the females because the sinewy 
strength in the principle of the voice is relaxed. This relaxation 
is just as if one should stretch a string and make it taut by 
hanging some weight on to it, as women do who weave at the 
loom, for they stretch the warp by attaching to it what are called 
'laiai'. For in this way are the testes attached to the seminal 
passages, and these again to the blood-vessel which takes its 
origin in the heart near the organ which sets the voice in 
motion. Hence as the seminal passages change towards the age 
at which they are now able to secrete the semen, this part also 
changes along with them. As this changes, the voice again 
changes, more indeed in males, but the same thing happens in 



2200 



females too, only not so plainly, the result being what some call 
'bleating' when the voice is uneven. After this it settles into the 
deep or high voice of the succeeding time of life. If the testes are 
removed the tension of the passages relaxes, as when the 
weight is taken off the string or the warp; as this relaxes, the 
organ which moves the voice is loosened in the same 
proportion. This, then, is the reason why the voice and the form 
generally changes to the female character in castrated animals; 
it is because the principle is relaxed upon which depends the 
tension of the body; not that, as some suppose, the testes are 
themselves a ganglion of many principles, but small changes 
are the causes of great ones, not per se but when it happens 
that a principle changes with them. For the principles, though 
small in size, are great in potency; this, indeed, is what is meant 
by a principle, that it is itself the cause of many things without 
anything else being higher than it for it to depend upon. 

The heat or cold also of their habitat contributes to make some 
animals of such a character as to be deep-voiced, and others 
high-voiced. For hot breath being thick causes depth, cold 
breath being thin the opposite. This is clear also in pipe-playing, 
for if the breath of the performer is hotter, that is to say if it is 
expelled as by a groan, the note is deeper. 

The cause of roughness and smoothness in the voice, and of all 
similar inequality, is that the part or organ through which the 
voice is conveyed is rough or smooth or generally even or 
uneven. This is plain when there is any moisture about the 
trachea or when it is roughened by any affection, for then the 
voice also becomes uneven. 

Flexibility depends on the softness or hardness of the organ, for 
what is soft can be regulated and assume any form, while what 
is hard cannot; thus the soft organ can utter a loud or a small 
note, and accordingly a high or a deep one, since it easily 



2201 



regulates the breath, becoming itself easily great or small. But 
hardness cannot be regulated. 

Let this be enough on all those points concerning the voice 
which have not been previously discussed in the treatise on 
sensation and in that on the soul. 



8 

With regard to the teeth it has been stated previously that they 
do not exist for a single purpose nor for the same purpose in all 
animals, but in some for nutrition only, in others also for 
fighting and for vocal speech. We must, however, consider it not 
alien to the discussion of generation and development to 
inquire into the reason why the front teeth are formed first and 
the grinders later, and why the latter are not shed but the 
former are shed and grow again. 

Democritus has spoken of these questions but not well, for he 
assigns the cause too generally without investigating the facts 
in all cases. He says that the early teeth are shed because they 
are formed in animals too early, for it is when animals are 
practically in their prime that they grow according to Nature, 
and suckling is the cause he assigns for their being found too 
early. Yet the pig also suckles but does not shed its teeth, and, 
further, all the animals with carnivorous dentition suckle, but 
some of them do not shed any teeth except the canines, e.g. 
lions. This mistake, then, was due to his speaking generally 
without examining what happens in all cases; but this is what 
we to do, for any one who makes any general statement must 
speak of all the particular cases. 



2202 



Now we assume, basing our assumption upon what we see, that 
Nature never fails nor does anything in vain so far as is possible 
in each case. And it is necessary, if an animal is to obtain food 
after the time of taking milk is over, that it should have 
instruments for the treatment of the food. If, then, as 
Democritus says, this happened about the time of reaching 
maturity, Nature would fail in something possible for her to do. 
And, besides, the operation of Nature would be contrary to 
Nature, for what is done by violence is contrary to Nature, and it 
is by violence that he says the formation of the first teeth is 
brought about. That this view then is not true is plain from 
these and other similar considerations. 

Now these teeth are developed before the flat teeth, in the first 
place because their function is earlier (for dividing comes before 
crushing, and the flat teeth are for crushing, the others for 
dividing), in the second place because the smaller is naturally 
developed quicker than the larger, even if both start together, 
and these teeth are smaller in size than the grinders, because 
the bone of the jaw is flat in that part but narrow towards the 
mouth. From the greater part, therefore, must flow more 
nutriment to form the teeth, and from the narrower part less. 

The act of sucking in itself contributes nothing to the formation 
of the teeth, but the heat of the milk makes them appear more 
quickly. A proof of this is that even in suckling animals those 
young which enjoy hotter milk grow their teeth quicker, heat 
being conducive to growth. 

They are shed, after they have been formed, partly because it is 
better so (for what is sharp is soon blunted, so that a fresh relay 
is needed for the work, whereas the flat teeth cannot be blunted 
but are only smoothed in time by wearing down), partly from 
necessity because, while the roots of the grinders are fixed 
where the jaw is flat and the bone strong, those of the front 



2203 



teeth are in a thin part, so that they are weak and easily moved. 
They grow again because they are shed while the bone is still 
growing and the animal is still young enough to grow teeth. A 
proof of this is that even the flat teeth grow for a long time, the 
last of them cutting the gum at about twenty years of age; 
indeed in some cases the last teeth have been grown in quite 
old age. This is because there is much nutriment in the broad 
part of the bones, whereas the front part being thin soon 
reaches perfection and no residual matter is found in it, the 
nutriment being consumed in its own growth. 

Democritus, however, neglecting the final cause, reduces to 
necessity all the operations of Nature. Now they are necessary, 
it is true, but yet they are for a final cause and for the sake of 
what is best in each case. Thus nothing prevents the teeth from 
being formed and being shed in this way; but it is not on 
account of these causes but on account of the end (or final 
cause); these are causes only in the sense of being the moving 
and efficient instruments and the material. So it is reasonable 
that Nature should perform most of her operations using breath 
as an instrument, for as some instruments serve many uses in 
the arts, e.g. the hammer and anvil in the smith's art, so does 
breath in the living things formed by Nature. But to say that 
necessity is the only cause is much as if we should think that 
the water has been drawn off from a dropsical patient on 
account of the lancet, not on account of health, for the sake of 
which the lancet made the incision. 

We have thus spoken of the teeth, saying why some are shed 
and grow again, and others not, and generally for what cause 
they are formed. And we have spoken of the other affections of 
the parts which are found to occur not for any final end but of 
necessity and on account of the motive or efficient cause. 



2204 



Aristotle - Metaphysics 
[Translated by W. D. Ross] 



Book A 



All men by nature desire to know. An indication of this is the 
delight we take in our senses; for even apart from their 
usefulness they are loved for themselves; and above all others 
the sense of sight. For not only with a view to action, but even 
when we are not going to do anything, we prefer seeing (one 
might say) to everything else. The reason is that this, most of all 
the senses, makes us know and brings to light many differences 
between things. 

By nature animals are born with the faculty of sensation, and 
from sensation memory is produced in some of them, though 
not in others. And therefore the former are more intelligent and 
apt at learning than those which cannot remember; those 
which are incapable of hearing sounds are intelligent though 
they cannot be taught, e.g. the bee, and any other race of 
animals that may be like it; and those which besides memory 
have this sense of hearing can be taught. 

The animals other than man live by appearances and 
memories, and have but little of connected experience; but the 
human race lives also by art and reasonings. Now from memory 
experience is produced in men; for the several memories of the 
same thing produce finally the capacity for a single experience. 
And experience seems pretty much like science and art, but 



2205 



really science and art come to men through experience; for 
'experience made art', as Polus says, 'but inexperience luck.' 
Now art arises when from many notions gained by experience 
one universal judgement about a class of objects is produced. 
For to have a judgement that when Callias was ill of this disease 
this did him good, and similarly in the case of Socrates and in 
many individual cases, is a matter of experience; but to judge 
that it has done good to all persons of a certain constitution, 
marked off in one class, when they were ill of this disease, e.g. 
to phlegmatic or bilious people when burning with fevers - this 
is a matter of art. 

With a view to action experience seems in no respect inferior to 
art, and men of experience succeed even better than those who 
have theory without experience. (The reason is that experience 
is knowledge of individuals, art of universals, and actions and 
productions are all concerned with the individual; for the 
physician does not cure man, except in an incidental way, but 
Callias or Socrates or some other called by some such individual 
name, who happens to be a man. If, then, a man has the theory 
without the experience, and recognizes the universal but does 
not know the individual included in this, he will often fail to 
cure; for it is the individual that is to be cured.) But yet we think 
that knowledge and understanding belong to art rather than to 
experience, and we suppose artists to be wiser than men of 
experience (which implies that Wisdom depends in all cases 
rather on knowledge); and this because the former know the 
cause, but the latter do not. For men of experience know that 
the thing is so, but do not know why, while the others know the 
'why' and the cause. Hence we think also that the 
masterworkers in each craft are more honourable and know in a 
truer sense and are wiser than the manual workers, because 
they know the causes of the things that are done (we think the 
manual workers are like certain lifeless things which act 
indeed, but act without knowing what they do, as fire burns, - 



2206 



but while the lifeless things perform each of their functions by a 
natural tendency, the labourers perform them through habit); 
thus we view them as being wiser not in virtue of being able to 
act, but of having the theory for themselves and knowing the 
causes. And in general it is a sign of the man who knows and of 
the man who does not know, that the former can teach, and 
therefore we think art more truly knowledge than experience is; 
for artists can teach, and men of mere experience cannot. 

Again, we do not regard any of the senses as Wisdom; yet surely 
these give the most authoritative knowledge of particulars. But 
they do not tell us the 'why' of anything - e.g. why fire is hot; 
they only say that it is hot. 

At first he who invented any art whatever that went beyond the 
common perceptions of man was naturally admired by men, 
not only because there was something useful in the inventions, 
but because he was thought wise and superior to the rest. But 
as more arts were invented, and some were directed to the 
necessities of life, others to recreation, the inventors of the 
latter were naturally always regarded as wiser than the 
inventors of the former, because their branches of knowledge 
did not aim at utility. Hence when all such inventions were 
already established, the sciences which do not aim at giving 
pleasure or at the necessities of life were discovered, and first in 
the places where men first began to have leisure. This is why 
the mathematical arts were founded in Egypt; for there the 
priestly caste was allowed to be at leisure. 

We have said in the Ethics what the difference is between art 
and science and the other kindred faculties; but the point of our 
present discussion is this, that all men suppose what is called 
Wisdom to deal with the first causes and the principles of 
things; so that, as has been said before, the man of experience is 
thought to be wiser than the possessors of any sense- 



2207 



perception whatever, the artist wiser than the men of 
experience, the masterworker than the mechanic, and the 
theoretical kinds of knowledge to be more of the nature of 
Wisdom than the productive. Clearly then Wisdom is knowledge 
about certain principles and causes. 



Since we are seeking this knowledge, we must inquire of what 
kind are the causes and the principles, the knowledge of which 
is Wisdom. If one were to take the notions we have about the 
wise man, this might perhaps make the answer more evident. 
We suppose first, then, that the wise man knows all things, as 
far as possible, although he has not knowledge of each of them 
in detail; secondly, that he who can learn things that are 
difficult, and not easy for man to know, is wise (sense- 
perception is common to all, and therefore easy and no mark of 
Wisdom); again, that he who is more exact and more capable of 
teaching the causes is wiser, in every branch of knowledge; and 
that of the sciences, also, that which is desirable on its own 
account and for the sake of knowing it is more of the nature of 
Wisdom than that which is desirable on account of its results, 
and the superior science is more of the nature of Wisdom than 
the ancillary; for the wise man must not be ordered but must 
order, and he must not obey another, but the less wise must 
obey him. 

Such and so many are the notions, then, which we have about 
Wisdom and the wise. Now of these characteristics that of 
knowing all things must belong to him who has in the highest 
degree universal knowledge; for he knows in a sense all the 
instances that fall under the universal. And these things, the 



2208 



most universal, are on the whole the hardest for men to know; 
for they are farthest from the senses. And the most exact of the 
sciences are those which deal most with first principles; for 
those which involve fewer principles are more exact than those 
which involve additional principles, e.g. arithmetic than 
geometry. But the science which investigates causes is also 
instructive, in a higher degree, for the people who instruct us 
are those who tell the causes of each thing. And understanding 
and knowledge pursued for their own sake are found most in 
the knowledge of that which is most knowable (for he who 
chooses to know for the sake of knowing will choose most 
readily that which is most truly knowledge, and such is the 
knowledge of that which is most knowable); and the first 
principles and the causes are most knowable; for by reason of 
these, and from these, all other things come to be known, and 
not these by means of the things subordinate to them. And the 
science which knows to what end each thing must be done is 
the most authoritative of the sciences, and more authoritative 
than any ancillary science; and this end is the good of that 
thing, and in general the supreme good in the whole of nature. 
Judged by all the tests we have mentioned, then, the name in 
question falls to the same science; this must be a science that 
investigates the first principles and causes; for the good, i.e. the 
end, is one of the causes. 

That it is not a science of production is clear even from the 
history of the earliest philosophers. For it is owing to their 
wonder that men both now begin and at first began to 
philosophize; they wondered originally at the obvious 
difficulties, then advanced little by little and stated difficulties 
about the greater matters, e.g. about the phenomena of the 
moon and those of the sun and of the stars, and about the 
genesis of the universe. And a man who is puzzled and wonders 
thinks himself ignorant (whence even the lover of myth is in a 
sense a lover of Wisdom, for the myth is composed of wonders); 



2209 



therefore since they philosophized order to escape from 
ignorance, evidently they were pursuing science in order to 
know, and not for any utilitarian end. And this is confirmed by 
the facts; for it was when almost all the necessities of life and 
the things that make for comfort and recreation had been 
secured, that such knowledge began to be sought. Evidently 
then we do not seek it for the sake of any other advantage; but 
as the man is free, we say, who exists for his own sake and not 
for another's, so we pursue this as the only free science, for it 
alone exists for its own sake. 

Hence also the possession of it might be justly regarded as 
beyond human power; for in many ways human nature is in 
bondage, so that according to Simonides 'God alone can have 
this privilege', and it is unfitting that man should not be content 
to seek the knowledge that is suited to him. If, then, there is 
something in what the poets say, and jealousy is natural to the 
divine power, it would probably occur in this case above all, and 
all who excelled in this knowledge would be unfortunate. But 
the divine power cannot be jealous (nay, according to the 
proverb, 'bards tell a lie'), nor should any other science be 
thought more honourable than one of this sort. For the most 
divine science is also most honourable; and this science alone 
must be, in two ways, most divine. For the science which it 
would be most meet for God to have is a divine science, and so 
is any science that deals with divine objects; and this science 
alone has both these qualities; for (1) God is thought to be 
among the causes of all things and to be a first principle, and (2) 
such a science either God alone can have, or God above all 
others. All the sciences, indeed, are more necessary than this, 
but none is better. 

Yet the acquisition of it must in a sense end in something 
which is the opposite of our original inquiries. For all men begin, 
as we said, by wondering that things are as they are, as they do 



2210 



about self-moving marionettes, or about the solstices or the 
incommensurability of the diagonal of a square with the side; 
for it seems wonderful to all who have not yet seen the reason, 
that there is a thing which cannot be measured even by the 
smallest unit. But we must end in the contrary and, according to 
the proverb, the better state, as is the case in these instances 
too when men learn the cause; for there is nothing which would 
surprise a geometer so much as if the diagonal turned out to be 
commensurable. 

We have stated, then, what is the nature of the science we are 
searching for, and what is the mark which our search and our 
whole investigation must reach. 



Evidently we have to acquire knowledge of the original causes 
(for we say we know each thing only when we think we 
recognize its first cause), and causes are spoken of in four 
senses. In one of these we mean the substance, i.e. the essence 
(for the 'why' is reducible finally to the definition, and the 
ultimate 'why' is a cause and principle); in another the matter 
or substratum, in a third the source of the change, and in a 
fourth the cause opposed to this, the purpose and the good (for 
this is the end of all generation and change). We have studied 
these causes sufficiently in our work on nature, but yet let us 
call to our aid those who have attacked the investigation of 
being and philosophized about reality before us. For obviously 
they too speak of certain principles and causes; to go over their 
views, then, will be of profit to the present inquiry, for we shall 
either find another kind of cause, or be more convinced of the 
correctness of those which we now maintain. 



2211 



Of the first philosophers, then, most thought the principles 
which were of the nature of matter were the only principles of 
all things. That of which all things that are consist, the first 
from which they come to be, the last into which they are 
resolved (the substance remaining, but changing in its 
modifications), this they say is the element and this the 
principle of things, and therefore they think nothing is either 
generated or destroyed, since this sort of entity is always 
conserved, as we say Socrates neither comes to be absolutely 
when he comes to be beautiful or musical, nor ceases to be 
when loses these characteristics, because the substratum, 
Socrates himself remains, just so they say nothing else comes to 
be or ceases to be; for there must be some entity - either one or 
more than one - from which all other things come to be, it being 
conserved. 

Yet they do not all agree as to the number and the nature of 
these principles. Thales, the founder of this type of philosophy, 
says the principle is water (for which reason he declared that 
the earth rests on water), getting the notion perhaps from 
seeing that the nutriment of all things is moist, and that heat 
itself is generated from the moist and kept alive by it (and that 
from which they come to be is a principle of all things). He got 
his notion from this fact, and from the fact that the seeds of all 
things have a moist nature, and that water is the origin of the 
nature of moist things. 

Some think that even the ancients who lived long before the 
present generation, and first framed accounts of the gods, had a 
similar view of nature; for they made Ocean and Tethys the 
parents of creation, and described the oath of the gods as being 
by water, to which they give the name of Styx; for what is oldest 
is most honourable, and the most honourable thing is that by 
which one swears. It may perhaps be uncertain whether this 
opinion about nature is primitive and ancient, but Thales at any 



2212 



rate is said to have declared himself thus about the first cause. 
Hippo no one would think fit to include among these thinkers, 
because of the paltriness of his thought. 

Anaximenes and Diogenes make air prior to water, and the 
most primary of the simple bodies, while Hippasus of 
Metapontium and Heraclitus of Ephesus say this of fire, and 
Empedocles says it of the four elements (adding a fourth-earth 
to those which have been named); for these, he says, always 
remain and do not come to be, except that they come to be 
more or fewer, being aggregated into one and segregated out of 
one. 

Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, who, though older than 
Empedocles, was later in his philosophical activity, says the 
principles are infinite in number; for he says almost all the 
things that are made of parts like themselves, in the manner of 
water or fire, are generated and destroyed in this way, only by 
aggregation and segregation, and are not in any other sense 
generated or destroyed, but remain eternally. 

From these facts one might think that the only cause is the so- 
called material cause; but as men thus advanced, the very facts 
opened the way for them and joined in forcing them to 
investigate the subject. However true it may be that all 
generation and destruction proceed from some one or (for that 
matter) from more elements, why does this happen and what is 
the cause? For at least the substratum itself does not make 
itself change; e.g. neither the wood nor the bronze causes the 
change of either of them, nor does the wood manufacture a bed 
and the bronze a statue, but something else is the cause of the 
change. And to seek this is to seek the second cause, as we 
should say, - that from which comes the beginning of the 
movement. Now those who at the very beginning set 
themselves to this kind of inquiry, and said the substratum was 



2213 



one, were not at all dissatisfied with themselves; but some at 
least of those who maintain it to be one - as though defeated by 
this search for the second cause - say the one and nature as a 
whole is unchangeable not only in respect of generation and 
destruction (for this is a primitive belief, and all agreed in it), but 
also of all other change; and this view is peculiar to them. Of 
those who said the universe was one, then none succeeded in 
discovering a cause of this sort, except perhaps Parmenides, and 
he only inasmuch as he supposes that there is not only one but 
also in some sense two causes. But for those who make more 
elements it is more possible to state the second cause, e.g. for 
those who make hot and cold, or fire and earth, the elements; 
for they treat fire as having a nature which fits it to move 
things, and water and earth and such things they treat in the 
contrary way. 

When these men and the principles of this kind had had their 
day, as the latter were found inadequate to generate the nature 
of things men were again forced by the truth itself, as we said, 
to inquire into the next kind of cause. For it is not likely either 
that fire or earth or any such element should be the reason why 
things manifest goodness and, beauty both in their being and in 
their coming to be, or that those thinkers should have supposed 
it was; nor again could it be right to entrust so great a matter to 
spontaneity and chance. When one man said, then, that reason 
was present - as in animals, so throughout nature - as the 
cause of order and of all arrangement, he seemed like a sober 
man in contrast with the random talk of his predecessors. We 
know that Anaxagoras certainly adopted these views, but 
Hermotimus of Clazomenae is credited with expressing them 
earlier. Those who thought thus stated that there is a principle 
of things which is at the same time the cause of beauty, and 
that sort of cause from which things acquire movement. 



2214 



One might suspect that Hesiod was the first to look for such a 
thing - or some one else who put love or desire among existing 
things as a principle, as Parmenides, too, does; for he, in 
constructing the genesis of the universe, says: - 

Love first of all the Gods she planned. 

And Hesiod says: - 

First of all things was chaos made, and then 

Broad-breasted earth... 

And love, mid all the gods pre-eminent, 

which implies that among existing things there must be from 
the first a cause which will move things and bring them 
together. How these thinkers should be arranged with regard to 
priority of discovery let us be allowed to decide later; but since 
the contraries of the various forms of good were also perceived 
to be present in nature - not only order and the beautiful, but 
also disorder and the ugly, and bad things in greater number 
than good, and ignoble things than beautiful - therefore another 
thinker introduced friendship and strife, each of the two the 
cause of one of these two sets of qualities. For if we were to 
follow out the view of Empedocles, and interpret it according to 
its meaning and not to its lisping expression, we should find 
that friendship is the cause of good things, and strife of bad. 
Therefore, if we said that Empedocles in a sense both mentions, 
and is the first to mention, the bad and the good as principles, 
we should perhaps be right, since the cause of all goods is the 
good itself. 



2215 



These thinkers, as we say, evidently grasped, and to this extent, 
two of the causes which we distinguished in our work on nature 
- the matter and the source of the movement - vaguely, 
however, and with no clearness, but as untrained men behave 
in fights; for they go round their opponents and often strike fine 
blows, but they do not fight on scientific principles, and so too 
these thinkers do not seem to know what they say; for it is 
evident that, as a rule, they make no use of their causes except 
to a small extent. For Anaxagoras uses reason as a deus ex 
machina for the making of the world, and when he is at a loss 
to tell from what cause something necessarily is, then he drags 
reason in, but in all other cases ascribes events to anything 
rather than to reason. And Empedocles, though he uses the 
causes to a greater extent than this, neither does so sufficiently 
nor attains consistency in their use. At least, in many cases he 
makes love segregate things, and strife aggregate them. For 
whenever the universe is dissolved into its elements by strife, 
fire is aggregated into one, and so is each of the other elements; 
but whenever again under the influence of love they come 
together into one, the parts must again be segregated out of 
each element. 

Empedocles, then, in contrast with his precessors, was the first 
to introduce the dividing of this cause, not positing one source 
of movement, but different and contrary sources. Again, he was 
the first to speak of four material elements; yet he does not use 
four, but treats them as two only; he treats fire by itself, and its 
opposite - earth, air, and water - as one kind of thing. We may 
learn this by study of his verses. 

This philosopher then, as we say, has spoken of the principles in 
this way, and made them of this number. Leucippus and his 
associate Democritus say that the full and the empty are the 
elements, calling the one being and the other non-being - the 
full and solid being being, the empty non-being (whence they 



2216 



say being no more is than non-being, because the solid no more 
is than the empty); and they make these the material causes of 
things. And as those who make the underlying substance one 
generate all other things by its modifications, supposing the 
rare and the dense to be the sources of the modifications, in the 
same way these philosophers say the differences in the 
elements are the causes of all other qualities. These differences, 
they say, are three-shape and order and position. For they say 
the real is differentiated only by 'rhythm and 'inter-contact' and 
'turning'; and of these rhythm is shape, inter-contact is order, 
and turning is position; for A differs from N in shape, AN from 
NA in order, M from W in position. The question of movement - 
whence or how it is to belong to things - these thinkers, like the 
others, lazily neglected. 

Regarding the two causes, then, as we say, the inquiry seems to 
have been pushed thus far by the early philosophers. 



Contemporaneously with these philosophers and before them, 
the so-called Pythagoreans, who were the first to take up 
mathematics, not only advanced this study, but also having 
been brought up in it they thought its principles were the 
principles of all things. Since of these principles numbers are by 
nature the first, and in numbers they seemed to see many 
resemblances to the things that exist and come into being - 
more than in fire and earth and water (such and such a 
modification of numbers being justice, another being soul and 
reason, another being opportunity - and similarly almost all 
other things being numerically expressible); since, again, they 
saw that the modifications and the ratios of the musical scales 



2217 



were expressible in numbers; - since, then, all other things 
seemed in their whole nature to be modelled on numbers, and 
numbers seemed to be the first things in the whole of nature, 
they supposed the elements of numbers to be the elements of 
all things, and the whole heaven to be a musical scale and a 
number. And all the properties of numbers and scales which 
they could show to agree with the attributes and parts and the 
whole arrangement of the heavens, they collected and fitted 
into their scheme; and if there was a gap anywhere, they readily 
made additions so as to make their whole theory coherent. E.g. 
as the number 10 is thought to be perfect and to comprise the 
whole nature of numbers, they say that the bodies which move 
through the heavens are ten, but as the visible bodies are only 
nine, to meet this they invent a tenth - the 'counter-earth'. We 
have discussed these matters more exactly elsewhere. 

But the object of our review is that we may learn from these 
philosophers also what they suppose to be the principles and 
how these fall under the causes we have named. Evidently, 
then, these thinkers also consider that number is the principle 
both as matter for things and as forming both their 
modifications and their permanent states, and hold that the 
elements of number are the even and the odd, and that of these 
the latter is limited, and the former unlimited; and that the One 
proceeds from both of these (for it is both even and odd), and 
number from the One; and that the whole heaven, as has been 
said, is numbers. 

Other members of this same school say there are ten principles, 
which they arrange in two columns of cognates - limit and 
unlimited, odd and even, one and plurality, right and left, male 
and female, resting and moving, straight and curved, light and 
darkness, good and bad, square and oblong. In this way 
Alcmaeon of Croton seems also to have conceived the matter, 
and either he got this view from them or they got it from him; 



2218 



for he expressed himself similarly to them. For he says most 
human affairs go in pairs, meaning not definite contrarieties 
such as the Pythagoreans speak of, but any chance contrarieties, 
e.g. white and black, sweet and bitter, good and bad, great and 
small. He threw out indefinite suggestions about the other 
contrarieties, but the Pythagoreans declared both how many 
and which their contrarieties are. 

From both these schools, then, we can learn this much, that the 
contraries are the principles of things; and how many these 
principles are and which they are, we can learn from one of the 
two schools. But how these principles can be brought together 
under the causes we have named has not been clearly and 
articulately stated by them; they seem, however, to range the 
elements under the head of matter; for out of these as 
immanent parts they say substance is composed and moulded. 

From these facts we may sufficiently perceive the meaning of 
the ancients who said the elements of nature were more than 
one; but there are some who spoke of the universe as if it were 
one entity, though they were not all alike either in the 
excellence of their statement or in its conformity to the facts of 
nature. The discussion of them is in no way appropriate to our 
present investigation of causes, for. they do not, like some of the 
natural philosophers, assume being to be one and yet generate 
it out of the one as out of matter, but they speak in another way; 
those others add change, since they generate the universe, but 
these thinkers say the universe is unchangeable. Yet this much 
is germane to the present inquiry: Parmenides seems to fasten 
on that which is one in definition, Melissus on that which is one 
in matter, for which reason the former says that it is limited, the 
latter that it is unlimited; while Xenophanes, the first of these 
partisans of the One (for Parmenides is said to have been his 
pupil), gave no clear statement, nor does he seem to have 
grasped the nature of either of these causes, but with reference 



2219 



to the whole material universe he says the One is God. Now 
these thinkers, as we said, must be neglected for the purposes 
of the present inquiry - two of them entirely, as being a little too 
naive, viz. Xenophanes and Melissus; but Parmenides seems in 
places to speak with more insight. For, claiming that, besides 
the existent, nothing non-existent exists, he thinks that of 
necessity one thing exists, viz. the existent and nothing else (on 
this we have spoken more clearly in our work on nature), but 
being forced to follow the observed facts, and supposing the 
existence of that which is one in definition, but more than one 
according to our sensations, he now posits two causes and two 
principles, calling them hot and cold, i.e. fire and earth; and of 
these he ranges the hot with the existent, and the other with 
the non-existent. 

From what has been said, then, and from the wise men who 
have now sat in council with us, we have got thus much - on 
the one hand from the earliest philosophers, who regard the 
first principle as corporeal (for water and fire and such things 
are bodies), and of whom some suppose that there is one 
corporeal principle, others that there are more than one, but 
both put these under the head of matter; and on the other hand 
from some who posit both this cause and besides this the 
source of movement, which we have got from some as single 
and from others as twofold. 

Down to the Italian school, then, and apart from it, philosophers 
have treated these subjects rather obscurely, except that, as we 
said, they have in fact used two kinds of cause, and one of these 
- the source of movement - some treat as one and others as 
two. But the Pythagoreans have said in the same way that there 
are two principles, but added this much, which is peculiar to 
them, that they thought that finitude and infinity were not 
attributes of certain other things, e.g. of fire or earth or anything 
else of this kind, but that infinity itself and unity itself were the 



2220 



substance of the things of which they are predicated. This is 
why number was the substance of all things. On this subject, 
then, they expressed themselves thus; and regarding the 
question of essence they began to make statements and 
definitions, but treated the matter too simply. For they both 
defined superficially and thought that the first subject of which 
a given definition was predicable was the substance of the thing 
defined, as if one supposed that 'double' and '2' were the same, 
because 2 is the first thing of which 'double' is predicable. But 
surely to be double and to be 2 are not the same; if they are, one 
thing will be many - a consequence which they actually drew. 
From the earlier philosophers, then, and from their successors 
we can learn thus much. 



After the systems we have named came the philosophy of Plato, 
which in most respects followed these thinkers, but had 
peculiarities that distinguished it from the philosophy of the 
Italians. For, having in his youth first become familiar with 
Cratylus and with the Heraclitean doctrines (that all sensible 
things are ever in a state of flux and there is no knowledge 
about them), these views he held even in later years. Socrates, 
however, was busying himself about ethical matters and 
neglecting the world of nature as a whole but seeking the 
universal in these ethical matters, and fixed thought for the 
first time on definitions; Plato accepted his teaching, but held 
that the problem applied not to sensible things but to entities of 
another kind - for this reason, that the common definition 
could not be a definition of any sensible thing, as they were 
always changing. Things of this other sort, then, he called Ideas, 
and sensible things, he said, were all named after these, and in 



2221 



virtue of a relation to these; for the many existed by 
participation in the Ideas that have the same name as they. 
Only the name 'participation' was new; for the Pythagoreans 
say that things exist by 'imitation' of numbers, and Plato says 
they exist by participation, changing the name. But what the 
participation or the imitation of the Forms could be they left an 
open question. 

Further, besides sensible things and Forms he says there are the 
objects of mathematics, which occupy an intermediate position, 
differing from sensible things in being eternal and 
unchangeable, from Forms in that there are many alike, while 
the Form itself is in each case unique. 

Since the Forms were the causes of all other things, he thought 
their elements were the elements of all things. As matter, the 
great and the small were principles; as essential reality, the One; 
for from the great and the small, by participation in the One, 
come the Numbers. 

But he agreed with the Pythagoreans in saying that the One is 
substance and not a predicate of something else; and in saying 
that the Numbers are the causes of the reality of other things he 
agreed with them; but positing a dyad and constructing the 
infinite out of great and small, instead of treating the infinite as 
one, is peculiar to him; and so is his view that the Numbers 
exist apart from sensible things, while they say that the things 
themselves are Numbers, and do not place the objects of 
mathematics between Forms and sensible things. His 
divergence from the Pythagoreans in making the One and the 
Numbers separate from things, and his introduction of the 
Forms, were due to his inquiries in the region of definitions (for 
the earlier thinkers had no tincture of dialectic), and his making 
the other entity besides the One a dyad was due to the belief 
that the numbers, except those which were prime, could be 



2222 



neatly produced out of the dyad as out of some plastic material. 
Yet what happens is the contrary; the theory is not a reasonable 
one. For they make many things out of the matter, and the form 
generates only once, but what we observe is that one table is 
made from one matter, while the man who applies the form, 
though he is one, makes many tables. And the relation of the 
male to the female is similar; for the latter is impregnated by 
one copulation, but the male impregnates many females; yet 
these are analogues of those first principles. 

Plato, then, declared himself thus on the points in question; it is 
evident from what has been said that he has used only two 
causes, that of the essence and the material cause (for the 
Forms are the causes of the essence of all other things, and the 
One is the cause of the essence of the Forms); and it is evident 
what the underlying matter is, of which the Forms are 
predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in the 
case of Forms, viz. that this is a dyad, the great and the small. 
Further, he has assigned the cause of good and that of evil to 
the elements, one to each of the two, as we say some of his 
predecessors sought to do, e.g. Empedocles and Anaxagoras. 



Our review of those who have spoken about first principles and 
reality and of the way in which they have spoken, has been 
concise and summary; but yet we have learnt this much from 
them, that of those who speak about 'principle' and 'cause' no 
one has mentioned any principle except those which have been 
distinguished in our work on nature, but all evidently have 
some inkling of them, though only vaguely. For some speak of 
the first principle as matter, whether they suppose one or more 



2223 



first principles, and whether they suppose this to be a body or 
to be incorporeal; e.g. Plato spoke of the great and the small, the 
Italians of the infinite, Empedocles of fire, earth, water, and air, 
Anaxagoras of the infinity of things composed of similar parts. 
These, then, have all had a notion of this kind of cause, and so 
have all who speak of air or fire or water, or something denser 
than fire and rarer than air; for some have said the prime 
element is of this kind. 

These thinkers grasped this cause only; but certain others have 
mentioned the source of movement, e.g. those who make 
friendship and strife, or reason, or love, a principle. 

The essence, i.e. the substantial reality, no one has expressed 
distinctly. It is hinted at chiefly by those who believe in the 
Forms; for they do not suppose either that the Forms are the 
matter of sensible things, and the One the matter of the Forms, 
or that they are the source of movement (for they say these are 
causes rather of immobility and of being at rest), but they 
furnish the Forms as the essence of every other thing, and the 
One as the essence of the Forms. 

That for whose sake actions and changes and movements take 
place, they assert to be a cause in a way, but not in this way, i.e. 
not in the way in which it is its nature to be a cause. For those 
who speak of reason or friendship class these causes as goods; 
they do not speak, however, as if anything that exists either 
existed or came into being for the sake of these, but as if 
movements started from these. In the same way those who say 
the One or the existent is the good, say that it is the cause of 
substance, but not that substance either is or comes to be for 
the sake of this. Therefore it turns out that in a sense they both 
say and do not say the good is a cause; for they do not call it a 
cause qua good but only incidentally. 



2224 



All these thinkers then, as they cannot pitch on another cause, 
seem to testify that we have determined rightly both how many 
and of what sort the causes are. Besides this it is plain that 
when the causes are being looked for, either all four must be 
sought thus or they must be sought in one of these four ways. 
Let us next discuss the possible difficulties with regard to the 
way in which each of these thinkers has spoken, and with 
regard to his situation relatively to the first principles. 



8 

Those, then, who say the universe is one and posit one kind of 
thing as matter, and as corporeal matter which has spatial 
magnitude, evidently go astray in many ways. For they posit the 
elements of bodies only, not of incorporeal things, though there 
are also incorporeal things. And in trying to state the causes of 
generation and destruction, and in giving a physical account of 
all things, they do away with the cause of movement. Further, 
they err in not positing the substance, i.e. the essence, as the 
cause of anything, and besides this in lightly calling any of the 
simple bodies except earth the first principle, without inquiring 
how they are produced out of one anothers - I mean fire, water, 
earth, and air. For some things are produced out of each other 
by combination, others by separation, and this makes the 
greatest difference to their priority and posteriority. For (1) in a 
way the property of being most elementary of all would seem to 
belong to the first thing from which they are produced by 
combination, and this property would belong to the most fine- 
grained and subtle of bodies. For this reason those who make 
fire the principle would be most in agreement with this 
argument. But each of the other thinkers agrees that the 
element of corporeal things is of this sort. At least none of those 



2225 



who named one element claimed that earth was the element, 
evidently because of the coarseness of its grain. (Of the other 
three elements each has found some judge on its side; for some 
maintain that fire, others that water, others that air is the 
element. Yet why, after all, do they not name earth also, as most 
men do? For people say all things are earth Hesiod says earth 
was produced first of corporeal things; so primitive and popular 
has the opinion been.) According to this argument, then, no one 
would be right who either says the first principle is any of the 
elements other than fire, or supposes it to be denser than air 
but rarer than water. But (2) if that which is later in generation 
is prior in nature, and that which is concocted and compounded 
is later in generation, the contrary of what we have been saying 
must be true, - water must be prior to air, and earth to water. 

So much, then, for those who posit one cause such as we 
mentioned; but the same is true if one supposes more of these, 
as Empedocles says matter of things is four bodies. For he too is 
confronted by consequences some of which are the same as 
have been mentioned, while others are peculiar to him. For we 
see these bodies produced from one another, which implies that 
the same body does not always remain fire or earth (we have 
spoken about this in our works on nature); and regarding the 
cause of movement and the question whether we must posit 
one or two, he must be thought to have spoken neither correctly 
nor altogether plausibly. And in general, change of quality is 
necessarily done away with for those who speak thus, for on 
their view cold will not come from hot nor hot from cold. For if 
it did there would be something that accepted the contraries 
themselves, and there would be some one entity that became 
fire and water, which Empedocles denies. 

As regards Anaxagoras, if one were to suppose that he said 
there were two elements, the supposition would accord 
thoroughly with an argument which Anaxagoras himself did 



2226 



not state articulately, but which he must have accepted if any- 
one had led him on to it. True, to say that in the beginning all 
things were mixed is absurd both on other grounds and because 
it follows that they must have existed before in an unmixed 
form, and because nature does not allow any chance thing to be 
mixed with any chance thing, and also because on this view 
modifications and accidents could be separated from 
substances (for the same things which are mixed can be 
separated); yet if one were to follow him up, piecing together 
what he means, he would perhaps be seen to be somewhat 
modern in his views. For when nothing was separated out, 
evidently nothing could be truly asserted of the substance that 
then existed. I mean, e.g. that it was neither white nor black, 
nor grey nor any other colour, but of necessity colourless; for if 
it had been coloured, it would have had one of these colours. 
And similarly, by this same argument, it was flavourless, nor 
had it any similar attribute; for it could not be either of any 
quality or of any size, nor could it be any definite kind of thing. 
For if it were, one of the particular forms would have belonged 
to it, and this is impossible, since all were mixed together; for 
the particular form would necessarily have been already 
separated out, but he all were mixed except reason, and this 
alone was unmixed and pure. From this it follows, then, that he 
must say the principles are the One (for this is simple and 
unmixed) and the Other, which is of such a nature as we 
suppose the indefinite to be before it is defined and partakes of 
some form. Therefore, while expressing himself neither rightly 
nor clearly, he means something like what the later thinkers say 
and what is now more clearly seen to be the case. 

But these thinkers are, after all, at home only in arguments 
about generation and destruction and movement; for it is 
practically only of this sort of substance that they seek the 
principles and the causes. But those who extend their vision to 
all things that exist, and of existing things suppose some to be 



2227 



perceptible and others not perceptible, evidently study both 
classes, which is all the more reason why one should devote 
some time to seeing what is good in their views and what bad 
from the standpoint of the inquiry we have now before us. 

The 'Pythagoreans' treat of principles and elements stranger 
than those of the physical philosophers (the reason is that they 
got the principles from non-sensible things, for the objects of 
mathematics, except those of astronomy, are of the class of 
things without movement); yet their discussions and 
investigations are all about nature; for they generate the 
heavens, and with regard to their parts and attributes and 
functions they observe the phenomena, and use up the 
principles and the causes in explaining these, which implies 
that they agree with the others, the physical philosophers, that 
the real is just all that which is perceptible and contained by the 
so-called 'heavens'. But the causes and the principles which 
they mention are, as we said, sufficient to act as steps even up 
to the higher realms of reality, and are more suited to these 
than to theories about nature. They do not tell us at all, however, 
how there can be movement if limit and unlimited and odd and 
even are the only things assumed, or how without movement 
and change there can be generation and destruction, or the 
bodies that move through the heavens can do what they do. 

Further, if one either granted them that spatial magnitude 
consists of these elements, or this were proved, still how would 
some bodies be light and others have weight? To judge from 
what they assume and maintain they are speaking no more of 
mathematical bodies than of perceptible; hence they have said 
nothing whatever about fire or earth or the other bodies of this 
sort, I suppose because they have nothing to say which applies 
peculiarly to perceptible things. 



2228 



Further, how are we to combine the beliefs that the attributes of 
number, and number itself, are causes of what exists and 
happens in the heavens both from the beginning and now, and 
that there is no other number than this number out of which 
the world is composed? When in one particular region they 
place opinion and opportunity, and, a little above or below, 
injustice and decision or mixture, and allege, as proof, that each 
of these is a number, and that there happens to be already in 
this place a plurality of the extended bodies composed of 
numbers, because these attributes of number attach to the 
various places, - this being so, is this number, which we must 
suppose each of these abstractions to be, the same number 
which is exhibited in the material universe, or is it another than 
this? Plato says it is different; yet even he thinks that both these 
bodies and their causes are numbers, but that the intelligible 
numbers are causes, while the others are sensible. 



Let us leave the Pythagoreans for the present; for it is enough to 
have touched on them as much as we have done. But as for 
those who posit the Ideas as causes, firstly, in seeking to grasp 
the causes of the things around us, they introduced others 
equal in number to these, as if a man who wanted to count 
things thought he would not be able to do it while they were 
few, but tried to count them when he had added to their 
number. For the Forms are practically equal to - or not fewer 
than - the things, in trying to explain which these thinkers 
proceeded from them to the Forms. For to each thing there 
answers an entity which has the same name and exists apart 
from the substances, and so also in the case of all other groups 



2229 



there is a one over many, whether the many are in this world or 
are eternal. 

Further, of the ways in which we prove that the Forms exist, 
none is convincing; for from some no inference necessarily 
follows, and from some arise Forms even of things of which we 
think there are no Forms. For according to the arguments from 
the existence of the sciences there will be Forms of all things of 
which there are sciences and according to the 'one over many' 
argument there will be Forms even of negations, and according 
to the argument that there is an object for thought even when 
the thing has perished, there will be Forms of perishable things; 
for we have an image of these. Further, of the more accurate 
arguments, some lead to Ideas of relations, of which we say 
there is no independent class, and others introduce the 'third 
man'. 

And in general the arguments for the Forms destroy the things 
for whose existence we are more zealous than for the existence 
of the Ideas; for it follows that not the dyad but number is first, 
i.e. that the relative is prior to the absolute, - besides all the 
other points on which certain people by following out the 
opinions held about the Ideas have come into conflict with the 
principles of the theory. 

Further, according to the assumption on which our belief in the 
Ideas rests, there will be Forms not only of substances but also 
of many other things (for the concept is single not only in the 
case of substances but also in the other cases, and there are 
sciences not only of substance but also of other things, and a 
thousand other such difficulties confront them). But according 
to the necessities of the case and the opinions held about the 
Forms, if Forms can be shared in there must be Ideas of 
substances only. For they are not shared in incidentally, but a 
thing must share in its Form as in something not predicated of 



2230 



a subject (by 'being shared in incidentally' I mean that e.g. if a 
thing shares in 'double itself, it shares also in 'eternal', but 
incidentally; for 'eternal' happens to be predicable of the 
'double'). Therefore the Forms will be substance; but the same 
terms indicate substance in this and in the ideal world (or what 
will be the meaning of saying that there is something apart 
from the particulars - the one over many?). And if the Ideas and 
the particulars that share in them have the same form, there 
will be something common to these; for why should '2' be one 
and the same in the perishable 2's or in those which are many 
but eternal, and not the same in the '2' itself as in the 
particular 2? But if they have not the same form, they must 
have only the name in common, and it is as if one were to call 
both Callias and a wooden image a 'man', without observing 
any community between them. 

Above all one might discuss the question what on earth the 
Forms contribute to sensible things, either to those that are 
eternal or to those that come into being and cease to be. For 
they cause neither movement nor any change in them. But 
again they help in no wise either towards the knowledge of the 
other things (for they are not even the substance of these, else 
they would have been in them), or towards their being, if they 
are not in the particulars which share in them; though if they 
were, they might be thought to be causes, as white causes 
whiteness in a white object by entering into its composition. But 
this argument, which first Anaxagoras and later Eudoxus and 
certain others used, is very easily upset; for it is not difficult to 
collect many insuperable objections to such a view. 

But, further, all other things cannot come from the Forms in any 
of the usual senses of 'from'. And to say that they are patterns 
and the other things share in them is to use empty words and 
poetical metaphors. For what is it that works, looking to the 
Ideas? And anything can either be, or become, like another 



2231 



without being copied from it, so that whether Socrates or not a 
man Socrates like might come to be; and evidently this might be 
so even if Socrates were eternal. And there will be several 
patterns of the same thing, and therefore several Forms; e.g. 
'animal' and 'two-footed' and also 'man himself will be Forms 
of man. Again, the Forms are patterns not only sensible things, 
but of Forms themselves also; i.e. the genus, as genus of various 
species, will be so; therefore the same thing will be pattern and 
copy. 

Again, it would seem impossible that the substance and that of 
which it is the substance should exist apart; how, therefore, 
could the Ideas, being the substances of things, exist apart? In 
the Phaedo' the case is stated in this way - that the Forms are 
causes both of being and of becoming; yet when the Forms 
exist, still the things that share in them do not come into being, 
unless there is something to originate movement; and many 
other things come into being (e.g. a house or a ring) of which we 
say there are no Forms. Clearly, therefore, even the other things 
can both be and come into being owing to such causes as 
produce the things just mentioned. 

Again, if the Forms are numbers, how can they be causes? Is it 
because existing things are other numbers, e.g. one number is 
man, another is Socrates, another Callias? Why then are the one 
set of numbers causes of the other set? It will not make any 
difference even if the former are eternal and the latter are not. 
But if it is because things in this sensible world (e.g. harmony) 
are ratios of numbers, evidently the things between which they 
are ratios are some one class of things. If, then, this - the matter 
- is some definite thing, evidently the numbers themselves too 
will be ratios of something to something else. E.g. if Callias is a 
numerical ratio between fire and earth and water and air, his 
Idea also will be a number of certain other underlying things; 
and man himself, whether it is a number in a sense or not, will 



2232 



still be a numerical ratio of certain things and not a number 
proper, nor will it be a of number merely because it is a 
numerical ratio. 

Again, from many numbers one number is produced, but how 
can one Form come from many Forms? And if the number 
comes not from the many numbers themselves but from the 
units in them, e.g. in 10,000, how is it with the units? If they are 
specifically alike, numerous absurdities will follow, and also if 
they are not alike (neither the units in one number being 
themselves like one another nor those in other numbers being 
all like to all); for in what will they differ, as they are without 
quality? This is not a plausible view, nor is it consistent with our 
thought on the matter. 

Further, they must set up a second kind of number (with which 
arithmetic deals), and all the objects which are called 
'intermediate' by some thinkers; and how do these exist or from 
what principles do they proceed? Or why must they be 
intermediate between the things in this sensible world and the 
things-themselves? 

Further, the units in must each come from a prior but this is 
impossible. 

Further, why is a number, when taken all together, one? 

Again, besides what has been said, if the units are diverse the 
Platonists should have spoken like those who say there are four, 
or two, elements; for each of these thinkers gives the name of 
element not to that which is common, e.g. to body, but to fire 
and earth, whether there is something common to them, viz. 
body, or not. But in fact the Platonists speak as if the One were 
homogeneous like fire or water; and if this is so, the numbers 
will not be substances. Evidently, if there is a One itself and this 



2233 



is a first principle, 'one' is being used in more than one sense; 
for otherwise the theory is impossible. 

When we wish to reduce substances to their principles, we state 
that lines come from the short and long (i.e. from a kind of 
small and great), and the plane from the broad and narrow, and 
body from the deep and shallow. Yet how then can either the 
plane contain a line, or the solid a line or a plane? For the broad 
and narrow is a different class from the deep and shallow. 
Therefore, just as number is not present in these, because the 
many and few are different from these, evidently no other of the 
higher classes will be present in the lower. But again the broad 
is not a genus which includes the deep, for then the solid would 
have been a species of plane. Further, from what principle will 
the presence of the points in the line be derived? Plato even 
used to object to this class of things as being a geometrical 
fiction. He gave the name of principle of the line - and this he 
often posited - to the indivisible lines. Yet these must have a 
limit; therefore the argument from which the existence of the 
line follows proves also the existence of the point. 

In general, though philosophy seeks the cause of perceptible 
things, we have given this up (for we say nothing of the cause 
from which change takes its start), but while we fancy we are 
stating the substance of perceptible things, we assert the 
existence of a second class of substances, while our account of 
the way in which they are the substances of perceptible things 
is empty talk; for 'sharing', as we said before, means nothing. 

Nor have the Forms any connexion with what we see to be the 
cause in the case of the arts, that for whose sake both all mind 
and the whole of nature are operative, - with this cause which 
we assert to be one of the first principles; but mathematics has 
come to be identical with philosophy for modern thinkers, 
though they say that it should be studied for the sake of other 



2234 



things. Further, one might suppose that the substance which 
according to them underlies as matter is too mathematical, and 
is a predicate and differentia of the substance, ie. of the matter, 
rather than matter itself; i.e. the great and the small are like the 
rare and the dense which the physical philosophers speak of, 
calling these the primary differentiae of the substratum; for 
these are a kind of excess and defect. And regarding movement, 
if the great and the small are to he movement, evidently the 
Forms will be moved; but if they are not to be movement, 
whence did movement come? The whole study of nature has 
been annihilated. 

And what is thought to be easy - to show that all things are one 
- is not done; for what is proved by the method of setting out 
instances is not that all things are one but that there is a One 
itself, - if we grant all the assumptions. And not even this 
follows, if we do not grant that the universal is a genus; and this 
in some cases it cannot be. 

Nor can it be explained either how the lines and planes and 
solids that come after the numbers exist or can exist, or what 
significance they have; for these can neither be Forms (for they 
are not numbers), nor the intermediates (for those are the 
objects of mathematics), nor the perishable things. This is 
evidently a distinct fourth class. 

In general, if we search for the elements of existing things 
without distinguishing the many senses in which things are 
said to exist, we cannot find them, especially if the search for 
the elements of which things are made is conducted in this 
manner. For it is surely impossible to discover what 'acting' or 
'being acted on', or 'the straight', is made of, but if elements can 
be discovered at all, it is only the elements of substances; 
therefore either to seek the elements of all existing things or to 
think one has them is incorrect. 



2235 



And how could we learn the elements of all things? Evidently 
we cannot start by knowing anything before. For as he who is 
learning geometry, though he may know other things before, 
knows none of the things with which the science deals and 
about which he is to learn, so is it in all other cases. Therefore if 
there is a science of all things, such as some assert to exist, he 
who is learning this will know nothing before. Yet all learning is 
by means of premisses which are (either all or some of them) 
known before, - whether the learning be by demonstration or by 
definitions; for the elements of the definition must be known 
before and be familiar; and learning by induction proceeds 
similarly. But again, if the science were actually innate, it were 
strange that we are unaware of our possession of the greatest of 
sciences. 

Again, how is one to come to know what all things are made of, 
and how is this to be made evident? This also affords a 
difficulty; for there might be a conflict of opinion, as there is 
about certain syllables; some say za is made out of s and d and 
a, while others say it is a distinct sound and none of those that 
are familiar. 

Further, how could we know the objects of sense without having 
the sense in question? Yet we ought to, if the elements of which 
all things consist, as complex sounds consist of the elements 
proper to sound, are the same. 



10 

It is evident, then, even from what we have said before, that all 
men seem to seek the causes named in the Physics, and that we 
cannot name any beyond these; but they seek these vaguely; 
and though in a sense they have all been described before, in a 



2236 



sense they have not been described at all. For the earliest 
philosophy is, on all subjects, like one who lisps, since it is 
young and in its beginnings. For even Empedocles says bone 
exists by virtue of the ratio in it. Now this is the essence and the 
substance of the thing. But it is similarly necessary that flesh 
and each of the other tissues should be the ratio of its elements, 
or that not one of them should; for it is on account of this that 
both flesh and bone and everything else will exist, and not on 
account of the matter, which he names, - fire and earth and 
water and air. But while he would necessarily have agreed if 
another had said this, he has not said it clearly. 

On these questions our views have been expressed before; but 
let us return to enumerate the difficulties that might be raised 
on these same points; for perhaps we may get from them some 
help towards our later difficulties. 



Book a 



The investigation of the truth is in one way hard, in another 
easy. An indication of this is found in the fact that no one is able 
to attain the truth adequately, while, on the other hand, we do 
not collectively fail, but every one says something true about 
the nature of things, and while individually we contribute little 
or nothing to the truth, by the union of all a considerable 
amount is amassed. Therefore, since the truth seems to be like 



2237 



the proverbial door, which no one can fail to hit, in this respect 
it must be easy, but the fact that we can have a whole truth and 
not the particular part we aim at shows the difficulty of it. 

Perhaps, too, as difficulties are of two kinds, the cause of the 
present difficulty is not in the facts but in us. For as the eyes of 
bats are to the blaze of day, so is the reason in our soul to the 
things which are by nature most evident of all. 

It is just that we should be grateful, not only to those with 
whose views we may agree, but also to those who have 
expressed more superficial views; for these also contributed 
something, by developing before us the powers of thought. It is 
true that if there had been no Timotheus we should have been 
without much of our lyric poetry; but if there had been no 
Phrynis there would have been no Timotheus. The same holds 
good of those who have expressed views about the truth; for 
from some thinkers we have inherited certain opinions, while 
the others have been responsible for the appearance of the 
former. 

It is right also that philosophy should be called knowledge of 
the truth. For the end of theoretical knowledge is truth, while 
that of practical knowledge is action (for even if they consider 
how things are, practical men do not study the eternal, but what 
is relative and in the present). Now we do not know a truth 
without its cause; and a thing has a quality in a higher degree 
than other things if in virtue of it the similar quality belongs to 
the other things as well (e.g. fire is the hottest of things; for it is 
the cause of the heat of all other things); so that that causes 
derivative truths to be true is most true. Hence the principles of 
eternal things must be always most true (for they are not 
merely sometimes true, nor is there any cause of their being, 
but they themselves are the cause of the being of other things), 



2238 



so that as each thing is in respect of being, so is it in respect of 
truth. 



But evidently there is a first principle, and the causes of things 
are neither an infinite series nor infinitely various in kind. For 
neither can one thing proceed from another, as from matter, ad 
infinitum (e.g. flesh from earth, earth from air, air from fire, and 
so on without stopping), nor can the sources of movement form 
an endless series (man for instance being acted on by air, air by 
the sun, the sun by Strife, and so on without limit). Similarly the 
final causes cannot go on ad infinitum, - walking being for the 
sake of health, this for the sake of happiness, happiness for the 
sake of something else, and so one thing always for the sake of 
another. And the case of the essence is similar. For in the case of 
intermediates, which have a last term and a term prior to them, 
the prior must be the cause of the later terms. For if we had to 
say which of the three is the cause, we should say the first; 
surely not the last, for the final term is the cause of none; nor 
even the intermediate, for it is the cause only of one. (It makes 
no difference whether there is one intermediate or more, nor 
whether they are infinite or finite in number.) But of series 
which are infinite in this way, and of the infinite in general, all 
the parts down to that now present are alike intermediates; so 
that if there is no first there is no cause at all. 

Nor can there be an infinite process downwards, with a 
beginning in the upward direction, so that water should proceed 
from fire, earth from water, and so always some other kind 
should be produced. For one thing comes from another in two 
ways - not in the sense in which 'from' means 'after' (as we say 



2239 



'from the Isthmian games come the Olympian'), but either (i) as 
the man comes from the boy, by the boy's changing, or (ii) as air 
comes from water. By 'as the man comes from the boy' we 
mean 'as that which has come to be from that which is coming 
to be' or 'as that which is finished from that which is being 
achieved' (for as becoming is between being and not being, so 
that which is becoming is always between that which is and 
that which is not; for the learner is a man of science in the 
making, and this is what is meant when we say that from a 
learner a man of science is being made); on the other hand, 
coming from another thing as water comes from air implies the 
destruction of the other thing. This is why changes of the 
former kind are not reversible, and the boy does not come from 
the man (for it is not that which comes to be something that 
comes to be as a result of coming to be, but that which exists 
after the coming to be; for it is thus that the day, too, comes 
from the morning - in the sense that it comes after the 
morning; which is the reason why the morning cannot come 
from the day); but changes of the other kind are reversible. But 
in both cases it is impossible that the number of terms should 
be infinite. For terms of the former kind, being intermediates, 
must have an end, and terms of the latter kind change back into 
one another, for the destruction of either is the generation of 
the other. 

At the same time it is impossible that the first cause, being 
eternal, should be destroyed; for since the process of becoming 
is not infinite in the upward direction, that which is the first 
thing by whose destruction something came to be must be non- 
eternal. 

Further, the final cause is an end, and that sort of end which is 
not for the sake of something else, but for whose sake 
everything else is; so that if there is to be a last term of this sort, 
the process will not be infinite; but if there is no such term, 



2240 



there will be no final cause, but those who maintain the infinite 
series eliminate the Good without knowing it (yet no one would 
try to do anything if he were not going to come to a limit); nor 
would there be reason in the world; the reasonable man, at 
least, always acts for a purpose, and this is a limit; for the end is 
a limit. 

But the essence, also, cannot be reduced to another definition 
which is fuller in expression. For the original definition is 
always more of a definition, and not the later one; and in a 
series in which the first term has not the required character, the 
next has not it either. Further, those who speak thus destroy 
science; for it is not possible to have this till one comes to the 
unanalysable terms. And knowledge becomes impossible; for 
how can one apprehend things that are infinite in this way? For 
this is not like the case of the line, to whose divisibility there is 
no stop, but which we cannot think if we do not make a stop 
(for which reason one who is tracing the infinitely divisible line 
cannot be counting the possibilities of section), but the whole 
line also must be apprehended by something in us that does not 
move from part to part. - Again, nothing infinite can exist; and 
if it could, at least the notion of infinity is not infinite. 

But if the kinds of causes had been infinite in number, then also 
knowledge would have been impossible; for we think we know, 
only when we have ascertained the causes, that but that which 
is infinite by addition cannot be gone through in a finite time. 



The effect which lectures produce on a hearer depends on his 
habits; for we demand the language we are accustomed to, and 
that which is different from this seems not in keeping but 



2241 



somewhat unintelligible and foreign because of its 
unwontedness. For it is the customary that is intelligible. The 
force of habit is shown by the laws, in which the legendary and 
childish elements prevail over our knowledge about them, 
owing to habit. Thus some people do not listen to a speaker 
unless he speaks mathematically, others unless he gives 
instances, while others expect him to cite a poet as witness. 
And some want to have everything done accurately, while 
others are annoyed by accuracy, either because they cannot 
follow the connexion of thought or because they regard it as 
pettifoggery. For accuracy has something of this character, so 
that as in trade so in argument some people think it mean. 
Hence one must be already trained to know how to take each 
sort of argument, since it is absurd to seek at the same time 
knowledge and the way of attaining knowledge; and it is not 
easy to get even one of the two. 

The minute accuracy of mathematics is not to be demanded in 
all cases, but only in the case of things which have no matter. 
Hence method is not that of natural science; for presumably the 
whole of nature has matter. Hence we must inquire first what 
nature is: for thus we shall also see what natural science treats 
of (and whether it belongs to one science or to more to 
investigate the causes and the principles of things). 



2242 



BookB 



We must, with a view to the science which we are seeking, first 
recount the subjects that should be first discussed. These 
include both the other opinions that some have held on the first 
principles, and any point besides these that happens to have 
been overlooked. For those who wish to get clear of difficulties 
it is advantageous to discuss the difficulties well; for the 
subsequent free play of thought implies the solution of the 
previous difficulties, and it is not possible to untie a knot of 
which one does not know. But the difficulty of our thinking 
points to a 'knot' in the object; for in so far as our thought is in 
difficulties, it is in like case with those who are bound; for in 
either case it is impossible to go forward. Hence one should 
have surveyed all the difficulties beforehand, both for the 
purposes we have stated and because people who inquire 
without first stating the difficulties are like those who do not 
know where they have to go; besides, a man does not otherwise 
know even whether he has at any given time found what he is 
looking for or not; for the end is not clear to such a man, while 
to him who has first discussed the difficulties it is clear. Further, 
he who has heard all the contending arguments, as if they were 
the parties to a case, must be in a better position forjudging. 

The first problem concerns the subject which we discussed in 
our prefatory remarks. It is this - (1) whether the investigation 
of the causes belongs to one or to more sciences, and (2) 
whether such a science should survey only the first principles 
of substance, or also the principles on which all men base their 
proofs, e.g. whether it is possible at the same time to assert and 



2243 



deny one and the same thing or not, and all other such 
questions; and (3) if the science in question deals with 
substance, whether one science deals with all substances, or 
more than one, and if more, whether all are akin, or some of 
them must be called forms of Wisdom and the others 
something else. And (4) this itself is also one of the things that 
must be discussed - whether sensible substances alone should 
be said to exist or others also besides them, and whether these 
others are of one kind or there are several classes of substances, 
as is supposed by those who believe both in Forms and in 
mathematical objects intermediate between these and sensible 
things. Into these questions, then, as we say, we must inquire, 
and also (5) whether our investigation is concerned only with 
substances or also with the essential attributes of substances. 
Further, with regard to the same and other and like and unlike 
and contrariety, and with regard to prior and posterior and all 
other such terms about which the dialecticians try to inquire, 
starting their investigation from probable premises only, - 
whose business is it to inquire into all these? Further, we must 
discuss the essential attributes of these themselves; and we 
must ask not only what each of these is, but also whether one 
thing always has one contrary. Again (6), are the principles and 
elements of things the genera, or the parts present in each 
thing, into which it is divided; and (7) if they are the genera, are 
they the genera that are predicated proximately of the 
individuals, or the highest genera, e.g. is animal or man the first 
principle and the more independent of the individual instance? 
And (8) we must inquire and discuss especially whether there is, 
besides the matter, any thing that is a cause in itself or not, and 
whether this can exist apart or not, and whether it is one or 
more in number, and whether there is something apart from 
the concrete thing (by the concrete thing I mean the matter 
with something already predicated of it), or there is nothing 
apart, or there is something in some cases though not in others, 



2244 



and what sort of cases these are. Again (9) we ask whether the 
principles are limited in number or in kind, both those in the 
definitions and those in the substratum; and (10) whether the 
principles of perishable and of imperishable things are the same 
or different; and whether they are all imperishable or those of 
perishable things are perishable. Further (11) there is the 
question which is hardest of all and most perplexing, whether 
unity and being, as the Pythagoreans and Plato said, are not 
attributes of something else but the substance of existing 
things, or this is not the case, but the substratum is something 
else, - as Empedocles says, love; as some one else says, fire; 
while another says water or air. Again (12) we ask whether the 
principles are universal or like individual things, and (13) 
whether they exist potentially or actually, and further, whether 
they are potential or actual in any other sense than in reference 
to movement; for these questions also would present much 
difficulty. Further (14), are numbers and lines and figures and 
points a kind of substance or not, and if they are substances are 
they separate from sensible things or present in them? With 
regard to all these matters not only is it hard to get possession 
of the truth, but it is not easy even to think out the difficulties 
well. 



(1) First then with regard to what we mentioned first, does it 
belong to one or to more sciences to investigate all the kinds of 
causes? How could it belong to one science to recognize the 
principles if these are not contrary? 

Further, there are many things to which not all the principles 
pertain. For how can a principle of change or the nature of the 



2245 



good exist for unchangeable things, since everything that in 
itself and by its own nature is good is an end, and a cause in the 
sense that for its sake the other things both come to be and are, 
and since an end or purpose is the end of some action, and all 
actions imply change? So in the case of unchangeable things 
this principle could not exist, nor could there be a good itself. 
This is why in mathematics nothing is proved by means of this 
kind of cause, nor is there any demonstration of this kind - 
'because it is better, or worse'; indeed no one even mentions 
anything of the kind. And so for this reason some of the 
Sophists, e.g. Aristippus, used to ridicule mathematics; for in 
the arts (he maintained), even in the industrial arts, e.g. in 
carpentry and cobbling, the reason always given is 'because it is 
better, or worse,' but the mathematical sciences take no account 
of goods and evils. 

But if there are several sciences of the causes, and a different 
science for each different principle, which of these sciences 
should be said to be that which we seek, or which of the people 
who possess them has the most scientific knowledge of the 
object in question? The same thing may have all the kinds of 
causes, e.g. the moving cause of a house is the art or the builder, 
the final cause is the function it fulfils, the matter is earth and 
stones, and the form is the definition. To judge from our 
previous discussion of the question which of the sciences 
should be called Wisdom, there is reason for applying the name 
to each of them. For inasmuch as it is most architectonic and 
authoritative and the other sciences, like slavewomen, may not 
even contradict it, the science of the end and of the good is of 
the nature of Wisdom (for the other things are for the sake of 
the end). But inasmuch as it was described' as dealing with the 
first causes and that which is in the highest sense object of 
knowledge, the science of substance must be of the nature of 
Wisdom. For since men may know the same thing in many 
ways, we say that he who recognizes what a thing is by its being 



2246 



so and so knows more fully than he who recognizes it by its not 
being so and so, and in the former class itself one knows more 
fully than another, and he knows most fully who knows what a 
thing is, not he who knows its quantity or quality or what it can 
by nature do or have done to it. And further in all cases also we 
think that the knowledge of each even of the things of which 
demonstration is possible is present only when we know what 
the thing is, e.g. what squaring a rectangle is, viz. that it is the 
finding of a mean; and similarly in all other cases. And we know 
about becomings and actions and about every change when we 
know the source of the movement; and this is other than and 
opposed to the end. Therefore it would seem to belong to 
different sciences to investigate these causes severally. 

But (2), taking the starting-points of demonstration as well as 
the causes, it is a disputable question whether they are the 
object of one science or of more (by the starting-points of 
demonstration I mean the common beliefs, on which all men 
base their proofs); e.g. that everything must be either affirmed 
or denied, and that a thing cannot at the same time be and not 
be, and all other such premisses: - the question is whether the 
same science deals with them as with substance, or a different 
science, and if it is not one science, which of the two must be 
identified with that which we now seek. - It is not reasonable 
that these topics should be the object of one science; for why 
should it be peculiarly appropriate to geometry or to any other 
science to understand these matters? If then it belongs to every 
science alike, and cannot belong to all, it is not peculiar to the 
science which investigates substances, any more than to any 
other science, to know about these topics. - And, at the same 
time, in what way can there be a science of the first principles? 
For we are aware even now what each of them in fact is (at least 
even other sciences use them as familiar); but if there is a 
demonstrative science which deals with them, there will have 
to be an underlying kind, and some of them must be 



2247 



demonstrable attributes and others must be axioms (for it is 
impossible that there should be demonstration about all of 
them); for the demonstration must start from certain premisses 
and be about a certain subject and prove certain attributes. 
Therefore it follows that all attributes that are proved must 
belong to a single class; for all demonstrative sciences use the 
axioms. 

But if the science of substance and the science which deals with 
the axioms are different, which of them is by nature more 
authoritative and prior? The axioms are most universal and are 
principles of all things. And if it is not the business of the 
philosopher, to whom else will it belong to inquire what is true 
and what is untrue about them? 

(3) In general, do all substances fall under one science or under 
more than one? If the latter, to what sort of substance is the 
present science to be assigned? - On the other hand, it is not 
reasonable that one science should deal with all. For then there 
would be one demonstrative science dealing with all attributes. 
For ever demonstrative science investigates with regard to some 
subject its essential attributes, starting from the common 
beliefs. Therefore to investigate the essential attributes of one 
class of things, starting from one set of beliefs, is the business 
of one science. For the subject belongs to one science, and the 
premisses belong to one, whether to the same or to another; so 
that the attributes do so too, whether they are investigated by 
these sciences or by one compounded out of them. 

(5) Further, does our investigation deal with substances alone or 
also with their attributes? I mean for instance, if the solid is a 
substance and so are lines and planes, is it the business of the 
same science to know these and to know the attributes of each 
of these classes (the attributes about which the mathematical 
sciences offer proofs), or of a different science? If of the same, 



2248 



the science of substance also must be a demonstrative science, 
but it is thought that there is no demonstration of the essence 
of things. And if of another, what will be the science that 
investigates the attributes of substance? This is a very difficult 
question. 

(4) Further, must we say that sensible substances alone exist, or 
that there are others besides these? And are substances of one 
kind or are there in fact several kinds of substances, as those 
say who assert the existence both of the Forms and of the 
intermediates, with which they say the mathematical sciences 
deal? - The sense in which we say the Forms are both causes 
and self-dependent substances has been explained in our first 
remarks about them; while the theory presents difficulties in 
many ways, the most paradoxical thing of all is the statement 
that there are certain things besides those in the material 
universe, and that these are the same as sensible things except 
that they are eternal while the latter are perishable. For they say 
there is a man-himself and a horse-itself and health-itself, with 
no further qualification, - a procedure like that of the people 
who said there are gods, but in human form. For they were 
positing nothing but eternal men, nor are the Platonists making 
the Forms anything other than eternal sensible things. 

Further, if we are to posit besides the Forms and the sensibles 
the intermediates between them, we shall have many 
difficulties. For clearly on the same principle there will be lines 
besides the lines-themselves and the sensible lines, and so with 
each of the other classes of things; so that since astronomy is 
one of these mathematical sciences there will also be a heaven 
besides the sensible heaven, and a sun and a moon (and so with 
the other heavenly bodies) besides the sensible. Yet how are we 
to believe in these things? It is not reasonable even to suppose 
such a body immovable, but to suppose it moving is quite 
impossible. - And similarly with the things of which optics and 



2249 



mathematical harmonics treat; for these also cannot exist apart 
from the sensible things, for the same reasons. For if there are 
sensible things and sensations intermediate between Form and 
individual, evidently there will also be animals intermediate 
between animals-themselves and the perishable animals. - We 
might also raise the question, with reference to which kind of 
existing things we must look for these sciences of 
intermediates. If geometry is to differ from mensuration only in 
this, that the latter deals with things that we perceive, and the 
former with things that are not perceptible, evidently there will 
also be a science other than medicine, intermediate between 
medical-science-itself and this individual medical science, and 
so with each of the other sciences. Yet how is this possible? 
There would have to be also healthy things besides the 
perceptible healthy things and the healthy-itself. - And at the 
same time not even this is true, that mensuration deals with 
perceptible and perishable magnitudes; for then it would have 
perished when they perished. 

But on the other hand astronomy cannot be dealing with 
perceptible magnitudes nor with this heaven above us. For 
neither are perceptible lines such lines as the geometer speaks 
of (for no perceptible thing is straight or round in the way in 
which he defines 'straight' and 'round'; for a hoop touches a 
straight edge not at a point, but as Protagoras used to say it did, 
in his refutation of the geometers), nor are the movements and 
spiral orbits in the heavens like those of which astronomy 
treats, nor have geometrical points the same nature as the 
actual stars. - Now there are some who say that these so-called 
intermediates between the Forms and the perceptible things 
exist, not apart from the perceptible things, however, but in 
these; the impossible results of this view would take too long to 
enumerate, but it is enough to consider even such points as the 
following: - It is not reasonable that this should be so only in 
the case of these intermediates, but clearly the Forms also 



2250 



might be in the perceptible things; for both statements are parts 
of the same theory. Further, it follows from this theory that 
there are two solids in the same place, and that the 
intermediates are not immovable, since they are in the moving 
perceptible things. And in general to what purpose would one 
suppose them to exist indeed, but to exist in perceptible things? 
For the same paradoxical results will follow which we have 
already mentioned; there will be a heaven besides the heaven, 
only it will be not apart but in the same place; which is still 
more impossible. 



(6) Apart from the great difficulty of stating the case truly with 
regard to these matters, it is very hard to say, with regard to the 
first principles, whether it is the genera that should be taken as 
elements and principles, or rather the primary constituents of a 
thing; e.g. it is the primary parts of which articulate sounds 
consist that are thought to be elements and principles of 
articulate sound, not the common genus-articulate sound; and 
we give the name of 'elements' to those geometrical 
propositions, the proofs of which are implied in the proofs of 
the others, either of all or of most. Further, both those who say 
there are several elements of corporeal things and those who 
say there is one, say the parts of which bodies are compounded 
and consist are principles; e.g. Empedocles says fire and water 
and the rest are the constituent elements of things, but does 
not describe these as genera of existing things. Besides this, if 
we want to examine the nature of anything else, we examine 
the parts of which, e.g. a bed consists and how they are put 
together, and then we know its nature. 



2251 



To judge from these arguments, then, the principles of things 
would not be the genera; but if we know each thing by its 
definition, and the genera are the principles or starting-points 
of definitions, the genera must also be the principles of 
definable things. And if to get the knowledge of the species 
according to which things are named is to get the knowledge of 
things, the genera are at least starting-points of the species. 
And some also of those who say unity or being, or the great and 
the small, are elements of things, seem to treat them as genera. 

But, again, it is not possible to describe the principles in both 
ways. For the formula of the essence is one; but definition by 
genera will be different from that which states the constituent 
parts of a thing. 

(7) Besides this, even if the genera are in the highest degree 
principles, should one regard the first of the genera as 
principles, or those which are predicated directly of the 
individuals? This also admits of dispute. For if the universals are 
always more of the nature of principles, evidently the 
uppermost of the genera are the principles; for these are 
predicated of all things. There will, then, be as many principles 
of things as there are primary genera, so that both being and 
unity will be principles and substances; for these are most of all 
predicated of all existing things. But it is not possible that either 
unity or being should be a single genus of things; for the 
differentiae of any genus must each of them both have being 
and be one, but it is not possible for the genus taken apart from 
its species (any more than for the species of the genus) to be 
predicated of its proper differentiae; so that if unity or being is a 
genus, no differentia will either have being or be one. But if 
unity and being are not genera, neither will they be principles, if 
the genera are the principles. Again, the intermediate kinds, in 
whose nature the differentiae are included, will on this theory 
be genera, down to the indivisible species; but as it is, some are 



2252 



thought to be genera and others are not thought to be so. 
Besides this, the differentiae are principles even more than the 
genera; and if these also are principles, there comes to be 
practically an infinite number of principles, especially if we 
suppose the highest genus to be a principle. - But again, if unity 
is more of the nature of a principle, and the indivisible is one, 
and everything indivisible is so either in quantity or in species, 
and that which is so in species is the prior, and genera are 
divisible into species for man is not the genus of individual 
men), that which is predicated directly of the individuals will 
have more unity. - Further, in the case of things in which the 
distinction of prior and posterior is present, that which is 
predicable of these things cannot be something apart from 
them (e.g. if two is the first of numbers, there will not be a 
Number apart from the kinds of numbers; and similarly there 
will not be a Figure apart from the kinds of figures; and if the 
genera of these things do not exist apart from the species, the 
genera of other things will scarcely do so; for genera of these 
things are thought to exist if any do). But among the individuals 
one is not prior and another posterior. Further, where one thing 
is better and another worse, the better is always prior; so that of 
these also no genus can exist. From these considerations, then, 
the species predicated of individuals seem to be principles 
rather than the genera. But again, it is not easy to say in what 
sense these are to be taken as principles. For the principle or 
cause must exist alongside of the things of which it is the 
principle, and must be capable of existing in separation from 
them; but for what reason should we suppose any such thing to 
exist alongside of the individual, except that it is predicated 
universally and of all? But if this is the reason, the things that 
are more universal must be supposed to be more of the nature 
of principles; so that the highest genera would be the principles. 



2253 



(8) There is a difficulty connected with these, the hardest of all 
and the most necessary to examine, and of this the discussion 
now awaits us. If, on the one hand, there is nothing apart from 
individual things, and the individuals are infinite in number, 
how then is it possible to get knowledge of the infinite 
individuals? For all things that we come to know, we come to 
know in so far as they have some unity and identity, and in so 
far as some attribute belongs to them universally. 

But if this is necessary, and there must be something apart from 
the individuals, it will be necessary that the genera exist apart 
from the individuals, either the lowest or the highest genera; 
but we found by discussion just now that this is impossible. 

Further, if we admit in the fullest sense that something exists 
apart from the concrete thing, whenever something is 
predicated of the matter, must there, if there is something 
apart, be something apart from each set of individuals, or from 
some and not from others, or from none? (A) If there is nothing 
apart from individuals, there will be no object of thought, but all 
things will be objects of sense, and there will not be knowledge 
of anything, unless we say that sensation is knowledge. Further, 
nothing will be eternal or unmovable; for all perceptible things 
perish and are in movement. But if there is nothing eternal, 
neither can there be a process of coming to be; for there must 
be something that comes to be, i.e. from which something 
comes to be, and the ultimate term in this series cannot have 
come to be, since the series has a limit and since nothing can 
come to be out of that which is not. Further, if generation and 
movement exist there must also be a limit; for no movement is 
infinite, but every movement has an end, and that which is 
incapable of completing its coming to be cannot be in process of 



2254 



coming to be; and that which has completed its coming to be 
must he as soon as it has come to be. Further, since the matter 
exists, because it is ungenerated, it is a fortiori reasonable that 
the substance or essence, that which the matter is at any time 
coming to be, should exist; for if neither essence nor matter is 
to be, nothing will be at all, and since this is impossible there 
must be something besides the concrete thing, viz. the shape or 
form. 

But again (B) if we are to suppose this, it is hard to say in which 
cases we are to suppose it and in which not. For evidently it is 
not possible to suppose it in all cases; we could not suppose 
that there is a house besides the particular houses. - Besides 
this, will the substance of all the individuals, e.g. of all men, be 
one? This is paradoxical, for all the things whose substance is 
one are one. But are the substances many and different? This 
also is unreasonable. - At the same time, how does the matter 
become each of the individuals, and how is the concrete thing 
these two elements? 

(9) Again, one might ask the following question also about the 
first principles. If they are one in kind only, nothing will be 
numerically one, not even unity-itself and being-itself; and how 
will knowing exist, if there is not to be something common to a 
whole set of individuals? 

But if there is a common element which is numerically one, and 
each of the principles is one, and the principles are not as in the 
case of perceptible things different for different things (e.g. 
since this particular syllable is the same in kind whenever it 
occurs, the elements it are also the same in kind; only in kind, 
for these also, like the syllable, are numerically different in 
different contexts), - if it is not like this but the principles of 
things are numerically one, there will be nothing else besides 
the elements (for there is no difference of meaning between 



2255 



'numerically one' and 'individual'; for this is just what we mean 
by the individual - the numerically one, and by the universal we 
mean that which is predicable of the individuals). Therefore it 
will be just as if the elements of articulate sound were limited 
in number; all the language in the world would be confined to 
the ABC, since there could not be two or more letters of the 
same kind. 

(10) One difficulty which is as great as any has been neglected 
both by modern philosophers and by their predecessors - 
whether the principles of perishable and those of imperishable 
things are the same or different. If they are the same, how are 
some things perishable and others imperishable, and for what 
reason? The school of Hesiod and all the theologians thought 
only of what was plausible to themselves, and had no regard to 
us. For, asserting the first principles to be gods and born of gods, 
they say that the beings which did not taste of nectar and 
ambrosia became mortal; and clearly they are using words 
which are familiar to themselves, yet what they have said about 
the very application of these causes is above our 
comprehension. For if the gods taste of nectar and ambrosia for 
their pleasure, these are in no wise the causes of their 
existence; and if they taste them to maintain their existence, 
how can gods who need food be eternal? - But into the 
subtleties of the mythologists it is not worth our while to 
inquire seriously; those, however, who use the language of proof 
we must cross-examine and ask why, after all, things which 
consist of the same elements are, some of them, eternal in 
nature, while others perish. Since these philosophers mention 
no cause, and it is unreasonable that things should be as they 
say, evidently the principles or causes of things cannot be the 
same. Even the man whom one might suppose to speak most 
consistently - Empedocles, even he has made the same mistake; 
for he maintains that strife is a principle that causes 
destruction, but even strife would seem no less to produce 



2256 



everything, except the One; for all things excepting God proceed 
from strife. At least he says: - 

From which all that was and is and will be hereafter - 

Trees, and men and women, took their growth, 

And beasts and birds and water-nourished fish, 

And long-aged gods. 

The implication is evident even apart from these words; for if 
strife had not been present in things, all things would have been 
one, according to him; for when they have come together, 'then 
strife stood outermost.' Hence it also follows on his theory that 
God most blessed is less wise than all others; for he does not 
know all the elements; for he has in him no strife, and 
knowledge is of the like by the like. 'For by earth,' he says, 

We see earth, by water water, 

By ether godlike ether, by fire wasting fire, 

Love by love, and strife by gloomy strife. 

But - and this is the point we started from this at least is 
evident, that on his theory it follows that strife is as much the 
cause of existence as of destruction. And similarly love is not 
specially the cause of existence; for in collecting things into the 
One it destroys all other things. And at the same time 
Empedocles mentions no cause of the change itself, except that 
things are so by nature. 

But when strife at last waxed great in the limbs of the Sphere, 

And sprang to assert its rights as the time was fulfilled 

Which is fixed for them in turn by a mighty oath. 



2257 



This implies that change was necessary; but he shows no cause 
of the necessity. But yet so far at least he alone speaks 
consistently; for he does not make some things perishable and 
others imperishable, but makes all perishable except the 
elements. The difficulty we are speaking of now is, why some 
things are perishable and others are not, if they consist of the 
same principles. 

Let this suffice as proof of the fact that the principles cannot be 
the same. But if there are different principles, one difficulty is 
whether these also will be imperishable or perishable. For if 
they are perishable, evidently these also must consist of certain 
elements (for all things that perish, perish by being resolved 
into the elements of which they consist); so that it follows that 
prior to the principles there are other principles. But this is 
impossible, whether the process has a limit or proceeds to 
infinity. Further, how will perishable things exist, if their 
principles are to be annulled? But if the principles are 
imperishable, why will things composed of some imperishable 
principles be perishable, while those composed of the others are 
imperishable? This is not probable, but is either impossible or 
needs much proof. Further, no one has even tried to maintain 
different principles; they maintain the same principles for all 
things. But they swallow the difficulty we stated first as if they 
took it to be something trifling. 

(11) The inquiry that is both the hardest of all and the most 
necessary for knowledge of the truth is whether being and unity 
are the substances of things, and whether each of them, 
without being anything else, is being or unity respectively, or we 
must inquire what being and unity are, with the implication 
that they have some other underlying nature. For some people 
think they are of the former, others think they are of the latter 
character. Plato and the Pythagoreans thought being and unity 
were nothing else, but this was their nature, their essence being 



2258 



just unity and being. But the natural philosophers take a 
different line; e.g. Empedocles - as though reducing to 
something more intelligible - says what unity is; for he would 
seem to say it is love: at least, this is for all things the cause of 
their being one. Others say this unity and being, of which things 
consist and have been made, is fire, and others say it is air. A 
similar view is expressed by those who make the elements 
more than one; for these also must say that unity and being are 
precisely all the things which they say are principles. 

(A) If we do not suppose unity and being to be substances, it 
follows that none of the other universals is a substance; for 
these are most universal of all, and if there is no unity-itself or 
being-itself, there will scarcely be in any other case anything 
apart from what are called the individuals. Further, if unity is 
not a substance, evidently number also will not exist as an 
entity separate from the individual things; for number is units, 
and the unit is precisely a certain kind of one. 

But (B) if there is a unity-itself and a being-itself, unity and 
being must be their substance; for it is not something else that 
is predicated universally of the things that are and are one, but 
just unity and being. But if there is to be a being-itself and a 
unity-itself, there is much difficulty in seeing how there will be 
anything else besides these, - I mean, how things will be more 
than one in number. For what is different from being does not 
exist, so that it necessarily follows, according to the argument of 
Parmenides, that all things that are are one and this is being. 

There are objections to both views. For whether unity is not a 
substance or there is a unity-itself, number cannot be a 
substance. We have already said why this result follows if unity 
is not a substance; and if it is, the same difficulty arises as arose 
with regard to being. For whence is there to be another one 



2259 



besides unity-itself? It must be not-one; but all things are either 
one or many, and of the many each is one. 

Further, if unity-itself is indivisible, according to Zeno's 
postulate it will be nothing. For that which neither when added 
makes a thing greater nor when subtracted makes it less, he 
asserts to have no being, evidently assuming that whatever has 
being is a spatial magnitude. And if it is a magnitude, it is 
corporeal; for the corporeal has being in every dimension, while 
the other objects of mathematics, e.g. a plane or a line, added in 
one way will increase what they are added to, but in another 
way will not do so, and a point or a unit does so in no way. But, 
since his theory is of a low order, and an indivisible thing can 
exist in such a way as to have a defence even against him (for 
the indivisible when added will make the number, though not 
the size, greater), - yet how can a magnitude proceed from one 
such indivisible or from many? It is like saying that the line is 
made out of points. 

But even if ore supposes the case to be such that, as some say, 
number proceeds from unity-itself and something else which is 
not one, none the less we must inquire why and how the 
product will be sometimes a number and sometimes a 
magnitude, if the not-one was inequality and was the same 
principle in either case. For it is not evident how magnitudes 
could proceed either from the one and this principle, or from 
some number and this principle. 



(14) A question connected with these is whether numbers and 
bodies and planes and points are substances of a kind, or not. If 
they are not, it baffles us to say what being is and what the 



2260 



substances of things are. For modifications and movements and 
relations and dispositions and ratios do not seem to indicate 
the substance of anything; for all are predicated of a subject, 
and none is a 'this'. And as to the things which might seem 
most of all to indicate substance, water and earth and fire and 
air, of which composite bodies consist, heat and cold and the 
like are modifications of these, not substances, and the body 
which is thus modified alone persists as something real and as 
a substance. But, on the other hand, the body is surely less of a 
substance than the surface, and the surface than the line, and 
the line than the unit and the point. For the body is bounded by 
these; and they are thought to be capable of existing without 
body, but body incapable of existing without these. This is why, 
while most of the philosophers and the earlier among them 
thought that substance and being were identical with body, and 
that all other things were modifications of this, so that the first 
principles of the bodies were the first principles of being, the 
more recent and those who were held to be wiser thought 
numbers were the first principles. As we said, then, if these are 
not substance, there is no substance and no being at all; for the 
accidents of these it cannot be right to call beings. 

But if this is admitted, that lines and points are substance more 
than bodies, but we do not see to what sort of bodies these 
could belong (for they cannot be in perceptible bodies), there 
can be no substance. - Further, these are all evidently divisions 
of body, - one in breadth, another in depth, another in length. 
Besides this, no sort of shape is present in the solid more than 
any other; so that if the Hermes is not in the stone, neither is 
the half of the cube in the cube as something determinate; 
therefore the surface is not in it either; for if any sort of surface 
were in it, the surface which marks off the half of the cube 
would be in it too. And the same account applies to the line and 
to the point and the unit. Therefore, if on the one hand body is 
in the highest degree substance, and on the other hand these 



2261 



things are so more than body, but these are not even instances 
of substance, it baffles us to say what being is and what the 
substance of things is. - For besides what has been said, the 
questions of generation and instruction confront us with 
further paradoxes. For if substance, not having existed before, 
now exists, or having existed before, afterwards does not exist, 
this change is thought to be accompanied by a process of 
becoming or perishing; but points and lines and surfaces cannot 
be in process either of becoming or of perishing, when they at 
one time exist and at another do not. For when bodies come 
into contact or are divided, their boundaries simultaneously 
become one in the one case when they touch, and two in the 
other - when they are divided; so that when they have been put 
together one boundary does not exist but has perished, and 
when they have been divided the boundaries exist which before 
did not exist (for it cannot be said that the point, which is 
indivisible, was divided into two). And if the boundaries come 
into being and cease to be, from what do they come into being? 
A similar account may also be given of the 'now' in time; for 
this also cannot be in process of coming into being or of ceasing 
to be, but yet seems to be always different, which shows that it 
is not a substance. And evidently the same is true of points and 
lines and planes; for the same argument applies, since they are 
all alike either limits or divisions. 



In general one might raise the question why after all, besides 
perceptible things and the intermediates, we have to look for 
another class of things, i.e. the Forms which we posit. If it is for 
this reason, because the objects of mathematics, while they 
differ from the things in this world in some other respect, differ 



2262 



not at all in that there are many of the same kind, so that their 
first principles cannot be limited in number (just as the 
elements of all the language in this sensible world are not 
limited in number, but in kind, unless one takes the elements of 
this individual syllable or of this individual articulate sound - 
whose elements will be limited even in number; so is it also in 
the case of the intermediates; for there also the members of the 
same kind are infinite in number), so that if there are not - 
besides perceptible and mathematical objects - others such as 
some maintain the Forms to be, there will be no substance 
which is one in number, but only in kind, nor will the first 
principles of things be determinate in number, but only in kind: 
- if then this must be so, the Forms also must therefore be held 
to exist. Even if those who support this view do not express it 
articulately, still this is what they mean, and they must be 
maintaining the Forms just because each of the Forms is a 
substance and none is by accident. 

But if we are to suppose both that the Forms exist and that the 
principles are one in number, not in kind, we have mentioned 
the impossible results that necessarily follow. 

(13) Closely connected with this is the question whether the 
elements exist potentially or in some other manner. If in some 
other way, there will be something else prior to the first 
principles; for the potency is prior to the actual cause, and it is 
not necessary for everything potential to be actual. - But if the 
elements exist potentially, it is possible that everything that is 
should not be. For even that which is not yet is capable of being; 
for that which is not comes to be, but nothing that is incapable 
of being comes to be. 

(12) We must not only raise these questions about the first 
principles, but also ask whether they are universal or what we 
call individuals. If they are universal, they will not be 



2263 



substances; for everything that is common indicates not a 'this' 
but a 'such', but substance is a 'this'. And if we are to be allowed 
to lay it down that a common predicate is a 'this' and a single 
thing, Socrates will be several animals - himself and 'man' and 
'animal', if each of these indicates a 'this' and a single thing. 

If, then, the principles are universals, these universal. Therefore 
if there is to be results follow; if they are not universals but of 
knowledge of the principles there must be the nature of 
individuals, they will not be other principles prior to them, 
namely those knowable; for the knowledge of anything is that 
are universally predicated of them. 



Bookr 



There is a science which investigates being as being and the 
attributes which belong to this in virtue of its own nature. Now 
this is not the same as any of the so-called special sciences; for 
none of these others treats universally of being as being. They 
cut off a part of being and investigate the attribute of this part; 
this is what the mathematical sciences for instance do. Now 
since we are seeking the first principles and the highest causes, 
clearly there must be some thing to which these belong in 
virtue of its own nature. If then those who sought the elements 
of existing things were seeking these same principles, it is 
necessary that the elements must be elements of being not by 



2264 



accident but just because it is being. Therefore it is of being as 
being that we also must grasp the first causes. 



There are many senses in which a thing may be said to 'be', but 
all that 'is' is related to one central point, one definite kind of 
thing, and is not said to 'be' by a mere ambiguity. Everything 
which is healthy is related to health, one thing in the sense that 
it preserves health, another in the sense that it produces it, 
another in the sense that it is a symptom of health, another 
because it is capable of it. And that which is medical is relative 
to the medical art, one thing being called medical because it 
possesses it, another because it is naturally adapted to it, 
another because it is a function of the medical art. And we shall 
find other words used similarly to these. So, too, there are many 
senses in which a thing is said to be, but all refer to one 
starting-point; some things are said to be because they are 
substances, others because they are affections of substance, 
others because they are a process towards substance, or 
destructions or privations or qualities of substance, or 
productive or generative of substance, or of things which are 
relative to substance, or negations of one of these thing of 
substance itself. It is for this reason that we say even of non- 
being that it is nonbeing. As, then, there is one science which 
deals with all healthy things, the same applies in the other 
cases also. For not only in the case of things which have one 
common notion does the investigation belong to one science, 
but also in the case of things which are related to one common 
nature; for even these in a sense have one common notion. It is 
clear then that it is the work of one science also to study the 
things that are, qua being. - But everywhere science deals 



2265 



chiefly with that which is primary, and on which the other 
things depend, and in virtue of which they get their names. If, 
then, this is substance, it will be of substances that the 
philosopher must grasp the principles and the causes. 

Now for each one class of things, as there is one perception, so 
there is one science, as for instance grammar, being one 
science, investigates all articulate sounds. Hence to investigate 
all the species of being qua being is the work of a science which 
is generically one, and to investigate the several species is the 
work of the specific parts of the science. 

If, now, being and unity are the same and are one thing in the 
sense that they are implied in one another as principle and 
cause are, not in the sense that they are explained by the same 
definition (though it makes no difference even if we suppose 
them to be like that - in fact this would even strengthen our 
case); for 'one man' and 'man' are the same thing, and so are 
'existent man' and 'man', and the doubling of the words in 'one 
man and one existent man' does not express anything different 
(it is clear that the two things are not separated either in 
coming to be or in ceasing to be); and similarly 'one existent 
man' adds nothing to 'existent man', and that it is obvious that 
the addition in these cases means the same thing, and unity is 
nothing apart from being; and if, further, the substance of each 
thing is one in no merely accidental way, and similarly is from 
its very nature something that is: - all this being so, there must 
be exactly as many species of being as of unity. And to 
investigate the essence of these is the work of a science which 
is generically one - I mean, for instance, the discussion of the 
same and the similar and the other concepts of this sort; and 
nearly all contraries may be referred to this origin; let us take 
them as having been investigated in the 'Selection of 
Contraries'. 



2266 



And there are as many parts of philosophy as there are kinds of 
substance, so that there must necessarily be among them a first 
philosophy and one which follows this. For being falls 
immediately into genera; for which reason the sciences too will 
correspond to these genera. For the philosopher is like the 
mathematician, as that word is used; for mathematics also has 
parts, and there is a first and a second science and other 
successive ones within the sphere of mathematics. 

Now since it is the work of one science to investigate opposites, 
and plurality is opposed to unity - and it belongs to one science 
to investigate the negation and the privation because in both 
cases we are really investigating the one thing of which the 
negation or the privation is a negation or privation (for we 
either say simply that that thing is not present, or that it is not 
present in some particular class; in the latter case difference is 
present over and above what is implied in negation; for 
negation means just the absence of the thing in question, while 
in privation there is also employed an underlying nature of 
which the privation is asserted): - in view of all these facts, the 
contraries of the concepts we named above, the other and the 
dissimilar and the unequal, and everything else which is 
derived either from these or from plurality and unity, must fall 
within the province of the science above named. And 
contrariety is one of these concepts; for contrariety is a kind of 
difference, and difference is a kind of otherness. Therefore, 
since there are many senses in which a thing is said to be one, 
these terms also will have many senses, but yet it belongs to 
one science to know them all; for a term belongs to different 
sciences not if it has different senses, but if it has not one 
meaning and its definitions cannot be referred to one central 
meaning. And since all things are referred to that which is 
primary, as for instance all things which are called one are 
referred to the primary one, we must say that this holds good 
also of the same and the other and of contraries in general; so 



2267 



that after distinguishing the various senses of each, we must 
then explain by reference to what is primary in the case of each 
of the predicates in question, saying how they are related to it; 
for some will be called what they are called because they 
possess it, others because they produce it, and others in other 
such ways. 

It is evident, then, that it belongs to one science to be able to 
give an account of these concepts as well as of substance (this 
was one of the questions in our book of problems), and that it is 
the function of the philosopher to be able to investigate all 
things. For if it is not the function of the philosopher, who is it 
who will inquire whether Socrates and Socrates seated are the 
same thing, or whether one thing has one contrary, or what 
contrariety is, or how many meanings it has? And similarly with 
all other such questions. Since, then, these are essential 
modifications of unity qua unity and of being qua being, not 
qua numbers or lines or fire, it is clear that it belongs to this 
science to investigate both the essence of these concepts and 
their properties. And those who study these properties err not 
by leaving the sphere of philosophy, but by forgetting that 
substance, of which they have no correct idea, is prior to these 
other things. For number qua number has peculiar attributes, 
such as oddness and evenness, commensurability and equality, 
excess and defect, and these belong to numbers either in 
themselves or in relation to one another. And similarly the solid 
and the motionless and that which is in motion and the 
weightless and that which has weight have other peculiar 
properties. So too there are certain properties peculiar to being 
as such, and it is about these that the philosopher has to 
investigate the truth. - An indication of this may be mentioned: 
dialecticians and sophists assume the same guise as the 
philosopher, for sophistic is Wisdom which exists only in 
semblance, and dialecticians embrace all things in their 
dialectic, and being is common to all things; but evidently their 



2268 



dialectic embraces these subjects because these are proper to 
philosophy. - For sophistic and dialectic turn on the same class 
of things as philosophy, but this differs from dialectic in the 
nature of the faculty required and from sophistic in respect of 
the purpose of the philosophic life. Dialectic is merely critical 
where philosophy claims to know, and sophistic is what 
appears to be philosophy but is not. 

Again, in the list of contraries one of the two columns is 
privative, and all contraries are reducible to being and non- 
being, and to unity and plurality, as for instance rest belongs to 
unity and movement to plurality. And nearly all thinkers agree 
that being and substance are composed of contraries; at least all 
name contraries as their first principles - some name odd and 
even, some hot and cold, some limit and the unlimited, some 
love and strife. And all the others as well are evidently reducible 
to unity and plurality (this reduction we must take for granted), 
and the principles stated by other thinkers fall entirely under 
these as their genera. It is obvious then from these 
considerations too that it belongs to one science to examine 
being qua being. For all things are either contraries or composed 
of contraries, and unity and plurality are the starting-points of 
all contraries. And these belong to one science, whether they 
have or have not one single meaning. Probably the truth is that 
they have not; yet even if 'one' has several meanings, the other 
meanings will be related to the primary meaning (and similarly 
in the case of the contraries), even if being or unity is not a 
universal and the same in every instance or is not separable 
from the particular instances (as in fact it probably is not; the 
unity is in some cases that of common reference, in some cases 
that of serial succession). And for this reason it does not belong 
to the geometer to inquire what is contrariety or completeness 
or unity or being or the same or the other, but only to 
presuppose these concepts and reason from this starting-point. 
- Obviously then it is the work of one science to examine being 



2269 



qua being, and the attributes which belong to it qua being, and 
the same science will examine not only substances but also 
their attributes, both those above named and the concepts 
'prior' and 'posterior', 'genus' and 'species', 'whole' and 'part', 
and the others of this sort. 



We must state whether it belongs to one or to different sciences 
to inquire into the truths which are in mathematics called 
axioms, and into substance. Evidently, the inquiry into these 
also belongs to one science, and that the science of the 
philosopher; for these truths hold good for everything that is, 
and not for some special genus apart from others. And all men 
use them, because they are true of being qua being and each 
genus has being. But men use them just so far as to satisfy their 
purposes; that is, as far as the genus to which their 
demonstrations refer extends. Therefore since these truths 
clearly hold good for all things qua being (for this is what is 
common to them), to him who studies being qua being belongs 
the inquiry into these as well. And for this reason no one who is 
conducting a special inquiry tries to say anything about their 
truth or falsity, - neither the geometer nor the arithmetician. 
Some natural philosophers indeed have done so, and their 
procedure was intelligible enough; for they thought that they 
alone were inquiring about the whole of nature and about 
being. But since there is one kind of thinker who is above even 
the natural philosopher (for nature is only one particular genus 
of being), the discussion of these truths also will belong to him 
whose inquiry is universal and deals with primary substance. 
Physics also is a kind of Wisdom, but it is not the first kind. - 
And the attempts of some of those who discuss the terms on 



2270 



which truth should be accepted, are due to a want of training in 
logic; for they should know these things already when they 
come to a special study, and not be inquiring into them while 
they are listening to lectures on it. 

Evidently then it belongs to the philosopher, i.e. to him who is 
studying the nature of all substance, to inquire also into the 
principles of syllogism. But he who knows best about each 
genus must be able to state the most certain principles of his 
subject, so that he whose subject is existing things qua existing 
must be able to state the most certain principles of all things. 
This is the philosopher, and the most certain principle of all is 
that regarding which it is impossible to be mistaken; for such a 
principle must be both the best known (for all men may be 
mistaken about things which they do not know), and non- 
hypothetical. For a principle which every one must have who 
understands anything that is, is not a hypothesis; and that 
which every one must know who knows anything, he must 
already have when he comes to a special study. Evidently then 
such a principle is the most certain of all; which principle this 
is, let us proceed to say. It is, that the same attribute cannot at 
the same time belong and not belong to the same subject and in 
the same respect; we must presuppose, to guard against 
dialectical objections, any further qualifications which might be 
added. This, then, is the most certain of all principles, since it 
answers to the definition given above. For it is impossible for 
any one to believe the same thing to be and not to be, as some 
think Heraclitus says. For what a man says, he does not 
necessarily believe; and if it is impossible that contrary 
attributes should belong at the same time to the same subject 
(the usual qualifications must be presupposed in this premiss 
too), and if an opinion which contradicts another is contrary to 
it, obviously it is impossible for the same man at the same time 
to believe the same thing to be and not to be; for if a man were 
mistaken on this point he would have contrary opinions at the 



2271 



same time. It is for this reason that all who are carrying out a 
demonstration reduce it to this as an ultimate belief; for this is 
naturally the starting-point even for all the other axioms. 



There are some who, as we said, both themselves assert that it 
is possible for the same thing to be and not to be, and say that 
people can judge this to be the case. And among others many 
writers about nature use this language. But we have now 
posited that it is impossible for anything at the same time to be 
and not to be, and by this means have shown that this is the 
most indisputable of all principles. - Some indeed demand that 
even this shall be demonstrated, but this they do through want 
of education, for not to know of what things one should 
demand demonstration, and of what one should not, argues 
want of education. For it is impossible that there should be 
demonstration of absolutely everything (there would be an 
infinite regress, so that there would still be no demonstration); 
but if there are things of which one should not demand 
demonstration, these persons could not say what principle they 
maintain to be more self-evident than the present one. 

We can, however, demonstrate negatively even that this view is 
impossible, if our opponent will only say something; and if he 
says nothing, it is absurd to seek to give an account of our views 
to one who cannot give an account of anything, in so far as he 
cannot do so. For such a man, as such, is from the start no 
better than a vegetable. Now negative demonstration I 
distinguish from demonstration proper, because in a 
demonstration one might be thought to be begging the 
question, but if another person is responsible for the 



2272 



assumption we shall have negative proof, not demonstration. 
The starting-point for all such arguments is not the demand 
that our opponent shall say that something either is or is not 
(for this one might perhaps take to be a begging of the 
question), but that he shall say something which is significant 
both for himself and for another; for this is necessary, if he 
really is to say anything. For, if he means nothing, such a man 
will not be capable of reasoning, either with himself or with 
another. But if any one grants this, demonstration will be 
possible; for we shall already have something definite. The 
person responsible for the proof, however, is not he who 
demonstrates but he who listens; for while disowning reason he 
listens to reason. And again he who admits this has admitted 
that something is true apart from demonstration (so that not 
everything will be 'so and not so'). 

First then this at least is obviously true, that the word 'be' or 
'not be' has a definite meaning, so that not everything will be 
'so and not so'. Again, if 'man' has one meaning, let this be 'two- 
footed animal'; by having one meaning I understand this: - if 
'man' means 'X', then if A is a man 'X' will be what 'being a 
man' means for him. (It makes no difference even if one were to 
say a word has several meanings, if only they are limited in 
number; for to each definition there might be assigned a 
different word. For instance, we might say that 'man' has not 
one meaning but several, one of which would have one 
definition, viz. 'two-footed animal', while there might be also 
several other definitions if only they were limited in number; for 
a peculiar name might be assigned to each of the definitions. If, 
however, they were not limited but one were to say that the 
word has an infinite number of meanings, obviously reasoning 
would be impossible; for not to have one meaning is to have no 
meaning, and if words have no meaning our reasoning with one 
another, and indeed with ourselves, has been annihilated; for it 
is impossible to think of anything if we do not think of one 



2273 



thing; but if this is possible, one name might be assigned to this 
thing.) 

Let it be assumed then, as was said at the beginning, that the 
name has a meaning and has one meaning; it is impossible, 
then, that 'being a man' should mean precisely 'not being a 
man', if 'man' not only signifies something about one subject 
but also has one significance (for we do not identify 'having one 
significance' with 'signifying something about one subject', 
since on that assumption even 'musical' and 'white' and 'man' 
would have had one significance, so that all things would have 
been one; for they would all have had the same significance). 

And it will not be possible to be and not to be the same thing, 
except in virtue of an ambiguity, just as if one whom we call 
'man', others were to call 'not-man'; but the point in question is 
not this, whether the same thing can at the same time be and 
not be a man in name, but whether it can in fact. Now if 'man' 
and 'not-man' mean nothing different, obviously 'not being a 
man' will mean nothing different from 'being a man'; so that 
'being a man' will be 'not being a man'; for they will be one. For 
being one means this - being related as 'raiment' and 'dress' 
are, if their definition is one. And if 'being a man' and 'being a 
not-man' are to be one, they must mean one thing. But it was 
shown earlier that they mean different things. - Therefore, if it 
is true to say of anything that it is a man, it must be a two- 
footed animal (for this was what 'man' meant); and if this is 
necessary, it is impossible that the same thing should not at 
that time be a two-footed animal; for this is what 'being 
necessary' means - that it is impossible for the thing not to be. 
It is, then, impossible that it should be at the same time true to 
say the same thing is a man and is not a man. 

The same account holds good with regard to 'not being a man', 
for 'being a man' and 'being a not-man' mean different things, 



2274 



since even 'being white' and 'being a man' are different; for the 
former terms are much more different so that they must a 
fortiori mean different things. And if any one says that 'white' 
means one and the same thing as 'man', again we shall say the 
same as what was said before, that it would follow that all 
things are one, and not only opposites. But if this is impossible, 
then what we have maintained will follow, if our opponent will 
only answer our question. 

And if, when one asks the question simply, he adds the 
contradictories, he is not answering the question. For there is 
nothing to prevent the same thing from being both a man and 
white and countless other things: but still, if one asks whether 
it is or is not true to say that this is a man, our opponent must 
give an answer which means one thing, and not add that 'it is 
also white and large'. For, besides other reasons, it is impossible 
to enumerate its accidental attributes, which are infinite in 
number; let him, then, enumerate either all or none. Similarly, 
therefore, even if the same thing is a thousand times a man and 
a not-man, he must not, in answering the question whether this 
is a man, add that it is also at the same time a not-man, unless 
he is bound to add also all the other accidents, all that the 
subject is or is not; and if he does this, he is not observing the 
rules of argument. 

And in general those who say this do away with substance and 
essence. For they must say that all attributes are accidents, and 
that there is no such thing as 'being essentially a man' or 'an 
animal'. For if there is to be any such thing as 'being essentially 
a man' this will not be 'being a not-man' or 'not being a man' 
(yet these are negations of it); for there was one thing which it 
meant, and this was the substance of something. And denoting 
the substance of a thing means that the essence of the thing is 
nothing else. But if its being essentially a man is to be the same 
as either being essentially a not-man or essentially not being a 



2275 



man, then its essence will be something else. Therefore our 
opponents must say that there cannot be such a definition of 
anything, but that all attributes are accidental; for this is the 
distinction between substance and accident - 'white' is 
accidental to man, because though he is white, whiteness is not 
his essence. But if all statements are accidental, there will be 
nothing primary about which they are made, if the accidental 
always implies predication about a subject. The predication, 
then, must go on ad infinitum. But this is impossible; for not 
even more than two terms can be combined in accidental 
predication. For (1) an accident is not an accident of an accident, 
unless it be because both are accidents of the same subject. I 
mean, for instance, that the white is musical and the latter is 
white, only because both are accidental to man. But (2) Socrates 
is musical, not in this sense, that both terms are accidental to 
something else. Since then some predicates are accidental in 
this and some in that sense, (a) those which are accidental in 
the latter sense, in which white is accidental to Socrates, cannot 
form an infinite series in the upward direction; e.g. Socrates the 
white has not yet another accident; for no unity can be got out 
of such a sum. Nor again (b) will 'white' have another term 
accidental to it, e.g. 'musical'. For this is no more accidental to 
that than that is to this; and at the same time we have drawn 
the distinction, that while some predicates are accidental in 
this sense, others are so in the sense in which 'musical' is 
accidental to Socrates; and the accident is an accident of an 
accident not in cases of the latter kind, but only in cases of the 
other kind, so that not all terms will be accidental. There must, 
then, even so be something which denotes substance. And if 
this is so, it has been shown that contradictories cannot be 
predicated at the same time. 

Again, if all contradictory statements are true of the same 
subject at the same time, evidently all things will be one. For the 
same thing will be a trireme, a wall, and a man, if of everything 



2276 



it is possible either to affirm or to deny anything (and this 
premiss must be accepted by those who share the views of 
Protagoras). For if any one thinks that the man is not a trireme, 
evidently he is not a trireme; so that he also is a trireme, if, as 
they say, contradictory statements are both true. And we thus 
get the doctrine of Anaxagoras, that all things are mixed 
together; so that nothing really exists. They seem, then, to be 
speaking of the indeterminate, and, while fancying themselves 
to be speaking of being, they are speaking about non-being; for 
it is that which exists potentially and not in complete reality 
that is indeterminate. But they must predicate of every subject 
the affirmation or the negation of every attribute. For it is 
absurd if of each subject its own negation is to be predicable, 
while the negation of something else which cannot be 
predicated of it is not to be predicable of it; for instance, if it is 
true to say of a man that he is not a man, evidently it is also 
true to say that he is either a trireme or not a trireme. If, then, 
the affirmative can be predicated, the negative must be 
predicable too; and if the affirmative is not predicable, the 
negative, at least, will be more predicable than the negative of 
the subject itself. If, then, even the latter negative is predicable, 
the negative of 'trireme' will be also predicable; and, if this is 
predicable, the affirmative will be so too. 

Those, then, who maintain this view are driven to this 
conclusion, and to the further conclusion that it is not 
necessary either to assert or to deny. For if it is true that a thing 
is a man and a not-man, evidently also it will be neither a man 
nor a not-man. For to the two assertions there answer two 
negations, and if the former is treated as a single proposition 
compounded out of two, the latter also is a single proposition 
opposite to the former. 

Again, either the theory is true in all cases, and a thing is both 
white and not-white, and existent and non-existent, and all 



2277 



other assertions and negations are similarly compatible or the 
theory is true of some statements and not of others. And if not 
of all, the exceptions will be contradictories of which admittedly 
only one is true; but if of all, again either the negation will be 
true wherever the assertion is, and the assertion true wherever 
the negation is, or the negation will be true where the assertion 
is, but the assertion not always true where the negation is. And 
(a) in the latter case there will be something which fixedly is 
not, and this will be an indisputable belief; and if non-being is 
something indisputable and knowable, the opposite assertion 
will be more knowable. But (b) if it is equally possible also to 
assert all that it is possible to deny, one must either be saying 
what is true when one separates the predicates (and says, for 
instance, that a thing is white, and again that it is not- white), or 
not. And if (i) it is not true to apply the predicates separately, 
our opponent is not saying what he professes to say, and also 
nothing at all exists; but how could non-existent things speak 
or walk, as he does? Also all things would on this view be one, 
as has been already said, and man and God and trireme and 
their contradictories will be the same. For if contradictories can 
be predicated alike of each subject, one thing will in no wise 
differ from another; for if it differ, this difference will be 
something true and peculiar to it. And (ii) if one may with truth 
apply the predicates separately, the above-mentioned result 
follows none the less, and, further, it follows that all would then 
be right and all would be in error, and our opponent himself 
confesses himself to be in error. - And at the same time our 
discussion with him is evidently about nothing at all; for he 
says nothing. For he says neither 'yes' nor 'no', but 'yes and no'; 
and again he denies both of these and says 'neither yes nor no'; 
for otherwise there would already be something definite. 

Again if when the assertion is true, the negation is false, and 
when this is true, the affirmation is false, it will not be possible 



2278 



to assert and deny the same thing truly at the same time. But 
perhaps they might say this was the very question at issue. 

Again, is he in error who judges either that the thing is so or 
that it is not so, and is he right who judges both? If he is right, 
what can they mean by saying that the nature of existing things 
is of this kind? And if he is not right, but more right than he 
who judges in the other way, being will already be of a definite 
nature, and this will be true, and not at the same time also not 
true. But if all are alike both wrong and right, one who is in this 
condition will not be able either to speak or to say anything 
intelligible; for he says at the same time both 'yes' and 'no.' And 
if he makes no judgement but 'thinks' and 'does not think', 
indifferently, what difference will there be between him and a 
vegetable? - Thus, then, it is in the highest degree evident that 
neither any one of those who maintain this view nor any one 
else is really in this position. For why does a man walk to 
Megara and not stay at home, when he thinks he ought to be 
walking there? Why does he not walk early some morning into 
a well or over a precipice, if one happens to be in his way? Why 
do we observe him guarding against this, evidently because he 
does not think that falling in is alike good and not good? 
Evidently, then, he judges one thing to be better and another 
worse. And if this is so, he must also judge one thing to be a 
man and another to be not-a-man, one thing to be sweet and 
another to be not-sweet. For he does not aim at and judge all 
things alike, when, thinking it desirable to drink water or to see 
a man, he proceeds to aim at these things; yet he ought, if the 
same thing were alike a man and not-a-man. But, as was said, 
there is no one who does not obviously avoid some things and 
not others. Therefore, as it seems, all men make unqualified 
judgements, if not about all things, still about what is better and 
worse. And if this is not knowledge but opinion, they should be 
all the more anxious about the truth, as a sick man should be 
more anxious about his health than one who is healthy; for he 



2279 



who has opinions is, in comparison with the man who knows, 
not in a healthy state as far as the truth is concerned. 

Again, however much all things may be 'so and not so', still 
there is a more and a less in the nature of things; for we should 
not say that two and three are equally even, nor is he who 
thinks four things are five equally wrong with him who thinks 
they are a thousand. If then they are not equally wrong, 
obviously one is less wrong and therefore more right. If then 
that which has more of any quality is nearer the norm, there 
must be some truth to which the more true is nearer. And even 
if there is not, still there is already something better founded 
and liker the truth, and we shall have got rid of the unqualified 
doctrine which would prevent us from determining anything in 
our thought. 



From the same opinion proceeds the doctrine of Protagoras, and 
both doctrines must be alike true or alike untrue. For on the one 
hand, if all opinions and appearances are true, all statements 
must be at the same time true and false. For many men hold 
beliefs in which they conflict with one another, and think those 
mistaken who have not the same opinions as themselves; so 
that the same thing must both be and not be. And on the other 
hand, if this is so, all opinions must be true; for those who are 
mistaken and those who are right are opposed to one another in 
their opinions; if, then, reality is such as the view in question 
supposes, all will be right in their beliefs. 

Evidently, then, both doctrines proceed from the same way of 
thinking. But the same method of discussion must not be used 
with all opponents; for some need persuasion, and others 



2280 



compulsion. Those who have been driven to this position by 
difficulties in their thinking can easily be cured of their 
ignorance; for it is not their expressed argument but their 
thought that one has to meet. But those who argue for the sake 
of argument can be cured only by refuting the argument as 
expressed in speech and in words. 

Those who really feel the difficulties have been led to this 
opinion by observation of the sensible world. (1) They think that 
contradictories or contraries are true at the same time, because 
they see contraries coming into existence out of the same thing. 
If, then, that which is not cannot come to be, the thing must 
have existed before as both contraries alike, as Anaxagoras says 
all is mixed in all, and Democritus too; for he says the void and 
the full exist alike in every part, and yet one of these is being, 
and the other non-being. To those, then, whose belief rests on 
these grounds, we shall say that in a sense they speak rightly 
and in a sense they err. For 'that which is' has two meanings, so 
that in some sense a thing can come to be out of that which is 
not, while in some sense it cannot, and the same thing can at 
the same time be in being and not in being - but not in the 
same respect. For the same thing can be potentially at the same 
time two contraries, but it cannot actually. And again we shall 
ask them to believe that among existing things there is also 
another kind of substance to which neither movement nor 
destruction nor generation at all belongs. 

And (2) similarly some have inferred from observation of the 
sensible world the truth of appearances. For they think that the 
truth should not be determined by the large or small number of 
those who hold a belief, and that the same thing is thought 
sweet by some when they taste it, and bitter by others, so that if 
all were ill or all were mad, and only two or three were well or 
sane, these would be thought ill and mad, and not the others. 



2281 



And again, they say that many of the other animals receive 
impressions contrary to ours; and that even to the senses of 
each individual, things do not always seem the same. Which, 
then, of these impressions are true and which are false is not 
obvious; for the one set is no more true than the other, but both 
are alike. And this is why Democritus, at any rate, says that 
either there is no truth or to us at least it is not evident. 

And in general it is because these thinkers suppose knowledge 
to be sensation, and this to be a physical alteration, that they 
say that what appears to our senses must be true; for it is for 
these reasons that both Empedocles and Democritus and, one 
may almost say, all the others have fallen victims to opinions of 
this sort. For Empedocles says that when men change their 
condition they change their knowledge; 

For wisdom increases in men according to what is before them. 

And elsewhere he says that: - 

So far as their nature changed, so far to them always 

Came changed thoughts into mind. 

And Parmenides also expresses himself in the same way: 

For as at each time the much-bent limbs are composed, 

So is the mind of men; for in each and all men 

'Tis one thing thinks - the substance of their limbs: 

For that of which there is more is thought. 

A saying of Anaxagoras to some of his friends is also related, - 
that things would be for them such as they supposed them to 
be. And they say that Homer also evidently had this opinion, 
because he made Hector, when he was unconscious from the 



2282 



blow, lie 'thinking other thoughts', - which implies that even 
those who are bereft of thought have thoughts, though not the 
same thoughts. Evidently, then, if both are forms of knowledge, 
the real things also are at the same time 'both so and not so'. 
And it is in this direction that the consequences are most 
difficult. For if those who have seen most of such truth as is 
possible for us (and these are those who seek and love it most) - 
if these have such opinions and express these views about the 
truth, is it not natural that beginners in philosophy should lose 
heart? For to seek the truth would be to follow flying game. 

But the reason why these thinkers held this opinion is that 
while they were inquiring into the truth of that which is, they 
thought, 'that which is' was identical with the sensible world; in 
this, however, there is largely present the nature of the 
indeterminate - of that which exists in the peculiar sense which 
we have explained; and therefore, while they speak plausibly, 
they do not say what is true (for it is fitting to put the matter so 
rather than as Epicharmus put it against Xenophanes). And 
again, because they saw that all this world of nature is in 
movement and that about that which changes no true 
statement can be made, they said that of course, regarding that 
which everywhere in every respect is changing, nothing could 
truly be affirmed. It was this belief that blossomed into the 
most extreme of the views above mentioned, that of the 
professed Heracliteans, such as was held by Cratylus, who 
finally did not think it right to say anything but only moved his 
finger, and criticized Heraclitus for saying that it is impossible 
to step twice into the same river; for he thought one could not 
do it even once. 

But we shall say in answer to this argument also that while 
there is some justification for their thinking that the changing, 
when it is changing, does not exist, yet it is after all disputable; 
for that which is losing a quality has something of that which is 



2283 



being lost, and of that which is coming to be, something must 
already be. And in general if a thing is perishing, will be present 
something that exists; and if a thing is coming to be, there must 
be something from which it comes to be and something by 
which it is generated, and this process cannot go on ad 
infinitum. - But, leaving these arguments, let us insist on this, 
that it is not the same thing to change in quantity and in 
quality. Grant that in quantity a thing is not constant; still it is 
in respect of its form that we know each thing. - And again, it 
would be fair to criticize those who hold this view for asserting 
about the whole material universe what they saw only in a 
minority even of sensible things. For only that region of the 
sensible world which immediately surrounds us is always in 
process of destruction and generation; but this is - so to speak - 
not even a fraction of the whole, so that it would have been 
juster to acquit this part of the world because of the other part, 
than to condemn the other because of this. - And again, 
obviously we shall make to them also the same reply that we 
made long ago; we must show them and persuade them that 
there is something whose nature is changeless. Indeed, those 
who say that things at the same time are and are not, should in 
consequence say that all things are at rest rather than that they 
are in movement; for there is nothing into which they can 
change, since all attributes belong already to all subjects. 

Regarding the nature of truth, we must maintain that not 
everything which appears is true; firstly, because even if 
sensation - at least of the object peculiar to the sense in 
question - is not false, still appearance is not the same as 
sensation. - Again, it is fair to express surprise at our 
opponents' raising the question whether magnitudes are as 
great, and colours are of such a nature, as they appear to people 
at a distance, or as they appear to those close at hand, and 
whether they are such as they appear to the healthy or to the 
sick, and whether those things are heavy which appear so to the 



2284 



weak or those which appear so to the strong, and those things 
true which appear to the slee ing or to the waking. For obviously 
they do not think these to be open questions; no one, at least, if 
when he is in Libya he has fancied one night that he is in 
Athens, starts for the concert hall. - And again with regard to 
the future, as Plato says, surely the opinion of the physician and 
that of the ignorant man are not equally weighty, for instance, 
on the question whether a man will get well or not. - And again, 
among sensations themselves the sensation of a foreign object 
and that of the appropriate object, or that of a kindred object 
and that of the object of the sense in question, are not equally 
authoritative, but in the case of colour sight, not taste, has the 
authority, and in the case of flavour taste, not sight; each of 
which senses never says at the same time of the same object 
that it simultaneously is 'so and not so'. - But not even at 
different times does one sense disagree about the quality, but 
only about that to which the quality belongs. I mean, for 
instance, that the same wine might seem, if either it or one's 
body changed, at one time sweet and at another time not sweet; 
but at least the sweet, such as it is when it exists, has never yet 
changed, but one is always right about it, and that which is to be 
sweet is of necessity of such and such a nature. Yet all these 
views destroy this necessity, leaving nothing to be of necessity, 
as they leave no essence of anything; for the necessary cannot 
be in this way and also in that, so that if anything is of 
necessity, it will not be 'both so and not so'. 

And, in general, if only the sensible exists, there would be 
nothing if animate things were not; for there would be no 
faculty of sense. Now the view that neither the sensible 
qualities nor the sensations would exist is doubtless true (for 
they are affections of the perceiver), but that the substrata 
which cause the sensation should not exist even apart from 
sensation is impossible. For sensation is surely not the 
sensation of itself, but there is something beyond the sensation, 



2285 



which must be prior to the sensation; for that which moves is 
prior in nature to that which is moved, and if they are 
correlative terms, this is no less the case. 



There are, both among those who have these convictions and 
among those who merely profess these views, some who raise a 
difficulty by asking, who is to be the judge of the healthy man, 
and in general who is likely to judge rightly on each class of 
questions. But such inquiries are like puzzling over the question 
whether we are now asleep or awake. And all such questions 
have the same meaning. These people demand that a reason 
shall be given for everything; for they seek a starting-point, and 
they seek to get this by demonstration, while it is obvious from 
their actions that they have no conviction. But their mistake is 
what we have stated it to be; they seek a reason for things for 
which no reason can be given; for the starting-point of 
demonstration is not demonstration. 

These, then, might be easily persuaded of this truth, for it is not 
difficult to grasp; but those who seek merely compulsion in 
argument seek what is impossible; for they demand to be 
allowed to contradict themselves - a claim which contradicts 
itself from the very first. - But if not all things are relative, but 
some are self-existent, not everything that appears will be true; 
for that which appears is apparent to some one; so that he who 
says all things that appear are true, makes all things relative. 
And, therefore, those who ask for an irresistible argument, and 
at the same time demand to be called to account for their views, 
must guard themselves by saying that the truth is not that what 
appears exists, but that what appears exists for him to whom it 



2286 



appears, and when, and to the sense to which, and under the 
conditions under which it appears. And if they give an account 
of their view, but do not give it in this way, they will soon find 
themselves contradicting themselves. For it is possible that the 
same thing may appear to be honey to the sight, but not to the 
taste, and that, since we have two eyes, things may not appear 
the same to each, if their sight is unlike. For to those who for 
the reasons named some time ago say that what appears is 
true, and therefore that all things are alike false and true, for 
things do not appear either the same to all men or always the 
same to the same man, but often have contrary appearances at 
the same time (for touch says there are two objects when we 
cross our fingers, while sight says there is one) - to these we 
shall say 'yes, but not to the same sense and in the same part of 
it and under the same conditions and at the same time', so that 
what appears will be with these qualifications true. But perhaps 
for this reason those who argue thus not because they feel a 
difficulty but for the sake of argument, should say that this is 
not true, but true for this man. And as has been said before, they 
must make everything relative - relative to opinion and 
perception, so that nothing either has come to be or will be 
without some one's first thinking so. But if things have come to 
be or will be, evidently not all things will be relative to opinion. - 
Again, if a thing is one, it is in relation to one thing or to a 
definite number of things; and if the same thing is both half 
and equal, it is not to the double that the equal is correlative. If, 
then, in relation to that which thinks, man and that which is 
thought are the same, man will not be that which thinks, but 
only that which is thought. And if each thing is to be relative to 
that which thinks, that which thinks will be relative to an 
infinity of specifically different things. 

Let this, then, suffice to show (1) that the most indisputable of 
all beliefs is that contradictory statements are not at the same 
time true, and (2) what consequences follow from the assertion 



2287 



that they are, and (3) why people do assert this. Now since it is 
impossible that contradictories should be at the same time true 
of the same thing, obviously contraries also cannot belong at 
the same time to the same thing. For of contraries, one is a 
privation no less than it is a contrary - and a privation of the 
essential nature; and privation is the denial of a predicate to a 
determinate genus. If, then, it is impossible to affirm and deny 
truly at the same time, it is also impossible that contraries 
should belong to a subject at the same time, unless both belong 
to it in particular relations, or one in a particular relation and 
one without qualification. 



But on the other hand there cannot be an intermediate between 
contradictories, but of one subject we must either affirm or 
deny any one predicate. This is clear, in the first place, if we 
define what the true and the false are. To say of what is that it is 
not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is 
that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true; so that he who 
says of anything that it is, or that it is not, will say either what is 
true or what is false; but neither what is nor what is not is said 
to be or not to be. - Again, the intermediate between the 
contradictories will be so either in the way in which grey is 
between black and white, or as that which is neither man nor 
horse is between man and horse, (a) If it were of the latter kind, 
it could not change into the extremes (for change is from not- 
good to good, or from good to not-good), but as a matter of fact 
when there is an intermediate it is always observed to change 
into the extremes. For there is no change except to opposites 
and to their intermediates, (b) But if it is really intermediate, in 
this way too there would have to be a change to white, which 



2288 



was not from not-white; but as it is, this is never seen. - Again, 
every object of understanding or reason the understanding 
either affirms or denies - this is obvious from the definition - 
whenever it says what is true or false. When it connects in one 
way by assertion or negation, it says what is true, and when it 
does so in another way, what is false. - Again, there must be an 
intermediate between all contradictories, if one is not arguing 
merely for the sake of argument; so that it will be possible for a 
man to say what is neither true nor untrue, and there will be a 
middle between that which is and that which is not, so that 
there will also be a kind of change intermediate between 
generation and destruction. - Again, in all classes in which the 
negation of an attribute involves the assertion of its contrary, 
even in these there will be an intermediate; for instance, in the 
sphere of numbers there will be number which is neither odd 
nor not-odd. But this is impossible, as is obvious from the 
definition. - Again, the process will go on ad infinitum, and the 
number of realities will be not only half as great again, but even 
greater. For again it will be possible to deny this intermediate 
with reference both to its assertion and to its negation, and this 
new term will be some definite thing; for its essence is 
something different. - Again, when a man, on being asked 
whether a thing is white, says 'no', he has denied nothing 
except that it is; and its not being is a negation. 

Some people have acquired this opinion as other paradoxical 
opinions have been acquired; when men cannot refute eristical 
arguments, they give in to the argument and agree that the 
conclusion is true. This, then, is why some express this view; 
others do so because they demand a reason for everything. And 
the starting-point in dealing with all such people is definition. 
Now the definition rests on the necessity of their meaning 
something; for the form of words of which the word is a sign 
will be its definition. - While the doctrine of Heraclitus, that all 
things are and are not, seems to make everything true, that of 



2289 



Anaxagoras, that there is an intermediate between the terms of 
a contradiction, seems to make everything false; for when 
things are mixed, the mixture is neither good nor not-good, so 
that one cannot say anything that is true. 



8 

In view of these distinctions it is obvious that the one-sided 
theories which some people express about all things cannot be 
valid - on the one hand the theory that nothing is true (for, say 
they, there is nothing to prevent every statement from being like 
the statement 'the diagonal of a square is commensurate with 
the side'), on the other hand the theory that everything is true. 
These views are practically the same as that of Heraclitus; for 
he who says that all things are true and all are false also makes 
each of these statements separately, so that since they are 
impossible, the double statement must be impossible too. - 
Again, there are obviously contradictories which cannot be at 
the same time true - nor on the other hand can all statements 
be false; yet this would seem more possible in the light of what 
has been said. - But against all such views we must postulate, as 
we said above,' not that something is or is not, but that 
something has a meaning, so that we must argue from a 
definition, viz. by assuming what falsity or truth means. If that 
which it is true to affirm is nothing other than that which it is 
false to deny, it is impossible that all statements should be false; 
for one side of the contradiction must be true. Again, if it is 
necessary with regard to everything either to assert or to deny 
it, it is impossible that both should be false; for it is one side of 
the contradiction that is false. - Therefore all such views are 
also exposed to the often expressed objection, that they destroy 
themselves. For he who says that everything is true makes even 



2290 



the statement contrary to his own true, and therefore his own 
not true (for the contrary statement denies that it is true), while 
he who says everything is false makes himself also false. - And 
if the former person excepts the contrary statement, saying it 
alone is not true, while the latter excepts his own as being not 
false, none the less they are driven to postulate the truth or 
falsity of an infinite number of statements; for that which says 
the true statement is true is true, and this process will go on to 
infinity 

Evidently, again, those who say all things are at rest are not 
right, nor are those who say all things are in movement. For if 
all things are at rest, the same statements will always be true 
and the same always false, - but this obviously changes; for he 
who makes a statement, himself at one time was not and again 
will not be. And if all things are in motion, nothing will be true; 
everything therefore will be false. But it has been shown that 
this is impossible. Again, it must be that which is that changes; 
for change is from something to something. But again it is not 
the case that all things are at rest or in motion sometimes, and 
nothing for ever; for there is something which always moves 
the things that are in motion, and the first mover is itself 
unmoved. 



2291 



Book A 



'Beginning' means (1) that part of a thing from which one would 
start first, e.g a line or a road has a beginning in either of the 
contrary directions. (2) That from which each thing would best 
be originated, e.g. even in learning we must sometimes begin 
not from the first point and the beginning of the subject, but 
from the point from which we should learn most easily. (4) That 
from which, as an immanent part, a thing first comes to be, e,g, 
as the keel of a ship and the foundation of a house, while in 
animals some suppose the heart, others the brain, others some 
other part, to be of this nature. (4) That from which, not as an 
immanent part, a thing first comes to be, and from which the 
movement or the change naturally first begins, as a child comes 
from its father and its mother, and a fight from abusive 
language. (5) That at whose will that which is moved is moved 
and that which changes changes, e.g. the magistracies in cities, 
and oligarchies and monarchies and tyrannies, are called 
arhchai, and so are the arts, and of these especially the 
architectonic arts. (6) That from which a thing can first be 
known, - this also is called the beginning of the thing, e.g. the 
hypotheses are the beginnings of demonstrations. (Causes are 
spoken of in an equal number of senses; for all causes are 
beginnings.) It is common, then, to all beginnings to be the first 
point from which a thing either is or comes to be or is known; 
but of these some are immanent in the thing and others are 
outside. Hence the nature of a thing is a beginning, and so is the 
element of a thing, and thought and will, and essence, and the 
final cause - for the good and the beautiful are the beginning 
both of the knowledge and of the movement of many things. 



2292 



'Cause' means (1) that from which, as immanent material, a 
thing comes into being, e.g. the bronze is the cause of the statue 
and the silver of the saucer, and so are the classes which 
include these. (2) The form or pattern, i.e. the definition of the 
essence, and the classes which include this (e.g. the ratio 2:1 
and number in general are causes of the octave), and the parts 
included in the definition. (3) That from which the change or the 
resting from change first begins; e.g. the adviser is a cause of 
the action, and the father a cause of the child, and in general 
the maker a cause of the thing made and the change-producing 
of the changing. (4) The end, i.e. that for the sake of which a 
thing is; e.g. health is the cause of walking. For 'Why does one 
walk?' we say; 'that one may be healthy'; and in speaking thus 
we think we have given the cause. The same is true of all the 
means that intervene before the end, when something else has 
put the process in motion, as e.g. thinning or purging or drugs 
or instruments intervene before health is reached; for all these 
are for the sake of the end, though they differ from one another 
in that some are instruments and others are actions. 

These, then, are practically all the senses in which causes are 
spoken of, and as they are spoken of in several senses it follows 
both that there are several causes of the same thing, and in no 
accidental sense (e.g. both the art of sculpture and the bronze 
are causes of the statue not in respect of anything else but qua 
statue; not, however, in the same way, but the one as matter 
and the other as source of the movement), and that things can 
be causes of one another (e.g. exercise of good condition, and 
the latter of exercise; not, however, in the same way, but the one 
as end and the other as source of movement). - Again, the same 



2293 



thing is the cause of contraries; for that which when present 
causes a particular thing, we sometimes charge, when absent, 
with the contrary, e.g. we impute the shipwreck to the absence 
of the steersman, whose presence was the cause of safety; and 
both - the presence and the privation - are causes as sources of 
movement. 

All the causes now mentioned fall under four senses which are 
the most obvious. For the letters are the cause of syllables, and 
the material is the cause of manufactured things, and fire and 
earth and all such things are the causes of bodies, and the parts 
are causes of the whole, and the hypotheses are causes of the 
conclusion, in the sense that they are that out of which these 
respectively are made; but of these some are cause as the 
substratum (e.g. the parts), others as the essence (the whole, the 
synthesis, and the form). The semen, the physician, the adviser, 
and in general the agent, are all sources of change or of rest. 
The remainder are causes as the end and the good of the other 
things; for that for the sake of which other things are tends to 
be the best and the end of the other things; let us take it as 
making no difference whether we call it good or apparent good. 

These, then, are the causes, and this is the number of their 
kinds, but the varieties of causes are many in number, though 
when summarized these also are comparatively few. Causes are 
spoken of in many senses, and even of those which are of the 
same kind some are causes in a prior and others in a posterior 
sense, e.g. both 'the physician' and 'the professional man' are 
causes of health, and both 'the ratio 2:1' and 'number' are 
causes of the octave, and the classes that include any particular 
cause are always causes of the particular effect. Again, there are 
accidental causes and the classes which include these; e.g. 
while in one sense 'the sculptor' causes the statue, in another 
sense 'Polyclitus' causes it, because the sculptor happens to be 
Polyclitus; and the classes that include the accidental cause are 



2294 



also causes, e.g. 'man' - or in general 'animal' - is the cause of 
the statue, because Polyclitus is a man, and man is an animal. 
Of accidental causes also some are more remote or nearer than 
others, as, for instance, if 'the white' and 'the musical' were 
called causes of the statue, and not only 'Polyclitus' or 'man'. 
But besides all these varieties of causes, whether proper or 
accidental, some are called causes as being able to act, others as 
acting; e.g. the cause of the house's being built is a builder, or a 
builder who is building. - The same variety of language will be 
found with regard to the effects of causes; e.g. a thing may be 
called the cause of this statue or of a statue or in general of an 
image, and of this bronze or of bronze or of matter in general; 
and similarly in the case of accidental effects. Again, both 
accidental and proper causes may be spoken of in combination; 
e.g. we may say not 'Polyclitus' nor 'the sculptor' but 'Polyclitus 
the sculptor'. Yet all these are but six in number, while each is 
spoken of in two ways; for (A) they are causes either as the 
individual, or as the genus, or as the accidental, or as the genus 
that includes the accidental, and these either as combined, or 
as taken simply; and (B) all may be taken as acting or as having 
a capacity. But they differ inasmuch as the acting causes, i.e. the 
individuals, exist, or do not exist, simultaneously with the 
things of which they are causes, e.g. this particular man who is 
healing, with this particular man who is recovering health, and 
this particular builder with this particular thing that is being 
built; but the potential causes are not always in this case; for 
the house does not perish at the same time as the builder. 



'Element' means (1) the primary component immanent in a 
thing, and indivisible in kind into other kinds; e.g. the elements 



2295 



of speech are the parts of which speech consists and into which 
it is ultimately divided, while they are no longer divided into 
other forms of speech different in kind from them. If they are 
divided, their parts are of the same kind, as a part of water is 
water (while a part of the syllable is not a syllable). Similarly 
those who speak of the elements of bodies mean the things into 
which bodies are ultimately divided, while they are no longer 
divided into other things differing in kind; and whether the 
things of this sort are one or more, they call these elements. The 
so-called elements of geometrical proofs, and in general the 
elements of demonstrations, have a similar character; for the 
primary demonstrations, each of which is implied in many 
demonstrations, are called elements of demonstrations; and the 
primary syllogisms, which have three terms and proceed by 
means of one middle, are of this nature. 

(2) People also transfer the word 'element' from this meaning 
and apply it to that which, being one and small, is useful for 
many purposes; for which reason what is small and simple and 
indivisible is called an element. Hence come the facts that the 
most universal things are elements (because each of them being 
one and simple is present in a plurality of things, either in all or 
in as many as possible), and that unity and the point are 
thought by some to be first principles. Now, since the so-called 
genera are universal and indivisible (for there is no definition of 
them), some say the genera are elements, and more so than the 
differentia, because the genus is more universal; for where the 
differentia is present, the genus accompanies it, but where the 
genus is present, the differentia is not always so. It is common 
to all the meanings that the element of each thing is the first 
component immanent in each. 



2296 



'Nature' means (1) the genesis of growing things - the meaning 
which would be suggested if one were to pronounce the 'u' in 
phusis long. - (2) That immanent part of a growing thing, from 
which its growth first proceeds. - (3) The source from which the 
primary movement in each natural object is present in it in 
virtue of its own essence. Those things are said to grow which 
derive increase from something else by contact and either by 
organic unity, or by organic adhesion as in the case of embryos. 
Organic unity differs from contact; for in the latter case there 
need not be anything besides the contact, but in organic unities 
there is something identical in both parts, which makes them 
grow together instead of merely touching, and be one in respect 
of continuity and quantity, though not of quality. - (4) 'Nature' 
means the primary material of which any natural object 
consists or out of which it is made, which is relatively unshaped 
and cannot be changed from its own potency, as e.g. bronze is 
said to be the nature of a statue and of bronze utensils, and 
wood the nature of wooden things; and so in all other cases; for 
when a product is made out of these materials, the first matter 
is preserved throughout. For it is in this way that people call the 
elements of natural objects also their nature, some naming fire, 
others earth, others air, others water, others something else of 
the sort, and some naming more than one of these, and others 
all of them. - (5) 'Nature' means the essence of natural objects, 
as with those who say the nature is the primary mode of 
composition, or as Empedocles says: - 

Nothing that is has a nature, 

But only mixing and parting of the mixed, 

And nature is but a name given them by men. 



2297 



Hence as regards the things that are or come to be by nature, 
though that from which they naturally come to be or are is 
already present, we say they have not their nature yet, unless 
they have their form or shape. That which comprises both of 
these exists by nature, e.g. the animals and their parts; and not 
only is the first matter nature (and this in two senses, either the 
first, counting from the thing, or the first in general; e.g. in the 
case of works in bronze, bronze is first with reference to them, 
but in general perhaps water is first, if all things that can be 
melted are water), but also the form or essence, which is the 
end of the process of becoming. - (6) By an extension of 
meaning from this sense of 'nature' every essence in general 
has come to be called a 'nature', because the nature of a thing is 
one kind of essence. 

From what has been said, then, it is plain that nature in the 
primary and strict sense is the essence of things which have in 
themselves, as such, a source of movement; for the matter is 
called the nature because it is qualified to receive this, and 
processes of becoming and growing are called nature because 
they are movements proceeding from this. And nature in this 
sense is the source of the movement of natural objects, being 
present in them somehow, either potentially or in complete 
reality. 



We call 'necessary' (1) (a) that without which, as a condition, a 
thing cannot live; e.g. breathing and food are necessary for an 
animal; for it is incapable of existing without these; (b) the 
conditions without which good cannot be or come to be, or 
without which we cannot get rid or be freed of evil; e.g. drinking 



2298 



the medicine is necessary in order that we may be cured of 
disease, and a man's sailing to Aegina is necessary in order that 
he may get his money - (2) The compulsory and compulsion, i.e. 
that which impedes and tends to hinder, contrary to impulse 
and purpose. For the compulsory is called necessary (whence 
the necessary is painful, as Evenus says: 'For every necessary 
thing is ever irksome'), and compulsion is a form of necessity, as 
Sophocles says: 'But force necessitates me to this act'. And 
necessity is held to be something that cannot be persuaded - 
and rightly, for it is contrary to the movement which accords 
with purpose and with reasoning. - (3) We say that that which 
cannot be otherwise is necessarily as it is. And from this sense 
of 'necessary' all the others are somehow derived; for a thing is 
said to do or suffer what is necessary in the sense of 
compulsory, only when it cannot act according to its impulse 
because of the compelling forces - which implies that necessity 
is that because of which a thing cannot be otherwise; and 
similarly as regards the conditions of life and of good; for when 
in the one case good, in the other life and being, are not possible 
without certain conditions, these are necessary, and this kind of 
cause is a sort of necessity. Again, demonstration is a necessary 
thing because the conclusion cannot be otherwise, if there has 
been demonstration in the unqualified sense; and the causes of 
this necessity are the first premisses, i.e. the fact that the 
propositions from which the syllogism proceeds cannot be 
otherwise. 

Now some things owe their necessity to something other than 
themselves; others do not, but are themselves the source of 
necessity in other things. Therefore the necessary in the 
primary and strict sense is the simple; for this does not admit of 
more states than one, so that it cannot even be in one state and 
also in another; for if it did it would already be in more than 
one. If, then, there are any things that are eternal and 



2299 



unmovable, nothing compulsory or against their nature 
attaches to them. 



'One' means (1) that which is one by accident, (2) that which is 
one by its own nature. (1) Instances of the accidentally one are 
'Coriscus and what is musical', and 'musical Coriscus' (for it is 
the same thing to say 'Coriscus and what is musical', and 
'musical Coriscus'), and 'what is musical and what is just', and 
'musical Coriscus and just Coriscus'. For all of these are called 
one by virtue of an accident, 'what is just and what is musical' 
because they are accidents of one substance, 'what is musical 
and Coriscus' because the one is an accident of the other; and 
similarly in a sense 'musical Coriscus' is one with 'Coriscus' 
because one of the parts of the phrase is an accident of the 
other, i.e. 'musical' is an accident of Coriscus; and 'musical 
Coriscus' is one with 'just Coriscus' because one part of each is 
an accident of one and the same subject. The case is similar if 
the accident is predicated of a genus or of any universal name, 
e.g. if one says that man is the same as 'musical man'; for this is 
either because 'musical' is an accident of man, which is one 
substance, or because both are accidents of some individual, e.g. 
Coriscus. Both, however, do not belong to him in the same way, 
but one presumably as genus and included in his substance, the 
other as a state or affection of the substance. 

The things, then, that are called one in virtue of an accident, are 
called so in this way. (2) Of things that are called one in virtue of 
their own nature some (a) are so called because they are 
continuous, e.g. a bundle is made one by a band, and pieces of 
wood are made one by glue; and a line, even if it is bent, is 



2300 



called one if it is continuous, as each part of the body is, e.g. the 
leg or the arm. Of these themselves, the continuous by nature 
are more one than the continuous by art. A thing is called 
continuous which has by its own nature one movement and 
cannot have any other; and the movement is one when it is 
indivisible, and it is indivisible in respect of time. Those things 
are continuous by their own nature which are one not merely by 
contact; for if you put pieces of wood touching one another, you 
will not say these are one piece of wood or one body or one 
continuum of any other sort. Things, then, that are continuous 
in any way called one, even if they admit of being bent, and still 
more those which cannot be bent; e.g. the shin or the thigh is 
more one than the leg, because the movement of the leg need 
not be one. And the straight line is more one than the bent; but 
that which is bent and has an angle we call both one and not 
one, because its movement may be either simultaneous or not 
simultaneous; but that of the straight line is always 
simultaneous, and no part of it which has magnitude rests 
while another moves, as in the bent line. 

(b)(i) Things are called one in another sense because their 
substratum does not differ in kind; it does not differ in the case 
of things whose kind is indivisible to sense. The substratum 
meant is either the nearest to, or the farthest from, the final 
state. For, one the one hand, wine is said to be one and water is 
said to be one, qua indivisible in kind; and, on the other hand, 
all juices, e.g. oil and wine, are said to be one, and so are all 
things that can be melted, because the ultimate substratum of 
all is the same; for all of these are water or air. 

(ii) Those things also are called one whose genus is one though 
distinguished by opposite differentiae - these too are all called 
one because the genus which underlies the differentiae is one 
(e.g. horse, man, and dog form a unity, because all are animals), 
and indeed in a way similar to that in which the matter is one. 



2301 



These are sometimes called one in this way, but sometimes it is 
the higher genus that is said to be the same (if they are infimae 
species of their genus) - the genus above the proximate genera; 
e.g. the isosceles and the equilateral are one and the same 
figure because both are triangles; but they are not the same 
triangles. 

(c) Two things are called one, when the definition which states 
the essence of one is indivisible from another definition which 
shows us the other (though in itself every definition is divisible). 
Thus even that which has increased or is diminishing is one, 
because its definition is one, as, in the case of plane figures, is 
the definition of their form. In general those things the thought 
of whose essence is indivisible, and cannot separate them 
either in time or in place or in definition, are most of all one, 
and of these especially those which are substances. For in 
general those things that do not admit of division are called one 
in so far as they do not admit of it; e.g. if two things are 
indistinguishable qua man, they are one kind of man; if qua 
animal, one kind of animal; if qua magnitude, one kind of 
magnitude. - Now most things are called one because they 
either do or have or suffer or are related to something else that 
is one, but the things that are primarily called one are those 
whose substance is one, - and one either in continuity or in 
form or in definition; for we count as more than one either 
things that are not continuous, or those whose form is not one, 
or those whose definition is not one. 

While in a sense we call anything one if it is a quantity and 
continuous, in a sense we do not unless it is a whole, i.e. unless 
it has unity of form; e.g. if we saw the parts of a shoe put 
together anyhow we should not call them one all the same 
(unless because of their continuity); we do this only if they are 
put together so as to be a shoe and to have already a certain 



2302 



single form. This is why the circle is of all lines most truly one, 
because it is whole and complete. 

(3) The essence of what is one is to be some kind of beginning of 
number; for the first measure is the beginning, since that by 
which we first know each class is the first measure of the class; 
the one, then, is the beginning of the knowable regarding each 
class. But the one is not the same in all classes. For here it is a 
quarter-tone, and there it is the vowel or the consonant; and 
there is another unit of weight and another of movement. But 
everywhere the one is indivisible either in quantity or in kind. 
Now that which is indivisible in quantity is called a unit if it is 
not divisible in any dimension and is without position, a point if 
it is not divisible in any dimension and has position, a line if it 
is divisible in one dimension, a plane if in two, a body if divisible 
in quantity in all - i.e. in three - dimensions. And, reversing the 
order, that which is divisible in two dimensions is a plane, that 
which is divisible in one a line, that which is in no way divisible 
in quantity is a point or a unit, - that which has not position a 
unit, that which has position a point. 

Again, some things are one in number, others in species, others 
in genus, others by analogy; in number those whose matter is 
one, in species those whose definition is one, in genus those to 
which the same figure of predication applies, by analogy those 
which are related as a third thing is to a fourth. The latter kinds 
of unity are always found when the former are; e.g. things that 
are one in number are also one in species, while things that are 
one in species are not all one in number; but things that are one 
in species are all one in genus, while things that are so in genus 
are not all one in species but are all one by analogy; while 
things that are one by analogy are not all one in genus. 

Evidently 'many' will have meanings opposite to those of 'one'; 
some things are many because they are not continuous, others 



2303 



because their matter - either the proximate matter or the 
ultimate - is divisible in kind, others because the definitions 
which state their essence are more than one. 



Things are said to 'be' (1) in an accidental sense, (2) by their own 
nature. 

(1) In an accidental sense, e.g. we say 'the righteous doer is 
musical', and 'the man is musical', and 'the musician is a man', 
just as we say 'the musician builds', because the builder 
happens to be musical or the musician to be a builder; for here 
'one thing is another' means 'one is an accident of another'. So 
in the cases we have mentioned; for when we say 'the man is 
musical' and 'the musician is a man', or 'he who is pale is 
musical' or 'the musician is pale', the last two mean that both 
attributes are accidents of the same thing; the first that the 
attribute is an accident of that which is, while 'the musical is a 
man' means that 'musical' is an accident of a man. (In this 
sense, too, the not-pale is said to be, because that of which it is 
an accident is.) Thus when one thing is said in an accidental 
sense to be another, this is either because both belong to the 
same thing, and this is, or because that to which the attribute 
belongs is, or because the subject which has as an attribute that 
of which it is itself predicated, itself is. 

(2) The kinds of essential being are precisely those that are 
indicated by the figures of predication; for the senses of 'being' 
are just as many as these figures. Since, then, some predicates 
indicate what the subject is, others its quality, others quantity, 
others relation, others activity or passivity, others its 'where', 
others its 'when', 'being' has a meaning answering to each of 



2304 



these. For there is no difference between 'the man is recovering' 
and 'the man recovers', nor between 'the man is walking or 
cutting' and 'the man walks' or 'cuts'; and similarly in all other 
cases. 

(3) Again, 'being' and 'is' mean that a statement is true, 'not 
being' that it is not true but false - and this alike in the case of 
affirmation and of negation; e.g. 'Socrates is musical' means 
that this is true, or 'Socrates is not-pale' means that this is true; 
but 'the diagonal of the square is not commensurate with the 
side' means that it is false to say it is. 

(4) Again, 'being' and 'that which is' mean that some of the 
things we have mentioned 'are' potentially, others in complete 
reality. For we say both of that which sees potentially and of 
that which sees actually, that it is 'seeing', and both of that 
which can actualize its knowledge and of that which is 
actualizing it, that it knows, and both of that to which rest is 
already present and of that which can rest, that it rests. And 
similarly in the case of substances; we say the Hermes is in the 
stone, and the half of the line is in the line, and we say of that 
which is not yet ripe that it is corn. When a thing is potential 
and when it is not yet potential must be explained elsewhere. 



8 

We call 'substance' (1) the simple bodies, i.e. earth and fire and 
water and everything of the sort, and in general bodies and the 
things composed of them, both animals and divine beings, and 
the parts of these. All these are called substance because they 
are not predicated of a subject but everything else is predicated 
of them. - (2) That which, being present in such things as are 
not predicated of a subject, is the cause of their being, as the 



2305 



soul is of the being of an animal. - (3) The parts which are 
present in such things, limiting them and marking them as 
individuals, and by whose destruction the whole is destroyed, 
as the body is by the destruction of the plane, as some say, and 
the plane by the destruction of the line; and in general number 
is thought by some to be of this nature; for if it is destroyed, 
they say, nothing exists, and it limits all things. - (4) The 
essence, the formula of which is a definition, is also called the 
substance of each thing. 

It follows, then, that 'substance' has two senses, (A) ultimate 
substratum, which is no longer predicated of anything else, and 
(B) that which, being a 'this', is also separable and of this nature 
is the shape or form of each thing. 



'The same' means (1) that which is the same in an accidental 
sense, e.g. 'the pale' and 'the musical' are the same because 
they are accidents of the same thing, and 'a man' and 'musical' 
because the one is an accident of the other; and 'the musical' is 
'a man' because it is an accident of the man. (The complex 
entity is the same as either of the simple ones and each of these 
is the same as it; for both 'the man' and 'the musical' are said to 
be the same as 'the musical man', and this the same as they.) 
This is why all of these statements are made not universally; for 
it is not true to say that every man is the same as 'the musical' 
(for universal attributes belong to things in virtue of their own 
nature, but accidents do not belong to them in virtue of their 
own nature); but of the individuals the statements are made 
without qualification. For 'Socrates' and 'musical Socrates' are 
thought to be the same; but 'Socrates' is not predicable of more 



2306 



than one subject, and therefore we do not say 'every Socrates' 
as we say 'every man'. 

Some things are said to be the same in this sense, others (2) are 
the same by their own nature, in as many senses as that which 
is one by its own nature is so; for both the things whose matter 
is one either in kind or in number, and those whose essence is 
one, are said to be the same. Clearly, therefore, sameness is a 
unity of the being either of more than one thing or of one thing 
when it is treated as more than one, ie. when we say a thing is 
the same as itself; for we treat it as two. 

Things are called 'other' if either their kinds or their matters or 
the definitions of their essence are more than one; and in 
general 'other' has meanings opposite to those of 'the same'. 

'Different' is applied (1) to those things which though other are 
the same in some respect, only not in number but either in 
species or in genus or by analogy; (2) to those whose genus is 
other, and to contraries, and to an things that have their 
otherness in their essence. 

Those things are called 'like' which have the same attributes in 
every respect, and those which have more attributes the same 
than different, and those whose quality is one; and that which 
shares with another thing the greater number or the more 
important of the attributes (each of them one of two contraries) 
in respect of which things are capable of altering, is like that 
other thing. The senses of 'unlike' are opposite to those of 'like'. 



2307 



10 

The term 'opposite' is applied to contradictories, and to 
contraries, and to relative terms, and to privation and 
possession, and to the extremes from which and into which 
generation and dissolution take place; and the attributes that 
cannot be present at the same time in that which is receptive of 
both, are said to be opposed, - either themselves of their 
constituents. Grey and white colour do not belong at the same 
time to the same thing; hence their constituents are opposed. 

The term 'contrary' is applied (1) to those attributes differing in 
genus which cannot belong at the same time to the same 
subject, (2) to the most different of the things in the same 
genus, (3) to the most different of the attributes in the same 
recipient subject, (4) to the most different of the things that fall 
under the same faculty, (5) to the things whose difference is 
greatest either absolutely or in genus or in species. The other 
things that are called contrary are so called, some because they 
possess contraries of the above kind, some because they are 
receptive of such, some because they are productive of or 
susceptible to such, or are producing or suffering them, or are 
losses or acquisitions, or possessions or privations, of such. 
Since 'one' and 'being' have many senses, the other terms 
which are derived from these, and therefore 'same', 'other', and 
'contrary', must correspond, so that they must be different for 
each category. 

The term 'other in species' is applied to things which being of 
the same genus are not subordinate the one to the other, or 
which being in the same genus have a difference, or which have 
a contrariety in their substance; and contraries are other than 
one another in species (either all contraries or those which are 
so called in the primary sense), and so are those things whose 
definitions differ in the infima species of the genus (e.g. man 



2308 



and horse are indivisible in genus, but their definitions are 
different), and those which being in the same substance have a 
difference. 'The same in species' has the various meanings 
opposite to these. 



11 

The words 'prior' and 'posterior' are applied (1) to some things 
(on the assumption that there is a first, i.e. a beginning, in each 
class) because they are nearer some beginning determined 
either absolutely and by nature, or by reference to something or 
in some place or by certain people; e.g. things are prior in place 
because they are nearer either to some place determined by 
nature (e.g. the middle or the last place), or to some chance 
object; and that which is farther is posterior. - Other things are 
prior in time; some by being farther from the present, i.e. in the 
case of past events (for the Trojan war is prior to the Persian, 
because it is farther from the present), others by being nearer 
the present, i.e. in the case of future events (for the Nemean 
games are prior to the Pythian, if we treat the present as 
beginning and first point, because they are nearer the present). 
- Other things are prior in movement; for that which is nearer 
the first mover is prior (e.g. the boy is prior to the man); and the 
prime mover also is a beginning absolutely. - Others are prior in 
power; for that which exceeds in power, i.e. the more powerful, 
is prior; and such is that according to whose will the other - i.e. 
the posterior - must follow, so that if the prior does not set it in 
motion the other does not move, and if it sets it in motion it 
does move; and here will is a beginning. - Others are prior in 
arrangement; these are the things that are placed at intervals in 
reference to some one definite thing according to some rule, e.g. 
in the chorus the second man is prior to the third, and in the 



2309 



lyre the second lowest string is prior to the lowest; for in the 
one case the leader and in the other the middle string is the 
beginning. 

These, then, are called prior in this sense, but (2) in another 
sense that which is prior for knowledge is treated as also 
absolutely prior; of these, the things that are prior in definition 
do not coincide with those that are prior in relation to 
perception. For in definition universals are prior, in relation to 
perception individuals. And in definition also the accident is 
prior to the whole, e.g. 'musical' to 'musical man', for the 
definition cannot exist as a whole without the part; yet 
musicalness cannot exist unless there is some one who is 
musical. 

(3) The attributes of prior things are called prior, e.g. 
straightness is prior to smoothness; for one is an attribute of a 
line as such, and the other of a surface. 

Some things then are called prior and posterior in this sense, 
others (4) in respect of nature and substance, i.e. those which 
can be without other things, while the others cannot be without 
them, - a distinction which Plato used. (If we consider the 
various senses of 'being', firstly the subject is prior, so that 
substance is prior; secondly, according as potency or complete 
reality is taken into account, different things are prior, for some 
things are prior in respect of potency, others in respect of 
complete reality, e.g. in potency the half line is prior to the 
whole line, and the part to the whole, and the matter to the 
concrete substance, but in complete reality these are posterior; 
for it is only when the whole has been dissolved that they will 
exist in complete reality.) In a sense, therefore, all things that 
are called prior and posterior are so called with reference to this 
fourth sense; for some things can exist without others in 
respect of generation, e.g. the whole without the parts, and 



2310 



others in respect of dissolution, e.g. the part without the whole. 
And the same is true in all other cases. 



12 

'Potency' means (1) a source of movement or change, which is in 
another thing than the thing moved or in the same thing qua 
other; e.g. the art of building is a potency which is not in the 
thing built, while the art of healing, which is a potency, may be 
in the man healed, but not in him qua healed. 'Potency' then 
means the source, in general, of change or movement in 
another thing or in the same thing qua other, and also (2) the 
source of a thing's being moved by another thing or by itself qua 
other. For in virtue of that principle, in virtue of which a patient 
suffers anything, we call it 'capable' of suffering; and this we do 
sometimes if it suffers anything at all, sometimes not in respect 
of everything it suffers, but only if it suffers a change for the 
better - (3) The capacity of performing this well or according to 
intention; for sometimes we say of those who merely can walk 
or speak but not well or not as they intend, that they cannot 
speak or walk. So too (4) in the case of passivity. - (5) The states 
in virtue of which things are absolutely impassive or 
unchangeable, or not easily changed for the worse, are called 
potencies; for things are broken and crushed and bent and in 
general destroyed not by having a potency but by not having 
one and by lacking something, and things are impassive with 
respect to such processes if they are scarcely and slightly 
affected by them, because of a 'potency' and because they 'can' 
do something and are in some positive state. 

'Potency' having this variety of meanings, so too the 'potent' or 
'capable' in one sense will mean that which can begin a 



2311 



movement (or a change in general, for even that which can 
bring things to rest is a 'potent' thing) in another thing or in 
itself qua other; and in one sense that over which something 
else has such a potency; and in one sense that which has a 
potency of changing into something, whether for the worse or 
for the better (for even that which perishes is thought to be 
'capable' of perishing, for it would not have perished if it had 
not been capable of it; but, as a matter of fact, it has a certain 
disposition and cause and principle which fits it to suffer this; 
sometimes it is thought to be of this sort because it has 
something, sometimes because it is deprived of something; but 
if privation is in a sense 'having' or 'habit', everything will be 
capable by having something, so that things are capable both by 
having a positive habit and principle, and by having the 
privation of this, if it is possible to have a privation; and if 
privation is not in a sense 'habit', 'capable' is used in two 
distinct senses); and a thing is capable in another sense because 
neither any other thing, nor itself qua other, has a potency or 
principle which can destroy it. Again, all of these are capable 
either merely because the thing might chance to happen or not 
to happen, or because it might do so well. This sort of potency is 
found even in lifeless things, e.g. in instruments; for we say one 
lyre can speak, and another cannot speak at all, if it has not a 
good tone. 

Incapacity is privation of capacity - i.e. of such a principle as 
has been described either in general or in the case of something 
that would naturally have the capacity, or even at the time 
when it would naturally already have it; for the senses in which 
we should call a boy and a man and a eunuch 'incapable of 
begetting' are distinct. - Again, to either kind of capacity there is 
an opposite incapacity - both to that which only can produce 
movement and to that which can produce it well. 



2312 



Some things, then, are called adunata in virtue of this kind of 
incapacity, while others are so in another sense; i.e. both 
dunaton and adunaton are used as follows. The impossible is 
that of which the contrary is of necessity true, e.g. that the 
diagonal of a square is commensurate with the side is 
impossible, because such a statement is a falsity of which the 
contrary is not only true but also necessary; that it is 
commensurate, then, is not only false but also of necessity false. 
The contrary of this, the possible, is found when it is not 
necessary that the contrary is false, e.g. that a man should be 
seated is possible; for that he is not seated is not of necessity 
false. The possible, then, in one sense, as has been said, means 
that which is not of necessity false; in one, that which is true; in 
one, that which may be true. - A 'potency' or 'power' in 
geometry is so called by a change of meaning. -These senses of 
'capable' or 'possible' involve no reference to potency. But the 
senses which involve a reference to potency all refer to the 
primary kind of potency; and this is a source of change in 
another thing or in the same thing qua other. For other things 
are called 'capable', some because something else has such a 
potency over them, some because it has not, some because it 
has it in a particular way. The same is true of the things that are 
incapable. Therefore the proper definition of the primary kind of 
potency will be 'a source of change in another thing or in the 
same thing qua other'. 



13 

'Quantum' means that which is divisible into two or more 
constituent parts of which each is by nature a 'one' and a 'this'. 
A quantum is a plurality if it is numerable, a magnitude if it is a 
measurable. 'Plurality' means that which is divisible potentially 



2313 



into non-continuous parts, 'magnitude' that which is divisible 
into continuous parts; of magnitude, that which is continuous 
in one dimension is length; in two breadth, in three depth. Of 
these, limited plurality is number, limited length is a line, 
breadth a surface, depth a solid. 

Again, some things are called quanta in virtue of their own 
nature, others incidentally; e.g. the line is a quantum by its own 
nature, the musical is one incidentally. Of the things that are 
quanta by their own nature some are so as substances, e.g. the 
line is a quantum (for 'a certain kind of quantum' is present in 
the definition which states what it is), and others are 
modifications and states of this kind of substance, e.g. much 
and little, long and short, broad and narrow, deep and shallow, 
heavy and light, and all other such attributes. And also great 
and small, and greater and smaller, both in themselves and 
when taken relatively to each other, are by their own nature 
attributes of what is quantitative; but these names are 
transferred to other things also. Of things that are quanta 
incidentally, some are so called in the sense in which it was said 
that the musical and the white were quanta, viz. because that to 
which musicalness and whiteness belong is a quantum, and 
some are quanta in the way in which movement and time are 
so; for these also are called quanta of a sort and continuous 
because the things of which these are attributes are divisible. I 
mean not that which is moved, but the space through which it 
is moved; for because that is a quantum movement also is a 
quantum, and because this is a quantum time is one. 



2314 



14 

'Quality' means (1) the differentia of the essence, e.g. man is an 
animal of a certain quality because he is two-footed, and the 
horse is so because it is four-footed; and a circle is a figure of 
particular quality because it is without angles, - which shows 
that the essential differentia is a quality. - This, then, is one 
meaning of quality - the differentia of the essence, but (2) there 
is another sense in which it applies to the unmovable objects of 
mathematics, the sense in which the numbers have a certain 
quality, e.g. the composite numbers which are not in one 
dimension only, but of which the plane and the solid are copies 
(these are those which have two or three factors); and in general 
that which exists in the essence of numbers besides quantity is 
quality; for the essence of each is what it is once, e.g. that of is 
not what it is twice or thrice, but what it is once; for 6 is once 6. 

(3) All the modifications of substances that move (e.g. heat and 
cold, whiteness and blackness, heaviness and lightness, and the 
others of the sort) in virtue of which, when they change, bodies 
are said to alter. (4) Quality in respect of virtue and vice, and in 
general, of evil and good. 

Quality, then, seems to have practically two meanings, and one 
of these is the more proper. The primary quality is the 
differentia of the essence, and of this the quality in numbers is 
a part; for it is a differentia of essences, but either not of things 
that move or not of them qua moving. Secondly, there are the 
modifications of things that move, qua moving, and the 
differentiae of movements. Virtue and vice fall among these 
modifications; for they indicate differentiae of the movement or 
activity, according to which the things in motion act or are 
acted on well or badly; for that which can be moved or act in 
one way is good, and that which can do so in another - the 
contrary - way is vicious. Good and evil indicate quality 



2315 



especially in living things, and among these especially in those 
which have purpose. 



15 

Things are 'relative' (1) as double to half, and treble to a third, 
and in general that which contains something else many times 
to that which is contained many times in something else, and 
that which exceeds to that which is exceeded; (2) as that which 
can heat to that which can be heated, and that which can cut to 
that which can be cut, and in general the active to the passive; 
(3) as the measurable to the measure, and the knowable to 
knowledge, and the perceptible to perception. 

(1) Relative terms of the first kind are numerically related either 
indefinitely or definitely, to numbers themselves or to 1. E.g. the 
double is in a definite numerical relation to 1, and that which is 
'many times as great' is in a numerical, but not a definite, 
relation to 1, i.e. not in this or in that numerical relation to it; 
the relation of that which is half as big again as something else 
to that something is a definite numerical relation to a number; 
that which is n+I/n times something else is in an indefinite 
relation to that something, as that which is 'many times as 
great' is in an indefinite relation to 1; the relation of that which 
exceeds to that which is exceeded is numerically quite 
indefinite; for number is always commensurate, and 'number' is 
not predicated of that which is not commensurate, but that 
which exceeds is, in relation to that which is exceeded, so much 
and something more; and this something is indefinite; for it 
can, indifferently, be either equal or not equal to that which is 
exceeded. - All these relations, then, are numerically expressed 
and are determinations of number, and so in another way are 



2316 



the equal and the like and the same. For all refer to unity. Those 
things are the same whose substance is one; those are like 
whose quality is one; those are equal whose quantity is one; 
and 1 is the beginning and measure of number, so that all these 
relations imply number, though not in the same way. 

(2) Things that are active or passive imply an active or a passive 
potency and the actualizations of the potencies; e.g. that which 
is capable of heating is related to that which is capable of being 
heated, because it can heat it, and, again, that which heats is 
related to that which is heated and that which cuts to that 
which is cut, in the sense that they actually do these things. But 
numerical relations are not actualized except in the sense 
which has been elsewhere stated; actualizations in the sense of 
movement they have not. Of relations which imply potency 
some further imply particular periods of time, e.g. that which 
has made is relative to that which has been made, and that 
which will make to that which will be made. For it is in this way 
that a father is called the father of his son; for the one has acted 
and the other has been acted on in a certain way. Further, some 
relative terms imply privation of potency, i.e. 'incapable' and 
terms of this sort, e.g. 'invisible'. 

Relative terms which imply number or potency, therefore, are all 
relative because their very essence includes in its nature a 
reference to something else, not because something else 
involves a reference to it; but (3) that which is measurable or 
knowable or thinkable is called relative because something else 
involves a reference to it. For 'that which is thinkable' implies 
that the thought of it is possible, but the thought is not relative 
to 'that of which it is the thought'; for we should then have said 
the same thing twice. Similarly sight is the sight of something, 
not 'of that of which it is the sight' (though of course it is true to 
say this); in fact it is relative to colour or to something else of 



2317 



the sort. But according to the other way of speaking the same 
thing would be said twice, - 'the sight is of that of which it is.' 

Things that are by their own nature called relative are called so 
sometimes in these senses, sometimes if the classes that 
include them are of this sort; e.g. medicine is a relative term 
because its genus, science, is thought to be a relative term. 
Further, there are the properties in virtue of which the things 
that have them are called relative, e.g. equality is relative 
because the equal is, and likeness because the like is. Other 
things are relative by accident; e.g. a man is relative because he 
happens to be double of something and double is a relative 
term; or the white is relative, if the same thing happens to be 
double and white. 



16 

What is called 'complete' is (1) that outside which it is not 
possible to find any, even one, of its parts; e.g. the complete 
time of each thing is that outside which it is not possible to find 
any time which is a part proper to it. - (2) That which in respect 
of excellence and goodness cannot be excelled in its kind; e.g. 
we have a complete doctor or a complete flute-player, when 
they lack nothing in respect of the form of their proper 
excellence. And thus, transferring the word to bad things, we 
speak of a complete scandal-monger and a complete thief; 
indeed we even call them good, i.e. a good thief and a good 
scandal-monger. And excellence is a completion; for each thing 
is complete and every substance is complete, when in respect of 
the form of its proper excellence it lacks no part of its natural 
magnitude. - (3) The things which have attained their end, this 
being good, are called complete; for things are complete in 



2318 



virtue of having attained their end. Therefore, since the end is 
something ultimate, we transfer the word to bad things and say 
a thing has been completely spoilt, and completely destroyed, 
when it in no wise falls short of destruction and badness, but is 
at its last point. This is why death, too, is by a figure of speech 
called the end, because both are last things. But the ultimate 
purpose is also an end. - Things, then, that are called complete 
in virtue of their own nature are so called in all these senses, 
some because in respect of goodness they lack nothing and 
cannot be excelled and no part proper to them can be found 
outside them, others in general because they cannot be 
exceeded in their several classes and no part proper to them is 
outside them; the others presuppose these first two kinds, and 
are called complete because they either make or have 
something of the sort or are adapted to it or in some way or 
other involve a reference to the things that are called complete 
in the primary sense. 



17 

'Limit' means (1) the last point of each thing, i.e. the first point 
beyond which it is not possible to find any part, and the first 
point within which every part is; (2) the form, whatever it may 
be, of a spatial magnitude or of a thing that has magnitude; (3) 
the end of each thing (and of this nature is that towards which 
the movement and the action are, not that from which they are 
- though sometimes it is both, that from which and that to 
which the movement is, i.e. the final cause); (4) the substance of 
each thing, and the essence of each; for this is the limit of 
knowledge; and if of knowledge, of the object also. Evidently, 
therefore, 'limit' has as many senses as 'beginning', and yet 



2319 



more; for the beginning is a limit, but not every limit is a 
beginning. 



18 

'That in virtue of which' has several meanings: - (1) the form or 
substance of each thing, e.g. that in virtue of which a man is 
good is the good itself, (2) the proximate subject in which it is 
the nature of an attribute to be found, e.g. colour in a surface. 
'That in virtue of which', then, in the primary sense is the form, 
and in a secondary sense the matter of each thing and the 
proximate substratum of each. - In general 'that in virtue of 
which' will found in the same number of senses as 'cause'; for 
we say indifferently (3) in virtue of what has he come?' or 'for 
what end has he come?'; and (4) in virtue of what has he 
inferred wrongly, or inferred?' or 'what is the cause of the 
inference, or of the wrong inference?' - Further (5) Kath' d is 
used in reference to position, e.g. 'at which he stands' or 'along 
which he walks; for all such phrases indicate place and 
position. 

Therefore 'in virtue of itself must likewise have several 
meanings. The following belong to a thing in virtue of itself: - (1) 
the essence of each thing, e.g. Callias is in virtue of himself 
Callias and what it was to be Callias; - (2) whatever is present in 
the 'what', e.g. Callias is in virtue of himself an animal. For 
'animal' is present in his definition; Callias is a particular 
animal. - (3) Whatever attribute a thing receives in itself directly 
or in one of its parts; e.g. a surface is white in virtue of itself, 
and a man is alive in virtue of himself; for the soul, in which life 
directly resides, is a part of the man. - (4) That which has no 
cause other than itself; man has more than one cause - animal, 



2320 



two-footed - but yet man is man in virtue of himself. - (5) 
Whatever attributes belong to a thing alone, and in so far as 
they belong to it merely by virtue of itself considered apart by 
itself. 



19 

'Disposition' means the arrangement of that which has parts, in 
respect either of place or of potency or of kind; for there must 
be a certain position, as even the word 'disposition' shows. 



20 

'Having' means (1) a kind of activity of the haver and of what he 
has - something like an action or movement. For when one 
thing makes and one is made, between them there is a making; 
so too between him who has a garment and the garment which 
he has there is a having. This sort of having, then, evidently we 
cannot have; for the process will go on to infinity, if it is to be 
possible to have the having of what we have. - (2) 'Having' or 
'habit' means a disposition according to which that which is 
disposed is either well or ill disposed, and either in itself or with 
reference to something else; e.g. health is a 'habit'; for it is such 
a disposition. - (3) We speak of a 'habit' if there is a portion of 
such a disposition; and so even the excellence of the parts is a 
'habit' of the whole thing. 



2321 



21 

'Affection' means (1) a quality in respect of which a thing can be 
altered, e.g. white and black, sweet and bitter, heaviness and 
lightness, and all others of the kind. - (2) The actualization of 
these - the already accomplished alterations. - (3) Especially, 
injurious alterations and movements, and, above all painful 
injuries. - (4) Misfortunes and painful experiences when on a 
large scale are called affections. 



22 

We speak of 'privation' (1) if something has not one of the 
attributes which a thing might naturally have, even if this thing 
itself would not naturally have it; e.g. a plant is said to be 
'deprived' of eyes. - (2) If, though either the thing itself or its 
genus would naturally have an attribute, it has it not; e.g. a blind 
man and a mole are in different senses 'deprived' of sight; the 
latter in contrast with its genus, the former in contrast with his 
own normal nature. - (3) If, though it would naturally have the 
attribute, and when it would naturally have it, it has it not; for 
blindness is a privation, but one is not 'blind' at any and every 
age, but only if one has not sight at the age at which one would 
naturally have it. Similarly a thing is called blind if it has not 
sight in the medium in which, and in respect of the organ in 
respect of which, and with reference to the object with 
reference to which, and in the circumstances in which, it would 
naturally have it. - (4) The violent taking away of anything is 
called privation. 

Indeed there are just as many kinds of privations as there are of 
words with negative prefixes; for a thing is called unequal 
because it has not equality though it would naturally have it, 



2322 



and invisible either because it has no colour at all or because it 
has a poor colour, and apodous either because it has no feet at 
all or because it has imperfect feet. Again, a privative term may 
be used because the thing has little of the attribute (and this 
means having it in a sense imperfectly), e.g. 'kernel-less'; or 
because it has it not easily or not well (e.g. we call a thing 
uncuttable not only if it cannot be cut but also if it cannot be cut 
easily or well); or because it has not the attribute at all; for it is 
not the one-eyed man but he who is sightless in both eyes that 
is called blind. This is why not every man is 'good' or 'bad', 'just' 
or 'unjust', but there is also an intermediate state. 



23 

To 'have' or 'hold' means many things: - (1) to treat a thing 
according to one's own nature or according to one's own 
impulse; so that fever is said to have a man, and tyrants to have 
their cities, and people to have the clothes they wear. - (2) That 
in which a thing is present as in something receptive of it is 
said to have the thing; e.g. the bronze has the form of the 
statue, and the body has the disease. - (3) As that which 
contains holds the things contained; for a thing is said to be 
held by that in which it is as in a container; e.g. we say that the 
vessel holds the liquid and the city holds men and the ship 
sailors; and so too that the whole holds the parts. - (4) That 
which hinders a thing from moving or acting according to its 
own impulse is said to hold it, as pillars hold the incumbent 
weights, and as the poets make Atlas hold the heavens, 
implying that otherwise they would collapse on the earth, as 
some of the natural philosophers also say. In this way also that 
which holds things together is said to hold the things it holds 



2323 



together, since they would otherwise separate, each according 
to its own impulse. 

'Being in something' has similar and corresponding meanings 
to 'holding' or 'having'. 



24 

'To come from something' means (1) to come from something 
as from matter, and this in two senses, either in respect of the 
highest genus or in respect of the lowest species; e.g. in a sense 
all things that can be melted come from water, but in a sense 
the statue comes from bronze. - (2) As from the first moving 
principle; e.g. 'what did the fight come from?' From abusive 
language, because this was the origin of the fight. - (3) From the 
compound of matter and shape, as the parts come from the 
whole, and the verse from the Iliad, and the stones from the 
house; (in every such case the whole is a compound of matter 
and shape,) for the shape is the end, and only that which 
attains an end is complete. - (4) As the form from its part, e.g. 
man from 'two-footed'and syllable from 'letter'; for this is a 
different sense from that in which the statue comes from 
bronze; for the composite substance comes from the sensible 
matter, but the form also comes from the matter of the form. - 
Some things, then, are said to come from something else in 
these senses; but (5) others are so described if one of these 
senses is applicable to a part of that other thing; e.g. the child 
comes from its father and mother, and plants come from the 
earth, because they come from a part of those things. - (6) It 
means coming after a thing in time, e.g. night comes from day 
and storm from fine weather, because the one comes after the 
other. Of these things some are so described because they admit 



2324 



of change into one another, as in the cases now mentioned; 
some merely because they are successive in time, e.g. the 
voyage took place 'from' the equinox, because it took place after 
the equinox, and the festival of the Thargelia comes 'from' the 
Dionysia, because after the Dionysia. 



25 

'Part' means (1) (a) that into which a quantum can in any way 
be divided; for that which is taken from a quantum qua 
quantum is always called a part of it, e.g. two is called in a sense 
a part of three. It means (b), of the parts in the first sense, only 
those which measure the whole; this is why two, though in one 
sense it is, in another is not, called a part of three. - (2) The 
elements into which a kind might be divided apart from the 
quantity are also called parts of it; for which reason we say the 
species are parts of the genus. - (3) The elements into which a 
whole is divided, or of which it consists - the 'whole' meaning 
either the form or that which has the form; e.g. of the bronze 
sphere or of the bronze cube both the bronze - i.e. the matter in 
which the form is - and the characteristic angle are parts. - (4) 
The elements in the definition which explains a thing are also 
parts of the whole; this is why the genus is called a part of the 
species, though in another sense the species is part of the 
genus. 



2325 



26 

'A whole' means (1) that from which is absent none of the parts 
of which it is said to be naturally a whole, and (2) that which so 
contains the things it contains that they form a unity; and this 
in two senses - either as being each severally one single thing, 
or as making up the unity between them. For (a) that which is 
true of a whole class and is said to hold good as a whole (which 
implies that it is a kind whole) is true of a whole in the sense 
that it contains many things by being predicated of each, and by 
all of them, e.g. man, horse, god, being severally one single 
thing, because all are living things. But (b) the continuous and 
limited is a whole, when it is a unity consisting of several parts, 
especially if they are present only potentially, but, failing this, 
even if they are present actually. Of these things themselves, 
those which are so by nature are wholes in a higher degree than 
those which are so by art, as we said in the case of unity also, 
wholeness being in fact a sort of oneness. 

Again (3) of quanta that have a beginning and a middle and an 
end, those to which the position does not make a difference are 
called totals, and those to which it does, wholes. Those which 
admit of both descriptions are both wholes and totals. These are 
the things whose nature remains the same after transposition, 
but whose form does not, e.g. wax or a coat; they are called both 
wholes and totals; for they have both characteristics. Water and 
all liquids and number are called totals, but 'the whole number' 
or 'the whole water' one does not speak of, except by an 
extension of meaning. To things, to which qua one the term 
'total' is applied, the term 'all' is applied when they are treated 
as separate; 'this total number,' 'all these units.' 



2326 



27 

It is not any chance quantitative thing that can be said to be 
'mutilated'; it must be a whole as well as divisible. For not only 
is two not 'mutilated' if one of the two ones is taken away (for 
the part removed by mutilation is never equal to the 
remainder), but in general no number is thus mutilated; for it is 
also necessary that the essence remain; if a cup is mutilated, it 
must still be a cup; but the number is no longer the same. 
Further, even if things consist of unlike parts, not even these 
things can all be said to be mutilated, for in a sense a number 
has unlike parts (e.g. two and three) as well as like; but in 
general of the things to which their position makes no 
difference, e.g. water or fire, none can be mutilated; to be 
mutilated, things must be such as in virtue of their essence 
have a certain position. Again, they must be continuous; for a 
musical scale consists of unlike parts and has position, but 
cannot become mutilated. Besides, not even the things that are 
wholes are mutilated by the privation of any part. For the parts 
removed must be neither those which determine the essence 
nor any chance parts, irrespective of their position; e.g. a cup is 
not mutilated if it is bored through, but only if the handle or a 
projecting part is removed, and a man is mutilated not if the 
flesh or the spleen is removed, but if an extremity is, and that 
not every extremity but one which when completely removed 
cannot grow again. Therefore baldness is not a mutilation. 



28 

The term 'race' or 'genus' is used (1) if generation of things 
which have the same form is continuous, e.g. 'while the race of 
men lasts' means 'while the generation of them goes on 



2327 



continuously'. - (2) It is used with reference to that which first 
brought things into existence; for it is thus that some are called 
Hellenes by race and others Ionians, because the former 
proceed from Hellen and the latter from Ion as their first 
begetter. And the word is used in reference to the begetter more 
than to the matter, though people also get a race-name from 
the female, e.g. 'the descendants of Pyrrha'. - (3) There is genus 
in the sense in which 'plane' is the genus of plane figures and 
solid' of solids; for each of the figures is in the one case a plane 
of such and such a kind, and in the other a solid of such and 
such a kind; and this is what underlies the differentiae. Again 
(4) in definitions the first constituent element, which is 
included in the 'what', is the genus, whose differentiae the 
qualities are said to be 'Genus' then is used in all these ways, (1) 
in reference to continuous generation of the same kind, (2) in 
reference to the first mover which is of the same kind as the 
things it moves, (3) as matter; for that to which the differentia 
or quality belongs is the substratum, which we call matter. 

Those things are said to be 'other in genus' whose proximate 
substratum is different, and which are not analysed the one 
into the other nor both into the same thing (e.g. form and 
matter are different in genus); and things which belong to 
different categories of being (for some of the things that are said 
to 'be' signify essence, others a quality, others the other 
categories we have before distinguished); these also are not 
analysed either into one another or into some one thing. 



29 

'The false' means (1) that which is false as a thing, and that (a) 
because it is not put together or cannot be put together, e.g. 



2328 



'that the diagonal of a square is commensurate with the side' or 
'that you are sitting'; for one of these is false always, and the 
other sometimes; it is in these two senses that they are non- 
existent, (b) There are things which exist, but whose nature it is 
to appear either not to be such as they are or to be things that 
do not exist, e.g. a sketch or a dream; for these are something, 
but are not the things the appearance of which they produce in 
us. We call things false in this way, then, - either because they 
themselves do not exist, or because the appearance which 
results from them is that of something that does not exist. 

(2) A false account is the account of non-existent objects, in so 
far as it is false. Hence every account is false when applied to 
something other than that of which it is true; e.g. the account of 
a circle is false when applied to a triangle. In a sense there is 
one account of each thing, i.e. the account of its essence, but in 
a sense there are many, since the thing itself and the thing itself 
with an attribute are in a sense the same, e.g. Socrates and 
musical Socrates (a false account is not the account of anything, 
except in a qualified sense). Hence Antisthenes was too simple- 
minded when he claimed that nothing could be described 
except by the account proper to it, - one predicate to one 
subject; from which the conclusion used to be drawn that there 
could be no contradiction, and almost that there could be no 
error. But it is possible to describe each thing not only by the 
account of itself, but also by that of something else. This may be 
done altogether falsely indeed, but there is also a way in which 
it may be done truly; e.g. eight may be described as a double 
number by the use of the definition of two. 

These things, then, are called false in these senses, but (3) a 
false man is one who is ready at and fond of such accounts, not 
for any other reason but for their own sake, and one who is 
good at impressing such accounts on other people, just as we 
say things are which produce a false appearance. This is why 



2329 



the proof in the Hippias that the same man is false and true is 
misleading. For it assumes that he is false who can deceive (i.e. 
the man who knows and is wise); and further that he who is 
willingly bad is better. This is a false result of induction - for a 
man who limps willingly is better than one who does so 
unwillingly - by 'limping' Plato means 'mimicking a limp', for if 
the man were lame willingly, he would presumably be worse in 
this case as in the corresponding case of moral character. 



30 

'Accident' means (1) that which attaches to something and can 
be truly asserted, but neither of necessity nor usually, e.g. if 
some one in digging a hole for a plant has found treasure. This - 
the finding of treasure - is for the man who dug the hole an 
accident; for neither does the one come of necessity from the 
other or after the other, nor, if a man plants, does he usually 
find treasure. And a musical man might be pale; but since this 
does not happen of necessity nor usually, we call it an accident. 
Therefore since there are attributes and they attach to subjects, 
and some of them attach to these only in a particular place and 
at a particular time, whatever attaches to a subject, but not 
because it was this subject, or the time this time, or the place 
this place, will be an accident. Therefore, too, there is no definite 
cause for an accident, but a chance cause, i.e. an indefinite one. 
Going to Aegina was an accident for a man, if he went not in 
order to get there, but because he was carried out of his way by 
a storm or captured by pirates. The accident has happened or 
exists, - not in virtue of the subject's nature, however, but of 
something else; for the storm was the cause of his coming to a 
place for which he was not sailing, and this was Aegina. 



2330 



'Accident' has also (2) another meaning, i.e. all that attaches to 
each thing in virtue of itself but is not in its essence, as having 
its angles equal to two right angles attaches to the triangle. And 
accidents of this sort may be eternal, but no accident of the 
other sort is. This is explained elsewhere. 



BookE 



We are seeking the principles and the causes of the things that 
are, and obviously of them qua being. For, while there is a cause 
of health and of good condition, and the objects of mathematics 
have first principles and elements and causes, and in general 
every science which is ratiocinative or at all involves reasoning 
deals with causes and principles, more or less precise, all these 
sciences mark off some particular being - some genus, and 
inquire into this, but not into being simply nor qua being, nor 
do they offer any discussion of the essence of the things of 
which they treat; but starting from the essence - some making 
it plain to the senses, others assuming it as a hypothesis - they 
then demonstrate, more or less cogently, the essential attributes 
of the genus with which they deal. It is obvious, therefore, that 
such an induction yields no demonstration of substance or of 
the essence, but some other way of exhibiting it. And similarly 
the sciences omit the question whether the genus with which 



2331 



they deal exists or does not exist, because it belongs to the 
same kind of thinking to show what it is and that it is. 

And since natural science, like other sciences, is in fact about 
one class of being, i.e. to that sort of substance which has the 
principle of its movement and rest present in itself, evidently it 
is neither practical nor productive. For in the case of things 
made the principle is in the maker - it is either reason or art or 
some faculty, while in the case of things done it is in the doer - 
viz. will, for that which is done and that which is willed are the 
same. Therefore, if all thought is either practical or productive 
or theoretical, physics must be a theoretical science, but it will 
theorize about such being as admits of being moved, and about 
substance - as defined for the most part only as not separable 
from matter. Now, we must not fail to notice the mode of being 
of the essence and of its definition, for, without this, inquiry is 
but idle. Of things defined, i.e. of 'whats', some are like 'snub', 
and some like 'concave'. And these differ because 'snub' is 
bound up with matter (for what is snub is a concave nose), 
while concavity is independent of perceptible matter. If then all 
natural things are a analogous to the snub in their nature; e.g. 
nose, eye, face, flesh, bone, and, in general, animal; leaf, root, 
bark, and, in general, plant (for none of these can be defined 
without reference to movement - they always have matter), it is 
clear how we must seek and define the 'what' in the case of 
natural objects, and also that it belongs to the student of nature 
to study even soul in a certain sense, i.e. so much of it as is not 
independent of matter. 

That physics, then, is a theoretical science, is plain from these 
considerations. Mathematics also, however, is theoretical; but 
whether its objects are immovable and separable from matter, is 
not at present clear; still, it is clear that some mathematical 
theorems consider them qua immovable and qua separable 
from matter. But if there is something which is eternal and 



2332 



immovable and separable, clearly the knowledge of it belongs to 
a theoretical science, - not, however, to physics (for physics 
deals with certain movable things) nor to mathematics, but to a 
science prior to both. For physics deals with things which exist 
separately but are not immovable, and some parts of 
mathematics deal with things which are immovable but 
presumably do not exist separately, but as embodied in matter; 
while the first science deals with things which both exist 
separately and are immovable. Now all causes must be eternal, 
but especially these; for they are the causes that operate on so 
much of the divine as appears to us. There must, then, be three 
theoretical philosophies, mathematics, physics, and what we 
may call theology, since it is obvious that if the divine is present 
anywhere, it is present in things of this sort. And the highest 
science must deal with the highest genus. Thus, while the 
theoretical sciences are more to be desired than the other 
sciences, this is more to be desired than the other theoretical 
sciences. For one might raise the question whether first 
philosophy is universal, or deals with one genus, i.e. some one 
kind of being; for not even the mathematical sciences are all 
alike in this respect, - geometry and astronomy deal with a 
certain particular kind of thing, while universal mathematics 
applies alike to all. We answer that if there is no substance 
other than those which are formed by nature, natural science 
will be the first science; but if there is an immovable substance, 
the science of this must be prior and must be first philosophy, 
and universal in this way, because it is first. And it will belong to 
this to consider being qua being - both what it is and the 
attributes which belong to it qua being. 



2333 



But since the unqualified term 'being' has several meanings, of 
which one was seen' to be the accidental, and another the true 
('non-being' being the false), while besides these there are the 
figures of predication (e.g. the 'what', quality, quantity, place, 
time, and any similar meanings which 'being' may have), and 
again besides all these there is that which 'is' potentially or 
actually: - since 'being' has many meanings, we must say 
regarding the accidental, that there can be no scientific 
treatment of it. This is confirmed by the fact that no science 
practical, productive, or theoretical troubles itself about it. For 
on the one hand he who produces a house does not produce all 
the attributes that come into being along with the house; for 
these are innumerable; the house that has been made may 
quite well be pleasant for some people, hurtful for some, and 
useful to others, and different - to put it shortly from all things 
that are; and the science of building does not aim at producing 
any of these attributes. And in the same way the geometer does 
not consider the attributes which attach thus to figures, nor 
whether 'triangle' is different from 'triangle whose angles are 
equal to two right angles'. -And this happens naturally enough; 
for the accidental is practically a mere name. And so Plato was 
in a sense not wrong in ranking sophistic as dealing with that 
which is not. For the arguments of the sophists deal, we may 
say, above all with the accidental; e.g. the question whether 
'musical' and 'lettered' are different or the same, and whether 
'musical Coriscus' and 'Coriscus' are the same, and whether 
'everything which is, but is not eternal, has come to be', with 
the paradoxical conclusion that if one who was musical has 
come to be lettered, he must also have been lettered and have 
come to be musical, and all the other arguments of this sort; the 
accidental is obviously akin to non-being. And this is clear also 
from arguments such as the following: things which are in 
another sense come into being and pass out of being by a 



2334 



process, but things which are accidentally do not. But still we 
must, as far as we can, say further, regarding the accidental, 
what its nature is and from what cause it proceeds; for it will 
perhaps at the same time become clear why there is no science 
of it. 

Since, among things which are, some are always in the same 
state and are of necessity (not necessity in the sense of 
compulsion but that which we assert of things because they 
cannot be otherwise), and some are not of necessity nor always, 
but for the most part, this is the principle and this the cause of 
the existence of the accidental; for that which is neither always 
nor for the most part, we call accidental. For instance, if in the 
dog-days there is wintry and cold weather, we say this is an 
accident, but not if there is sultry heat, because the latter is 
always or for the most part so, but not the former. And it is an 
accident that a man is pale (for this is neither always nor for the 
most part so), but it is not by accident that he is an animal. And 
that the builder produces health is an accident, because it is the 
nature not of the builder but of the doctor to do this, - but the 
builder happened to be a doctor. Again, a confectioner, aiming 
at giving pleasure, may make something wholesome, but not in 
virtue of the confectioner's art; and therefore we say 'it was an 
accident', and while there is a sense in which he makes it, in 
the unqualified sense he does not. For to other things answer 
faculties productive of them, but to accidental results there 
corresponds no determinate art nor faculty; for of things which 
are or come to be by accident, the cause also is accidental. 
Therefore, since not all things either are or come to be of 
necessity and always, but, the majority of things are for the 
most part, the accidental must exist; for instance a pale man is 
not always nor for the most part musical, but since this 
sometimes happens, it must be accidental (if not, everything 
will be of necessity). The matter, therefore, which is capable of 
being otherwise than as it usually is, must be the cause of the 



2335 



accidental. And we must take as our starting-point the question 
whether there is nothing that is neither always nor for the most 
part. Surely this is impossible. There is, then, besides these 
something which is fortuitous and accidental. But while the 
usual exists, can nothing be said to be always, or are there 
eternal things? This must be considered later,' but that there is 
no science of the accidental is obvious; for all science is either 
of that which is always or of that which is for the most part. (For 
how else is one to learn or to teach another? The thing must be 
determined as occurring either always or for the most part, e.g. 
that honey-water is useful for a patient in a fever is true for the 
most part.) But that which is contrary to the usual law science 
will be unable to state, i.e. when the thing does not happen, 
e.g.'on the day of new moon'; for even that which happens on 
the day of new moon happens then either always or for the 
most part; but the accidental is contrary to such laws. We have 
stated, then, what the accidental is, and from what cause it 
arises, and that there is no science which deals with it. 



That there are principles and causes which are generable and 
destructible without ever being in course of being generated or 
destroyed, is obvious. For otherwise all things will be of 
necessity, since that which is being generated or destroyed 
must have a cause which is not accidentally its cause. Will A 
exist or not? It will if B happens; and if not, not. And B will exist 
if C happens. And thus if time is constantly subtracted from a 
limited extent of time, one will obviously come to the present. 
This man, then, will die by violence, if he goes out; and he will 
do this if he gets thirsty; and he will get thirsty if something 
else happens; and thus we shall come to that which is now 



2336 



present, or to some past event. For instance, he will go out if he 
gets thirsty; and he will get thirsty if he is eating pungent food; 
and this is either the case or not; so that he will of necessity die, 
or of necessity not die. And similarly if one jumps over to past 
events, the same account will hold good; for this - I mean the 
past condition - is already present in something. Everything, 
therefore, that will be, will be of necessity; e.g. it is necessary 
that he who lives shall one day die; for already some condition 
has come into existence, e.g. the presence of contraries in the 
same body. But whether he is to die by disease or by violence is 
not yet determined, but depends on the happening of 
something else. Clearly then the process goes back to a certain 
starting-point, but this no longer points to something further. 
This then will be the starting-point for the fortuitous, and will 
have nothing else as cause of its coming to be. But to what sort 
of starting-point and what sort of cause we thus refer the 
fortuitous - whether to matter or to the purpose or to the 
motive power, must be carefully considered. 



Let us dismiss accidental being; for we have sufficiently 
determined its nature. But since that which is in the sense of 
being true, or is not in the sense of being false, depends on 
combination and separation, and truth and falsity together 
depend on the allocation of a pair of contradictory judgements 
(for the true judgement affirms where the subject and predicate 
really are combined, and denies where they are separated, while 
the false judgement has the opposite of this allocation; it is 
another question, how it happens that we think things together 
or apart; by 'together' and 'apart' I mean thinking them so that 
there is no succession in the thoughts but they become a unity); 



2337 



for falsity and truth are not in things - it is not as if the good 
were true, and the bad were in itself false - but in thought; 
while with regard to simple concepts and 'whats' falsity and 
truth do not exist even in thought - this being so, we must 
consider later what has to be discussed with regard to that 
which is or is not in this sense. But since the combination and 
the separation are in thought and not in the things, and that 
which is in this sense is a different sort of 'being' from the 
things that are in the full sense (for the thought attaches or 
removes either the subject's 'what' or its having a certain 
quality or quantity or something else), that which is 
accidentally and that which is in the sense of being true must 
be dismissed. For the cause of the former is indeterminate, and 
that of the latter is some affection of the thought, and both are 
related to the remaining genus of being, and do not indicate the 
existence of any separate class of being. Therefore let these be 
dismissed, and let us consider the causes and the principles of 
being itself, qua being. (It was clear in our discussion of the 
various meanings of terms, that 'being' has several meanings.) 



BookZ 



There are several senses in which a thing may be said to 'be', as 
we pointed out previously in our book on the various senses of 
words;' for in one sense the 'being' meant is 'what a thing is' or 



2338 



a 'this', and in another sense it means a quality or quantity or 
one of the other things that are predicated as these are. While 
'being' has all these senses, obviously that which 'is' primarily is 
the 'what', which indicates the substance of the thing. For when 
we say of what quality a thing is, we say that it is good or bad, 
not that it is three cubits long or that it is a man; but when we 
say what it is, we do not say 'white' or 'hot' or 'three cubits 
long', but 'a man' or 'a 'god'. And all other things are said to be 
because they are, some of them, quantities of that which is in 
this primary sense, others qualities of it, others affections of it, 
and others some other determination of it. And so one might 
even raise the question whether the words 'to walk', 'to be 
healthy', 'to sit' imply that each of these things is existent, and 
similarly in any other case of this sort; for none of them is 
either self-subsistent or capable of being separated from 
substance, but rather, if anything, it is that which walks or sits 
or is healthy that is an existent thing. Now these are seen to be 
more real because there is something definite which underlies 
them (i.e. the substance or individual), which is implied in such 
a predicate; for we never use the word 'good' or 'sitting' without 
implying this. Clearly then it is in virtue of this category that 
each of the others also is. Therefore that which is primarily, i.e. 
not in a qualified sense but without qualification, must be 
substance. 

Now there are several senses in which a thing is said to be first; 
yet substance is first in every sense - (1) in definition, (2) in 
order of knowledge, (3) in time. For (3) of the other categories 
none can exist independently, but only substance. And (1) in 
definition also this is first; for in the definition of each term the 
definition of its substance must be present. And (2) we think we 
know each thing most fully, when we know what it is, e.g. what 
man is or what fire is, rather than when we know its quality, its 
quantity, or its place; since we know each of these predicates 
also, only when we know what the quantity or the quality is. 



2339 



And indeed the question which was raised of old and is raised 
now and always, and is always the subject of doubt, viz. what 
being is, is just the question, what is substance? For it is this 
that some assert to be one, others more than one, and that 
some assert to be limited in number, others unlimited. And so 
we also must consider chiefly and primarily and almost 
exclusively what that is which is in this sense. 



Substance is thought to belong most obviously to bodies; and so 
we say that not only animals and plants and their parts are 
substances, but also natural bodies such as fire and water and 
earth and everything of the sort, and all things that are either 
parts of these or composed of these (either of parts or of the 
whole bodies), e.g. the physical universe and its parts, stars and 
moon and sun. But whether these alone are substances, or there 
are also others, or only some of these, or others as well, or none 
of these but only some other things, are substances, must be 
considered. Some think the limits of body, i.e. surface, line, 
point, and unit, are substances, and more so than body or the 
solid. 

Further, some do not think there is anything substantial besides 
sensible things, but others think there are eternal substances 
which are more in number and more real; e.g. Plato posited two 
kinds of substance - the Forms and objects of mathematics - as 
well as a third kind, viz. the substance of sensible bodies. And 
Speusippus made still more kinds of substance, beginning with 
the One, and assuming principles for each kind of substance, 
one for numbers, another for spatial magnitudes, and then 
another for the soul; and by going on in this way he multiplies 



2340 



the kinds of substance. And some say Forms and numbers have 
the same nature, and the other things come after them - lines 
and planes - until we come to the substance of the material 
universe and to sensible bodies. 

Regarding these matters, then, we must inquire which of the 
common statements are right and which are not right, and 
what substances there are, and whether there are or are not any 
besides sensible substances, and how sensible substances exist, 
and whether there is a substance capable of separate existence 
(and if so why and how) or no such substance, apart from 
sensible substances; and we must first sketch the nature of 
substance. 



The word 'substance' is applied, if not in more senses, still at 
least to four main objects; for both the essence and the 
universal and the genus, are thought to be the substance of 
each thing, and fourthly the substratum. Now the substratum is 
that of which everything else is predicated, while it is itself not 
predicated of anything else. And so we must first determine the 
nature of this; for that which underlies a thing primarily is 
thought to be in the truest sense its substance. And in one 
sense matter is said to be of the nature of substratum, in 
another, shape, and in a third, the compound of these. (By the 
matter I mean, for instance, the bronze, by the shape the 
pattern of its form, and by the compound of these the statue, 
the concrete whole.) Therefore if the form is prior to the matter 
and more real, it will be prior also to the compound of both, for 
the same reason. 



2341 



We have now outlined the nature of substance, showing that it 
is that which is not predicated of a stratum, but of which all 
else is predicated. But we must not merely state the matter 
thus; for this is not enough. The statement itself is obscure, and 
further, on this view, matter becomes substance. For if this is 
not substance, it baffles us to say what else is. When all else is 
stripped off evidently nothing but matter remains. For while the 
rest are affections, products, and potencies of bodies, length, 
breadth, and depth are quantities and not substances (for a 
quantity is not a substance), but the substance is rather that to 
which these belong primarily. But when length and breadth and 
depth are taken away we see nothing left unless there is 
something that is bounded by these; so that to those who 
consider the question thus matter alone must seem to be 
substance. By matter I mean that which in itself is neither a 
particular thing nor of a certain quantity nor assigned to any 
other of the categories by which being is determined. For there 
is something of which each of these is predicated, whose being 
is different from that of each of the predicates (for the 
predicates other than substance are predicated of substance, 
while substance is predicated of matter). Therefore the ultimate 
substratum is of itself neither a particular thing nor of a 
particular quantity nor otherwise positively characterized; nor 
yet is it the negations of these, for negations also will belong to 
it only by accident. 

If we adopt this point of view, then, it follows that matter is 
substance. But this is impossible; for both separability and 
'thisness' are thought to belong chiefly to substance. And so 
form and the compound of form and matter would be thought 
to be substance, rather than matter. The substance 
compounded of both, i.e. of matter and shape, may be 
dismissed; for it is posterior and its nature is obvious. And 
matter also is in a sense manifest. But we must inquire into the 
third kind of substance; for this is the most perplexing. 



2342 



Some of the sensible substances are generally admitted to be 
substances, so that we must look first among these. For it is an 
advantage to advance to that which is more knowable. For 
learning proceeds for all in this way - through that which is less 
knowable by nature to that which is more knowable; and just as 
in conduct our task is to start from what is good for each and 
make what is without qualification good good for each, so it is 
our task to start from what is more knowable to oneself and 
make what is knowable by nature knowable to oneself. Now 
what is knowable and primary for particular sets of people is 
often knowable to a very small extent, and has little or nothing 
of reality. But yet one must start from that which is barely 
knowable but knowable to oneself, and try to know what is 
knowable without qualification, passing, as has been said, by 
way of those very things which one does know. 



Since at the start we distinguished the various marks by which 
we determine substance, and one of these was thought to be 
the essence, we must investigate this. And first let us make 
some linguistic remarks about it. The essence of each thing is 
what it is said to be propter se. For being you is not being 
musical, since you are not by your very nature musical. What, 
then, you are by your very nature is your essence. 

Nor yet is the whole of this the essence of a thing; not that 
which is propter se as white is to a surface, because being a 
surface is not identical with being white. But again the 
combination of both - 'being a white surface' - is not the 
essence of surface, because 'surface' itself is added. The 
formula, therefore, in which the term itself is not present but its 



2343 



meaning is expressed, this is the formula of the essence of each 
thing. Therefore if to be a white surface is to be a smooth 
surface, to be white and to be smooth are one and the same. 

But since there are also compounds answering to the other 
categories (for there is a substratum for each category, e.g. for 
quality, quantity, time, place, and motion), we must inquire 
whether there is a formula of the essence of each of them, i.e. 
whether to these compounds also there belongs an essence, e.g. 
'white man'. Let the compound be denoted by 'cloak'. What is 
the essence of cloak? But, it may be said, this also is not a 
propter se expression. We reply that there are just two ways in 
which a predicate may fail to be true of a subject propter se, and 
one of these results from the addition, and the other from the 
omission, of a determinant. One kind of predicate is not propter 
se because the term that is being defined is combined with 
another determinant, e.g. if in defining the essence of white one 
were to state the formula of white man; the other because in 
the subject another determinant is combined with that which is 
expressed in the formula, e.g. if 'cloak' meant 'white man', and 
one were to define cloak as white; white man is white indeed, 
but its essence is not to be white. 

But is being-a-cloak an essence at all? Probably not. For the 
essence is precisely what something is; but when an attribute is 
asserted of a subject other than itself, the complex is not 
precisely what some 'this' is, e.g. white man is not precisely 
what some 'this' is, since thisness belongs only to substances. 
Therefore there is an essence only of those things whose 
formula is a definition. But we have a definition not where we 
have a word and a formula identical in meaning (for in that case 
all formulae or sets of words would be definitions; for there will 
be some name for any set of words whatever, so that even the 
Iliad will be a definition), but where there is a formula of 
something primary; and primary things are those which do not 



2344 



imply the predication of one element in them of another 
element. Nothing, then, which is not a species of a genus will 
have an essence - only species will have it, for these are thought 
to imply not merely that the subject participates in the attribute 
and has it as an affection, or has it by accident; but for ever 
thing else as well, if it has a name, there be a formula of its 
meaning - viz. that this attribute belongs to this subject; or 
instead of a simple formula we shall be able to give a more 
accurate one; but there will be no definition nor essence. 

Or has 'definition', like 'what a thing is', several meanings? 
'What a thing is' in one sense means substance and the 'this', in 
another one or other of the predicates, quantity, quality, and the 
like. For as 'is' belongs to all things, not however in the same 
sense, but to one sort of thing primarily and to others in a 
secondary way, so too 'what a thing is' belongs in the simple 
sense to substance, but in a limited sense to the other 
categories. For even of a quality we might ask what it is, so that 
quality also is a 'what a thing is', - not in the simple sense, 
however, but just as, in the case of that which is not, some say, 
emphasizing the linguistic form, that that is which is not is-not 
is simply, but is non-existent; so too with quality. 

We must no doubt inquire how we should express ourselves on 
each point, but certainly not more than how the facts actually 
stand. And so now also, since it is evident what language we 
use, essence will belong, just as 'what a thing is' does, primarily 
and in the simple sense to substance, and in a secondary way to 
the other categories also, - not essence in the simple sense, but 
the essence of a quality or of a quantity. For it must be either by 
an equivocation that we say these are, or by adding to and 
taking from the meaning of 'are' (in the way in which that 
which is not known may be said to be known), - the truth being 
that we use the word neither ambiguously nor in the same 
sense, but just as we apply the word 'medical' by virtue of a 



2345 



reference to one and the same thing, not meaning one and the 
same thing, nor yet speaking ambiguously; for a patient and an 
operation and an instrument are called medical neither by an 
ambiguity nor with a single meaning, but with reference to a 
common end. But it does not matter at all in which of the two 
ways one likes to describe the facts; this is evident, that 
definition and essence in the primary and simple sense belong 
to substances. Still they belong to other things as well, only not 
in the primary sense. For if we suppose this it does not follow 
that there is a definition of every word which means the same 
as any formula; it must mean the same as a particular kind of 
formula; and this condition is satisfied if it is a formula of 
something which is one, not by continuity like the Iliad or the 
things that are one by being bound together, but in one of the 
main senses of 'one', which answer to the senses of 'is'; now 
'that which is' in one sense denotes a 'this', in another a 
quantity, in another a quality. And so there can be a formula or 
definition even of white man, but not in the sense in which 
there is a definition either of white or of a substance. 



It is a difficult question, if one denies that a formula with an 
added determinant is a definition, whether any of the terms 
that are not simple but coupled will be definable. For we must 
explain them by adding a determinant. E.g. there is the nose, 
and concavity, and snubness, which is compounded out of the 
two by the presence of the one in the other, and it is not by 
accident that the nose has the attribute either of concavity or of 
snubness, but in virtue of its nature; nor do they attach to it as 
whiteness does to Callias, or to man (because Callias, who 
happens to be a man, is white), but as 'male' attaches to animal 



2346 



and 'equal' to quantity, and as all so-called 'attributes propter 
se' attach to their subjects. And such attributes are those in 
which is involved either the formula or the name of the subject 
of the particular attribute, and which cannot be explained 
without this; e.g. white can be explained apart from man, but 
not female apart from animal. Therefore there is either no 
essence and definition of any of these things, or if there is, it is 
in another sense, as we have said. 

But there is also a second difficulty about them. For if snub nose 
and concave nose are the same thing, snub and concave will be 
the thing; but if snub and concave are not the same (because it 
is impossible to speak of snubness apart from the thing of 
which it is an attribute propter se, for snubness is concavity-in- 
a-nose), either it is impossible to say 'snub nose' or the same 
thing will have been said twice, concave-nose nose; for snub 
nose will be concave-nose nose. And so it is absurd that such 
things should have an essence; if they have, there will be an 
infinite regress; for in snub-nose nose yet another 'nose' will be 
involved. 

Clearly, then, only substance is definable. For if the other 
categories also are definable, it must be by addition of a 
determinant, e.g. the qualitative is defined thus, and so is the 
odd, for it cannot be defined apart from number; nor can female 
be defined apart from animal. (When I say 'by addition' I mean 
the expressions in which it turns out that we are saying the 
same thing twice, as in these instances.) And if this is true, 
coupled terms also, like 'odd number', will not be definable (but 
this escapes our notice because our formulae are not accurate.). 
But if these also are definable, either it is in some other way or, 
as we definition and essence must be said to have more than 
one sense. Therefore in one sense nothing will have a definition 
and nothing will have an essence, except substances, but in 
another sense other things will have them. Clearly, then, 



2347 



definition is the formula of the essence, and essence belongs to 
substances either alone or chiefly and primarily and in the 
unqualified sense. 



We must inquire whether each thing and its essence are the 
same or different. This is of some use for the inquiry concerning 
substance; for each thing is thought to be not different from its 
substance, and the essence is said to be the substance of each 
thing. 

Now in the case of accidental unities the two would be 
generally thought to be different, e.g. white man would be 
thought to be different from the essence of white man. For if 
they are the same, the essence of man and that of white man 
are also the same; for a man and a white man are the same 
thing, as people say, so that the essence of white man and that 
of man would be also the same. But perhaps it does not follow 
that the essence of accidental unities should be the same as 
that of the simple terms. For the extreme terms are not in the 
same way identical with the middle term. But perhaps this 
might be thought to follow, that the extreme terms, the 
accidents, should turn out to be the same, e.g. the essence of 
white and that of musical; but this is not actually thought to be 
the case. 

But in the case of so-called self-subsistent things, is a thing 
necessarily the same as its essence? E.g. if there are some 
substances which have no other substances nor entities prior to 
them - substances such as some assert the Ideas to be? - If the 
essence of good is to be different from good-itself, and the 
essence of animal from animal-itself, and the essence of being 



2348 



from being-itself, there will, firstly, be other substances and 
entities and Ideas besides those which are asserted, and, 
secondly, these others will be prior substances, if essence is 
substance. And if the posterior substances and the prior are 
severed from each other, (a) there will be no knowledge of the 
former, and (b) the latter will have no being. (By 'severed' I 
mean, if the good-itself has not the essence of good, and the 
latter has not the property of being good.) For (a) there is 
knowledge of each thing only when we know its essence. And 
(b) the case is the same for other things as for the good; so that 
if the essence of good is not good, neither is the essence of 
reality real, nor the essence of unity one. And all essences alike 
exist or none of them does; so that if the essence of reality is 
not real, neither is any of the others. Again, that to which the 
essence of good does not belong is not good. - The good, then, 
must be one with the essence of good, and the beautiful with 
the essence of beauty, and so with all things which do not 
depend on something else but are self-subsistent and primary. 
For it is enough if they are this, even if they are not Forms; or 
rather, perhaps, even if they are Forms. (At the same time it is 
clear that if there are Ideas such as some people say there are, it 
will not be substratum that is substance; for these must be 
substances, but not predicable of a substratum; for if they were 
they would exist only by being participated in.) 

Each thing itself, then, and its essence are one and the same in 
no merely accidental way, as is evident both from the preceding 
arguments and because to know each thing, at least, is just to 
know its essence, so that even by the exhibition of instances it 
becomes clear that both must be one. 

(But of an accidental term, e.g.'the musical' or 'the white', since 
it has two meanings, it is not true to say that it itself is identical 
with its essence; for both that to which the accidental quality 
belongs, and the accidental quality, are white, so that in a sense 



2349 



the accident and its essence are the same, and in a sense they 
are not; for the essence of white is not the same as the man or 
the white man, but it is the same as the attribute white.) 

The absurdity of the separation would appear also if one were 
to assign a name to each of the essences; for there would be yet 
another essence besides the original one, e.g. to the essence of 
horse there will belong a second essence. Yet why should not 
some things be their essences from the start, since essence is 
substance? But indeed not only are a thing and its essence one, 
but the formula of them is also the same, as is clear even from 
what has been said; for it is not by accident that the essence of 
one, and the one, are one. Further, if they are to be different, the 
process will go on to infinity; for we shall have (1) the essence of 
one, and (2) the one, so that to terms of the former kind the 
same argument will be applicable. 

Clearly, then, each primary and self-subsistent thing is one and 
the same as its essence. The sophistical objections to this 
position, and the question whether Socrates and to be Socrates 
are the same thing, are obviously answered by the same 
solution; for there is no difference either in the standpoint from 
which the question would be asked, or in that from which one 
could answer it successfully. We have explained, then, in what 
sense each thing is the same as its essence and in what sense it 
is not. 



Of things that come to be, some come to be by nature, some by 
art, some spontaneously. Now everything that comes to be 
comes to be by the agency of something and from something 
and comes to be something. And the something which I say it 



2350 



comes to be may be found in any category; it may come to be 
either a 'this' or of some size or of some quality or somewhere. 

Now natural comings to be are the comings to be of those 
things which come to be by nature; and that out of which they 
come to be is what we call matter; and that by which they come 
to be is something which exists naturally; and the something 
which they come to be is a man or a plant or one of the things 
of this kind, which we say are substances if anything is - all 
things produced either by nature or by art have matter; for each 
of them is capable both of being and of not being, and this 
capacity is the matter in each - and, in general, both that from 
which they are produced is nature, and the type according to 
which they are produced is nature (for that which is produced, 
e.g. a plant or an animal, has a nature), and so is that by which 
they are produced - the so-called 'formal' nature, which is 
specifically the same (though this is in another individual); for 
man begets man. 

Thus, then, are natural products produced; all other productions 
are called 'makings'. And all makings proceed either from art or 
from a faculty or from thought. Some of them happen also 
spontaneously or by luck just as natural products sometimes 
do; for there also the same things sometimes are produced 
without seed as well as from seed. Concerning these cases, 
then, we must inquire later, but from art proceed the things of 
which the form is in the soul of the artist. (By form I mean the 
essence of each thing and its primary substance.) For even 
contraries have in a sense the same form; for the substance of a 
privation is the opposite substance, e.g. health is the substance 
of disease (for disease is the absence of health); and health is 
the formula in the soul or the knowledge of it. The healthy 
subject is produced as the result of the following train of 
thought: - since this is health, if the subject is to be healthy this 
must first be present, e.g. a uniform state of body, and if this is 



2351 



to be present, there must be heat; and the physician goes on 
thinking thus until he reduces the matter to a final something 
which he himself can produce. Then the process from this point 
onward, i.e. the process towards health, is called a 'making'. 
Therefore it follows that in a sense health comes from health 
and house from house, that with matter from that without 
matter; for the medical art and the building art are the form of 
health and of the house, and when I speak of substance without 
matter I mean the essence. 

Of the productions or processes one part is called thinking and 
the other making, - that which proceeds from the starting-point 
and the form is thinking, and that which proceeds from the 
final step of the thinking is making. And each of the other, 
intermediate, things is produced in the same way. I mean, for 
instance, if the subject is to be healthy his bodily state must be 
made uniform. What then does being made uniform imply? 
This or that. And this depends on his being made warm. What 
does this imply? Something else. And this something is present 
potentially; and what is present potentially is already in the 
physician's power. 

The active principle then and the starting point for the process 
of becoming healthy is, if it happens by art, the form in the soul, 
and if spontaneously, it is that, whatever it is, which starts the 
making, for the man who makes by art, as in healing the 
starting-point is perhaps the production of warmth (and this 
the physician produces by rubbing). Warmth in the body, then, is 
either a part of health or is followed (either directly or through 
several intermediate steps) by something similar which is a part 
of health; and this, viz. that which produces the part of health, 
is the limiting-point - and so too with a house (the stones are 
the limiting-point here) and in all other cases. Therefore, as the 
saying goes, it is impossible that anything should be produced if 
there were nothing existing before. Obviously then some part of 



2352 



the result will pre-exist of necessity; for the matter is a part; for 
this is present in the process and it is this that becomes 
something. But is the matter an element even in the formula? 
We certainly describe in both ways what brazen circles are; we 
describe both the matter by saying it is brass, and the form by 
saying that it is such and such a figure; and figure is the 
proximate genus in which it is placed. The brazen circle, then, 
has its matter in its formula. 

As for that out of which as matter they are produced, some 
things are said, when they have been produced, to be not that 
but 'thaten'; e.g. the statue is not gold but golden. And a healthy 
man is not said to be that from which he has come. The reason 
is that though a thing comes both from its privation and from 
its substratum, which we call its matter (e.g. what becomes 
healthy is both a man and an invalid), it is said to come rather 
from its privation (e.g. it is from an invalid rather than from a 
man that a healthy subject is produced). And so the healthy 
subject is not said to he an invalid, but to be a man, and the 
man is said to be healthy. But as for the things whose privation 
is obscure and nameless, e.g. in brass the privation of a 
particular shape or in bricks and timber the privation of 
arrangement as a house, the thing is thought to be produced 
from these materials, as in the former case the healthy man is 
produced from an invalid. And so, as there also a thing is not 
said to be that from which it comes, here the statue is not said 
to be wood but is said by a verbal change to be wooden, not 
brass but brazen, not gold but golden, and the house is said to 
be not bricks but bricken (though we should not say without 
qualification, if we looked at the matter carefully, even that a 
statue is produced from wood or a house from bricks, because 
coming to be implies change in that from which a thing comes 
to be, and not permanence). It is for this reason, then, that we 
use this way of speaking. 



2353 



8 

Since anything which is produced is produced by something 
(and this I call the starting-point of the production), and from 
something (and let this be taken to be not the privation but the 
matter; for the meaning we attach to this has already been 
explained), and since something is produced (and this is either 
a sphere or a circle or whatever else it may chance to be), just as 
we do not make the substratum (the brass), so we do not make 
the sphere, except incidentally, because the brazen sphere is a 
sphere and we make the forme. For to make a 'this' is to make a 
'this' out of the substratum in the full sense of the word. (I 
mean that to make the brass round is not to make the round or 
the sphere, but something else, i.e. to produce this form in 
something different from itself. For if we make the form, we 
must make it out of something else; for this was assumed. E.g. 
we make a brazen sphere; and that in the sense that out of this, 
which is brass, we make this other, which is a sphere.) If, then, 
we also make the substratum itself, clearly we shall make it in 
the same way, and the processes of making will regress to 
infinity. Obviously then the form also, or whatever we ought to 
call the shape present in the sensible thing, is not produced, nor 
is there any production of it, nor is the essence produced; for 
this is that which is made to be in something else either by art 
or by nature or by some faculty. But that there is a brazen 
sphere, this we make. For we make it out of brass and the 
sphere; we bring the form into this particular matter, and the 
result is a brazen sphere. But if the essence of sphere in general 
is to be produced, something must be produced out of 
something. For the product will always have to be divisible, and 
one part must be this and another that; I mean the one must be 



2354 



matter and the other form. If, then, a sphere is 'the figure whose 
circumference is at all points equidistant from the centre', part 
of this will be the medium in which the thing made will be, and 
part will be in that medium, and the whole will be the thing 
produced, which corresponds to the brazen sphere. It is obvious, 
then, from what has been said, that that which is spoken of as 
form or substance is not produced, but the concrete thing which 
gets its name from this is produced, and that in everything 
which is generated matter is present, and one part of the thing 
is matter and the other form. 

Is there, then, a sphere apart from the individual spheres or a 
house apart from the bricks? Rather we may say that no 'this' 
would ever have been coming to be, if this had been so, but that 
the 'form' means the 'such', and is not a 'this' - a definite thing; 
but the artist makes, or the father begets, a 'such' out of a 'this'; 
and when it has been begotten, it is a 'this such'. And the whole 
'this', Callias or Socrates, is analogous to 'this brazen sphere', 
but man and animal to 'brazen sphere' in general. Obviously, 
then, the cause which consists of the Forms (taken in the sense 
in which some maintain the existence of the Forms, i.e. if they 
are something apart from the individuals) is useless, at least 
with regard to comings-to-be and to substances; and the Forms 
need not, for this reason at least, be self-subsistent substances. 
In some cases indeed it is even obvious that the begetter is of 
the same kind as the begotten (not, however, the same nor one 
in number, but in form), i.e. in the case of natural products (for 
man begets man), unless something happens contrary to 
nature, e.g. the production of a mule by a horse. (And even these 
cases are similar; for that which would be found to be common 
to horse and ass, the genus next above them, has not received a 
name, but it would doubtless be both in fact something like a 
mule.) Obviously, therefore, it is quite unnecessary to set up a 
Form as a pattern (for we should have looked for Forms in these 
cases if in any; for these are substances if anything is so); the 



2355 



begetter is adequate to the making of the product and to the 
causing of the form in the matter. And when we have the whole, 
such and such a form in this flesh and in these bones, this is 
Callias or Socrates; and they are different in virtue of their 
matter (for that is different), but the same in form; for their 
form is indivisible. 



The question might be raised, why some things are produced 
spontaneously as well as by art, e.g. health, while others are not, 
e.g. a house. The reason is that in some cases the matter which 
governs the production in the making and producing of any 
work of art, and in which a part of the product is present, - 
some matter is such as to be set in motion by itself and some is 
not of this nature, and of the former kind some can move itself 
in the particular way required, while other matter is incapable 
of this; for many things can be set in motion by themselves but 
not in some particular way, e.g. that of dancing. The things, 
then, whose matter is of this sort, e.g. stones, cannot be moved 
in the particular way required, except by something else, but in 
another way they can move themselves - and so it is with fire. 
Therefore some things will not exist apart from some one who 
has the art of making them, while others will; for motion will be 
started by these things which have not the art but can 
themselves be moved by other things which have not the art or 
with a motion starting from a part of the product. 

And it is clear also from what has been said that in a sense 
every product of art is produced from a thing which shares its 
name (as natural products are produced), or from a part of itself 
which shares its name (e.g. the house is produced from a house, 



2356 



qua produced by reason; for the art of building is the form of 
the house), or from something which contains a art of it, - if we 
exclude things produced by accident; for the cause of the thing's 
producing the product directly per se is a part of the product. 
The heat in the movement caused heat in the body, and this is 
either health, or a part of health, or is followed by a part of 
health or by health itself. And so it is said to cause health, 
because it causes that to which health attaches as a 
consequence. 

Therefore, as in syllogisms, substance is the starting-point of 
everything. It is from 'what a thing is' that syllogisms start; and 
from it also we now find processes of production to start. 

Things which are formed by nature are in the same case as 
these products of art. For the seed is productive in the same 
way as the things that work by art; for it has the form 
potentially, and that from which the seed comes has in a sense 
the same name as the offspring only in a sense, for we must not 
expect parent and offspring always to have exactly the same 
name, as in the production of 'human being' from 'human' for a 
'woman' also can be produced by a 'man' - unless the offspring 
be an imperfect form; which is the reason why the parent of a 
mule is not a mule. The natural things which (like the artificial 
objects previously considered) can be produced spontaneously 
are those whose matter can be moved even by itself in the way 
in which the seed usually moves it; those things which have not 
such matter cannot be produced except from the parent 
animals themselves. 

But not only regarding substance does our argument prove that 
its form does not come to be, but the argument applies to all the 
primary classes alike, i.e. quantity, quality, and the other 
categories. For as the brazen sphere comes to be, but not the 
sphere nor the brass, and so too in the case of brass itself, if it 



2357 



comes to be, it is its concrete unity that comes to be (for the 
matter and the form must always exist before), so is it both in 
the case of substance and in that of quality and quantity and 
the other categories likewise; for the quality does not come to 
be, but the wood of that quality, and the quantity does not come 
to be, but the wood or the animal of that size. But we may learn 
from these instances a peculiarity of substance, that there must 
exist beforehand in complete reality another substance which 
produces it, e.g. an animal if an animal is produced; but it is not 
necessary that a quality or quantity should pre-exist otherwise 
than potentially. 



10 

Since a definition is a formula, and every formula has parts, and 
as the formula is to the thing, so is the part of the formula to 
the part of the thing, the question is already being asked 
whether the formula of the parts must be present in the 
formula of the whole or not. For in some cases the formulae of 
the parts are seen to be present, and in some not. The formula 
of the circle does not include that of the segments, but that of 
the syllable includes that of the letters; yet the circle is divided 
into segments as the syllable is into letters. - And further if the 
parts are prior to the whole, and the acute angle is a part of the 
right angle and the finger a part of the animal, the acute angle 
will be prior to the right angle and finger to the man. But the 
latter are thought to be prior; for in formula the parts are 
explained by reference to them, and in respect also of the power 
of existing apart from each other the wholes are prior to the 
parts. 



2358 



Perhaps we should rather say that 'part' is used in several 
senses. One of these is 'that which measures another thing in 
respect of quantity'. But let this sense be set aside; let us inquire 
about the parts of which substance consists. If then matter is 
one thing, form another, the compound of these a third, and 
both the matter and the form and the compound are substance 
even the matter is in a sense called part of a thing, while in a 
sense it is not, but only the elements of which the formula of 
the form consists. E.g. of concavity flesh (for this is the matter 
in which it is produced) is not a part, but of snubness it is a part; 
and the bronze is a part of the concrete statue, but not of the 
statue when this is spoken of in the sense of the form. (For the 
form, or the thing as having form, should be said to be the 
thing, but the material element by itself must never be said to 
be so.) And so the formula of the circle does not include that of 
the segments, but the formula of the syllable includes that of 
the letters; for the letters are parts of the formula of the form, 
and not matter, but the segments are parts in the sense of 
matter on which the form supervenes; yet they are nearer the 
form than the bronze is when roundness is produced in bronze. 
But in a sense not even every kind of letter will be present in the 
formula of the syllable, e.g. particular waxen letters or the 
letters as movements in the air; for in these also we have 
already something that is part of the syllable only in the sense 
that it is its perceptible matter. For even if the line when divided 
passes away into its halves, or the man into bones and muscles 
and flesh, it does not follow that they are composed of these as 
parts of their essence, but rather as matter; and these are parts 
of the concrete thing, but not also of the form, i.e. of that to 
which the formula refers; wherefore also they are not present in 
the formulae. In one kind of formula, then, the formula of such 
parts will be present, but in another it must not be present, 
where the formula does not refer to the concrete object. For it is 
for this reason that some things have as their constituent 



2359 



principles parts into which they pass away, while some have 
not. Those things which are the form and the matter taken 
together, e.g. the snub, or the bronze circle, pass away into these 
materials, and the matter is a part of them; but those things 
which do not involve matter but are without matter, and whose 
formulae are formulae of the form only, do not pass away, - 
either not at all or at any rate not in this way. Therefore these 
materials are principles and parts of the concrete things, while 
of the form they are neither parts nor principles. And therefore 
the clay statue is resolved into clay and the ball into bronze and 
Callias into flesh and bones, and again the circle into its 
segments; for there is a sense of 'circle' in which involves 
matter. For 'circle' is used ambiguously, meaning both the circle, 
unqualified, and the individual circle, because there is no name 
peculiar to the individuals. 

The truth has indeed now been stated, but still let us state it yet 
more clearly, taking up the question again. The parts of the 
formula, into which the formula is divided, are prior to it, either 
all or some of them. The formula of the right angle, however, 
does not include the formula of the acute, but the formula of 
the acute includes that of the right angle; for he who defines 
the acute uses the right angle; for the acute is 'less than a right 
angle'. The circle and the semicircle also are in a like relation; 
for the semicircle is defined by the circle; and so is the finger by 
the whole body, for a finger is 'such and such a part of a man'. 
Therefore the parts which are of the nature of matter, and into 
which as its matter a thing is divided, are posterior; but those 
which are of the nature of parts of the formula, and of the 
substance according to its formula, are prior, either all or some 
of them. And since the soul of animals (for this is the substance 
of a living being) is their substance according to the formula, i.e. 
the form and the essence of a body of a certain kind (at least we 
shall define each part, if we define it well, not without reference 
to its function, and this cannot belong to it without perception), 



2360 



so that the parts of soul are prior, either all or some of them, to 
the concrete 'animal', and so too with each individual animal; 
and the body and parts are posterior to this, the essential 
substance, and it is not the substance but the concrete thing 
that is divided into these parts as its matter: - this being so, to 
the concrete thing these are in a sense prior, but in a sense they 
are not. For they cannot even exist if severed from the whole; 
for it is not a finger in any and every state that is the finger of a 
living thing, but a dead finger is a finger only in name. Some 
parts are neither prior nor posterior to the whole, i.e. those 
which are dominant and in which the formula, i.e. the essential 
substance, is immediately present, e.g. perhaps the heart or the 
brain; for it does not matter in the least which of the two has 
this quality. But man and horse and terms which are thus 
applied to individuals, but universally, are not substance but 
something composed of this particular formula and this 
particular matter treated as universal; and as regards the 
individual, Socrates already includes in him ultimate individual 
matter; and similarly in all other cases. 'A part' may be a part 
either of the form (i.e. of the essence), or of the compound of 
the form and the matter, or of the matter itself. But only the 
parts of the form are parts of the formula, and the formula is of 
the universal; for 'being a circle' is the same as the circle, and 
'being a soul' the same as the soul. But when we come to the 
concrete thing, e.g. this circle, i.e. one of the individual circles, 
whether perceptible or intelligible (I mean by intelligible circles 
the mathematical, and by perceptible circles those of bronze 
and of wood), - of these there is no definition, but they are 
known by the aid of intuitive thinking or of perception; and 
when they pass out of this complete realization it is not clear 
whether they exist or not; but they are always stated and 
recognized by means of the universal formula. But matter is 
unknowable in itself. And some matter is perceptible and some 
intelligible, perceptible matter being for instance bronze and 



2361 



wood and all matter that is changeable, and intelligible matter 
being that which is present in perceptible things not qua 
perceptible, i.e. the objects of mathematics. 

We have stated, then, how matters stand with regard to whole 
and part, and their priority and posteriority. But when any one 
asks whether the right angle and the circle and the animal are 
prior, or the things into which they are divided and of which 
they consist, i.e. the parts, we must meet the inquiry by saying 
that the question cannot be answered simply. For if even bare 
soul is the animal or the living thing, or the soul of each 
individual is the individual itself, and 'being a circle' is the 
circle, and 'being a right angle' and the essence of the right 
angle is the right angle, then the whole in one sense must be 
called posterior to the art in one sense, i.e. to the parts included 
in the formula and to the parts of the individual right angle (for 
both the material right angle which is made of bronze, and that 
which is formed by individual lines, are posterior to their parts); 
while the immaterial right angle is posterior to the parts 
included in the formula, but prior to those included in the 
particular instance, and the question must not be answered 
simply. If, however, the soul is something different and is not 
identical with the animal, even so some parts must, as we have 
maintained, be called prior and others must not. 



11 

Another question is naturally raised, viz. what sort of parts 
belong to the form and what sort not to the form, but to the 
concrete thing. Yet if this is not plain it is not possible to define 
any thing; for definition is of the universal and of the form. If 
then it is not evident what sort of parts are of the nature of 



2362 



matter and what sort are not, neither will the formula of the 
thing be evident. In the case of things which are found to occur 
in specifically different materials, as a circle may exist in bronze 
or stone or wood, it seems plain that these, the bronze or the 
stone, are no part of the essence of the circle, since it is found 
apart from them. Of things which are not seen to exist apart, 
there is no reason why the same may not be true, just as if all 
circles that had ever been seen were of bronze; for none the less 
the bronze would be no part of the form; but it is hard to 
eliminate it in thought. E.g. the form of man is always found in 
flesh and bones and parts of this kind; are these then also parts 
of the form and the formula? No, they are matter; but because 
man is not found also in other matters we are unable to 
perform the abstraction. 

Since this is thought to be possible, but it is not clear when it is 
the case, some people already raise the question even in the 
case of the circle and the triangle, thinking that it is not right to 
define these by reference to lines and to the continuous, but 
that all these are to the circle or the triangle as flesh and bones 
are to man, and bronze or stone to the statue; and they reduce 
all things to numbers, and they say the formula of 'line' is that 
of 'two'. And of those who assert the Ideas some make 'two' the 
line-itself, and others make it the Form of the line; for in some 
cases they say the Form and that of which it is the Form are the 
same, e.g. 'two' and the Form of two; but in the case of 'line' 
they say this is no longer so. 

It follows then that there is one Form for many things whose 
form is evidently different (a conclusion which confronted the 
Pythagoreans also); and it is possible to make one thing the 
Form-itself of all, and to hold that the others are not Forms; but 
thus all things will be one. 



2363 



We have pointed out, then, that the question of definitions 
contains some difficulty, and why this is so. And so to reduce all 
things thus to Forms and to eliminate the matter is useless 
labour; for some things surely are a particular form in a 
particular matter, or particular things in a particular state. And 
the comparison which Socrates the younger used to make in 
the case of 'animal' is not sound; for it leads away from the 
truth, and makes one suppose that man can possibly exist 
without his parts, as the circle can without the bronze. But the 
case is not similar; for an animal is something perceptible, and 
it is not possible to define it without reference to movement - 
nor, therefore, without reference to the parts' being in a certain 
state. For it is not a hand in any and every state that is a part of 
man, but only when it can fulfil its work, and therefore only 
when it is alive; if it is not alive it is not a part. 

Regarding the objects of mathematics, why are the formulae of 
the parts not parts of the formulae of the wholes; e.g. why are 
not the semicircles included in the formula of the circle? It 
cannot be said, 'because these parts are perceptible things'; for 
they are not. But perhaps this makes no difference; for even 
some things which are not perceptible must have matter; 
indeed there is some matter in everything which is not an 
essence and a bare form but a 'this'. The semicircles, then, will 
not be parts of the universal circle, but will be parts of the 
individual circles, as has been said before; for while one kind of 
matter is perceptible, there is another which is intelligible. 

It is clear also that the soul is the primary substance and the 
body is matter, and man or animal is the compound of both 
taken universally; and 'Socrates' or 'Coriscus', if even the soul of 
Socrates may be called Socrates, has two meanings (for some 
mean by such a term the soul, and others mean the concrete 
thing), but if 'Socrates' or 'Coriscus' means simply this 



2364 



particular soul and this particular body, the individual is 
analogous to the universal in its composition. 

Whether there is, apart from the matter of such substances, 
another kind of matter, and one should look for some substance 
other than these, e.g. numbers or something of the sort, must be 
considered later. For it is for the sake of this that we are trying 
to determine the nature of perceptible substances as well, since 
in a sense the inquiry about perceptible substances is the work 
of physics, i.e. of second philosophy; for the physicist must 
come to know not only about the matter, but also about the 
substance expressed in the formula, and even more than about 
the other. And in the case of definitions, how the elements in 
the formula are parts of the definition, and why the definition is 
one formula (for clearly the thing is one, but in virtue of what is 
the thing one, although it has parts?), - this must be considered 
later. 

What the essence is and in what sense it is independent, has 
been stated universally in a way which is true of every case, and 
also why the formula of the essence of some things contains 
the parts of the thing defined, while that of others does not. 
And we have stated that in the formula of the substance the 
material parts will not be present (for they are not even parts of 
the substance in that sense, but of the concrete substance; but 
of this there is in a sense a formula, and in a sense there is not; 
for there is no formula of it with its matter, for this is indefinite, 
but there is a formula of it with reference to its primary 
substance - e.g. in the case of man the formula of the soul - , for 
the substance is the indwelling form, from which and the 
matter the so-called concrete substance is derived; e.g. 
concavity is a form of this sort, for from this and the nose arise 
'snub nose' and 'snubness'); but in the concrete substance, e.g. a 
snub nose or Callias, the matter also will be present. And we 
have stated that the essence and the thing itself are in some 



2365 



cases the same; ie. in the case of primary substances, e.g. 
curvature and the essence of curvature if this is primary. (By a 
'primary' substance I mean one which does not imply the 
presence of something in something else, i.e. in something that 
underlies it which acts as matter.) But things which are of the 
nature of matter, or of wholes that include matter, are not the 
same as their essences, nor are accidental unities like that of 
'Socrates' and 'musical'; for these are the same only by accident. 



12 

Now let us treat first of definition, in so far as we have not 
treated of it in the Analytics; for the problem stated in them is 
useful for our inquiries concerning substance. I mean this 
problem: - wherein can consist the unity of that, the formula of 
which we call a definition, as for instance, in the case of man, 
'two-footed animal'; for let this be the formula of man. Why, 
then, is this one, and not many, viz. 'animal' and 'two-footed? 
For in the case of 'man' and 'pale' there is a plurality when one 
term does not belong to the other, but a unity when it does 
belong and the subject, man, has a certain attribute; for then a 
unity is produced and we have 'the pale man'. In the present 
case, on the other hand, one does not share in the other; the 
genus is not thought to share in its differentiae (for then the 
same thing would share in contraries; for the differentiae by 
which the genus is divided are contrary). And even if the genus 
does share in them, the same argument applies, since the 
differentiae present in man are many, e.g. endowed with feet, 
two-footed, featherless. Why are these one and not many? Not 
because they are present in one thing; for on this principle a 
unity can be made out of all the attributes of a thing. But surely 
all the attributes in the definition must be one; for the 



2366 



definition is a single formula and a formula of substance, so 
that it must be a formula of some one thing; for substance 
means a 'one' and a 'this', as we maintain. 

We must first inquire about definitions reached by the method 
of divisions. There is nothing in the definition except the first- 
named and the differentiae. The other genera are the first genus 
and along with this the differentiae that are taken with it, e.g. 
the first may be 'animal', the next 'animal which is two-footed', 
and again 'animal which is two-footed and featherless', and 
similarly if the definition includes more terms. And in general it 
makes no difference whether it includes many or few terms, - 
nor, therefore, whether it includes few or simply two; and of the 
two the one is differentia and the other genus; e.g. in 'two- 
footed animal' 'animal' is genus, and the other is differentia. 

If then the genus absolutely does not exist apart from the 
species-of-a-genus, or if it exists but exists as matter (for the 
voice is genus and matter, but its differentiae make the species, 
i.e. the letters, out of it), clearly the definition is the formula 
which comprises the differentiae. 

But it is also necessary that the division be by the differentia of 
the diferentia; e.g. 'endowed with feet' is a differentia of 
'animal'; again the differentia of 'animal endowed with feet' 
must be of it qua endowed with feet. Therefore we must not say, 
if we are to speak rightly, that of that which is endowed with 
feet one part has feathers and one is featherless (if we do this 
we do it through incapacity); we must divide it only into cloven- 
footed and not cloven; for these are differentiae in the foot; 
cloven-footedness is a form of footedness. And the process 
wants always to go on so till it reaches the species that contain 
no differences. And then there will be as many kinds of foot as 
there are differentiae, and the kinds of animals endowed with 
feet will be equal in number to the differentiae. If then this is so, 



2367 



clearly the last differentia will be the substance of the thing and 
its definition, since it is not right to state the same things more 
than once in our definitions; for it is superfluous. And this does 
happen; for when we say 'animal endowed with feet and two- 
footed' we have said nothing other than 'animal having feet, 
having two feet'; and if we divide this by the proper division, we 
shall be saying the same thing more than once - as many times 
as there are differentiae. 

If then a differentia of a differentia be taken at each step, one 
differentia - the last - will be the form and the substance; but if 
we divide according to accidental qualities, e.g. if we were to 
divide that which is endowed with feet into the white and the 
black, there will be as many differentiae as there are cuts. 
Therefore it is plain that the definition is the formula which 
contains the differentiae, or, according to the right method, the 
last of these. This would be evident, if we were to change the 
order of such definitions, e.g. of that of man, saying 'animal 
which is two-footed and endowed with feet'; for 'endowed with 
feet' is superfluous when 'two-footed' has been said. But there 
is no order in the substance; for how are we to think the one 
element posterior and the other prior? Regarding the 
definitions, then, which are reached by the method of divisions, 
let this suffice as our first attempt at stating their nature. 



13 

Let us return to the subject of our inquiry, which is substance. 
As the substratum and the essence and the compound of these 
are called substance, so also is the universal. About two of these 
we have spoken; both about the essence and about the 
substratum, of which we have said that it underlies in two 



2368 



senses, either being a 'this' - which is the way in which an 
animal underlies its attributes - or as the matter underlies the 
complete reality. The universal also is thought by some to be in 
the fullest sense a cause, and a principle; therefore let us attack 
the discussion of this point also. For it seems impossible that 
any universal term should be the name of a substance. For 
firstly the substance of each thing is that which is peculiar to it, 
which does not belong to anything else; but the universal is 
common, since that is called universal which is such as to 
belong to more than one thing. Of which individual then will 
this be the substance? Either of all or of none; but it cannot be 
the substance of all. And if it is to be the substance of one, this 
one will be the others also; for things whose substance is one 
and whose essence is one are themselves also one. 

Further, substance means that which is not predicable of a 
subject, but the universal is predicable of some subject always. 

But perhaps the universal, while it cannot be substance in the 
way in which the essence is so, can be present in this; e.g. 
'animal' can be present in 'man' and 'horse'. Then clearly it is a 
formula of the essence. And it makes no difference even if it is 
not a formula of everything that is in the substance; for none 
the less the universal will be the substance of something, as 
'man' is the substance of the individual man in whom it is 
present, so that the same result will follow once more; for the 
universal, e.g. 'animal', will be the substance of that in which it 
is present as something peculiar to it. And further it is 
impossible and absurd that the 'this', i.e. the substance, if it 
consists of parts, should not consist of substances nor of what 
is a 'this', but of quality; for that which is not substance, i.e. the 
quality, will then be prior to substance and to the 'this'. Which is 
impossible; for neither in formula nor in time nor in coming to 
be can the modifications be prior to the substance; for then they 
will also be separable from it. Further, Socrates will contain a 



2369 



substance present in a substance, so that this will be the 
substance of two things. And in general it follows, if man and 
such things are substance, that none of the elements in their 
formulae is the substance of anything, nor does it exist apart 
from the species or in anything else; I mean, for instance, that 
no 'animal' exists apart from the particular kinds of animal, nor 
does any other of the elements present in formulae exist apart. 

If, then, we view the matter from these standpoints, it is plain 
that no universal attribute is a substance, and this is plain also 
from the fact that no common predicate indicates a 'this', but 
rather a 'such'. If not, many difficulties follow and especially the 
'third man'. 

The conclusion is evident also from the following consideration. 
A substance cannot consist of substances present in it in 
complete reality; for things that are thus in complete reality two 
are never in complete reality one, though if they are potentially 
two, they can be one (e.g. the double line consists of two halves 
- potentially; for the complete realization of the halves divides 
them from one another); therefore if the substance is one, it will 
not consist of substances present in it and present in this way, 
which Democritus describes rightly; he says one thing cannot be 
made out of two nor two out of one; for he identifies substances 
with his indivisible magnitudes. It is clear therefore that the 
same will hold good of number, if number is a synthesis of 
units, as is said by some; for two is either not one, or there is no 
unit present in it in complete reality. But our result involves a 
difficulty. If no substance can consist of universals because a 
universal indicates a 'such', not a 'this', and if no substance can 
be composed of substances existing in complete reality, every 
substance would be incomposite, so that there would not even 
be a formula of any substance. But it is thought by all and was 
stated long ago that it is either only, or primarily, substance that 
can defined; yet now it seems that not even substance can. 



2370 



There cannot, then, be a definition of anything; or in a sense 
there can be, and in a sense there cannot. And what we are 
saying will be plainer from what follows. 



14 

It is clear also from these very facts what consequence 
confronts those who say the Ideas are substances capable of 
separate existence, and at the same time make the Form consist 
of the genus and the differentiae. For if the Forms exist and 
'animal' is present in 'man' and 'horse', it is either one and the 
same in number, or different. (In formula it is clearly one; for he 
who states the formula will go through the formula in either 
case.) If then there is a 'man-in-himself who is a 'this' and 
exists apart, the parts also of which he consists, e.g. 'animal' 
and 'two-footed', must indicate 'thises', and be capable of 
separate existence, and substances; therefore 'animal', as well 
as 'man', must be of this sort. 

Now (1) if the 'animal' in 'the horse' and in 'man' is one and the 
same, as you are with yourself, (a) how will the one in things 
that exist apart be one, and how will this 'animal' escape being 
divided even from itself? 

Further, (b) if it is to share in 'two-footed' and 'many-footed', an 
impossible conclusion follows; for contrary attributes will 
belong at the same time to it although it is one and a 'this'. If it 
is not to share in them, what is the relation implied when one 
says the animal is two-footed or possessed of feet? But perhaps 
the two things are 'put together' and are 'in contact', or are 
'mixed'. Yet all these expressions are absurd. 



2371 



But (2) suppose the Form to be different in each species. Then 
there will be practically an infinite number of things whose 
substance is animal'; for it is not by accident that 'man' has 
'animal' for one of its elements. Further, many things will be 
'animal-itself. For (i) the 'animal' in each species will be the 
substance of the species; for it is after nothing else that the 
species is called; if it were, that other would be an element in 
'man', i.e. would be the genus of man. And further, (ii) all the 
elements of which 'man' is composed will be Ideas. None of 
them, then, will be the Idea of one thing and the substance of 
another; this is impossible. The 'animal', then, present in each 
species of animals will be animal-itself. Further, from what is 
this 'animal' in each species derived, and how will it be derived 
from animal-itself? Or how can this 'animal', whose essence is 
simply animality, exist apart from animal-itself? 

Further, (3)in the case of sensible things both these 
consequences and others still more absurd follow. If, then, these 
consequences are impossible, clearly there are not Forms of 
sensible things in the sense in which some maintain their 
existence. 



15 

Since substance is of two kinds, the concrete thing and the 
formula (I mean that one kind of substance is the formula taken 
with the matter, while another kind is the formula in its 
generality), substances in the former sense are capable of 
destruction (for they are capable also of generation), but there is 
no destruction of the formula in the sense that it is ever in 
course of being destroyed (for there is no generation of it either; 
the being of house is not generated, but only the being of this 



2372 



house), but without generation and destruction formulae are 
and are not; for it has been shown that no one begets nor 
makes these. For this reason, also, there is neither definition of 
nor demonstration about sensible individual substances, 
because they have matter whose nature is such that they are 
capable both of being and of not being; for which reason all the 
individual instances of them are destructible. If then 
demonstration is of necessary truths and definition is a 
scientific process, and if, just as knowledge cannot be 
sometimes knowledge and sometimes ignorance, but the state 
which varies thus is opinion, so too demonstration and 
definition cannot vary thus, but it is opinion that deals with 
that which can be otherwise than as it is, clearly there can 
neither be definition of nor demonstration about sensible 
individuals. For perishing things are obscure to those who have 
the relevant knowledge, when they have passed from our 
perception; and though the formulae remain in the soul 
unchanged, there will no longer be either definition or 
demonstration. And so when one of the definition-mongers 
defines any individual, he must recognize that his definition 
may always be overthrown; for it is not possible to define such 
things. 

Nor is it possible to define any Idea. For the Idea is, as its 
supporters say, an individual, and can exist apart; and the 
formula must consist of words; and he who defines must not 
invent a word (for it would be unknown), but the established 
words are common to all the members of a class; these then 
must apply to something besides the thing defined; e.g. if one 
were defining you, he would say 'an animal which is lean' or 
'pale', or something else which will apply also to some one 
other than you. If any one were to say that perhaps all the 
attributes taken apart may belong to many subjects, but 
together they belong only to this one, we must reply first that 
they belong also to both the elements; e.g. 'two-footed animal' 



2373 



belongs to animal and to the two-footed. (And in the case of 
eternal entities this is even necessary, since the elements are 
prior to and parts of the compound; nay more, they can also 
exist apart, if 'man' can exist apart. For either neither or both 
can. If, then, neither can, the genus will not exist apart from the 
various species; but if it does, the differentia will also.) Secondly, 
we must reply that 'animal' and 'two-footed' are prior in being 
to 'two-footed animal'; and things which are prior to others are 
not destroyed when the others are. 

Again, if the Ideas consist of Ideas (as they must, since elements 
are simpler than the compound), it will be further necessary 
that the elements also of which the Idea consists, e.g. 'animal' 
and 'two-footed', should be predicated of many subjects. If not, 
how will they come to be known? For there will then be an Idea 
which cannot be predicated of more subjects than one. But this 
is not thought possible - every Idea is thought to be capable of 
being shared. 

As has been said, then, the impossibility of defining individuals 
escapes notice in the case of eternal things, especially those 
which are unique, like the sun or the moon. For people err not 
only by adding attributes whose removal the sun would survive, 
e.g. 'going round the earth' or 'night-hidden' (for from their view 
it follows that if it stands still or is visible, it will no longer be 
the sun; but it is strange if this is so; for 'the sun' means a 
certain substance); but also by the mention of attributes which 
can belong to another subject; e.g. if another thing with the 
stated attributes comes into existence, clearly it will be a sun; 
the formula therefore is general. But the sun was supposed to 
be an individual, like Cleon or Socrates. After all, why does not 
one of the supporters of the Ideas produce a definition of an 
Idea? It would become clear, if they tried, that what has now 
been said is true. 



2374 



16 

Evidently even of the things that are thought to be substances, 
most are only potencies, - both the parts of animals (for none of 
them exists separately; and when they are separated, then too 
they exist, all of them, merely as matter) and earth and fire and 
air; for none of them is a unity, but as it were a mere heap, till 
they are worked up and some unity is made out of them. One 
might most readily suppose the parts of living things and the 
parts of the soul nearly related to them to turn out to be both, 
i.e. existent in complete reality as well as in potency, because 
they have sources of movement in something in their joints; for 
which reason some animals live when divided. Yet all the parts 
must exist only potentially, when they are one and continuous 
by nature, - not by force or by growing into one, for such a 
phenomenon is an abnormality. 

Since the term 'unity' is used like the term 'being', and the 
substance of that which is one is one, and things whose 
substance is numerically one are numerically one, evidently 
neither unity nor being can be the substance of things, just as 
being an element or a principle cannot be the substance, but we 
ask what, then, the principle is, that we may reduce the thing to 
something more knowable. Now of these concepts 'being' and 
'unity' are more substantial than 'principle' or 'element' or 
'cause', but not even the former are substance, since in general 
nothing that is common is substance; for substance does not 
belong to anything but to itself and to that which has it, of 
which it is the substance. Further, that which is one cannot be 
in many places at the same time, but that which is common is 
present in many places at the same time; so that clearly no 
universal exists apart from its individuals. 



2375 



But those who say the Forms exist, in one respect are right, in 
giving the Forms separate existence, if they are substances; but 
in another respect they are not right, because they say the one 
over many is a Form. The reason for their doing this is that they 
cannot declare what are the substances of this sort, the 
imperishable substances which exist apart from the individual 
and sensible substances. They make them, then, the same in 
kind as the perishable things (for this kind of substance we 
know) - 'man-himself and 'horse-itself , adding to the sensible 
things the word 'itself. Yet even if we had not seen the stars, 
none the less, I suppose, would they have been eternal 
substances apart from those which we knew; so that now also if 
we do not know what non-sensible substances there are, yet it 
is doubtless necessary that there should he some. - Clearly, 
then, no universal term is the name of a substance, and no 
substance is composed of substances. 



17 

Let us state what, i.e. what kind of thing, substance should be 
said to be, taking once more another starting-point; for perhaps 
from this we shall get a clear view also of that substance which 
exists apart from sensible substances. Since, then, substance is 
a principle and a cause, let us pursue it from this starting-point. 
The 'why' is always sought in this form - 'why does one thing 
attach to some other?' For to inquire why the musical man is a 
musical man, is either to inquire - as we have said why the man 
is musical, or it is something else. Now 'why a thing is itself is a 
meaningless inquiry (for (to give meaning to the question 'why') 
the fact or the existence of the thing must already be evident - 
e.g. that the moon is eclipsed - but the fact that a thing is itself 
is the single reason and the single cause to be given in answer 



2376 



to all such questions as why the man is man, or the musician 
musical', unless one were to answer 'because each thing is 
inseparable from itself, and its being one just meant this'; this, 
however, is common to all things and is a short and easy way 
with the question). But we can inquire why man is an animal of 
such and such a nature. This, then, is plain, that we are not 
inquiring why he who is a man is a man. We are inquiring, then, 
why something is predicable of something (that it is predicable 
must be clear; for if not, the inquiry is an inquiry into nothing). 
E.g. why does it thunder? This is the same as 'why is sound 
produced in the clouds?' Thus the inquiry is about the 
predication of one thing of another. And why are these things, 
i.e. bricks and stones, a house? Plainly we are seeking the cause. 
And this is the essence (to speak abstractly), which in some 
cases is the end, e.g. perhaps in the case of a house or a bed, 
and in some cases is the first mover; for this also is a cause. But 
while the efficient cause is sought in the case of genesis and 
destruction, the final cause is sought in the case of being also. 

The object of the inquiry is most easily overlooked where one 
term is not expressly predicated of another (e.g. when we 
inquire 'what man is'), because we do not distinguish and do 
not say definitely that certain elements make up a certain 
whole. But we must articulate our meaning before we begin to 
inquire; if not, the inquiry is on the border-line between being a 
search for something and a search for nothing. Since we must 
have the existence of the thing as something given, clearly the 
question is why the matter is some definite thing; e.g. why are 
these materials a house? Because that which was the essence of 
a house is present. And why is this individual thing, or this body 
having this form, a man? Therefore what we seek is the cause, 
i.e. the form, by reason of which the matter is some definite 
thing; and this is the substance of the thing. Evidently, then, in 
the case of simple terms no inquiry nor teaching is possible; our 
attitude towards such things is other than that of inquiry. 



2377 



Since that which is compounded out of something so that the 
whole is one, not like a heap but like a syllable - now the 
syllable is not its elements, ba is not the same as b and a, nor is 
flesh fire and earth (for when these are separated the wholes, 
i.e. the flesh and the syllable, no longer exist, but the elements 
of the syllable exist, and so do fire and earth); the syllable, then, 
is something - not only its elements (the vowel and the 
consonant) but also something else, and the flesh is not only 
fire and earth or the hot and the cold, but also something else: - 
if, then, that something must itself be either an element or 
composed of elements, (1) if it is an element the same argument 
will again apply; for flesh will consist of this and fire and earth 
and something still further, so that the process will go on to 
infinity. But (2) if it is a compound, clearly it will be a compound 
not of one but of more than one (or else that one will be the 
thing itself), so that again in this case we can use the same 
argument as in the case of flesh or of the syllable. But it would 
seem that this 'other' is something, and not an element, and 
that it is the cause which makes this thing flesh and that a 
syllable. And similarly in all other cases. And this is the 
substance of each thing (for this is the primary cause of its 
being); and since, while some things are not substances, as 
many as are substances are formed in accordance with a nature 
of their own and by a process of nature, their substance would 
seem to be this kind of 'nature', which is not an element but a 
principle. An element, on the other hand, is that into which a 
thing is divided and which is present in it as matter; e.g. a and b 
are the elements of the syllable. 



2378 



BookH 



We must reckon up the results arising from what has been said, 
and compute the sum of them, and put the finishing touch to 
our inquiry. We have said that the causes, principles, and 
elements of substances are the object of our search. And some 
substances are recognized by every one, but some have been 
advocated by particular schools. Those generally recognized are 
the natural substances, i.e. fire, earth, water, air, &c, the simple 
bodies; second plants and their parts, and animals and the 
parts of animals; and finally the physical universe and its parts; 
while some particular schools say that Forms and the objects of 
mathematics are substances. But there are arguments which 
lead to the conclusion that there are other substances, the 
essence and the substratum. Again, in another way the genus 
seems more substantial than the various species, and the 
universal than the particulars. And with the universal and the 
genus the Ideas are connected; it is in virtue of the same 
argument that they are thought to be substances. And since the 
essence is substance, and the definition is a formula of the 
essence, for this reason we have discussed definition and 
essential predication. Since the definition is a formula, and a 
formula has parts, we had to consider also with respect to the 
notion of 'part', what are parts of the substance and what are 
not, and whether the parts of the substance are also parts of the 
definition. Further, too, neither the universal nor the genus is a 
substance; we must inquire later into the Ideas and the objects 
of mathematics; for some say these are substances as well as 
the sensible substances. 



2379 



But now let us resume the discussion of the generally 
recognized substances. These are the sensible substances, and 
sensible substances all have matter. The substratum is 
substance, and this is in one sense the matter (and by matter I 
mean that which, not being a 'this' actually, is potentially a 
'this'), and in another sense the formula or shape (that which 
being a 'this' can be separately formulated), and thirdly the 
complex of these two, which alone is generated and destroyed, 
and is, without qualification, capable of separate existence; for 
of substances completely expressible in a formula some are 
separable and some are separable and some are not. 

But clearly matter also is substance; for in all the opposite 
changes that occur there is something which underlies the 
changes, e.g. in respect of place that which is now here and 
again elsewhere, and in respect of increase that which is now of 
one size and again less or greater, and in respect of alteration 
that which is now healthy and again diseased; and similarly in 
respect of substance there is something that is now being 
generated and again being destroyed, and now underlies the 
process as a 'this' and again underlies it in respect of a privation 
of positive character. And in this change the others are involved. 
But in either one or two of the others this is not involved; for it 
is not necessary if a thing has matter for change of place that it 
should also have matter for generation and destruction. 

The difference between becoming in the full sense and 
becoming in a qualified sense has been stated in our physical 
works. 



2380 



Since the substance which exists as underlying and as matter is 
generally recognized, and this that which exists potentially, it 
remains for us to say what is the substance, in the sense of 
actuality, of sensible things. Democritus seems to think there 
are three kinds of difference between things; the underlying 
body, the matter, is one and the same, but they differ either in 
rhythm, i.e. shape, or in turning, i.e. position, or in inter-contact, 
i.e. order. But evidently there are many differences; for instance, 
some things are characterized by the mode of composition of 
their matter, e.g. the things formed by blending, such as honey- 
water; and others by being bound together, e.g. bundle; and 
others by being glued together, e.g. a book; and others by being 
nailed together, e.g. a casket; and others in more than one of 
these ways; and others by position, e.g. threshold and lintel (for 
these differ by being placed in a certain way); and others by 
time, e.g. dinner and breakfast; and others by place, e.g. the 
winds; and others by the affections proper to sensible things, 
e.g. hardness and softness, density and rarity, dryness and 
wetness; and some things by some of these qualities, others by 
them all, and in general some by excess and some by defect. 
Clearly, then, the word 'is' has just as many meanings; a thing is 
a threshold because it lies in such and such a position, and its 
being means its lying in that position, while being ice means 
having been solidified in such and such a way. And the being of 
some things will be defined by all these qualities, because some 
parts of them are mixed, others are blended, others are bound 
together, others are solidified, and others use the other 
differentiae; e.g. the hand or the foot requires such complex 
definition. We must grasp, then, the kinds of differentiae (for 
these will be the principles of the being of things), e.g. the 
things characterized by the more and the less, or by the dense 
and the rare, and by other such qualities; for all these are forms 
of excess and defect. And anything that is characterized by 



2381 



shape or by smoothness and roughness is characterized by the 
straight and the curved. And for other things their being will 
mean their being mixed, and their not being will mean the 
opposite. 

It is clear, then, from these facts that, since its substance is the 
cause of each thing's being, we must seek in these differentiae 
what is the cause of the being of each of these things. Now none 
of these differentiae is substance, even when coupled with 
matter, yet it is what is analogous to substance in each case; 
and as in substances that which is predicated of the matter is 
the actuality itself, in all other definitions also it is what most 
resembles full actuality. E.g. if we had to define a threshold, we 
should say 'wood or stone in such and such a position', and a 
house we should define as 'bricks and timbers in such and such 
a position', (or a purpose may exist as well in some cases), and if 
we had to define ice we should say 'water frozen or solidified in 
such and such a way', and harmony is 'such and such a 
blending of high and low'; and similarly in all other cases. 

Obviously, then, the actuality or the formula is different when 
the matter is different; for in some cases it is the composition, 
in others the mixing, and in others some other of the attributes 
we have named. And so, of the people who go in for defining, 
those who define a house as stones, bricks, and timbers are 
speaking of the potential house, for these are the matter; but 
those who propose 'a receptacle to shelter chattels and living 
beings', or something of the sort, speak of the actuality. Those 
who combine both of these speak of the third kind of substance, 
which is composed of matter and form (for the formula that 
gives the differentiae seems to be an account of the form or 
actuality, while that which gives the components is rather an 
account of the matter); and the same is true of the kind of 
definitions which Archytas used to accept; they are accounts of 
the combined form and matter. E.g. what is still weather? 



2382 



Absence of motion in a large expanse of air; air is the matter, 
and absence of motion is the actuality and substance. What is a 
calm? Smoothness of sea; the material substratum is the sea, 
and the actuality or shape is smoothness. It is obvious then, 
from what has been said, what sensible substance is and how it 
exists - one kind of it as matter, another as form or actuality, 
while the third kind is that which is composed of these two. 



We must not fail to notice that sometimes it is not clear 
whether a name means the composite substance, or the 
actuality or form, e.g. whether 'house' is a sign for the 
composite thing, 'a covering consisting of bricks and stones laid 
thus and thus', or for the actuality or form, 'a covering', and 
whether a line is 'twoness in length' or 'twoness', and whether 
an animal is soul in a body' or 'a soul'; for soul is the substance 
or actuality of some body. 'Animal' might even be applied to 
both, not as something definable by one formula, but as related 
to a single thing. But this question, while important for another 
purpose, is of no importance for the inquiry into sensible 
substance; for the essence certainly attaches to the form and 
the actuality. For 'soul' and 'to be soul' are the same, but 'to be 
man' and 'man' are not the same, unless even the bare soul is to 
be called man; and thus on one interpretation the thing is the 
same as its essence, and on another it is not. 

If we examine we find that the syllable does not consist of the 
letters + juxtaposition, nor is the house bricks + juxtaposition. 
And this is right; for the juxtaposition or mixing does not 
consist of those things of which it is the juxtaposition or 
mixing. And the same is true in all other cases; e.g. if the 



2383 



threshold is characterized by its position, the position is not 
constituted by the threshold, but rather the latter is constituted 
by the former. Nor is man animal + biped, but there must be 
something besides these, if these are matter, - something which 
is neither an element in the whole nor a compound, but is the 
substance; but this people eliminate, and state only the matter. 
If, then, this is the cause of the thing's being, and if the cause of 
its being is its substance, they will not be stating the substance 
itself. 

(This, then, must either be eternal or it must be destructible 
without being ever in course of being destroyed, and must have 
come to be without ever being in course of coming to be. But it 
has been proved and explained elsewhere that no one makes or 
begets the form, but it is the individual that is made, i.e. the 
complex of form and matter that is generated. Whether the 
substances of destructible things can exist apart, is not yet at all 
clear; except that obviously this is impossible in some cases - in 
the case of things which cannot exist apart from the individual 
instances, e.g. house or utensil. Perhaps, indeed, neither these 
things themselves, nor any of the other things which are not 
formed by nature, are substances at all; for one might say that 
the nature in natural objects is the only substance to be found 
in destructible things.) 

Therefore the difficulty which used to be raised by the school of 
Antisthenes and other such uneducated people has a certain 
timeliness. They said that the 'what' cannot be defined (for the 
definition so called is a 'long rigmarole') but of what sort a 
thing, e.g. silver, is, they thought it possible actually to explain, 
not saying what it is, but that it is like tin. Therefore one kind of 
substance can be defined and formulated, i.e. the composite 
kind, whether it be perceptible or intelligible; but the primary 
parts of which this consists cannot be defined, since a 
definitory formula predicates something of something, and one 



2384 



part of the definition must play the part of matter and the other 
that of form. 

It is also obvious that, if substances are in a sense numbers, 
they are so in this sense and not, as some say, as numbers of 
units. For a definition is a sort of number; for (1) it is divisible, 
and into indivisible parts (for definitory formulae are not 
infinite), and number also is of this nature. And (2) as, when one 
of the parts of which a number consists has been taken from or 
added to the number, it is no longer the same number, but a 
different one, even if it is the very smallest part that has been 
taken away or added, so the definition and the essence will no 
longer remain when anything has been taken away or added. 
And (3) the number must be something in virtue of which it is 
one, and this these thinkers cannot state, what makes it one, if 
it is one (for either it is not one but a sort of heap, or if it is, we 
ought to say what it is that makes one out of many); and the 
definition is one, but similarly they cannot say what makes it 
one. And this is a natural result; for the same reason is 
applicable, and substance is one in the sense which we have 
explained, and not, as some say, by being a sort of unit or point; 
each is a complete reality and a definite nature. And (4) as 
number does not admit of the more and the less, neither does 
substance, in the sense of form, but if any substance does, it is 
only the substance which involves matter. Let this, then, suffice 
for an account of the generation and destruction of so-called 
substances in what sense it is possible and in what sense 
impossible - and of the reduction of things to number. 



2385 



Regarding material substance we must not forget that even if all 
things come from the same first cause or have the same things 
for their first causes, and if the same matter serves as starting- 
point for their generation, yet there is a matter proper to each, 
e.g. for phlegm the sweet or the fat, and for bile the bitter, or 
something else; though perhaps these come from the same 
original matter. And there come to be several matters for the 
same thing, when the one matter is matter for the other; e.g. 
phlegm comes from the fat and from the sweet, if the fat comes 
from the sweet; and it comes from bile by analysis of the bile 
into its ultimate matter. For one thing comes from another in 
two senses, either because it will be found at a later stage, or 
because it is produced if the other is analysed into its original 
constituents. When the matter is one, different things may be 
produced owing to difference in the moving cause; e.g. from 
wood may be made both a chest and a bed. But some different 
things must have their matter different; e.g. a saw could not be 
made of wood, nor is this in the power of the moving cause; for 
it could not make a saw of wool or of wood. But if, as a matter of 
fact, the same thing can be made of different material, clearly 
the art, i.e. the moving principle, is the same; for if both the 
matter and the moving cause were different, the product would 
be so too. 

When one inquires into the cause of something, one should, 
since 'causes' are spoken of in several senses, state all the 
possible causes, what is the material cause of man? Shall we 
say 'the menstrual fluid? What is moving cause? Shall we say 
'the seed? The formal cause? His essence. The final cause? His 
end. But perhaps the latter two are the same. - It is the 
proximate causes we must state. What is the material cause? 
We must name not fire or earth, but the matter peculiar to the 
thing. 



2386 



Regarding the substances that are natural and generable, if the 
causes are really these and of this number and we have to learn 
the causes, we must inquire thus, if we are to inquire rightly. 
But in the case of natural but eternal substances another 
account must be given. For perhaps some have no matter, or not 
matter of this sort but only such as can be moved in respect of 
place. Nor does matter belong to those things which exist by 
nature but are not substances; their substratum is the 
substance. E.g what is the cause of eclipse? What is its matter? 
There is none; the moon is that which suffers eclipse. What is 
the moving cause which extinguished the light? The earth. The 
final cause perhaps does not exist. The formal principle is the 
definitory formula, but this is obscure if it does not include the 
cause. E.g. what is eclipse? Deprivation of light. But if we add 'by 
the earth's coming in between', this is the formula which 
includes the cause. In the case of sleep it is not clear what it is 
that proximately has this affection. Shall we say that it is the 
animal? Yes, but the animal in virtue of what, i.e. what is the 
proximate subject? The heart or some other part. Next, by what 
is it produced? Next, what is the affection - that of the 
proximate subject, not of the whole animal? Shall we say that it 
is immobility of such and such a kind? Yes, but to what process 
in the proximate subject is this due? 



Since some things are and are not, without coming to be and 
ceasing to be, e.g. points, if they can be said to be, and in general 
forms (for it is not 'white' comes to be, but the wood comes to 
be white, if everything that comes to be comes from something 
and comes to be something), not all contraries can come from 
one another, but it is in different senses that a pale man comes 



2387 



from a dark man, and pale comes from dark. Nor has everything 
matter, but only those things which come to be and change into 
one another. Those things which, without ever being in course 
of changing, are or are not, have no matter. 

There is difficulty in the question how the matter of each thing 
is related to its contrary states. E.g. if the body is potentially 
healthy, and disease is contrary to health, is it potentially both 
healthy and diseased? And is water potentially wine and 
vinegar? We answer that it is the matter of one in virtue of its 
positive state and its form, and of the other in virtue of the 
privation of its positive state and the corruption of it contrary to 
its nature. It is also hard to say why wine is not said to be the 
matter of vinegar nor potentially vinegar (though vinegar is 
produced from it), and why a living man is not said to be 
potentially dead. In fact they are not, but the corruptions in 
question are accidental, and it is the matter of the animal that 
is itself in virtue of its corruption the potency and matter of a 
corpse, and it is water that is the matter of vinegar. For the 
corpse comes from the animal, and vinegar from wine, as night 
from day. And all the things which change thus into one 
another must go back to their matter; e.g. if from a corpse is 
produced an animal, the corpse first goes back to its matter, and 
only then becomes an animal; and vinegar first goes back to 
water, and only then becomes wine. 



To return to the difficulty which has been stated with respect 
both to definitions and to numbers, what is the cause of their 
unity? In the case of all things which have several parts and in 
which the totality is not, as it were, a mere heap, but the whole 



2388 



is something beside the parts, there is a cause; for even in 
bodies contact is the cause of unity in some cases, and in others 
viscosity or some other such quality. And a definition is a set of 
words which is one not by being connected together, like the 
Iliad, but by dealing with one object. - What then, is it that 
makes man one; why is he one and not many, e.g. animal + 
biped, especially if there are, as some say, an animal-itself and a 
biped-itself? Why are not those Forms themselves the man, so 
that men would exist by participation not in man, nor in one 
Form, but in two, animal and biped, and in general man would 
be not one but more than one thing, animal and biped? 

Clearly, then, if people proceed thus in their usual manner of 
definition and speech, they cannot explain and solve the 
difficulty. But if, as we say, one element is matter and another is 
form, and one is potentially and the other actually, the question 
will no longer be thought a difficulty. For this difficulty is the 
same as would arise if 'round bronze' were the definition of 
'cloak'; for this word would be a sign of the definitory formula, 
so that the question is, what is the cause of the unity of 'round' 
and 'bronze? The difficulty disappears, because the one is 
matter, the other form. What, then, causes this - that which was 
potentially to be actually - except, in the case of things which 
are generated, the agent? For there is no other cause of the 
potential sphere's becoming actually a sphere, but this was the 
essence of either. Of matter some is intelligible, some 
perceptible, and in a formula there is always an element of 
matter as well as one of actuality; e.g. the circle is 'a plane 
figure'. But of the things which have no matter, either 
intelligible or perceptible, each is by its nature essentially a kind 
of unity, as it is essentially a kind of being - individual 
substance, quality, or quantity (and so neither 'existent' nor 
'one' is present in their definitions), and the essence of each of 
them is by its very nature a kind of unity as it is a kind of being 
- and so none of these has any reason outside itself, for being 



2389 



one, nor for being a kind of being; for each is by its nature a kind 
of being and a kind of unity, not as being in the genus 'being' or 
'one' nor in the sense that being and unity can exist apart from 
particulars. 

Owing to the difficulty about unity some speak of 
'participation', and raise the question, what is the cause of 
participation and what is it to participate; and others speak of 
'communion', as Lycophron says knowledge is a communion of 
knowing with the soul; and others say life is a 'composition' or 
'connexion' of soul with body. Yet the same account applies to 
all cases; for being healthy, too, will on this showing be either a 
'communion' or a 'connexion' or a 'composition' of soul and 
health, and the fact that the bronze is a triangle will be a 
'composition' of bronze and triangle, and the fact that a thing is 
white will be a 'composition' of surface and whiteness. The 
reason is that people look for a unifying formula, and a 
difference, between potency and complete reality. But, as has 
been said, the proximate matter and the form are one and the 
same thing, the one potentially, and the other actually. 
Therefore it is like asking what in general is the cause of unity 
and of a thing's being one; for each thing is a unity, and the 
potential and the actual are somehow one. Therefore there is no 
other cause here unless there is something which caused the 
movement from potency into actuality. And all things which 
have no matter are without qualification essentially unities. 



2390 



BookG 



We have treated of that which is primarily and to which all the 
other categories of being are referred - i.e. of substance. For it is 
in virtue of the concept of substance that the others also are 
said to be - quantity and quality and the like; for all will be 
found to involve the concept of substance, as we said in the first 
part of our work. And since 'being' is in one way divided into 
individual thing, quality, and quantity, and is in another way 
distinguished in respect of potency and complete reality, and of 
function, let us now add a discussion of potency and complete 
reality. And first let us explain potency in the strictest sense, 
which is, however, not the most useful for our present purpose. 
For potency and actuality extend beyond the cases that involve 
a reference to motion. But when we have spoken of this first 
kind, we shall in our discussions of actuality' explain the other 
kinds of potency as well. 

We have pointed out elsewhere that 'potency' and the word 
'can' have several senses. Of these we may neglect all the 
potencies that are so called by an equivocation. For some are 
called so by analogy, as in geometry we say one thing is or is not 
a 'power' of another by virtue of the presence or absence of 
some relation between them. But all potencies that conform to 
the same type are originative sources of some kind, and are 
called potencies in reference to one primary kind of potency, 
which is an originative source of change in another thing or in 
the thing itself qua other. For one kind is a potency of being 
acted on, i.e. the originative source, in the very thing acted on, 
of its being passively changed by another thing or by itself qua 



2391 



other; and another kind is a state of insusceptibility to change 
for the worse and to destruction by another thing or by the 
thing itself qua other by virtue of an originative source of 
change. In all these definitions is implied the formula if potency 
in the primary sense. - And again these so-called potencies are 
potencies either of merely acting or being acted on, or of acting 
or being acted on well, so that even in the formulae of the latter 
the formulae of the prior kinds of potency are somehow 
implied. 

Obviously, then, in a sense the potency of acting and of being 
acted on is one (for a thing may be 'capable' either because it 
can itself be acted on or because something else can be acted 
on by it), but in a sense the potencies are different. For the one 
is in the thing acted on; it is because it contains a certain 
originative source, and because even the matter is an originative 
source, that the thing acted on is acted on, and one thing by 
one, another by another; for that which is oily can be burnt, and 
that which yields in a particular way can be crushed; and 
similarly in all other cases. But the other potency is in the agent, 
e.g. heat and the art of building are present, one in that which 
can produce heat and the other in the man who can build. And 
so, in so far as a thing is an organic unity, it cannot be acted on 
by itself; for it is one and not two different things. And 
'impotence'and 'impotent' stand for the privation which is 
contrary to potency of this sort, so that every potency belongs to 
the same subject and refers to the same process as a 
corresponding impotence. Privation has several senses; for it 
means (1) that which has not a certain quality and (2) that 
which might naturally have it but has not it, either (a) in general 
or (b) when it might naturally have it, and either (a) in some 
particular way, e.g. when it has not it completely, or (b) when it 
has not it at all. And in certain cases if things which naturally 
have a quality lose it by violence, we say they have suffered 
privation. 



2392 



Since some such originative sources are present in soulless 
things, and others in things possessed of soul, and in soul, and 
in the rational part of the soul, clearly some potencies will, be 
non-rational and some will be non-rational and some will be 
accompanied by a rational formula. This is why all arts, i.e. all 
productive forms of knowledge, are potencies; they are 
originative sources of change in another thing or in the artist 
himself considered as other. 

And each of those which are accompanied by a rational formula 
is alike capable of contrary effects, but one non-rational power 
produces one effect; e.g. the hot is capable only of heating, but 
the medical art can produce both disease and health. The 
reason is that science is a rational formula, and the same 
rational formula explains a thing and its privation, only not in 
the same way; and in a sense it applies to both, but in a sense it 
applies rather to the positive fact. Therefore such sciences must 
deal with contraries, but with one in virtue of their own nature 
and with the other not in virtue of their nature; for the rational 
formula applies to one object in virtue of that object's nature, 
and to the other, in a sense, accidentally. For it is by denial and 
removal that it exhibits the contrary; for the contrary is the 
primary privation, and this is the removal of the positive term. 
Now since contraries do not occur in the same thing, but 
science is a potency which depends on the possession of a 
rational formula, and the soul possesses an originative source of 
movement; therefore, while the wholesome produces only 
health and the calorific only heat and the frigorific only cold, 
the scientific man produces both the contrary effects. For the 
rational formula is one which applies to both, though not in the 



2393 



same way, and it is in a soul which possesses an originative 
source of movement; so that the soul will start both processes 
from the same originative source, having linked them up with 
the same thing. And so the things whose potency is according 
to a rational formula act contrariwise to the things whose 
potency is non-rational; for the products of the former are 
included under one originative source, the rational formula. 

It is obvious also that the potency of merely doing a thing or 
having it done to one is implied in that of doing it or having it 
done well, but the latter is not always implied in the former: for 
he who does a thing well must also do it, but he who does it 
merely need not also do it well. 



There are some who say, as the Megaric school does, that a 
thing 'can' act only when it is acting, and when it is not acting it 
'cannot' act, e.g. that he who is not building cannot build, but 
only he who is building, when he is building; and so in all other 
cases. It is not hard to see the absurdities that attend this view. 

For it is clear that on this view a man will not be a builder 
unless he is building (for to be a builder is to be able to build), 
and so with the other arts. If, then, it is impossible to have such 
arts if one has not at some time learnt and acquired them, and 
it is then impossible not to have them if one has not sometime 
lost them (either by forgetfulness or by some accident or by 
time; for it cannot be by the destruction of the object, for that 
lasts for ever), a man will not have the art when he has ceased 
to use it, and yet he may immediately build again; how then will 
he have got the art? And similarly with regard to lifeless things; 
nothing will be either cold or hot or sweet or perceptible at all if 



2394 



people are not perceiving it; so that the upholders of this view 
will have to maintain the doctrine of Protagoras. But, indeed, 
nothing will even have perception if it is not perceiving, i.e. 
exercising its perception. If, then, that is blind which has not 
sight though it would naturally have it, when it would naturally 
have it and when it still exists, the same people will be blind 
many times in the day - and deaf too. 

Again, if that which is deprived of potency is incapable, that 
which is not happening will be incapable of happening; but he 
who says of that which is incapable of happening either that it 
is or that it will be will say what is untrue; for this is what 
incapacity meant. Therefore these views do away with both 
movement and becoming. For that which stands will always 
stand, and that which sits will always sit, since if it is sitting it 
will not get up; for that which, as we are told, cannot get up will 
be incapable of getting up. But we cannot say this, so that 
evidently potency and actuality are different (but these views 
make potency and actuality the same, and so it is no small 
thing they are seeking to annihilate), so that it is possible that a 
thing may be capable of being and not he, and capable of not 
being and yet he, and similarly with the other kinds of 
predicate; it may be capable of walking and yet not walk, or 
capable of not walking and yet walk. And a thing is capable of 
doing something if there will be nothing impossible in its 
having the actuality of that of which it is said to have the 
capacity. I mean, for instance, if a thing is capable of sitting and 
it is open to it to sit, there will be nothing impossible in its 
actually sitting; and similarly if it is capable of being moved or 
moving, or of standing or making to stand, or of being or 
coming to be, or of not being or not coming to be. 

The word 'actuality', which we connect with 'complete reality', 
has, in the main, been extended from movements to other 
things; for actuality in the strict sense is thought to be identical 



2395 



with movement. And so people do not assign movement to non- 
existent things, though they do assign some other predicates. 
E.g. they say that non-existent things are objects of thought and 
desire, but not that they are moved; and this because, while ex 
hypothesi they do not actually exist, they would have to exist 
actually if they were moved. For of non-existent things some 
exist potentially; but they do not exist, because they do not exist 
in complete reality. 



If what we have described is identical with the capable or 
convertible with it, evidently it cannot be true to say 'this is 
capable of being but will not be', which would imply that the 
things incapable of being would on this showing vanish. 
Suppose, for instance, that a man - one who did not take 
account of that which is incapable of being - were to say that 
the diagonal of the square is capable of being measured but will 
not be measured, because a thing may well be capable of being 
or coming to be, and yet not be or be about to be. But from the 
premisses this necessarily follows, that if we actually supposed 
that which is not, but is capable of being, to be or to have come 
to be, there will be nothing impossible in this; but the result will 
be impossible, for the measuring of the diagonal is impossible. 
For the false and the impossible are not the same; that you are 
standing now is false, but that you should be standing is not 
impossible. 

At the same time it is clear that if, when A is real, B must be 
real, then, when A is possible, B also must be possible. For if B 
need not be possible, there is nothing to prevent its not being 
possible. Now let A be supposed possible. Then, when A was 



2396 



possible, we agreed that nothing impossible followed if A were 
supposed to be real; and then B must of course be real. But we 
supposed B to be impossible. Let it be impossible then. If, then, 
B is impossible, A also must be so. But the first was supposed 
impossible; therefore the second also is impossible. If, then, A is 
possible, B also will be possible, if they were so related that if 
A,is real, B must be real. If, then, A and B being thus related, B is 
not possible on this condition, and B will not be related as was 
supposed. And if when A is possible, B must be possible, then if 
A is real, B also must be real. For to say that B must be possible, 
if A is possible, means this, that if A is real both at the time 
when and in the way in which it was supposed capable of being 
real, B also must then and in that way be real. 



As all potencies are either innate, like the senses, or come by 
practice, like the power of playing the flute, or by learning, like 
artistic power, those which come by practice or by rational 
formula we must acquire by previous exercise but this is not 
necessary with those which are not of this nature and which 
imply passivity. 

Since that which is 'capable' is capable of something and at 
some time in some way (with all the other qualifications which 
must be present in the definition), and since some things can 
produce change according to a rational formula and their 
potencies involve such a formula, while other things are 
nonrational and their potencies are non-rational, and the 
former potencies must be in a living thing, while the latter can 
be both in the living and in the lifeless; as regards potencies of 
the latter kind, when the agent and the patient meet in the way 



2397 



appropriate to the potency in question, the one must act and 
the other be acted on, but with the former kind of potency this 
is not necessary. For the nonrational potencies are all 
productive of one effect each, but the rational produce contrary 
effects, so that if they produced their effects necessarily they 
would produce contrary effects at the same time; but this is 
impossible. There must, then, be something else that decides; I 
mean by this, desire or will. For whichever of two things the 
animal desires decisively, it will do, when it is present, and 
meets the passive object, in the way appropriate to the potency 
in question. Therefore everything which has a rational potency, 
when it desires that for which it has a potency and in the 
circumstances in which it has the potency, must do this. And it 
has the potency in question when the passive object is present 
and is in a certain state; if not it will not be able to act. (To add 
the qualification 'if nothing external prevents it' is not further 
necessary; for it has the potency on the terms on which this is a 
potency of acting, and it is this not in all circumstances but on 
certain conditions, among which will be the exclusion of 
external hindrances; for these are barred by some of the 
positive qualifications.) And so even if one has a rational wish, 
or an appetite, to do two things or contrary things at the same 
time, one will not do them; for it is not on these terms that one 
has the potency for them, nor is it a potency of doing both at 
the same time, since one will do the things which it is a potency 
of doing, on the terms on which one has the potency. 



Since we have treated of the kind of potency which is related to 
movement, let us discuss actuality - what, and what kind of 
thing, actuality is. For in the course of our analysis it will also 



2398 



become clear, with regard to the potential, that we not only 
ascribe potency to that whose nature it is to move something 
else, or to be moved by something else, either without 
qualification or in some particular way, but also use the word in 
another sense, which is the reason of the inquiry in the course 
of which we have discussed these previous senses also. 
Actuality, then, is the existence of a thing not in the way which 
we express by 'potentially'; we say that potentially, for instance, 
a statue of Hermes is in the block of wood and the half- line is in 
the whole, because it might be separated out, and we call even 
the man who is not studying a man of science, if he is capable 
of studying; the thing that stands in contrast to each of these 
exists actually. Our meaning can be seen in the particular cases 
by induction, and we must not seek a definition of everything 
but be content to grasp the analogy, that it is as that which is 
building is to that which is capable of building, and the waking 
to the sleeping, and that which is seeing to that which has its 
eyes shut but has sight, and that which has been shaped out of 
the matter to the matter, and that which has been wrought up 
to the unwrought. Let actuality be defined by one member of 
this antithesis, and the potential by the other. But all things are 
not said in the same sense to exist actually, but only by analogy 
- as A is in B or to B, C is in D or to D; for some are as movement 
to potency, and the others as substance to some sort of matter. 

But also the infinite and the void and all similar things are said 
to exist potentially and actually in a different sense from that 
which applies to many other things, e.g. to that which sees or 
walks or is seen. For of the latter class these predicates can at 
some time be also truly asserted without qualification; for the 
seen is so called sometimes because it is being seen, sometimes 
because it is capable of being seen. But the infinite does not 
exist potentially in the sense that it will ever actually have 
separate existence; it exists potentially only for knowledge. For 
the fact that the process of dividing never comes to an end 



2399 



ensures that this activity exists potentially, but not that the 
infinite exists separately. 

Since of the actions which have a limit none is an end but all 
are relative to the end, e.g. the removing of fat, or fat-removal, 
and the bodily parts themselves when one is making them thin 
are in movement in this way (i.e. without being already that at 
which the movement aims), this is not an action or at least not 
a complete one (for it is not an end); but that movement in 
which the end is present is an action. E.g. at the same time we 
are seeing and have seen, are understanding and have 
understood, are thinking and have thought (while it is not true 
that at the same time we are learning and have learnt, or are 
being cured and have been cured). At the same time we are 
living well and have lived well, and are happy and have been 
happy. If not, the process would have had sometime to cease, as 
the process of making thin ceases: but, as things are, it does not 
cease; we are living and have lived. Of these processes, then, we 
must call the one set movements, and the other actualities. For 
every movement is incomplete - making thin, learning, walking, 
building; these are movements, and incomplete at that. For it is 
not true that at the same time a thing is walking and has 
walked, or is building and has built, or is coming to be and has 
come to be, or is being moved and has been moved, but what is 
being moved is different from what has been moved, and what 
is moving from what has moved. But it is the same thing that at 
the same time has seen and is seeing, seeing, or is thinking and 
has thought. The latter sort of process, then, I call an actuality, 
and the former a movement. 



2400 



What, and what kind of thing, the actual is, may be taken as 
explained by these and similar considerations. But we must 
distinguish when a thing exists potentially and when it does 
not; for it is not at any and every time. E.g. is earth potentially a 
man? No - but rather when it has already become seed, and 
perhaps not even then. It is just as it is with being healed; not 
everything can be healed by the medical art or by luck, but there 
is a certain kind of thing which is capable of it, and only this is 
potentially healthy. And (1) the delimiting mark of that which as 
a result of thought comes to exist in complete reality from 
having existed potentially is that if the agent has willed it it 
comes to pass if nothing external hinders, while the condition 
on the other side - viz. in that which is healed - is that nothing 
in it hinders the result. It is on similar terms that we have what 
is potentially a house; if nothing in the thing acted on - i.e. in 
the matter - prevents it from becoming a house, and if there is 
nothing which must be added or taken away or changed, this is 
potentially a house; and the same is true of all other things the 
source of whose becoming is external. And (2) in the cases in 
which the source of the becoming is in the very thing which 
comes to be, a thing is potentially all those things which it will 
be of itself if nothing external hinders it. E.g. the seed is not yet 
potentially a man; for it must be deposited in something other 
than itself and undergo a change. But when through its own 
motive principle it has already got such and such attributes, in 
this state it is already potentially a man; while in the former 
state it needs another motive principle, just as earth is not yet 
potentially a statue (for it must first change in order to become 
brass.) 

It seems that when we call a thing not something else but 
'thaten' - e.g. a casket is not 'wood' but 'wooden', and wood is 
not 'earth' but 'earthen', and again earth will illustrate our point 



2401 



if it is similarly not something else but 'thaten' - that other 
thing is always potentially (in the full sense of that word) the 
thing which comes after it in this series. E.g. a casket is not 
'earthen' nor 'earth', but 'wooden'; for this is potentially a 
casket and this is the matter of a casket, wood in general of a 
casket in general, and this particular wood of this particular 
casket. And if there is a first thing, which is no longer, in 
reference to something else, called 'thaten', this is prime 
matter; e.g. if earth is 'airy' and air is not 'fire' but 'fiery', fire is 
prime matter, which is not a 'this'. For the subject or substratum 
is differentiated by being a 'this' or not being one; i.e. the 
substratum of modifications is, e.g. a man, i.e. a body and a soul, 
while the modification is 'musical' or 'pale'. (The subject is 
called, when music comes to be present in it, not 'music' but 
'musical', and the man is not 'paleness' but 'pale', and not 
'ambulation' or 'movement' but 'walking' or 'moving', - which is 
akin to the 'thaten'.) Wherever this is so, then, the ultimate 
subject is a substance; but when this is not so but the predicate 
is a form and a 'this', the ultimate subject is matter and 
material substance. And it is only right that 'thaten' should be 
used with reference both to the matter and to the accidents; for 
both are indeterminates. 

We have stated, then, when a thing is to be said to exist 
potentially and when it is not. 



8 

From our discussion of the various senses of 'prior', it is clear 
that actuality is prior to potency. And I mean by potency not 
only that definite kind which is said to be a principle of change 
in another thing or in the thing itself regarded as other, but in 



2402 



general every principle of movement or of rest. For nature also 
is in the same genus as potency; for it is a principle of 
movement - not, however, in something else but in the thing 
itself qua itself. To all such potency, then, actuality is prior both 
in formula and in substantiality; and in time it is prior in one 
sense, and in another not. 

(1) Clearly it is prior in formula; for that which is in the primary 
sense potential is potential because it is possible for it to 
become active; e.g. I mean by 'capable of building' that which 
can build, and by 'capable of seeing' that which can see, and by 
'visible' that which can be seen. And the same account applies 
to all other cases, so that the formula and the knowledge of the 
one must precede the knowledge of the other. 

(2) In time it is prior in this sense: the actual which is identical 
in species though not in number with a potentially existing 
thing is to it. I mean that to this particular man who now exists 
actually and to the corn and to the seeing subject the matter 
and the seed and that which is capable of seeing, which are 
potentially a man and corn and seeing, but not yet actually so, 
are prior in time; but prior in time to these are other actually 
existing things, from which they were produced. For from the 
potentially existing the actually existing is always produced by 
an actually existing thing, e.g. man from man, musician by 
musician; there is always a first mover, and the mover already 
exists actually. We have said in our account of substance that 
everything that is produced is something produced from 
something and by something, and that the same in species as it. 

This is why it is thought impossible to be a builder if one has 
built nothing or a harper if one has never played the harp; for 
he who learns to play the harp learns to play it by playing it, 
and all other learners do similarly. And thence arose the 
sophistical quibble, that one who does not possess a science 



2403 



will be doing that which is the object of the science; for he who 
is learning it does not possess it. But since, of that which is 
coming to be, some part must have come to be, and, of that 
which, in general, is changing, some part must have changed 
(this is shown in the treatise on movement), he who is learning 
must, it would seem, possess some part of the science. But here 
too, then, it is clear that actuality is in this sense also, viz. in 
order of generation and of time, prior to potency. 

But (3) it is also prior in substantiality; firstly, (a) because the 
things that are posterior in becoming are prior in form and in 
substantiality (e.g. man is prior to boy and human being to seed; 
for the one already has its form, and the other has not), and 
because everything that comes to be moves towards a principle, 
i.e. an end (for that for the sake of which a thing is, is its 
principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end), and the 
actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the 
potency is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they 
may have sight, but they have sight that they may see. And 
similarly men have the art of building that they may build, and 
theoretical science that they may theorize; but they do not 
theorize that they may have theoretical science, except those 
who are learning by practice; and these do not theorize except 
in a limited sense, or because they have no need to theorize. 
Further, matter exists in a potential state, just because it may 
come to its form; and when it exists actually, then it is in its 
form. And the same holds good in all cases, even those in which 
the end is a movement. And so, as teachers think they have 
achieved their end when they have exhibited the pupil at work, 
nature does likewise. For if this is not the case, we shall have 
Pauson's Hermes over again, since it will be hard to say about 
the knowledge, as about the figure in the picture, whether it is 
within or without. For the action is the end, and the actuality is 
the action. And so even the word 'actuality' is derived from 
'action', and points to the complete reality. 



2404 



And while in some cases the exercise is the ultimate thing (e.g. 
in sight the ultimate thing is seeing, and no other product 
besides this results from sight), but from some things a product 
follows (e.g. from the art of building there results a house as 
well as the act of building), yet none the less the act is in the 
former case the end and in the latter more of an end than the 
potency is. For the act of building is realized in the thing that is 
being built, and comes to be, and is, at the same time as the 
house. 

Where, then, the result is something apart from the exercise, 
the actuality is in the thing that is being made, e.g. the act of 
building is in the thing that is being built and that of weaving in 
the thing that is being woven, and similarly in all other cases, 
and in general the movement is in the thing that is being 
moved; but where there is no product apart from the actuality, 
the actuality is present in the agents, e.g. the act of seeing is in 
the seeing subject and that of theorizing in the theorizing 
subject and the life is in the soul (and therefore well-being also; 
for it is a certain kind of life). 

Obviously, therefore, the substance or form is actuality. 
According to this argument, then, it is obvious that actuality is 
prior in substantial being to potency; and as we have said, one 
actuality always precedes another in time right back to the 
actuality of the eternal prime mover. 

But (b) actuality is prior in a stricter sense also; for eternal 
things are prior in substance to perishable things, and no 
eternal thing exists potentially. The reason is this. Every potency 
is at one and the same time a potency of the opposite; for, while 
that which is not capable of being present in a subject cannot be 
present, everything that is capable of being may possibly not be 
actual. That, then, which is capable of being may either be or 
not be; the same thing, then, is capable both of being and of not 



2405 



being. And that which is capable of not being may possibly not 
be; and that which may possibly not be is perishable, either in 
the full sense, or in the precise sense in which it is said that it 
possibly may not be, i.e. in respect either of place or of quantity 
or quality; 'in the full sense' means 'in respect of substance'. 
Nothing, then, which is in the full sense imperishable is in the 
full sense potentially existent (though there is nothing to 
prevent its being so in some respect, e.g. potentially of a certain 
quality or in a certain place); all imperishable things, then, exist 
actually. Nor can anything which is of necessity exist 
potentially; yet these things are primary; for if these did not 
exist, nothing would exist. Nor does eternal movement, if there 
be such, exist potentially; and, if there is an eternal mobile, it is 
not in motion in virtue of a potentiality, except in respect of 
'whence' and 'whither' (there is nothing to prevent its having 
matter which makes it capable of movement in various 
directions). And so the sun and the stars and the whole heaven 
are ever active, and there is no fear that they may sometime 
stand still, as the natural philosophers fear they may. Nor do 
they tire in this activity; for movement is not for them, as it is 
for perishable things, connected with the potentiality for 
opposites, so that the continuity of the movement should be 
laborious; for it is that kind of substance which is matter and 
potency, not actuality, that causes this. 

Imperishable things are imitated by those that are involved in 
change, e.g. earth and fire. For these also are ever active; for 
they have their movement of themselves and in themselves. But 
the other potencies, according to our previous discussion, are all 
potencies for opposites; for that which can move another in this 
way can also move it not in this way, i.e. if it acts according to a 
rational formula; and the same non-rational potencies will 
produce opposite results by their presence or absence. 



2406 



If, then, there are any entities or substances such as the 
dialecticians say the Ideas are, there must be something much 
more scientific than science-itself and something more mobile 
than movement-itself; for these will be more of the nature of 
actualities, while science-itself and movement-itself are 
potencies for these. 

Obviously, then, actuality is prior both to potency and to every 
principle of change. 



That the actuality is also better and more valuable than the 
good potency is evident from the following argument. 
Everything of which we say that it can do something, is alike 
capable of contraries, e.g. that of which we say that it can be 
well is the same as that which can be ill, and has both potencies 
at once; for the same potency is a potency of health and illness, 
of rest and motion, of building and throwing down, of being 
built and being thrown down. The capacity for contraries, then, 
is present at the same time; but contraries cannot be present at 
the same time, and the actualities also cannot be present at the 
same time, e.g. health and illness. Therefore, while the good 
must be one of them, the capacity is both alike, or neither; the 
actuality, then, is better. Also in the case of bad things the end 
or actuality must be worse than the potency; for that which 
'can' is both contraries alike. Clearly, then, the bad does not 
exist apart from bad things; for the bad is in its nature posterior 
to the potency. And therefore we may also say that in the things 
which are from the beginning, i.e. in eternal things, there is 
nothing bad, nothing defective, nothing perverted (for 
perversion is something bad). 



2407 



It is an activity also that geometrical constructions are 
discovered; for we find them by dividing. If the figures had been 
already divided, the constructions would have been obvious; but 
as it is they are present only potentially. Why are the angles of 
the triangle equal to two right angles? Because the angles about 
one point are equal to two right angles. If, then, the line parallel 
to the side had been already drawn upwards, the reason would 
have been evident to any one as soon as he saw the figure. Why 
is the angle in a semicircle in all cases a right angle? If three 
lines are equal the two which form the base, and the 
perpendicular from the centre - the conclusion is evident at a 
glance to one who knows the former proposition. Obviously, 
therefore, the potentially existing constructions are discovered 
by being brought to actuality; the reason is that the geometer's 
thinking is an actuality; so that the potency proceeds from an 
actuality; and therefore it is by making constructions that 
people come to know them (though the single actuality is later 
in generation than the corresponding potency). (See diagram.) 



10 

The terms 'being' and 'non-being' are employed firstly with 
reference to the categories, and secondly with reference to the 
potency or actuality of these or their non-potency or 
nonactuality, and thirdly in the sense of true and false. This 
depends, on the side of the objects, on their being combined or 
separated, so that he who thinks the separated to be separated 
and the combined to be combined has the truth, while he 
whose thought is in a state contrary to that of the objects is in 
error. This being so, when is what is called truth or falsity 
present, and when is it not? We must consider what we mean 
by these terms. It is not because we think truly that you are 



2408 



pale, that you are pale, but because you are pale we who say 
this have the truth. If, then, some things are always combined 
and cannot be separated, and others are always separated and 
cannot be combined, while others are capable either of 
combination or of separation, 'being' is being combined and 
one, and 'not being' is being not combined but more than one. 
Regarding contingent facts, then, the same opinion or the same 
statement comes to be false and true, and it is possible for it to 
be at one time correct and at another erroneous; but regarding 
things that cannot be otherwise opinions are not at one time 
true and at another false, but the same opinions are always true 
or always false. 

But with regard to incomposites, what is being or not being, and 
truth or falsity? A thing of this sort is not composite, so as to 
'be' when it is compounded, and not to 'be' if it is separated, like 
'that the wood is white' or 'that the diagonal is 
incommensurable'; nor will truth and falsity be still present in 
the same way as in the previous cases. In fact, as truth is not 
the same in these cases, so also being is not the same; but (a) 
truth or falsity is as follows - contact and assertion are truth 
(assertion not being the same as affirmation), and ignorance is 
non-contact. For it is not possible to be in error regarding the 
question what a thing is, save in an accidental sense; and the 
same holds good regarding non-composite substances (for it is 
not possible to be in error about them). And they all exist 
actually, not potentially; for otherwise they would have come to 
be and ceased to be; but, as it is, being itself does not come to be 
(nor cease to be); for if it had done so it would have had to come 
out of something. About the things, then, which are essences 
and actualities, it is not possible to be in error, but only to know 
them or not to know them. But we do inquire what they are, viz. 
whether they are of such and such a nature or not. 



2409 



(b) As regards the 'being' that answers to truth and the 'non- 
being' that answers to falsity, in one case there is truth if the 
subject and the attribute are really combined, and falsity if they 
are not combined; in the other case, if the object is existent it 
exists in a particular way, and if it does not exist in this way 
does not exist at all. And truth means knowing these objects, 
and falsity does not exist, nor error, but only ignorance - and 
not an ignorance which is like blindness; for blindness is akin to 
a total absence of the faculty of thinking. 

It is evident also that about unchangeable things there can be 
no error in respect of time, if we assume them to be 
unchangeable. E.g. if we suppose that the triangle does not 
change, we shall not suppose that at one time its angles are 
equal to two right angles while at another time they are not (for 
that would imply change). It is possible, however, to suppose 
that one member of such a class has a certain attribute and 
another has not; e.g. while we may suppose that no even 
number is prime, we may suppose that some are and some are 
not. But regarding a numerically single number not even this 
form of error is possible; for we cannot in this case suppose that 
one instance has an attribute and another has not, but whether 
our judgement be true or false, it is implied that the fact is 
eternal. 



2410 



Book I 



We have said previously, in our distinction of the various 
meanings of words, that 'one' has several meanings; the things 
that are directly and of their own nature and not accidentally 
called one may be summarized under four heads, though the 
word is used in more senses. (1) There is the continuous, either 
in general, or especially that which is continuous by nature and 
not by contact nor by being together; and of these, that has 
more unity and is prior, whose movement is more indivisible 
and simpler. (2) That which is a whole and has a certain shape 
and form is one in a still higher degree; and especially if a thing 
is of this sort by nature, and not by force like the things which 
are unified by glue or nails or by being tied together, i.e. if it has 
in itself the cause of its continuity. A thing is of this sort 
because its movement is one and indivisible in place and time; 
so that evidently if a thing has by nature a principle of 
movement that is of the first kind (i.e. local movement) and the 
first in that kind (i.e. circular movement), this is in the primary 
sense one extended thing. Some things, then, are one in this 
way, qua continuous or whole, and the other things that are one 
are those whose definition is one. Of this sort are the things the 
thought of which is one, i.e. those the thought of which is 
indivisible; and it is indivisible if the thing is indivisible in kind 
or in number. (3) In number, then, the individual is indivisible, 
and (4) in kind, that which in intelligibility and in knowledge is 
indivisible, so that that which causes substances to be one must 
be one in the primary sense. 'One', then, has all these meanings 
- the naturally continuous and the whole, and the individual 
and the universal. And all these are one because in some cases 



2411 



the movement, in others the thought or the definition is 
indivisible. 

But it must be observed that the questions, what sort of things 
are said to be one, and what it is to be one and what is the 
definition of it, should not be assumed to be the same. 'One' has 
all these meanings, and each of the things to which one of 
these kinds of unity belongs will be one; but 'to be one' will 
sometimes mean being one of these things, and sometimes 
being something else which is even nearer to the meaning of 
the word 'one' while these other things approximate to its 
application. This is also true of 'element' or 'cause', if one had 
both to specify the things of which it is predicable and to render 
the definition of the word. For in a sense fire is an element (and 
doubtless also 'the indefinite' or something else of the sort is by 
its own nature the element), but in a sense it is not; for it is not 
the same thing to be fire and to be an element, but while as a 
particular thing with a nature of its own fire is an element, the 
name 'element' means that it has this attribute, that there is 
something which is made of it as a primary constituent. And so 
with 'cause' and 'one' and all such terms. For this reason, too, 
'to be one' means 'to be indivisible, being essentially one means 
a «this» and capable of being isolated either in place, or in form 
or thought'; or perhaps 'to be whole and indivisible'; but it 
means especially 'to be the first measure of a kind', and most 
strictly of quantity; for it is from this that it has been extended 
to the other categories. For measure is that by which quantity is 
known; and quantity qua quantity is known either by a 'one' or 
by a number, and all number is known by a 'one'. Therefore all 
quantity qua quantity is known by the one, and that by which 
quantities are primarily known is the one itself; and so the one 
is the starting-point of number qua number. And hence in the 
other classes too 'measure' means that by which each is first 
known, and the measure of each is a unit - in length, in breadth, 
in depth, in weight, in speed. (The words 'weight' and 'speed' 



2412 



are common to both contraries; for each of them has two 
meanings - 'weight' means both that which has any amount of 
gravity and that which has an excess of gravity, and 'speed' both 
that which has any amount of movement and that which has 
an excess of movement; for even the slow has a certain speed 
and the comparatively light a certain weight.) 

In all these, then, the measure and starting-point is something 
one and indivisible, since even in lines we treat as indivisible 
the line a foot long. For everywhere we seek as the measure 
something one and indivisible; and this is that which is simple 
either in quality or in quantity. Now where it is thought 
impossible to take away or to add, there the measure is exact 
(hence that of number is most exact; for we posit the unit as 
indivisible in every respect); but in all other cases we imitate 
this sort of measure. For in the case of a furlong or a talent or of 
anything comparatively large any addition or subtraction might 
more easily escape our notice than in the case of something 
smaller; so that the first thing from which, as far as our 
perception goes, nothing can be subtracted, all men make the 
measure, whether of liquids or of solids, whether of weight or of 
size; and they think they know the quantity when they know it 
by means of this measure. And indeed they know movement 
too by the simple movement and the quickest; for this occupies 
least time. And so in astronomy a 'one' of this sort is the 
starting-point and measure (for they assume the movement of 
the heavens to be uniform and the quickest, and judge the 
others by reference to it), and in music the quarter-tone 
(because it is the least interval), and in speech the letter. And all 
these are ones in this sense - not that 'one' is something 
predicable in the same sense of all of these, but in the sense we 
have mentioned. 

But the measure is not always one in number - sometimes there 
are several; e.g. the quarter-tones (not to the ear, but as 



2413 



determined by the ratios) are two, and the articulate sounds by 
which we measure are more than one, and the diagonal of the 
square and its side are measured by two quantities, and all 
spatial magnitudes reveal similar varieties of unit. Thus, then, 
the one is the measure of all things, because we come to know 
the elements in the substance by dividing the things either in 
respect of quantity or in respect of kind. And the one is 
indivisible just because the first of each class of things is 
indivisible. But it is not in the same way that every 'one' is 
indivisible e.g. a foot and a unit; the latter is indivisible in every 
respect, while the former must be placed among things which 
are undivided to perception, as has been said already - only to 
perception, for doubtless every continuous thing is divisible. 

The measure is always homogeneous with the thing measured; 
the measure of spatial magnitudes is a spatial magnitude, and 
in particular that of length is a length, that of breadth a breadth, 
that of articulate sound an articulate sound, that of weight a 
weight, that of units a unit. (For we must state the matter so, 
and not say that the measure of numbers is a number; we ought 
indeed to say this if we were to use the corresponding form of 
words, but the claim does not really correspond - it is as if one 
claimed that the measure of units is units and not a unit; 
number is a plurality of units.) 

Knowledge, also, and perception, we call the measure of things 
for the same reason, because we come to know something by 
them - while as a matter of fact they are measured rather than 
measure other things. But it is with us as if some one else 
measured us and we came to know how big we are by seeing 
that he applied the cubit-measure to such and such a fraction of 
us. But Protagoras says 'man is the measure of all things', as if 
he had said 'the man who knows' or 'the man who perceives'; 
and these because they have respectively knowledge and 
perception, which we say are the measures of objects. Such 



2414 



thinkers are saying nothing, then, while they appear to be 
saying something remarkable. 

Evidently, then, unity in the strictest sense, if we define it 
according to the meaning of the word, is a measure, and most 
properly of quantity, and secondly of quality. And some things 
will be one if they are indivisible in quantity, and others if they 
are indivisible in quality; and so that which is one is indivisible, 
either absolutely or qua one. 



With regard to the substance and nature of the one we must ask 
in which of two ways it exists. This is the very question that we 
reviewed in our discussion of problems, viz. what the one is and 
how we must conceive of it, whether we must take the one 
itself as being a substance (as both the Pythagoreans say in 
earlier and Plato in later times), or there is, rather, an underlying 
nature and the one should be described more intelligibly and 
more in the manner of the physical philosophers, of whom one 
says the one is love, another says it is air, and another the 
indefinite. 

If, then, no universal can be a substance, as has been said our 
discussion of substance and being, and if being itself cannot be 
a substance in the sense of a one apart from the many (for it is 
common to the many), but is only a predicate, clearly unity also 
cannot be a substance; for being and unity are the most 
universal of all predicates. Therefore, on the one hand, genera 
are not certain entities and substances separable from other 
things; and on the other hand the one cannot be a genus, for 
the same reasons for which being and substance cannot be 
genera. 



2415 



Further, the position must be similar in all the kinds of unity. 
Now 'unity' has just as many meanings as 'being'; so that since 
in the sphere of qualities the one is something definite - some 
particular kind of thing - and similarly in the sphere of 
quantities, clearly we must in every category ask what the one 
is, as we must ask what the existent is, since it is not enough to 
say that its nature is just to be one or existent. But in colours 
the one is a colour, e.g. white, and then the other colours are 
observed to be produced out of this and black, and black is the 
privation of white, as darkness of light. Therefore if all existent 
things were colours, existent things would have been a number, 
indeed, but of what? Clearly of colours; and the 'one' would 
have been a particular 'one', i.e. white. And similarly if all 
existing things were tunes, they would have been a number, but 
a number of quarter-tones, and their essence would not have 
been number; and the one would have been something whose 
substance was not to be one but to be the quarter-tone. And 
similarly if all existent things had been articulate sounds, they 
would have been a number of letters, and the one would have 
been a vowel. And if all existent things were rectilinear figures, 
they would have been a number of figures, and the one would 
have been the triangle. And the same argument applies to all 
other classes. Since, therefore, while there are numbers and a 
one both in affections and in qualities and in quantities and in 
movement, in all cases the number is a number of particular 
things and the one is one something, and its substance is not 
just to be one, the same must be true of substances also; for it is 
true of all cases alike. 

That the one, then, in every class is a definite thing, and in no 
case is its nature just this, unity, is evident; but as in colours the 
one-itself which we must seek is one colour, so too in substance 
the one-itself is one substance. That in a sense unity means the 
same as being is clear from the facts that its meanings 
correspond to the categories one to one, and it is not comprised 



2416 



within any category (e.g. it is comprised neither in 'what a thing 
is' nor in quality, but is related to them just as being is); that in 
'one man' nothing more is predicated than in 'man' (just as 
being is nothing apart from substance or quality or quantity); 
and that to be one is just to be a particular thing. 



The one and the many are opposed in several ways, of which 
one is the opposition of the one and plurality as indivisible and 
divisible; for that which is either divided or divisible is called a 
plurality, and that which is indivisible or not divided is called 
one. Now since opposition is of four kinds, and one of these two 
terms is privative in meaning, they must be contraries, and 
neither contradictory nor correlative in meaning. And the one 
derives its name and its explanation from its contrary, the 
indivisible from the divisible, because plurality and the divisible 
is more perceptible than the indivisible, so that in definition 
plurality is prior to the indivisible, because of the conditions of 
perception. 

To the one belong, as we indicated graphically in our distinction 
of the contraries, the same and the like and the equal, and to 
plurality belong the other and the unlike and the unequal. 'The 
same' has several meanings; (1) we sometimes mean 'the same 
numerically'; again, (2) we call a thing the same if it is one both 
in definition and in number, e.g. you are one with yourself both 
in form and in matter; and again, (3) if the definition of its 
primary essence is one; e.g. equal straight lines are the same, 
and so are equal and equal-angled quadrilaterals; there are 
many such, but in these equality constitutes unity. 



2417 



Things are like if, not being absolutely the same, nor without 
difference in respect of their concrete substance, they are the 
same in form; e.g. the larger square is like the smaller, and 
unequal straight lines are like; they are like, but not absolutely 
the same. Other things are like, if, having the same form, and 
being things in which difference of degree is possible, they have 
no difference of degree. Other things, if they have a quality that 
is in form one and same - e.g. whiteness - in a greater or less 
degree, are called like because their form is one. Other things 
are called like if the qualities they have in common are more 
numerous than those in which they differ - either the qualities 
in general or the prominent qualities; e.g. tin is like silver, qua 
white, and gold is like fire, qua yellow and red. 

Evidently, then, 'other' and 'unlike' also have several meanings. 
And the other in one sense is the opposite of the same (so that 
everything is either the same as or other than everything else). 
In another sense things are other unless both their matter and 
their definition are one (so that you are other than your 
neighbour). The other in the third sense is exemplified in the 
objects of mathematics. 'Other or the same' can therefore be 
predicated of everything with regard to everything else - but 
only if the things are one and existent, for 'other' is not the 
contradictory of 'the same'; which is why it is not predicated of 
non-existent things (while 'not the same' is so predicated). It is 
predicated of all existing things; for everything that is existent 
and one is by its very nature either one or not one with 
anything else. 

The other, then, and the same are thus opposed. But difference 
is not the same as otherness. For the other and that which it is 
other than need not be other in some definite respect (for 
everything that is existent is either other or the same), but that 
which is different is different from some particular thing in 
some particular respect, so that there must be something 



2418 



identical whereby they differ. And this identical thing is genus 
or species; for everything that differs differs either in genus or 
in species, in genus if the things have not their matter in 
common and are not generated out of each other (i.e. if they 
belong to different figures of predication), and in species if they 
have the same genus ('genus' meaning that identical thing 
which is essentially predicated of both the different things). 

Contraries are different, and contrariety is a kind of difference. 
That we are right in this supposition is shown by induction. For 
all of these too are seen to be different; they are not merely 
other, but some are other in genus, and others are in the same 
line of predication, and therefore in the same genus, and the 
same in genus. We have distinguished elsewhere what sort of 
things are the same or other in genus. 



Since things which differ may differ from one another more or 
less, there is also a greatest difference, and this I call contrariety. 
That contrariety is the greatest difference is made clear by 
induction. For things which differ in genus have no way to one 
another, but are too far distant and are not comparable; and for 
things that differ in species the extremes from which 
generation takes place are the contraries, and the distance 
between extremes - and therefore that between the contraries - 
is the greatest. 

But surely that which is greatest in each class is complete. For 
that is greatest which cannot be exceeded, and that is complete 
beyond which nothing can be found. For the complete 
difference marks the end of a series (just as the other things 
which are called complete are so called because they have 



2419 



attained an end), and beyond the end there is nothing; for in 
everything it is the extreme and includes all else, and therefore 
there is nothing beyond the end, and the complete needs 
nothing further. From this, then, it is clear that contrariety is 
complete difference; and as contraries are so called in several 
senses, their modes of completeness will answer to the various 
modes of contrariety which attach to the contraries. 

This being so, it is clear that one thing have more than one 
contrary (for neither can there be anything more extreme than 
the extreme, nor can there be more than two extremes for the 
one interval), and, to put the matter generally, this is clear if 
contrariety is a difference, and if difference, and therefore also 
the complete difference, must be between two things. 

And the other commonly accepted definitions of contraries are 
also necessarily true. For not only is (1) the complete difference 
the greatest difference (for we can get no difference beyond it of 
things differing either in genus or in species; for it has been 
shown that there is no 'difference' between anything and the 
things outside its genus, and among the things which differ in 
species the complete difference is the greatest); but also (2) the 
things in the same genus which differ most are contrary (for the 
complete difference is the greatest difference between species 
of the same genus); and (3) the things in the same receptive 
material which differ most are contrary (for the matter is the 
same for contraries); and (4) of the things which fall under the 
same faculty the most different are contrary (for one science 
deals with one class of things, and in these the complete 
difference is the greatest). 

The primary contrariety is that between positive state and 
privation - not every privation, however (for 'privation' has 
several meanings), but that which is complete. And the other 
contraries must be called so with reference to these, some 



2420 



because they possess these, others because they produce or 
tend to produce them, others because they are acquisitions or 
losses of these or of other contraries. Now if the kinds of 
opposition are contradiction and privation and contrariety and 
relation, and of these the first is contradiction, and 
contradiction admits of no intermediate, while contraries admit 
of one, clearly contradiction and contrariety are not the same. 
But privation is a kind of contradiction; for what suffers 
privation, either in general or in some determinate way, either 
that which is quite incapable of having some attribute or that 
which, being of such a nature as to have it, has it not; here we 
have already a variety of meanings, which have been 
distinguished elsewhere. Privation, therefore, is a contradiction 
or incapacity which is determinate or taken along with the 
receptive material. This is the reason why, while contradiction 
does not admit of an intermediate, privation sometimes does; 
for everything is equal or not equal, but not everything is equal 
or unequal, or if it is, it is only within the sphere of that which is 
receptive of equality. If, then, the comings-to-be which happen 
to the matter start from the contraries, and proceed either from 
the form and the possession of the form or from a privation of 
the form or shape, clearly all contrariety must be privation, but 
presumably not all privation is contrariety (the reason being 
that that has suffered privation may have suffered it in several 
ways); for it is only the extremes from which changes proceed 
that are contraries. 

And this is obvious also by induction. For every contrariety 
involves, as one of its terms, a privation, but not all cases are 
alike; inequality is the privation of equality and unlikeness of 
likeness, and on the other hand vice is the privation of virtue. 
But the cases differ in a way already described; in one case we 
mean simply that the thing has suffered privation, in another 
case that it has done so either at a certain time or in a certain 
part (e.g. at a certain age or in the dominant part), or 



2421 



throughout. This is why in some cases there is a mean (there 
are men who are neither good nor bad), and in others there is 
not (a number must be either odd or even). Further, some 
contraries have their subject defined, others have not. Therefore 
it is evident that one of the contraries is always privative; but it 
is enough if this is true of the first - i.e. the generic - contraries, 
e.g. the one and the many; for the others can be reduced to 
these. 



Since one thing has one contrary, we might raise the question 
how the one is opposed to the many, and the equal to the great 
and the small. For if we used the word 'whether' only in an 
antithesis such as 'whether it is white or black', or 'whether it is 
white or not white' (we do not ask 'whether it is a man or 
white'), unless we are proceeding on a prior assumption and 
asking something such as 'whether it was Cleon or Socrates 
that came' as this is not a necessary disjunction in any class of 
things; yet even this is an extension from the case of opposites; 
for opposites alone cannot be present together; and we assume 
this incompatibility here too in asking which of the two came; 
for if they might both have come, the question would have been 
absurd; but if they might, even so this falls just as much into an 
antithesis, that of the 'one or many', i.e. 'whether both came or 
one of the two': - if, then, the question 'whether' is always 
concerned with opposites, and we can ask 'whether it is greater 
or less or equal', what is the opposition of the equal to the other 
two? It is not contrary either to one alone or to both; for why 
should it be contrary to the greater rather than to the less? 
Further, the equal is contrary to the unequal. Therefore if it is 
contrary to the greater and the less, it will be contrary to more 



2422 



things than one. But if the unequal means the same as both the 
greater and the less together, the equal will be opposite to both 
(and the difficulty supports those who say the unequal is a 
'two'), but it follows that one thing is contrary to two others, 
which is impossible. Again, the equal is evidently intermediate 
between the great and the small, but no contrariety is either 
observed to be intermediate, or, from its definition, can be so; 
for it would not be complete if it were intermediate between 
any two things, but rather it always has something intermediate 
between its own terms. 

It remains, then, that it is opposed either as negation or as 
privation. It cannot be the negation or privation of one of the 
two; for why of the great rather than of the small? It is, then, the 
privative negation of both. This is why 'whether' is said with 
reference to both, not to one of the two (e.g. 'whether it is 
greater or equal' or 'whether it is equal or less'); there are 
always three cases. But it is not a necessary privation; for not 
everything which is not greater or less is equal, but only the 
things which are of such a nature as to have these attributes. 

The equal, then, is that which is neither great nor small but is 
naturally fitted to be either great or small; and it is opposed to 
both as a privative negation (and therefore is also intermediate). 
And that which is neither good nor bad is opposed to both, but 
has no name; for each of these has several meanings and the 
recipient subject is not one; but that which is neither white nor 
black has more claim to unity. Yet even this has not one name, 
though the colours of which this negation is privatively 
predicated are in a way limited; for they must be either grey or 
yellow or something else of the kind. Therefore it is an incorrect 
criticism that is passed by those who think that all such phrases 
are used in the same way, so that that which is neither a shoe 
nor a hand would be intermediate between a shoe and a hand, 
since that which is neither good nor bad is intermediate 



2423 



between the good and the bad - as if there must be an 
intermediate in all cases. But this does not necessarily follow. 
For the one phrase is a joint denial of opposites between which 
there is an intermediate and a certain natural interval; but 
between the other two there is no 'difference'; for the things, 
the denials of which are combined, belong to different classes, 
so that the substratum is not one. 



We might raise similar questions about the one and the many. 
For if the many are absolutely opposed to the one, certain 
impossible results follow. One will then be few, whether few be 
treated here as singular or plural; for the many are opposed also 
to the few. Further, two will be many, since the double is 
multiple and 'double' derives its meaning from 'two'; therefore 
one will be few; for what is that in comparison with which two 
are many, except one, which must therefore be few? For there is 
nothing fewer. Further, if the much and the little are in plurality 
what the long and the short are in length, and whatever is 
much is also many, and the many are much (unless, indeed, 
there is a difference in the case of an easily-bounded 
continuum), the little (or few) will be a plurality. Therefore one is 
a plurality if it is few; and this it must be, if two are many. But 
perhaps, while the 'many' are in a sense said to be also 'much', 
it is with a difference; e.g. water is much but not many. But 
'many' is applied to the things that are divisible; in the one 
sense it means a plurality which is excessive either absolutely 
or relatively (while 'few' is similarly a plurality which is 
deficient), and in another sense it means number, in which 
sense alone it is opposed to the one. For we say 'one or many', 
just as if one were to say 'one and ones' or 'white thing and 



2424 



white things', or to compare the things that have been 
measured with the measure. It is in this sense also that 
multiples are so called. For each number is said to be many 
because it consists of ones and because each number is 
measurable by one; and it is 'many' as that which is opposed to 
one, not to the few. In this sense, then, even two is many - not, 
however, in the sense of a plurality which is excessive either 
relatively or absolutely; it is the first plurality. But without 
qualification two is few; for it is first plurality which is deficient 
(for this reason Anaxagoras was not right in leaving the subject 
with the statement that 'all things were together, boundless 
both in plurality and in smallness' - where for 'and in 
smallness' he should have said 'and in fewness'; for they could 
not have been boundless in fewness), since it is not one, as 
some say, but two, that make a few. 

The one is opposed then to the many in numbers as measure to 
thing measurable; and these are opposed as are the relatives 
which are not from their very nature relatives. We have 
distinguished elsewhere the two senses in which relatives are 
so called: - (1) as contraries; (2) as knowledge to thing known, a 
term being called relative because another is relative to it. There 
is nothing to prevent one from being fewer than something, e.g. 
than two; for if one is fewer, it is not therefore few. Plurality is as 
it were the class to which number belongs; for number is 
plurality measurable by one, and one and number are in a sense 
opposed, not as contrary, but as we have said some relative 
terms are opposed; for inasmuch as one is measure and the 
other measurable, they are opposed. This is why not everything 
that is one is a number; i.e. if the thing is indivisible it is not a 
number. But though knowledge is similarly spoken of as relative 
to the knowable, the relation does not work out similarly; for 
while knowledge might be thought to be the measure, and the 
knowable the thing measured, the fact that all knowledge is 
knowable, but not all that is knowable is knowledge, because in 



2425 



a sense knowledge is measured by the knowable. - Plurality is 
contrary neither to the few (the many being contrary to this as 
excessive plurality to plurality exceeded), nor to the one in 
every sense; but in the one sense these are contrary, as has been 
said, because the former is divisible and the latter indivisible, 
while in another sense they are relative as knowledge is to 
knowable, if plurality is number and the one is a measure. 



Since contraries admit of an intermediate and in some cases 
have it, intermediates must be composed of the contraries. For 
(1) all intermediates are in the same genus as the things 
between which they stand. For we call those things 
intermediates, into which that which changes must change 
first; e.g. if we were to pass from the highest string to the lowest 
by the smallest intervals, we should come sooner to the 
intermediate notes, and in colours if we were to pass from 
white to black, we should come sooner to crimson and grey 
than to black; and similarly in all other cases. But to change 
from one genus to another genus is not possible except in an 
incidental way, as from colour to figure. Intermediates, then, 
must be in the same genus both as one another and as the 
things they stand between. 

But (2) all intermediates stand between opposites of some kind; 
for only between these can change take place in virtue of their 
own nature (so that an intermediate is impossible between 
things which are not opposite; for then there would be change 
which was not from one opposite towards the other). Of 
opposites, contradictories admit of no middle term; for this is 
what contradiction is - an opposition, one or other side of 



2426 



which must attach to anything whatever, i.e. which has no 
intermediate. Of other opposites, some are relative, others 
privative, others contrary. Of relative terms, those which are not 
contrary have no intermediate; the reason is that they are not in 
the same genus. For what intermediate could there be between 
knowledge and knowable? But between great and small there is 
one. 

(3) If intermediates are in the same genus, as has been shown, 
and stand between contraries, they must be composed of these 
contraries. For either there will be a genus including the 
contraries or there will be none. And if (a) there is to be a genus 
in such a way that it is something prior to the contraries, the 
differentiae which constituted the contrary species-of-a-genus 
will be contraries prior to the species; for species are composed 
of the genus and the differentiae. (E.g. if white and black are 
contraries, and one is a piercing colour and the other a 
compressing colour, these differentiae - 'piercing' and 
'compressing' - are prior; so that these are prior contraries of 
one another.) But, again, the species which differ contrariwise 
are the more truly contrary species. And the other.species, i.e. 
the intermediates, must be composed of their genus and their 
differentiae. (E.g. all colours which are between white and black 
must be said to be composed of the genus, i.e. colour, and 
certain differentiae. But these differentiae will not be the 
primary contraries; otherwise every colour would be either 
white or black. They are different, then, from the primary 
contraries; and therefore they will be between the primary 
contraries; the primary differentiae are 'piercing' and 
'compressing'.) 

Therefore it is (b) with regard to these contraries which do not 
fall within a genus that we must first ask of what their 
intermediates are composed. (For things which are in the same 
genus must be composed of terms in which the genus is not an 



2427 



element, or else be themselves incomposite.) Now contraries do 
not involve one another in their composition, and are therefore 
first principles; but the intermediates are either all incomposite, 
or none of them. But there is something compounded out of the 
contraries, so that there can be a change from a contrary to it 
sooner than to the other contrary; for it will have less of the 
quality in question than the one contrary and more than the 
other. This also, then, will come between the contraries. All the 
other intermediates also, therefore, are composite; for that 
which has more of a quality than one thing and less than 
another is compounded somehow out of the things than which 
it is said to have more and less respectively of the quality. And 
since there are no other things prior to the contraries and 
homogeneous with the intermediates, all intermediates must 
be compounded out of the contraries. Therefore also all the 
inferior classes, both the contraries and their intermediates, will 
be compounded out of the primary contraries. Clearly, then, 
intermediates are (1) all in the same genus and (2) intermediate 
between contraries, and (3) all compounded out of the 
contraries. 



8 

That which is other in species is other than something in 
something, and this must belong to both; e.g. if it is an animal 
other in species, both are animals. The things, then, which are 
other in species must be in the same genus. For by genus I 
mean that one identical thing which is predicated of both and is 
differentiated in no merely accidental way, whether conceived 
as matter or otherwise. For not only must the common nature 
attach to the different things, e.g. not only must both be 
animals, but this very animality must also be different for each 



2428 



(e.g. in the one case equinity, in the other humanity), and so this 
common nature is specifically different for each from what it is 
for the other. One, then, will be in virtue of its own nature one 
sort of animal, and the other another, e.g. one a horse and the 
other a man. This difference, then, must be an otherness of the 
genus. For I give the name of 'difference in the genus' an 
otherness which makes the genus itself other. 

This, then, will be a contrariety (as can be shown also by 
induction). For all things are divided by opposites, and it has 
been proved that contraries are in the same genus. For 
contrariety was seen to be complete difference; and all 
difference in species is a difference from something in 
something; so that this is the same for both and is their genus. 
(Hence also all contraries which are different in species and not 
in genus are in the same line of predication, and other than one 
another in the highest degree - for the difference is complete - , 
and cannot be present along with one another.) The difference, 
then, is a contrariety. 

This, then, is what it is to be 'other in species' - to have a 
contrariety, being in the same genus and being indivisible (and 
those things are the same in species which have no contrariety, 
being indivisible); we say 'being indivisible', for in the process of 
division contrarieties arise in the intermediate stages before we 
come to the indivisibles. Evidently, therefore, with reference to 
that which is called the genus, none of the species-of-a-genus is 
either the same as it or other than it in species (and this is 
fitting; for the matter is indicated by negation, and the genus is 
the matter of that of which it is called the genus, not in the 
sense in which we speak of the genus or family of the 
Heraclidae, but in that in which the genus is an element in a 
thing's nature), nor is it so with reference to things which are 
not in the same genus, but it will differ in genus from them, and 
in species from things in the same genus. For a thing's 



2429 



difference from that from which it differs in species must be a 
contrariety; and this belongs only to things in the same genus. 



One might raise the question, why woman does not differ from 
man in species, when female and male are contrary and their 
difference is a contrariety; and why a female and a male animal 
are not different in species, though this difference belongs to 
animal in virtue of its own nature, and not as paleness or 
darkness does; both 'female' and 'male' belong to it qua animal. 
This question is almost the same as the other, why one 
contrariety makes things different in species and another does 
not, e.g. 'with feet' and 'with wings' do, but paleness and 
darkness do not. Perhaps it is because the former are 
modifications peculiar to the genus, and the latter are less so. 
And since one element is definition and one is matter, 
contrarieties which are in the definition make a difference in 
species, but those which are in the thing taken as including its 
matter do not make one. And so paleness in a man, or darkness, 
does not make one, nor is there a difference in species between 
the pale man and the dark man, not even if each of them be 
denoted by one word. For man is here being considered on his 
material side, and matter does not create a difference; for it 
does not make individual men species of man, though the flesh 
and the bones of which this man and that man consist are 
other. The concrete thing is other, but not other in species, 
because in the definition there is no contrariety. This is the 
ultimate indivisible kind. Callias is definition + matter, the pale 
man, then, is so also, because it is the individual Callias that is 
pale; man, then, is pale only incidentally. Neither do a brazen 
and a wooden circle, then, differ in species; and if a brazen 



2430 



triangle and a wooden circle differ in species, it is not because 
of the matter, but because there is a contrariety in the 
definition. But does the matter not make things other in 
species, when it is other in a certain way, or is there a sense in 
which it does? For why is this horse other than this man in 
species, although their matter is included with their 
definitions? Doubtless because there is a contrariety in the 
definition. For while there is a contrariety also between pale 
man and dark horse, and it is a contrariety in species, it does 
not depend on the paleness of the one and the darkness of the 
other, since even if both had been pale, yet they would have 
been other in species. But male and female, while they are 
modifications peculiar to 'animal', are so not in virtue of its 
essence but in the matter, ie. the body. This is why the same 
seed becomes female or male by being acted on in a certain 
way. We have stated, then, what it is to be other in species, and 
why some things differ in species and others do not. 



10 

Since contraries are other in form, and the perishable and the 
imperishable are contraries (for privation is a determinate 
incapacity), the perishable and the imperishable must be 
different in kind. 

Now so far we have spoken of the general terms themselves, so 
that it might be thought not to be necessary that every 
imperishable thing should be different from every perishable 
thing in form, just as not every pale thing is different in form 
from every dark thing. For the same thing can be both, and even 
at the same time if it is a universal (e.g. man can be both pale 
and dark), and if it is an individual it can still be both; for the 



2431 



same man can be, though not at the same time, pale and dark. 
Yet pale is contrary to dark. 

But while some contraries belong to certain things by accident 
(e.g. both those now mentioned and many others), others 
cannot, and among these are 'perishable' and 'imperishable'. For 
nothing is by accident perishable. For what is accidental is 
capable of not being present, but perishableness is one of the 
attributes that belong of necessity to the things to which they 
belong; or else one and the same thing may be perishable and 
imperishable, if perishableness is capable of not belonging to it. 
Perishableness then must either be the essence or be present in 
the essence of each perishable thing. The same account holds 
good for imperishableness also; for both are attributes which 
are present of necessity. The characteristics, then, in respect of 
which and in direct consequence of which one thing is 
perishable and another imperishable, are opposite, so that the 
things must be different in kind. 

Evidently, then, there cannot be Forms such as some maintain, 
for then one man would be perishable and another 
imperishable. Yet the Forms are said to be the same in form 
with the individuals and not merely to have the same name; but 
things which differ in kind are farther apart than those which 
differ in form. 



2432 



BookK 



That Wisdom is a science of first principles is evident from the 
introductory chapters, in which we have raised objections to the 
statements of others about the first principles; but one might 
ask the question whether Wisdom is to be conceived as one 
science or as several. If as one, it may be objected that one 
science always deals with contraries, but the first principles are 
not contrary. If it is not one, what sort of sciences are those with 
which it is to be identified? 

Further, is it the business of one science, or of more than one, to 
examine the first principles of demonstration? If of one, why of 
this rather than of any other? If of more, what sort of sciences 
must these be said to be? 

Further, does Wisdom investigate all substances or not? If not 
all, it is hard to say which; but if, being one, it investigates them 
all, it is doubtful how the same science can embrace several 
subject-matters. 

Further, does it deal with substances only or also with their 
attributes? If in the case of attributes demonstration is possible, 
in that of substances it is not. But if the two sciences are 
different, what is each of them and which is Wisdom? If we 
think of it as demonstrative, the science of the attributes is 
Wisdom, but if as dealing with what is primary, the science of 
substances claims the tide. 

But again the science we are looking for must not be supposed 
to deal with the causes which have been mentioned in the 



2433 



Physics. For (A) it does not deal with the final cause (for that is 
the nature of the good, and this is found in the field of action 
and movement; and it is the first mover - for that is the nature 
of the end - but in the case of things unmovable there is 
nothing that moved them first), and (B) in general it is hard to 
say whether perchance the science we are now looking for deals 
with perceptible substances or not with them, but with certain 
others. If with others, it must deal either with the Forms or with 
the objects of mathematics. Now (a) evidently the Forms do not 
exist. (But it is hard to say, even if one suppose them to exist, 
why in the world the same is not true of the other things of 
which there are Forms, as of the objects of mathematics. I mean 
that these thinkers place the objects of mathematics between 
the Forms and perceptible things, as a kind of third set of things 
apart both from the Forms and from the things in this world; 
but there is not a third man or horse besides the ideal and the 
individuals. If on the other hand it is not as they say, with what 
sort of things must the mathematician be supposed to deal? 
Certainly not with the things in this world; for none of these is 
the sort of thing which the mathematical sciences demand.) 
Nor (b) does the science which we are now seeking treat of the 
objects of mathematics; for none of them can exist separately. 
But again it does not deal with perceptible substances; for they 
are perishable. 

In general one might raise the question, to what kind of science 
it belongs to discuss the difficulties about the matter of the 
objects of mathematics. Neither to physics (because the whole 
inquiry of the physicist is about the things that have in 
themselves a principle, of movement and rest), nor yet to the 
science which inquires into demonstration and science; for this 
is just the subject which it investigates. It remains then that it is 
the philosophy which we have set before ourselves that treats 
of those subjects. 



2434 



One might discuss the question whether the science we are 
seeking should be said to deal with the principles which are by 
some called elements; all men suppose these to be present in 
composite things. But it might be thought that the science we 
seek should treat rather of universals; for every definition and 
every science is of universals and not of infimae species, so that 
as far as this goes it would deal with the highest genera. These 
would turn out to be being and unity; for these might most of 
all be supposed to contain all things that are, and to be most 
like principles because they are by nature; for if they perish all 
other things are destroyed with them; for everything is and is 
one. But inasmuch as, if one is to suppose them to be genera, 
they must be predicable of their differentiae, and no genus is 
predicable of any of its differentiae, in this way it would seem 
that we should not make them genera nor principles. Further, if 
the simpler is more of a principle than the less simple, and the 
ultimate members of the genus are simpler than the genera (for 
they are indivisible, but the genera are divided into many and 
differing species), the species might seem to be the principles, 
rather than the genera. But inasmuch as the species are 
involved in the destruction of the genera, the genera are more 
like principles; for that which involves another in its destruction 
is a principle of it. These and others of the kind are the subjects 
that involve difficulties. 



Further, must we suppose something apart from individual 
things, or is it these that the science we are seeking treats of? 
But these are infinite in number. Yet the things that are apart 
from the individuals are genera or species; but the science we 
now seek treats of neither of these. The reason why this is 



2435 



impossible has been stated. Indeed, it is in general hard to say 
whether one must assume that there is a separable substance 
besides the sensible substances (i.e. the substances in this 
world), or that these are the real things and Wisdom is 
concerned with them. For we seem to seek another kind of 
substance, and this is our problem, i.e. to see if there is 
something which can exist apart by itself and belongs to no 
sensible thing. - Further, if there is another substance apart 
from and corresponding to sensible substances, which kinds of 
sensible substance must be supposed to have this 
corresponding to them? Why should one suppose men or 
horses to have it, more than either the other animals or even all 
lifeless things? On the other hand to set up other and eternal 
substances equal in number to the sensible and perishable 
substances would seem to fall beyond the bounds of probability. 
- But if the principle we now seek is not separable from 
corporeal things, what has a better claim to the name matter? 
This, however, does not exist in actuality, but exists in potency. 
And it would seem rather that the form or shape is a more 
important principle than this; but the form is perishable, so that 
there is no eternal substance at all which can exist apart and 
independent. But this is paradoxical; for such a principle and 
substance seems to exist and is sought by nearly all the most 
refined thinkers as something that exists; for how is there to be 
order unless there is something eternal and independent and 
permanent? 

Further, if there is a substance or principle of such a nature as 
that which we are now seeking, and if this is one for all things, 
and the same for eternal and for perishable things, it is hard to 
say why in the world, if there is the same principle, some of the 
things that fall under the principle are eternal, and others are 
not eternal; this is paradoxical. But if there is one principle of 
perishable and another of eternal things, we shall be in a like 
difficulty if the principle of perishable things, as well as that of 



2436 



eternal, is eternal; for why, if the principle is eternal, are not the 
things that fall under the principle also eternal? But if it is 
perishable another principle is involved to account for it, and 
another to account for that, and this will go on to infinity. 

If on the other hand we are to set up what are thought to be the 
most unchangeable principles, being and unity, firstly, if each of 
these does not indicate a 'this' or substance, how will they be 
separable and independent? Yet we expect the eternal and 
primary principles to be so. But if each of them does signify a 
'this' or substance, all things that are are substances; for being 
is predicated of all things (and unity also of some); but that all 
things that are are substance is false. Further, how can they be 
right who say that the first principle is unity and this is 
substance, and generate number as the first product from unity 
and from matter, assert that number is substance? How are we 
to think of 'two', and each of the other numbers composed of 
units, as one? On this point neither do they say anything nor is 
it easy to say anything. But if we are to suppose lines or what 
comes after these (I mean the primary surfaces) to be principles, 
these at least are not separable substances, but sections and 
divisions - the former of surfaces, the latter of bodies (while 
points are sections and divisions of lines); and further they are 
limits of these same things; and all these are in other things 
and none is separable. Further, how are we to suppose that 
there is a substance of unity and the point? Every substance 
comes into being by a gradual process, but a point does not; for 
the point is a division. 

A further difficulty is raised by the fact that all knowledge is of 
universals and of the 'such', but substance is not a universal, 
but is rather a 'this' - a separable thing, so that if there is 
knowledge about the first principles, the question arises, how 
are we to suppose the first principle to be substance? 



2437 



Further, is there anything apart from the concrete thing (by 
which I mean the matter and that which is joined with it), or 
not? If not, we are met by the objection that all things that are 
in matter are perishable. But if there is something, it must be 
the form or shape. Now it is hard to determine in which cases 
this exists apart and in which it does not; for in some cases the 
form is evidently not separable, e.g. in the case of a house. 

Further, are the principles the same in kind or in number? If 
they are one in number, all things will be the same. 



Since the science of the philosopher treats of being qua being 
universally and not in respect of a part of it, and 'being' has 
many senses and is not used in one only, it follows that if the 
word is used equivocally and in virtue of nothing common to its 
various uses, being does not fall under one science (for the 
meanings of an equivocal term do not form one genus); but if 
the word is used in virtue of something common, being will fall 
under one science. The term seems to be used in the way we 
have mentioned, like 'medical' and 'healthy'. For each of these 
also we use in many senses. Terms are used in this way by 
virtue of some kind of reference, in the one case to medical 
science, in the other to health, in others to something else, but 
in each case to one identical concept. For a discussion and a 
knife are called medical because the former proceeds from 
medical science, and the latter is useful to it. And a thing is 
called healthy in a similar way; one thing because it is 
indicative of health, another because it is productive of it. And 
the same is true in the other cases. Everything that is, then, is 
said to 'be' in this same way; each thing that is is said to 'be' 



2438 



because it is a modification of being qua being or a permanent 
or a transient state or a movement of it, or something else of 
the sort. And since everything that is may be referred to 
something single and common, each of the contrarieties also 
may be referred to the first differences and contrarieties of 
being, whether the first differences of being are plurality and 
unity, or likeness and unlikeness, or some other differences; let 
these be taken as already discussed. It makes no difference 
whether that which is be referred to being or to unity. For even 
if they are not the same but different, at least they are 
convertible; for that which is one is also somehow being, and 
that which is being is one. 

But since every pair of contraries falls to be examined by one 
and the same science, and in each pair one term is the privative 
of the other though one might regarding some contraries raise 
the question, how they can be privately related, viz. those which 
have an intermediate, e.g. unjust and just - in all such cases one 
must maintain that the privation is not of the whole definition, 
but of the infima species, if the just man is 'by virtue of some 
permanent disposition obedient to the laws', the unjust man 
will not in every case have the whole definition denied of him, 
but may be merely 'in some respect deficient in obedience to 
the laws', and in this respect the privation will attach to him; 
and similarly in all other cases. 

As the mathematician investigates abstractions (for before 
beginning his investigation he strips off all the sensible 
qualities, e.g. weight and lightness, hardness and its contrary, 
and also heat and cold and the other sensible contrarieties, and 
leaves only the quantitative and continuous, sometimes in one, 
sometimes in two, sometimes in three dimensions, and the 
attributes of these qua quantitative and continuous, and does 
not consider them in any other respect, and examines the 
relative positions of some and the attributes of these, and the 



2439 



commensurabilities and incommensurabilities of others, and 
the ratios of others; but yet we posit one and the same science 
of all these things - geometry) - the same is true with regard to 
being. For the attributes of this in so far as it is being, and the 
contrarieties in it qua being, it is the business of no other 
science than philosophy to investigate; for to physics one would 
assign the study of things not qua being, but rather qua sharing 
in movement; while dialectic and sophistic deal with the 
attributes of things that are, but not of things qua being, and 
not with being itself in so far as it is being; therefore it remains 
that it is the philosopher who studies the things we have 
named, in so far as they are being. Since all that is is to 'be' in 
virtue of something single and common, though the term has 
many meanings, and contraries are in the same case (for they 
are referred to the first contrarieties and differences of being), 
and things of this sort can fall under one science, the difficulty 
we stated at the beginning appears to be solved, - I mean the 
question how there can be a single science of things which are 
many and different in genus. 



Since even the mathematician uses the common axioms only in 
a special application, it must be the business of first philosophy 
to examine the principles of mathematics also. That when 
equals are taken from equals the remainders are equal, is 
common to all quantities, but mathematics studies a part of its 
proper matter which it has detached, e.g. lines or angles or 
numbers or some other kind of quantity - not, however, qua 
being but in so far as each of them is continuous in one or two 
or three dimensions; but philosophy does not inquire about 
particular subjects in so far as each of them has some attribute 



2440 



or other, but speculates about being, in so far as each particular 
thing is. - Physics is in the same position as mathematics; for 
physics studies the attributes and the principles of the things 
that are, qua moving and not qua being (whereas the primary 
science, we have said, deals with these, only in so far as the 
underlying subjects are existent, and not in virtue of any other 
character); and so both physics and mathematics must be 
classed as parts of Wisdom. 



There is a principle in things, about which we cannot be 
deceived, but must always, on the contrary recognize the truth, 
- viz. that the same thing cannot at one and the same time be 
and not be, or admit any other similar pair of opposites. About 
such matters there is no proof in the full sense, though there is 
proof ad hominem. For it is not possible to infer this truth itself 
from a more certain principle, yet this is necessary if there is to 
be completed proof of it in the full sense. But he who wants to 
prove to the asserter of opposites that he is wrong must get 
from him an admission which shall be identical with the 
principle that the same thing cannot be and not be at one and 
the same time, but shall not seem to be identical; for thus alone 
can his thesis be demonstrated to the man who asserts that 
opposite statements can be truly made about the same subject. 
Those, then, who are to join in argument with one another must 
to some extent understand one another; for if this does not 
happen how are they to join in argument with one another? 
Therefore every word must be intelligible and indicate 
something, and not many things but only one; and if it signifies 
more than one thing, it must be made plain to which of these 
the word is being applied. He, then, who says 'this is and is not' 



2441 



denies what he affirms, so that what the word signifies, he says 
it does not signify; and this is impossible. Therefore if 'this is' 
signifies something, one cannot truly assert its contradictory. 

Further, if the word signifies something and this is asserted 
truly, this connexion must be necessary; and it is not possible 
that that which necessarily is should ever not be; it is not 
possible therefore to make the opposed affirmations and 
negations truly of the same subject. Further, if the affirmation is 
no more true than the negation, he who says 'man' will be no 
more right than he who says 'not-man'. It would seem also that 
in saying the man is not a horse one would be either more or 
not less right than in saying he is not a man, so that one will 
also be right in saying that the same person is a horse; for it was 
assumed to be possible to make opposite statements equally 
truly. It follows then that the same person is a man and a horse, 
or any other animal. 

While, then, there is no proof of these things in the full sense, 
there is a proof which may suffice against one who will make 
these suppositions. And perhaps if one had questioned 
Heraclitus himself in this way one might have forced him to 
confess that opposite statements can never be true of the same 
subjects. But, as it is, he adopted this opinion without 
understanding what his statement involves. But in any case if 
what is said by him is true, not even this itself will be true - viz. 
that the same thing can at one and the same time both be and 
not be. For as, when the statements are separated, the 
affirmation is no more true than the negation, in the same way 
- the combined and complex statement being like a single 
affirmation - the whole taken as an affirmation will be no more 
true than the negation. Further, if it is not possible to affirm 
anything truly, this itself will be false - the assertion that there 
is no true affirmation. But if a true affirmation exists, this 



2442 



appears to refute what is said by those who raise such 
objections and utterly destroy rational discourse. 



The saying of Protagoras is like the views we have mentioned; 
he said that man is the measure of all things, meaning simply 
that that which seems to each man also assuredly is. If this is 
so, it follows that the same thing both is and is not, and is bad 
and good, and that the contents of all other opposite 
statements are true, because often a particular thing appears 
beautiful to some and the contrary of beautiful to others, and 
that which appears to each man is the measure. This difficulty 
may be solved by considering the source of this opinion. It 
seems to have arisen in some cases from the doctrine of the 
natural philosophers, and in others from the fact that all men 
have not the same views about the same things, but a particular 
thing appears pleasant to some and the contrary of pleasant to 
others. 

That nothing comes to be out of that which is not, but 
everything out of that which is, is a dogma common to nearly 
all the natural philosophers. Since, then, white cannot come to 
be if the perfectly white and in no respect not-white existed 
before, that which becomes white must come from that which 
is not white; so that it must come to be out of that which is not 
(so they argue), unless the same thing was at the beginning 
white and not-white. But it is not hard to solve this difficulty; 
for we have said in our works on physics in what sense things 
that come to be come to be from that which is not, and in what 
sense from that which is. 



2443 



But to attend equally to the opinions and the fancies of 
disputing parties is childish; for clearly one of them must be 
mistaken. And this is evident from what happens in respect of 
sensation; for the same thing never appears sweet to some and 
the contrary of sweet to others, unless in the one case the 
sense-organ which discriminates the aforesaid flavours has 
been perverted and injured. And if this is so the one party must 
be taken to be the measure, and the other must not. And say the 
same of good and bad, and beautiful and ugly, and all other 
such qualities. For to maintain the view we are opposing is just 
like maintaining that the things that appear to people who put 
their finger under their eye and make the object appear two 
instead of one must be two (because they appear to be of that 
number) and again one (for to those who do not interfere with 
their eye the one object appears one). 

In general, it is absurd to make the fact that the things of this 
earth are observed to change and never to remain in the same 
state, the basis of our judgement about the truth. For in 
pursuing the truth one must start from the things that are 
always in the same state and suffer no change. Such are the 
heavenly bodies; for these do not appear to be now of one 
nature and again of another, but are manifestly always the 
same and share in no change. 

Further, if there is movement, there is also something moved, 
and everything is moved out of something and into something; 
it follows that that that which is moved must first be in that out 
of which it is to be moved, and then not be in it, and move into 
the other and come to be in it, and that the contradictory 
statements are not true at the same time, as these thinkers 
assert they are. 

And if the things of this earth continuously flow and move in 
respect of quantity - if one were to suppose this, although it is 



2444 



not true - why should they not endure in respect of quality? For 
the assertion of contradictory statements about the same thing 
seems to have arisen largely from the belief that the quantity of 
bodies does not endure, which, our opponents hold, justifies 
them in saying that the same thing both is and is not four 
cubits long. But essence depends on quality, and this is of 
determinate nature, though quantity is of indeterminate. 

Further, when the doctor orders people to take some particular 
food, why do they take it? In what respect is 'this is bread' truer 
than 'this is not bread'? And so it would make no difference 
whether one ate or not. But as a matter of fact they take the 
food which is ordered, assuming that they know the truth about 
it and that it is bread. Yet they should not, if there were no fixed 
constant nature in sensible things, but all natures moved and 
flowed for ever. 

Again, if we are always changing and never remain the same, 
what wonder is it if to us, as to the sick, things never appear the 
same? (For to them also, because they are not in the same 
condition as when they were well, sensible qualities do not 
appear alike; yet, for all that, the sensible things themselves 
need not share in any change, though they produce different, 
and not identical, sensations in the sick. And the same must 
surely happen to the healthy if the afore-said change takes 
place.) But if we do not change but remain the same, there will 
be something that endures. 

As for those to whom the difficulties mentioned are suggested 
by reasoning, it is not easy to solve the difficulties to their 
satisfaction, unless they will posit something and no longer 
demand a reason for it; for it is only thus that all reasoning and 
all proof is accomplished; if they posit nothing, they destroy 
discussion and all reasoning. Therefore with such men there is 
no reasoning. But as for those who are perplexed by the 



2445 



traditional difficulties, it is easy to meet them and to dissipate 
the causes of their perplexity. This is evident from what has 
been said. 

It is manifest, therefore, from these arguments that 
contradictory statements cannot be truly made about the same 
subject at one time, nor can contrary statements, because every 
contrariety depends on privation. This is evident if we reduce 
the definitions of contraries to their principle. 

Similarly, no intermediate between contraries can be predicated 
of one and the same subject, of which one of the contraries is 
predicated. If the subject is white we shall be wrong in saying it 
is neither black nor white, for then it follows that it is and is not 
white; for the second of the two terms we have put together is 
true of it, and this is the contradictory of white. 

We could not be right, then, in accepting the views either of 
Heraclitus or of Anaxagoras. If we were, it would follow that 
contraries would be predicated of the same subject; for when 
Anaxagoras says that in everything there is a part of everything, 
he says nothing is sweet any more than it is bitter, and so with 
any other pair of contraries, since in everything everything is 
present not potentially only, but actually and separately. And 
similarly all statements cannot be false nor all true, both 
because of many other difficulties which might be adduced as 
arising from this position, and because if all are false it will not 
be true to say even this, and if all are true it will not be false to 
say all are false. 



2446 



Every science seeks certain principles and causes for each of its 
objects - e.g. medicine and gymnastics and each of the other 
sciences, whether productive or mathematical. For each of 
these marks off a certain class of things for itself and busies 
itself about this as about something existing and real, - not 
however qua real; the science that does this is another distinct 
from these. Of the sciences mentioned each gets somehow the 
'what' in some class of things and tries to prove the other 
truths, with more or less precision. Some get the 'what' through 
perception, others by hypothesis; so that it is clear from an 
induction of this sort that there is no demonstration, of the 
substance or 'what'. 

There is a science of nature, and evidently it must be different 
both from practical and from productive science. For in the case 
of productive science the principle of movement is in the 
producer and not in the product, and is either an art or some 
other faculty. And similarly in practical science the movement is 
not in the thing done, but rather in the doers. But the science of 
the natural philosopher deals with the things that have in 
themselves a principle of movement. It is clear from these facts, 
then, that natural science must be neither practical nor 
productive, but theoretical (for it must fall into some one of 
these classes). And since each of the sciences must somehow 
know the 'what' and use this as a principle, we must not fall to 
observe how the natural philosopher should define things and 
how he should state the definition of the essence - whether as 
akin to 'snub' or rather to 'concave'. For of these the definition 
of 'snub' includes the matter of the thing, but that of 'concave' 
is independent of the matter; for snubness is found in a nose, so 
that we look for its definition without eliminating the nose, for 
what is snub is a concave nose. Evidently then the definition of 



2447 



flesh also and of the eye and of the other parts must always be 
stated without eliminating the matter. 

Since there is a science of being qua being and capable of 
existing apart, we must consider whether this is to be regarded 
as the same as physics or rather as different. Physics deals with 
the things that have a principle of movement in themselves; 
mathematics is theoretical, and is a science that deals with 
things that are at rest, but its subjects cannot exist apart. 
Therefore about that which can exist apart and is unmovable 
there is a science different from both of these, if there is a 
substance of this nature (I mean separable and unmovable), as 
we shall try to prove there is. And if there is such a kind of thing 
in the world, here must surely be the divine, and this must be 
the first and most dominant principle. Evidently, then, there are 
three kinds of theoretical sciences - physics, mathematics, 
theology. The class of theoretical sciences is the best, and of 
these themselves the last named is best; for it deals with the 
highest of existing things, and each science is called better or 
worse in virtue of its proper object. 

One might raise the question whether the science of being qua 
being is to be regarded as universal or not. Each of the 
mathematical sciences deals with some one determinate class 
of things, but universal mathematics applies alike to all. Now if 
natural substances are the first of existing things, physics must 
be the first of sciences; but if there is another entity and 
substance, separable and unmovable, the knowledge of it must 
be different and prior to physics and universal because it is 
prior. 



2448 



8 

Since 'being' in general has several senses, of which one is 
'being by accident', we must consider first that which 'is' in this 
sense. Evidently none of the traditional sciences busies itself 
about the accidental. For neither does architecture consider 
what will happen to those who are to use the house (e.g. 
whether they have a painful life in it or not), nor does weaving, 
or shoemaking, or the confectioner's art, do the like; but each of 
these sciences considers only what is peculiar to it, i.e. its 
proper end. And as for the argument that 'when he who is 
musical becomes lettered he'll be both at once, not having been 
both before; and that which is, not always having been, must 
have come to be; therefore he must have at once become 
musical and lettered', - this none of the recognized sciences 
considers, but only sophistic; for this alone busies itself about 
the accidental, so that Plato is not far wrong when he says that 
the sophist spends his time on non-being. 

That a science of the accidental is not even possible will be 
evident if we try to see what the accidental really is. We say that 
everything either is always and of necessity (necessity not in 
the sense of violence, but that which we appeal to in 
demonstrations), or is for the most part, or is neither for the 
most part, nor always and of necessity, but merely as it chances; 
e.g. there might be cold in the dogdays, but this occurs neither 
always and of necessity, nor for the most part, though it might 
happen sometimes. The accidental, then, is what occurs, but not 
always nor of necessity, nor for the most part. Now we have said 
what the accidental is, and it is obvious why there is no science 
of such a thing; for all science is of that which is always or for 
the most part, but the accidental is in neither of these classes. 

Evidently there are not causes and principles of the accidental, 
of the same kind as there are of the essential; for if there were, 



2449 



everything would be of necessity. If A is when B is, and B is 
when C is, and if C exists not by chance but of necessity, that 
also of which C was cause will exist of necessity, down to the 
last causatum as it is called (but this was supposed to be 
accidental). Therefore all things will be of necessity, and chance 
and the possibility of a thing's either occurring or not occurring 
are removed entirely from the range of events. And if the cause 
be supposed not to exist but to be coming to be, the same 
results will follow; everything will occur of necessity. For to- 
morrow's eclipse will occur if A occurs, and A if B occurs, and B 
if C occurs; and in this way if we subtract time from the limited 
time between now and to-morrow we shall come sometime to 
the already existing condition. Therefore since this exists, 
everything after this will occur of necessity, so that all things 
occur of necessity. 

As to that which 'is' in the sense of being true or of being by 
accident, the former depends on a combination in thought and 
is an affection of thought (which is the reason why it is the 
principles, not of that which 'is' in this sense, but of that which 
is outside and can exist apart, that are sought); and the latter is 
not necessary but indeterminate (I mean the accidental); and of 
such a thing the causes are unordered and indefinite. 

Adaptation to an end is found in events that happen by nature 
or as the result of thought. It is 'luck' when one of these events 
happens by accident. For as a thing may exist, so it may be a 
cause, either by its own nature or by accident. Luck is an 
accidental cause at work in such events adapted to an end as 
are usually effected in accordance with purpose. And so luck 
and thought are concerned with the same sphere; for purpose 
cannot exist without thought. The causes from which lucky 
results might happen are indeterminate; and so luck is obscure 
to human calculation and is a cause by accident, but in the 
unqualified sense a cause of nothing. It is good or bad luck 



2450 



when the result is good or evil; and prosperity or misfortune 
when the scale of the results is large. 

Since nothing accidental is prior to the essential, neither are 
accidental causes prior. If, then, luck or spontaneity is a cause of 
the material universe, reason and nature are causes before it. 



Some things are only actually, some potentially, some 
potentially and actually, what they are, viz. in one case a 
particular reality, in another, characterized by a particular 
quantity, or the like. There is no movement apart from things; 
for change is always according to the categories of being, and 
there is nothing common to these and in no one category. But 
each of the categories belongs to all its subjects in either of two 
ways (e.g. 'this-ness' - for one kind of it is 'positive form', and 
the other is 'privation'; and as regards quality one kind is 'white' 
and the other 'black', and as regards quantity one kind is 
'complete' and the other 'incomplete', and as regards spatial 
movement one is 'upwards' and the other 'downwards', or one 
thing is 'light' and another 'heavy'); so that there are as many 
kinds of movement and change as of being. There being a 
distinction in each class of things between the potential and the 
completely real, I call the actuality of the potential as such, 
movement. That what we say is true, is plain from the following 
facts. When the 'buildable', in so far as it is what we mean by 
'buildable', exists actually, it is being built, and this is the 
process of building. Similarly with learning, healing, walking, 
leaping, ageing, ripening. Movement takes when the complete 
reality itself exists, and neither earlier nor later. The complete 
reality, then, of that which exists potentially, when it is 



2451 



completely real and actual, not qua itself, but qua movable, is 
movement. By qua I mean this: bronze is potentially a statue; 
but yet it is not the complete reality of bronze qua bronze that 
is movement. For it is not the same thing to be bronze and to be 
a certain potency. If it were absolutely the same in its definition, 
the complete reality of bronze would have been a movement. 
But it is not the same. (This is evident in the case of contraries; 
for to be capable of being well and to be capable of being ill are 
not the same - for if they were, being well and being ill would 
have been the same - it is that which underlies and is healthy 
or diseased, whether it is moisture or blood, that is one and the 
same.) And since it is not. the same, as colour and the visible 
are not the same, it is the complete reality of the potential, and 
as potential, that is movement. That it is this, and that 
movement takes place when the complete reality itself exists, 
and neither earlier nor later, is evident. For each thing is capable 
of being sometimes actual, sometimes not, e.g. the buildable 
qua buildable; and the actuality of the buildable qua buildable is 
building. For the actuality is either this - the act of building - or 
the house. But when the house exists, it is no longer buildable; 
the buildable is what is being built. The actuality, then, must be 
the act of building, and this is a movement. And the same 
account applies to all other movements. 

That what we have said is right is evident from what all others 
say about movement, and from the fact that it is not easy to 
define it otherwise. For firstly one cannot put it in any class. 
This is evident from what people say. Some call it otherness and 
inequality and the unreal; none of these, however, is necessarily 
moved, and further, change is not either to these or from these 
any more than from their opposites. The reason why people put 
movement in these classes is that it is thought to be something 
indefinite, and the principles in one of the two 'columns of 
contraries' are indefinite because they are privative, for none of 
them is either a 'this' or a 'such' or in any of the other 



2452 



categories. And the reason why movement is thought to be 
indefinite is that it cannot be classed either with the potency of 
things or with their actuality; for neither that which is capable 
of being of a certain quantity, nor that which is actually of a 
certain quantity, is of necessity moved, and movement is 
thought to be an actuality, but incomplete; the reason is that 
the potential, whose actuality it is, is incomplete. And therefore 
it is hard to grasp what movement is; for it must be classed 
either under privation or under potency or under absolute 
actuality, but evidently none of these is possible. Therefore what 
remains is that it must be what we said - both actuality and the 
actuality we have described - which is hard to detect but 
capable of existing. 

And evidently movement is in the movable; for it is the 
complete realization of this by that which is capable of causing 
movement. And the actuality of that which is capable of causing 
movement is no other than that of the movable. For it must be 
the complete reality of both. For while a thing is capable of 
causing movement because it can do this, it is a mover because 
it is active; but it is on the movable that it is capable of acting, 
so that the actuality of both is one, just as there is the same 
interval from one to two as from two to one, and as the steep 
ascent and the steep descent are one, but the being of them is 
not one; the case of the mover and the moved is similar. 



10 

The infinite is either that which is incapable of being traversed 
because it is not its nature to be traversed (this corresponds to 
the sense in which the voice is 'invisible'), or that which admits 
only of incomplete traverse or scarcely admits of traverse, or 



2453 



that which, though it naturally admits of traverse, is not 
traversed or limited; further, a thing may be infinite in respect 
of addition or of subtraction, or both. The infinite cannot be a 
separate, independent thing. For if it is neither a spatial 
magnitude nor a plurality, but infinity itself is its substance and 
not an accident of it, it will be indivisible; for the divisible is 
either magnitude or plurality. But if indivisible, it is not infinite, 
except as the voice is invisible; but people do not mean this, nor 
are we examining this sort of infinite, but the infinite as 
untraversable. Further, how can an infinite exist by itself, unless 
number and magnitude also exist by themselvess - since 
infinity is an attribute of these? Further, if the infinite is an 
accident of something else, it cannot be qua infinite an element 
in things, as the invisible is not an element in speech, though 
the voice is invisible. And evidently the infinite cannot exist 
actually. For then any part of it that might be taken would be 
infinite (for 'to be infinite' and 'the infinite' are the same, if the 
infinite is substance and not predicated of a subject). Therefore 
it is either indivisible, or if it is partible, it is divisible into 
infinites; but the same thing cannot be many infinites (as a part 
of air is air, so a part of the infinite would be infinite, if the 
infinite is substance and a principle). Therefore it must be 
impartible and indivisible. But the actually infinite cannot be 
indivisible; for it must be of a certain quantity. Therefore infinity 
belongs to its subject incidentally. But if so, then (as we have 
said) it cannot be it that is a principle, but that of which it is an 
accident - the air or the even number. 

This inquiry is universal; but that the infinite is not among 
sensible things, is evident from the following argument. If the 
definition of a body is 'that which is bounded by planes', there 
cannot be an infinite body either sensible or intelligible; nor a 
separate and infinite number, for number or that which has a 
number is numerable. Concretely, the truth is evident from the 
following argument. The infinite can neither be composite nor 



2454 



simple. For (a) it cannot be a composite body, since the elements 
are limited in multitude. For the contraries must be equal and 
no one of them must be infinite; for if one of the two bodies 
falls at all short of the other in potency, the finite will be 
destroyed by the infinite. And that each should be infinite is 
impossible. For body is that which has extension in all 
directions, and the infinite is the boundlessly extended, so that 
if the infinite is a body it will be infinite in every direction. Nor 
(b) can the infinite body be one and simple - neither, as some 
say, something apart from the elements, from which they 
generate these (for there is no such body apart from the 
elements; for everything can be resolved into that of which it 
consists, but no such product of analysis is observed except the 
simple bodies), nor fire nor any other of the elements. For apart 
from the question how any of them could be infinite, the All, 
even if it is finite, cannot either be or become any one of them, 
as Heraclitus says all things sometime become fire. The same 
argument applies to this as to the One which the natural 
philosophers posit besides the elements. For everything 
changes from contrary to contrary, e.g. from hot to cold. 

Further, a sensible body is somewhere, and whole and part have 
the same proper place, e.g. the whole earth and part of the 
earth. Therefore if (a) the infinite body is homogeneous, it will 
be unmovable or it will be always moving. But this is impossible; 
for why should it rather rest, or move, down, up, or anywhere, 
rather than anywhere else? E.g. if there were a clod which were 
part of an infinite body, where will this move or rest? The proper 
place of the body which is homogeneous with it is infinite. Will 
the clod occupy the whole place, then? And how? (This is 
impossible.) What then is its rest or its movement? It will either 
rest everywhere, and then it cannot move; or it will move 
everywhere, and then it cannot be still. But (b) if the All has 
unlike parts, the proper places of the parts are unlike also, and, 
firstly, the body of the All is not one except by contact, and, 



2455 



secondly, the parts will be either finite or infinite in variety of 
kind. Finite they cannot be; for then those of one kind will be 
infinite in quantity and those of another will not (if the All is 
infinite), e.g. fire or water would be infinite, but such an infinite 
element would be destruction to the contrary elements. But if 
the parts are infinite and simple, their places also are infinite 
and there will be an infinite number of elements; and if this is 
impossible, and the places are finite, the All also must be 
limited. 

In general, there cannot be an infinite body and also a proper 
place for bodies, if every sensible body has either weight or 
lightness. For it must move either towards the middle or 
upwards, and the infinite either the whole or the half of it - 
cannot do either; for how will you divide it? Or how will part of 
the infinite be down and part up, or part extreme and part 
middle? Further, every sensible body is in a place, and there are 
six kinds of place, but these cannot exist in an infinite body. In 
general, if there cannot be an infinite place, there cannot be an 
infinite body; (and there cannot be an infinite place,) for that 
which is in a place is somewhere, and this means either up or 
down or in one of the other directions, and each of these is a 
limit. 

The infinite is not the same in the sense that it is a single thing 
whether exhibited in distance or in movement or in time, but 
the posterior among these is called infinite in virtue of its 
relation to the prior; i.e. a movement is called infinite in virtue 
of the distance covered by the spatial movement or alteration or 
growth, and a time is called infinite because of the movement 
which occupies it. 



2456 



11 

Of things which change, some change in an accidental sense, 
like that in which 'the musical' may be said to walk, and others 
are said, without qualification, to change, because something in 
them changes, i.e. the things that change in parts; the body 
becomes healthy, because the eye does. But there is something 
which is by its own nature moved directly, and this is the 
essentially movable. The same distinction is found in the case of 
the mover; for it causes movement either in an accidental sense 
or in respect of a part of itself or essentially. There is something 
that directly causes movement; and there is something that is 
moved, also the time in which it is moved, and that from which 
and that into which it is moved. But the forms and the 
affections and the place, which are the terminals of the 
movement of moving things, are unmovable, e.g. knowledge or 
heat; it is not heat that is a movement, but heating. Change 
which is not accidental is found not in all things, but between 
contraries, and their intermediates, and between 
contradictories. We may convince ourselves of this by induction. 

That which changes changes either from positive into positive, 
or from negative into negative, or from positive into negative, or 
from negative into positive. (By positive I mean that which is 
expressed by an affirmative term.) Therefore there must be 
three changes; that from negative into negative is not change, 
because (since the terms are neither contraries nor 
contradictories) there is no opposition. The change from the 
negative into the positive which is its contradictory is 
generation - absolute change absolute generation, and partial 
change partial generation; and the change from positive to 
negative is destruction - absolute change absolute destruction, 
and partial change partial destruction. If, then, 'that which is 
not' has several senses, and movement can attach neither to 
that which implies putting together or separating, nor to that 



2457 



which implies potency and is opposed to that which is in the 
full sense (true, the not-white or not-good can be moved 
incidentally, for the not-white might be a man; but that which is 
not a particular thing at all can in no wise be moved), that 
which is not cannot be moved (and if this is so, generation 
cannot be movement; for that which is not is generated; for 
even if we admit to the full that its generation is accidental, yet 
it is true to say that 'not-being' is predicable of that which is 
generated absolutely). Similarly rest cannot be long to that 
which is not. These consequences, then, turn out to be 
awkward, and also this, that everything that is moved is in a 
place, but that which is not is not in a place; for then it would be 
somewhere. Nor is destruction movement; for the contrary of 
movement is rest, but the contrary of destruction is generation. 
Since every movement is a change, and the kinds of change are 
the three named above, and of these those in the way of 
generation and destruction are not movements, and these are 
the changes from a thing to its contradictory, it follows that only 
the change from positive into positive is movement. And the 
positives are either contrary or intermediate (for even privation 
must be regarded as contrary), and are expressed by an 
affirmative term, e.g. 'naked' or 'toothless' or 'black'. 



12 

If the categories are classified as substance, quality, place, acting 
or being acted on, relation, quantity, there must be three kinds 
of movement - of quality, of quantity, of place. There is no 
movement in respect of substance (because there is nothing 
contrary to substance), nor of relation (for it is possible that if 
one of two things in relation changes, the relative term which 
was true of the other thing ceases to be true, though this other 



2458 



does not change at all, - so that their movement is accidental), 
nor of agent and patient, or mover and moved, because there is 
no movement of movement nor generation of generation, nor, 
in general, change of change. For there might be movement of 
movement in two senses; (1) movement might be the subject 
moved, as a man is moved because he changes from pale to 
dark, - so that on this showing movement, too, may be either 
heated or cooled or change its place or increase. But this is 
impossible; for change is not a subject. Or (2) some other subject 
might change from change into some other form of existence 
(e.g. a man from disease into health). But this also is not 
possible except incidentally. For every movement is change 
from something into something. (And so are generation and 
destruction; only, these are changes into things opposed in 
certain ways while the other, movement, is into things opposed 
in another way.) A thing changes, then, at the same time from 
health into illness, and from this change itself into another. 
Clearly, then, if it has become ill, it will have changed into 
whatever may be the other change concerned (though it may be 
at rest), and, further, into a determinate change each time; and 
that new change will be from something definite into some 
other definite thing; therefore it will be the opposite change, 
that of growing well. We answer that this happens only 
incidentally; e.g. there is a change from the process of 
recollection to that of forgetting, only because that to which the 
process attaches is changing, now into a state of knowledge, 
now into one of ignorance. 

Further, the process will go on to infinity, if there is to be change 
of change and coming to be of coming to be. What is true of the 
later, then, must be true of the earlier; e.g. if the simple coming 
to be was once coming to be, that which comes to be something 
was also once coming to be; therefore that which simply comes 
to be something was not yet in existence, but something which 
was coming to be coming to be something was already in 



2459 



existence. And this was once coming to be, so that at that time 
it was not yet coming to be something else. Now since of an 
infinite number of terms there is not a first, the first in this 
series will not exist, and therefore no following term exist. 
Nothing, then, can either come term wi to be or move or 
change. Further, that which is capable of a movement is also 
capable of the contrary movement and rest, and that which 
comes to be also ceases to be. Therefore that which is coming to 
be is ceasing to be when it has come to be coming to be; for it 
cannot cease to be as soon as it is coming to be coming to be, 
nor after it has come to be; for that which is ceasing to be must 
be. Further, there must be a matter underlying that which 
comes to be and changes. What will this be, then, - what is it 
that becomes movement or becoming, as body or soul is that 
which suffers alteration? And; again, what is it that they move 
into? For it must be the movement or becoming of something 
from something into something. How, then, can this condition 
be fulfilled? There can be no learning of learning, and therefore 
no becoming of becoming. Since there is not movement either 
of substance or of relation or of activity and passivity, it remains 
that movement is in respect of quality and quantity and place; 
for each of these admits of contrariety. By quality I mean not 
that which is in the substance (for even the differentia is a 
quality), but the passive quality, in virtue of which a thing is 
said to be acted on or to be incapable of being acted on. The 
immobile is either that which is wholly incapable of being 
moved, or that which is moved with difficulty in a long time or 
begins slowly, or that which is of a nature to be moved and can 
be moved but is not moved when and where and as it would 
naturally be moved. This alone among immobiles I describe as 
being at rest; for rest is contrary to movement, so that it must 
be a privation in that which is receptive of movement. 

Things which are in one proximate place are together in place, 
and things which are in different places are apart: things whose 



2460 



extremes are together touch: that at which a changing thing, if 
it changes continuously according to its nature, naturally arrives 
before it arrives at the extreme into which it is changing, is 
between. That which is most distant in a straight line is 
contrary in place. That is successive which is after the beginning 
(the order being determined by position or form or in some 
other way) and has nothing of the same class between it and 
that which it succeeds, e.g. lines in the case of a line, units in 
that of a unit, or a house in that of a house. (There is nothing to 
prevent a thing of some other class from being between.) For 
the successive succeeds something and is something later; 'one' 
does not succeed 'two', nor the first day of the month the 
second. That which, being successive, touches, is contiguous. 
(Since all change is between opposites, and these are either 
contraries or contradictories, and there is no middle term for 
contradictories, clearly that which is between is between 
contraries.) The continuous is a species of the contiguous. I call 
two things continuous when the limits of each, with which they 
touch and by which they are kept together, become one and the 
same, so that plainly the continuous is found in the things out 
of which a unity naturally arises in virtue of their contact. And 
plainly the successive is the first of these concepts (for the 
successive does not necessarily touch, but that which touches is 
successive; and if a thing is continuous, it touches, but if it 
touches, it is not necessarily continuous; and in things in which 
there is no touching, there is no organic unity); therefore a point 
is not the same as a unit; for contact belongs to points, but not 
to units, which have only succession; and there is something 
between two of the former, but not between two of the latter. 



2461 



Book A 



The subject of our inquiry is substance; for the principles and 
the causes we are seeking are those of substances. For if the 
universe is of the nature of a whole, substance is its first part; 
and if it coheres merely by virtue of serial succession, on this 
view also substance is first, and is succeeded by quality, and 
then by quantity. At the same time these latter are not even 
being in the full sense, but are qualities and movements of it, - 
or else even the not-white and the not-straight would be being; 
at least we say even these are, e.g. 'there is a not-white'. Further, 
none of the categories other than substance can exist apart. 
And the early philosophers also in practice testify to the 
primacy of substance; for it was of substance that they sought 
the principles and elements and causes. The thinkers of the 
present day tend to rank universals as substances (for genera 
are universals, and these they tend to describe as principles and 
substances, owing to the abstract nature of their inquiry); but 
the thinkers of old ranked particular things as substances, e.g. 
fire and earth, not what is common to both, body. 

There are three kinds of substance - one that is sensible (of 
which one subdivision is eternal and another is perishable; the 
latter is recognized by all men, and includes e.g. plants and 
animals), of which we must grasp the elements, whether one or 
many; and another that is immovable, and this certain thinkers 
assert to be capable of existing apart, some dividing it into two, 
others identifying the Forms and the objects of mathematics, 
and others positing, of these two, only the objects of 
mathematics. The former two kinds of substance are the subject 



2462 



of physics (for they imply movement); but the third kind 
belongs to another science, if there is no principle common to it 
and to the other kinds. 



Sensible substance is changeable. Now if change proceeds from 
opposites or from intermediates, and not from all opposites (for 
the voice is not-white, but it does not therefore change to 
white), but from the contrary, there must be something 
underlying which changes into the contrary state; for the 
contraries do not change. Further, something persists, but the 
contrary does not persist; there is, then, some third thing 
besides the contraries, viz. the matter. Now since changes are of 
four kinds - either in respect of the 'what' or of the quality or of 
the quantity or of the place, and change in respect of 'thisness' 
is simple generation and destruction, and change in quantity is 
increase and diminution, and change in respect of an affection 
is alteration, and change of place is motion, changes will be 
from given states into those contrary to them in these several 
respects. The matter, then, which changes must be capable of 
both states. And since that which 'is' has two senses, we must 
say that everything changes from that which is potentially to 
that which is actually, e.g. from potentially white to actually 
white, and similarly in the case of increase and diminution. 
Therefore not only can a thing come to be, incidentally, out of 
that which is not, but also all things come to be out of that 
which is, but is potentially, and is not actually. And this is the 
'One' of Anaxagoras; for instead of 'all things were together' - 
and the 'Mixture' of Empedocles and Anaximander and the 
account given by Democritus - it is better to say 'all things were 
together potentially but not actually'. Therefore these thinkers 



2463 



seem to have had some notion of matter. Now all things that 
change have matter, but different matter; and of eternal things 
those which are not generable but are movable in space have 
matter - not matter for generation, however, but for motion 
from one place to another. 

One might raise the question from what sort of non-being 
generation proceeds; for 'non-being' has three senses. If, then, 
one form of non-being exists potentially, still it is not by virtue 
of a potentiality for any and every thing, but different things 
come from different things; nor is it satisfactory to say that 'all 
things were together'; for they differ in their matter, since 
otherwise why did an infinity of things come to be, and not one 
thing? For 'reason' is one, so that if matter also were one, that 
must have come to be in actuality which the matter was in 
potency. The causes and the principles, then, are three, two 
being the pair of contraries of which one is definition and form 
and the other is privation, and the third being the matter. 



Note, next, that neither the matter nor the form comes to be - 
and I mean the last matter and form. For everything that 
changes is something and is changed by something and into 
something. That by which it is changed is the immediate mover; 
that which is changed, the matter; that into which it is changed, 
the form. The process, then, will go on to infinity, if not only the 
bronze comes to be round but also the round or the bronze 
comes to be; therefore there must be a stop. 

Note, next, that each substance comes into being out of 
something that shares its name. (Natural objects and other 
things both rank as substances.) For things come into being 



2464 



either by art or by nature or by luck or by spontaneity. Now art is 
a principle of movement in something other than the thing 
moved, nature is a principle in the thing itself (for man begets 
man), and the other causes are privations of these two. 

There are three kinds of substance - the matter, which is a 'this' 
in appearance (for all things that are characterized by contact 
and not, by organic unity are matter and substratum, e.g. fire, 
flesh, head; for these are all matter, and the last matter is the 
matter of that which is in the full sense substance); the nature, 
which is a 'this' or positive state towards which movement 
takes place; and again, thirdly, the particular substance which is 
composed of these two, e.g. Socrates or Callias. Now in some 
cases the 'this' does not exist apart from the composite 
substance, e.g. the form of house does not so exist, unless the 
art of building exists apart (nor is there generation and 
destruction of these forms, but it is in another way that the 
house apart from its matter, and health, and all ideals of art, 
exist and do not exist); but if the 'this' exists apart from the 
concrete thing, it is only in the case of natural objects. And so 
Plato was not far wrong when he said that there are as many 
Forms as there are kinds of natural object (if there are Forms 
distinct from the things of this earth). The moving causes exist 
as things preceding the effects, but causes in the sense of 
definitions are simultaneous with their effects. For when a man 
is healthy, then health also exists; and the shape of a bronze 
sphere exists at the same time as the bronze sphere. (But we 
must examine whether any form also survives afterwards. For 
in some cases there is nothing to prevent this; e.g. the soul may 
be of this sort - not all soul but the reason; for presumably it is 
impossible that all soul should survive.) Evidently then there is 
no necessity, on this ground at least, for the existence of the 
Ideas. For man is begotten by man, a given man by an individual 
father; and similarly in the arts; for the medical art is the formal 
cause of health. 



2465 



The causes and the principles of different things are in a sense 
different, but in a sense, if one speaks universally and 
analogically, they are the same for all. For one might raise the 
question whether the principles and elements are different or 
the same for substances and for relative terms, and similarly in 
the case of each of the categories. But it would be paradoxical if 
they were the same for all. For then from the same elements 
will proceed relative terms and substances. What then will this 
common element be? For (1) (a) there is nothing common to and 
distinct from substance and the other categories, viz. those 
which are predicated; but an element is prior to the things of 
which it is an element. But again (b) substance is not an 
element in relative terms, nor is any of these an element in 
substance. Further, (2) how can all things have the same 
elements? For none of the elements can be the same as that 
which is composed of elements, e.g. b or a cannot be the same 
as ba. (None, therefore, of the intelligibles, e.g. being or unity, is 
an element; for these are predicable of each of the compounds 
as well.) None of the elements, then, will be either a substance 
or a relative term; but it must be one or other. All things, then, 
have not the same elements. 

Or, as we are wont to put it, in a sense they have and in a sense 
they have not; e.g. perhaps the elements of perceptible bodies 
are, as form, the hot, and in another sense the cold, which is the 
privation; and, as matter, that which directly and of itself 
potentially has these attributes; and substances comprise both 
these and the things composed of these, of which these are the 
principles, or any unity which is produced out of the hot and 
the cold, e.g. flesh or bone; for the product must be different 



2466 



from the elements. These things then have the same elements 
and principles (though specifically different things have 
specifically different elements); but all things have not the same 
elements in this sense, but only analogically; i.e. one might say 
that there are three principles - the form, the privation, and the 
matter. But each of these is different for each class; e.g. in 
colour they are white, black, and surface, and in day and night 
they are light, darkness, and air. 

Since not only the elements present in a thing are causes, but 
also something external, i.e. the moving cause, clearly while 
'principle' and 'element' are different both are causes, and 
'principle' is divided into these two kinds; and that which acts 
as producing movement or rest is a principle and a substance. 
Therefore analogically there are three elements, and four 
causes and principles; but the elements are different in 
different things, and the proximate moving cause is different 
for different things. Health, disease, body; the moving cause is 
the medical art. Form, disorder of a particular kind, bricks; the 
moving cause is the building art. And since the moving cause in 
the case of natural things is - for man, for instance, man, and in 
the products of thought the form or its contrary, there will be in 
a sense three causes, while in a sense there are four. For the 
medical art is in some sense health, and the building art is the 
form of the house, and man begets man; further, besides these 
there is that which as first of all things moves all things. 



Some things can exist apart and some cannot, and it is the 
former that are substances. And therefore all things have the 
same causes, because, without substances, modifications and 



2467 



movements do not exist. Further, these causes will probably be 
soul and body, or reason and desire and body. 

And in yet another way, analogically identical things are 
principles, i.e. actuality and potency; but these also are not only 
different for different things but also apply in different ways to 
them. For in some cases the same thing exists at one time 
actually and at another potentially, e.g. wine or flesh or man 
does so. (And these too fall under the above-named causes. For 
the form exists actually, if it can exist apart, and so does the 
complex of form and matter, and the privation, e.g. darkness or 
disease; but the matter exists potentially; for this is that which 
can become qualified either by the form or by the privation.) But 
the distinction of actuality and potentiality applies in another 
way to cases where the matter of cause and of effect is not the 
same, in some of which cases the form is not the same but 
different; e.g. the cause of man is (1) the elements in man (viz. 
fire and earth as matter, and the peculiar form), and further (2) 
something else outside, i.e. the father, and (3) besides these the 
sun and its oblique course, which are neither matter nor form 
nor privation of man nor of the same species with him, but 
moving causes. 

Further, one must observe that some causes can be expressed in 
universal terms, and some cannot. The proximate principles of 
all things are the 'this' which is proximate in actuality, and 
another which is proximate in potentiality. The universal 
causes, then, of which we spoke do not exist. For it is the 
individual that is the originative principle of the individuals. For 
while man is the originative principle of man universally, there 
is no universal man, but Peleus is the originative principle of 
Achilles, and your father of you, and this particular b of this 
particular ba, though b in general is the originative principle of 
ba taken without qualification. 



2468 



Further, if the causes of substances are the causes of all things, 
yet different things have different causes and elements, as was 
said; the causes of things that are not in the same class, e.g. of 
colours and sounds, of substances and quantities, are different 
except in an analogical sense; and those of things in the same 
species are different, not in species, but in the sense that the 
causes of different individuals are different, your matter and 
form and moving cause being different from mine, while in 
their universal definition they are the same. And if we inquire 
what are the principles or elements of substances and relations 
and qualities - whether they are the same or different - clearly 
when the names of the causes are used in several senses the 
causes of each are the same, but when the senses are 
distinguished the causes are not the same but different, except 
that in the following senses the causes of all are the same. They 
are (1) the same or analogous in this sense, that matter, form, 
privation, and the moving cause are common to all things; and 
(2) the causes of substances may be treated as causes of all 
things in this sense, that when substances are removed all 
things are removed; further, (3) that which is first in respect of 
complete reality is the cause of all things. But in another sense 
there are different first causes, viz. all the contraries which are 
neither generic nor ambiguous terms; and, further, the matters 
of different things are different. We have stated, then, what are 
the principles of sensible things and how many they are, and in 
what sense they are the same and in what sense different. 



Since there were three kinds of substance, two of them physical 
and one unmovable, regarding the latter we must assert that it 
is necessary that there should be an eternal unmovable 



2469 



substance. For substances are the first of existing things, and if 
they are all destructible, all things are destructible. But it is 
impossible that movement should either have come into being 
or cease to be (for it must always have existed), or that time 
should. For there could not be a before and an after if time did 
not exist. Movement also is continuous, then, in the sense in 
which time is; for time is either the same thing as movement or 
an attribute of movement. And there is no continuous 
movement except movement in place, and of this only that 
which is circular is continuous. 

But if there is something which is capable of moving things or 
acting on them, but is not actually doing so, there will not 
necessarily be movement; for that which has a potency need 
not exercise it. Nothing, then, is gained even if we suppose 
eternal substances, as the believers in the Forms do, unless 
there is to be in them some principle which can cause change; 
nay, even this is not enough, nor is another substance besides 
the Forms enough; for if it is not to act, there will be no 
movement. Further even if it acts, this will not be enough, if its 
essence is potency; for there will not be eternal movement, 
since that which is potentially may possibly not be. There must, 
then, be such a principle, whose very essence is actuality. 
Further, then, these substances must be without matter; for 
they must be eternal, if anything is eternal. Therefore they must 
be actuality. 

Yet there is a difficulty; for it is thought that everything that 
acts is able to act, but that not everything that is able to act acts, 
so that the potency is prior. But if this is so, nothing that is need 
be; for it is possible for all things to be capable of existing but 
not yet to exist. 

Yet if we follow the theologians who generate the world from 
night, or the natural philosophers who say that 'all things were 



2470 



together', the same impossible result ensues. For how will there 
be movement, if there is no actually existing cause? Wood will 
surely not move itself - the carpenter's art must act on it; nor 
will the menstrual blood nor the earth set themselves in 
motion, but the seeds must act on the earth and the semen on 
the menstrual blood. 

This is why some suppose eternal actuality - e.g. Leucippus and 
Plato; for they say there is always movement. But why and what 
this movement is they do say, nor, if the world moves in this 
way or that, do they tell us the cause of its doing so. Now 
nothing is moved at random, but there must always be 
something present to move it; e.g. as a matter of fact a thing 
moves in one way by nature, and in another by force or through 
the influence of reason or something else. (Further, what sort of 
movement is primary? This makes a vast difference.) But again 
for Plato, at least, it is not permissible to name here that which 
he sometimes supposes to be the source of movement - that 
which moves itself; for the soul is later, and coeval with the 
heavens, according to his account. To suppose potency prior to 
actuality, then, is in a sense right, and in a sense not; and we 
have specified these senses. That actuality is prior is testified by 
Anaxagoras (for his 'reason' is actuality) and by Empedocles in 
his doctrine of love and strife, and by those who say that there 
is always movement, e.g. Leucippus. Therefore chaos or night 
did not exist for an infinite time, but the same things have 
always existed (either passing through a cycle of changes or 
obeying some other law), since actuality is prior to potency. If, 
then, there is a constant cycle, something must always remain, 
acting in the same way. And if there is to be generation and 
destruction, there must be something else which is always 
acting in different ways. This must, then, act in one way in 
virtue of itself, and in another in virtue of something else - 
either of a third agent, therefore, or of the first. Now it must be 
in virtue of the first. For otherwise this again causes the motion 



2471 



both of the second agent and of the third. Therefore it is better 
to say 'the first'. For it was the cause of eternal uniformity; and 
something else is the cause of variety, and evidently both 
together are the cause of eternal variety. This, accordingly, is the 
character which the motions actually exhibit. What need then is 
there to seek for other principles? 



Since (1) this is a possible account of the matter, and (2) if it 
were not true, the world would have proceeded out of night and 
'all things together' and out of non-being, these difficulties may 
be taken as solved. There is, then, something which is always 
moved with an unceasing motion, which is motion in a circle; 
and this is plain not in theory only but in fact. Therefore the 
first heaven must be eternal. There is therefore also something 
which moves it. And since that which moves and is moved is 
intermediate, there is something which moves without being 
moved, being eternal, substance, and actuality. And the object of 
desire and the object of thought move in this way; they move 
without being moved. The primary objects of desire and of 
thought are the same. For the apparent good is the object of 
appetite, and the real good is the primary object of rational 
wish. But desire is consequent on opinion rather than opinion 
on desire; for the thinking is the starting-point. And thought is 
moved by the object of thought, and one of the two columns of 
opposites is in itself the object of thought; and in this, 
substance is first, and in substance, that which is simple and 
exists actually. (The one and the simple are not the same; for 
'one' means a measure, but 'simple' means that the thing itself 
has a certain nature.) But the beautiful, also, and that which is 



2472 



in itself desirable are in the same column; and the first in any 
class is always best, or analogous to the best. 

That a final cause may exist among unchangeable entities is 
shown by the distinction of its meanings. For the final cause is 
(a) some being for whose good an action is done, and (b) 
something at which the action aims; and of these the latter 
exists among unchangeable entities though the former does 
not. The final cause, then, produces motion as being loved, but 
all other things move by being moved. Now if something is 
moved it is capable of being otherwise than as it is. Therefore if 
its actuality is the primary form of spatial motion, then in so far 
as it is subject to change, in this respect it is capable of being 
otherwise, - in place, even if not in substance. But since there is 
something which moves while itself unmoved, existing actually, 
this can in no way be otherwise than as it is. For motion in 
space is the first of the kinds of change, and motion in a circle 
the first kind of spatial motion; and this the first mover 
produces. The first mover, then, exists of necessity; and in so far 
as it exists by necessity, its mode of being is good, and it is in 
this sense a first principle. For the necessary has all these 
senses - that which is necessary perforce because it is contrary 
to the natural impulse, that without which the good is 
impossible, and that which cannot be otherwise but can exist 
only in a single way. 

On such a principle, then, depend the heavens and the world of 
nature. And it is a life such as the best which we enjoy, and 
enjoy for but a short time (for it is ever in this state, which we 
cannot be), since its actuality is also pleasure. (And for this 
reason are waking, perception, and thinking most pleasant, and 
hopes and memories are so on account of these.) And thinking 
in itself deals with that which is best in itself, and that which is 
thinking in the fullest sense with that which is best in the 
fullest sense. And thought thinks on itself because it shares the 



2473 



nature of the object of thought; for it becomes an object of 
thought in coming into contact with and thinking its objects, so 
that thought and object of thought are the same. For that which 
is capable of receiving the object of thought, i.e. the essence, is 
thought. But it is active when it possesses this object. Therefore 
the possession rather than the receptivity is the divine element 
which thought seems to contain, and the act of contemplation 
is what is most pleasant and best. If, then, God is always in that 
good state in which we sometimes are, this compels our 
wonder; and if in a better this compels it yet more. And God is 
in a better state. And life also belongs to God; for the actuality of 
thought is life, and God is that actuality; and God's self- 
dependent actuality is life most good and eternal. We say 
therefore that God is a living being, eternal, most good, so that 
life and duration continuous and eternal belong to God; for this 
is God. 

Those who suppose, as the Pythagoreans and Speusippus do, 
that supreme beauty and goodness are not present in the 
beginning, because the beginnings both of plants and of 
animals are causes, but beauty and completeness are in the 
effects of these, are wrong in their opinion. For the seed comes 
from other individuals which are prior and complete, and the 
first thing is not seed but the complete being; e.g. we must say 
that before the seed there is a man, - not the man produced 
from the seed, but another from whom the seed comes. 

It is clear then from what has been said that there is a 
substance which is eternal and unmovable and separate from 
sensible things. It has been shown also that this substance 
cannot have any magnitude, but is without parts and indivisible 
(for it produces movement through infinite time, but nothing 
finite has infinite power; and, while every magnitude is either 
infinite or finite, it cannot, for the above reason, have finite 
magnitude, and it cannot have infinite magnitude because there 



2474 



is no infinite magnitude at all). But it has also been shown that 
it is impassive and unalterable; for all the other changes are 
posterior to change of place. 



8 

It is clear, then, why these things are as they are. But we must 
not ignore the question whether we have to suppose one such 
substance or more than one, and if the latter, how many; we 
must also mention, regarding the opinions expressed by others, 
that they have said nothing about the number of the substances 
that can even be clearly stated. For the theory of Ideas has no 
special discussion of the subject; for those who speak of Ideas 
say the Ideas are numbers, and they speak of numbers now as 
unlimited, now as limited by the number 10; but as for the 
reason why there should be just so many numbers, nothing is 
said with any demonstrative exactness. We however must 
discuss the subject, starting from the presuppositions and 
distinctions we have mentioned. The first principle or primary 
being is not movable either in itself or accidentally, but 
produces the primary eternal and single movement. But since 
that which is moved must be moved by something, and the first 
mover must be in itself unmovable, and eternal movement 
must be produced by something eternal and a single movement 
by a single thing, and since we see that besides the simple 
spatial movement of the universe, which we say the first and 
unmovable substance produces, there are other spatial 
movements - those of the planets - which are eternal (for a 
body which moves in a circle is eternal and unresting; we have 
proved these points in the physical treatises), each of these 
movements also must be caused by a substance both 
unmovable in itself and eternal. For the nature of the stars is 



2475 



eternal just because it is a certain kind of substance, and the 
mover is eternal and prior to the moved, and that which is prior 
to a substance must be a substance. Evidently, then, there must 
be substances which are of the same number as the movements 
of the stars, and in their nature eternal, and in themselves 
unmovable, and without magnitude, for the reason before 
mentioned. That the movers are substances, then, and that one 
of these is first and another second according to the same order 
as the movements of the stars, is evident. But in the number of 
the movements we reach a problem which must be treated from 
the standpoint of that one of the mathematical sciences which 
is most akin to philosophy - viz. of astronomy; for this science 
speculates about substance which is perceptible but eternal, but 
the other mathematical sciences, i.e. arithmetic and geometry, 
treat of no substance. That the movements are more numerous 
than the bodies that are moved is evident to those who have 
given even moderate attention to the matter; for each of the 
planets has more than one movement. But as to the actual 
number of these movements, we now - to give some notion of 
the subject - quote what some of the mathematicians say, that 
our thought may have some definite number to grasp; but, for 
the rest, we must partly investigate for ourselves, Partly learn 
from other investigators, and if those who study this subject 
form an opinion contrary to what we have now stated, we must 
esteem both parties indeed, but follow the more accurate. 

Eudoxus supposed that the motion of the sun or of the moon 
involves, in either case, three spheres, of which the first is the 
sphere of the fixed stars, and the second moves in the circle 
which runs along the middle of the zodiac, and the third in the 
circle which is inclined across the breadth of the zodiac; but the 
circle in which the moon moves is inclined at a greater angle 
than that in which the sun moves. And the motion of the 
planets involves, in each case, four spheres, and of these also 
the first and second are the same as the first two mentioned 



2476 



above (for the sphere of the fixed stars is that which moves all 
the other spheres, and that which is placed beneath this and 
has its movement in the circle which bisects the zodiac is 
common to all), but the poles of the third sphere of each planet 
are in the circle which bisects the zodiac, and the motion of the 
fourth sphere is in the circle which is inclined at an angle to the 
equator of the third sphere; and the poles of the third sphere 
are different for each of the other planets, but those of Venus 
and Mercury are the same. 

Callippus made the position of the spheres the same as 
Eudoxus did, but while he assigned the same number as 
Eudoxus did to Jupiter and to Saturn, he thought two more 
spheres should be added to the sun and two to the moon, if one 
is to explain the observed facts; and one more to each of the 
other planets. 

But it is necessary, if all the spheres combined are to explain the 
observed facts, that for each of the planets there should be 
other spheres (one fewer than those hitherto assigned) which 
counteract those already mentioned and bring back to the same 
position the outermost sphere of the star which in each case is 
situated below the star in question; for only thus can all the 
forces at work produce the observed motion of the planets. 
Since, then, the spheres involved in the movement of the 
planets themselves are - eight for Saturn and Jupiter and 
twenty-five for the others, and of these only those involved in 
the movement of the lowest-situated planet need not be 
counteracted the spheres which counteract those of the 
outermost two planets will be six in number, and the spheres 
which counteract those of the next four planets will be sixteen; 
therefore the number of all the spheres - both those which 
move the planets and those which counteract these - will be 
fifty-five. And if one were not to add to the moon and to the sun 



2477 



the movements we mentioned, the whole set of spheres will be 
forty-seven in number. 

Let this, then, be taken as the number of the spheres, so that 
the unmovable substances and principles also may probably be 
taken as just so many; the assertion of necessity must be left to 
more powerful thinkers. But if there can be no spatial 
movement which does not conduce to the moving of a star, and 
if further every being and every substance which is immune 
from change and in virtue of itself has attained to the best must 
be considered an end, there can be no other being apart from 
these we have named, but this must be the number of the 
substances. For if there are others, they will cause change as 
being a final cause of movement; but there cannot he other 
movements besides those mentioned. And it is reasonable to 
infer this from a consideration of the bodies that are moved; for 
if everything that moves is for the sake of that which is moved, 
and every movement belongs to something that is moved, no 
movement can be for the sake of itself or of another movement, 
but all the movements must be for the sake of the stars. For if 
there is to be a movement for the sake of a movement, this 
latter also will have to be for the sake of something else; so that 
since there cannot be an infinite regress, the end of every 
movement will be one of the divine bodies which move through 
the heaven. 

(Evidently there is but one heaven. For if there are many 
heavens as there are many men, the moving principles, of 
which each heaven will have one, will be one in form but in 
number many. But all things that are many in number have 
matter; for one and the same definition, e.g. that of man, 
applies to many things, while Socrates is one. But the primary 
essence has not matter; for it is complete reality. So the 
unmovable first mover is one both in definition and in number; 
so too, therefore, is that which is moved always and 



2478 



continuously; therefore there is one heaven alone.) Our 
forefathers in the most remote ages have handed down to their 
posterity a tradition, in the form of a myth, that these bodies 
are gods, and that the divine encloses the whole of nature. The 
rest of the tradition has been added later in mythical form with 
a view to the persuasion of the multitude and to its legal and 
utilitarian expediency; they say these gods are in the form of 
men or like some of the other animals, and they say other 
things consequent on and similar to these which we have 
mentioned. But if one were to separate the first point from 
these additions and take it alone - that they thought the first 
substances to be gods, one must regard this as an inspired 
utterance, and reflect that, while probably each art and each 
science has often been developed as far as possible and has 
again perished, these opinions, with others, have been 
preserved until the present like relics of the ancient treasure. 
Only thus far, then, is the opinion of our ancestors and of our 
earliest predecessors clear to us. 



The nature of the divine thought involves certain problems; for 
while thought is held to be the most divine of things observed 
by us, the question how it must be situated in order to have that 
character involves difficulties. For if it thinks of nothing, what is 
there here of dignity? It is just like one who sleeps. And if it 
thinks, but this depends on something else, then (since that 
which is its substance is not the act of thinking, but a potency) 
it cannot be the best substance; for it is through thinking that 
its value belongs to it. Further, whether its substance is the 
faculty of thought or the act of thinking, what does it think of? 
Either of itself or of something else; and if of something else, 



2479 



either of the same thing always or of something different. Does 
it matter, then, or not, whether it thinks of the good or of any 
chance thing? Are there not some things about which it is 
incredible that it should think? Evidently, then, it thinks of that 
which is most divine and precious, and it does not change; for 
change would be change for the worse, and this would be 
already a movement. First, then, if 'thought' is not the act of 
thinking but a potency, it would be reasonable to suppose that 
the continuity of its thinking is wearisome to it. Secondly, there 
would evidently be something else more precious than thought, 
viz. that which is thought of. For both thinking and the act of 
thought will belong even to one who thinks of the worst thing 
in the world, so that if this ought to be avoided (and it ought, for 
there are even some things which it is better not to see than to 
see), the act of thinking cannot be the best of things. Therefore 
it must be of itself that the divine thought thinks (since it is the 
most excellent of things), and its thinking is a thinking on 
thinking. 

But evidently knowledge and perception and opinion and 
understanding have always something else as their object, and 
themselves only by the way. Further, if thinking and being 
thought of are different, in respect of which does goodness 
belong to thought? For to he an act of thinking and to he an 
object of thought are not the same thing. We answer that in 
some cases the knowledge is the object. In the productive 
sciences it is the substance or essence of the object, matter 
omitted, and in the theoretical sciences the definition or the act 
of thinking is the object. Since, then, thought and the object of 
thought are not different in the case of things that have not 
matter, the divine thought and its object will be the same, i.e. 
the thinking will be one with the object of its thought. 

A further question is left - whether the object of the divine 
thought is composite; for if it were, thought would change in 



2480 



passing from part to part of the whole. We answer that 
everything which has not matter is indivisible - as human 
thought, or rather the thought of composite beings, is in a 
certain period of time (for it does not possess the good at this 
moment or at that, but its best, being something different from 
it, is attained only in a whole period of time), so throughout 
eternity is the thought which has itself for its object. 



10 

We must consider also in which of two ways the nature of the 
universe contains the good, and the highest good, whether as 
something separate and by itself, or as the order of the parts. 
Probably in both ways, as an army does; for its good is found 
both in its order and in its leader, and more in the latter; for he 
does not depend on the order but it depends on him. And all 
things are ordered together somehow, but not all alike, - both 
fishes and fowls and plants; and the world is not such that one 
thing has nothing to do with another, but they are connected. 
For all are ordered together to one end, but it is as in a house, 
where the freemen are least at liberty to act at random, but all 
things or most things are already ordained for them, while the 
slaves and the animals do little for the common good, and for 
the most part live at random; for this is the sort of principle that 
constitutes the nature of each. I mean, for instance, that all 
must at least come to be dissolved into their elements, and 
there are other functions similarly in which all share for the 
good of the whole. 

We must not fail to observe how many impossible or 
paradoxical results confront those who hold different views 
from our own, and what are the views of the subtler thinkers, 



2481 



and which views are attended by fewest difficulties. All make all 
things out of contraries. But neither 'all things' nor 'out of 
contraries' is right; nor do these thinkers tell us how all the 
things in which the contraries are present can be made out of 
the contraries; for contraries are not affected by one another. 
Now for us this difficulty is solved naturally by the fact that 
there is a third element. These thinkers however make one of 
the two contraries matter; this is done for instance by those 
who make the unequal matter for the equal, or the many 
matter for the one. But this also is refuted in the same way; for 
the one matter which underlies any pair of contraries is 
contrary to nothing. Further, all things, except the one, will, on 
the view we are criticizing, partake of evil; for the bad itself is 
one of the two elements. But the other school does not treat the 
good and the bad even as principles; yet in all things the good is 
in the highest degree a principle. The school we first mentioned 
is right in saying that it is a principle, but how the good is a 
principle they do not say -whether as end or as mover or as 
form. 

Empedocles also has a paradoxical view; for he identifies the 
good with love, but this is a principle both as mover (for it brings 
things together) and as matter (for it is part of the mixture). 
Now even if it happens that the same thing is a principle both 
as matter and as mover, still the being, at least, of the two is not 
the same. In which respect then is love a principle? It is 
paradoxical also that strife should be imperishable; the nature 
of his 'evil' is just strife. 

Anaxagoras makes the good a motive principle; for his 'reason' 
moves things. But it moves them for an end, which must be 
something other than it, except according to our way of stating 
the case; for, on our view, the medical art is in a sense health. It 
is paradoxical also not to suppose a contrary to the good, i.e. to 
reason. But all who speak of the contraries make no use of the 



2482 



contraries, unless we bring their views into shape. And why 
some things are perishable and others imperishable, no one 
tells us; for they make all existing things out of the same 
principles. Further, some make existing things out of the 
nonexistent; and others to avoid the necessity of this make all 
things one. 

Further, why should there always be becoming, and what is the 
cause of becoming? - This no one tells us. And those who 
suppose two principles must suppose another, a superior 
principle, and so must those who believe in the Forms; for why 
did things come to participate, or why do they participate, in the 
Forms? And all other thinkers are confronted by the necessary 
consequence that there is something contrary to Wisdom, i.e. to 
the highest knowledge; but we are not. For there is nothing 
contrary to that which is primary; for all contraries have matter, 
and things that have matter exist only potentially; and the 
ignorance which is contrary to any knowledge leads to an object 
contrary to the object of the knowledge; but what is primary has 
no contrary. 

Again, if besides sensible things no others exist, there will be no 
first principle, no order, no becoming, no heavenly bodies, but 
each principle will have a principle before it, as in the accounts 
of the theologians and all the natural philosophers. But if the 
Forms or the numbers are to exist, they will be causes of 
nothing; or if not that, at least not of movement. Further, how is 
extension, i.e. a continuum, to be produced out of unextended 
parts? For number will not, either as mover or as form, produce 
a continuum. But again there cannot be any contrary that is also 
essentially a productive or moving principle; for it would be 
possible for it not to be. Or at least its action would be posterior 
to its potency. The world, then, would not be eternal. But it is; 
one of these premisses, then, must be denied. And we have said 
how this must be done. Further, in virtue of what the numbers, 



2483 



or the soul and the body, or in general the form and the thing, 
are one - of this no one tells us anything; nor can any one tell, 
unless he says, as we do, that the mover makes them one. And 
those who say mathematical number is first and go on to 
generate one kind of substance after another and give different 
principles for each, make the substance of the universe a mere 
series of episodes (for one substance has no influence on 
another by its existence or nonexistence), and they give us 
many governing principles; but the world refuses to be governed 
badly. 

'The rule of many is not good; one ruler let there be.' 



BookM 



We have stated what is the substance of sensible things, dealing 
in the treatise on physics with matter, and later with the 
substance which has actual existence. Now since our inquiry is 
whether there is or is not besides the sensible substances any 
which is immovable and eternal, and, if there is, what it is, we 
must first consider what is said by others, so that, if there is 
anything which they say wrongly, we may not be liable to the 
same objections, while, if there is any opinion common to them 
and us, we shall have no private grievance against ourselves on 
that account; for one must be content to state some points 
better than one's predecessors, and others no worse. 



2484 



Two opinions are held on this subject; it is said that the objects 
of mathematics - i.e. numbers and lines and the like - are 
substances, and again that the Ideas are substances. And (1) 
since some recognize these as two different classes - the Ideas 
and the mathematical numbers, and (2) some recognize both as 
having one nature, while (3) some others say that the 
mathematical substances are the only substances, we must 
consider first the objects of mathematics, not qualifying them 
by any other characteristic - not asking, for instance, whether 
they are in fact Ideas or not, or whether they are the principles 
and substances of existing things or not, but only whether as 
objects of mathematics they exist or not, and if they exist, how 
they exist. Then after this we must separately consider the 
Ideas themselves in a general way, and only as far as the 
accepted mode of treatment demands; for most of the points 
have been repeatedly made even by the discussions outside our 
school, and, further, the greater part of our account must finish 
by throwing light on that inquiry, viz. when we examine 
whether the substances and the principles of existing things are 
numbers and Ideas; for after the discussion of the Ideas this 
remans as a third inquiry. 

If the objects of mathematics exist, they must exist either in 
sensible objects, as some say, or separate from sensible objects 
(and this also is said by some); or if they exist in neither of these 
ways, either they do not exist, or they exist only in some special 
sense. So that the subject of our discussion will be not whether 
they exist but how they exist. 



2485 



That it is impossible for mathematical objects to exist in 
sensible things, and at the same time that the doctrine in 
question is an artificial one, has been said already in our 
discussion of difficulties we have pointed out that it is 
impossible for two solids to be in the same place, and also that 
according to the same argument the other powers and 
characteristics also should exist in sensible things and none of 
them separately. This we have said already. But, further, it is 
obvious that on this theory it is impossible for any body 
whatever to be divided; for it would have to be divided at a 
plane, and the plane at a line, and the line at a point, so that if 
the point cannot be divided, neither can the line, and if the line 
cannot, neither can the plane nor the solid. What difference, 
then, does it make whether sensible things are such indivisible 
entities, or, without being so themselves, have indivisible 
entities in them? The result will be the same; if the sensible 
entities are divided the others will be divided too, or else not 
even the sensible entities can be divided. 

But, again, it is not possible that such entities should exist 
separately. For if besides the sensible solids there are to be other 
solids which are separate from them and prior to the sensible 
solids, it is plain that besides the planes also there must be 
other and separate planes and points and lines; for consistency 
requires this. But if these exist, again besides the planes and 
lines and points of the mathematical solid there must be others 
which are separate. (For incomposites are prior to compounds; 
and if there are, prior to the sensible bodies, bodies which are 
not sensible, by the same argument the planes which exist by 
themselves must be prior to those which are in the motionless 
solids. Therefore these will be planes and lines other than those 
that exist along with the mathematical solids to which these 
thinkers assign separate existence; for the latter exist along 



2486 



with the mathematical solids, while the others are prior to the 
mathematical solids.) Again, therefore, there will be, belonging 
to these planes, lines, and prior to them there will have to be, by 
the same argument, other lines and points; and prior to these 
points in the prior lines there will have to be other points, 
though there will be no others prior to these. Now (1) the 
accumulation becomes absurd; for we find ourselves with one 
set of solids apart from the sensible solids; three sets of planes 
apart from the sensible planes - those which exist apart from 
the sensible planes, and those in the mathematical solids, and 
those which exist apart from those in the mathematical solids; 
four sets of lines, and five sets of points. With which of these, 
then, will the mathematical sciences deal? Certainly not with 
the planes and lines and points in the motionless solid; for 
science always deals with what is prior. And (the same account 
will apply also to numbers; for there will be a different set of 
units apart from each set of points, and also apart from each set 
of realities, from the objects of sense and again from those of 
thought; so that there will be various classes of mathematical 
numbers. 

Again, how is it possible to solve the questions which we have 
already enumerated in our discussion of difficulties? For the 
objects of astronomy will exist apart from sensible things just 
as the objects of geometry will; but how is it possible that a 
heaven and its parts - or anything else which has movement - 
should exist apart? Similarly also the objects of optics and of 
harmonics will exist apart; for there will be both voice and sight 
besides the sensible or individual voices and sights. Therefore it 
is plain that the other senses as well, and the other objects of 
sense, will exist apart; for why should one set of them do so and 
another not? And if this is so, there will also be animals existing 
apart, since there will be senses. 



2487 



Again, there are certain mathematical theorems that are 
universal, extending beyond these substances. Here then we 
shall have another intermediate substance separate both from 
the Ideas and from the intermediates, - a substance which is 
neither number nor points nor spatial magnitude nor time. And 
if this is impossible, plainly it is also impossible that the former 
entities should exist separate from sensible things. 

And, in general, conclusion contrary alike to the truth and to 
the usual views follow, if one is to suppose the objects of 
mathematics to exist thus as separate entities. For because they 
exist thus they must be prior to sensible spatial magnitudes, but 
in truth they must be posterior; for the incomplete spatial 
magnitude is in the order of generation prior, but in the order of 
substance posterior, as the lifeless is to the living. 

Again, by virtue of what, and when, will mathematical 
magnitudes be one? For things in our perceptible world are one 
in virtue of soul, or of a part of soul, or of something else that is 
reasonable enough; when these are not present, the thing is a 
plurality, and splits up into parts. But in the case of the subjects 
of mathematics, which are divisible and are quantities, what is 
the cause of their being one and holding together? 

Again, the modes of generation of the objects of mathematics 
show that we are right. For the dimension first generated is 
length, then comes breadth, lastly depth, and the process is 
complete. If, then, that which is posterior in the order of 
generation is prior in the order of substantiality, the solid will be 
prior to the plane and the line. And in this way also it is both 
more complete and more whole, because it can become 
animate. How, on the other hand, could a line or a plane be 
animate? The supposition passes the power of our senses. 

Again, the solid is a sort of substance; for it already has in a 
sense completeness. But how can lines be substances? Neither 



2488 



as a form or shape, as the soul perhaps is, nor as matter, like the 
solid; for we have no experience of anything that can be put 
together out of lines or planes or points, while if these had been 
a sort of material substance, we should have observed things 
which could be put together out of them. 

Grant, then, that they are prior in definition. Still not all things 
that are prior in definition are also prior in substantiality. For 
those things are prior in substantiality which when separated 
from other things surpass them in the power of independent 
existence, but things are prior in definition to those whose 
definitions are compounded out of their definitions; and these 
two properties are not coextensive. For if attributes do not exist 
apart from the substances (e.g. a 'mobile' or a pale'), pale is prior 
to the pale man in definition, but not in substantiality. For it 
cannot exist separately, but is always along with the concrete 
thing; and by the concrete thing I mean the pale man. Therefore 
it is plain that neither is the result of abstraction prior nor that 
which is produced by adding determinants posterior; for it is by 
adding a determinant to pale that we speak of the pale man. 

It has, then, been sufficiently pointed out that the objects of 
mathematics are not substances in a higher degree than bodies 
are, and that they are not prior to sensibles in being, but only in 
definition, and that they cannot exist somewhere apart. But 
since it was not possible for them to exist in sensibles either, it 
is plain that they either do not exist at all or exist in a special 
sense and therefore do not 'exist' without qualification. For 
'exist' has many senses. 



2489 



For just as the universal propositions of mathematics deal not 
with objects which exist separately, apart from extended 
magnitudes and from numbers, but with magnitudes and 
numbers, not however qua such as to have magnitude or to be 
divisible, clearly it is possible that there should also be both 
propositions and demonstrations about sensible magnitudes, 
not however qua sensible but qua possessed of certain definite 
qualities. For as there are many propositions about things 
merely considered as in motion, apart from what each such 
thing is and from their accidents, and as it is not therefore 
necessary that there should be either a mobile separate from 
sensibles, or a distinct mobile entity in the sensibles, so too in 
the case of mobiles there will be propositions and sciences, 
which treat them however not qua mobile but only qua bodies, 
or again only qua planes, or only qua lines, or qua divisibles, or 
qua indivisibles having position, or only qua indivisibles. Thus 
since it is true to say without qualification that not only things 
which are separable but also things which are inseparable exist 
(for instance, that mobiles exist), it is true also to say without 
qualification that the objects of mathematics exist, and with 
the character ascribed to them by mathematicians. And as it is 
true to say of the other sciences too, without qualification, that 
they deal with such and such a subject - not with what is 
accidental to it (e.g. not with the pale, if the healthy thing is 
pale, and the science has the healthy as its subject), but with 
that which is the subject of each science - with the healthy if it 
treats its object qua healthy, with man if qua man: - so too is it 
with geometry; if its subjects happen to be sensible, though it 
does not treat them qua sensible, the mathematical sciences 
will not for that reason be sciences of sensibles - nor, on the 
other hand, of other things separate from sensibles. Many 
properties attach to things in virtue of their own nature as 
possessed of each such character; e.g. there are attributes 



2490 



peculiar to the animal qua female or qua male (yet there is no 
'female' nor 'male' separate from animals); so that there are 
also attributes which belong to things merely as lengths or as 
planes. And in proportion as we are dealing with things which 
are prior in definition and simpler, our knowledge has more 
accuracy, i.e. simplicity. Therefore a science which abstracts 
from spatial magnitude is more precise than one which takes it 
into account; and a science is most precise if it abstracts from 
movement, but if it takes account of movement, it is most 
precise if it deals with the primary movement, for this is the 
simplest; and of this again uniform movement is the simplest 
form. 

The same account may be given of harmonics and optics; for 
neither considers its objects qua sight or qua voice, but qua 
lines and numbers; but the latter are attributes proper to the 
former. And mechanics too proceeds in the same way. Therefore 
if we suppose attributes separated from their fellow attributes 
and make any inquiry concerning them as such, we shall not for 
this reason be in error, any more than when one draws a line on 
the ground and calls it a foot long when it is not; for the error is 
not included in the premisses. 

Each question will be best investigated in this way - by setting 
up by an act of separation what is not separate, as the 
arithmetician and the geometer do. For a man qua man is one 
indivisible thing; and the arithmetician supposed one 
indivisible thing, and then considered whether any attribute 
belongs to a man qua indivisible. But the geometer treats him 
neither qua man nor qua indivisible, but as a solid. For evidently 
the properties which would have belonged to him even if 
perchance he had not been indivisible, can belong to him even 
apart from these attributes. Thus, then, geometers speak 
correctly; they talk about existing things, and their subjects do 



2491 



exist; for being has two forms - it exists not only in complete 
reality but also materially. 

Now since the good and the beautiful are different (for the 
former always implies conduct as its subject, while the 
beautiful is found also in motionless things), those who assert 
that the mathematical sciences say nothing of the beautiful or 
the good are in error. For these sciences say and prove a great 
deal about them; if they do not expressly mention them, but 
prove attributes which are their results or their definitions, it is 
not true to say that they tell us nothing about them. The chief 
forms of beauty are order and symmetry and definiteness, 
which the mathematical sciences demonstrate in a special 
degree. And since these (e.g. order and definiteness) are 
obviously causes of many things, evidently these sciences must 
treat this sort of causative principle also (i.e. the beautiful) as in 
some sense a cause. But we shall speak more plainly elsewhere 
about these matters. 



So much then for the objects of mathematics; we have said that 
they exist and in what sense they exist, and in what sense they 
are prior and in what sense not prior. Now, regarding the Ideas, 
we must first examine the ideal theory itself, not connecting it 
in any way with the nature of numbers, but treating it in the 
form in which it was originally understood by those who first 
maintained the existence of the Ideas. The supporters of the 
ideal theory were led to it because on the question about the 
truth of things they accepted the Heraclitean sayings which 
describe all sensible things as ever passing away, so that if 
knowledge or thought is to have an object, there must be some 



2492 



other and permanent entities, apart from those which are 
sensible; for there could be no knowledge of things which were 
in a state of flux. But when Socrates was occupying himself 
with the excellences of character, and in connexion with them 
became the first to raise the problem of universal definition (for 
of the physicists Democritus only touched on the subject to a 
small extent, and defined, after a fashion, the hot and the cold; 
while the Pythagoreans had before this treated of a few things, 
whose definitions - e.g. those of opportunity, justice, or 
marriage - they connected with numbers; but it was natural 
that Socrates should be seeking the essence, for he was seeking 
to syllogize, and 'what a thing is' is the starting-point of 
syllogisms; for there was as yet none of the dialectical power 
which enables people even without knowledge of the essence to 
speculate about contraries and inquire whether the same 
science deals with contraries; for two things may be fairly 
ascribed to Socrates - inductive arguments and universal 
definition, both of which are concerned with the starting-point 
of science): - but Socrates did not make the universals or the 
definitions exist apart: they, however, gave them separate 
existence, and this was the kind of thing they called Ideas. 
Therefore it followed for them, almost by the same argument, 
that there must be Ideas of all things that are spoken of 
universally, and it was almost as if a man wished to count 
certain things, and while they were few thought he would not 
be able to count them, but made more of them and then 
counted them; for the Forms are, one may say, more numerous 
than the particular sensible things, yet it was in seeking the 
causes of these that they proceeded from them to the Forms. 
For to each thing there answers an entity which has the same 
name and exists apart from the substances, and so also in the 
case of all other groups there is a one over many, whether these 
be of this world or eternal. 



2493 



Again, of the ways in which it is proved that the Forms exist, 
none is convincing; for from some no inference necessarily 
follows, and from some arise Forms even of things of which 
they think there are no Forms. For according to the arguments 
from the sciences there will be Forms of all things of which 
there are sciences, and according to the argument of the 'one 
over many' there will be Forms even of negations, and according 
to the argument that thought has an object when the individual 
object has perished, there will be Forms of perishable things; for 
we have an image of these. Again, of the most accurate 
arguments, some lead to Ideas of relations, of which they say 
there is no independent class, and others introduce the 'third 
man'. 

And in general the arguments for the Forms destroy things for 
whose existence the believers in Forms are more zealous than 
for the existence of the Ideas; for it follows that not the dyad 
but number is first, and that prior to number is the relative, and 
that this is prior to the absolute - besides all the other points on 
which certain people, by following out the opinions held about 
the Forms, came into conflict with the principles of the theory. 

Again, according to the assumption on the belief in the Ideas 
rests, there will be Forms not only of substances but also of 
many other things; for the concept is single not only in the case 
of substances, but also in that of non-substances, and there are 
sciences of other things than substance; and a thousand other 
such difficulties confront them. But according to the necessities 
of the case and the opinions about the Forms, if they can be 
shared in there must be Ideas of substances only. For they are 
not shared in incidentally, but each Form must be shared in as 
something not predicated of a subject. (By 'being shared in 
incidentally' I mean that if a thing shares in 'double itself, it 
shares also in 'eternal', but incidentally; for 'the double' 
happens to be eternal.) Therefore the Forms will be substance. 



2494 



But the same names indicate substance in this and in the ideal 
world (or what will be the meaning of saying that there is 
something apart from the particulars - the one over many?). 
And if the Ideas and the things that share in them have the 
same form, there will be something common: for why should '2' 
be one and the same in the perishable 2's, or in the 2's which 
are many but eternal, and not the same in the '2 itself as in the 
individual 2? But if they have not the same form, they will have 
only the name in common, and it is as if one were to call both 
Callias and a piece of wood a 'man', without observing any 
community between them. 

But if we are to suppose that in other respects the common 
definitions apply to the Forms, e.g. that 'plane figure' and the 
other parts of the definition apply to the circle itself, but 'what 
really is' has to be added, we must inquire whether this is not 
absolutely meaningless. For to what is this to be added? To 
'centre' or to 'plane' or to all the parts of the definition? For all 
the elements in the essence are Ideas, e.g. 'animal' and 'two- 
footed'. Further, there must be some Ideal answering to 'plane' 
above, some nature which will be present in all the Forms as 
their genus. 



Above all one might discuss the question what in the world the 
Forms contribute to sensible things, either to those that are 
eternal or to those that come into being and cease to be; for 
they cause neither movement nor any change in them. But 
again they help in no wise either towards the knowledge of 
other things (for they are not even the substance of these, else 
they would have been in them), or towards their being, if they 



2495 



are not in the individuals which share in them; though if they 
were, they might be thought to be causes, as white causes 
whiteness in a white object by entering into its composition. But 
this argument, which was used first by Anaxagoras, and later by 
Eudoxus in his discussion of difficulties and by certain others, is 
very easily upset; for it is easy to collect many and insuperable 
objections to such a view. 

But, further, all other things cannot come from the Forms in any 
of the usual senses of 'from'. And to say that they are patterns 
and the other things share in them is to use empty words and 
poetical metaphors. For what is it that works, looking to the 
Ideas? And any thing can both be and come into being without 
being copied from something else, so that, whether Socrates 
exists or not, a man like Socrates might come to be. And 
evidently this might be so even if Socrates were eternal. And 
there will be several patterns of the same thing, and therefore 
several Forms; e.g. 'animal' and 'two-footed', and also 'man- 
himself, will be Forms of man. Again, the Forms are patterns 
not only of sensible things, but of Forms themselves also; i.e. 
the genus is the pattern of the various forms-of-a-genus; 
therefore the same thing will be pattern and copy. 

Again, it would seem impossible that substance and that whose 
substance it is should exist apart; how, therefore, could the 
Ideas, being the substances of things, exist apart? 

In the Phaedo the case is stated in this way - that the Forms are 
causes both of being and of becoming. Yet though the Forms 
exist, still things do not come into being, unless there is 
something to originate movement; and many other things come 
into being (e.g. a house or a ring) of which they say there are no 
Forms. Clearly therefore even the things of which they say there 
are Ideas can both be and come into being owing to such causes 
as produce the things just mentioned, and not owing to the 



2496 



Forms. But regarding the Ideas it is possible, both in this way 
and by more abstract and accurate arguments, to collect many 
objections like those we have considered. 



Since we have discussed these points, it is well to consider 
again the results regarding numbers which confront those who 
say that numbers are separable substances and first causes of 
things. If number is an entity and its substance is nothing other 
than just number, as some say, it follows that either (1) there is 
a first in it and a second, each being different in species, - and 
either (a) this is true of the units without exception, and any 
unit is inassociable with any unit, or (b) they are all without 
exception successive, and any of them are associable with any, 
as they say is the case with mathematical number; for in 
mathematical number no one unit is in any way different from 
another. Or (c) some units must be associable and some not; e.g. 
suppose that 2 is first after 1, and then comes 3 and then the 
rest of the number series, and the units in each number are 
associable, e.g. those in the first 2 are associable with one 
another, and those in the first 3 with one another, and so with 
the other numbers; but the units in the '2-itself are inassociable 
with those in the '3-itself ; and similarly in the case of the other 
successive numbers. And so while mathematical number is 
counted thus - after 1, 2 (which consists of another 1 besides 
the former 1), and 3 which consists of another 1 besides these 
two), and the other numbers similarly, ideal number is counted 
thus - after 1, a distinct 2 which does not include the first 1, and 
a 3 which does not include the 2 and the rest of the number 
series similarly. Or (2) one kind of number must be like the first 



2497 



that was named, one like that which the mathematicians speak 
of, and that which we have named last must be a third kind. 

Again, these kinds of numbers must either be separable from 
things, or not separable but in objects of perception (not 
however in the way which we first considered, in the sense that 
objects of perception consists of numbers which are present in 
them) - either one kind and not another, or all of them. 

These are of necessity the only ways in which the numbers can 
exist. And of those who say that the 1 is the beginning and 
substance and element of all things, and that number is formed 
from the 1 and something else, almost every one has described 
number in one of these ways; only no one has said all the units 
are inassociable. And this has happened reasonably enough; for 
there can be no way besides those mentioned. Some say both 
kinds of number exist, that which has a before and after being 
identical with the Ideas, and mathematical number being 
different from the Ideas and from sensible things, and both 
being separable from sensible things; and others say 
mathematical number alone exists, as the first of realities, 
separate from sensible things. And the Pythagoreans, also, 
believe in one kind of number - the mathematical; only they say 
it is not separate but sensible substances are formed out of it. 
For they construct the whole universe out of numbers - only not 
numbers consisting of abstract units; they suppose the units to 
have spatial magnitude. But how the first 1 was constructed so 
as to have magnitude, they seem unable to say. 

Another thinker says the first kind of number, that of the Forms, 
alone exists, and some say mathematical number is identical 
with this. 

The case of lines, planes, and solids is similar. For some think 
that those which are the objects of mathematics are different 
from those which come after the Ideas; and of those who 



2498 



express themselves otherwise some speak of the objects of 
mathematics and in a mathematical way - viz. those who do 
not make the Ideas numbers nor say that Ideas exist; and others 
speak of the objects of mathematics, but not mathematically; 
for they say that neither is every spatial magnitude divisible 
into magnitudes, nor do any two units taken at random make 2. 
All who say the 1 is an element and principle of things suppose 
numbers to consist of abstract units, except the Pythagoreans; 
but they suppose the numbers to have magnitude, as has been 
said before. It is clear from this statement, then, in how many 
ways numbers may be described, and that all the ways have 
been mentioned; and all these views are impossible, but some 
perhaps more than others. 



First, then, let us inquire if the units are associable or 
inassociable, and if inassociable, in which of the two ways we 
distinguished. For it is possible that any unity is inassociable 
with any, and it is possible that those in the 'itself are 
inassociable with those in the 'itself, and, generally, that those 
in each ideal number are inassociable with those in other ideal 
numbers. Now (1) all units are associable and without 
difference, we get mathematical number - only one kind of 
number, and the Ideas cannot be the numbers. For what sort of 
number will man-himself or animal-itself or any other Form be? 
There is one Idea of each thing e.g. one of man-himself and 
another one of animal-itself; but the similar and 
undifferentiated numbers are infinitely many, so that any 
particular 3 is no more man-himself than any other 3. But if the 
Ideas are not numbers, neither can they exist at all. For from 
what principles will the Ideas come? It is number that comes 



2499 



from the 1 and the indefinite dyad, and the principles or 
elements are said to be principles and elements of number, and 
the Ideas cannot be ranked as either prior or posterior to the 
numbers. 

But (2) if the units are inassociable, and inassociable in the 
sense that any is inassociable with any other, number of this 
sort cannot be mathematical number; for mathematical 
number consists of undifferentiated units, and the truths 
proved of it suit this character. Nor can it be ideal number. For 2 
will not proceed immediately from 1 and the indefinite dyad, 
and be followed by the successive numbers, as they say '2,3,4' 
for the units in the ideal are generated at the same time, 
whether, as the first holder of the theory said, from unequals 
(coming into being when these were equalized) or in some other 
way - since, if one unit is to be prior to the other, it will be prior 
also to 2 the composed of these; for when there is one thing 
prior and another posterior, the resultant of these will be prior 
to one and posterior to the other. Again, since the 1-itself is 
first, and then there is a particular 1 which is first among the 
others and next after the 1-itself, and again a third which is 
next after the second and next but one after the first 1, - so the 
units must be prior to the numbers after which they are named 
when we count them; e.g. there will be a third unit in 2 before 3 
exists, and a fourth and a fifth in 3 before the numbers 4 and 5 
exist. - Now none of these thinkers has said the units are 
inassociable in this way, but according to their principles it is 
reasonable that they should be so even in this way, though in 
truth it is impossible. For it is reasonable both that the units 
should have priority and posteriority if there is a first unit or 
first 1, and also that the 2's should if there is a first 2; for after 
the first it is reasonable and necessary that there should be a 
second, and if a second, a third, and so with the others 
successively. (And to say both things at the same time, that a 
unit is first and another unit is second after the ideal 1, and that 



2500 



a 2 is first after it, is impossible.) But they make a first unit or 1, 
but not also a second and a third, and a first 2, but not also a 
second and a third. Clearly, also, it is not possible, if all the units 
are inassociable, that there should be a 2-itself and a 3-itself; 
and so with the other numbers. For whether the units are 
undifferentiated or different each from each, number must be 
counted by addition, e.g. 2 by adding another 1 to the one, 3 by 
adding another 1 to the two, and similarly. This being so, 
numbers cannot be generated as they generate them, from the 2 
and the 1; for 2 becomes part of 3 and 3 of 4 and the same 
happens in the case of the succeeding numbers, but they say 4 
came from the first 2 and the indefinite which makes it two 2's 
other than the 2-itself; if not, the 2-itself will be a part of 4 and 
one other 2 will be added. And similarly 2 will consist of the 1- 
itself and another 1; but if this is so, the other element cannot 
be an indefinite 2; for it generates one unit, not, as the 
indefinite 2 does, a definite 2. 

Again, besides the 3-itself and the 2-itself how can there be 
other 3's and 2's? And how do they consist of prior and posterior 
units? All this is absurd and fictitious, and there cannot be a 
first 2 and then a 3-itself. Yet there must, if the 1 and the 
indefinite dyad are to be the elements. But if the results are 
impossible, it is also impossible that these are the generating 
principles. 

If the units, then, are differentiated, each from each, these 
results and others similar to these follow of necessity. But (3) if 
those in different numbers are differentiated, but those in the 
same number are alone undifferentiated from one another, 
even so the difficulties that follow are no less. E.g. in the 10- 
itself their are ten units, and the 10 is composed both of them 
and of two 5's. But since the 10-itself is not any chance number 
nor composed of any chance 5's - or, for that matter, units - the 
units in this 10 must differ. For if they do not differ, neither will 



2501 



the 5's of which the 10 consists differ; but since these differ, the 
units also will differ. But if they differ, will there be no other 5's 
in the 10 but only these two, or will there be others? If there are 
not, this is paradoxical; and if there are, what sort of 10 will 
consist of them? For there is no other in the 10 but the 10 itself. 
But it is actually necessary on their view that the 4 should not 
consist of any chance 2's; for the indefinite as they say, received 
the definite 2 and made two 2's; for its nature was to double 
what it received. 

Again, as to the 2 being an entity apart from its two units, and 
the 3 an entity apart from its three units, how is this possible? 
Either by one's sharing in the other, as 'pale man' is different 
from 'pale' and 'man' (for it shares in these), or when one is a 
differentia of the other, as 'man' is different from 'animal' and 
'two-footed'. 

Again, some things are one by contact, some by intermixture, 
some by position; none of which can belong to the units of 
which the 2 or the 3 consists; but as two men are not a unity 
apart from both, so must it be with the units. And their being 
indivisible will make no difference to them; for points too are 
indivisible, but yet a pair of them is nothing apart from the two. 

But this consequence also we must not forget, that it follows 
that there are prior and posterior 2 and similarly with the other 
numbers. For let the 2's in the 4 be simultaneous; yet these are 
prior to those in the 8 and as the 2 generated them, they 
generated the 4's in the 8-itself. Therefore if the first 2 is an 
Idea, these 2's also will be Ideas of some kind. And the same 
account applies to the units; for the units in the first 2 generate 
the four in 4, so that all the units come to be Ideas and an Idea 
will be composed of Ideas. Clearly therefore those things also of 
which these happen to be the Ideas will be composite, e.g. one 



2502 



might say that animals are composed of animals, if there are 
Ideas of them. 

In general, to differentiate the units in any way is an absurdity 
and a fiction; and by a fiction I mean a forced statement made 
to suit a hypothesis. For neither in quantity nor in quality do we 
see unit differing from unit, and number must be either equal 
or unequal - all number but especially that which consists of 
abstract units - so that if one number is neither greater nor less 
than another, it is equal to it; but things that are equal and in 
no wise differentiated we take to be the same when we are 
speaking of numbers. If not, not even the 2 in the 10-itself will 
be undifferentiated, though they are equal; for what reason will 
the man who alleges that they are not differentiated be able to 
give? 

Again, if every unit + another unit makes two, a unit from the 2- 
itself and one from the 3-itself will make a 2. Now (a) this will 
consist of differentiated units; and will it be prior to the 3 or 
posterior? It rather seems that it must be prior; for one of the 
units is simultaneous with the 3 and the other is simultaneous 
with the 2. And we, for our part, suppose that in general 1 and 1, 
whether the things are equal or unequal, is 2, e.g. the good and 
the bad, or a man and a horse; but those who hold these views 
say that not even two units are 2. 

If the number of the 3-itself is not greater than that of the 2, this 
is surprising; and if it is greater, clearly there is also a number in 
it equal to the 2, so that this is not different from the 2-itself. 
But this is not possible, if there is a first and a second number. 

Nor will the Ideas be numbers. For in this particular point they 
are right who claim that the units must be different, if there are 
to be Ideas; as has been said before. For the Form is unique; but 
if the units are not different, the 2's and the 3's also will not be 
different. This is also the reason why they must say that when 



2503 



we count thus - '1,2' - we do not proceed by adding to the given 
number; for if we do, neither will the numbers be generated 
from the indefinite dyad, nor can a number be an Idea; for then 
one Idea will be in another, and all Forms will be parts of one 
Form. And so with a view to their hypothesis their statements 
are right, but as a whole they are wrong; for their view is very 
destructive, since they will admit that this question itself 
affords some difficulty - whether, when we count and say - 
1,2,3 - we count by addition or by separate portions. But we do 
both; and so it is absurd to reason back from this problem to so 
great a difference of essence. 



8 

First of all it is well to determine what is the differentia of a 
number - and of a unit, if it has a differentia. Units must differ 
either in quantity or in quality; and neither of these seems to be 
possible. But number qua number differs in quantity. And if the 
units also did differ in quantity, number would differ from 
number, though equal in number of units. Again, are the first 
units greater or smaller, and do the later ones increase or 
diminish? All these are irrational suppositions. But neither can 
they differ in quality. For no attribute can attach to them; for 
even to numbers quality is said to belong after quantity. Again, 
quality could not come to them either from the 1 or the dyad; 
for the former has no quality, and the latter gives quantity; for 
this entity is what makes things to be many. If the facts are 
really otherwise, they should state this quite at the beginning 
and determine if possible, regarding the differentia of the unit, 
why it must exist, and, failing this, what differentia they mean. 



2504 



Evidently then, if the Ideas are numbers, the units cannot all be 
associable, nor can they be inassociable in either of the two 
ways. But neither is the way in which some others speak about 
numbers correct. These are those who do not think there are 
Ideas, either without qualification or as identified with certain 
numbers, but think the objects of mathematics exist and the 
numbers are the first of existing things, and the 1-itself is the 
starting-point of them. It is paradoxical that there should be a 1 
which is first of l's, as they say, but not a 2 which is first of 2's, 
nor a 3 of 3's; for the same reasoning applies to all. If, then, the 
facts with regard to number are so, and one supposes 
mathematical number alone to exist, the 1 is not the starting- 
point (for this sort of 1 must differ from the other units; and if 
this is so, there must also be a 2 which is first of 2's, and 
similarly with the other successive numbers). But if the 1 is the 
starting-point, the truth about the numbers must rather be 
what Plato used to say, and there must be a first 2 and 3 and 
numbers must not be associable with one another. But if on the 
other hand one supposes this, many impossible results, as we 
have said, follow. But either this or the other must be the case, 
so that if neither is, number cannot exist separately. 

It is evident, also, from this that the third version is the worst, - 
the view ideal and mathematical number is the same. For two 
mistakes must then meet in the one opinion. (1) Mathematical 
number cannot be of this sort, but the holder of this view has to 
spin it out by making suppositions peculiar to himself. And (2) 
he must also admit all the consequences that confront those 
who speak of number in the sense of 'Forms'. 

The Pythagorean version in one way affords fewer difficulties 
than those before named, but in another way has others 
peculiar to itself. For not thinking of number as capable of 
existing separately removes many of the impossible 
consequences; but that bodies should be composed of numbers, 



2505 



and that this should be mathematical number, is impossible. 
For it is not true to speak of indivisible spatial magnitudes; and 
however much there might be magnitudes of this sort, units at 
least have not magnitude; and how can a magnitude be 
composed of indivisibles? But arithmetical number, at least, 
consists of units, while these thinkers identify number with real 
things; at any rate they apply their propositions to bodies as if 
they consisted of those numbers. 

If, then, it is necessary, if number is a self-subsistent real thing, 
that it should exist in one of these ways which have been 
mentioned, and if it cannot exist in any of these, evidently 
number has no such nature as those who make it separable set 
up for it. 

Again, does each unit come from the great and the small, 
equalized, or one from the small, another from the great? (a) If 
the latter, neither does each thing contain all the elements, nor 
are the units without difference; for in one there is the great 
and in another the small, which is contrary in its nature to the 
great. Again, how is it with the units in the 3-itself? One of them 
is an odd unit. But perhaps it is for this reason that they give 1- 
itself the middle place in odd numbers, (b) But if each of the two 
units consists of both the great and the small, equalized, how 
will the 2 which is a single thing, consist of the great and the 
small? Or how will it differ from the unit? Again, the unit is 
prior to the 2; for when it is destroyed the 2 is destroyed. It 
must, then, be the Idea of an Idea since it is prior to an Idea, and 
it must have come into being before it. From what, then? Not 
from the indefinite dyad, for its function was to double. 

Again, number must be either infinite or finite; for these 
thinkers think of number as capable of existing separately, so 
that it is not possible that neither of those alternatives should 
be true. Clearly it cannot be infinite; for infinite number is 



2506 



neither odd nor even, but the generation of numbers is always 
the generation either of an odd or of an even number; in one 
way, when 1 operates on an even number, an odd number is 
produced; in another way, when 2 operates, the numbers got 
from 1 by doubling are produced; in another way, when the odd 
numbers operate, the other even numbers are produced. Again, 
if every Idea is an Idea of something, and the numbers are 
Ideas, infinite number itself will be an Idea of something, either 
of some sensible thing or of something else. Yet this is not 
possible in view of their thesis any more than it is reasonable in 
itself, at least if they arrange the Ideas as they do. 

But if number is finite, how far does it go? With regard to this 
not only the fact but the reason should be stated. But if number 
goes only up to 10 as some say, firstly the Forms will soon run 
short; e.g. if 3 is man-himself, what number will be the horse- 
itself? The series of the numbers which are the several things- 
themselves goes up to 10. It must, then, be one of the numbers 
within these limits; for it is these that are substances and Ideas. 
Yet they will run short; for the various forms of animal will 
outnumber them. At the same time it is clear that if in this way 
the 3 is man-himself, the other 3's are so also (for those in 
identical numbers are similar), so that there will be an infinite 
number of men; if each 3 is an Idea, each of the numbers will be 
man-himself, and if not, they will at least be men. And if the 
smaller number is part of the greater (being number of such a 
sort that the units in the same number are associable), then if 
the 4-itself is an Idea of something, e.g. of 'horse' or of 'white', 
man will be a part of horse, if man is It is paradoxical also that 
there should be an Idea of 10 but not of 11, nor of the 
succeeding numbers. Again, there both are and come to be 
certain things of which there are no Forms; why, then, are there 
not Forms of them also? We infer that the Forms are not causes. 
Again, it is paradoxical - if the number series up to 10 is more of 
a real thing and a Form than 10 itself. There is no generation of 



2507 



the former as one thing, and there is of the latter. But they try to 
work on the assumption that the series of numbers up to 10 is a 
complete series. At least they generate the derivatives - e.g. the 
void, proportion, the odd, and the others of this kind - within 
the decade. For some things, e.g. movement and rest, good and 
bad, they assign to the originative principles, and the others to 
the numbers. This is why they identify the odd with 1; for if the 
odd implied 3 how would 5 be odd? Again, spatial magnitudes 
and all such things are explained without going beyond a 
definite number; e.g. the first, the indivisible, line, then the 2 
&c; these entities also extend only up to 10. 

Again, if number can exist separately, one might ask which is 
prior -1, or 3 or 2? Inasmuch as the number is composite, 1 is 
prior, but inasmuch as the universal and the form is prior, the 
number is prior; for each of the units is part of the number as 
its matter, and the number acts as form. And in a sense the 
right angle is prior to the acute, because it is determinate and in 
virtue of its definition; but in a sense the acute is prior, because 
it is a part and the right angle is divided into acute angles. As 
matter, then, the acute angle and the element and the unit are 
prior, but in respect of the form and of the substance as 
expressed in the definition, the right angle, and the whole 
consisting of the matter and the form, are prior; for the concrete 
thing is nearer to the form and to what is expressed in the 
definition, though in generation it is later. How then is 1 the 
starting-point? Because it is not divisiable, they say; but both 
the universal, and the particular or the element, are indivisible. 
But they are starting-points in different ways, one in definition 
and the other in time. In which way, then, is 1 the starting- 
point? As has been said, the right angle is thought to be prior to 
the acute, and the acute to the right, and each is one. 
Accordingly they make 1 the starting-point in both ways. But 
this is impossible. For the universal is one as form or substance, 
while the element is one as a part or as matter. For each of the 



2508 



two is in a sense one - in truth each of the two units exists 
potentially (at least if the number is a unity and not like a heap, 
i.e. if different numbers consist of differentiated units, as they 
say), but not in complete reality; and the cause of the error they 
fell into is that they were conducting their inquiry at the same 
time from the standpoint of mathematics and from that of 
universal definitions, so that (1) from the former standpoint 
they treated unity, their first principle, as a point; for the unit is 
a point without position. They put things together out of the 
smallest parts, as some others also have done. Therefore the 
unit becomes the matter of numbers and at the same time prior 
to 2; and again posterior, 2 being treated as a whole, a unity, and 
a form. But (2) because they were seeking the universal they 
treated the unity which can be predicated of a number, as in 
this sense also a part of the number. But these characteristics 
cannot belong at the same time to the same thing. 

If the 1-itself must be unitary (for it differs in nothing from 
other l's except that it is the starting-point), and the 2 is 
divisible but the unit is not, the unit must be liker the 1-itself 
than the 2 is. But if the unit is liker it, it must be liker to the unit 
than to the 2; therefore each of the units in 2 must be prior to 
the 2. But they deny this; at least they generate the 2 first. 
Again, if the 2-itself is a unity and the 3-itself is one also, both 
form a 2. From what, then, is this 2 produced? 



Since there is not contact in numbers, but succession, viz. 
between the units between which there is nothing, e.g. between 
those in 2 or in 3 one might ask whether these succeed the 1- 



2509 



itself or not, and whether, of the terms that succeed it, 2 or 
either of the units in 2 is prior. 

Similar difficulties occur with regard to the classes of things 
posterior to number, - the line, the plane, and the solid. For 
some construct these out of the species of the 'great and small'; 
e.g. lines from the 'long and short', planes from the 'broad and 
narrow', masses from the 'deep and shallow'; which are species 
of the 'great and small'. And the originative principle of such 
things which answers to the 1 different thinkers describe in 
different ways, And in these also the impossibilities, the 
fictions, and the contradictions of all probability are seen to be 
innumerable. For (i) geometrical classes are severed from one 
another, unless the principles of these are implied in one 
another in such a way that the 'broad and narrow' is also 'long 
and short' (but if this is so, the plane will be line and the solid a 
plane; again, how will angles and figures and such things be 
explained?). And (ii) the same happens as in regard to number; 
for 'long and short', &c, are attributes of magnitude, but 
magnitude does not consist of these, any more than the line 
consists of 'straight and curved', or solids of 'smooth and 
rough'. 

(All these views share a difficulty which occurs with regard to 
species-of-a-genus, when one posits the universals, viz. 
whether it is animal-itself or something other than animal- 
itself that is in the particular animal. True, if the universal is not 
separable from sensible things, this will present no difficulty; 
but if the 1 and the numbers are separable, as those who 
express these views say, it is not easy to solve the difficulty, if 
one may apply the words 'not easy' to the impossible. For when 
we apprehend the unity in 2, or in general in a number, do we 
apprehend a thing-itself or something else?). 



2510 



Some, then, generate spatial magnitudes from matter of this 
sort, others from the point - and the point is thought by them to 
be not 1 but something like 1 - and from other matter like 
plurality, but not identical with it; about which principles none 
the less the same difficulties occur. For if the matter is one, line 
and plane - and soli will be the same; for from the same 
elements will come one and the same thing. But if the matters 
are more than one, and there is one for the line and a second 
for the plane and another for the solid, they either are implied 
in one another or not, so that the same results will follow even 
so; for either the plane will not contain a line or it will he a line. 

Again, how number can consist of the one and plurality, they 
make no attempt to explain; but however they express 
themselves, the same objections arise as confront those who 
construct number out of the one and the indefinite dyad. For 
the one view generates number from the universally predicated 
plurality, and not from a particular plurality; and the other 
generates it from a particular plurality, but the first; for 2 is said 
to be a 'first plurality'. Therefore there is practically no 
difference, but the same difficulties will follow, - is it 
intermixture or position or blending or generation? and so on. 
Above all one might press the question 'if each unit is one, what 
does it come from?' Certainly each is not the one-itself. It must, 
then, come from the one itself and plurality, or a part of 
plurality. To say that the unit is a plurality is impossible, for it is 
indivisible; and to generate it from a part of plurality involves 
many other objections; for (a) each of the parts must be 
indivisible (or it will be a plurality and the unit will be divisible) 
and the elements will not be the one and plurality; for the 
single units do not come from plurality and the one. Again, (,the 
holder of this view does nothing but presuppose another 
number; for his plurality of indivisibles is a number. Again, we 
must inquire, in view of this theory also, whether the number is 
infinite or finite. For there was at first, as it seems, a plurality 



2511 



that was itself finite, from which and from the one comes the 
finite number of units. And there is another plurality that is 
plurality-itself and infinite plurality; which sort of plurality, 
then, is the element which co-operates with the one? One 
might inquire similarly about the point, i.e. the element out of 
which they make spatial magnitudes. For surely this is not the 
one and only point; at any rate, then, let them say out of what 
each of the points is formed. Certainly not of some distance + 
the point-itself. Nor again can there be indivisible parts of a 
distance, as the elements out of which the units are said to be 
made are indivisible parts of plurality; for number consists of 
indivisibles, but spatial magnitudes do not. 

All these objections, then, and others of the sort make it evident 
that number and spatial magnitudes cannot exist apart from 
things. Again, the discord about numbers between the various 
versions is a sign that it is the incorrectness of the alleged facts 
themselves that brings confusion into the theories. For those 
who make the objects of mathematics alone exist apart from 
sensible things, seeing the difficulty about the Forms and their 
fictitiousness, abandoned ideal number and posited 
mathematical. But those who wished to make the Forms at the 
same time also numbers, but did not see, if one assumed these 
principles, how mathematical number was to exist apart from 
ideal, made ideal and mathematical number the same in words, 
since in fact mathematical number has been destroyed; for they 
state hypotheses peculiar to themselves and not those of 
mathematics. And he who first supposed that the Forms exist 
and that the Forms are numbers and that the objects of 
mathematics exist, naturally separated the two. Therefore it 
turns out that all of them are right in some respect, but on the 
whole not right. And they themselves confirm this, for their 
statements do not agree but conflict. The cause is that their 
hypotheses and their principles are false. And it is hard to make 



2512 



a good case out of bad materials, according to Epicharmus: 'as 
soon as 'tis said, 'tis seen to be wrong.' 

But regarding numbers the questions we have raised and the 
conclusions we have reached are sufficient (for while he who is 
already convinced might be further convinced by a longer 
discussion, one not yet convinced would not come any nearer to 
conviction); regarding the first principles and the first causes 
and elements, the views expressed by those who discuss only 
sensible substance have been partly stated in our works on 
nature, and partly do not belong to the present inquiry; but the 
views of those who assert that there are other substances 
besides the sensible must be considered next after those we 
have been mentioning. Since, then, some say that the Ideas and 
the numbers are such substances, and that the elements of 
these are elements and principles of real things, we must 
inquire regarding these what they say and in what sense they 
say it. 

Those who posit numbers only, and these mathematical, must 
be considered later; but as regards those who believe in the 
Ideas one might survey at the same time their way of thinking 
and the difficulty into which they fall. For they at the same time 
make the Ideas universal and again treat them as separable and 
as individuals. That this is not possible has been argued before. 
The reason why those who described their substances as 
universal combined these two characteristics in one thing, is 
that they did not make substances identical with sensible 
things. They thought that the particulars in the sensible world 
were a state of flux and none of them remained, but that the 
universal was apart from these and something different. And 
Socrates gave the impulse to this theory, as we said in our 
earlier discussion, by reason of his definitions, but he did not 
separate universals from individuals; and in this he thought 
rightly, in not separating them. This is plain from the results; for 



2513 



without the universal it is not possible to get knowledge, but the 
separation is the cause of the objections that arise with regard 
to the Ideas. His successors, however, treating it as necessary, if 
there are to be any substances besides the sensible and 
transient substances, that they must be separable, had no 
others, but gave separate existence to these universally 
predicated substances, so that it followed that universals and 
individuals were almost the same sort of thing. This in itself, 
then, would be one difficulty in the view we have mentioned. 



10 

Let us now mention a point which presents a certain difficulty 
both to those who believe in the Ideas and to those who do not, 
and which was stated before, at the beginning, among the 
problems. If we do not suppose substances to be separate, and 
in the way in which individual things are said to be separate, we 
shall destroy substance in the sense in which we understand 
'substance'; but if we conceive substances to be separable, how 
are we to conceive their elements and their principles? 

If they are individual and not universal, (a) real things will be 
just of the same number as the elements, and (b) the elements 
will not be knowable. For (a) let the syllables in speech be 
substances, and their elements elements of substances; then 
there must be only one 'ba' and one of each of the syllables, 
since they are not universal and the same in form but each is 
one in number and a 'this' and not a kind possessed of a 
common name (and again they suppose that the 'just what a 
thing is' is in each case one). And if the syllables are unique, so 
too are the parts of which they consist; there will not, then, be 
more a's than one, nor more than one of any of the other 



2514 



elements, on the same principle on which an identical syllable 
cannot exist in the plural number. But if this is so, there will not 
be other things existing besides the elements, but only the 
elements. 

(b) Again, the elements will not be even knowable; for they are 
not universal, and knowledge is of universals. This is clear from 
demonstrations and from definitions; for we do not conclude 
that this triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, unless 
every triangle has its angles equal to two right angles, nor that 
this man is an animal, unless every man is an animal. 

But if the principles are universal, either the substances 
composed of them are also universal, or non-substance will be 
prior to substance; for the universal is not a substance, but the 
element or principle is universal, and the element or principle is 
prior to the things of which it is the principle or element. 

All these difficulties follow naturally, when they make the Ideas 
out of elements and at the same time claim that apart from the 
substances which have the same form there are Ideas, a single 
separate entity. But if, e.g. in the case of the elements of speech, 
the a's and the b's may quite well be many and there need be no 
a-itself and b-itself besides the many, there may be, so far as 
this goes, an infinite number of similar syllables. The statement 
that an knowledge is universal, so that the principles of things 
must also be universal and not separate substances, presents 
indeed, of all the points we have mentioned, the greatest 
difficulty, but yet the statement is in a sense true, although in a 
sense it is not. For knowledge, like the verb 'to know', means 
two things, of which one is potential and one actual. The 
potency, being, as matter, universal and indefinite, deals with 
the universal and indefinite; but the actuality, being definite, 
deals with a definite object, being a 'this', it deals with a 'this'. 
But per accidens sight sees universal colour, because this 



2515 



individual colour which it sees is colour; and this individual a 
which the grammarian investigates is an a. For if the principles 
must be universal, what is derived from them must also be 
universal, as in demonstrations; and if this is so, there will be 
nothing capable of separate existence - i.e. no substance. But 
evidently in a sense knowledge is universal, and in a sense it is 
not. 



BookN 



Regarding this kind of substance, what we have said must be 
taken as sufficient. All philosophers make the first principles 
contraries: as in natural things, so also in the case of 
unchangeable substances. But since there cannot be anything 
prior to the first principle of all things, the principle cannot be 
the principle and yet be an attribute of something else. To 
suggest this is like saying that the white is a first principle, not 
qua anything else but qua white, but yet that it is predicable of a 
subject, i.e. that its being white presupposes its being 
something else; this is absurd, for then that subject will be prior. 
But all things which are generated from their contraries involve 
an underlying subject; a subject, then, must be present in the 
case of contraries, if anywhere. All contraries, then, are always 
predicable of a subject, and none can exist apart, but just as 
appearances suggest that there is nothing contrary to 



2516 



substance, argument confirms this. No contrary, then, is the 
first principle of all things in the full sense; the first principle is 
something different. 

But these thinkers make one of the contraries matter, some 
making the unequal which they take to be the essence of 
plurality-matter for the One, and others making plurality matter 
for the One. (The former generate numbers out of the dyad of 
the unequal, i.e. of the great and small, and the other thinker 
we have referred to generates them out of plurality, while 
according to both it is generated by the essence of the One.) For 
even the philosopher who says the unequal and the One are the 
elements, and the unequal is a dyad composed of the great and 
small, treats the unequal, or the great and the small, as being 
one, and does not draw the distinction that they are one in 
definition, but not in number. But they do not describe rightly 
even the principles which they call elements, for some name 
the great and the small with the One and treat these three as 
elements of numbers, two being matter, one the form; while 
others name the many and few, because the great and the small 
are more appropriate in their nature to magnitude than to 
number; and others name rather the universal character 
common to these - 'that which exceeds and that which is 
exceeded'. None of these varieties of opinion makes any 
difference to speak of, in view of some of the consequences; 
they affect only the abstract objections, which these thinkers 
take care to avoid because the demonstrations they themselves 
offer are abstract, - with this exception, that if the exceeding 
and the exceeded are the principles, and not the great and the 
small, consistency requires that number should come from the 
elements before does; for number is more universal than as the 
exceeding and the exceeded are more universal than the great 
and the small. But as it is, they say one of these things but do 
not say the other. Others oppose the different and the other to 
the One, and others oppose plurality to the One. But if, as they 



2517 



claim, things consist of contraries, and to the One either there is 
nothing contrary, or if there is to be anything it is plurality, and 
the unequal is contrary to the equal, and the different to the 
same, and the other to the thing itself, those who oppose the 
One to plurality have most claim to plausibility, but even their 
view is inadequate, for the One would on their view be a few; for 
plurality is opposed to fewness, and the many to the few. 

'The one' evidently means a measure. And in every case there is 
some underlying thing with a distinct nature of its own, e.g. in 
the scale a quarter-tone, in spatial magnitude a finger or a foot 
or something of the sort, in rhythms a beat or a syllable; and 
similarly in gravity it is a definite weight; and in the same way 
in all cases, in qualities a quality, in quantities a quantity (and 
the measure is indivisible, in the former case in kind, and in the 
latter to the sense); which implies that the one is not in itself 
the substance of anything. And this is reasonable; for 'the one' 
means the measure of some plurality, and 'number' means a 
measured plurality and a plurality of measures. (Thus it is 
natural that one is not a number; for the measure is not 
measures, but both the measure and the one are starting- 
points.) The measure must always be some identical thing 
predicable of all the things it measures, e.g. if the things are 
horses, the measure is 'horse', and if they are men, 'man'. If 
they are a man, a horse, and a god, the measure is perhaps 
'living being', and the number of them will be a number of 
living beings. If the things are 'man' and 'pale' and 'walking', 
these will scarcely have a number, because all belong to a 
subject which is one and the same in number, yet the number 
of these will be a number of 'kinds' or of some such term. 

Those who treat the unequal as one thing, and the dyad as an 
indefinite compound of great and small, say what is very far 
from being probable or possible. For (a) these are modifications 
and accidents, rather than substrata, of numbers and 



2518 



magnitudes - the many and few of number, and the great and 
small of magnitude - like even and odd, smooth and rough, 
straight and curved. Again, (b) apart from this mistake, the great 
and the small, and so on, must be relative to something; but 
what is relative is least of all things a kind of entity or 
substance, and is posterior to quality and quantity; and the 
relative is an accident of quantity, as was said, not its matter, 
since something with a distinct nature of its own must serve as 
matter both to the relative in general and to its parts and kinds. 
For there is nothing either great or small, many or few, or, in 
general, relative to something else, which without having a 
nature of its own is many or few, great or small, or relative to 
something else. A sign that the relative is least of all a 
substance and a real thing is the fact that it alone has no proper 
generation or destruction or movement, as in respect of 
quantity there is increase and diminution, in respect of quality 
alteration, in respect of place locomotion, in respect of 
substance simple generation and destruction. In respect of 
relation there is no proper change; for, without changing, a 
thing will be now greater and now less or equal, if that with 
which it is compared has changed in quantity. And (c) the 
matter of each thing, and therefore of substance, must be that 
which is potentially of the nature in question; but the relative is 
neither potentially nor actually substance. It is strange, then, or 
rather impossible, to make not-substance an element in, and 
prior to, substance; for all the categories are posterior to 
substance. Again, (d) elements are not predicated of the things 
of which they are elements, but many and few are predicated 
both apart and together of number, and long and short of the 
line, and both broad and narrow apply to the plane. If there is a 
plurality, then, of which the one term, viz. few, is always 
predicated, e.g. 2 (which cannot be many, for if it were many, 1 
would be few), there must be also one which is absolutely many, 
e.g. 10 is many (if there is no number which is greater than 10), 



2519 



or 10,000. How then, in view of this, can number consist of few 
and many? Either both ought to be predicated of it, or neither; 
but in fact only the one or the other is predicated. 



We must inquire generally, whether eternal things can consist 
of elements. If they do, they will have matter; for everything 
that consists of elements is composite. Since, then, even if a 
thing exists for ever, out of that of which it consists it would 
necessarily also, if it had come into being, have come into being, 
and since everything comes to be what it comes to be out of 
that which is it potentially (for it could not have come to be out 
of that which had not this capacity, nor could it consist of such 
elements), and since the potential can be either actual or not, - 
this being so, however everlasting number or anything else that 
has matter is, it must be capable of not existing, just as that 
which is any number of years old is as capable of not existing as 
that which is a day old; if this is capable of not existing, so is 
that which has lasted for a time so long that it has no limit. 
They cannot, then, be eternal, since that which is capable of not 
existing is not eternal, as we had occasion to show in another 
context. If that which we are now saying is true universally - 
that no substance is eternal unless it is actuality - and if the 
elements are matter that underlies substance, no eternal 
substance can have elements present in it, of which it consists. 

There are some who describe the element which acts with the 
One as an indefinite dyad, and object to 'the unequal', 
reasonably enough, because of the ensuing difficulties; but they 
have got rid only of those objections which inevitably arise from 
the treatment of the unequal, i.e. the relative, as an element; 



2520 



those which arise apart from this opinion must confront even 
these thinkers, whether it is ideal number, or mathematical, 
that they construct out of those elements. 

There are many causes which led them off into these 
explanations, and especially the fact that they framed the 
difficulty in an obsolete form. For they thought that all things 
that are would be one (viz. Being itself), if one did not join issue 
with and refute the saying of Parmenides: 

'For never will this he proved, that things that are not are.' 

They thought it necessary to prove that that which is not is; for 
only thus - of that which is and something else - could the 
things that are be composed, if they are many. 

But, first, if 'being' has many senses (for it means sometimes 
substance, sometimes that it is of a certain quality, sometimes 
that it is of a certain quantity, and at other times the other 
categories), what sort of 'one', then, are all the things that are, if 
non-being is to be supposed not to be? Is it the substances that 
are one, or the affections and similarly the other categories as 
well, or all together - so that the 'this' and the 'such' and the 'so 
much' and the other categories that indicate each some one 
class of being will all be one? But it is strange, or rather 
impossible, that the coming into play of a single thing should 
bring it about that part of that which is is a 'this', part a 'such', 
part a 'so much', part a 'here'. 

Secondly, of what sort of non-being and being do the things that 
are consist? For 'nonbeing' also has many senses, since 'being' 
has; and 'not being a man' means not being a certain substance, 
'not being straight' not being of a certain quality, 'not being 
three cubits long' not being of a certain quantity. What sort of 
being and non-being, then, by their union pluralize the things 
that are? This thinker means by the non-being the union of 



2521 



which with being pluralizes the things that are, the false and 
the character of falsity. This is also why it used to be said that 
we must assume something that is false, as geometers assume 
the line which is not a foot long to be a foot long. But this 
cannot be so. For neither do geometers assume anything false 
(for the enunciation is extraneous to the inference), nor is it 
non-being in this sense that the things that are are generated 
from or resolved into. But since 'non-being' taken in its various 
cases has as many senses as there are categories, and besides 
this the false is said not to be, and so is the potential, it is from 
this that generation proceeds, man from that which is not man 
but potentially man, and white from that which is not white but 
potentially white, and this whether it is some one thing that is 
generated or many. 

The question evidently is, how being, in the sense of 'the 
substances', is many; for the things that are generated are 
numbers and lines and bodies. Now it is strange to inquire how 
being in the sense of the 'what' is many, and not how either 
qualities or quantities are many. For surely the indefinite dyad 
or 'the great and the small' is not a reason why there should be 
two kinds of white or many colours or flavours or shapes; for 
then these also would be numbers and units. But if they had 
attacked these other categories, they would have seen the cause 
of the plurality in substances also; for the same thing or 
something analogous is the cause. This aberration is the reason 
also why in seeking the opposite of being and the one, from 
which with being and the one the things that are proceed, they 
posited the relative term (i.e. the unequal), which is neither the 
contrary nor the contradictory of these, and is one kind of being 
as 'what' and quality also are. 

They should have asked this question also, how relative terms 
are many and not one. But as it is, they inquire how there are 
many units besides the first 1, but do not go on to inquire how 



2522 



there are many unequals besides the unequal. Yet they use 
them and speak of great and small, many and few (from which 
proceed numbers), long and short (from which proceeds the 
line), broad and narrow (from which proceeds the plane), deep 
and shallow (from which proceed solids); and they speak of yet 
more kinds of relative term. What is the reason, then, why there 
is a plurality of these? 

It is necessary, then, as we say, to presuppose for each thing 
that which is it potentially; and the holder of these views 
further declared what that is which is potentially a 'this' and a 
substance but is not in itself being - viz. that it is the relative (as 
if he had said 'the qualitative'), which is neither potentially the 
one or being, nor the negation of the one nor of being, but one 
among beings. And it was much more necessary, as we said, if 
he was inquiring how beings are many, not to inquire about 
those in the same category - how there are many substances or 
many qualities - but how beings as a whole are many; for some 
are substances, some modifications, some relations. In the 
categories other than substance there is yet another problem 
involved in the existence of plurality. Since they are not 
separable from substances, qualities and quantities are many 
just because their substratum becomes and is many; yet there 
ought to be a matter for each category; only it cannot be 
separable from substances. But in the case of 'thises', it is 
possible to explain how the 'this' is many things, unless a thing 
is to be treated as both a 'this' and a general character. The 
difficulty arising from the facts about substances is rather this, 
how there are actually many substances and not one. 

But further, if the 'this' and the quantitative are not the same, 
we are not told how and why the things that are are many, but 
how quantities are many. For all 'number' means a quantity, and 
so does the 'unit', unless it means a measure or the 
quantitatively indivisible. If, then, the quantitative and the 



2523 



'what' are different, we are not told whence or how the 'what' is 
many; but if any one says they are the same, he has to face 
many inconsistencies. 

One might fix one's attention also on the question, regarding 
the numbers, what justifies the belief that they exist. To the 
believer in Ideas they provide some sort of cause for existing 
things, since each number is an Idea, and the Idea is to other 
things somehow or other the cause of their being; for let this 
supposition be granted them. But as for him who does not hold 
this view because he sees the inherent objections to the Ideas 
(so that it is not for this reason that he posits numbers), but 
who posits mathematical number, why must we believe his 
statement that such number exists, and of what use is such 
number to other things? Neither does he who says it exists 
maintain that it is the cause of anything (he rather says it is a 
thing existing by itself), nor is it observed to be the cause of 
anything; for the theorems of arithmeticians will all be found 
true even of sensible things, as was said before. 



As for those, then, who suppose the Ideas to exist and to be 
numbers, by their assumption in virtue of the method of setting 
out each term apart from its instances - of the unity of each 
general term they try at least to explain somehow why number 
must exist. Since their reasons, however, are neither conclusive 
nor in themselves possible, one must not, for these reasons at 
least, assert the existence of number. Again, the Pythagoreans, 
because they saw many attributes of numbers belonging te 
sensible bodies, supposed real things to be numbers - not 
separable numbers, however, but numbers of which real things 



2524 



consist. But why? Because the attributes of numbers are present 
in a musical scale and in the heavens and in many other things. 
Those, however, who say that mathematical number alone 
exists cannot according to their hypotheses say anything of this 
sort, but it used to be urged that these sensible things could not 
be the subject of the sciences. But we maintain that they are, as 
we said before. And it is evident that the objects of mathematics 
do not exist apart; for if they existed apart their attributes 
would not have been present in bodies. Now the Pythagoreans 
in this point are open to no objection; but in that they construct 
natural bodies out of numbers, things that have lightness and 
weight out of things that have not weight or lightness, they 
seem to speak of another heaven and other bodies, not of the 
sensible. But those who make number separable assume that it 
both exists and is separable because the axioms would not be 
true of sensible things, while the statements of mathematics 
are true and 'greet the soul'; and similarly with the spatial 
magnitudes of mathematics. It is evident, then, both that the 
rival theory will say the contrary of this, and that the difficulty 
we raised just now, why if numbers are in no way present in 
sensible things their attributes are present in sensible things, 
has to be solved by those who hold these views. 

There are some who, because the point is the limit and extreme 
of the line, the line of the plane, and the plane of the solid, think 
there must be real things of this sort. We must therefore 
examine this argument too, and see whether it is not 
remarkably weak. For (i) extremes are not substances, but rather 
all these things are limits. For even walking, and movement in 
general, has a limit, so that on their theory this will be a 'this' 
and a substance. But that is absurd. Not but what (ii) even if 
they are substances, they will all be the substances of the 
sensible things in this world; for it is to these that the argument 
applied. Why then should they be capable of existing apart? 



2525 



Again, if we are not too easily satisfied, we may, regarding all 
number and the objects of mathematics, press this difficulty, 
that they contribute nothing to one another, the prior to the 
posterior; for if number did not exist, none the less spatial 
magnitudes would exist for those who maintain the existence 
of the objects of mathematics only, and if spatial magnitudes 
did not exist, soul and sensible bodies would exist. But the 
observed facts show that nature is not a series of episodes, like 
a bad tragedy. As for the believers in the Ideas, this difficulty 
misses them; for they construct spatial magnitudes out of 
matter and number, lines out of the number planes doubtless 
out of solids out of or they use other numbers, which makes no 
difference. But will these magnitudes be Ideas, or what is their 
manner of existence, and what do they contribute to things? 
These contribute nothing, as the objects of mathematics 
contribute nothing. But not even is any theorem true of them, 
unless we want to change the objects of mathematics and 
invent doctrines of our own. But it is not hard to assume any 
random hypotheses and spin out a long string of conclusions. 
These thinkers, then, are wrong in this way, in wanting to unite 
the objects of mathematics with the Ideas. And those who first 
posited two kinds of number, that of the Forms and that which 
is mathematical, neither have said nor can say how 
mathematical number is to exist and of what it is to consist. For 
they place it between ideal and sensible number. If (i) it consists 
of the great and small, it will be the same as the other-ideal- 
number (he makes spatial magnitudes out of some other small 
and great). And if (ii) he names some other element, he will be 
making his elements rather many. And if the principle of each 
of the two kinds of number is a 1, unity will be something 
common to these, and we must inquire how the one is these 
many things, while at the same time number, according to him, 
cannot be generated except from one and an indefinite dyad. 



2526 



All this is absurd, and conflicts both with itself and with the 
probabilities, and we seem to see in it Simonides 'long 
rigmarole' for the long rigmarole comes into play, like those of 
slaves, when men have nothing sound to say. And the very 
elements - the great and the small - seem to cry out against the 
violence that is done to them; for they cannot in any way 
generate numbers other than those got from 1 by doubling. 

It is strange also to attribute generation to things that are 
eternal, or rather this is one of the things that are impossible. 
There need be no doubt whether the Pythagoreans attribute 
generation to them or not; for they say plainly that when the 
one had been constructed, whether out of planes or of surface 
or of seed or of elements which they cannot express, 
immediately the nearest part of the unlimited began to be 
constrained and limited by the limit. But since they are 
constructing a world and wish to speak the language of natural 
science, it is fair to make some examination of their physical 
theories, but to let them off from the present inquiry; for we are 
investigating the principles at work in unchangeable things, so 
that it is numbers of this kind whose genesis we must study. 



These thinkers say there is no generation of the odd number, 
which evidently implies that there is generation of the even; 
and some present the even as produced first from unequals - 
the great and the small - when these are equalized. The 
inequality, then, must belong to them before they are equalized. 
If they had always been equalized, they would not have been 
unequal before; for there is nothing before that which is always. 
Therefore evidently they are not giving their account of the 



2527 



generation of numbers merely to assist contemplation of their 
nature. 

A difficulty, and a reproach to any one who finds it no difficulty, 
are contained in the question how the elements and the 
principles are related to the good and the beautiful; the 
difficulty is this, whether any of the elements is such a thing as 
we mean by the good itself and the best, or this is not so, but 
these are later in origin than the elements. The theologians 
seem to agree with some thinkers of the present day, who 
answer the question in the negative, and say that both the good 
and the beautiful appear in the nature of things only when that 
nature has made some progress. (This they do to avoid a real 
objection which confronts those who say, as some do, that the 
one is a first principle. The objection arises not from their 
ascribing goodness to the first principle as an attribute, but from 
their making the one a principle - and a principle in the sense 
of an element - and generating number from the one.) The old 
poets agree with this inasmuch as they say that not those who 
are first in time, e.g. Night and Heaven or Chaos or Ocean, reign 
and rule, but Zeus. These poets, however, are led to speak thus 
only because they think of the rulers of the world as changing; 
for those of them who combine the two characters in that they 
do not use mythical language throughout, e.g. Pherecydes and 
some others, make the original generating agent the Best, and 
so do the Magi, and some of the later sages also, e.g. both 
Empedocles and Anaxagoras, of whom one made love an 
element, and the other made reason a principle. Of those who 
maintain the existence of the unchangeable substances some 
say the One itself is the good itself; but they thought its 
substance lay mainly in its unity. 

This, then, is the problem, - which of the two ways of speaking 
is right. It would be strange if to that which is primary and 
eternal and most self-sufficient this very quality - self- 



2528 



sufficiency and self-maintenance - belongs primarily in some 
other way than as a good. But indeed it can be for no other 
reason indestructible or self-sufficient than because its nature 
is good. Therefore to say that the first principle is good is 
probably correct; but that this principle should be the One or, if 
not that, at least an element, and an element of numbers, is 
impossible. Powerful objections arise, to avoid which some have 
given up the theory (viz. those who agree that the One is a first 
principle and element, but only of mathematical number). For 
on this view all the units become identical with species of good, 
and there is a great profusion of goods. Again, if the Forms are 
numbers, all the Forms are identical with species of good. But 
let a man assume Ideas of anything he pleases. If these are 
Ideas only of goods, the Ideas will not be substances; but if the 
Ideas are also Ideas of substances, all animals and plants and 
all individuals that share in Ideas will be good. 

These absurdities follow, and it also follows that the contrary 
element, whether it is plurality or the unequal, i.e. the great and 
small, is the bad-itself. (Hence one thinker avoided attaching 
the good to the One, because it would necessarily follow, since 
generation is from contraries, that badness is the fundamental 
nature of plurality; while others say inequality is the nature of 
the bad.) It follows, then, that all things partake of the bad 
except one - the One itself, and that numbers partake of it in a 
more undiluted form than spatial magnitudes, and that the bad 
is the space in which the good is realized, and that it partakes 
in and desires that which tends to destroy it; for contrary tends 
to destroy contrary. And if, as we were saying, the matter is that 
which is potentially each thing, e.g. that of actual fire is that 
which is potentially fire, the bad will be just the potentially 
good. 

All these objections, then, follow, partly because they make 
every principle an element, partly because they make contraries 



2529 



principles, partly because they make the One a principle, partly 
because they treat the numbers as the first substances, and as 
capable of existing apart, and as Forms. 



If, then, it is equally impossible not to put the good among the 
first principles and to put it among them in this way, evidently 
the principles are not being correctly described, nor are the first 
substances. Nor does any one conceive the matter correctly if 
he compares the principles of the universe to that of animals 
and plants, on the ground that the more complete always 
comes from the indefinite and incomplete - which is what leads 
this thinker to say that this is also true of the first principles of 
reality, so that the One itself is not even an existing thing. This 
is incorrect, for even in this world of animals and plants the 
principles from which these come are complete; for it is a man 
that produces a man, and the seed is not first. 

It is out of place, also, to generate place simultaneously with the 
mathematical solids (for place is peculiar to the individual 
things, and hence they are separate in place; but mathematical 
objects are nowhere), and to say that they must be somewhere, 
but not say what kind of thing their place is. 

Those who say that existing things come from elements and 
that the first of existing things are the numbers, should have 
first distinguished the senses in which one thing comes from 
another, and then said in which sense number comes from its 
first principles. 

By intermixture? But (1) not everything is capable of 
intermixture, and (2) that which is produced by it is different 



2530 



from its elements, and on this view the one will not remain 
separate or a distinct entity; but they want it to be so. 

By juxtaposition, like a syllable? But then (1) the elements must 
have position; and (2) he who thinks of number will be able to 
think of the unity and the plurality apart; number then will be 
this - a unit and plurality, or the one and the unequal. 

Again, coming from certain things means in one sense that 
these are still to be found in the product, and in another that 
they are not; which sense does number come from these 
elements? Only things that are generated can come from 
elements which are present in them. Does number come, then, 
from its elements as from seed? But nothing can be excreted 
from that which is indivisible. Does it come from its contrary, its 
contrary not persisting? But all things that come in this way 
come also from something else which does persist. Since, then, 
one thinker places the 1 as contrary to plurality, and another 
places it as contrary to the unequal, treating the 1 as equal, 
number must be being treated as coming from contraries. There 
is, then, something else that persists, from which and from one 
contrary the compound is or has come to be. Again, why in the 
world do the other things that come from contraries, or that 
have contraries, perish (even when all of the contrary is used to 
produce them), while number does not? Nothing is said about 
this. Yet whether present or not present in the compound the 
contrary destroys it, e.g. 'strife' destroys the 'mixture' (yet it 
should not; for it is not to that that is contrary). 

Once more, it has not been determined at all in which way 
numbers are the causes of substances and of being - whether 
(1) as boundaries (as points are of spatial magnitudes). This is 
how Eurytus decided what was the number of what (e.g. one of 
man and another of horse), viz. by imitating the figures of living 
things with pebbles, as some people bring numbers into the 



2531 



forms of triangle and square. Or (2) is it because harmony is a 
ratio of numbers, and so is man and everything else? But how 
are the attributes - white and sweet and hot - numbers? 
Evidently it is not the numbers that are the essence or the 
causes of the form; for the ratio is the essence, while the 
number the causes of the form; for the ratio is the essence, 
while the number is the matter. E.g. the essence of flesh or bone 
is number only in this way, 'three parts of fire and two of earth'. 
And a number, whatever number it is, is always a number of 
certain things, either of parts of fire or earth or of units; but the 
essence is that there is so much of one thing to so much of 
another in the mixture; and this is no longer a number but a 
ratio of mixture of numbers, whether these are corporeal or of 
any other kind. 

Number, then, whether it be number in general or the number 
which consists of abstract units, is neither the cause as agent, 
nor the matter, nor the ratio and form of things. Nor, of course, 
is it the final cause. 



One might also raise the question what the good is that things 
get from numbers because their composition is expressible by a 
number, either by one which is easily calculable or by an odd 
number. For in fact honey-water is no more wholesome if it is 
mixed in the proportion of three times three, but it would do 
more good if it were in no particular ratio but well diluted than 
if it were numerically expressible but strong. Again, the ratios of 
mixtures are expressed by the adding of numbers, not by mere 
numbers; e.g. it is 'three parts to two', not 'three times two'. For 
in any multiplication the genus of the things multiplied must be 



2532 



the same; therefore the product 1x2x3 must be measurable by 1, 
and 4x5x6 by 4 and therefore all products into which the same 
factor enters must be measurable by that factor. The number of 
fire, then, cannot be 2x5x3x6 and at the same time that of water 
2x3. 

If all things must share in number, it must follow that many 
things are the same, and the same number must belong to one 
thing and to another. Is number the cause, then, and does the 
thing exist because of its number, or is this not certain? E.g. the 
motions of the sun have a number, and again those of the 
moon, - yes, and the life and prime of each animal. Why, then, 
should not some of these numbers be squares, some cubes, and 
some equal, others double? There is no reason why they should 
not, and indeed they must move within these limits, since all 
things were assumed to share in number. And it was assumed 
that things that differed might fall under the same number. 
Therefore if the same number had belonged to certain things, 
these would have been the same as one another, since they 
would have had the same form of number; e.g. sun and moon 
would have been the same. But why need these numbers be 
causes? There are seven vowels, the scale consists of seven 
strings, the Pleiades are seven, at seven animals lose their teeth 
(at least some do, though some do not), and the champions who 
fought against Thebes were seven. Is it then because the 
number is the kind of number it is, that the champions were 
seven or the Pleiad consists of seven stars? Surely the 
champions were seven because there were seven gates or for 
some other reason, and the Pleiad we count as seven, as we 
count the Bear as twelve, while other peoples count more stars 
in both. Nay they even say that X, Ps and Z are concords and 
that because there are three concords, the double consonants 
also are three. They quite neglect the fact that there might be a 
thousand such letters; for one symbol might be assigned to GP. 
But if they say that each of these three is equal to two of the 



2533 



other letters, and no other is so, and if the cause is that there 
are three parts of the mouth and one letter is in each applied to 
sigma, it is for this reason that there are only three, not because 
the concords are three; since as a matter of fact the concords 
are more than three, but of double consonants there cannot be 
more. 

These people are like the old-fashioned Homeric scholars, who 
see small resemblances but neglect great ones. Some say that 
there are many such cases, e.g. that the middle strings are 
represented by nine and eight, and that the epic verse has 
seventeen syllables, which is equal in number to the two 
strings, and that the scansion is, in the right half of the line nine 
syllables, and in the left eight. And they say that the distance in 
the letters from alpha to omega is equal to that from the lowest 
note of the flute to the highest, and that the number of this 
note is equal to that of the whole choir of heaven. It may be 
suspected that no one could find difficulty either in stating such 
analogies or in finding them in eternal things, since they can be 
found even in perishable things. 

But the lauded characteristics of numbers, and the contraries of 
these, and generally the mathematical relations, as some 
describe them, making them causes of nature, seem, when we 
inspect them in this way, to vanish; for none of them is a cause 
in any of the senses that have been distinguished in reference 
to the first principles. In a sense, however, they make it plain 
that goodness belongs to numbers, and that the odd, the 
straight, the square, the potencies of certain numbers, are in the 
column of the beautiful. For the seasons and a particular kind of 
number go together; and the other agreements that they collect 
from the theorems of mathematics all have this meaning. 
Hence they are like coincidences. For they are accidents, but the 
things that agree are all appropriate to one another, and one by 
analogy. For in each category of being an analogous term is 



2534 



found - as the straight is in length, so is the level in surface, 
perhaps the odd in number, and the white in colour. 

Again, it is not the ideal numbers that are the causes of musical 
phenomena and the like (for equal ideal numbers differ from 
one another in form; for even the units do); so that we need not 
assume Ideas for this reason at least. 

These, then, are the results of the theory, and yet more might be 
brought together. The fact that our opponnts have much trouble 
with the generation of numbers and can in no way make a 
system of them, seems to indicate that the objects of 
mathematics are not separable from sensible things, as some 
say, and that they are not the first principles. 



2535 



Aristotle - Nicomachean Ethics 
[Translated by W. D. Ross] 



Book I 



Every art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and 
pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason the 
good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things 
aim. But a certain difference is found among ends; some are 
activities, others are products apart from the activities that 
produce them. Where there are ends apart from the actions, it is 
the nature of the products to be better than the activities. Now, 
as there are many actions, arts, and sciences, their ends also are 
many; the end of the medical art is health, that of shipbuilding 
a vessel, that of strategy victory, that of economics wealth. But 
where such arts fall under a single capacity - as bridle-making 
and the other arts concerned with the equipment of horses fall 
under the art of riding, and this and every military action under 
strategy, in the same way other arts fall under yet others - in all 
of these the ends of the master arts are to be preferred to all the 
subordinate ends; for it is for the sake of the former that the 
latter are pursued. It makes no difference whether the activities 
themselves are the ends of the actions, or something else apart 
from the activities, as in the case of the sciences just 
mentioned. 



2536 



If, then, there is some end of the things we do, which we desire 
for its own sake (everything else being desired for the sake of 
this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of 
something else (for at that rate the process would go on to 
infinity, so that our desire would be empty and vain), clearly 
this must be the good and the chief good. Will not the 
knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on life? Shall we 
not, like archers who have a mark to aim at, be more likely to 
hit upon what is right? If so, we must try, in outline at least, to 
determine what it is, and of which of the sciences or capacities 
it is the object. It would seem to belong to the most 
authoritative art and that which is most truly the master art. 
And politics appears to be of this nature; for it is this that 
ordains which of the sciences should be studied in a state, and 
which each class of citizens should learn and up to what point 
they should learn them; and we see even the most highly 
esteemed of capacities to fall under this, e.g. strategy, 
economics, rhetoric; now, since politics uses the rest of the 
sciences, and since, again, it legislates as to what we are to do 
and what we are to abstain from, the end of this science must 
include those of the others, so that this end must be the good 
for man. For even if the end is the same for a single man and for 
a state, that of the state seems at all events something greater 
and more complete whether to attain or to preserve; though it 
is worth while to attain the end merely for one man, it is finer 
and more godlike to attain it for a nation or for city-states. 
These, then, are the ends at which our inquiry aims, since it is 
political science, in one sense of that term. 



2537 



Our discussion will be adequate if it has as much clearness as 
the subject-matter admits of, for precision is not to be sought 
for alike in all discussions, any more than in all the products of 
the crafts. Now fine and just actions, which political science 
investigates, admit of much variety and fluctuation of opinion, 
so that they may be thought to exist only by convention, and 
not by nature. And goods also give rise to a similar fluctuation 
because they bring harm to many people; for before now men 
have been undone by reason of their wealth, and others by 
reason of their courage. We must be content, then, in speaking 
of such subjects and with such premisses to indicate the truth 
roughly and in outline, and in speaking about things which are 
only for the most part true and with premisses of the same kind 
to reach conclusions that are no better. In the same spirit, 
therefore, should each type of statement be received; for it is 
the mark of an educated man to look for precision in each class 
of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits; it is 
evidently equally foolish to accept probable reasoning from a 
mathematician and to demand from a rhetorician scientific 
proofs. 

Now each man judges well the things he knows, and of these he 
is a good judge. And so the man who has been educated in a 
subject is a good judge of that subject, and the man who has 
received an all-round education is a good judge in general. 
Hence a young man is not a proper hearer of lectures on 
political science; for he is inexperienced in the actions that 
occur in life, but its discussions start from these and are about 
these; and, further, since he tends to follow his passions, his 
study will be vain and unprofitable, because the end aimed at is 
not knowledge but action. And it makes no difference whether 
he is young in years or youthful in character; the defect does 
not depend on time, but on his living, and pursuing each 



2538 



successive object, as passion directs. For to such persons, as to 
the incontinent, knowledge brings no profit; but to those who 
desire and act in accordance with a rational principle 
knowledge about such matters will be of great benefit. 

These remarks about the student, the sort of treatment to be 
expected, and the purpose of the inquiry, may be taken as our 
preface. 



Let us resume our inquiry and state, in view of the fact that all 
knowledge and every pursuit aims at some good, what it is that 
we say political science aims at and what is the highest of all 
goods achievable by action. Verbally there is very general 
agreement; for both the general run of men and people of 
superior refinement say that it is happiness, and identify living 
well and doing well with being happy; but with regard to what 
happiness is they differ, and the many do not give the same 
account as the wise. For the former think it is some plain and 
obvious thing, like pleasure, wealth, or honour; they differ, 
however, from one another - and often even the same man 
identifies it with different things, with health when he is ill, 
with wealth when he is poor; but, conscious of their ignorance, 
they admire those who proclaim some great ideal that is above 
their comprehension. Now some thought that apart from these 
many goods there is another which is self-subsistent and 
causes the goodness of all these as well. To examine all the 
opinions that have been held were perhaps somewhat fruitless; 
enough to examine those that are most prevalent or that seem 
to be arguable. 



2539 



Let us not fail to notice, however, that there is a difference 
between arguments from and those to the first principles. For 
Plato, too, was right in raising this question and asking, as he 
used to do, 'are we on the way from or to the first principles?' 
There is a difference, as there is in a race-course between the 
course from the judges to the turning-point and the way back. 
For, while we must begin with what is known, things are objects 
of knowledge in two senses - some to us, some without 
qualification. Presumably, then, we must begin with things 
known to us. Hence any one who is to listen intelligently to 
lectures about what is noble and just, and generally, about the 
subjects of political science must have been brought up in good 
habits. For the fact is the starting-point, and if this is 
sufficiently plain to him, he will not at the start need the reason 
as well; and the man who has been well brought up has or can 
easily get startingpoints. And as for him who neither has nor 
can get them, let him hear the words of Hesiod: 

Far best is he who knows all things himself; 

Good, he that hearkens when men counsel right; 

But he who neither knows, nor lays to heart 

Another's wisdom, is a useless wight. 



Let us, however, resume our discussion from the point at which 
we digressed. To judge from the lives that men lead, most men, 
and men of the most vulgar type, seem (not without some 
ground) to identify the good, or happiness, with pleasure; which 
is the reason why they love the life of enjoyment. For there are, 



2540 



we may say, three prominent types of life - that just mentioned, 
the political, and thirdly the contemplative life. Now the mass of 
mankind are evidently quite slavish in their tastes, preferring a 
life suitable to beasts, but they get some ground for their view 
from the fact that many of those in high places share the tastes 
of Sardanapallus. A consideration of the prominent types of life 
shows that people of superior refinement and of active 
disposition identify happiness with honour; for this is, roughly 
speaking, the end of the political life. But it seems too 
superficial to be what we are looking for, since it is thought to 
depend on those who bestow honour rather than on him who 
receives it, but the good we divine to be something proper to a 
man and not easily taken from him. Further, men seem to 
pursue honour in order that they may be assured of their 
goodness; at least it is by men of practical wisdom that they 
seek to be honoured, and among those who know them, and on 
the ground of their virtue; clearly, then, according to them, at 
any rate, virtue is better. And perhaps one might even suppose 
this to be, rather than honour, the end of the political life. But 
even this appears somewhat incomplete; for possession of 
virtue seems actually compatible with being asleep, or with 
lifelong inactivity, and, further, with the greatest sufferings and 
misfortunes; but a man who was living so no one would call 
happy, unless he were maintaining a thesis at all costs. But 
enough of this; for the subject has been sufficiently treated even 
in the current discussions. Third comes the contemplative life, 
which we shall consider later. 

The life of money-making is one undertaken under compulsion, 
and wealth is evidently not the good we are seeking; for it is 
merely useful and for the sake of something else. And so one 
might rather take the aforenamed objects to be ends; for they 
are loved for themselves. But it is evident that not even these 
are ends; yet many arguments have been thrown away in 
support of them. Let us leave this subject, then. 



2541 



We had perhaps better consider the universal good and discuss 
thoroughly what is meant by it, although such an inquiry is 
made an uphill one by the fact that the Forms have been 
introduced by friends of our own. Yet it would perhaps be 
thought to be better, indeed to be our duty, for the sake of 
maintaining the truth even to destroy what touches us closely, 
especially as we are philosophers or lovers of wisdom; for, while 
both are dear, piety requires us to honour truth above our 
friends. 

The men who introduced this doctrine did not posit Ideas of 
classes within which they recognized priority and posteriority 
(which is the reason why they did not maintain the existence of 
an Idea embracing all numbers); but the term 'good' is used 
both in the category of substance and in that of quality and in 
that of relation, and that which is per se, i.e. substance, is prior 
in nature to the relative (for the latter is like an off shoot and 
accident of being); so that there could not be a common Idea set 
over all these goods. Further, since 'good' has as many senses as 
'being' (for it is predicated both in the category of substance, as 
of God and of reason, and in quality, i.e. of the virtues, and in 
quantity, i.e. of that which is moderate, and in relation, i.e. of 
the useful, and in time, i.e. of the right opportunity, and in place, 
i.e. of the right locality and the like), clearly it cannot be 
something universally present in all cases and single; for then it 
could not have been predicated in all the categories but in one 
only. Further, since of the things answering to one Idea there is 
one science, there would have been one science of all the goods; 
but as it is there are many sciences even of the things that fall 
under one category, e.g. of opportunity, for opportunity in war is 



2542 



studied by strategics and in disease by medicine, and the 
moderate in food is studied by medicine and in exercise by the 
science of gymnastics. And one might ask the question, what in 
the world they mean by 'a thing itself, is (as is the case) in 'man 
himself and in a particular man the account of man is one and 
the same. For in so far as they are man, they will in no respect 
differ; and if this is so, neither will 'good itself and particular 
goods, in so far as they are good. But again it will not be good 
any the more for being eternal, since that which lasts long is no 
whiter than that which perishes in a day. The Pythagoreans 
seem to give a more plausible account of the good, when they 
place the one in the column of goods; and it is they that 
Speusippus seems to have followed. 

But let us discuss these matters elsewhere; an objection to what 
we have said, however, may be discerned in the fact that the 
Platonists have not been speaking about all goods, and that the 
goods that are pursued and loved for themselves are called 
good by reference to a single Form, while those which tend to 
produce or to preserve these somehow or to prevent their 
contraries are called so by reference to these, and in a 
secondary sense. Clearly, then, goods must be spoken of in two 
ways, and some must be good in themselves, the others by 
reason of these. Let us separate, then, things good in themselves 
from things useful, and consider whether the former are called 
good by reference to a single Idea. What sort of goods would one 
call good in themselves? Is it those that are pursued even when 
isolated from others, such as intelligence, sight, and certain 
pleasures and honours? Certainly, if we pursue these also for 
the sake of something else, yet one would place them among 
things good in themselves. Or is nothing other than the Idea of 
good good in itself? In that case the Form will be empty. But if 
the things we have named are also things good in themselves, 
the account of the good will have to appear as something 
identical in them all, as that of whiteness is identical in snow 



2543 



and in white lead. But of honour, wisdom, and pleasure, just in 
respect of their goodness, the accounts are distinct and diverse. 
The good, therefore, is not some common element answering to 
one Idea. 

But what then do we mean by the good? It is surely not like the 
things that only chance to have the same name. Are goods one, 
then, by being derived from one good or by all contributing to 
one good, or are they rather one by analogy? Certainly as sight 
is in the body, so is reason in the soul, and so on in other cases. 
But perhaps these subjects had better be dismissed for the 
present; for perfect precision about them would be more 
appropriate to another branch of philosophy. And similarly with 
regard to the Idea; even if there is some one good which is 
universally predicable of goods or is capable of separate and 
independent existence, clearly it could not be achieved or 
attained by man; but we are now seeking something attainable. 
Perhaps, however, some one might think it worth while to 
recognize this with a view to the goods that are attainable and 
achievable; for having this as a sort of pattern we shall know 
better the goods that are good for us, and if we know them shall 
attain them. This argument has some plausibility, but seems to 
clash with the procedure of the sciences; for all of these, though 
they aim at some good and seek to supply the deficiency of it, 
leave on one side the knowledge of the good. Yet that all the 
exponents of the arts should be ignorant of, and should not 
even seek, so great an aid is not probable. It is hard, too, to see 
how a weaver or a carpenter will be benefited in regard to his 
own craft by knowing this 'good itself, or how the man who has 
viewed the Idea itself will be a better doctor or general thereby. 
For a doctor seems not even to study health in this way, but the 
health of man, or perhaps rather the health of a particular man; 
it is individuals that he is healing. But enough of these topics. 



2544 



Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it 
can be. It seems different in different actions and arts; it is 
different in medicine, in strategy, and in the other arts likewise. 
What then is the good of each? Surely that for whose sake 
everything else is done. In medicine this is health, in strategy 
victory, in architecture a house, in any other sphere something 
else, and in every action and pursuit the end; for it is for the 
sake of this that all men do whatever else they do. Therefore, if 
there is an end for all that we do, this will be the good 
achievable by action, and if there are more than one, these will 
be the goods achievable by action. 

So the argument has by a different course reached the same 
point; but we must try to state this even more clearly. Since 
there are evidently more than one end, and we choose some of 
these (e.g. wealth, flutes, and in general instruments) for the 
sake of something else, clearly not all ends are final ends; but 
the chief good is evidently something final. Therefore, if there is 
only one final end, this will be what we are seeking, and if there 
are more than one, the most final of these will be what we are 
seeking. Now we call that which is in itself worthy of pursuit 
more final than that which is worthy of pursuit for the sake of 
something else, and that which is never desirable for the sake of 
something else more final than the things that are desirable 
both in themselves and for the sake of that other thing, and 
therefore we call final without qualification that which is 
always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something 
else. 

Now such a thing happiness, above all else, is held to be; for this 
we choose always for self and never for the sake of something 
else, but honour, pleasure, reason, and every virtue we choose 



2545 



indeed for themselves (for if nothing resulted from them we 
should still choose each of them), but we choose them also for 
the sake of happiness, judging that by means of them we shall 
be happy. Happiness, on the other hand, no one chooses for the 
sake of these, nor, in general, for anything other than itself. 

From the point of view of self-sufficiency the same result seems 
to follow; for the final good is thought to be self-sufficient. Now 
by self-sufficient we do not mean that which is sufficient for a 
man by himself, for one who lives a solitary life, but also for 
parents, children, wife, and in general for his friends and fellow 
citizens, since man is born for citizenship. But some limit must 
be set to this; for if we extend our requirement to ancestors and 
descendants and friends' friends we are in for an infinite series. 
Let us examine this question, however, on another occasion; the 
self-sufficient we now define as that which when isolated 
makes life desirable and lacking in nothing; and such we think 
happiness to be; and further we think it most desirable of all 
things, without being counted as one good thing among others - 
if it were so counted it would clearly be made more desirable by 
the addition of even the least of goods; for that which is added 
becomes an excess of goods, and of goods the greater is always 
more desirable. Happiness, then, is something final and self- 
sufficient, and is the end of action. 

Presumably, however, to say that happiness is the chief good 
seems a platitude, and a clearer account of what it is still 
desired. This might perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain 
the function of man. For just as for a flute-player, a sculptor, or 
an artist, and, in general, for all things that have a function or 
activity, the good and the 'well' is thought to reside in the 
function, so would it seem to be for man, if he has a function. 
Have the carpenter, then, and the tanner certain functions or 
activities, and has man none? Is he born without a function? Or 
as eye, hand, foot, and in general each of the parts evidently has 



2546 



a function, may one lay it down that man similarly has a 
function apart from all these? What then can this be? Life 
seems to be common even to plants, but we are seeking what is 
peculiar to man. Let us exclude, therefore, the life of nutrition 
and growth. Next there would be a life of perception, but it also 
seems to be common even to the horse, the ox, and every 
animal. There remains, then, an active life of the element that 
has a rational principle; of this, one part has such a principle in 
the sense of being obedient to one, the other in the sense of 
possessing one and exercising thought. And, as 'life of the 
rational element' also has two meanings, we must state that life 
in the sense of activity is what we mean; for this seems to be 
the more proper sense of the term. Now if the function of man 
is an activity of soul which follows or implies a rational 
principle, and if we say 'so-and-so-and 'a good so-and-so' have a 
function which is the same in kind, e.g. a lyre, and a good lyre- 
player, and so without qualification in all cases, eminence in 
respect of goodness being idded to the name of the function (for 
the function of a lyre-player is to play the lyre, and that of a 
good lyre-player is to do so well): if this is the case, and we state 
the function of man to be a certain kind of life, and this to be an 
activity or actions of the soul implying a rational principle, and 
the function of a good man to be the good and noble 
performance of these, and if any action is well performed when 
it is performed in accordance with the appropriate excellence: if 
this is the case, human good turns out to be activity of soul in 
accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in 
accordance with the best and most complete. 

But we must add 'in a complete life.' For one swallow does not 
make a summer, nor does one day; and so too one day, or a 
short time, does not make a man blessed and happy. 

Let this serve as an outline of the good; for we must presumably 
first sketch it roughly, and then later fill in the details. But it 



2547 



would seem that any one is capable of carrying on and 
articulating what has once been well outlined, and that time is 
a good discoverer or partner in such a work; to which facts the 
advances of the arts are due; for any one can add what is 
lacking. And we must also remember what has been said before, 
and not look for precision in all things alike, but in each class of 
things such precision as accords with the subject-matter, and so 
much as is appropriate to the inquiry. For a carpenter and a 
geometer investigate the right angle in different ways; the 
former does so in so far as the right angle is useful for his work, 
while the latter inquires what it is or what sort of thing it is; for 
he is a spectator of the truth. We must act in the same way, 
then, in all other matters as well, that our main task may not be 
subordinated to minor questions. Nor must we demand the 
cause in all matters alike; it is enough in some cases that the 
fact be well established, as in the case of the first principles; the 
fact is the primary thing or first principle. Now of first principles 
we see some by induction, some by perception, some by a 
certain habituation, and others too in other ways. But each set 
of principles we must try to investigate in the natural way, and 
we must take pains to state them definitely, since they have a 
great influence on what follows. For the beginning is thought to 
be more than half of the whole, and many of the questions we 
ask are cleared up by it. 



8 

We must consider it, however, in the light not only of our 
conclusion and our premisses, but also of what is commonly 
said about it; for with a true view all the data harmonize, but 
with a false one the facts soon clash. Now goods have been 
divided into three classes, and some are described as external, 



2548 



others as relating to soul or to body; we call those that relate to 
soul most properly and truly goods, and psychical actions and 
activities we class as relating to soul. Therefore our account 
must be sound, at least according to this view, which is an old 
one and agreed on by philosophers. It is correct also in that we 
identify the end with certain actions and activities; for thus it 
falls among goods of the soul and not among external goods. 
Another belief which harmonizes with our account is that the 
happy man lives well and does well; for we have practically 
defined happiness as a sort of good life and good action. The 
characteristics that are looked for in happiness seem also, all of 
them, to belong to what we have defined happiness as being. 
For some identify happiness with virtue, some with practical 
wisdom, others with a kind of philosophic wisdom, others with 
these, or one of these, accompanied by pleasure or not without 
pleasure; while others include also external prosperity. Now 
some of these views have been held by many men and men of 
old, others by a few eminent persons; and it is not probable that 
either of these should be entirely mistaken, but rather that they 
should be right in at least some one respect or even in most 
respects. 

With those who identify happiness with virtue or some one 
virtue our account is in harmony; for to virtue belongs virtuous 
activity. But it makes, perhaps, no small difference whether we 
place the chief good in possession or in use, in state of mind or 
in activity. For the state of mind may exist without producing 
any good result, as in a man who is asleep or in some other way 
quite inactive, but the activity cannot; for one who has the 
activity will of necessity be acting, and acting well. And as in the 
Olympic Games it is not the most beautiful and the strongest 
that are crowned but those who compete (for it is some of these 
that are victorious), so those who act win, and rightly win, the 
noble and good things in life. 



2549 



Their life is also in itself pleasant. For pleasure is a state of soul, 
and to each man that which he is said to be a lover of is 
pleasant; e.g. not only is a horse pleasant to the lover of horses, 
and a spectacle to the lover of sights, but also in the same way 
just acts are pleasant to the lover of justice and in general 
virtuous acts to the lover of virtue. Now for most men their 
pleasures are in conflict with one another because these are not 
by nature pleasant, but the lovers of what is noble find pleasant 
the things that are by nature pleasant; and virtuous actions are 
such, so that these are pleasant for such men as well as in their 
own nature. Their life, therefore, has no further need of pleasure 
as a sort of adventitious charm, but has its pleasure in itself. For, 
besides what we have said, the man who does not rejoice in 
noble actions is not even good; since no one would call a man 
just who did not enjoy acting justly, nor any man liberal who 
did not enjoy liberal actions; and similarly in all other cases. If 
this is so, virtuous actions must be in themselves pleasant. But 
they are also good and noble, and have each of these attributes 
in the highest degree, since the good man judges well about 
these attributes; his judgement is such as we have described. 
Happiness then is the best, noblest, and most pleasant thing in 
the world, and these attributes are not severed as in the 
inscription at Delos: 

Most noble is that which is justest, and best is health; 

But pleasantest is it to win what we love. 

For all these properties belong to the best activities; and these, 
or one - the best - of these, we identify with happiness. 

Yet evidently, as we said, it needs the external goods as well; for 
it is impossible, or not easy, to do noble acts without the proper 
equipment. In many actions we use friends and riches and 
political power as instruments; and there are some things the 
lack of which takes the lustre from happiness, as good birth, 



2550 



goodly children, beauty; for the man who is very ugly in 
appearance or ill-born or solitary and childless is not very likely 
to be happy, and perhaps a man would be still less likely if he 
had thoroughly bad children or friends or had lost good children 
or friends by death. As we said, then, happiness seems to need 
this sort of prosperity in addition; for which reason some 
identify happiness with good fortune, though others identify it 
with virtue. 



For this reason also the question is asked, whether happiness is 
to be acquired by learning or by habituation or some other sort 
of training, or comes in virtue of some divine providence or 
again by chance. Now if there is any gift of the gods to men, it is 
reasonable that happiness should be god-given, and most surely 
god-given of all human things inasmuch as it is the best. But 
this question would perhaps be more appropriate to another 
inquiry; happiness seems, however, even if it is not god-sent but 
comes as a result of virtue and some process of learning or 
training, to be among the most godlike things; for that which is 
the prize and end of virtue seems to be the best thing in the 
world, and something godlike and blessed. 

It will also on this view be very generally shared; for all who are 
not maimed as regards their potentiality for virtue may win it 
by a certain kind of study and care. But if it is better to be happy 
thus than by chance, it is reasonable that the facts should be so, 
since everything that depends on the action of nature is by 
nature as good as it can be, and similarly everything that 
depends on art or any rational cause, and especially if it 



2551 



depends on the best of all causes. To entrust to chance what is 
greatest and most noble would be a very defective arrangement. 

The answer to the question we are asking is plain also from the 
definition of happiness; for it has been said to be a virtuous 
activity of soul, of a certain kind. Of the remaining goods, some 
must necessarily pre-exist as conditions of happiness, and 
others are naturally co-operative and useful as instruments. 
And this will be found to agree with what we said at the outset; 
for we stated the end of political science to be the best end, and 
political science spends most of its pains on making the citizens 
to be of a certain character, viz. good and capable of noble acts. 

It is natural, then, that we call neither ox nor horse nor any 
other of the animals happy; for none of them is capable of 
sharing in such activity. For this reason also a boy is not happy; 
for he is not yet capable of such acts, owing to his age; and boys 
who are called happy are being congratulated by reason of the 
hopes we have for them. For there is required, as we said, not 
only complete virtue but also a complete life, since many 
changes occur in life, and all manner of chances, and the most 
prosperous may fall into great misfortunes in old age, as is told 
of Priam in the Trojan Cycle; and one who has experienced such 
chances and has ended wretchedly no one calls happy. 



10 

Must no one at all, then, be called happy while he lives; must 
we, as Solon says, see the end? Even if we are to lay down this 
doctrine, is it also the case that a man is happy when he is 
dead? Or is not this quite absurd, especially for us who say that 
happiness is an activity? But if we do not call the dead man 
happy, and if Solon does not mean this, but that one can then 



2552 



safely call a man blessed as being at last beyond evils and 
misfortunes, this also affords matter for discussion; for both evil 
and good are thought to exist for a dead man, as much as for 
one who is alive but not aware of them; e.g. honours and 
dishonours and the good or bad fortunes of children and in 
general of descendants. And this also presents a problem; for 
though a man has lived happily up to old age and has had a 
death worthy of his life, many reverses may befall his 
descendants - some of them may be good and attain the life 
they deserve, while with others the opposite may be the case; 
and clearly too the degrees of relationship between them and 
their ancestors may vary indefinitely. It would be odd, then, if 
the dead man were to share in these changes and become at 
one time happy, at another wretched; while it would also be odd 
if the fortunes of the descendants did not for some time have 
some effect on the happiness of their ancestors. 

But we must return to our first difficulty; for perhaps by a 
consideration of it our present problem might be solved. Now if 
we must see the end and only then call a man happy, not as 
being happy but as having been so before, surely this is a 
paradox, that when he is happy the attribute that belongs to 
him is not to be truly predicated of him because we do not wish 
to call living men happy, on account of the changes that may 
befall them, and because we have assumed happiness to be 
something permanent and by no means easily changed, while a 
single man may suffer many turns of fortune's wheel. For 
clearly if we were to keep pace with his fortunes, we should 
often call the same man happy and again wretched, making the 
happy man out to be chameleon and insecurely based. Or is this 
keeping pace with his fortunes quite wrong? Success or failure 
in life does not depend on these, but human life, as we said, 
needs these as mere additions, while virtuous activities or their 
opposites are what constitute happiness or the reverse. 



2553 



The question we have now discussed confirms our definition. 
For no function of man has so much permanence as virtuous 
activities (these are thought to be more durable even than 
knowledge of the sciences), and of these themselves the most 
valuable are more durable because those who are happy spend 
their life most readily and most continuously in these; for this 
seems to be the reason why we do not forget them. The 
attribute in question, then, will belong to the happy man, and 
he will be happy throughout his life; for always, or by preference 
to everything else, he will be engaged in virtuous action and 
contemplation, and he will bear the chances of life most nobly 
and altogether decorously, if he is 'truly good' and 'foursquare 
beyond reproach'. 

Now many events happen by chance, and events differing in 
importance; small pieces of good fortune or of its opposite 
clearly do not weigh down the scales of life one way or the 
other, but a multitude of great events if they turn out well will 
make life happier (for not only are they themselves such as to 
add beauty to life, but the way a man deals with them may be 
noble and good), while if they turn out ill they crush and maim 
happiness; for they both bring pain with them and hinder many 
activities. Yet even in these nobility shines through, when a 
man bears with resignation many great misfortunes, not 
through insensibility to pain but through nobility and greatness 
of soul. 

If activities are, as we said, what gives life its character, no 
happy man can become miserable; for he will never do the acts 
that are hateful and mean. For the man who is truly good and 
wise, we think, bears all the chances life becomingly and always 
makes the best of circumstances, as a good general makes the 
best military use of the army at his command and a good 
shoemaker makes the best shoes out of the hides that are given 
him; and so with all other craftsmen. And if this is the case, the 



2554 



happy man can never become miserable; though he will not 
reach blessedness, if he meet with fortunes like those of Priam. 

Nor, again, is he many-coloured and changeable; for neither will 
he be moved from his happy state easily or by any ordinary 
misadventures, but only by many great ones, nor, if he has had 
many great misadventures, will he recover his happiness in a 
short time, but if at all, only in a long and complete one in 
which he has attained many splendid successes. 

When then should we not say that he is happy who is active in 
accordance with complete virtue and is sufficiently equipped 
with external goods, not for some chance period but throughout 
a complete life? Or must we add 'and who is destined to live 
thus and die as befits his life'? Certainly the future is obscure to 
us, while happiness, we claim, is an end and something in every 
way final. If so, we shall call happy those among living men in 
whom these conditions are, and are to be, fulfilled - but happy 
men. So much for these questions. 



11 

That the fortunes of descendants and of all a man's friends 
should not affect his happiness at all seems a very unfriendly 
doctrine, and one opposed to the opinions men hold; but since 
the events that happen are numerous and admit of all sorts of 
difference, and some come more near to us and others less so, it 
seems a long - nay, an infinite - task to discuss each in detail; a 
general outline will perhaps suffice. If, then, as some of a man's 
own misadventures have a certain weight and influence on life 
while others are, as it were, lighter, so too there are differences 
among the misadventures of our friends taken as a whole, and 
it makes a difference whether the various suffering befall the 



2555 



living or the dead (much more even than whether lawless and 
terrible deeds are presupposed in a tragedy or done on the 
stage), this difference also must be taken into account; or rather, 
perhaps, the fact that doubt is felt whether the dead share in 
any good or evil. For it seems, from these considerations, that 
even if anything whether good or evil penetrates to them, it 
must be something weak and negligible, either in itself or for 
them, or if not, at least it must be such in degree and kind as 
not to make happy those who are not happy nor to take away 
their blessedness from those who are. The good or bad fortunes 
of friends, then, seem to have some effects on the dead, but 
effects of such a kind and degree as neither to make the happy 
unhappy nor to produce any other change of the kind. 



12 

These questions having been definitely answered, let us 
consider whether happiness is among the things that are 
praised or rather among the things that are prized; for clearly it 
is not to be placed among potentialities. Everything that is 
praised seems to be praised because it is of a certain kind and is 
related somehow to something else; for we praise the just or 
brave man and in general both the good man and virtue itself 
because of the actions and functions involved, and we praise 
the strong man, the good runner, and so on, because he is of a 
certain kind and is related in a certain way to something good 
and important. This is clear also from the praises of the gods; 
for it seems absurd that the gods should be referred to our 
standard, but this is done because praise involves a reference, to 
something else. But if if praise is for things such as we have 
described, clearly what applies to the best things is not praise, 
but something greater and better, as is indeed obvious; for what 



2556 



we do to the gods and the most godlike of men is to call them 
blessed and happy. And so too with good things; no one praises 
happiness as he does justice, but rather calls it blessed, as being 
something more divine and better. 

Eudoxus also seems to have been right in his method of 
advocating the supremacy of pleasure; he thought that the fact 
that, though a good, it is not praised indicated it to be better 
than the things that are praised, and that this is what God and 
the good are; for by reference to these all other things are 
judged. Praise is appropriate to virtue, for as a result of virtue 
men tend to do noble deeds, but encomia are bestowed on acts, 
whether of the body or of the soul. But perhaps nicety in these 
matters is more proper to those who have made a study of 
encomia; to us it is clear from what has been said that 
happiness is among the things that are prized and perfect. It 
seems to be so also from the fact that it is a first principle; for it 
is for the sake of this that we all do all that we do, and the first 
principle and cause of goods is, we claim, something prized and 
divine. 



13 

Since happiness is an activity of soul in accordance with perfect 
virtue, we must consider the nature of virtue; for perhaps we 
shall thus see better the nature of happiness. The true student 
of politics, too, is thought to have studied virtue above all 
things; for he wishes to make his fellow citizens good and 
obedient to the laws. As an example of this we have the 
lawgivers of the Cretans and the Spartans, and any others of the 
kind that there may have been. And if this inquiry belongs to 
political science, clearly the pursuit of it will be in accordance 



2557 



with our original plan. But clearly the virtue we must study is 
human virtue; for the good we were seeking was human good 
and the happiness human happiness. By human virtue we 
mean not that of the body but that of the soul; and happiness 
also we call an activity of soul. But if this is so, clearly the 
student of politics must know somehow the facts about soul, as 
the man who is to heal the eyes or the body as a whole must 
know about the eyes or the body; and all the more since politics 
is more prized and better than medicine; but even among 
doctors the best educated spend much labour on acquiring 
knowledge of the body. The student of politics, then, must study 
the soul, and must study it with these objects in view, and do so 
just to the extent which is sufficient for the questions we are 
discussing; for further precision is perhaps something more 
laborious than our purposes require. 

Some things are said about it, adequately enough, even in the 
discussions outside our school, and we must use these; e.g. that 
one element in the soul is irrational and one has a rational 
principle. Whether these are separated as the parts of the body 
or of anything divisible are, or are distinct by definition but by 
nature inseparable, like convex and concave in the 
circumference of a circle, does not affect the present question. 

Of the irrational element one division seems to be widely 
distributed, and vegetative in its nature, I mean that which 
causes nutrition and growth; for it is this kind of power of the 
soul that one must assign to all nurslings and to embryos, and 
this same power to fullgrown creatures; this is more reasonable 
than to assign some different power to them. Now the 
excellence of this seems to be common to all species and not 
specifically human; for this part or faculty seems to function 
most in sleep, while goodness and badness are least manifest in 
sleep (whence comes the saying that the happy are not better 
off than the wretched for half their lives; and this happens 



2558 



naturally enough, since sleep is an inactivity of the soul in that 
respect in which it is called good or bad), unless perhaps to a 
small extent some of the movements actually penetrate to the 
soul, and in this respect the dreams of good men are better than 
those of ordinary people. Enough of this subject, however; let us 
leave the nutritive faculty alone, since it has by its nature no 
share in human excellence. 

There seems to be also another irrational element in the soul- 
one which in a sense, however, shares in a rational principle. For 
we praise the rational principle of the continent man and of the 
incontinent, and the part of their soul that has such a principle, 
since it urges them aright and towards the best objects; but 
there is found in them also another element naturally opposed 
to the rational principle, which fights against and resists that 
principle. For exactly as paralysed limbs when we intend to 
move them to the right turn on the contrary to the left, so is it 
with the soul; the impulses of incontinent people move in 
contrary directions. But while in the body we see that which 
moves astray, in the soul we do not. No doubt, however, we 
must none the less suppose that in the soul too there is 
something contrary to the rational principle, resisting and 
opposing it. In what sense it is distinct from the other elements 
does not concern us. Now even this seems to have a share in a 
rational principle, as we said; at any rate in the continent man it 
obeys the rational principle and presumably in the temperate 
and brave man it is still more obedient; for in him it speaks, on 
all matters, with the same voice as the rational principle. 

Therefore the irrational element also appears to be two-fold. For 
the vegetative element in no way shares in a rational principle, 
but the appetitive and in general the desiring element in a 
sense shares in it, in so far as it listens to and obeys it; this is 
the sense in which we speak of 'taking account' of one's father 
or one's friends, not that in which we speak of 'accounting for a 



2559 



mathematical property. That the irrational element is in some 
sense persuaded by a rational principle is indicated also by the 
giving of advice and by all reproof and exhortation. And if this 
element also must be said to have a rational principle, that 
which has a rational principle (as well as that which has not) 
will be twofold, one subdivision having it in the strict sense and 
in itself, and the other having a tendency to obey as one does 
one's father. 

Virtue too is distinguished into kinds in accordance with this 
difference; for we say that some of the virtues are intellectual 
and others moral, philosophic wisdom and understanding and 
practical wisdom being intellectual, liberality and temperance 
moral. For in speaking about a man's character we do not say 
that he is wise or has understanding but that he is good- 
tempered or temperate; yet we praise the wise man also with 
respect to his state of mind; and of states of mind we call those 
which merit praise virtues. 



Book II 



Virtue, then, being of two kinds, intellectual and moral, 
intellectual virtue in the main owes both its birth and its growth 
to teaching (for which reason it requires experience and time), 
while moral virtue comes about as a result of habit, whence also 
its name (ethike) is one that is formed by a slight variation from 



2560 



the word ethos (habit). From this it is also plain that none of the 
moral virtues arises in us by nature; for nothing that exists by 
nature can form a habit contrary to its nature. For instance the 
stone which by nature moves downwards cannot be habituated 
to move upwards, not even if one tries to train it by throwing it 
up ten thousand times; nor can fire be habituated to move 
downwards, nor can anything else that by nature behaves in 
one way be trained to behave in another. Neither by nature, 
then, nor contrary to nature do the virtues arise in us; rather we 
are adapted by nature to receive them, and are made perfect by 
habit. 

Again, of all the things that come to us by nature we first 
acquire the potentiality and later exhibit the activity (this is 
plain in the case of the senses; for it was not by often seeing or 
often hearing that we got these senses, but on the contrary we 
had them before we used them, and did not come to have them 
by using them); but the virtues we get by first exercising them, 
as also happens in the case of the arts as well. For the things we 
have to learn before we can do them, we learn by doing them, 
e.g. men become builders by building and lyreplayers by playing 
the lyre; so too we become just by doing just acts, temperate by 
doing temperate acts, brave by doing brave acts. 

This is confirmed by what happens in states; for legislators 
make the citizens good by forming habits in them, and this is 
the wish of every legislator, and those who do not effect it miss 
their mark, and it is in this that a good constitution differs from 
a bad one. 

Again, it is from the same causes and by the same means that 
every virtue is both produced and destroyed, and similarly every 
art; for it is from playing the lyre that both good and bad lyre- 
players are produced. And the corresponding statement is true 
of builders and of all the rest; men will be good or bad builders 



2561 



as a result of building well or badly. For if this were not so, there 
would have been no need of a teacher, but all men would have 
been born good or bad at their craft. This, then, is the case with 
the virtues also; by doing the acts that we do in our transactions 
with other men we become just or unjust, and by doing the acts 
that we do in the presence of danger, and being habituated to 
feel fear or confidence, we become brave or cowardly. The same 
is true of appetites and feelings of anger; some men become 
temperate and good-tempered, others self-indulgent and 
irascible, by behaving in one way or the other in the appropriate 
circumstances. Thus, in one word, states of character arise out 
of like activities. This is why the activities we exhibit must be of 
a certain kind; it is because the states of character correspond 
to the differences between these. It makes no small difference, 
then, whether we form habits of one kind or of another from 
our very youth; it makes a very great difference, or rather all the 
difference. 



Since, then, the present inquiry does not aim at theoretical 
knowledge like the others (for we are inquiring not in order to 
know what virtue is, but in order to become good, since 
otherwise our inquiry would have been of no use), we must 
examine the nature of actions, namely how we ought to do 
them; for these determine also the nature of the states of 
character that are produced, as we have said. Now, that we must 
act according to the right rule is a common principle and must 
be assumed - it will be discussed later, i.e. both what the right 
rule is, and how it is related to the other virtues. But this must 
be agreed upon beforehand, that the whole account of matters 
of conduct must be given in outline and not precisely, as we 



2562 



said at the very beginning that the accounts we demand must 
be in accordance with the subject-matter; matters concerned 
with conduct and questions of what is good for us have no 
fixity, any more than matters of health. The general account 
being of this nature, the account of particular cases is yet more 
lacking in exactness; for they do not fall under any art or 
precept but the agents themselves must in each case consider 
what is appropriate to the occasion, as happens also in the art 
of medicine or of navigation. 

But though our present account is of this nature we must give 
what help we can. First, then, let us consider this, that it is the 
nature of such things to be destroyed by defect and excess, as 
we see in the case of strength and of health (for to gain light on 
things imperceptible we must use the evidence of sensible 
things); both excessive and defective exercise destroys the 
strength, and similarly drink or food which is above or below a 
certain amount destroys the health, while that which is 
proportionate both produces and increases and preserves it. So 
too is it, then, in the case of temperance and courage and the 
other virtues. For the man who flies from and fears everything 
and does not stand his ground against anything becomes a 
coward, and the man who fears nothing at all but goes to meet 
every danger becomes rash; and similarly the man who 
indulges in every pleasure and abstains from none becomes 
self-indulgent, while the man who shuns every pleasure, as 
boors do, becomes in a way insensible; temperance and courage, 
then, are destroyed by excess and defect, and preserved by the 
mean. 

But not only are the sources and causes of their origination and 
growth the same as those of their destruction, but also the 
sphere of their actualization will be the same; for this is also 
true of the things which are more evident to sense, e.g. of 
strength; it is produced by taking much food and undergoing 



2563 



much exertion, and it is the strong man that will be most able to 
do these things. So too is it with the virtues; by abstaining from 
pleasures we become temperate, and it is when we have 
become so that we are most able to abstain from them; and 
similarly too in the case of courage; for by being habituated to 
despise things that are terrible and to stand our ground against 
them we become brave, and it is when we have become so that 
we shall be most able to stand our ground against them. 



We must take as a sign of states of character the pleasure or 
pain that ensues on acts; for the man who abstains from bodily 
pleasures and delights in this very fact is temperate, while the 
man who is annoyed at it is self-indulgent, and he who stands 
his ground against things that are terrible and delights in this or 
at least is not pained is brave, while the man who is pained is a 
coward. For moral excellence is concerned with pleasures and 
pains; it is on account of the pleasure that we do bad things, 
and on account of the pain that we abstain from noble ones. 
Hence we ought to have been brought up in a particular way 
from our very youth, as Plato says, so as both to delight in and 
to be pained by the things that we ought; for this is the right 
education. 

Again, if the virtues are concerned with actions and passions, 
and every passion and every action is accompanied by pleasure 
and pain, for this reason also virtue will be concerned with 
pleasures and pains. This is indicated also by the fact that 
punishment is inflicted by these means; for it is a kind of cure, 
and it is the nature of cures to be effected by contraries. 



2564 



Again, as we said but lately, every state of soul has a nature 
relative to and concerned with the kind of things by which it 
tends to be made worse or better; but it is by reason of 
pleasures and pains that men become bad, by pursuing and 
avoiding these - either the pleasures and pains they ought not 
or when they ought not or as they ought not, or by going wrong 
in one of the other similar ways that may be distinguished. 
Hence men even define the virtues as certain states of 
impassivity and rest; not well, however, because they speak 
absolutely, and do not say 'as one ought' and 'as one ought not' 
and 'when one ought or ought not', and the other things that 
may be added. We assume, then, that this kind of excellence 
tends to do what is best with regard to pleasures and pains, and 
vice does the contrary. 

The following facts also may show us that virtue and vice are 
concerned with these same things. There being three objects of 
choice and three of avoidance, the noble, the advantageous, the 
pleasant, and their contraries, the base, the injurious, the 
painful, about all of these the good man tends to go right and 
the bad man to go wrong, and especially about pleasure; for this 
is common to the animals, and also it accompanies all objects 
of choice; for even the noble and the advantageous appear 
pleasant. 

Again, it has grown up with us all from our infancy; this is why 
it is difficult to rub off this passion, engrained as it is in our life. 
And we measure even our actions, some of us more and others 
less, by the rule of pleasure and pain. For this reason, then, our 
whole inquiry must be about these; for to feel delight and pain 
rightly or wrongly has no small effect on our actions. 

Again, it is harder to fight with pleasure than with anger, to use 
Heraclitus' phrase', but both art and virtue are always 
concerned with what is harder; for even the good is better when 



2565 



it is harder. Therefore for this reason also the whole concern 
both of virtue and of political science is with pleasures and 
pains; for the man who uses these well will be good, he who 
uses them badly bad. 

That virtue, then, is concerned with pleasures and pains, and 
that by the acts from which it arises it is both increased and, if 
they are done differently, destroyed, and that the acts from 
which it arose are those in which it actualizes itself - let this be 
taken as said. 



The question might be asked,; what we mean by saying that we 
must become just by doing just acts, and temperate by doing 
temperate acts; for if men do just and temperate acts, they are 
already just and temperate, exactly as, if they do what is in 
accordance with the laws of grammar and of music, they are 
grammarians and musicians. 

Or is this not true even of the arts? It is possible to do 
something that is in accordance with the laws of grammar, 
either by chance or at the suggestion of another. A man will be a 
grammarian, then, only when he has both done something 
grammatical and done it grammatically; and this means doing 
it in accordance with the grammatical knowledge in himself. 

Again, the case of the arts and that of the virtues are not 
similar; for the products of the arts have their goodness in 
themselves, so that it is enough that they should have a certain 
character, but if the acts that are in accordance with the virtues 
have themselves a certain character it does not follow that they 
are done justly or temperately. The agent also must be in a 



2566 



certain condition when he does them; in the first place he must 
have knowledge, secondly he must choose the acts, and choose 
them for their own sakes, and thirdly his action must proceed 
from a firm and unchangeable character. These are not 
reckoned in as conditions of the possession of the arts, except 
the bare knowledge; but as a condition of the possession of the 
virtues knowledge has little or no weight, while the other 
conditions count not for a little but for everything, i.e. the very 
conditions which result from often doing just and temperate 
acts. 

Actions, then, are called just and temperate when they are such 
as the just or the temperate man would do; but it is not the man 
who does these that is just and temperate, but the man who 
also does them as just and temperate men do them. It is well 
said, then, that it is by doing just acts that the just man is 
produced, and by doing temperate acts the temperate man; 
without doing these no one would have even a prospect of 
becoming good. 

But most people do not do these, but take refuge in theory and 
think they are being philosophers and will become good in this 
way, behaving somewhat like patients who listen attentively to 
their doctors, but do none of the things they are ordered to do. 
As the latter will not be made well in body by such a course of 
treatment, the former will not be made well in soul by such a 
course of philosophy. 



Next we must consider what virtue is. Since things that are 
found in the soul are of three kinds - passions, faculties, states 
of character, virtue must be one of these. By passions I mean 



2567 



appetite, anger, fear, confidence, envy, joy, friendly feeling, 
hatred, longing, emulation, pity, and in general the feelings that 
are accompanied by pleasure or pain; by faculties the things in 
virtue of which we are said to be capable of feeling these, e.g. of 
becoming angry or being pained or feeling pity; by states of 
character the things in virtue of which we stand well or badly 
with reference to the passions, e.g. with reference to anger we 
stand badly if we feel it violently or too weakly, and well if we 
feel it moderately; and similarly with reference to the other 
passions. 

Now neither the virtues nor the vices are passions, because we 
are not called good or bad on the ground of our passions, but 
are so called on the ground of our virtues and our vices, and 
because we are neither praised nor blamed for our passions (for 
the man who feels fear or anger is not praised, nor is the man 
who simply feels anger blamed, but the man who feels it in a 
certain way), but for our virtues and our vices we are praised or 
blamed. 

Again, we feel anger and fear without choice, but the virtues are 
modes of choice or involve choice. Further, in respect of the 
passions we are said to be moved, but in respect of the virtues 
and the vices we are said not to be moved but to be disposed in 
a particular way. 

For these reasons also they are not faculties; for we are neither 
called good nor bad, nor praised nor blamed, for the simple 
capacity of feeling the passions; again, we have the faculties by 
nature, but we are not made good or bad by nature; we have 
spoken of this before. If, then, the virtues are neither passions 
nor faculties, all that remains is that they should be states of 
character. 

Thus we have stated what virtue is in respect of its genus. 



2568 



We must, however, not only describe virtue as a state of 
character, but also say what sort of state it is. We may remark, 
then, that every virtue or excellence both brings into good 
condition the thing of which it is the excellence and makes the 
work of that thing be done well; e.g. the excellence of the eye 
makes both the eye and its work good; for it is by the excellence 
of the eye that we see well. Similarly the excellence of the horse 
makes a horse both good in itself and good at running and at 
carrying its rider and at awaiting the attack of the enemy. 
Therefore, if this is true in every case, the virtue of man also will 
be the state of character which makes a man good and which 
makes him do his own work well. 

How this is to happen we have stated already, but it will be 
made plain also by the following consideration of the specific 
nature of virtue. In everything that is continuous and divisible it 
is possible to take more, less, or an equal amount, and that 
either in terms of the thing itself or relatively to us; and the 
equal is an intermediate between excess and defect. By the 
intermediate in the object I mean that which is equidistant 
from each of the extremes, which is one and the same for all 
men; by the intermediate relatively to us that which is neither 
too much nor too little - and this is not one, nor the same for 
all. For instance, if ten is many and two is few, six is the 
intermediate, taken in terms of the object; for it exceeds and is 
exceeded by an equal amount; this is intermediate according to 
arithmetical proportion. But the intermediate relatively to us is 
not to be taken so; if ten pounds are too much for a particular 
person to eat and two too little, it does not follow that the 
trainer will order six pounds; for this also is perhaps too much 



2569 



for the person who is to take it, or too little - too little for Milo, 
too much for the beginner in athletic exercises. The same is true 
of running and wrestling. Thus a master of any art avoids 
excess and defect, but seeks the intermediate and chooses this 
- the intermediate not in the object but relatively to us. 

If it is thus, then, that every art does its work well - by looking 
to the intermediate and judgling its works by this standard (so 
that we often say of good works of art that it is not possible 
either to take away or to add anything, implying that excess and 
defect destroy the goodness of works of art, while the mean 
preserves it; and good artists, as we say, look to this in their 
work), and if, further, virtue is more exact and better than any 
art, as nature also is, then virtue must have the quality of 
aiming at the intermediate. I mean moral virtue; for it is this 
that is concerned with passions and actions, and in these there 
is excess, defect, and the intermediate. For instance, both fear 
and confidence and appetite and anger and pity and in general 
pleasure and pain may be felt both too much and too little, and 
in both cases not well; but to feel them at the right times, with 
reference to the right objects, towards the right people, with the 
right motive, and in the right way, is what is both intermediate 
and best, and this is characteristic of virtue. Similarly with 
regard to actions also there is excess, defect, and the 
intermediate. Now virtue is concerned with passions and 
actions, in which excess is a form of failure, and so is defect, 
while the intermediate is praised and is a form of success; and 
being praised and being successful are both characteristics of 
virtue. Therefore virtue is a kind of mean, since, as we have 
seen, it aims at what is intermediate. 

Again, it is possible to fail in many ways (for evil belongs to the 
class of the unlimited, as the Pythagoreans conjectured, and 
good to that of the limited), while to succeed is possible only in 
one way (for which reason also one is easy and the other 



2570 



difficult - to miss the mark easy, to hit it difficult); for these 
reasons also, then, excess and defect are characteristic of vice, 
and the mean of virtue; 

For men are good in but one way, but bad in many. 

Virtue, then, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying 
in a mean, i.e. the mean relative to us, this being determined by 
a rational principle, and by that principle by which the man of 
practical wisdom would determine it. Now it is a mean between 
two vices, that which depends on excess and that which 
depends on defect; and again it is a mean because the vices 
respectively fall short of or exceed what is right in both 
passions and actions, while virtue both finds and chooses that 
which is intermediate. Hence in respect of its substance and the 
definition which states its essence virtue is a mean, with regard 
to what is best and right an extreme. 

But not every action nor every passion admits of a mean; for 
some have names that already imply badness, e.g. spite, 
shamelessness, envy, and in the case of actions adultery, theft, 
murder; for all of these and suchlike things imply by their 
names that they are themselves bad, and not the excesses or 
deficiencies of them. It is not possible, then, ever to be right 
with regard to them; one must always be wrong. Nor does 
goodness or badness with regard to such things depend on 
committing adultery with the right woman, at the right time, 
and in the right way, but simply to do any of them is to go 
wrong. It would be equally absurd, then, to expect that in 
unjust, cowardly, and voluptuous action there should be a 
mean, an excess, and a deficiency; for at that rate there would 
be a mean of excess and of deficiency, an excess of excess, and 
a deficiency of deficiency. But as there is no excess and 
deficiency of temperance and courage because what is 
intermediate is in a sense an extreme, so too of the actions we 



2571 



have mentioned there is no mean nor any excess and 
deficiency, but however they are done they are wrong; for in 
general there is neither a mean of excess and deficiency, nor 
excess and deficiency of a mean. 



We must, however, not only make this general statement, but 
also apply it to the individual facts. For among statements about 
conduct those which are general apply more widely, but those 
which are particular are more genuine, since conduct has to do 
with individual cases, and our statements must harmonize with 
the facts in these cases. We may take these cases from our table. 
With regard to feelings of fear and confidence courage is the 
mean; of the people who exceed, he who exceeds in 
fearlessness has no name (many of the states have no name), 
while the man who exceeds in confidence is rash, and he who 
exceeds in fear and falls short in confidence is a coward. With 
regard to pleasures and pains - not all of them, and not so much 
with regard to the pains - the mean is temperance, the excess 
self-indulgence. Persons deficient with regard to the pleasures 
are not often found; hence such persons also have received no 
name. But let us call them 'insensible'. 

With regard to giving and taking of money the mean is liberality, 
the excess and the defect prodigality and meanness. In these 
actions people exceed and fall short in contrary ways; the 
prodigal exceeds in spending and falls short in taking, while the 
mean man exceeds in taking and falls short in spending. (At 
present we are giving a mere outline or summary, and are 
satisfied with this; later these states will be more exactly 
determined.) With regard to money there are also other 



2572 



dispositions - a mean, magnificence (for the magnificent man 
differs from the liberal man; the former deals with large sums, 
the latter with small ones), an excess, tastelessness and 
vulgarity, and a deficiency, niggardliness; these differ from the 
states opposed to liberality, and the mode of their difference 
will be stated later. With regard to honour and dishonour the 
mean is proper pride, the excess is known as a sort of 'empty 
vanity', and the deficiency is undue humility; and as we said 
liberality was related to magnificence, differing from it by 
dealing with small sums, so there is a state similarly related to 
proper pride, being concerned with small honours while that is 
concerned with great. For it is possible to desire honour as one 
ought, and more than one ought, and less, and the man who 
exceeds in his desires is called ambitious, the man who falls 
short unambitious, while the intermediate person has no name. 
The dispositions also are nameless, except that that of the 
ambitious man is called ambition. Hence the people who are at 
the extremes lay claim to the middle place; and we ourselves 
sometimes call the intermediate person ambitious and 
sometimes unambitious, and sometimes praise the ambitious 
man and sometimes the unambitious. The reason of our doing 
this will be stated in what follows; but now let us speak of the 
remaining states according to the method which has been 
indicated. 

With regard to anger also there is an excess, a deficiency, and a 
mean. Although they can scarcely be said to have names, yet 
since we call the intermediate person good-tempered let us call 
the mean good temper; of the persons at the extremes let the 
one who exceeds be called irascible, and his vice irascibility, and 
the man who falls short an inirascible sort of person, and the 
deficiency inirascibility. 

There are also three other means, which have a certain likeness 
to one another, but differ from one another: for they are all 



2573 



concerned with intercourse in words and actions, but differ in 
that one is concerned with truth in this sphere, the other two 
with pleasantness; and of this one kind is exhibited in giving 
amusement, the other in all the circumstances of life. We must 
therefore speak of these too, that we may the better see that in 
all things the mean is praise-worthy, and the extremes neither 
praiseworthy nor right, but worthy of blame. Now most of these 
states also have no names, but we must try, as in the other 
cases, to invent names ourselves so that we may be clear and 
easy to follow. With regard to truth, then, the intermediate is a 
truthful sort of person and the mean may be called 
truthfulness, while the pretence which exaggerates is 
boastfulness and the person characterized by it a boaster, and 
that which understates is mock modesty and the person 
characterized by it mock-modest. With regard to pleasantness in 
the giving of amusement the intermediate person is ready- 
witted and the disposition ready wit, the excess is buffoonery 
and the person characterized by it a buffoon, while the man 
who falls short is a sort of boor and his state is boorishness. 
With regard to the remaining kind of pleasantness, that which 
is exhibited in life in general, the man who is pleasant in the 
right way is friendly and the mean is friendliness, while the 
man who exceeds is an obsequious person if he has no end in 
view, a flatterer if he is aiming at his own advantage, and the 
man who falls short and is unpleasant in all circumstances is a 
quarrelsome and surly sort of person. 

There are also means in the passions and concerned with the 
passions; since shame is not a virtue, and yet praise is extended 
to the modest man. For even in these matters one man is said 
to be intermediate, and another to exceed, as for instance the 
bashful man who is ashamed of everything; while he who falls 
short or is not ashamed of anything at all is shameless, and the 
intermediate person is modest. Righteous indignation is a mean 
between envy and spite, and these states are concerned with 



2574 



the pain and pleasure that are felt at the fortunes of our 
neighbours; the man who is characterized by righteous 
indignation is pained at undeserved good fortune, the envious 
man, going beyond him, is pained at all good fortune, and the 
spiteful man falls so far short of being pained that he even 
rejoices. But these states there will be an opportunity of 
describing elsewhere; with regard to justice, since it has not one 
simple meaning, we shall, after describing the other states, 
distinguish its two kinds and say how each of them is a mean; 
and similarly we shall treat also of the rational virtues. 



8 

There are three kinds of disposition, then, two of them vices, 
involving excess and deficiency respectively, and one a virtue, 
viz. the mean, and all are in a sense opposed to all; for the 
extreme states are contrary both to the intermediate state and 
to each other, and the intermediate to the extremes; as the 
equal is greater relatively to the less, less relatively to the 
greater, so the middle states are excessive relatively to the 
deficiencies, deficient relatively to the excesses, both in 
passions and in actions. For the brave man appears rash 
relatively to the coward, and cowardly relatively to the rash 
man; and similarly the temperate man appears self-indulgent 
relatively to the insensible man, insensible relatively to the self- 
indulgent, and the liberal man prodigal relatively to the mean 
man, mean relatively to the prodigal. Hence also the people at 
the extremes push the intermediate man each over to the other, 
and the brave man is called rash by the coward, cowardly by the 
rash man, and correspondingly in the other cases. 



2575 



These states being thus opposed to one another, the greatest 
contrariety is that of the extremes to each other, rather than to 
the intermediate; for these are further from each other than 
from the intermediate, as the great is further from the small 
and the small from the great than both are from the equal. 
Again, to the intermediate some extremes show a certain 
likeness, as that of rashness to courage and that of prodigality 
to liberality; but the extremes show the greatest unlikeness to 
each other; now contraries are defined as the things that are 
furthest from each other, so that things that are further apart 
are more contrary. 

To the mean in some cases the deficiency, in some the excess is 
more opposed; e.g. it is not rashness, which is an excess, but 
cowardice, which is a deficiency, that is more opposed to 
courage, and not insensibility, which is a deficiency, but self- 
indulgence, which is an excess, that is more opposed to 
temperance. This happens from two reasons, one being drawn 
from the thing itself; for because one extreme is nearer and 
liker to the intermediate, we oppose not this but rather its 
contrary to the intermediate. E.g. since rashness is thought liker 
and nearer to courage, and cowardice more unlike, we oppose 
rather the latter to courage; for things that are further from the 
intermediate are thought more contrary to it. This, then, is one 
cause, drawn from the thing itself; another is drawn from 
ourselves; for the things to which we ourselves more naturally 
tend seem more contrary to the intermediate. For instance, we 
ourselves tend more naturally to pleasures, and hence are more 
easily carried away towards self-indulgence than towards 
propriety. We describe as contrary to the mean, then, rather the 
directions in which we more often go to great lengths; and 
therefore self-indulgence, which is an excess, is the more 
contrary to temperance. 



2576 



That moral virtue is a mean, then, and in what sense it is so, 
and that it is a mean between two vices, the one involving 
excess, the other deficiency, and that it is such because its 
character is to aim at what is intermediate in passions and in 
actions, has been sufficiently stated. Hence also it is no easy 
task to be good. For in everything it is no easy task to find the 
middle, e.g. to find the middle of a circle is not for every one but 
for him who knows; so, too, any one can get angry - that is easy 
- or give or spend money; but to do this to the right person, to 
the right extent, at the right time, with the right motive, and in 
the right way, that is not for every one, nor is it easy; wherefore 
goodness is both rare and laudable and noble. 

Hence he who aims at the intermediate must first depart from 
what is the more contrary to it, as Calypso advises: 

Hold the ship out beyond that surf and spray. 

For of the extremes one is more erroneous, one less so; 
therefore, since to hit the mean is hard in the extreme, we must 
as a second best, as people say, take the least of the evils; and 
this will be done best in the way we describe. But we must 
consider the things towards which we ourselves also are easily 
carried away; for some of us tend to one thing, some to another; 
and this will be recognizable from the pleasure and the pain we 
feel. We must drag ourselves away to the contrary extreme; for 
we shall get into the intermediate state by drawing well away 
from error, as people do in straightening sticks that are bent. 

Now in everything the pleasant or pleasure is most to be 
guarded against; for we do not judge it impartially. We ought, 
then, to feel towards pleasure as the elders of the people felt 
towards Helen, and in all circumstances repeat their saying; for 



2577 



if we dismiss pleasure thus we are less likely to go astray. It is by 
doing this, then, (to sum the matter up) that we shall best be 
able to hit the mean. 

But this is no doubt difficult, and especially in individual cases; 
for or is not easy to determine both how and with whom and on 
what provocation and how long one should be angry; for we too 
sometimes praise those who fall short and call them good- 
tempered, but sometimes we praise those who get angry and 
call them manly. The man, however, who deviates little from 
goodness is not blamed, whether he do so in the direction of the 
more or of the less, but only the man who deviates more widely; 
for he does not fail to be noticed. But up to what point and to 
what extent a man must deviate before he becomes 
blameworthy it is not easy to determine by reasoning, any more 
than anything else that is perceived by the senses; such things 
depend on particular facts, and the decision rests with 
perception. So much, then, is plain, that the intermediate state 
is in all things to be praised, but that we must incline 
sometimes towards the excess, sometimes towards the 
deficiency; for so shall we most easily hit the mean and what is 
right. 



2578 



Book III 



Since virtue is concerned with passions and actions, and on 
voluntary passions and actions praise and blame are bestowed, 
on those that are involuntary pardon, and sometimes also pity, 
to distinguish the voluntary and the involuntary is presumably 
necessary for those who are studying the nature of virtue, and 
useful also for legislators with a view to the assigning both of 
honours and of punishments. Those things, then, are thought- 
involuntary, which take place under compulsion or owing to 
ignorance; and that is compulsory of which the moving 
principle is outside, being a principle in which nothing is 
contributed by the person who is acting or is feeling the 
passion, e.g. if he were to be carried somewhere by a wind, or by 
men who had him in their power. 

But with regard to the things that are done from fear of greater 
evils or for some noble object (e.g. if a tyrant were to order one 
to do something base, having one's parents and children in his 
power, and if one did the action they were to be saved, but 
otherwise would be put to death), it may be debated whether 
such actions are involuntary or voluntary. Something of the sort 
happens also with regard to the throwing of goods overboard in 
a storm; for in the abstract no one throws goods away 
voluntarily, but on condition of its securing the safety of himself 
and his crew any sensible man does so. Such actions, then, are 
mixed, but are more like voluntary actions; for they are worthy 
of choice at the time when they are done, and the end of an 
action is relative to the occasion. Both the terms, then, 
'voluntary' and 'involuntary', must be used with reference to the 



2579 



moment of action. Now the man acts voluntarily; for the 
principle that moves the instrumental parts of the body in such 
actions is in him, and the things of which the moving principle 
is in a man himself are in his power to do or not to do. Such 
actions, therefore, are voluntary, but in the abstract perhaps 
involuntary; for no one would choose any such act in itself. 

For such actions men are sometimes even praised, when they 
endure something base or painful in return for great and noble 
objects gained; in the opposite case they are blamed, since to 
endure the greatest indignities for no noble end or for a trifling 
end is the mark of an inferior person. On some actions praise 
indeed is not bestowed, but pardon is, when one does what he 
ought not under pressure which overstrains human nature and 
which no one could withstand. But some acts, perhaps, we 
cannot be forced to do, but ought rather to face death after the 
most fearful sufferings; for the things that 'forced' Euripides 
Alcmaeon to slay his mother seem absurd. It is difficult 
sometimes to determine what should be chosen at what cost, 
and what should be endured in return for what gain, and yet 
more difficult to abide by our decisions; for as a rule what is 
expected is painful, and what we are forced to do is base, 
whence praise and blame are bestowed on those who have been 
compelled or have not. 

What sort of acts, then, should be called compulsory? We 
answer that without qualification actions are so when the cause 
is in the external circumstances and the agent contributes 
nothing. But the things that in themselves are involuntary, but 
now and in return for these gains are worthy of choice, and 
whose moving principle is in the agent, are in themselves 
involuntary, but now and in return for these gains voluntary. 
They are more like voluntary acts; for actions are in the class of 
particulars, and the particular acts here are voluntary. What sort 



2580 



of things are to be chosen, and in return for what, it is not easy 
to state; for there are many differences in the particular cases. 

But if some one were to say that pleasant and noble objects 
have a compelling power, forcing us from without, all acts 
would be for him compulsory; for it is for these objects that all 
men do everything they do. And those who act under 
compulsion and unwillingly act with pain, but those who do 
acts for their pleasantness and nobility do them with pleasure; 
it is absurd to make external circumstances responsible, and 
not oneself, as being easily caught by such attractions, and to 
make oneself responsible for noble acts but the pleasant objects 
responsible for base acts. The compulsory, then, seems to be 
that whose moving principle is outside, the person compelled 
contributing nothing. 

Everything that is done by reason of ignorance is not voluntary; 
it is only what produces pain and repentance that is 
involuntary. For the man who has done something owing to 
ignorance, and feels not the least vexation at his action, has not 
acted voluntarily, since he did not know what he was doing, nor 
yet involuntarily, since he is not pained. Of people, then, who 
act by reason of ignorance he who repents is thought an 
involuntary agent, and the man who does not repent may, since 
he is different, be called a not voluntary agent; for, since he 
differs from the other, it is better that he should have a name of 
his own. 

Acting by reason of ignorance seems also to be different from 
acting in ignorance; for the man who is drunk or in a rage is 
thought to act as a result not of ignorance but of one of the 
causes mentioned, yet not knowingly but in ignorance. 

Now every wicked man is ignorant of what he ought to do and 
what he ought to abstain from, and it is by reason of error of 
this kind that men become unjust and in general bad; but the 



2581 



term 'involuntary' tends to be used not if a man is ignorant of 
what is to his advantage - for it is not mistaken purpose that 
causes involuntary action (it leads rather to wickedness), nor 
ignorance of the universal (for that men are blamed), but 
ignorance of particulars, i.e. of the circumstances of the action 
and the objects with which it is concerned. For it is on these 
that both pity and pardon depend, since the person who is 
ignorant of any of these acts involuntarily. 

Perhaps it is just as well, therefore, to determine their nature 
and number. A man may be ignorant, then, of who he is, what 
he is doing, what or whom he is acting on, and sometimes also 
what (e.g. what instrument) he is doing it with, and to what end 
(e.g. he may think his act will conduce to some one's safety), 
and how he is doing it (e.g. whether gently or violently). Now of 
all of these no one could be ignorant unless he were mad, and 
evidently also he could not be ignorant of the agent; for how 
could he not know himself? But of what he is doing a man 
might be ignorant, as for instance people say 'it slipped out of 
their mouths as they were speaking', or 'they did not know it 
was a secret', as Aeschylus said of the mysteries, or a man 
might say he 'let it go off when he merely wanted to show its 
working', as the man did with the catapult. Again, one might 
think one's son was an enemy, as Merope did, or that a pointed 
spear had a button on it, or that a stone was pumicestone; or 
one might give a man a draught to save him, and really kill him; 
or one might want to touch a man, as people do in sparring, and 
really wound him. The ignorance may relate, then, to any of 
these things, i.e. of the circumstances of the action, and the 
man who was ignorant of any of these is thought to have acted 
involuntarily, and especially if he was ignorant on the most 
important points; and these are thought to be the 
circumstances of the action and its end. Further, the doing of an 
act that is called involuntary in virtue of ignorance of this sort 
must be painful and involve repentance. 



2582 



Since that which is done under compulsion or by reason of 
ignorance is involuntary, the voluntary would seem to be that of 
which the moving principle is in the agent himself, he being 
aware of the particular circumstances of the action. Presumably 
acts done by reason of anger or appetite are not rightly called 
involuntary. For in the first place, on that showing none of the 
other animals will act voluntarily, nor will children; and 
secondly, is it meant that we do not do voluntarily any of the 
acts that are due to appetite or anger, or that we do the noble 
acts voluntarily and the base acts involuntarily? Is not this 
absurd, when one and the same thing is the cause? But it would 
surely be odd to describe as involuntary the things one ought to 
desire; and we ought both to be angry at certain things and to 
have an appetite for certain things, e.g. for health and for 
learning. Also what is involuntary is thought to be painful, but 
what is in accordance with appetite is thought to be pleasant. 
Again, what is the difference in respect of involuntariness 
between errors committed upon calculation and those 
committed in anger? Both are to be avoided, but the irrational 
passions are thought not less human than reason is, and 
therefore also the actions which proceed from anger or appetite 
are the man's actions. It would be odd, then, to treat them as 
involuntary. 



Both the voluntary and the involuntary having been delimited, 
we must next discuss choice; for it is thought to be most closely 
bound up with virtue and to discriminate characters better than 
actions do. 



2583 



Choice, then, seems to be voluntary, but not the same thing as 
the voluntary; the latter extends more widely For both children 
and the lower animals share in voluntary action, but not in 
choice, and acts done on the spur of the moment we describe as 
voluntary, but not as chosen. 

Those who say it is appetite or anger or wish or a kind of 
opinion do not seem to be right. For choice is not common to 
irrational creatures as well, but appetite and anger are. Again, 
the incontinent man acts with appetite, but not with choice; 
while the continent man on the contrary acts with choice, but 
not with appetite. Again, appetite is contrary to choice, but not 
appetite to appetite. Again, appetite relates to the pleasant and 
the painful, choice neither to the painful nor to the pleasant. 

Still less is it anger; for acts due to anger are thought to be less 
than any others objects of choice. 

But neither is it wish, though it seems near to it; for choice 
cannot relate to impossibles, and if any one said he chose them 
he would be thought silly; but there may be a wish even for 
impossibles, e.g. for immortality. And wish may relate to things 
that could in no way be brought about by one's own efforts, e.g. 
that a particular actor or athlete should win in a competition; 
but no one chooses such things, but only the things that he 
thinks could be brought about by his own efforts. Again, wish 
relates rather to the end, choice to the means; for instance, we 
wish to be healthy, but we choose the acts which will make us 
healthy, and we wish to be happy and say we do, but we cannot 
well say we choose to be so; for, in general, choice seems to 
relate to the things that are in our own power. 

For this reason, too, it cannot be opinion; for opinion is thought 
to relate to all kinds of things, no less to eternal things and 
impossible things than to things in our own power; and it is 



2584 



distinguished by its falsity or truth, not by its badness or 
goodness, while choice is distinguished rather by these. 

Now with opinion in general perhaps no one even says it is 
identical. But it is not identical even with any kind of opinion; 
for by choosing what is good or bad we are men of a certain 
character, which we are not by holding certain opinions. And we 
choose to get or avoid something good or bad, but we have 
opinions about what a thing is or whom it is good for or how it 
is good for him; we can hardly be said to opine to get or avoid 
anything. And choice is praised for being related to the right 
object rather than for being rightly related to it, opinion for 
being truly related to its object. And we choose what we best 
know to be good, but we opine what we do not quite know; and 
it is not the same people that are thought to make the best 
choices and to have the best opinions, but some are thought to 
have fairly good opinions, but by reason of vice to choose what 
they should not. If opinion precedes choice or accompanies it, 
that makes no difference; for it is not this that we are 
considering, but whether it is identical with some kind of 
opinion. 

What, then, or what kind of thing is it, since it is none of the 
things we have mentioned? It seems to be voluntary, but not all 
that is voluntary to be an object of choice. Is it, then, what has 
been decided on by previous deliberation? At any rate choice 
involves a rational principle and thought. Even the name seems 
to suggest that it is what is chosen before other things. 



Do we deliberate about everything, and is everything a possible 
subject of deliberation, or is deliberation impossible about some 



2585 



things? We ought presumably to call not what a fool or a 
madman would deliberate about, but what a sensible man 
would deliberate about, a subject of deliberation. Now about 
eternal things no one deliberates, e.g. about the material 
universe or the incommensurability of the diagonal and the side 
of a square. But no more do we deliberate about the things that 
involve movement but always happen in the same way, whether 
of necessity or by nature or from any other cause, e.g. the 
solstices and the risings of the stars; nor about things that 
happen now in one way, now in another, e.g. droughts and 
rains; nor about chance events, like the finding of treasure. But 
we do not deliberate even about all human affairs; for instance, 
no Spartan deliberates about the best constitution for the 
Scythians. For none of these things can be brought about by our 
own efforts. 

We deliberate about things that are in our power and can be 
done; and these are in fact what is left. For nature, necessity, 
and chance are thought to be causes, and also reason and 
everything that depends on man. Now every class of men 
deliberates about the things that can be done by their own 
efforts. And in the case of exact and self-contained sciences 
there is no deliberation, e.g. about the letters of the alphabet 
(for we have no doubt how they should be written); but the 
things that are brought about by our own efforts, but not always 
in the same way, are the things about which we deliberate, e.g. 
questions of medical treatment or of money-making. And we do 
so more in the case of the art of navigation than in that of 
gymnastics, inasmuch as it has been less exactly worked out, 
and again about other things in the same ratio, and more also in 
the case of the arts than in that of the sciences; for we have 
more doubt about the former. Deliberation is concerned with 
things that happen in a certain way for the most part, but in 
which the event is obscure, and with things in which it is 
indeterminate. We call in others to aid us in deliberation on 



2586 



important questions, distrusting ourselves as not being equal to 
deciding. 

We deliberate not about ends but about means. For a doctor 
does not deliberate whether he shall heal, nor an orator 
whether he shall persuade, nor a statesman whether he shall 
produce law and order, nor does any one else deliberate about 
his end. They assume the end and consider how and by what 
means it is to be attained; and if it seems to be produced by 
several means they consider by which it is most easily and best 
produced, while if it is achieved by one only they consider how 
it will be achieved by this and by what means this will be 
achieved, till they come to the first cause, which in the order of 
discovery is last. For the person who deliberates seems to 
investigate and analyse in the way described as though he were 
analysing a geometrical construction (not all investigation 
appears to be deliberation - for instance mathematical 
investigations - but all deliberation is investigation), and what is 
last in the order of analysis seems to be first in the order of 
becoming. And if we come on an impossibility, we give up the 
search, e.g. if we need money and this cannot be got; but if a 
thing appears possible we try to do it. By 'possible' things I 
mean things that might be brought about by our own efforts; 
and these in a sense include things that can be brought about 
by the efforts of our friends, since the moving principle is in 
ourselves. The subject of investigation is sometimes the 
instruments, sometimes the use of them; and similarly in the 
other cases - sometimes the means, sometimes the mode of 
using it or the means of bringing it about. It seems, then, as has 
been said, that man is a moving principle of actions; now 
deliberation is about the things to be done by the agent himself, 
and actions are for the sake of things other than themselves. 
For the end cannot be a subject of deliberation, but only the 
means; nor indeed can the particular facts be a subject of it, as 
whether this is bread or has been baked as it should; for these 



2587 



are matters of perception. If we are to be always deliberating, we 
shall have to go on to infinity. 

The same thing is deliberated upon and is chosen, except that 
the object of choice is already determinate, since it is that which 
has been decided upon as a result of deliberation that is the 
object of choice. For every one ceases to inquire how he is to act 
when he has brought the moving principle back to himself and 
to the ruling part of himself; for this is what chooses. This is 
plain also from the ancient constitutions, which Homer 
represented; for the kings announced their choices to the 
people. The object of choice being one of the things in our own 
power which is desired after deliberation, choice will be 
deliberate desire of things in our own power; for when we have 
decided as a result of deliberation, we desire in accordance with 
our deliberation. 

We may take it, then, that we have described choice in outline, 
and stated the nature of its objects and the fact that it is 
concerned with means. 



That wish is for the end has already been stated; some think it 
is for the good, others for the apparent good. Now those who 
say that the good is the object of wish must admit in 
consequence that that which the man who does not choose 
aright wishes for is not an object of wish (for if it is to be so, it 
must also be good; but it was, if it so happened, bad); while 
those who say the apparent good is the object of wish must 
admit that there is no natural object of wish, but only what 
seems good to each man. Now different things appear good to 
different people, and, if it so happens, even contrary things. 



2588 



If these consequences are unpleasing, are we to say that 
absolutely and in truth the good is the object of wish, but for 
each person the apparent good; that that which is in truth an 
object of wish is an object of wish to the good man, while any 
chance thing may be so the bad man, as in the case of bodies 
also the things that are in truth wholesome are wholesome for 
bodies which are in good condition, while for those that are 
diseased other things are wholesome - or bitter or sweet or hot 
or heavy, and so on; since the good man judges each class of 
things rightly, and in each the truth appears to him? For each 
state of character has its own ideas of the noble and the 
pleasant, and perhaps the good man differs from others most 
by seeing the truth in each class of things, being as it were the 
norm and measure of them. In most things the error seems to 
be due to pleasure; for it appears a good when it is not. We 
therefore choose the pleasant as a good, and avoid pain as an 
evil. 



The end, then, being what we wish for, the means what we 
deliberate about and choose, actions concerning means must be 
according to choice and voluntary. Now the exercise of the 
virtues is concerned with means. Therefore virtue also is in our 
own power, and so too vice. For where it is in our power to act it 
is also in our power not to act, and vice versa; so that, if to act, 
where this is noble, is in our power, not to act, which will be 
base, will also be in our power, and if not to act, where this is 
noble, is in our power, to act, which will be base, will also be in 
our power. Now if it is in our power to do noble or base acts, and 
likewise in our power not to do them, and this was what being 



2589 



good or bad meant, then it is in our power to be virtuous or 
vicious. 

The saying that 'no one is voluntarily wicked nor involuntarily 
happy' seems to be partly false and partly true; for no one is 
involuntarily happy, but wickedness is voluntary. Or else we 
shall have to dispute what has just been said, at any rate, and 
deny that man is a moving principle or begetter of his actions as 
of children. But if these facts are evident and we cannot refer 
actions to moving principles other than those in ourselves, the 
acts whose moving principles are in us must themselves also be 
in our power and voluntary. 

Witness seems to be borne to this both by individuals in their 
private capacity and by legislators themselves; for these punish 
and take vengeance on those who do wicked acts (unless they 
have acted under compulsion or as a result of ignorance for 
which they are not themselves responsible), while they honour 
those who do noble acts, as though they meant to encourage 
the latter and deter the former. But no one is encouraged to do 
the things that are neither in our power nor voluntary; it is 
assumed that there is no gain in being persuaded not to be hot 
or in pain or hungry or the like, since we shall experience these 
feelings none the less. Indeed, we punish a man for his very 
ignorance, if he is thought responsible for the ignorance, as 
when penalties are doubled in the case of drunkenness; for the 
moving principle is in the man himself, since he had the power 
of not getting drunk and his getting drunk was the cause of his 
ignorance. And we punish those who are ignorant of anything in 
the laws that they ought to know and that is not difficult, and 
so too in the case of anything else that they are thought to be 
ignorant of through carelessness; we assume that it is in their 
power not to be ignorant, since they have the power of taking 
care. 



2590 



But perhaps a man is the kind of man not to take care. Still they 
are themselves by their slack lives responsible for becoming 
men of that kind, and men make themselves responsible for 
being unjust or self-indulgent, in the one case by cheating and 
in the other by spending their time in drinking bouts and the 
like; for it is activities exercised on particular objects that make 
the corresponding character. This is plain from the case of 
people training for any contest or action; they practise the 
activity the whole time. Now not to know that it is from the 
exercise of activities on particular objects that states of 
character are produced is the mark of a thoroughly senseless 
person. Again, it is irrational to suppose that a man who acts 
unjustly does not wish to be unjust or a man who acts self- 
indulgently to be self-indulgent. But if without being ignorant a 
man does the things which will make him unjust, he will be 
unjust voluntarily. Yet it does not follow that if he wishes he will 
cease to be unjust and will be just. For neither does the man 
who is ill become well on those terms. We may suppose a case 
in which he is ill voluntarily, through living incontinently and 
disobeying his doctors. In that case it was then open to him not 
to be ill, but not now, when he has thrown away his chance, just 
as when you have let a stone go it is too late to recover it; but 
yet it was in your power to throw it, since the moving principle 
was in you. So, too, to the unjust and to the self-indulgent man 
it was open at the beginning not to become men of this kind, 
and so they are unjust and selfindulgent voluntarily; but now 
that they have become so it is not possible for them not to be 
so. 

But not only are the vices of the soul voluntary, but those of the 
body also for some men, whom we accordingly blame; while no 
one blames those who are ugly by nature, we blame those who 
are so owing to want of exercise and care. So it is, too, with 
respect to weakness and infirmity; no one would reproach a 
man blind from birth or by disease or from a blow, but rather 



2591 



pity him, while every one would blame a man who was blind 
from drunkenness or some other form of self-indulgence. Of 
vices of the body, then, those in our own power are blamed, 
those not in our power are not. And if this be so, in the other 
cases also the vices that are blamed must be in our own power. 

Now some one may say that all men desire the apparent good, 
but have no control over the appearance, but the end appears to 
each man in a form answering to his character. We reply that if 
each man is somehow responsible for his state of mind, he will 
also be himself somehow responsible for the appearance; but if 
not, no one is responsible for his own evildoing, but every one 
does evil acts through ignorance of the end, thinking that by 
these he will get what is best, and the aiming at the end is not 
self-chosen but one must be born with an eye, as it were, by 
which to judge rightly and choose what is truly good, and he is 
well endowed by nature who is well endowed with this. For it is 
what is greatest and most noble, and what we cannot get or 
learn from another, but must have just such as it was when 
given us at birth, and to be well and nobly endowed with this 
will be perfect and true excellence of natural endowment. If this 
is true, then, how will virtue be more voluntary than vice? To 
both men alike, the good and the bad, the end appears and is 
fixed by nature or however it may be, and it is by referring 
everything else to this that men do whatever they do. 

Whether, then, it is not by nature that the end appears to each 
man such as it does appear, but something also depends on 
him, or the end is natural but because the good man adopts the 
means voluntarily virtue is voluntary, vice also will be none the 
less voluntary; for in the case of the bad man there is equally 
present that which depends on himself in his actions even if 
not in his end. If, then, as is asserted, the virtues are voluntary 
(for we are ourselves somehow partly responsible for our states 
of character, and it is by being persons of a certain kind that we 



2592 



assume the end to be so and so), the vices also will be 
voluntary; for the same is true of them. 

With regard to the virtues in general we have stated their genus 
in outline, viz. that they are means and that they are states of 
character, and that they tend, and by their own nature, to the 
doing of the acts by which they are produced, and that they are 
in our power and voluntary, and act as the right rule prescribes. 
But actions and states of character are not voluntary in the 
same way; for we are masters of our actions from the beginning 
right to the end, if we know the particular facts, but though we 
control the beginning of our states of character the gradual 
progress is not obvious any more than it is in illnesses; because 
it was in our power, however, to act in this way or not in this 
way, therefore the states are voluntary. 

Let us take up the several virtues, however, and say which they 
are and what sort of things they are concerned with and how 
they are concerned with them; at the same time it will become 
plain how many they are. And first let us speak of courage. 



That it is a mean with regard to feelings of fear and confidence 
has already been made evident; and plainly the things we fear 
are terrible things, and these are, to speak without qualification, 
evils; for which reason people even define fear as expectation of 
evil. Now we fear all evils, e.g. disgrace, poverty, disease, 
friendlessness, death, but the brave man is not thought to be 
concerned with all; for to fear some things is even right and 
noble, and it is base not to fear them - e.g. disgrace; he who 
fears this is good and modest, and he who does not is 
shameless. He is, however, by some people called brave, by a 



2593 



transference of the word to a new meaning; for he has in him 
something which is like the brave man, since the brave man 
also is a fearless person. Poverty and disease we perhaps ought 
not to fear, nor in general the things that do not proceed from 
vice and are not due to a man himself. But not even the man 
who is fearless of these is brave. Yet we apply the word to him 
also in virtue of a similarity; for some who in the dangers of war 
are cowards are liberal and are confident in face of the loss of 
money. Nor is a man a coward if he fears insult to his wife and 
children or envy or anything of the kind; nor brave if he is 
confident when he is about to be flogged. With what sort of 
terrible things, then, is the brave man concerned? Surely with 
the greatest; for no one is more likely than he to stand his 
ground against what is awe-inspiring. Now death is the most 
terrible of all things; for it is the end, and nothing is thought to 
be any longer either good or bad for the dead. But the brave 
man would not seem to be concerned even with death in all 
circumstances, e.g. at sea or in disease. In what circumstances, 
then? Surely in the noblest. Now such deaths are those in battle; 
for these take place in the greatest and noblest danger. And 
these are correspondingly honoured in city-states and at the 
courts of monarchs. Properly, then, he will be called brave who 
is fearless in face of a noble death, and of all emergencies that 
involve death; and the emergencies of war are in the highest 
degree of this kind. Yet at sea also, and in disease, the brave 
man is fearless, but not in the same way as the seaman; for he 
has given up hope of safety, and is disliking the thought of 
death in this shape, while they are hopeful because of their 
experience. At the same time, we show courage in situations 
where there is the opportunity of showing prowess or where 
death is noble; but in these forms of death neither of these 
conditions is fulfilled. 



2594 



What is terrible is not the same for all men; but we say there are 
things terrible even beyond human strength. These, then, are 
terrible to every one - at least to every sensible man; but the 
terrible things that are not beyond human strength differ in 
magnitude and degree, and so too do the things that inspire 
confidence. Now the brave man is as dauntless as man may be. 
Therefore, while he will fear even the things that are not beyond 
human strength, he will face them as he ought and as the rule 
directs, for honour's sake; for this is the end of virtue. But it is 
possible to fear these more, or less, and again to fear things that 
are not terrible as if they were. Of the faults that are committed 
one consists in fearing what one should not, another in fearing 
as we should not, another in fearing when we should not, and 
so on; and so too with respect to the things that inspire 
confidence. The man, then, who faces and who fears the right 
things and from the right motive, in the right way and from the 
right time, and who feels confidence under the corresponding 
conditions, is brave; for the brave man feels and acts according 
to the merits of the case and in whatever way the rule directs. 
Now the end of every activity is conformity to the 
corresponding state of character. This is true, therefore, of the 
brave man as well as of others. But courage is noble. Therefore 
the end also is noble; for each thing is defined by its end. 
Therefore it is for a noble end that the brave man endures and 
acts as courage directs. 

Of those who go to excess he who exceeds in fearlessness has 
no name (we have said previously that many states of character 
have no names), but he would be a sort of madman or 
insensible person if he feared nothing, neither earthquakes nor 
the waves, as they say the Celts do not; while the man who 



2595 



exceeds in confidence about what really is terrible is rash. The 
rash man, however, is also thought to be boastful and only a 
pretender to courage; at all events, as the brave man is with 
regard to what is terrible, so the rash man wishes to appear; and 
so he imitates him in situations where he can. Hence also most 
of them are a mixture of rashness and cowardice; for, while in 
these situations they display confidence, they do not hold their 
ground against what is really terrible. The man who exceeds in 
fear is a coward; for he fears both what he ought not and as he 
ought not, and all the similar characterizations attach to him. 
He is lacking also in confidence; but he is more conspicuous for 
his excess of fear in painful situations. The coward, then, is a 
despairing sort of person; for he fears everything. The brave 
man, on the other hand, has the opposite disposition; for 
confidence is the mark of a hopeful disposition. The coward, the 
rash man, and the brave man, then, are concerned with the 
same objects but are differently disposed towards them; for the 
first two exceed and fall short, while the third holds the middle, 
which is the right, position; and rash men are precipitate, and 
wish for dangers beforehand but draw back when they are in 
them, while brave men are keen in the moment of action, but 
quiet beforehand. 

As we have said, then, courage is a mean with respect to things 
that inspire confidence or fear, in the circumstances that have 
been stated; and it chooses or endures things because it is noble 
to do so, or because it is base not to do so. But to die to escape 
from poverty or love or anything painful is not the mark of a 
brave man, but rather of a coward; for it is softness to fly from 
what is troublesome, and such a man endures death not 
because it is noble but to fly from evil. 



2596 



8 

Courage, then, is something of this sort, but the name is also 
applied to five other kinds. 

First comes the courage of the citizen-soldier; for this is most 
like true courage. Citizen-soldiers seem to face dangers because 
of the penalties imposed by the laws and the reproaches they 
would otherwise incur, and because of the honours they win by 
such action; and therefore those peoples seem to be bravest 
among whom cowards are held in dishonour and brave men in 
honour. This is the kind of courage that Homer depicts, e.g. in 
Diomede and in Hector: 

First will Polydamas be to heap reproach on me then; and 

For Hector one day 'mid the Trojans shall utter his vaulting 
harangue: 

Afraid was Tydeides, and fled from my face. 

This kind of courage is most like to that which we described 
earlier, because it is due to virtue; for it is due to shame and to 
desire of a noble object (i.e. honour) and avoidance of disgrace, 
which is ignoble. One might rank in the same class even those 
who are compelled by their rulers; but they are inferior, 
inasmuch as they do what they do not from shame but from 
fear, and to avoid not what is disgraceful but what is painful; for 
their masters compel them, as Hector does: 

But if I shall spy any dastard that cowers far from the fight, 

Vainly will such an one hope to escape from the dogs. 

And those who give them their posts, and beat them if they 
retreat, do the same, and so do those who draw them up with 
trenches or something of the sort behind them; all of these 



2597 



apply compulsion. But one ought to be brave not under 
compulsion but because it is noble to be so. 

(2) Experience with regard to particular facts is also thought to 
be courage; this is indeed the reason why Socrates thought 
courage was knowledge. Other people exhibit this quality in 
other dangers, and professional soldiers exhibit it in the 
dangers of war; for there seem to be many empty alarms in war, 
of which these have had the most comprehensive experience; 
therefore they seem brave, because the others do not know the 
nature of the facts. Again, their experience makes them most 
capable in attack and in defence, since they can use their arms 
and have the kind that are likely to be best both for attack and 
for defence; therefore they fight like armed men against 
unarmed or like trained athletes against amateurs; for in such 
contests too it is not the bravest men that fight best, but those 
who are strongest and have their bodies in the best condition. 
Professional soldiers turn cowards, however, when the danger 
puts too great a strain on them and they are inferior in numbers 
and equipment; for they are the first to fly, while citizen-forces 
die at their posts, as in fact happened at the temple of Hermes. 
For to the latter flight is disgraceful and death is preferable to 
safety on those terms; while the former from the very beginning 
faced the danger on the assumption that they were stronger, 
and when they know the facts they fly, fearing death more than 
disgrace; but the brave man is not that sort of person. 

(3) Passion also is sometimes reckoned as courage; those who 
act from passion, like wild beasts rushing at those who have 
wounded them, are thought to be brave, because brave men also 
are passionate; for passion above all things is eager to rush on 
danger, and hence Homer's 'put strength into his passion' and 
'aroused their spirit and passion and 'hard he breathed panting' 
and 'his blood boiled'. For all such expressions seem to indicate 
the stirring and onset of passion. Now brave men act for 



2598 



honour's sake, but passion aids them; while wild beasts act 
under the influence of pain; for they attack because they have 
been wounded or because they are afraid, since if they are in a 
forest they do not come near one. Thus they are not brave 
because, driven by pain and passion, they rush on danger 
without foreseeing any of the perils, since at that rate even 
asses would be brave when they are hungry; for blows will not 
drive them from their food; and lust also makes adulterers do 
many daring things. (Those creatures are not brave, then, which 
are driven on to danger by pain or passion.) The 'courage' that is 
due to passion seems to be the most natural, and to be courage 
if choice and motive be added. 

Men, then, as well as beasts, suffer pain when they are angry, 
and are pleased when they exact their revenge; those who fight 
for these reasons, however, are pugnacious but not brave; for 
they do not act for honour's sake nor as the rule directs, but 
from strength of feeling; they have, however, something akin to 
courage. 

(4) Nor are sanguine people brave; for they are confident in 
danger only because they have conquered often and against 
many foes. Yet they closely resemble brave men, because both 
are confident; but brave men are confident for the reasons 
stated earlier, while these are so because they think they are the 
strongest and can suffer nothing. (Drunken men also behave in 
this way; they become sanguine). When their adventures do not 
succeed, however, they run away; but it was the mark of a brave 
man to face things that are, and seem, terrible for a man, 
because it is noble to do so and disgraceful not to do so. Hence 
also it is thought the mark of a braver man to be fearless and 
undisturbed in sudden alarms than to be so in those that are 
foreseen; for it must have proceeded more from a state of 
character, because less from preparation; acts that are foreseen 



2599 



may be chosen by calculation and rule, but sudden actions must 
be in accordance with one's state of character. 

(5) People who are ignorant of the danger also appear brave, and 
they are not far removed from those of a sanguine temper, but 
are inferior inasmuch as they have no self-reliance while these 
have. Hence also the sanguine hold their ground for a time; but 
those who have been deceived about the facts fly if they know 
or suspect that these are different from what they supposed, as 
happened to the Argives when they fell in with the Spartans 
and took them for Sicyonians. 

We have, then, described the character both of brave men and of 
those who are thought to be brave. 



Though courage is concerned with feelings of confidence and of 
fear, it is not concerned with both alike, but more with the 
things that inspire fear; for he who is undisturbed in face of 
these and bears himself as he should towards these is more 
truly brave than the man who does so towards the things that 
inspire confidence. It is for facing what is painful, then, as has 
been said, that men are called brave. Hence also courage 
involves pain, and is justly praised; for it is harder to face what 
is painful than to abstain from what is pleasant. 

Yet the end which courage sets before it would seem to be 
pleasant, but to be concealed by the attending circumstances, as 
happens also in athletic contests; for the end at which boxers 
aim is pleasant - the crown and the honours - but the blows 
they take are distressing to flesh and blood, and painful, and so 
is their whole exertion; and because the blows and the 



2600 



exertions are many the end, which is but small, appears to have 
nothing pleasant in it. And so, if the case of courage is similar, 
death and wounds will be painful to the brave man and against 
his will, but he will face them because it is noble to do so or 
because it is base not to do so. And the more he is possessed of 
virtue in its entirety and the happier he is, the more he will be 
pained at the thought of death; for life is best worth living for 
such a man, and he is knowingly losing the greatest goods, and 
this is painful. But he is none the less brave, and perhaps all the 
more so, because he chooses noble deeds of war at that cost. It 
is not the case, then, with all the virtues that the exercise of 
them is pleasant, except in so far as it reaches its end. But it is 
quite possible that the best soldiers may be not men of this sort 
but those who are less brave but have no other good; for these 
are ready to face danger, and they sell their life for trifling gains. 

So much, then, for courage; it is not difficult to grasp its nature 
in outline, at any rate, from what has been said. 



10 

After courage let us speak of temperance; for these seem to be 
the virtues of the irrational parts. We have said that temperance 
is a mean with regard to pleasures (for it is less, and not in the 
same way, concerned with pains); self-indulgence also is 
manifested in the same sphere. Now, therefore, let us determine 
with what sort of pleasures they are concerned. We may assume 
the distinction between bodily pleasures and those of the soul, 
such as love of honour and love of learning; for the lover of each 
of these delights in that of which he is a lover, the body being in 
no way affected, but rather the mind; but men who are 
concerned with such pleasures are called neither temperate nor 



2601 



self-indulgent. Nor, again, are those who are concerned with the 
other pleasures that are not bodily; for those who are fond of 
hearing and telling stories and who spend their days on 
anything that turns up are called gossips, but not self-indulgent, 
nor are those who are pained at the loss of money or of friends. 

Temperance must be concerned with bodily pleasures, but not 
all even of these; for those who delight in objects of vision, such 
as colours and shapes and painting, are called neither 
temperate nor self-indulgent; yet it would seem possible to 
delight even in these either as one should or to excess or to a 
deficient degree. 

And so too is it with objects of hearing; no one calls those who 
delight extravagantly in music or acting self-indulgent, nor 
those who do so as they ought temperate. 

Nor do we apply these names to those who delight in odour, 
unless it be incidentally; we do not call those self-indulgent 
who delight in the odour of apples or roses or incense, but 
rather those who delight in the odour of unguents or of dainty 
dishes; for self-indulgent people delight in these because these 
remind them of the objects of their appetite. And one may see 
even other people, when they are hungry, delighting in the 
smell of food; but to delight in this kind of thing is the mark of 
the self-indulgent man; for these are objects of appetite to him. 

Nor is there in animals other than man any pleasure connected 
with these senses, except incidentally. For dogs do not delight in 
the scent of hares, but in the eating of them, but the scent told 
them the hares were there; nor does the lion delight in the 
lowing of the ox, but in eating it; but he perceived by the lowing 
that it was near, and therefore appears to delight in the lowing; 
and similarly he does not delight because he sees 'a stag or a 
wild goat', but because he is going to make a meal of it. 
Temperance and self-indulgence, however, are concerned with 



2602 



the kind of pleasures that the other animals share in, which 
therefore appear slavish and brutish; these are touch and taste. 
But even of taste they appear to make little or no use; for the 
business of taste is the discriminating of flavours, which is done 
by winetasters and people who season dishes; but they hardly 
take pleasure in making these discriminations, or at least self- 
indulgent people do not, but in the actual enjoyment, which in 
all cases comes through touch, both in the case of food and in 
that of drink and in that of sexual intercourse. This is why a 
certain gourmand prayed that his throat might become longer 
than a crane's, implying that it was the contact that he took 
pleasure in. Thus the sense with which self-indulgence is 
connected is the most widely shared of the senses; and self- 
indulgence would seem to be justly a matter of reproach, 
because it attaches to us not as men but as animals. To delight 
in such things, then, and to love them above all others, is 
brutish. For even of the pleasures of touch the most liberal have 
been eliminated, e.g. those produced in the gymnasium by 
rubbing and by the consequent heat; for the contact 
characteristic of the self-indulgent man does not affect the 
whole body but only certain parts. 



11 

Of the appetites some seem to be common, others to be 
peculiar to individuals and acquired; e.g. the appetite for food is 
natural, since every one who is without it craves for food or 
drink, and sometimes for both, and for love also (as Homer says) 
if he is young and lusty; but not every one craves for this or that 
kind of nourishment or love, nor for the same things. Hence 
such craving appears to be our very own. Yet it has of course 
something natural about it; for different things are pleasant to 



2603 



different kinds of people, and some things are more pleasant to 
every one than chance objects. Now in the natural appetites few 
go wrong, and only in one direction, that of excess; for to eat or 
drink whatever offers itself till one is surfeited is to exceed the 
natural amount, since natural appetite is the replenishment of 
one's deficiency. Hence these people are called belly-gods, this 
implying that they fill their belly beyond what is right. It is 
people of entirely slavish character that become like this. But 
with regard to the pleasures peculiar to individuals many 
people go wrong and in many ways. For while the people who 
are 'fond of so and so' are so called because they delight either 
in the wrong things, or more than most people do, or in the 
wrong way, the self-indulgent exceed in all three ways; they 
both delight in some things that they ought not to delight in 
(since they are hateful), and if one ought to delight in some of 
the things they delight in, they do so more than one ought and 
than most men do. 

Plainly, then, excess with regard to pleasures is self-indulgence 
and is culpable; with regard to pains one is not, as in the case of 
courage, called temperate for facing them or self-indulgent for 
not doing so, but the selfindulgent man is so called because he 
is pained more than he ought at not getting pleasant things 
(even his pain being caused by pleasure), and the temperate 
man is so called because he is not pained at the absence of 
what is pleasant and at his abstinence from it. 

The self-indulgent man, then, craves for all pleasant things or 
those that are most pleasant, and is led by his appetite to 
choose these at the cost of everything else; hence he is pained 
both when he fails to get them and when he is merely craving 
for them (for appetite involves pain); but it seems absurd to be 
pained for the sake of pleasure. People who fall short with 
regard to pleasures and delight in them less than they should 
are hardly found; for such insensibility is not human. Even the 



2604 



other animals distinguish different kinds of food and enjoy 
some and not others; and if there is any one who finds nothing 
pleasant and nothing more attractive than anything else, he 
must be something quite different from a man; this sort of 
person has not received a name because he hardly occurs. The 
temperate man occupies a middle position with regard to these 
objects. For he neither enjoys the things that the self-indulgent 
man enjoys most - but rather dislikes them - nor in general the 
things that he should not, nor anything of this sort to excess, 
nor does he feel pain or craving when they are absent, or does 
so only to a moderate degree, and not more than he should, nor 
when he should not, and so on; but the things that, being 
pleasant, make for health or for good condition, he will desire 
moderately and as he should, and also other pleasant things if 
they are not hindrances to these ends, or contrary to what is 
noble, or beyond his means. For he who neglects these 
conditions loves such pleasures more than they are worth, but 
the temperate man is not that sort of person, but the sort of 
person that the right rule prescribes. 



12 

Self-indulgence is more like a voluntary state than cowardice. 
For the former is actuated by pleasure, the latter by pain, of 
which the one is to be chosen and the other to be avoided; and 
pain upsets and destroys the nature of the person who feels it, 
while pleasure does nothing of the sort. Therefore self- 
indulgence is more voluntary. Hence also it is more a matter of 
reproach; for it is easier to become accustomed to its objects, 
since there are many things of this sort in life, and the process 
of habituation to them is free from danger, while with terrible 
objects the reverse is the case. But cowardice would seem to be 



2605 



voluntary in a different degree from its particular 
manifestations; for it is itself painless, but in these we are upset 
by pain, so that we even throw down our arms and disgrace 
ourselves in other ways; hence our acts are even thought to be 
done under compulsion. For the self-indulgent man, on the 
other hand, the particular acts are voluntary (for he does them 
with craving and desire), but the whole state is less so; for no 
one craves to be self-indulgent. 

The name self-indulgence is applied also to childish faults; for 
they bear a certain resemblance to what we have been 
considering. Which is called after which, makes no difference to 
our present purpose; plainly, however, the later is called after 
the earlier. The transference of the name seems not a bad one; 
for that which desires what is base and which develops quickly 
ought to be kept in a chastened condition, and these 
characteristics belong above all to appetite and to the child, 
since children in fact live at the beck and call of appetite, and it 
is in them that the desire for what is pleasant is strongest. If, 
then, it is not going to be obedient and subject to the ruling 
principle, it will go to great lengths; for in an irrational being the 
desire for pleasure is insatiable even if it tries every source of 
gratification, and the exercise of appetite increases its innate 
force, and if appetites are strong and violent they even expel the 
power of calculation. Hence they should be moderate and few, 
and should in no way oppose the rational principle - and this is 
what we call an obedient and chastened state - and as the child 
should live according to the direction of his tutor, so the 
appetitive element should live according to rational principle. 
Hence the appetitive element in a temperate man should 
harmonize with the rational principle; for the noble is the mark 
at which both aim, and the temperate man craves for the things 
be ought, as he ought, as when he ought; and when he ought; 
and this is what rational principle directs. 



2606 



Here we conclude our account of temperance. 



Book IV 



Let us speak next of liberality. It seems to be the mean with 
regard to wealth; for the liberal man is praised not in respect of 
military matters, nor of those in respect of which the temrate 
man is praised, nor of judicial decisions, but with regard to the 
giving and taking of wealth, and especially in respect of giving. 
Now by 'wealth' we mean all the things whose value is 
measured by money. Further, prodigality and meanness are 
excesses and defects with regard to wealth; and meanness we 
always impute to those who care more than they ought for 
wealth, but we sometimes apply the word 'prodigality' in a 
complex sense; for we call those men prodigals who are 
incontinent and spend money on self-indulgence. Hence also 
they are thought the poorest characters; for they combine more 
vices than one. Therefore the application of the word to them is 
not its proper use; for a 'prodigal' means a man who has a 
single evil quality, that of wasting his substance; since a 
prodigal is one who is being ruined by his own fault, and the 
wasting of substance is thought to be a sort of ruining of 
oneself, life being held to depend on possession of substance. 

This, then, is the sense in which we take the word 'prodigality'. 
Now the things that have a use may be used either well or 



2607 



badly; and riches is a useful thing; and everything is used best 
by the man who has the virtue concerned with it; riches, 
therefore, will be used best by the man who has the virtue 
concerned with wealth; and this is the liberal man. Now 
spending and giving seem to be the using of wealth; taking and 
keeping rather the possession of it. Hence it is more the mark of 
the liberal man to give to the right people than to take from the 
right sources and not to take from the wrong. For it is more 
characteristic of virtue to do good than to have good done to 
one, and more characteristic to do what is noble than not to do 
what is base; and it is not hard to see that giving implies doing 
good and doing what is noble, and taking implies having good 
done to one or not acting basely. And gratitude is felt towards 
him who gives, not towards him who does not take, and praise 
also is bestowed more on him. It is easier, also, not to take than 
to give; for men are apter to give away their own too little than 
to take what is another's. Givers, too, are called liberal; but those 
who do not take are not praised for liberality but rather for 
justice; while those who take are hardly praised at all. And the 
liberal are almost the most loved of all virtuous characters, 
since they are useful; and this depends on their giving. 

Now virtuous actions are noble and done for the sake of the 
noble. Therefore the liberal man, like other virtuous men, will 
give for the sake of the noble, and rightly; for he will give to the 
right people, the right amounts, and at the right time, with all 
the other qualifications that accompany right giving; and that 
too with pleasure or without pain; for that which is virtuous is 
pleasant or free from pain - least of all will it be painful. But he 
who gives to the wrong people or not for the sake of the noble 
but for some other cause, will be called not liberal but by some 
other name. Nor is he liberal who gives with pain; for he would 
prefer the wealth to the noble act, and this is not characteristic 
of a liberal man. But no more will the liberal man take from 
wrong sources; for such taking is not characteristic of the man 



2608 



who sets no store by wealth. Nor will he be a ready asker; for it 
is not characteristic of a man who confers benefits to accept 
them lightly. But he will take from the right sources, e.g. from 
his own possessions, not as something noble but as a necessity, 
that he may have something to give. Nor will he neglect his own 
property, since he wishes by means of this to help others. And 
he will refrain from giving to anybody and everybody, that he 
may have something to give to the right people, at the right 
time, and where it is noble to do so. It is highly characteristic of 
a liberal man also to go to excess in giving, so that he leaves too 
little for himself; for it is the nature of a liberal man not to look 
to himself. The term 'liberality' is used relatively to a man's 
substance; for liberality resides not in the multitude of the gifts 
but in the state of character of the giver, and this is relative to 
the giver's substance. There is therefore nothing to prevent the 
man who gives less from being the more liberal man, if he has 
less to give those are thought to be more liberal who have not 
made their wealth but inherited it; for in the first place they 
have no experience of want, and secondly all men are fonder of 
their own productions, as are parents and poets. It is not easy 
for the liberal man to be rich, since he is not apt either at taking 
or at keeping, but at giving away, and does not value wealth for 
its own sake but as a means to giving. Hence comes the charge 
that is brought against fortune, that those who deserve riches 
most get it least. But it is not unreasonable that it should turn 
out so; for he cannot have wealth, any more than anything else, 
if he does not take pains to have it. Yet he will not give to the 
wrong people nor at the wrong time, and so on; for he would no 
longer be acting in accordance with liberality, and if he spent on 
these objects he would have nothing to spend on the right 
objects. For, as has been said, he is liberal who spends according 
to his substance and on the right objects; and he who exceeds is 
prodigal. Hence we do not call despots prodigal; for it is thought 
not easy for them to give and spend beyond the amount of their 



2609 



possessions. Liberality, then, being a mean with regard to giving 
and taking of wealth, the liberal man will both give and spend 
the right amounts and on the right objects, alike in small things 
and in great, and that with pleasure; he will also take the right 
amounts and from the right sources. For, the virtue being a 
mean with regard to both, he will do both as he ought; since 
this sort of taking accompanies proper giving, and that which is 
not of this sort is contrary to it, and accordingly the giving and 
taking that accompany each other are present together in the 
same man, while the contrary kinds evidently are not. But if he 
happens to spend in a manner contrary to what is right and 
noble, he will be pained, but moderately and as he ought; for it 
is the mark of virtue both to be pleased and to be pained at the 
right objects and in the right way. Further, the liberal man is 
easy to deal with in money matters; for he can be got the better 
of, since he sets no store by money, and is more annoyed if he 
has not spent something that he ought than pained if he has 
spent something that he ought not, and does not agree with the 
saying of Simonides. 

The prodigal errs in these respects also; for he is neither 
pleased nor pained at the right things or in the right way; this 
will be more evident as we go on. We have said that prodigality 
and meanness are excesses and deficiencies, and in two things, 
in giving and in taking; for we include spending under giving. 
Now prodigality exceeds in giving and not taking, while 
meanness falls short in giving, and exceeds in taking, except in 
small things. 

The characteristics of prodigality are not often combined; for it 
is not easy to give to all if you take from none; private persons 
soon exhaust their substance with giving, and it is to these that 
the name of prodigals is applied - though a man of this sort 
would seem to be in no small degree better than a mean man. 
For he is easily cured both by age and by poverty, and thus he 



2610 



may move towards the middle state. For he has the 
characteristics of the liberal man, since he both gives and 
refrains from taking, though he does neither of these in the 
right manner or well. Therefore if he were brought to do so by 
habituation or in some other way, he would be liberal; for he 
will then give to the right people, and will not take from the 
wrong sources. This is why he is thought to have not a bad 
character; it is not the mark of a wicked or ignoble man to go to 
excess in giving and not taking, but only of a foolish one. The 
man who is prodigal in this way is thought much better than 
the mean man both for the aforesaid reasons and because he 
benefits many while the other benefits no one, not even 
himself. 

But most prodigal people, as has been said, also take from the 
wrong sources, and are in this respect mean. They become apt 
to take because they wish to spend and cannot do this easily; 
for their possessions soon run short. Thus they are forced to 
provide means from some other source. At the same time, 
because they care nothing for honour, they take recklessly and 
from any source; for they have an appetite for giving, and they 
do not mind how or from what source. Hence also their giving is 
not liberal; for it is not noble, nor does it aim at nobility, nor is it 
done in the right way; sometimes they make rich those who 
should be poor, and will give nothing to people of respectable 
character, and much to flatterers or those who provide them 
with some other pleasure. Hence also most of them are self- 
indulgent; for they spend lightly and waste money on their 
indulgences, and incline towards pleasures because they do not 
live with a view to what is noble. 

The prodigal man, then, turns into what we have described if he 
is left untutored, but if he is treated with care he will arrive at 
the intermediate and right state. But meanness is both 
incurable (for old age and every disability is thought to make 



2611 



men mean) and more innate in men than prodigality; for most 
men are fonder of getting money than of giving. It also extends 
widely, and is multiform, since there seem to be many kinds of 
meanness. 

For it consists in two things, deficiency in giving and excess in 
taking, and is not found complete in all men but is sometimes 
divided; some men go to excess in taking, others fall short in 
giving. Those who are called by such names as 'miserly', 'close', 
'stingy', all fall short in giving, but do not covet the possessions 
of others nor wish to get them. In some this is due to a sort of 
honesty and avoidance of what is disgraceful (for some seem, or 
at least profess, to hoard their money for this reason, that they 
may not some day be forced to do something disgraceful; to this 
class belong the cheeseparer and every one of the sort; he is so 
called from his excess of unwillingness to give anything); while 
others again keep their hands off the property of others from 
fear, on the ground that it is not easy, if one takes the property 
of others oneself, to avoid having one's own taken by them; they 
are therefore content neither to take nor to give. 

Others again exceed in respect of taking by taking anything and 
from any source, e.g. those who ply sordid trades, pimps and all 
such people, and those who lend small sums and at high rates. 
For all of these take more than they ought and from wrong 
sources. What is common to them is evidently sordid love of 
gain; they all put up with a bad name for the sake of gain, and 
little gain at that. For those who make great gains but from 
wrong sources, and not the right gains, e.g. despots when they 
sack cities and spoil temples, we do not call mean but rather 
wicked, impious, and unjust. But the gamester and the footpad 
(and the highwayman) belong to the class of the mean, since 
they have a sordid love of gain. For it is for gain that both of 
them ply their craft and endure the disgrace of it, and the one 
faces the greatest dangers for the sake of the booty, while the 



2612 



other makes gain from his friends, to whom he ought to be 
giving. Both, then, since they are willing to make gain from 
wrong sources, are sordid lovers of gain; therefore all such 
forms of taking are mean. 

And it is natural that meanness is described as the contrary of 
liberality; for not only is it a greater evil than prodigality, but 
men err more often in this direction than in the way of 
prodigality as we have described it. 

So much, then, for liberality and the opposed vices. 



It would seem proper to discuss magnificence next. For this also 
seems to be a virtue concerned with wealth; but it does not like 
liberality extend to all the actions that are concerned with 
wealth, but only to those that involve expenditure; and in these 
it surpasses liberality in scale. For, as the name itself suggests, it 
is a fitting expenditure involving largeness of scale. But the 
scale is relative; for the expense of equipping a trireme is not 
the same as that of heading a sacred embassy. It is what is 
fitting, then, in relation to the agent, and to the circumstances 
and the object. The man who in small or middling things 
spends according to the merits of the case is not called 
magnificent (e.g. the man who can say 'many a gift I gave the 
wanderer'), but only the man who does so in great things. For 
the magnificent man is liberal, but the liberal man is not 
necessarily magnificent. The deficiency of this state of character 
is called niggardliness, the excess vulgarity, lack of taste, and 
the like, which do not go to excess in the amount spent on right 
objects, but by showy expenditure in the wrong circumstances 
and the wrong manner; we shall speak of these vices later. 



2613 



The magnificent man is like an artist; for he can see what is 
fitting and spend large sums tastefully. For, as we said at the 
begining, a state of character is determined by its activities and 
by its objects. Now the expenses of the magnificent man are 
large and fitting. Such, therefore, are also his results; for thus 
there will be a great expenditure and one that is fitting to its 
result. Therefore the result should be worthy of the expense, 
and the expense should be worthy of the result, or should even 
exceed it. And the magnificent man will spend such sums for 
honour's sake; for this is common to the virtues. And further he 
will do so gladly and lavishly; for nice calculation is a niggardly 
thing. And he will consider how the result can be made most 
beautiful and most becoming rather than for how much it can 
be produced and how it can be produced most cheaply. It is 
necessary, then, that the magnificent man be also liberal. For 
the liberal man also will spend what he ought and as he ought; 
and it is in these matters that the greatness implied in the 
name of the magnificent man - his bigness, as it were - is 
manifested, since liberality is concerned with these matters; 
and at an equal expense he will produce a more magnificent 
work of art. For a possession and a work of art have not the 
same excellence. The most valuable possession is that which is 
worth most, e.g. gold, but the most valuable work of art is that 
which is great and beautiful (for the contemplation of such a 
work inspires admiration, and so does magnificence); and a 
work has an excellence - viz. magnificence - which involves 
magnitude. Magnificence is an attribute of expenditures of the 
kind which we call honourable, e.g. those connected with the 
gods - votive offerings, buildings, and sacrifices - and similarly 
with any form of religious worship, and all those that are proper 
objects of public-spirited ambition, as when people think they 
ought to equip a chorus or a trireme, or entertain the city, in a 
brilliant way. But in all cases, as has been said, we have regard 
to the agent as well and ask who he is and what means he has; 



2614 



for the expenditure should be worthy of his means, and suit not 
only the result but also the producer. Hence a poor man cannot 
be magnificent, since he has not the means with which to 
spend large sums fittingly; and he who tries is a fool, since he 
spends beyond what can be expected of him and what is proper, 
but it is right expenditure that is virtuous. But great expenditure 
is becoming to those who have suitable means to start with, 
acquired by their own efforts or from ancestors or connexions, 
and to people of high birth or reputation, and so on; for all these 
things bring with them greatness and prestige. Primarily, then, 
the magnificent man is of this sort, and magnificence is shown 
in expenditures of this sort, as has been said; for these are the 
greatest and most honourable. Of private occasions of 
expenditure the most suitable are those that take place once for 
all, e.g. a wedding or anything of the kind, or anything that 
interests the whole city or the people of position in it, and also 
the receiving of foreign guests and the sending of them on their 
way, and gifts and counter-gifts; for the magnificent man 
spends not on himself but on public objects, and gifts bear 
some resemblance to votive offerings. A magnificent man will 
also furnish his house suitably to his wealth (for even a house is 
a sort of public ornament), and will spend by preference on 
those works that are lasting (for these are the most beautiful), 
and on every class of things he will spend what is becoming; for 
the same things are not suitable for gods and for men, nor in a 
temple and in a tomb. And since each expenditure may be great 
of its kind, and what is most magnificent absolutely is great 
expenditure on a great object, but what is magnificent here is 
what is great in these circumstances, and greatness in the work 
differs from greatness in the expense (for the most beautiful 
ball or bottle is magnificent as a gift to a child, but the price of it 
is small and mean), - therefore it is characteristic of the 
magnificent man, whatever kind of result he is producing, to 



2615 



produce it magnificently (for such a result is not easily 
surpassed) and to make it worthy of the expenditure. 

Such, then, is the magnificent man; the man who goes to excess 
and is vulgar exceeds, as has been said, by spending beyond 
what is right. For on small objects of expenditure he spends 
much and displays a tasteless showiness; e.g. he gives a club 
dinner on the scale of a wedding banquet, and when he 
provides the chorus for a comedy he brings them on to the 
stage in purple, as they do at Megara. And all such things he will 
do not for honour's sake but to show off his wealth, and because 
he thinks he is admired for these things, and where he ought to 
spend much he spends little and where little, much. The 
niggardly man on the other hand will fall short in everything, 
and after spending the greatest sums will spoil the beauty of 
the result for a trifle, and whatever he is doing he will hesitate 
and consider how he may spend least, and lament even that, 
and think he is doing everything on a bigger scale than he 
ought. 

These states of character, then, are vices; yet they do not bring 
disgrace because they are neither harmful to one's neighbour 
nor very unseemly. 



Pride seems even from its name to be concerned with great 
things; what sort of great things, is the first question we must 
try to answer. It makes no difference whether we consider the 
state of character or the man characterized by it. Now the man 
is thought to be proud who thinks himself worthy of great 
things, being worthy of them; for he who does so beyond his 
deserts is a fool, but no virtuous man is foolish or silly. The 



2616 



proud man, then, is the man we have described. For he who is 
worthy of little and thinks himself worthy of little is temperate, 
but not proud; for pride implies greatness, as beauty implies a 
goodsized body, and little people may be neat and well- 
proportioned but cannot be beautiful. On the other hand, he 
who thinks himself worthy of great things, being unworthy of 
them, is vain; though not every one who thinks himself worthy 
of more than he really is worthy of in vain. The man who thinks 
himself worthy of worthy of less than he is really worthy of is 
unduly humble, whether his deserts be great or moderate, or his 
deserts be small but his claims yet smaller. And the man whose 
deserts are great would seem most unduly humble; for what 
would he have done if they had been less? The proud man, then, 
is an extreme in respect of the greatness of his claims, but a 
mean in respect of the Tightness of them; for he claims what is 
accordance with his merits, while the others go to excess or fall 
short. 

If, then, he deserves and claims great things, and above all the 
great things, he will be concerned with one thing in particular. 
Desert is relative to external goods; and the greatest of these, 
we should say, is that which we render to the gods, and which 
people of position most aim at, and which is the prize 
appointed for the noblest deeds; and this is honour; that is 
surely the greatest of external goods. Honours and dishonours, 
therefore, are the objects with respect to which the proud man 
is as he should be. And even apart from argument it is with 
honour that proud men appear to be concerned; for it is honour 
that they chiefly claim, but in accordance with their deserts. 
The unduly humble man falls short both in comparison with his 
own merits and in comparison with the proud man's claims. 
The vain man goes to excess in comparison with his own 
merits, but does not exceed the proud man's claims. 



2617 



Now the proud man, since he deserves most, must be good in 
the highest degree; for the better man always deserves more, 
and the best man most. Therefore the truly proud man must be 
good. And greatness in every virtue would seem to be 
characteristic of a proud man. And it would be most 
unbecoming for a proud man to fly from danger, swinging his 
arms by his sides, or to wrong another; for to what end should 
he do disgraceful acts, he to whom nothing is great? If we 
consider him point by point we shall see the utter absurdity of a 
proud man who is not good. Nor, again, would he be worthy of 
honour if he were bad; for honour is the prize of virtue, and it is 
to the good that it is rendered. Pride, then, seems to be a sort of 
crown of the virtues; for it makes them greater, and it is not 
found without them. Therefore it is hard to be truly proud; for it 
is impossible without nobility and goodness of character. It is 
chiefly with honours and dishonours, then, that the proud man 
is concerned; and at honours that are great and conferred by 
good men he will be moderately Pleased, thinking that he is 
coming by his own or even less than his own; for there can be 
no honour that is worthy of perfect virtue, yet he will at any rate 
accept it since they have nothing greater to bestow on him; but 
honour from casual people and on trifling grounds he will 
utterly despise, since it is not this that he deserves, and 
dishonour too, since in his case it cannot be just. In the first 
place, then, as has been said, the proud man is concerned with 
honours; yet he will also bear himself with moderation towards 
wealth and power and all good or evil fortune, whatever may 
befall him, and will be neither over-joyed by good fortune nor 
over-pained by evil. For not even towards honour does he bear 
himself as if it were a very great thing. Power and wealth are 
desirable for the sake of honour (at least those who have them 
wish to get honour by means of them); and for him to whom 
even honour is a little thing the others must be so too. Hence 
proud men are thought to be disdainful. 



2618 



The goods of fortune also are thought to contribute towards 
pride. For men who are well-born are thought worthy of honour, 
and so are those who enjoy power or wealth; for they are in a 
superior position, and everything that has a superiority in 
something good is held in greater honour. Hence even such 
things make men prouder; for they are honoured by some for 
having them; but in truth the good man alone is to be 
honoured; he, however, who has both advantages is thought the 
more worthy of honour. But those who without virtue have such 
goods are neither justified in making great claims nor entitled 
to the name of 'proud'; for these things imply perfect virtue. 
Disdainful and insolent, however, even those who have such 
goods become. For without virtue it is not easy to bear 
gracefully the goods of fortune; and, being unable to bear them, 
and thinking themselves superior to others, they despise others 
and themselves do what they please. They imitate the proud 
man without being like him, and this they do where they can; 
so they do not act virtuously, but they do despise others. For the 
proud man despises justly (since he thinks truly), but the many 
do so at random. 

He does not run into trifling dangers, nor is he fond of danger, 
because he honours few things; but he will face great dangers, 
and when he is in danger he is unsparing of his life, knowing 
that there are conditions on which life is not worth having. And 
he is the sort of man to confer benefits, but he is ashamed of 
receiving them; for the one is the mark of a superior, the other 
of an inferior. And he is apt to confer greater benefits in return; 
for thus the original benefactor besides being paid will incur a 
debt to him, and will be the gainer by the transaction. They 
seem also to remember any service they have done, but not 
those they have received (for he who receives a service is 
inferior to him who has done it, but the proud man wishes to be 
superior), and to hear of the former with pleasure, of the latter 
with displeasure; this, it seems, is why Thetis did not mention 



2619 



to Zeus the services she had done him, and why the Spartans 
did not recount their services to the Athenians, but those they 
had received. It is a mark of the proud man also to ask for 
nothing or scarcely anything, but to give help readily, and to be 
dignified towards people who enjoy high position and good 
fortune, but unassuming towards those of the middle class; for 
it is a difficult and lofty thing to be superior to the former, but 
easy to be so to the latter, and a lofty bearing over the former is 
no mark of ill-breeding, but among humble people it is as vulgar 
as a display of strength against the weak. Again, it is 
characteristic of the proud man not to aim at the things 
commonly held in honour, or the things in which others excel; 
to be sluggish and to hold back except where great honour or a 
great work is at stake, and to be a man of few deeds, but of great 
and notable ones. He must also be open in his hate and in his 
love (for to conceal one's feelings, i.e. to care less for truth than 
for what people will think, is a coward's part), and must speak 
and act openly; for he is free of speech because he is 
contemptuous, and he is given to telling the truth, except when 
he speaks in irony to the vulgar. He must be unable to make his 
life revolve round another, unless it be a friend; for this is 
slavish, and for this reason all flatterers are servile and people 
lacking in self-respect are flatterers. Nor is he given to 
admiration; for nothing to him is great. Nor is he mindful of 
wrongs; for it is not the part of a proud man to have a long 
memory, especially for wrongs, but rather to overlook them. Nor 
is he a gossip; for he will speak neither about himself nor about 
another, since he cares not to be praised nor for others to be 
blamed; nor again is he given to praise; and for the same reason 
he is not an evil-speaker, even about his enemies, except from 
haughtiness. With regard to necessary or small matters he is 
least of all me given to lamentation or the asking of favours; for 
it is the part of one who takes such matters seriously to behave 
so with respect to them. He is one who will possess beautiful 



2620 



and profitless things rather than profitable and useful ones; for 
this is more proper to a character that suffices to itself. 

Further, a slow step is thought proper to the proud man, a deep 
voice, and a level utterance; for the man who takes few things 
seriously is not likely to be hurried, nor the man who thinks 
nothing great to be excited, while a shrill voice and a rapid gait 
are the results of hurry and excitement. 

Such, then, is the proud man; the man who falls short of him is 
unduly humble, and the man who goes beyond him is vain. Now 
even these are not thought to be bad (for they are not 
malicious), but only mistaken. For the unduly humble man, 
being worthy of good things, robs himself of what he deserves, 
and to have something bad about him from the fact that he 
does not think himself worthy of good things, and seems also 
not to know himself; else he would have desired the things he 
was worthy of, since these were good. Yet such people are not 
thought to be fools, but rather unduly retiring. Such a 
reputation, however, seems actually to make them worse; for 
each class of people aims at what corresponds to its worth, and 
these people stand back even from noble actions and 
undertakings, deeming themselves unworthy, and from external 
goods no less. Vain people, on the other hand, are fools and 
ignorant of themselves, and that manifestly; for, not being 
worthy of them, they attempt honourable undertakings, and 
then are found out; and tetadorn themselves with clothing and 
outward show and such things, and wish their strokes of good 
fortune to be made public, and speak about them as if they 
would be honoured for them. But undue humility is more 
opposed to pride than vanity is; for it is both commoner and 
worse. 

Pride, then, is concerned with honour on the grand scale, as has 
been said. 



2621 



There seems to be in the sphere of honour also, as was said in 
our first remarks on the subject, a virtue which would appear to 
be related to pride as liberality is to magnificence. For neither of 
these has anything to do with the grand scale, but both dispose 
us as is right with regard to middling and unimportant objects; 
as in getting and giving of wealth there is a mean and an excess 
and defect, so too honour may be desired more than is right, or 
less, or from the right sources and in the right way. We blame 
both the ambitious man as am at honour more than is right and 
from wrong sources, and the unambitious man as not willing to 
be honoured even for noble reasons. But sometimes we praise 
the ambitious man as being manly and a lover of what is noble, 
and the unambitious man as being moderate and self- 
controlled, as we said in our first treatment of the subject. 
Evidently, since 'fond of such and such an object' has more than 
one meaning, we do not assign the term 'ambition' or 'love of 
honour' always to the same thing, but when we praise the 
quality we think of the man who loves honour more than most 
people, and when we blame it we think of him who loves it 
more than is right. The mean being without a name, the 
extremes seem to dispute for its place as though that were 
vacant by default. But where there is excess and defect, there is 
also an intermediate; now men desire honour both more than 
they should and less; therefore it is possible also to do so as one 
should; at all events this is the state of character that is praised, 
being an unnamed mean in respect of honour. Relatively to 
ambition it seems to be unambitiousness, and relatively to 
unambitiousness it seems to be ambition, while relatively to 
both severally it seems in a sense to be both together. This 



2622 



appears to be true of the other virtues also. But in this case the 
extremes seem to be contradictories because the mean has not 
received a name. 



Good temper is a mean with respect to anger; the middle state 
being unnamed, and the extremes almost without a name as 
well, we place good temper in the middle position, though it 
inclines towards the deficiency, which is without a name. The 
excess might called a sort of 'irascibility'. For the passion is 
anger, while its causes are many and diverse. 

The man who is angry at the right things and with the right 
people, and, further, as he ought, when he ought, and as long as 
he ought, is praised. This will be the good-tempered man, then, 
since good temper is praised. For the good-tempered man tends 
to be unperturbed and not to be led by passion, but to be angry 
in the manner, at the things, and for the length of time, that the 
rule dictates; but he is thought to err rather in the direction of 
deficiency; for the good-tempered man is not revengeful, but 
rather tends to make allowances. 

The deficiency, whether it is a sort of 'inirascibility' or whatever 
it is, is blamed. For those who are not angry at the things they 
should be angry at are thought to be fools, and so are those who 
are not angry in the right way, at the right time, or with the right 
persons; for such a man is thought not to feel things nor to be 
pained by them, and, since he does not get angry, he is thought 
unlikely to defend himself; and to endure being insulted and 
put up with insult to one's friends is slavish. 



2623 



The excess can be manifested in all the points that have been 
named (for one can be angry with the wrong persons, at the 
wrong things, more than is right, too quickly, or too long); yet all 
are not found in the same person. Indeed they could not; for evil 
destroys even itself, and if it is complete becomes unbearable. 
Now hot-tempered people get angry quickly and with the wrong 
persons and at the wrong things and more than is right, but 
their anger ceases quickly - which is the best point about them. 
This happens to them because they do not restrain their anger 
but retaliate openly owing to their quickness of temper, and 
then their anger ceases. By reason of excess choleric people are 
quick-tempered and ready to be angry with everything and on 
every occasion; whence their name. Sulky people are hard to 
appease, and retain their anger long; for they repress their 
passion. But it ceases when they retaliate; for revenge relieves 
them of their anger, producing in them pleasure instead of pain. 
If this does not happen they retain their burden; for owing to its 
not being obvious no one even reasons with them, and to digest 
one's anger in oneself takes time. Such people are most 
troublesome to themselves and to their dearest friends. We call 
bad-tempered those who are angry at the wrong things, more 
than is right, and longer, and cannot be appeased until they 
inflict vengeance or punishment. 

To good temper we oppose the excess rather than the defect; for 
not only is it commoner since revenge is the more human), but 
bad-tempered people are worse to live with. 

What we have said in our earlier treatment of the subject is 
plain also from what we are now saying; viz. that it is not easy 
to define how, with whom, at what, and how long one should be 
angry, and at what point right action ceases and wrong begins. 
For the man who strays a little from the path, either towards the 
more or towards the less, is not blamed; since sometimes we 
praise those who exhibit the deficiency, and call them good- 



2624 



tempered, and sometimes we call angry people manly, as being 
capable of ruling. How far, therefore, and how a man must stray 
before he becomes blameworthy, it is not easy to state in words; 
for the decision depends on the particular facts and on 
perception. But so much at least is plain, that the middle state is 
praiseworthy - that in virtue of which we are angry with the 
right people, at the right things, in the right way, and so on, 
while the excesses and defects are blameworthy - slightly so if 
they are present in a low degree, more if in a higher degree, and 
very much if in a high degree. Evidently, then, we must cling to 
the middle state. - Enough of the states relative to anger. 



In gatherings of men, in social life and the interchange of words 
and deeds, some men are thought to be obsequious, viz. those 
who to give pleasure praise everything and never oppose, but 
think it their duty 'to give no pain to the people they meet'; 
while those who, on the contrary, oppose everything and care 
not a whit about giving pain are called churlish and 
contentious. That the states we have named are culpable is 
plain enough, and that the middle state is laudable - that in 
virtue of which a man will put up with, and will resent, the right 
things and in the right way; but no name has been assigned to 
it, though it most resembles friendship. For the man who 
corresponds to this middle state is very much what, with 
affection added, we call a good friend. But the state in question 
differs from friendship in that it implies no passion or affection 
for one's associates; since it is not by reason of loving or hating 
that such a man takes everything in the right way, but by being 
a man of a certain kind. For he will behave so alike towards 
those he knows and those he does not know, towards intimates 



2625 



and those who are not so, except that in each of these cases he 
will behave as is befitting; for it is not proper to have the same 
care for intimates and for strangers, nor again is it the same 
conditions that make it right to give pain to them. Now we have 
said generally that he will associate with people in the right 
way; but it is by reference to what is honourable and expedient 
that he will aim at not giving pain or at contributing pleasure. 
For he seems to be concerned with the pleasures and pains of 
social life; and wherever it is not honourable, or is harmful, for 
him to contribute pleasure, he will refuse, and will choose 
rather to give pain; also if his acquiescence in another's action 
would bring disgrace, and that in a high degree, or injury, on 
that other, while his opposition brings a little pain, he will not 
acquiesce but will decline. He will associate differently with 
people in high station and with ordinary people, with closer and 
more distant acquaintances, and so too with regard to all other 
differences, rendering to each class what is befitting, and while 
for its own sake he chooses to contribute pleasure, and avoids 
the giving of pain, he will be guided by the consequences, if 
these are greater, i.e. honour and expediency. For the sake of a 
great future pleasure, too, he will inflict small pains. 

The man who attains the mean, then, is such as we have 
described, but has not received a name; of those who contribute 
pleasure, the man who aims at being pleasant with no ulterior 
object is obsequious, but the man who does so in order that he 
may get some advantage in the direction of money or the things 
that money buys is a flatterer; while the man who quarrels with 
everything is, as has been said, churlish and contentious. And 
the extremes seem to be contradictory to each other because 
the mean is without a name. 



2626 



The mean opposed to boastfulness is found in almost the same 
sphere; and this also is without a name. It will be no bad plan to 
describe these states as well; for we shall both know the facts 
about character better if we go through them in detail, and we 
shall be convinced that the virtues are means if we see this to 
be so in all cases. In the field of social life those who make the 
giving of pleasure or pain their object in associating with others 
have been described; let us now describe those who pursue 
truth or falsehood alike in words and deeds and in the claims 
they put forward. The boastful man, then, is thought to be apt to 
claim the things that bring glory, when he has not got them, or 
to claim more of them than he has, and the mock-modest man 
on the other hand to disclaim what he has or belittle it, while 
the man who observes the mean is one who calls a thing by its 
own name, being truthful both in life and in word, owning to 
what he has, and neither more nor less. Now each of these 
courses may be adopted either with or without an object. But 
each man speaks and acts and lives in accordance with his 
character, if he is not acting for some ulterior object. And 
falsehood is in itself mean and culpable, and truth noble and 
worthy of praise. Thus the truthful man is another case of a 
man who, being in the mean, is worthy of praise, and both 
forms of untruthful man are culpable, and particularly the 
boastful man. 

Let us discuss them both, but first of all the truthful man. We 
are not speaking of the man who keeps faith in his agreements, 
i.e. in the things that pertain to justice or injustice (for this 
would belong to another virtue), but the man who in the 
matters in which nothing of this sort is at stake is true both in 
word and in life because his character is such. But such a man 
would seem to be as a matter of fact equitable. For the man who 
loves truth, and is truthful where nothing is at stake, will still 



2627 



more be truthful where something is at stake; he will avoid 
falsehood as something base, seeing that he avoided it even for 
its own sake; and such a man is worthy of praise. He inclines 
rather to understate the truth; for this seems in better taste 
because exaggerations are wearisome. 

He who claims more than he has with no ulterior object is a 
contemptible sort of fellow (otherwise he would not have 
delighted in falsehood), but seems futile rather than bad; but if 
he does it for an object, he who does it for the sake of 
reputation or honour is (for a boaster) not very much to be 
blamed, but he who does it for money, or the things that lead to 
money, is an uglier character (it is not the capacity that makes 
the boaster, but the purpose; for it is in virtue of his state of 
character and by being a man of a certain kind that he is 
boaster); as one man is a liar because he enjoys the lie itself, 
and another because he desires reputation or gain. Now those 
who boast for the sake of reputation claim such qualities as will 
praise or congratulation, but those whose object is gain claim 
qualities which are of value to one's neighbours and one's lack 
of which is not easily detected, e.g. the powers of a seer, a sage, 
or a physician. For this reason it is such things as these that 
most people claim and boast about; for in them the above- 
mentioned qualities are found. 

Mock-modest people, who understate things, seem more 
attractive in character; for they are thought to speak not for 
gain but to avoid parade; and here too it is qualities which bring 
reputation that they disclaim, as Socrates used to do. Those who 
disclaim trifling and obvious qualities are called humbugs and 
are more contemptible; and sometimes this seems to be 
boastfulness, like the Spartan dress; for both excess and great 
deficiency are boastful. But those who use understatement with 
moderation and understate about matters that do not very 
much force themselves on our notice seem attractive. And it is 



2628 



the boaster that seems to be opposed to the truthful man; for he 
is the worse character. 



8 

Since life includes rest as well as activity, and in this is included 
leisure and amusement, there seems here also to be a kind of 
intercourse which is tasteful; there is such a thing as saying - 
and again listening to - what one should and as one should. The 
kind of people one is speaking or listening to will also make a 
difference. Evidently here also there is both an excess and a 
deficiency as compared with the mean. Those who carry 
humour to excess are thought to be vulgar buffoons, striving 
after humour at all costs, and aiming rather at raising a laugh 
than at saying what is becoming and at avoiding pain to the 
object of their fun; while those who can neither make a joke 
themselves nor put up with those who do are thought to be 
boorish and unpolished. But those who joke in a tasteful way 
are called ready-witted, which implies a sort of readiness to 
turn this way and that; for such sallies are thought to be 
movements of the character, and as bodies are discriminated by 
their movements, so too are characters. The ridiculous side of 
things is not far to seek, however, and most people delight more 
than they should in amusement and in jestinly. and so even 
buffoons are called ready-witted because they are found 
attractive; but that they differ from the ready-witted man, and 
to no small extent, is clear from what has been said. 

To the middle state belongs also tact; it is the mark of a tactful 
man to say and listen to such things as befit a good and well- 
bred man; for there are some things that it befits such a man to 
say and to hear by way of jest, and the well-bred man's jesting 



2629 



differs from that of a vulgar man, and the joking of an educated 
man from that of an uneducated. One may see this even from 
the old and the new comedies; to the authors of the former 
indecency of language was amusing, to those of the latter 
innuendo is more so; and these differ in no small degree in 
respect of propriety. Now should we define the man who jokes 
well by his saying what is not unbecoming to a well-bred man, 
or by his not giving pain, or even giving delight, to the hearer? 
Or is the latter definition, at any rate, itself indefinite, since 
different things are hateful or pleasant to different people? The 
kind of jokes he will listen to will be the same; for the kind he 
can put up with are also the kind he seems to make. There are, 
then, jokes he will not make; for the jest is a sort of abuse, and 
there are things that lawgivers forbid us to abuse; and they 
should, perhaps, have forbidden us even to make a jest of such. 
The refined and well-bred man, therefore, will be as we have 
described, being as it were a law to himself. 

Such, then, is the man who observes the mean, whether he be 
called tactful or ready-witted. The buffoon, on the other hand, is 
the slave of his sense of humour, and spares neither himself nor 
others if he can raise a laugh, and says things none of which a 
man of refinement would say, and to some of which he would 
not even listen. The boor, again, is useless for such social 
intercourse; for he contributes nothing and finds fault with 
everything. But relaxation and amusement are thought to be a 
necessary element in life. 

The means in life that have been described, then, are three in 
number, and are all concerned with an interchange of words 
and deeds of some kind. They differ, however, in that one is 
concerned with truth; and the other two with pleasantness. Of 
those concerned with pleasure, one is displayed in jests, the 
other in the general social intercourse of life. 



2630 



Shame should not be described as a virtue; for it is more like a 
feeling than a state of character. It is defined, at any rate, as a 
kind of fear of dishonour, and produces an effect similar to that 
produced by fear of danger; for people who feel disgraced blush, 
and those who fear death turn pale. Both, therefore, seem to be 
in a sense bodily conditions, which is thought to be 
characteristic of feeling rather than of a state of character. 

The feeling is not becoming to every age, but only to youth. For 
we think young people should be prone to the feeling of shame 
because they live by feeling and therefore commit many errors, 
but are restrained by shame; and we praise young people who 
are prone to this feeling, but an older person no one would 
praise for being prone to the sense of disgrace, since we think 
he should not do anything that need cause this sense. For the 
sense of disgrace is not even characteristic of a good man, since 
it is consequent on bad actions (for such actions should not be 
done; and if some actions are disgraceful in very truth and 
others only according to common opinion, this makes no 
difference; for neither class of actions should be done, so that 
no disgrace should be felt); and it is a mark of a bad man even 
to be such as to do any disgraceful action. To be so constituted 
as to feel disgraced if one does such an action, and for this 
reason to think oneself good, is absurd; for it is for voluntary 
actions that shame is felt, and the good man will never 
voluntarily do bad actions. But shame may be said to be 
conditionally a good thing; if a good man does such actions, he 
will feel disgraced; but the virtues are not subject to such a 
qualification. And if shamelessness - not to be ashamed of 
doing base actions - is bad, that does not make it good to be 



2631 



ashamed of doing such actions. Continence too is not virtue, but 
a mixed sort of state; this will be shown later. Now, however, let 
us discuss justice. 



BookV 



With regards to justice and injustice we must (1) consider what 
kind of actions they are concerned with, (2) what sort of mean 
justice is, and (3) between what extremes the just act is 
intermediate. Our investigation shall follow the same course as 
the preceding discussions. 

We see that all men mean by justice that kind of state of 
character which makes people disposed to do what is just and 
makes them act justly and wish for what is just; and similarly 
by injustice that state which makes them act unjustly and wish 
for what is unjust. Let us too, then, lay this down as a general 
basis. For the same is not true of the sciences and the faculties 
as of states of character. A faculty or a science which is one and 
the same is held to relate to contrary objects, but a state of 
character which is one of two contraries does not produce the 
contrary results; e.g. as a result of health we do not do what is 
the opposite of healthy, but only what is healthy; for we say a 
man walks healthily, when he walks as a healthy man would. 



2632 



Now often one contrary state is recognized from its contrary, 
and often states are recognized from the subjects that exhibit 
them; for (A) if good condition is known, bad condition also 
becomes known, and (B) good condition is known from the 
things that are in good condition, and they from it. If good 
condition is firmness of flesh, it is necessary both that bad 
condition should be flabbiness of flesh and that the wholesome 
should be that which causes firmness in flesh. And it follows for 
the most part that if one contrary is ambiguous the other also 
will be ambiguous; e.g. if 'just' is so, that 'unjust' will be so too. 

Now 'justice' and 'injustice' seem to be ambiguous, but because 
their different meanings approach near to one another the 
ambiguity escapes notice and is not obvious as it is, 
comparatively, when the meanings are far apart, e.g. (for here 
the difference in outward form is great) as the ambiguity in the 
use of kleis for the collar-bone of an animal and for that with 
which we lock a door. Let us take as a starting-point, then, the 
various meanings of 'an unjust man'. Both the lawless man and 
the grasping and unfair man are thought to be unjust, so that 
evidently both the law-abiding and the fair man will be just. The 
just, then, is the lawful and the fair, the unjust the unlawful and 
the unfair. 

Since the unjust man is grasping, he must be concerned with 
goods - not all goods, but those with which prosperity and 
adversity have to do, which taken absolutely are always good, 
but for a particular person are not always good. Now men pray 
for and pursue these things; but they should not, but should 
pray that the things that are good absolutely may also be good 
for them, and should choose the things that are good for them. 
The unjust man does not always choose the greater, but also the 
less - in the case of things bad absolutely; but because the 
lesser evil is itself thought to be in a sense good, and 
graspingness is directed at the good, therefore he is thought to 



2633 



be grasping. And he is unfair; for this contains and is common 
to both. 

Since the lawless man was seen to be unjust and the law- 
abiding man just, evidently all lawful acts are in a sense just 
acts; for the acts laid down by the legislative art are lawful, and 
each of these, we say, is just. Now the laws in their enactments 
on all subjects aim at the common advantage either of all or of 
the best or of those who hold power, or something of the sort; 
so that in one sense we call those acts just that tend to produce 
and preserve happiness and its components for the political 
society. And the law bids us do both the acts of a brave man (e.g. 
not to desert our post nor take to flight nor throw away our 
arms), and those of a temperate man (e.g. not to commit 
adultery nor to gratify one's lust), and those of a good-tempered 
man (e.g. not to strike another nor to speak evil), and similarly 
with regard to the other virtues and forms of wickedness, 
commanding some acts and forbidding others; and the rightly- 
framed law does this rightly, and the hastily conceived one less 
well. This form of justice, then, is complete virtue, but not 
absolutely, but in relation to our neighbour. And therefore 
justice is often thought to be the greatest of virtues, and 
'neither evening nor morning star' is so wonderful; and 
proverbially 'in justice is every virtue comprehended'. And it is 
complete virtue in its fullest sense, because it is the actual 
exercise of complete virtue. It is complete because he who 
possesses it can exercise his virtue not only in himself but 
towards his neighbour also; for many men can exercise virtue in 
their own affairs, but not in their relations to their neighbour. 
This is why the saying of Bias is thought to be true, that 'rule 
will show the man'; for a ruler is necessarily in relation to other 
men and a member of a society. For this same reason justice, 
alone of the virtues, is thought to be 'another's good', because it 
is related to our neighbour; for it does what is advantageous to 
another, either a ruler or a copartner. Now the worst man is he 



2634 



who exercises his wickedness both towards himself and 
towards his friends, and the best man is not he who exercises 
his virtue towards himself but he who exercises it towards 
another; for this is a difficult task. Justice in this sense, then, is 
not part of virtue but virtue entire, nor is the contrary injustice 
a part of vice but vice entire. What the difference is between 
virtue and justice in this sense is plain from what we have said; 
they are the same but their essence is not the same; what, as a 
relation to one's neighbour, is justice is, as a certain kind of 
state without qualification, virtue. 



But at all events what we are investigating is the justice which 
is a part of virtue; for there is a justice of this kind, as we 
maintain. Similarly it is with injustice in the particular sense 
that we are concerned. 

That there is such a thing is indicated by the fact that while the 
man who exhibits in action the other forms of wickedness acts 
wrongly indeed, but not graspingly (e.g. the man who throws 
away his shield through cowardice or speaks harshly through 
bad temper or fails to help a friend with money through 
meanness), when a man acts graspingly he often exhibits none 
of these vices, - no, nor all together, but certainly wickedness of 
some kind (for we blame him) and injustice. There is, then, 
another kind of injustice which is a part of injustice in the wide 
sense, and a use of the word 'unjust' which answers to a part of 
what is unjust in the wide sense of 'contrary to the law'. Again if 
one man commits adultery for the sake of gain and makes 
money by it, while another does so at the bidding of appetite 
though he loses money and is penalized for it, the latter would 



2635 



be held to be self-indulgent rather than grasping, but the former 
is unjust, but not self-indulgent; evidently, therefore, he is 
unjust by reason of his making gain by his act. Again, all other 
unjust acts are ascribed invariably to some particular kind of 
wickedness, e.g. adultery to self-indulgence, the desertion of a 
comrade in battle to cowardice, physical violence to anger; but if 
a man makes gain, his action is ascribed to no form of 
wickedness but injustice. Evidently, therefore, there is apart 
from injustice in the wide sense another, 'particular', injustice 
which shares the name and nature of the first, because its 
definition falls within the same genus; for the significance of 
both consists in a relation to one's neighbour, but the one is 
concerned with honour or money or safety - or that which 
includes all these, if we had a single name for it - and its motive 
is the pleasure that arises from gain; while the other is 
concerned with all the objects with which the good man is 
concerned. 

It is clear, then, that there is more than one kind of justice, and 
that there is one which is distinct from virtue entire; we must 
try to grasp its genus and differentia. 

The unjust has been divided into the unlawful and the unfair, 
and the just into the lawful and the fair. To the unlawful 
answers the afore-mentioned sense of injustice. But since 
unfair and the unlawful are not the same, but are different as a 
part is from its whole (for all that is unfair is unlawful, but not 
all that is unlawful is unfair), the unjust and injustice in the 
sense of the unfair are not the same as but different from the 
former kind, as part from whole; for injustice in this sense is a 
part of injustice in the wide sense, and similarly justice in the 
one sense of justice in the other. Therefore we must speak also 
about particular justice and particular and similarly about the 
just and the unjust. The justice, then, which answers to the 
whole of virtue, and the corresponding injustice, one being the 



2636 



exercise of virtue as a whole, and the other that of vice as a 
whole, towards one's neighbour, we may leave on one side. And 
how the meanings of 'just' and 'unjust' which answer to these 
are to be distinguished is evident; for practically the majority of 
the acts commanded by the law are those which are prescribed 
from the point of view of virtue taken as a whole; for the law 
bids us practise every virtue and forbids us to practise any vice. 
And the things that tend to produce virtue taken as a whole are 
those of the acts prescribed by the law which have been 
prescribed with a view to education for the common good. But 
with regard to the education of the individual as such, which 
makes him without qualification a good man, we must 
determine later whether this is the function of the political art 
or of another; for perhaps it is not the same to be a good man 
and a good citizen of any state taken at random. 

Of particular justice and that which is just in the corresponding 
sense, (A) one kind is that which is manifested in distributions 
of honour or money or the other things that fall to be divided 
among those who have a share in the constitution (for in these 
it is possible for one man to have a share either unequal or 
equal to that of another), and (B) one is that which plays a 
rectifying part in transactions between man and man. Of this 
there are two divisions; of transactions (1) some are voluntary 
and (2) others involuntary - voluntary such transactions as sale, 
purchase, loan for consumption, pledging, loan for use, 
depositing, letting (they are called voluntary because the origin 
of these transactions is voluntary), while of the involuntary (a) 
some are clandestine, such as theft, adultery, poisoning, 
procuring, enticement of slaves, assassination, false witness, 
and (b) others are violent, such as assault, imprisonment, 
murder, robbery with violence, mutilation, abuse, insult. 



2637 



(A) We have shown that both the unjust man and the unjust act 
are unfair or unequal; now it is clear that there is also an 
intermediate between the two unequals involved in either case. 
And this is the equal; for in any kind of action in which there's a 
more and a less there is also what is equal. If, then, the unjust is 
unequal, just is equal, as all men suppose it to be, even apart 
from argument. And since the equal is intermediate, the just 
will be an intermediate. Now equality implies at least two 
things. The just, then, must be both intermediate and equal and 
relative (i.e. for certain persons). And since the equall 
intermediate it must be between certain things (which are 
respectively greater and less); equal, it involves two things; qua 
just, it is for certain people. The just, therefore, involves at least 
four terms; for the persons for whom it is in fact just are two, 
and the things in which it is manifested, the objects distributed, 
are two. And the same equality will exist between the persons 
and between the things concerned; for as the latter the things 
concerned are related, so are the former; if they are not equal, 
they will not have what is equal, but this is the origin of 
quarrels and complaints - when either equals have and are 
awarded unequal shares, or unequals equal shares. Further, this 
is plain from the fact that awards should be 'according to merit'; 
for all men agree that what is just in distribution must be 
according to merit in some sense, though they do not all specify 
the same sort of merit, but democrats identify it with the status 
of freeman, supporters of oligarchy with wealth (or with noble 
birth), and supporters of aristocracy with excellence. 

The just, then, is a species of the proportionate (proportion 
being not a property only of the kind of number which consists 
of abstract units, but of number in general). For proportion is 



2638 



equality of ratios, and involves four terms at least (that discrete 
proportion involves four terms is plain, but so does continuous 
proportion, for it uses one term as two and mentions it twice; 
e.g. 'as the line A is to the line B, so is the line B to the line C; 
the line B, then, has been mentioned twice, so that if the line B 
be assumed twice, the proportional terms will be four); and the 
just, too, involves at least four terms, and the ratio between one 
pair is the same as that between the other pair; for there is a 
similar distinction between the persons and between the 
things. As the term A, then, is to B, so will C be to D, and 
therefore, alternando, as A is to C, B will be to D. Therefore also 
the whole is in the same ratio to the whole; and this coupling 
the distribution effects, and, if the terms are so combined, 
effects justly. The conjunction, then, of the term A with C and of 
B with D is what is just in distribution, and this species of the 
just is intermediate, and the unjust is what violates the 
proportion; for the proportional is intermediate, and the just is 
proportional. (Mathematicians call this kind of proportion 
geometrical; for it is in geometrical proportion that it follows 
that the whole is to the whole as either part is to the 
corresponding part.) This proportion is not continuous; for we 
cannot get a single term standing for a person and a thing. 

This, then, is what the just is - the proportional; the unjust is 
what violates the proportion. Hence one term becomes too 
great, the other too small, as indeed happens in practice; for the 
man who acts unjustly has too much, and the man who is 
unjustly treated too little, of what is good. In the case of evil the 
reverse is true; for the lesser evil is reckoned a good in 
comparison with the greater evil, since the lesser evil is rather 
to be chosen than the greater, and what is worthy of choice is 
good, and what is worthier of choice a greater good. 

This, then, is one species of the just. 



2639 



(B) The remaining one is the rectificatory, which arises in 
connexion with transactions both voluntary and involuntary. 
This form of the just has a different specific character from the 
former. For the justice which distributes common possessions is 
always in accordance with the kind of proportion mentioned 
above (for in the case also in which the distribution is made 
from the common funds of a partnership it will be according to 
the same ratio which the funds put into the business by the 
partners bear to one another); and the injustice opposed to this 
kind of justice is that which violates the proportion. But the 
justice in transactions between man and man is a sort of 
equality indeed, and the injustice a sort of inequality; not 
according to that kind of proportion, however, but according to 
arithmetical proportion. For it makes no difference whether a 
good man has defrauded a bad man or a bad man a good one, 
nor whether it is a good or a bad man that has committed 
adultery; the law looks only to the distinctive character of the 
injury, and treats the parties as equal, if one is in the wrong and 
the other is being wronged, and if one inflicted injury and the 
other has received it. Therefore, this kind of injustice being an 
inequality, the judge tries to equalize it; for in the case also in 
which one has received and the other has inflicted a wound, or 
one has slain and the other been slain, the suffering and the 
action have been unequally distributed; but the judge tries to 
equalize by means of the penalty, taking away from the gain of 
the assailant. For the term 'gain' is applied generally to such 
cases, even if it be not a term appropriate to certain cases, e.g. to 
the person who inflicts a woundand 'loss' to the sufferer; at all 
events when the suffering has been estimated, the one is called 



2640 



loss and the other gain. Therefore the equal is intermediate 
between the greater and the less, but the gain and the loss are 
respectively greater and less in contrary ways; more of the good 
and less of the evil are gain, and the contrary is loss; 
intermediate between them is, as we saw, equal, which we say 
is just; therefore corrective justice will be the intermediate 
between loss and gain. This is why, when people dispute, they 
take refuge in the judge; and to go to the judge is to go to 
justice; for the nature of the judge is to be a sort of animate 
justice; and they seek the judge as an intermediate, and in some 
states they call judges mediators, on the assumption that if they 
get what is intermediate they will get what is just. The just, 
then, is an intermediate, since the judge is so. Now the judge 
restores equality; it is as though there were a line divided into 
unequal parts, and he took away that by which the greater 
segment exceeds the half, and added it to the smaller segment. 
And when the whole has been equally divided, then they say 
they have 'their own' - i.e. when they have got what is equal. 
The equal is intermediate between the greater and the lesser 
line according to arithmetical proportion. It is for this reason 
also that it is called just (sikaion), because it is a division into 
two equal parts (sicha), just as if one were to call it sichaion; 
and the judge (sikastes) is one who bisects (sichastes). For when 
something is subtracted from one of two equals and added to 
the other, the other is in excess by these two; since if what was 
taken from the one had not been added to the other, the latter 
would have been in excess by one only. It therefore exceeds the 
intermediate by one, and the intermediate exceeds by one that 
from which something was taken. By this, then, we shall 
recognize both what we must subtract from that which has 
more, and what we must add to that which has less; we must 
add to the latter that by which the intermediate exceeds it, and 
subtract from the greatest that by which it exceeds the 
intermediate. Let the lines AA', BB', CC be equal to one another; 



2641 



from the line AA' let the segment AE have been subtracted, and 
to the line CC let the segment CD have been added, so that the 
whole line DCC exceeds the line EA' by the segment CD and the 
segment CF; therefore it exceeds the line BB' by the segment CD. 
(See diagram.) 

These names, both loss and gain, have come from voluntary 
exchange; for to have more than one's own is called gaining, 
and to have less than one's original share is called losing, e.g. in 
buying and selling and in all other matters in which the law has 
left people free to make their own terms; but when they get 
neither more nor less but just what belongs to themselves, they 
say that they have their own and that they neither lose nor 
gain. 

Therefore the just is intermediate between a sort of gain and a 
sort of loss, viz. those which are involuntary; it consists in 
having an equal amount before and after the transaction. 



Some think that reciprocity is without qualification just, as the 
Pythagoreans said; for they defined justice without qualification 
as reciprocity. Now 'reciprocity' fits neither distributive nor 
rectificatory justice - yet people want even the justice of 
Rhadamanthus to mean this: 

Should a man suffer what he did, right justice would be done - 
for in many cases reciprocity and rectificatory justice are not in 
accord; e.g. (1) if an official has inflicted a wound, he should not 
be wounded in return, and if some one has wounded an official, 
he ought not to be wounded only but punished in addition. 
Further (2) there is a great difference between a voluntary and 



2642 



an involuntary act. But in associations for exchange this sort of 
justice does hold men together - reciprocity in accordance with 
a proportion and not on the basis of precisely equal return. For 
it is by proportionate requital that the city holds together. Men 
seek to return either evil for evil - and if they cannot do so, 
think their position mere slavery - or good for good - and if they 
cannot do so there is no exchange, but it is by exchange that 
they hold together. This is why they give a prominent place to 
the temple of the Graces - to promote the requital of services; 
for this is characteristic of grace - we should serve in return one 
who has shown grace to us, and should another time take the 
initiative in showing it. 

Now proportionate return is secured by cross-conjunction. Let A 
be a builder, B a shoemaker, C a house, D a shoe. The builder, 
then, must get from the shoemaker the latter's work, and must 
himself give him in return his own. If, then, first there is 
proportionate equality of goods, and then reciprocal action 
takes place, the result we mention will be effected. If not, the 
bargain is not equal, and does not hold; for there is nothing to 
prevent the work of the one being better than that of the other; 
they must therefore be equated. (And this is true of the other 
arts also; for they would have been destroyed if what the 
patient suffered had not been just what the agent did, and of 
the same amount and kind.) For it is not two doctors that 
associate for exchange, but a doctor and a farmer, or in general 
people who are different and unequal; but these must be 
equated. This is why all things that are exchanged must be 
somehow comparable. It is for this end that money has been 
introduced, and it becomes in a sense an intermediate; for it 
measures all things, and therefore the excess and the defect - 
how many shoes are equal to a house or to a given amount of 
food. The number of shoes exchanged for a house (or for a given 
amount of food) must therefore correspond to the ratio of 
builder to shoemaker. For if this be not so, there will be no 



2643 



exchange and no intercourse. And this proportion will not be 
effected unless the goods are somehow equal. All goods must 
therefore be measured by some one thing, as we said before. 
Now this unit is in truth demand, which holds all things 
together (for if men did not need one another's goods at all, or 
did not need them equally, there would be either no exchange 
or not the same exchange); but money has become by 
convention a sort of representative of demand; and this is why 
it has the name 'money' (nomisma) - because it exists not by 
nature but by law (nomos) and it is in our power to change it 
and make it useless. There will, then, be reciprocity when the 
terms have been equated so that as farmer is to shoemaker, the 
amount of the shoemaker's work is to that of the farmer's work 
for which it exchanges. But we must not bring them into a 
figure of proportion when they have already exchanged 
(otherwise one extreme will have both excesses), but when they 
still have their own goods. Thus they are equals and associates 
just because this equality can be effected in their case. Let A be 
a farmer, C food, B a shoemaker, D his product equated to C. If it 
had not been possible for reciprocity to be thus effected, there 
would have been no association of the parties. That demand 
holds things together as a single unit is shown by the fact that 
when men do not need one another, i.e. when neither needs the 
other or one does not need the other, they do not exchange, as 
we do when some one wants what one has oneself, e.g. when 
people permit the exportation of corn in exchange for wine. 
This equation therefore must be established. And for the future 
exchange - that if we do not need a thing now we shall have it if 
ever we do need it - money is as it were our surety; for it must 
be possible for us to get what we want by bringing the money. 
Now the same thing happens to money itself as to goods - it is 
not always worth the same; yet it tends to be steadier. This is 
why all goods must have a price set on them; for then there will 
always be exchange, and if so, association of man with man. 



2644 



Money, then, acting as a measure, makes goods commensurate 
and equates them; for neither would there have been 
association if there were not exchange, nor exchange if there 
were not equality, nor equality if there were not 
commensurability. Now in truth it is impossible that things 
differing so much should become commensurate, but with 
reference to demand they may become so sufficiently. There 
must, then, be a unit, and that fixed by agreement (for which 
reason it is called money); for it is this that makes all things 
commensurate, since all things are measured by money. Let A 
be a house, B ten minae, C a bed. A is half of B, if the house is 
worth five minae or equal to them; the bed, C, is a tenth of B; it 
is plain, then, how many beds are equal to a house, viz. five. 
That exchange took place thus before there was money is plain; 
for it makes no difference whether it is five beds that exchange 
for a house, or the money value of five beds. 

We have now defined the unjust and the just. These having 
been marked off from each other, it is plain that just action is 
intermediate between acting unjustly and being unjustly 
treated; for the one is to have too much and the other to have 
too little. Justice is a kind of mean, but not in the same way as 
the other virtues, but because it relates to an intermediate 
amount, while injustice relates to the extremes. And justice is 
that in virtue of which the just man is said to be a doer, by 
choice, of that which is just, and one who will distribute either 
between himself and another or between two others not so as 
to give more of what is desirable to himself and less to his 
neighbour (and conversely with what is harmful), but so as to 
give what is equal in accordance with proportion; and similarly 
in distributing between two other persons. Injustice on the 
other hand is similarly related to the unjust, which is excess 
and defect, contrary to proportion, of the useful or hurtful. For 
which reason injustice is excess and defect, viz. because it is 
productive of excess and defect - in one's own case excess of 



2645 



what is in its own nature useful and defect of what is hurtful, 
while in the case of others it is as a whole like what it is in one's 
own case, but proportion may be violated in either direction. In 
the unjust act to have too little is to be unjustly treated; to have 
too much is to act unjustly. 

Let this be taken as our account of the nature of justice and 
injustice, and similarly of the just and the unjust in general. 



Since acting unjustly does not necessarily imply being unjust, 
we must ask what sort of unjust acts imply that the doer is 
unjust with respect to each type of injustice, e.g. a thief, an 
adulterer, or a brigand. Surely the answer does not turn on the 
difference between these types. For a man might even lie with a 
woman knowing who she was, but the origin of his might be not 
deliberate choice but passion. He acts unjustly, then, but is not 
unjust; e.g. a man is not a thief, yet he stole, nor an adulterer, 
yet he committed adultery; and similarly in all other cases. 

Now we have previously stated how the reciprocal is related to 
the just; but we must not forget that what we are looking for is 
not only what is just without qualification but also political 
justice. This is found among men who share their life with a 
view to selfsufficiency, men who are free and either 
proportionately or arithmetically equal, so that between those 
who do not fulfil this condition there is no political justice but 
justice in a special sense and by analogy. For justice exists only 
between men whose mutual relations are governed by law; and 
law exists for men between whom there is injustice; for legal 
justice is the discrimination of the just and the unjust. And 
between men between whom there is injustice there is also 



2646 



unjust action (though there is not injustice between all between 
whom there is unjust action), and this is assigning too much to 
oneself of things good in themselves and too little of things evil 
in themselves. This is why we do not allow a man to rule, but 
rational principle, because a man behaves thus in his own 
interests and becomes a tyrant. The magistrate on the other 
hand is the guardian of justice, and, if of justice, then of equality 
also. And since he is assumed to have no more than his share, if 
he is just (for he does not assign to himself more of what is 
good in itself, unless such a share is proportional to his merits - 
so that it is for others that he labours, and it is for this reason 
that men, as we stated previously, say that justice is 'another's 
good'), therefore a reward must be given him, and this is honour 
and privilege; but those for whom such things are not enough 
become tyrants. 

The justice of a master and that of a father are not the same as 
the justice of citizens, though they are like it; for there can be 
no injustice in the unqualified sense towards thing that are 
one's own, but a man's chattel, and his child until it reaches a 
certain age and sets up for itself, are as it were part of himself, 
and no one chooses to hurt himself (for which reason there can 
be no injustice towards oneself). Therefore the justice or 
injustice of citizens is not manifested in these relations; for it 
was as we saw according to law, and between people naturally 
subject to law, and these as we saw' are people who have an 
equal share in ruling and being ruled. Hence justice can more 
truly be manifested towards a wife than towards children and 
chattels, for the former is household justice; but even this is 
different from political justice. 



2647 



Of political justice part is natural, part legal, natural, that which 
everywhere has the same force and does not exist by people's 
thinking this or that; legal, that which is originally indifferent, 
but when it has been laid down is not indifferent, e.g. that a 
prisoner's ransom shall be a mina, or that a goat and not two 
sheep shall be sacrificed, and again all the laws that are passed 
for particular cases, e.g. that sacrifice shall be made in honour 
of Brasidas, and the provisions of decrees. Now some think that 
all justice is of this sort, because that which is by nature is 
unchangeable and has everywhere the same force (as fire burns 
both here and in Persia), while they see change in the things 
recognized as just. This, however, is not true in this unqualified 
way, but is true in a sense; or rather, with the gods it is perhaps 
not true at all, while with us there is something that is just even 
by nature, yet all of it is changeable; but still some is by nature, 
some not by nature. It is evident which sort of thing, among 
things capable of being otherwise, is by nature, and which is not 
but is legal and conventional, assuming that both are equally 
changeable. And in all other things the same distinction will 
apply; by nature the right hand is stronger, yet it is possible that 
all men should come to be ambidextrous. The things which are 
just by virtue of convention and expediency are like measures; 
for wine and corn measures are not everywhere equal, but 
larger in wholesale and smaller in retail markets. Similarly, the 
things which are just not by nature but by human enactment 
are not everywhere the same, since constitutions also are not 
the same, though there is but one which is everywhere by 
nature the best. Of things just and lawful each is related as the 
universal to its particulars; for the things that are done are 
many, but of them each is one, since it is universal. 

There is a difference between the act of injustice and what is 
unjust, and between the act of justice and what is just; for a 



2648 



thing is unjust by nature or by enactment; and this very thing, 
when it has been done, is an act of injustice, but before it is 
done is not yet that but is unjust. So, too, with an act of justice 
(though the general term is rather 'just action', and 'act of 
justice' is applied to the correction of the act of injustice). 

Each of these must later be examined separately with regard to 
the nature and number of its species and the nature of the 
things with which it is concerned. 



8 

Acts just and unjust being as we have described them, a man 
acts unjustly or justly whenever he does such acts voluntarily; 
when involuntarily, he acts neither unjustly nor justly except in 
an incidental way; for he does things which happen to be just or 
unjust. Whether an act is or is not one of injustice (or of justice) 
is determined by its voluntariness or involuntariness; for when 
it is voluntary it is blamed, and at the same time is then an act 
of injustice; so that there will be things that are unjust but not 
yet acts of injustice, if voluntariness be not present as well. By 
the voluntary I mean, as has been said before, any of the things 
in a man's own power which he does with knowledge, i.e. not in 
ignorance either of the person acted on or of the instrument 
used or of the end that will be attained (e.g. whom he is striking, 
with what, and to what end), each such act being done not 
incidentally nor under compulsion (e.g. if A takes B's hand and 
therewith strikes C, B does not act voluntarily; for the act was 
not in his own power). The person struck may be the striker's 
father, and the striker may know that it is a man or one of the 
persons present, but not know that it is his father; a similar 
distinction may be made in the case of the end, and with regard 



2649 



to the whole action. Therefore that which is done in ignorance, 
or though not done in ignorance is not in the agent's power, or 
is done under compulsion, is involuntary (for many natural 
processes, even, we knowingly both perform and experience, 
none of which is either voluntary or involuntary; e.g. growing 
old or dying). But in the case of unjust and just acts alike the 
injustice or justice may be only incidental; for a man might 
return a deposit unwillingly and from fear, and then he must 
not be said either to do what is just or to act justly, except in an 
incidental way. Similarly the man who under compulsion and 
unwillingly fails to return the deposit must be said to act 
unjustly, and to do what is unjust, only incidentally. Of 
voluntary acts we do some by choice, others not by choice; by 
choice those which we do after deliberation, not by choice those 
which we do without previous deliberation. Thus there are three 
kinds of injury in transactions between man and man; those 
done in ignorance are mistakes when the person acted on, the 
act, the instrument, or the end that will be attained is other 
than the agent supposed; the agent thought either that he was 
not hiting any one or that he was not hitting with this missile or 
not hitting this person or to this end, but a result followed other 
than that which he thought likely (e.g. he threw not with intent 
to wound but only to prick), or the person hit or the missile was 
other than he supposed. Now when (1) the injury takes place 
contrary to reasonable expectation, it is a misadventure. When 
(2) it is not contrary to reasonable expectation, but does not 
imply vice, it is a mistake (for a man makes a mistake when the 
fault originates in him, but is the victim of accident when the 
origin lies outside him). When (3) he acts with knowledge but 
not after deliberation, it is an act of injustice - e.g. the acts due 
to anger or to other passions necessary or natural to man; for 
when men do such harmful and mistaken acts they act 
unjustly, and the acts are acts of injustice, but this does not 
imply that the doers are unjust or wicked; for the injury is not 



2650 



due to vice. But when (4) a man acts from choice, he is an unjust 
man and a vicious man. 

Hence acts proceeding from anger are rightly judged not to be 
done of malice aforethought; for it is not the man who acts in 
anger but he who enraged him that starts the mischief. Again, 
the matter in dispute is not whether the thing happened or not, 
but its justice; for it is apparent injustice that occasions rage. 
For they do not dispute about the occurrence of the act - as in 
commercial transactions where one of the two parties must be 
vicious - unless they do so owing to forgetfulness; but, agreeing 
about the fact, they dispute on which side justice lies (whereas 
a man who has deliberately injured another cannot help 
knowing that he has done so), so that the one thinks he is being 
treated unjustly and the other disagrees. 

But if a man harms another by choice, he acts unjustly; and 
these are the acts of injustice which imply that the doer is an 
unjust man, provided that the act violates proportion or 
equality. Similarly, a man is just when he acts justly by choice; 
but he acts justly if he merely acts voluntarily. 

Of involuntary acts some are excusable, others not. For the 
mistakes which men make not only in ignorance but also from 
ignorance are excusable, while those which men do not from 
ignorance but (though they do them in ignorance) owing to a 
passion which is neither natural nor such as man is liable to, 
are not excusable. 



2651 



Assuming that we have sufficiently defined the suffering and 
doing of injustice, it may be asked (1) whether the truth in 
expressed in Euripides' paradoxical words: 

I slew my mother, that's my tale in brief. 

Were you both willing, or unwilling both? 

Is it truly possible to be willingly treated unjustly, or is all 
suffering of injustice the contrary involuntary, as all unjust 
action is voluntary? And is all suffering of injustice of the latter 
kind or else all of the former, or is it sometimes voluntary, 
sometimes involuntary? So, too, with the case of being justly 
treated; all just action is voluntary, so that it is reasonable that 
there should be a similar opposition in either case - that both 
being unjustly and being justly treated should be either alike 
voluntary or alike involuntary. But it would be thought 
paradoxical even in the case of being justly treated, if it were 
always voluntary; for some are unwillingly treated justly. (2) One 
might raise this question also, whether every one who has 
suffered what is unjust is being unjustly treated, or on the other 
hand it is with suffering as with acting. In action and in 
passivity alike it is possible to partake of justice incidentally, 
and similarly (it is plain) of injustice; for to do what is unjust is 
not the same as to act unjustly, nor to suffer what is unjust as 
to be treated unjustly, and similarly in the case of acting justly 
and being justly treated; for it is impossible to be unjustly 
treated if the other does not act unjustly, or justly treated unless 
he acts justly. Now if to act unjustly is simply to harm some one 
voluntarily, and 'voluntarily' means 'knowing the person acted 
on, the instrument, and the manner of one's acting', and the 
incontinent man voluntarily harms himself, not only will he 
voluntarily be unjustly treated but it will be possible to treat 
oneself unjustly. (This also is one of the questions in doubt, 



2652 



whether a man can treat himself unjustly.) Again, a man may 
voluntarily, owing to incontinence, be harmed by another who 
acts voluntarily, so that it would be possible to be voluntarily 
treated unjustly. Or is our definition incorrect; must we to 
'harming another, with knowledge both of the person acted on, 
of the instrument, and of the manner' add 'contrary to the wish 
of the person acted on? Then a man may be voluntarily harmed 
and voluntarily suffer what is unjust, but no one is voluntarily 
treated unjustly; for no one wishes to be unjustly treated, not 
even the incontinent man. He acts contrary to his wish; for no 
one wishes for what he does not think to be good, but the 
incontinent man does do things that he does not think he ought 
to do. Again, one who gives what is his own, as Homer says 
Glaucus gave Diomede Armour of gold for brazen, the price of a 
hundred beeves for nine, is not unjustly treated; for though to 
give is in his power, to be unjustly treated is not, but there must 
be some one to treat him unjustly. It is plain, then, that being 
unjustly treated is not voluntary. 

Of the questions we intended to discuss two still remain for 
discussion; (3) whether it is the man who has assigned to 
another more than his share that acts unjustly, or he who has 
the excessive share, and (4) whether it is possible to treat 
oneself unjustly. The questions are connected; for if the former 
alternative is possible and the distributor acts unjustly and not 
the man who has the excessive share, then if a man assigns 
more to another than to himself, knowingly and voluntarily, he 
treats himself unjustly; which is what modest people seem to 
do, since the virtuous man tends to take less than his share. Or 
does this statement too need qualification? For (a) he perhaps 
gets more than his share of some other good, e.g. of honour or 
of intrinsic nobility, (b) The question is solved by applying the 
distinction we applied to unjust action; for he suffers nothing 
contrary to his own wish, so that he is not unjustly treated as 
far as this goes, but at most only suffers harm. 



2653 



It is plain too that the distributor acts unjustly, but not always 
the man who has the excessive share; for it is not he to whom 
what is unjust appertains that acts unjustly, but he to whom it 
appertains to do the unjust act voluntarily, i.e. the person in 
whom lies the origin of the action, and this lies in the 
distributor, not in the receiver. Again, since the word 'do' is 
ambiguous, and there is a sense in which lifeless things, or a 
hand, or a servant who obeys an order, may be said to slay, he 
who gets an excessive share does not act unjustly, though he 
'does' what is unjust. 

Again, if the distributor gave his judgement in ignorance, he 
does not act unjustly in respect of legal justice, and his 
judgement is not unjust in this sense, but in a sense it is unjust 
(for legal justice and primordial justice are different); but if with 
knowledge he judged unjustly, he is himself aiming at an 
excessive share either of gratitude or of revenge. As much, then, 
as if he were to share in the plunder, the man who has judged 
unjustly for these reasons has got too much; the fact that what 
he gets is different from what he distributes makes no 
difference, for even if he awards land with a view to sharing in 
the plunder he gets not land but money. 

Men think that acting unjustly is in their power, and therefore 
that being just is easy. But it is not; to lie with one's neighbour's 
wife, to wound another, to deliver a bribe, is easy and in our 
power, but to do these things as a result of a certain state of 
character is neither easy nor in our power. Similarly to know 
what is just and what is unjust requires, men think, no great 
wisdom, because it is not hard to understand the matters dealt 
with by the laws (though these are not the things that are just, 
except incidentally); but how actions must be done and 
distributions effected in order to be just, to know this is a 
greater achievement than knowing what is good for the health; 
though even there, while it is easy to know that honey, wine, 



2654 



hellebore, cautery, and the use of the knife are so, to know how, 
to whom, and when these should be applied with a view to 
producing health, is no less an achievement than that of being a 
physician. Again, for this very reason men think that acting 
unjustly is characteristic of the just man no less than of the 
unjust, because he would be not less but even more capable of 
doing each of these unjust acts; for he could lie with a woman 
or wound a neighbour; and the brave man could throw away his 
shield and turn to flight in this direction or in that. But to play 
the coward or to act unjustly consists not in doing these things, 
except incidentally, but in doing them as the result of a certain 
state of character, just as to practise medicine and healing 
consists not in applying or not applying the knife, in using or 
not using medicines, but in doing so in a certain way. 

Just acts occur between people who participate in things good 
in themselves and can have too much or too little of them; for 
some beings (e.g. presumably the gods) cannot have too much 
of them, and to others, those who are incurably bad, not even 
the smallest share in them is beneficial but all such goods are 
harmful, while to others they are beneficial up to a point; 
therefore justice is essentially something human. 



10 

Our next subject is equity and the equitable (to epiekes), and 
their respective relations to justice and the just. For on 
examination they appear to be neither absolutely the same nor 
generically different; and while we sometime praise what is 
equitable and the equitable man (so that we apply the name by 
way of praise even to instances of the other virtues, instead of 
'good' meaning by epieikestebon that a thing is better), at other 



2655 



times, when we reason it out, it seems strange if the equitable, 
being something different from the just, is yet praiseworthy; for 
either the just or the equitable is not good, if they are different; 
or, if both are good, they are the same. 

These, then, are pretty much the considerations that give rise to 
the problem about the equitable; they are all in a sense correct 
and not opposed to one another; for the equitable, though it is 
better than one kind of justice, yet is just, and it is not as being 
a different class of thing that it is better than the just. The same 
thing, then, is just and equitable, and while both are good the 
equitable is superior. What creates the problem is that the 
equitable is just, but not the legally just but a correction of legal 
justice. The reason is that all law is universal but about some 
things it is not possible to make a universal statement which 
shall be correct. In those cases, then, in which it is necessary to 
speak universally, but not possible to do so correctly, the law 
takes the usual case, though it is not ignorant of the possibility 
of error. And it is none the less correct; for the error is in the law 
nor in the legislator but in the nature of the thing, since the 
matter of practical affairs is of this kind from the start. When 
the law speaks universally, then, and a case arises on it which is 
not covered by the universal statement, then it is right, where 
the legislator fails us and has erred by oversimplicity, to correct 
the omission - to say what the legislator himself would have 
said had he been present, and would have put into his law if he 
had known. Hence the equitable is just, and better than one 
kind of justice - not better than absolute justice but better than 
the error that arises from the absoluteness of the statement. 
And this is the nature of the equitable, a correction of law 
where it is defective owing to its universality. In fact this is the 
reason why all things are not determined by law, that about 
some things it is impossible to lay down a law, so that a decree 
is needed. For when the thing is indefinite the rule also is 
indefinite, like the leaden rule used in making the Lesbian 



2656 



moulding; the rule adapts itself to the shape of the stone and is 
not rigid, and so too the decree is adapted to the facts. 

It is plain, then, what the equitable is, and that it is just and is 
better than one kind of justice. It is evident also from this who 
the equitable man is; the man who chooses and does such acts, 
and is no stickler for his rights in a bad sense but tends to take 
less than his share though he has the law oft his side, is 
equitable, and this state of character is equity, which is a sort of 
justice and not a different state of character. 



11 

Whether a man can treat himself unjustly or not, is evident 
from what has been said. For (a) one class of just acts are those 
acts in accordance with any virtue which are prescribed by the 
law; e.g. the law does not expressly permit suicide, and what it 
does not expressly permit it forbids. Again, when a man in 
violation of the law harms another (otherwise than in 
retaliation) voluntarily, he acts unjustly, and a voluntary agent is 
one who knows both the person he is affecting by his action 
and the instrument he is using; and he who through anger 
voluntarily stabs himself does this contrary to the right rule of 
life, and this the law does not allow; therefore he is acting 
unjustly. But towards whom? Surely towards the state, not 
towards himself. For he suffers voluntarily, but no one is 
voluntarily treated unjustly. This is also the reason why the 
state punishes; a certain loss of civil rights attaches to the man 
who destroys himself, on the ground that he is treating the 
state unjustly. 

Further (b) in that sense of 'acting unjustly' in which the man 
who 'acts unjustly' is unjust only and not bad all round, it is not 



2657 



possible to treat oneself unjustly (this is different from the 
former sense; the unjust man in one sense of the term is 
wicked in a particularized way just as the coward is, not in the 
sense of being wicked all round, so that his 'unjust act' does not 
manifest wickedness in general). For (i) that would imply the 
possibility of the same thing's having been subtracted from and 
added to the same thing at the same time; but this is impossible 
- the just and the unjust always involve more than one person. 
Further, (ii) unjust action is voluntary and done by choice, and 
takes the initiative (for the man who because he has suffered 
does the same in return is not thought to act unjustly); but if a 
man harms himself he suffers and does the same things at the 
same time. Further, (iii) if a man could treat himself unjustly, he 
could be voluntarily treated unjustly. Besides, (iv) no one acts 
unjustly without committing particular acts of injustice; but no 
one can commit adultery with his own wife or housebreaking 
on his own house or theft on his own property, 

In general, the question 'can a man treat himself unjustly?' is 
solved also by the distinction we applied to the question 'can a 
man be voluntarily treated unjustly?' 

(It is evident too that both are bad, being unjustly treated and 
acting unjustly; for the one means having less and the other 
having more than the intermediate amount, which plays the 
part here that the healthy does in the medical art, and that good 
condition does in the art of bodily training. But still acting 
unjustly is the worse, for it involves vice and is blameworthy - 
involves vice which is either of the complete and unqualified 
kind or almost so (we must admit the latter alternative, because 
not all voluntary unjust action implies injustice as a state of 
character), while being unjustly treated does not involve vice 
and injustice in oneself. In itself, then, being unjustly treated is 
less bad, but there is nothing to prevent its being incidentally a 
greater evil. But theory cares nothing for this; it calls pleurisy a 



2658 



more serious mischief than a stumble; yet the latter may 
become incidentally the more serious, if the fall due to it leads 
to your being taken prisoner or put to death the enemy.) 

Metaphorically and in virtue of a certain resemblance there is a 
justice, not indeed between a man and himself, but between 
certain parts of him; yet not every kind of justice but that of 
master and servant or that of husband and wife. For these are 
the ratios in which the part of the soul that has a rational 
principle stands to the irrational part; and it is with a view to 
these parts that people also think a man can be unjust to 
himself, viz. because these parts are liable to suffer something 
contrary to their respective desires; there is therefore thought to 
be a mutual justice between them as between ruler and ruled. 

Let this be taken as our account of justice and the other, i.e. the 
other moral, virtues. 



Book VI 



Since we have previously said that one ought to choose that 
which is intermediate, not the excess nor the defect, and that 
the intermediate is determined by the dictates of the right rule, 
let us discuss the nature of these dictates. In all the states of 
character we have mentioned, as in all other matters, there is a 
mark to which the man who has the rule looks, and heightens 



2659 



or relaxes his activity accordingly, and there is a standard which 
determines the mean states which we say are intermediate 
between excess and defect, being in accordance with the right 
rule. But such a statement, though true, is by no means clear; 
for not only here but in all other pursuits which are objects of 
knowledge it is indeed true to say that we must not exert 
ourselves nor relax our efforts too much nor too little, but to an 
intermediate extent and as the right rule dictates; but if a man 
had only this knowledge he would be none the wiser e.g. we 
should not know what sort of medicines to apply to our body if 
some one were to say 'all those which the medical art 
prescribes, and which agree with the practice of one who 
possesses the art'. Hence it is necessary with regard to the 
states of the soul also not only that this true statement should 
be made, but also that it should be determined what is the right 
rule and what is the standard that fixes it. 

We divided the virtues of the soul and a said that some are 
virtues of character and others of intellect. Now we have 
discussed in detail the moral virtues; with regard to the others 
let us express our view as follows, beginning with some remarks 
about the soul. We said before that there are two parts of the 
soul - that which grasps a rule or rational principle, and the 
irrational; let us now draw a similar distinction within the part 
which grasps a rational principle. And let it be assumed that 
there are two parts which grasp a rational principle - one by 
which we contemplate the kind of things whose originative 
causes are invariable, and one by which we contemplate 
variable things; for where objects differ in kind the part of the 
soul answering to each of the two is different in kind, since it is 
in virtue of a certain likeness and kinship with their objects that 
they have the knowledge they have. Let one of these parts be 
called the scientific and the other the calculative; for to 
deliberate and to calculate are the same thing, but no one 
deliberates about the invariable. Therefore the calculative is one 



2660 



part of the faculty which grasps a rational principle. We must, 
then, learn what is the best state of each of these two parts; for 
this is the virtue of each. 



The virtue of a thing is relative to its proper work. Now there are 
three things in the soul which control action and truth - 
sensation, reason, desire. 

Of these sensation originates no action; this is plain from the 
fact that the lower animals have sensation but no share in 
action. 

What affirmation and negation are in thinking, pursuit and 
avoidance are in desire; so that since moral virtue is a state of 
character concerned with choice, and choice is deliberate desire, 
therefore both the reasoning must be true and the desire right, 
if the choice is to be good, and the latter must pursue just what 
the former asserts. Now this kind of intellect and of truth is 
practical; of the intellect which is contemplative, not practical 
nor productive, the good and the bad state are truth and falsity 
respectively (for this is the work of everything intellectual); 
while of the part which is practical and intellectual the good 
state is truth in agreement with right desire. 

The origin of action - its efficient, not its final cause - is choice, 
and that of choice is desire and reasoning with a view to an end. 
This is why choice cannot exist either without reason and 
intellect or without a moral state; for good action and its 
opposite cannot exist without a combination of intellect and 
character. Intellect itself, however, moves nothing, but only the 
intellect which aims at an end and is practical; for this rules the 



2661 



productive intellect, as well, since every one who makes makes 
for an end, and that which is made is not an end in the 
unqualified sense (but only an end in a particular relation, and 
the end of a particular operation) - only that which is done is 
that; for good action is an end, and desire aims at this. Hence 
choice is either desiderative reason or ratiocinative desire, and 
such an origin of action is a man. (It is to be noted that nothing 
that is past is an object of choice, e.g. no one chooses to have 
sacked Troy; for no one deliberates about the past, but about 
what is future and capable of being otherwise, while what is 
past is not capable of not having taken place; hence Agathon is 
right in saying 

For this alone is lacking even to God, 

To make undone things thathave once been done.) 

The work of both the intellectual parts, then, is truth. Therefore 
the states that are most strictly those in respect of which each 
of these parts will reach truth are the virtues of the two parts. 



Let us begin, then, from the beginning, and discuss these states 
once more. Let it be assumed that the states by virtue of which 
the soul possesses truth by way of affirmation or denial are five 
in number, i.e. art, scientific knowledge, practical wisdom, 
philosophic wisdom, intuitive reason; we do not include 
judgement and opinion because in these we may be mistaken. 

Now what scientific knowledge is, if we are to speak exactly and 
not follow mere similarities, is plain from what follows. We all 
suppose that what we know is not even capable of being 



2662 



otherwise; of things capable of being otherwise we do not know, 
when they have passed outside our observation, whether they 
exist or not. Therefore the object of scientific knowledge is of 
necessity. Therefore it is eternal; for things that are of necessity 
in the unqualified sense are all eternal; and things that are 
eternal are ungenerated and imperishable. Again, every science 
is thought to be capable of being taught, and its object of being 
learned. And all teaching starts from what is already known, as 
we maintain in the Analytics also; for it proceeds sometimes 
through induction and sometimes by syllogism. Now induction 
is the starting-point which knowledge even of the universal 
presupposes, while syllogism proceeds from universals. There 
are therefore starting-points from which syllogism proceeds, 
which are not reached by syllogism; it is therefore by induction 
that they are acquired. Scientific knowledge is, then, a state of 
capacity to demonstrate, and has the other limiting 
characteristics which we specify in the Analytics, for it is when 
a man believes in a certain way and the starting-points are 
known to him that he has scientific knowledge, since if they are 
not better known to him than the conclusion, he will have his 
knowledge only incidentally. 

Let this, then, be taken as our account of scientific knowledge. 



In the variable are included both things made and things done; 
making and acting are different (for their nature we treat even 
the discussions outside our school as reliable); so that the 
reasoned state of capacity to act is different from the reasoned 
state of capacity to make. Hence too they are not included one 
in the other; for neither is acting making nor is making acting. 



2663 



Now since architecture is an art and is essentially a reasoned 
state of capacity to make, and there is neither any art that is not 
such a state nor any such state that is not an art, art is identical 
with a state of capacity to make, involving a true course of 
reasoning. All art is concerned with coming into being, i.e. with 
contriving and considering how something may come into 
being which is capable of either being or not being, and whose 
origin is in the maker and not in the thing made; for art is 
concerned neither with things that are, or come into being, by 
necessity, nor with things that do so in accordance with nature 
(since these have their origin in themselves). Making and acting 
being different, art must be a matter of making, not of acting. 
And in a sense chance and art are concerned with the same 
objects; as Agathon says, 'art loves chance and chance loves art'. 
Art, then, as has been is a state concerned with making, 
involving a true course of reasoning, and lack of art on the 
contrary is a state concerned with making, involving a false 
course of reasoning; both are concerned with the variable. 



Regarding practical wisdom we shall get at the truth by 
considering who are the persons we credit with it. Now it is 
thought to be the mark of a man of practical wisdom to be able 
to deliberate well about what is good and expedient for himself, 
not in some particular respect, e.g. about what sorts of thing 
conduce to health or to strength, but about what sorts of thing 
conduce to the good life in general. This is shown by the fact 
that we credit men with practical wisdom in some particular 
respect when they have calculated well with a view to some 
good end which is one of those that are not the object of any 
art. It follows that in the general sense also the man who is 



2664 



capable of deliberating has practical wisdom. Now no one 
deliberates about things that are invariable, nor about things 
that it is impossible for him to do. Therefore, since scientific 
knowledge involves demonstration, but there is no 
demonstration of things whose first principles are variable (for 
all such things might actually be otherwise), and since it is 
impossible to deliberate about things that are of necessity, 
practical wisdom cannot be scientific knowledge nor art; not 
science because that which can be done is capable of being 
otherwise, not art because action and making are different 
kinds of thing. The remaining alternative, then, is that it is a 
true and reasoned state of capacity to act with regard to the 
things that are good or bad for man. For while making has an 
end other than itself, action cannot; for good action itself is its 
end. It is for this reason that we think Pericles and men like him 
have practical wisdom, viz. because they can see what is good 
for themselves and what is good for men in general; we 
consider that those can do this who are good at managing 
households or states. (This is why we call temperance 
(sophrosune) by this name; we imply that it preserves one's 
practical wisdom (sozousa tan phronsin). Now what it preserves 
is a judgement of the kind we have described. For it is not any 
and every judgement that pleasant and painful objects destroy 
and pervert, e.g. the judgement that the triangle has or has not 
its angles equal to two right angles, but only judgements about 
what is to be done. For the originating causes of the things that 
are done consist in the end at which they are aimed; but the 
man who has been ruined by pleasure or pain forthwith fails to 
see any such originating cause - to see that for the sake of this 
or because of this he ought to choose and do whatever he 
chooses and does; for vice is destructive of the originating cause 
of action.) Practical wisdom, then, must be a reasoned and true 
state of capacity to act with regard to human goods. But further, 
while there is such a thing as excellence in art, there is no such 



2665 



thing as excellence in practical wisdom; and in art he who errs 
willingly is preferable, but in practical wisdom, as in the virtues, 
he is the reverse. Plainly, then, practical wisdom is a virtue and 
not an art. There being two parts of the soul that can follow a 
course of reasoning, it must be the virtue of one of the two, i.e. 
of that part which forms opinions; for opinion is about the 
variable and so is practical wisdom. But yet it is not only a 
reasoned state; this is shown by the fact that a state of that sort 
may forgotten but practical wisdom cannot. 



Scientific knowledge is judgement about things that are 
universal and necessary, and the conclusions of demonstration, 
and all scientific knowledge, follow from first principles (for 
scientific knowledge involves apprehension of a rational 
ground). This being so, the first principle from which what is 
scientifically known follows cannot be an object of scientific 
knowledge, of art, or of practical wisdom; for that which can be 
scientifically known can be demonstrated, and art and practical 
wisdom deal with things that are variable. Nor are these first 
principles the objects of philosophic wisdom, for it is a mark of 
the philosopher to have demonstration about some things. If, 
then, the states of mind by which we have truth and are never 
deceived about things invariable or even variable are scientific 
knowlededge, practical wisdom, philosophic wisdom, and 
intuitive reason, and it cannot be any of the three (i.e. practical 
wisdom, scientific knowledge, or philosophic wisdom), the 
remaining alternative is that it is intuitive reason that grasps 
the first principles. 



2666 



Wisdom (1) in the arts we ascribe to their most finished 
exponents, e.g. to Phidias as a sculptor and to Polyclitus as a 
maker of portrait-statues, and here we mean nothing by 
wisdom except excellence in art; but (2) we think that some 
people are wise in general, not in some particular field or in any 
other limited respect, as Homer says in the Margites, 

Him did the gods make neither a digger nor yet a ploughman 

Nor wise in anything else. Therefore wisdom must plainly be 
the most finished of the forms of knowledge. It follows that the 
wise man must not only know what follows from the first 
principles, but must also possess truth about the first principles. 
Therefore wisdom must be intuitive reason combined with 
scientific knowledge - scientific knowledge of the highest 
objects which has received as it were its proper completion. 

Of the highest objects, we say; for it would be strange to think 
that the art of politics, or practical wisdom, is the best 
knowledge, since man is not the best thing in the world. Now if 
what is healthy or good is different for men and for fishes, but 
what is white or straight is always the same, any one would say 
that what is wise is the same but what is practically wise is 
different; for it is to that which observes well the various 
matters concerning itself that one ascribes practical wisdom, 
and it is to this that one will entrust such matters. This is why 
we say that some even of the lower animals have practical 
wisdom, viz. those which are found to have a power of foresight 
with regard to their own life. It is evident also that philosophic 
wisdom and the art of politics cannot be the same; for if the 
state of mind concerned with a man's own interests is to be 
called philosophic wisdom, there will be many philosophic 



2667 



wisdoms; there will not be one concerned with the good of all 
animals (any more than there is one art of medicine for all 
existing things), but a different philosophic wisdom about the 
good of each species. 

But if the argument be that man is the best of the animals, this 
makes no difference; for there are other things much more 
divine in their nature even than man, e.g., most conspicuously, 
the bodies of which the heavens are framed. From what has 
been said it is plain, then, that philosophic wisdom is scientific 
knowledge, combined with intuitive reason, of the things that 
are highest by nature. This is why we say Anaxagoras, Thales, 
and men like them have philosophic but not practical wisdom, 
when we see them ignorant of what is to their own advantage, 
and why we say that they know things that are remarkable, 
admirable, difficult, and divine, but useless; viz. because it is not 
human goods that they seek. 

Practical wisdom on the other hand is concerned with things 
human and things about which it is possible to deliberate; for 
we say this is above all the work of the man of practical 
wisdom, to deliberate well, but no one deliberates about things 
invariable, nor about things which have not an end, and that a 
good that can be brought about by action. The man who is 
without qualification good at deliberating is the man who is 
capable of aiming in accordance with calculation at the best for 
man of things attainable by action. Nor is practical wisdom 
concerned with universals only - it must also recognize the 
particulars; for it is practical, and practice is concerned with 
particulars. This is why some who do not know, and especially 
those who have experience, are more practical than others who 
know; for if a man knew that light meats are digestible and 
wholesome, but did not know which sorts of meat are light, he 
would not produce health, but the man who knows that chicken 
is wholesome is more likely to produce health. 



2668 



Now practical wisdom is concerned with action; therefore one 
should have both forms of it, or the latter in preference to the 
former. But of practical as of philosophic wisdom there must be 
a controlling kind. 



8 

Political wisdom and practical wisdom are the same state of 
mind, but their essence is not the same. Of the wisdom 
concerned with the city, the practical wisdom which plays a 
controlling part is legislative wisdom, while that which is 
related to this as particulars to their universal is known by the 
general name 'political wisdom'; this has to do with action and 
deliberation, for a decree is a thing to be carried out in the form 
of an individual act. This is why the exponents of this art are 
alone said to 'take part in polities'; for these alone 'do things' as 
manual labourers 'do things'. 

Practical wisdom also is identified especially with that form of it 
which is concerned with a man himself - with the individual; 
and this is known by the general name 'practical wisdom'; of 
the other kinds one is called household management, another 
legislation, the third politics, and of the latter one part is called 
deliberative and the other judicial. Now knowing what is good 
for oneself will be one kind of knowledge, but it is very different 
from the other kinds; and the man who knows and concerns 
himself with his own interests is thought to have practical 
wisdom, while politicians are thought to be busybodies; hence 
the word of Euripides, 

But how could I be wise, who might at ease, 

Numbered among the army's multitude, 



2669 



Have had an equal share? 

For those who aim too high and do too much. Those who think 
thus seek their own good, and consider that one ought to do so. 
From this opinion, then, has come the view that such men have 
practical wisdom; yet perhaps one's own good cannot exist 
without household management, nor without a form of 
government. Further, how one should order one's own affairs is 
not clear and needs inquiry. 

What has been said is confirmed by the fact that while young 
men become geometricians and mathematicians and wise in 
matters like these, it is thought that a young man of practical 
wisdom cannot be found. The cause is that such wisdom is 
concerned not only with universals but with particulars, which 
become familiar from experience, but a young man has no 
experience, for it is length of time that gives experience; indeed 
one might ask this question too, why a boy may become a 
mathematician, but not a philosopher or a physicist. It is 
because the objects of mathematics exist by abstraction, while 
the first principles of these other subjects come from 
experience, and because young men have no conviction about 
the latter but merely use the proper language, while the essence 
of mathematical objects is plain enough to them? 

Further, error in deliberation may be either about the universal 
or about the particular; we may fall to know either that all water 
that weighs heavy is bad, or that this particular water weighs 
heavy. 

That practical wisdom is not scientific knowledge is evident; for 
it is, as has been said, concerned with the ultimate particular 
fact, since the thing to be done is of this nature. It is opposed, 
then, to intuitive reason; for intuitive reason is of the limiting 
premisses, for which no reason can be given, while practical 
wisdom is concerned with the ultimate particular, which is the 



2670 



object not of scientific knowledge but of perception - not the 
perception of qualities peculiar to one sense but a perception 
akin to that by which we perceive that the particular figure 
before us is a triangle; for in that direction as well as in that of 
the major premiss there will be a limit. But this is rather 
perception than practical wisdom, though it is another kind of 
perception than that of the qualities peculiar to each sense. 



There is a difference between inquiry and deliberation; for 
deliberation is inquiry into a particular kind of thing. We must 
grasp the nature of excellence in deliberation as well whether it 
is a form of scientific knowledge, or opinion, or skill in 
conjecture, or some other kind of thing. Scientific knowledge it 
is not; for men do not inquire about the things they know about, 
but good deliberation is a kind of deliberation, and he who 
deliberates inquires and calculates. Nor is it skill in conjecture; 
for this both involves no reasoning and is something that is 
quick in its operation, while men deliberate a long time, and 
they say that one should carry out quickly the conclusions of 
one's deliberation, but should deliberate slowly. Again, readiness 
of mind is different from excellence in deliberation; it is a sort 
of skill in conjecture. Nor again is excellence in deliberation 
opinion of any sort. But since the man who deliberates badly 
makes a mistake, while he who deliberates well does so 
correctly, excellence in deliberation is clearly a kind of 
correctness, but neither of knowledge nor of opinion; for there 
is no such thing as correctness of knowledge (since there is no 
such thing as error of knowledge), and correctness of opinion is 
truth; and at the same time everything that is an object of 
opinion is already determined. But again excellence in 



2671 



deliberation involves reasoning. The remaining alternative, 
then, is that it is correctness of thinking; for this is not yet 
assertion, since, while even opinion is not inquiry but has 
reached the stage of assertion, the man who is deliberating, 
whether he does so well or ill, is searching for something and 
calculating. 

But excellence in deliberation is a certain correctness of 
deliberation; hence we must first inquire what deliberation is 
and what it is about. And, there being more than one kind of 
correctness, plainly excellence in deliberation is not any and 
every kind; for (1) the incontinent man and the bad man, if he is 
clever, will reach as a result of his calculation what he sets 
before himself, so that he will have deliberated correctly, but he 
will have got for himself a great evil. Now to have deliberated 
well is thought to be a good thing; for it is this kind of 
correctness of deliberation that is excellence in deliberation, viz. 
that which tends to attain what is good. But (2) it is possible to 
attain even good by a false syllogism, and to attain what one 
ought to do but not by the right means, the middle term being 
false; so that this too is not yet excellence in deliberation this 
state in virtue of which one attains what one ought but not by 
the right means. Again (3) it is possible to attain it by long 
deliberation while another man attains it quickly. Therefore in 
the former case we have not yet got excellence in deliberation, 
which is Tightness with regard to the expedient - Tightness in 
respect both of the end, the manner, and the time. (4) Further it 
is possible to have deliberated well either in the unqualified 
sense or with reference to a particular end. Excellence in 
deliberation in the unqualified sense, then, is that which 
succeeds with reference to what is the end in the unqualified 
sense, and excellence in deliberation in a particular sense is 
that which succeeds relatively to a particular end. If, then, it is 
characteristic of men of practical wisdom to have deliberated 
well, excellence in deliberation will be correctness with regard 



2672 



to what conduces to the end of which practical wisdom is the 
true apprehension. 



10 

Understanding, also, and goodness of understanding, in virtue 
of which men are said to be men of understanding or of good 
understanding, are neither entirely the same as opinion or 
scientific knowledge (for at that rate all men would have been 
men of understanding), nor are they one of the particular 
sciences, such as medicine, the science of things connected 
with health, or geometry, the science of spatial magnitudes. For 
understanding is neither about things that are always and are 
unchangeable, nor about any and every one of the things that 
come into being, but about things which may become subjects 
of questioning and deliberation. Hence it is about the same 
objects as practical wisdom; but understanding and practical 
wisdom are not the same. For practical wisdom issues 
commands, since its end is what ought to be done or not to be 
done; but understanding only judges. (Understanding is 
identical with goodness of understanding, men of 
understanding with men of good understanding.) Now 
understanding is neither the having nor the acquiring of 
practical wisdom; but as learning is called understanding when 
it means the exercise of the faculty of knowledge, so 
'understanding' is applicable to the exercise of the faculty of 
opinion for the purpose of judging of what some one else says 
about matters with which practical wisdom is concerned - and 
of judging soundly; for 'well' and 'soundly' are the same thing. 
And from this has come the use of the name 'understanding' in 
virtue of which men are said to be 'of good understanding', viz. 



2673 



from the application of the word to the grasping of scientific 
truth; for we often call such grasping understanding. 



11 

What is called judgement, in virtue of which men are said to 'be 
sympathetic judges' and to 'have judgement', is the right 
discrimination of the equitable. This is shown by the fact that 
we say the equitable man is above all others a man of 
sympathetic judgement, and identify equity with sympathetic 
judgement about certain facts. And sympathetic judgement is 
judgement which discriminates what is equitable and does so 
correctly; and correct judgement is that which judges what is 
true. 

Now all the states we have considered converge, as might be 
expected, to the same point; for when we speak of judgement 
and understanding and practical wisdom and intuitive reason 
we credit the same people with possessing judgement and 
having reached years of reason and with having practical 
wisdom and understanding. For all these faculties deal with 
ultimates, i.e. with particulars; and being a man of 
understanding and of good or sympathetic judgement consists 
in being able judge about the things with which practical 
wisdom is concerned; for the equities are common to all good 
men in relation to other men. Now all things which have to be 
done are included among particulars or ultimates; for not only 
must the man of practical wisdom know particular facts, but 
understanding and judgement are also concerned with things 
to be done, and these are ultimates. And intuitive reason is 
concerned with the ultimates in both directions; for both the 
first terms and the last are objects of intuitive reason and not of 



2674 



argument, and the intuitive reason which is presupposed by 
demonstrations grasps the unchangeable and first terms, while 
the intuitive reason involved in practical reasonings grasps the 
last and variable fact, i.e. the minor premiss. For these variable 
facts are the starting-points for the apprehension of the end, 
since the universals are reached from the particulars; of these 
therefore we must have perception, and this perception is 
intuitive reason. 

This is why these states are thought to be natural endowments 
- why, while no one is thought to be a philosopher by nature, 
people are thought to have by nature judgement, 
understanding, and intuitive reason. This is shown by the fact 
that we think our powers correspond to our time of life, and 
that a particular age brings with it intuitive reason and 
judgement; this implies that nature is the cause. (Hence 
intuitive reason is both beginning and end; for demonstrations 
are from these and about these.) Therefore we ought to attend 
to the undemonstrated sayings and opinions of experienced 
and older people or of people of practical wisdom not less than 
to demonstrations; for because experience has given them an 
eye they see aright. 

We have stated, then, what practical and philosophic wisdom 
are, and with what each of them is concerned, and we have said 
that each is the virtue of a different part of the soul. 



12 

Difficulties might be raised as to the utility of these qualities of 
mind. For (1) philosophic wisdom will contemplate none of the 
things that will make a man happy (for it is not concerned with 
any coming into being), and though practical wisdom has this 



2675 



merit, for what purpose do we need it? Practical wisdom is the 
quality of mind concerned with things just and noble and good 
for man, but these are the things which it is the mark of a good 
man to do, and we are none the more able to act for knowing 
them if the virtues are states of character, just as we are none 
the better able to act for knowing the things that are healthy 
and sound, in the sense not of producing but of issuing from the 
state of health; for we are none the more able to act for having 
the art of medicine or of gymnastics. But (2) if we are to say that 
a man should have practical wisdom not for the sake of 
knowing moral truths but for the sake of becoming good, 
practical wisdom will be of no use to those who are good; again 
it is of no use to those who have not virtue; for it will make no 
difference whether they have practical wisdom themselves or 
obey others who have it, and it would be enough for us to do 
what we do in the case of health; though we wish to become 
healthy, yet we do not learn the art of medicine. (3) Besides this, 
it would be thought strange if practical wisdom, being inferior 
to philosophic wisdom, is to be put in authority over it, as 
seems to be implied by the fact that the art which produces 
anything rules and issues commands about that thing. 

These, then, are the questions we must discuss; so far we have 
only stated the difficulties. 

(1) Now first let us say that in themselves these states must be 
worthy of choice because they are the virtues of the two parts of 
the soul respectively, even if neither of them produce anything. 

(2) Secondly, they do produce something, not as the art of 
medicine produces health, however, but as health produces 
health; so does philosophic wisdom produce happiness; for, 
being a part of virtue entire, by being possessed and by 
actualizing itself it makes a man happy. 



2676 



(3) Again, the work of man is achieved only in accordance with 
practical wisdom as well as with moral virtue; for virtue makes 
us aim at the right mark, and practical wisdom makes us take 
the right means. (Of the fourth part of the soul - the nutritive - 
there is no such virtue; for there is nothing which it is in its 
power to do or not to do.) 

(4) With regard to our being none the more able to do because of 
our practical wisdom what is noble and just, let us begin a little 
further back, starting with the following principle. As we say 
that some people who do just acts are not necessarily just, i.e. 
those who do the acts ordained by the laws either unwillingly or 
owing to ignorance or for some other reason and not for the 
sake of the acts themselves (though, to be sure, they do what 
they should and all the things that the good man ought), so is it, 
it seems, that in order to be good one must be in a certain state 
when one does the several acts, i.e. one must do them as a 
result of choice and for the sake of the acts themselves. Now 
virtue makes the choice right, but the question of the things 
which should naturally be done to carry out our choice belongs 
not to virtue but to another faculty. We must devote our 
attention to these matters and give a clearer statement about 
them. There is a faculty which is called cleverness; and this is 
such as to be able to do the things that tend towards the mark 
we have set before ourselves, and to hit it. Now if the mark be 
noble, the cleverness is laudable, but if the mark be bad, the 
cleverness is mere smartness; hence we call even men of 
practical wisdom clever or smart. Practical wisdom is not the 
faculty, but it does not exist without this faculty. And this eye of 
the soul acquires its formed state not without the aid of virtue, 
as has been said and is plain; for the syllogisms which deal with 
acts to be done are things which involve a starting-point, viz. 
'since the end, i.e. what is best, is of such and such a nature', 
whatever it may be (let it for the sake of argument be what we 
please); and this is not evident except to the good man; for 



2677 



wickedness perverts us and causes us to be deceived about the 
starting-points of action. Therefore it is evident that it is 
impossible to be practically wise without being good. 



13 

We must therefore consider virtue also once more; for virtue too 
is similarly related; as practical wisdom is to cleverness - not 
the same, but like it - so is natural virtue to virtue in the strict 
sense. For all men think that each type of character belongs to 
its possessors in some sense by nature; for from the very 
moment of birth we are just or fitted for selfcontrol or brave or 
have the other moral qualities; but yet we seek something else 
as that which is good in the strict sense - we seek for the 
presence of such qualities in another way. For both children and 
brutes have the natural dispositions to these qualities, but 
without reason these are evidently hurtful. Only we seem to see 
this much, that, while one may be led astray by them, as a 
strong body which moves without sight may stumble badly 
because of its lack of sight, still, if a man once acquires reason, 
that makes a difference in action; and his state, while still like 
what it was, will then be virtue in the strict sense. Therefore, as 
in the part of us which forms opinions there are two types, 
cleverness and practical wisdom, so too in the moral part there 
are two types, natural virtue and virtue in the strict sense, and 
of these the latter involves practical wisdom. This is why some 
say that all the virtues are forms of practical wisdom, and why 
Socrates in one respect was on the right track while in another 
he went astray; in thinking that all the virtues were forms of 
practical wisdom he was wrong, but in saying they implied 
practical wisdom he was right. This is confirmed by the fact that 
even now all men, when they define virtue, after naming the 



2678 



state of character and its objects add 'that (state) which is in 
accordance with the right rule'; now the right rule is that which 
is in accordance with practical wisdom. All men, then, seem 
somehow to divine that this kind of state is virtue, viz. that 
which is in accordance with practical wisdom. But we must go a 
little further. For it is not merely the state in accordance with 
the right rule, but the state that implies the presence of the 
right rule, that is virtue; and practical wisdom is a right rule 
about such matters. Socrates, then, thought the virtues were 
rules or rational principles (for he thought they were, all of 
them, forms of scientific knowledge), while we think they 
involve a rational principle. 

It is clear, then, from what has been said, that it is not possible 
to be good in the strict sense without practical wisdom, nor 
practically wise without moral virtue. But in this way we may 
also refute the dialectical argument whereby it might be 
contended that the virtues exist in separation from each other; 
the same man, it might be said, is not best equipped by nature 
for all the virtues, so that he will have already acquired one 
when he has not yet acquired another. This is possible in 
respect of the natural virtues, but not in respect of those in 
respect of which a man is called without qualification good; for 
with the presence of the one quality, practical wisdom, will be 
given all the virtues. And it is plain that, even if it were of no 
practical value, we should have needed it because it is the virtue 
of the part of us in question; plain too that the choice will not 
be right without practical wisdom any more than without 
virtue; for the one deter, mines the end and the other makes us 
do the things that lead to the end. 

But again it is not supreme over philosophic wisdom, i.e. over 
the superior part of us, any more than the art of medicine is 
over health; for it does not use it but provides for its coming 
into being; it issues orders, then, for its sake, but not to it. 



2679 



Further, to maintain its supremacy would be like saying that the 
art of politics rules the gods because it issues orders about all 
the affairs of the state. 



Book VII 



Let us now make a fresh beginning and point out that of moral 
states to be avoided there are three kinds - vice, incontinence, 
brutishness. The contraries of two of these are evident, - one we 
call virtue, the other continence; to brutishness it would be 
most fitting to oppose superhuman virtue, a heroic and divine 
kind of virtue, as Homer has represented Priam saying of Hector 
that he was very good, 

For he seemed not, he, 

The child of a mortal man, but as one that of God's seed came. 

Therefore if, as they say, men become gods by excess of virtue, 
of this kind must evidently be the state opposed to the brutish 
state; for as a brute has no vice or virtue, so neither has a god; 
his state is higher than virtue, and that of a brute is a different 
kind of state from vice. 

Now, since it is rarely that a godlike man is found - to use the 
epithet of the Spartans, who when they admire any one highly 
call him a 'godlike man' - so too the brutish type is rarely found 



2680 



among men; it is found chiefly among barbarians, but some 
brutish qualities are also produced by disease or deformity; and 
we also call by this evil name those men who go beyond all 
ordinary standards by reason of vice. Of this kind of disposition, 
however, we must later make some mention, while we have 
discussed vice before we must now discuss incontinence and 
softness (or effeminacy), and continence and endurance; for we 
must treat each of the two neither as identical with virtue or 
wickedness, nor as a different genus. We must, as in all other 
cases, set the observed facts before us and, after first discussing 
the difficulties, go on to prove, if possible, the truth of all the 
common opinions about these affections of the mind, or, failing 
this, of the greater number and the most authoritative; for if we 
both refute the objections and leave the common opinions 
undisturbed, we shall have proved the case sufficiently. 

Now (1) both continence and endurance are thought to be 
included among things good and praiseworthy, and both 
incontinence and soft, ness among things bad and 
blameworthy; and the same man is thought to be continent and 
ready to abide by the result of his calculations, or incontinent 
and ready to abandon them. And (2) the incontinent man, 
knowing that what he does is bad, does it as a result of passion, 
while the continent man, knowing that his appetites are bad, 
refuses on account of his rational principle to follow them (3) 
The temperate man all men call continent and disposed to 
endurance, while the continent man some maintain to be 
always temperate but others do not; and some call the self- 
indulgent man incontinent and the incontinent man 
selfindulgent indiscriminately, while others distinguish them. 
(4) The man of practical wisdom, they sometimes say, cannot be 
incontinent, while sometimes they say that some who are 
practically wise and clever are incontinent. Again (5) men are 
said to be incontinent even with respect to anger, honour, and 
gain. -These, then, are the things that are said. 



2681 



Now we may ask (1) how a man who judges rightly can behave 
incontinently. That he should behave so when he has 
knowledge, some say is impossible; for it would be strange - so 
Socrates thought - if when knowledge was in a man something 
else could master it and drag it about like a slave. For Socrates 
was entirely opposed to the view in question, holding that there 
is no such thing as incontinence; no one, he said, when he 
judges acts against what he judges best-people act so only by 
reason of ignorance. Now this view plainly contradicts the 
observed facts, and we must inquire about what happens to 
such a man; if he acts by reason of ignorance, what is the 
manner of his ignorance? For that the man who behaves 
incontinently does not, before he gets into this state, think he 
ought to act so, is evident. But there are some who concede 
certain of Socrates' contentions but not others; that nothing is 
stronger than knowledge they admit, but not that on one acts 
contrary to what has seemed to him the better course, and 
therefore they say that the incontinent man has not knowledge 
when he is mastered by his pleasures, but opinion. But if it is 
opinion and not knowledge, if it is not a strong conviction that 
resists but a weak one, as in men who hesitate, we sympathize 
with their failure to stand by such convictions against strong 
appetites; but we do not sympathize with wickedness, nor with 
any of the other blameworthy states. Is it then practical wisdom 
whose resistance is mastered? That is the strongest of all states. 
But this is absurd; the same man will be at once practically wise 
and incontinent, but no one would say that it is the part of a 
practically wise man to do willingly the basest acts. Besides, it 
has been shown before that the man of practical wisdom is one 



2682 



who will act (for he is a man concerned with the individual 
facts) and who has the other virtues. 

(2) Further, if continence involves having strong and bad 
appetites, the temperate man will not be continent nor the 
continent man temperate; for a temperate man will have 
neither excessive nor bad appetites. But the continent man 
must; for if the appetites are good, the state of character that 
restrains us from following them is bad, so that not all 
continence will be good; while if they are weak and not bad, 
there is nothing admirable in resisting them, and if they are 
weak and bad, there is nothing great in resisting these either. 

(3) Further, if continence makes a man ready to stand by any 
and every opinion, it is bad, i.e. if it mak